Dataset Preview
Full Screen
The full dataset viewer is not available (click to read why). Only showing a preview of the rows.
The dataset generation failed because of a cast error
Error code:   DatasetGenerationCastError
Exception:    DatasetGenerationCastError
Message:      An error occurred while generating the dataset

All the data files must have the same columns, but at some point there are 1 new columns ({'text'}) and 4 missing columns ({'num_embeddings', 'embedding_offset', 'passage_offset', 'num_passages'}).

This happened while the json dataset builder was generating data using

hf://datasets/forcemultiplier/diverse_subjects_nov13/colbert/indexes/pdf_files_index/collection.json (at revision 71885d6a36bc82e9dc30ba65e58681d1384ac230)

Please either edit the data files to have matching columns, or separate them into different configurations (see docs at https://hf.co/docs/hub/datasets-manual-configuration#multiple-configurations)
Traceback:    Traceback (most recent call last):
                File "/src/services/worker/.venv/lib/python3.9/site-packages/datasets/builder.py", line 1870, in _prepare_split_single
                  writer.write_table(table)
                File "/src/services/worker/.venv/lib/python3.9/site-packages/datasets/arrow_writer.py", line 622, in write_table
                  pa_table = table_cast(pa_table, self._schema)
                File "/src/services/worker/.venv/lib/python3.9/site-packages/datasets/table.py", line 2292, in table_cast
                  return cast_table_to_schema(table, schema)
                File "/src/services/worker/.venv/lib/python3.9/site-packages/datasets/table.py", line 2240, in cast_table_to_schema
                  raise CastError(
              datasets.table.CastError: Couldn't cast
              text: string
              -- schema metadata --
              pandas: '{"index_columns": [], "column_indexes": [], "columns": [{"name":' + 192
              to
              {'passage_offset': Value(dtype='int64', id=None), 'num_passages': Value(dtype='int64', id=None), 'num_embeddings': Value(dtype='int64', id=None), 'embedding_offset': Value(dtype='int64', id=None)}
              because column names don't match
              
              During handling of the above exception, another exception occurred:
              
              Traceback (most recent call last):
                File "/src/services/worker/src/worker/job_runners/config/parquet_and_info.py", line 1417, in compute_config_parquet_and_info_response
                  parquet_operations = convert_to_parquet(builder)
                File "/src/services/worker/src/worker/job_runners/config/parquet_and_info.py", line 1049, in convert_to_parquet
                  builder.download_and_prepare(
                File "/src/services/worker/.venv/lib/python3.9/site-packages/datasets/builder.py", line 924, in download_and_prepare
                  self._download_and_prepare(
                File "/src/services/worker/.venv/lib/python3.9/site-packages/datasets/builder.py", line 1000, in _download_and_prepare
                  self._prepare_split(split_generator, **prepare_split_kwargs)
                File "/src/services/worker/.venv/lib/python3.9/site-packages/datasets/builder.py", line 1741, in _prepare_split
                  for job_id, done, content in self._prepare_split_single(
                File "/src/services/worker/.venv/lib/python3.9/site-packages/datasets/builder.py", line 1872, in _prepare_split_single
                  raise DatasetGenerationCastError.from_cast_error(
              datasets.exceptions.DatasetGenerationCastError: An error occurred while generating the dataset
              
              All the data files must have the same columns, but at some point there are 1 new columns ({'text'}) and 4 missing columns ({'num_embeddings', 'embedding_offset', 'passage_offset', 'num_passages'}).
              
              This happened while the json dataset builder was generating data using
              
              hf://datasets/forcemultiplier/diverse_subjects_nov13/colbert/indexes/pdf_files_index/collection.json (at revision 71885d6a36bc82e9dc30ba65e58681d1384ac230)
              
              Please either edit the data files to have matching columns, or separate them into different configurations (see docs at https://hf.co/docs/hub/datasets-manual-configuration#multiple-configurations)

Need help to make the dataset viewer work? Make sure to review how to configure the dataset viewer, and open a discussion for direct support.

passage_offset
int64
num_passages
int64
num_embeddings
int64
embedding_offset
int64
text
string
0
22,909
6,115,434
0
null
null
null
null
null
AN INTRODUCTION TO BOUNDARY LAYER METEOROLOGY
null
null
null
null
ROLAND B. STULL Atmospheric Science Programme, Department of Geography The University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada. An Introduction to Boundary Layer Meteorology KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS DORDRECHT / BOSTON / LONDON
null
null
null
null
Libfary 01 Congress Cataloging in Publication Data SIUI I. RolinG S .. 1950- An ,n'"OOuct lon to b. "n alrY loy," • • ' "O"OlogV " o," 'V! ~. CI. -- (AUos~~or,c Hllne U ' Rollno e. 5'ul'. IncluUS O'O II .G""O~ '" Ona I na ... ISIIN,'3: 918-9().2n·2769-5 ,. Bou nOlry I IY", ' MIII.ralcgv' OCe90.4.B655194 ,999 551.!I--ocI9 ISBN-I): 978·90-2n-2769·5 001: IO.1007/978·94..(X)9·3027_8 c· ISBN·I): 978·94..((19..3027·8 aa- 15564 '" Published by Kluwe. Academic Publishe.s. P.O. 80x 17. 3300 AA Dordred1t. The NetheflandS. Kluwer Academic Publishers incorporates the publishing proglammes 01 D. Reidel. Martinus Nijhotl. Dr W. Junk and MTP Press. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Academic: Publishers. tOt Philip Orive. Norwell, MA 02061. U.S.A. In all othel countries. sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publ ishers GrOl)P. P.O. 80x 322, 3.300 AH Dordlecht. The Netherlands. H~t publislled 1999 RCIlO"inted 1989. 199 1. 1993. 1994 Reprinted with cITata 1991 R""rintoo 1999. 2001.
null
null
null
null
H~t publislled 1999 RCIlO"inted 1989. 199 1. 1993. 1994 Reprinted with cITata 1991 R""rintoo 1999. 2001. 2003 Printtd on acid-fru paptr All Rights Reserved © t 988 by Kh./We, ACademic Publishers SoftOOvef reprint of the hardoover tst edition t988 No part 01 the material protected by this copyright nOlice may be reproduced or uhlized In any lorm or by any means. electronic or mechanical Includin g photocopying. recording or by any inlormation "Iorage arid retrieval system , without written permissioo Irom the copyright owner
null
null
null
null
C!oo[co[s Preface XI Mean Boundary Layer Characteristics Turbulent transport Taylor's hypothesis 1.1 A bowlCjary-layer definition 1.2 Wind and flow 1.3 1.4 l.5 Virtual potential temperature 1.6 Boundary layer depth and slructure 1.7 Micrometeorology 1.8 1.9 General references 1.10 References for this chapter 1.11 Exercises Significance of the boundary layer 2 3 4 5 7 9 19 21 23 25 26 Some Mathematical and Conceptual Tools: Part 1. Statistics 29 1 2 The significance of turbulence and its spectrum Some basic statistical methods Turbulence kinetic energy 2.1 2.2 The spectral gap 2.3 Mean and turbulent parts 2.4 2.5 2.6 Kinematic flux 2.7 Eddy flux 2.8 Summation notation 2.9 Stress 2.10 Friction velocity 2.11 References 2.12 Exercises 29 33 33 35 45 47 51 57 63 67 68 70
null
null
null
null
vi 3 4 5 BOUNDARYLAYER~OROLOGY Application or the Governing Equations to Turbulent Flow 75 Simplifications, approximations, and scaling arguments 3.1 Methodology 3.2 Basic governing equations 3.3 3.4 Equations for mean variables in a turbulent flow 3.5 Summary of equations, with simplifications 3.6 Case studies 3.7 References 3.8 Exercises 76 76 80 87 93 97 110 111 Prognostic Equations for Turbulent Fluxes and Variances 115 Prognostic equations for the turbulent departures Free convection scaling variables Prognostic equations for variances Prognostic equations for turbulent fluxes 4.1 4.2 4.3 4.4 4.5 References 4.6 Exercises 115 117 120 134 147 148 Turbulence Kinetic Energy, Stability, and Scaling 151 5.1 The TKE budget derivation 5.2 Contributions 10 the TKE budget 5.3 TKE budget contributions as a function of eddy size 5.4 Mean kinetic energy and its interaction with turbulence Stability concepts 5.5 5.6 The Richardson number 5.7 The Obukhov length 5.8 Dimensionless gradients 5.9 Miscellaneous scaling parameters 5.10 Combined stability tables 5.11 References 5.12 Exercises 6 Turbulence Closure Techniques 6.1 The closure problem 6.2 Parameterization rules 6.3 Local closure - 6.4 Local closure - 6.5 Local closure - 6.6 Local closure - 6.7 Local closure - 6.8 Nonlocal closure - 6.9 Nonlocal closure - 6.10 References 6.
null
null
null
null
3 Local closure - 6.4 Local closure - 6.5 Local closure - 6.6 Local closure - 6.7 Local closure - 6.8 Nonlocal closure - 6.9 Nonlocal closure - 6.10 References 6.11 Exercises zero and half order first order one-and·a·half order second order third order transilient turbulence theory spectral diffusivity theory 151 153 166 168 169 175 180 183 184 186 187 189 197 200 202 203 214 220 224 225 240 242 245 197
null
null
null
null
COmENTS vii 7 8 Boundary Conditions and External Forcings 251 7.1 Effective surface turbulent flux 7.2 Heat budget at the surface 7.3 Radiation budget 7.4 Auxes at interfaces 7.5 Partitioning of flux into sensible and latent portions 7.6 Aux 10 and from the ground 7.7 References 7.8 Exercises 251 253 256 261 272 282 289 292 Some Mathematical and Conceptual Tools: Part 2. Time Series 295 Fast Fourier Transfonn 8.1 Time and space series 8.2 Autocorrelation 8.3 Structure function 8.4 Discrete Fourier transfonn 8.5 8.6 Energy spectrum 8.7 Spectral characteristics 8.8 Spectra of two variables 8.9 Periodogram 8.10 Nonlocal spectra 8.11 Spectral decomposition of the TKE equation 8.12 References 8.13 Exercises 9 Similarity Theory 9.1 An overview 9.2 Buckingham Pi dimensional analysis methods 9.3 Scaling variables 9.4 Stable boundary layer similarity relationship lislS 9.5 Neutral boundary layer similarity relationship lislS 9.6 Convective boundary layer similarity relationship IislS 9.7 The log wind profile 9.8 Rossby-number similarity and proftle matching 9.9 Spectral similarity 9.10 Similarity scaling domains 9.11 References 9.12 Exercises 295 296 300 303 310 312 318 329 335 336 340 342 344 347 350 354 360 364 368 376 386 389 394 395 399 347
null
null
null
null
viii BOUNDARY LAYER MmTEOROLOGY 10 Measurement and Simulation Techniques 405 Instrument platforms 10.1 Sensor and measurement categories 10.2 Sensor lists 10.3 Active remote sensor observations of morphology 10.4 10.5 Field experiments 10.6 Simulation methods 10.7 Analysis methods 10.8 References 10.9 Exercises 11 Convective Mixed Layer 11.1 The unstable surface layer 11.2 The mixed layer 11.3 Enrrainment zone 11.4 Enrrainment velocity and its parameterization 11.5 Subsidence and advection 11.6 References 11.7 Exercises 12 Stable Boundary Layer 12.1 Mean Characteristics 12.2 Processc:; 12.3 Evolution 12.4 Other Depth Models 12 .5 Low-level (nocturnal) jet 12.6 Buoyancy (gravity) waves 12.7 Terrain slope and drainage winds 12.8 References 12.9 Exercises 13 Boundary Layer Clouds 13.1 Thermodynamics 13.2 Radiation 13.3 Cloud enrrainment mechanisms 13.4 Fair-weather cumulus 13.5 Stratocumulus 13 .6 Fog 13.7 References 13.8 Exercises 405 407 410 413 417 420 427 434 438 442 450 473 477 483 487 494 499 506 516 518 520 526 534 538 542 545 555 558 562 570 576 578 583 441 499 545
null
null
null
null
14 Geographic Effects 14.1 Geographically generated local winds 14.2 Geographically modified flow 14.3 Urban heat island 14.4 References 14.5 Exercises Appendices Scaling variables and dimensionless groups A. B. Notation C. Useful constants, parameters and conversion factors D. Derivation of virtual potential temperature Subject Index Errata section CONTENTS ix 587 595 609 613 617 621 629 639 645 587 619 649 667
null
null
null
null
Preface Part of the excitement of boundary-layer meteorology is the challenge in :;tudying and one of the unsolved problems of classical physics. understanding turbulent flow - Additional excitement stems from the rich diversity of topics and research methods that we collect under the umbrella of boundary-layer meteorology. That we live our lives within the boundary layer makes it a subject that touches us, and allows us to touch it. I've tried to capture some of the excitement, challenges and diversity within this book. I wrote this book with a variety of goals in mind. First and foremost, this book is designed as a textbook. Fundamental concepts and mathematics are presented prior to their use, physical interpretations of equation tenns are given, sample data is shown, examples are solved, and exercises are included. Second, the book is organized as a reference, with tables of parameterizations, procedures, field experiments, useful constants, and graphs of various phenomena in a variety of conditions. Third, the last several chapters are presented as a literature review of the current ideas and methods in boundary layer meteorology. It is assumed that this book will be used at the beginning graduate level for students with an undergraduate background in meteorology. However, a diversity in the background of the readers is anticipated. Those with a strong mathematical background can skip portions of Chapter 2 on statistics, and those with experience with time series can skip Chapter 8. These two mathematics chapters were separated to offer the reader a chance to apply the first dose of statistics to boundary layer applications before delving back into more math. Some students might have had a course on geophysical turbulence or statistical fluid mechanics, and .can skim through the fll'st 5 chapters to get to the boundary-layer applications. By excluding a few chapters, instructors can easily fit the remaining material into a one-semester course.
null
null
null
null
By excluding a few chapters, instructors can easily fit the remaining material into a one-semester course. With supplemental readings, the book can serve as a two-semester sequence in atmospheric turbulence and boundary-layer meteorology. Notational diversity proved to be the greatest difficulty. Each subdiscipline appeared to have its own set of notation, which often conflicted with the notation of other subdisciplines. To use the published notation would have lead to confusion. I was therefore forced to select a consistent set of notation to use throughout the book. In most cases I've tried to retain the notation most frequently used in the literature, or to add subscripts or make logical extensions to existing notation. In other cases, I had to depart from previously published notation. Readers are referred to Appendix B for a comprehensive list of notation. xi
null
null
null
null
~ BOUNDARYLAYER~OROLOGY I certainly cannot claim to be an expert in all the myriad subdisciplines of boundary layer meteorology. yet I knew the book should be comprehensive to be useful. My interest and enthusiasm in writing this book motivated many trips to the library. and stimulated my analysis of many research papers to learn the underlying themes and common tools used in the diverse areas of boundary layer meteorology. Unfortunately. the limited space within this book necessitated some difficult decisions regarding the amount and level of material to include. Hopefully I've presented sufficient background to lay the building blocks upon which more advanced concepts can be built by other instructors and researchers. Certain topics such as atmospheric dispersion and agricultural micrometeorology are not covered here. because there are other excellent books on these subjects. Many colleagues and friends helped with this book and contributed significantly to its final form and quality. Michelle Vandall deserves special recognition and thanks for drawing most of the figures. designing the page and chapter headers. and for her overall dedication to this project. Colleagues Steve Stage. Larry Mahrt. George Young. Jacq Schols. Chandran Kaimal. Steve Silberberg. Beth Ebert. and Bruce Albrecht reviewed various chapters and provided valuable suggestions. Information regarding field experiments was provided by Anton Beljaars. Ad Driedonks. Jean-Claude Andre. Jean Paul Goutorbe. Anne Jochum. Steve Nelson. Bob Murphy. Ruwim Berkowicz. Peter Hildebrand. Don Lenschow. and others. Eric Nelson proofread the manuscript. and helped with the list of notation. Sam Zhang compiled the index.
null
null
null
null
Bob Murphy. Ruwim Berkowicz. Peter Hildebrand. Don Lenschow. and others. Eric Nelson proofread the manuscript. and helped with the list of notation. Sam Zhang compiled the index. Some of the equations were typeset by Camille Riner and Michelle Vlllldall (her name keeps reappearing). Four years of students in my micrometeorology courses at Wisconsin graciously tolerated various unfinished drafts of the book. and caught many mistakes. The patient editors of Kluwer Academic Publishers (formerly D. Reidel) provided constant encouragement. and are to be congratulated for their foresight and advice. The American Meteorological Society is acknowledged for permission to reproduce figures 10.7. 12.10 and 12.19. To all of these people and the many more to whom I apologize for not naming here. I thank you. To my wife. Linda. I give my gratitude for her devotion during this exciting and exhausting episode of my life. Roland B. Stull Boundary Layer Research Team Madison. Wisconsin
null
null
null
null
Z (m) 1000 500 0 (a) z (m) 500 250 o (b) 1000 Range from lidar (km) Range from lidar (km) Frontispiece lidar images of the aerosol-laden boundary layer, obtained during the FIFE field experiment in Kansas. (a) Convective mixed layer observed at 1030 local time on 1 July 1987, when winds were generally less than 2 mls. (b) Slightly-stable boundary layer with shear-generated turbulence, observed at 530 local time on 7 July 1987. Winds ranged from 5 mls near the surface to 15 mls near the top of the boundary layer. Photographs from the Univ. of Wisconsin lidar are courtesy of E. Eloranta, Boundary Layer Research Team.
null
null
null
null
Claude V. Palisca HUMANISM IN ITALIAN RENAISSANCE MUSICAL THOUGHT Yale University Press New Haven and London
null
null
null
null
Humanism in Italian Renaissance Musical Thought
null
null
null
null
To tile memory of my motller Gisella Fleisch/lacker Palisca (1895-1944) I'ublishcd wilh .1SsUtanCr from the Louis 51t'", Memori;al Fund. Copyright 4) 1985 by Yale UniversilY. All righls reserved. This book may 1101 br reproduced. in whole or in pUI. ill ;any form (beyolld Ih;al copy illS permilled by Sections 1117 ;and \08 of Iht' U. S. Copyrighl L.t w .and c"cepl by rc:viewers for II\!: public prcss). wilhout wrinc:n permission Irom the publishers. DcsigllC.'d by N.ancy Ovedovill lllli 5C:1 in Ilembo typc: by Rainsford Type. I)rilllell in the United 51311:5 of America by Edwards Brothers. Inc .• Ann Arhor. Michigan. Library of Congrcss Cataloging ill I)ublicatioll Dala l'alisC:I. Claude V. Humanism in h.alian Rm.:aissance musical thOllghl Bibliognphy: p. Includc.'S index. I. Music-haly-15th century-History ;and criticism. 2. Music h.:aly-16th cmlury-History .and crilicism. 3. nen;aissance-haly. 4. Humanism. I. Tide.
null
null
null
null
I. Music-haly-15th century-History ;and criticism. 2. Music h.:aly-16th cmlury-History .and crilicism. 3. nen;aissance-haly. 4. Humanism. I. Tide. ML2'JeI.2.1)34 1985781.745 as-8ICJO ISDN 0-300-03302-8 The paprr in Ihis book meets thr guidelincs for permanence and du rability of the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Lon gevily of Ihe Council on Libnry Resources. 10 I) 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 I
null
null
null
null
Contents Preface ONE Introduction: An Italian Renaissance in Music? TWO The Rediscovery of the Ancient Sources THREE The Earliest Musical Humanists: Pietro d'Abano FOUR The Earliest Musical Humanists: Giorgio Valla FIVE The Earliest Musical Humanists: Carlo Valgulio The Proem to Plm:lrch's De tllllsica A Reply to an Opponent of Music The Translation of the De IHilsica of Plutarch SIX The Early Translators: Burana, Lconiceno, Augio Giovanni Fr:mcesco Burana Nicolo Leoniceno Giovanni Battista Augio SEVEN Antonio Goga va Ptolemy's Harmotlics Pseudo-Aristotlc's De alldibiliblls Aristoxcnus' Harmonic Elements Bomigari's Corrections vii xi 23 51 67 88 111 133
null
null
null
null
Contents TWELVE A Natural New Alliance of the Arts Grammar Mei on tonic accent Pietro Bembo THIRTEEN The Poetics of Music Music as Poetry Vincenzo Galilci The Poetics of Imitation The Case against Mimesis: Francesco Patrizi Expressing the Affections FOURTEEN Theory of Dramatic Music Francesco Patrizi Girolamo Mei Jacopo Peri Works Cited Index ix 333 369 408 435 453 viii Contents EIGHT Harmonics and Disharmonies of the Spheres 161 Ugolino of Orvieto Giorgio Anselmi Franchino Gaffurio Gioseffo Zarlino Johannes Tinctoris Francisco de Salinas Giovanni Battista Benedetti Celestial Harmony as Myth and Metaphor NINE GatTurio as a Humanist TEN The Ancient Musica Speclliativa and Renaissance Musical Science Franchino Gaffurio Hamos de Pareja Giovanni Spataro Lodovico Fogliano Gioscffo Zarlino Francisco de Salinas Girolamo Fracastoro Giov:mni Battista Benedetti Girolamo Mei and Vincenzo Galilci ELEVEN Greek Tonality and Western Modality Johannes Gallicus Erasmus of Horitz Giorgio Valla Nicolo Leoniceno Franchino Gaffurio Gioseffo Zarlino Francisco de Salinas Girolamo Mei Vincenzo Galilei The Tonoi and the Waning of Modality Giovanni Bardi Giovanni Battista Doni 191 226 280
null
null
null
null
Preface Music historians have long been aware of a link between the revival of ancient learning and the changes in musical style and theory that occurred during the Renaissance. But the ties to antiquity have been hard to pin down. because ancient music could not be recreated as could ancient lit erature and architecture. Instead. the objects of revival were ancient attitudes and thoughts about music. The route by which these reached Renaissance musicians and critics has not been studied with any precision or thorough ness. Indeed. the men most rt.'sponsible for the transmission of Greek thought about music have been practically ignored. Their names. some of which head chapters or sections in this book-Pietro d·Abano. Giorgio Valla. Carlo Valgulio. Antonio Gogava. Francesco Burana. Nicolo Leoniceno are missing from even the most comprehensive accounts of the musical culture of the Renaissance. This book aims to document the debt that Renaissance musical thought owes to ancient. particularly Greek. musical thought and to trace its path of transmission in Italy. I have had to rely almost entirely on primary sources. Because of this necessity. the previous literature on musical hu manism and on music in the Renaissance has been given less attention than it truly deserves. Therefore I want to express here my debt to those who earlier explored musical humanism and lighted my way, particularly Ed ward E. Lowinsky. PaulO. Kristeller. Nino Pirrotta, Leo Schrade, D. P. Walker.
null
null
null
null
PaulO. Kristeller. Nino Pirrotta, Leo Schrade, D. P. Walker. and Edith Weber, for I have learned enormously from them. In general the field has been dominated by the hunt for parallels between musical manifestations and those in other ans and humanities that show a strong reliance on ancient models. But even where parallels have been found. there has been little direct evidence of relationships among the composers. writers. philosophers. architects. and artists whose work is involved. I cannot claim to have discovered many such associations either, so the search must continue, for where no direct connections can be shown. the con- r xi
null
null
null
null
Preface xiii University. enriched and enhanced this book in many ways. by lending me microfilms of Greek manuscripts that once belonged to Giorgio Valla. by letting me use some of the information in the catalog of Greek manuscripts of music theory he is preparing for the RepertOire imernationale des sources musicales, by reviewing my translations of the Latin versions of Greek trea tises by Burana. Leoniceno. Gogava. and Augio and offering many prov ident corrections and excellent suggestions. and. finally. by reading and commenting on the entire manuscript. To these scholars I. and the reader too. owe sincere thanks. Among others who have stood behind this work. I give special thanks to Edward Tripp. Editor-in-Chief of the Yale University Press. for his encouragement and interest. to jean van Altena for her very attentive reading and sympathetic editing. to Michael Pepper and jay Williams for their resourceful recoding and production of the manuscript from its electronic state. to my daughter Madeline for her punctilious drafting of the index. and to my wife. Jane. for advice on many matters. big and small. and for her confidence and unfailing support. Branford October 1984 xii Preface current trends. like parallel lines. never meet. and we can learn little from simply contemplating the striking analogil'S. I have avoided drawing such parallels. limiting myself to those connections between music and ancient thought that we know existed in the minds of Renaissance men because they are recorded in writing. These considerations. too.
null
null
null
null
limiting myself to those connections between music and ancient thought that we know existed in the minds of Renaissance men because they are recorded in writing. These considerations. too. explain why I have not allocated much space to past literature on musical humanism. As a consequence of this approach and the interdisciplinary scope of my study. the secondary literature referred to in the footnotes is restricted to those works that were specifically utilized for the material in the text. and the bibliography lists only these. Some chapters may strike the reader as almost anthologies of extracts from Renaissance writings on music and related subjects. Since so many of the works quoted are unpublished or extremely rare. this was the only way I could let my authors speak for themselves. And since none of them wrote in English. I wanted to let the reader experience the power of their own words. with the aid of parallel translations. Whenever possible the material in the two columns corresponds line for line. consequences of which are a certain literalness and a ragged format. The translations are my own except where I have indicated otherwise. Many organizations and individuals have generously supported my re search over the years. It was begun in Florence on a Guggenheim Fellowship and completed on a second one twenty years later. In between. a Senior Fellowship of the National Endowment for the Humanities permitted a year in Paris at the remarkable collection of Renaissance books of the Biblio theque Nationale. The Whitney Griswold Fund of Yale University aided the preparation of the manuscript. And. of course. the Yale libraries.
null
null
null
null
The Whitney Griswold Fund of Yale University aided the preparation of the manuscript. And. of course. the Yale libraries. p~r­ ticularly the Music Library and the Beinecke: Rare Book and Manuscnpt Library. provided a solid home base for my investigations. Several of my students at Yale have helped me during various stages. joseph DiGiovanni. of the Renaissance Studies Program. transcribed parts of Leoniceno's translation ofPtolemy's Harmonics. Deborah Narani. of the Medieval Studies Program. checked my translations of Pietro d'Abano's commentary on the pseudo-Aristotle Problems. Otto Stein mayer. of the Classics Depanment. reviewed most of my translations from Latin and made many essential improvements in them. Of the many colleagues to whom I feel indebted. I should name seve~al. jon Solomon. of the University of Arizona. kindly made available his trans lation ofCleonides' Harmonic introduction. Frank d' Accone, of the University of California, Los Angeles, and james Haar. of the University of North Carolina, contributed to my thinking with their learned commentaries on my first chapter when it was delivered as a lecture in honor of A. Tillman Merritt's retirement from Harvard. Thomas J. Mathiesen, of Brigham Young
null
null
null
null
It ONE Introduction: An Italian Renaissance in Music? istorians generally view the Renaissance as a movement that began in Italy and spread northward. Music histo rians. however. have habitually begun the study of music in the Renaissance with composers associated with France Jnd the Low Countries. Gustave Reese organized his book lHIIsi( i" th,' R"lldiSSI1I1((' on the premise that a central mus ical language arose in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries in France. the Low Countries. and Italy. and spread to Spain. Portugal. Germany. Eng land. and eastt:rn Europe. In the first part of the book he defines this language in terms of the music of Dufay. Busnois. and Ockeghem. who were active principally in the north. 1 Similarly Howard Mayer Brown takes the view that music in the: Ren aissance "is a northern art. or at least an art by northerners. All of the great composers of the fifteenth and early sixteenth centuries were born in what is today northern France. Belgium. and Holland.": Thus. while the impetus for the Renaissance in the visual arts. literature. and philosophy is generally recognized to have come from Italy and moved across the Alps, we are confronted in music history with the thesis that music. of all artistic expressions. moved in the opposite direction. Now contrary motion may be a praiseworthy polyphonic practice. but it is dis concerting when applied to cultural historiography. If history in general has a proverbial "problem of the Renaissance." how much more acute it is in music history! Heinrich Besseler.
null
null
null
null
but it is dis concerting when applied to cultural historiography. If history in general has a proverbial "problem of the Renaissance." how much more acute it is in music history! Heinrich Besseler. reflecting on his own work in Renaissance studies since I. Gustave: R.e:rse. MIlS;( ;11 IlIr RtI,a;ssalltt (New York. 1954). Pt. I. 2. Howard Mayer Brown. ''''lIs;( ;11 tI,r R.."a;ssallcr (Englewood Cliffs. 1976). p. 4. Leo Schrade:. in "Renaissance: the Historical Conception of an Epoch." K"'~~Tfss·B('r;("t drT IIII(r. IIa/;ollalt Gtstllscl,aft fiir Mllsikll·;swrstl",,,,fi. Utrtc/It 1951 (Amsterdam. 1953). pp. 19-32. took a similar view: "In contrast to the bonae lillerae and to the visual arts as well. the rebirth of music came to pass as an achievement of northern composers ... " (p. 3U) .• r 1
null
null
null
null
Game Theory
null
null
null
null
GAME THEORY Analysis of Conflict ROGER B. MYERSON HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England
null
null
null
null
Copyright © 1991 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America First Harvard University Press paperback edition, 1997 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Myerson, Roger B. Game theory : analysis of conflict / Roger B. Myerson. p. (cid:9) cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-674-34115-5 (cloth) ISBN 0-674-34116-3 (pbk.) 1. Game Theory (cid:9) I. Title H61.25.M94 (cid:9) 519.3—dc20 (cid:9) 1991 90-42901 (cid:9) (cid:9)
null
null
null
null
For Gina, Daniel, and Rebecca With the hope that a better understanding of conflict may help create a safer and more peaceful world
null
null
null
null
Contents Preface (cid:9) 1 Decision-Theoretic Foundations (cid:9) 1.1 (cid:9) Game Theory, Rationality, and Intelligence 1.2 Basic Concepts of Decision Theory 5 1.3 Axioms 9 1.4 The Expected-Utility Maximization Theorem 12 1.5 (cid:9) 1.6 Bayesian Conditional-Probability Systems 21 1.7 Limitations of the Bayesian Model 22 1.8 Domination 26 1.9 Proofs of the Domination Theorems 31 Equivalent Representations 18 Exercises 33 2 Basic Models (cid:9) 2.1 Games in Extensive Form 37 2.2 Strategic Form and the Normal Representation 46 2.3 Equivalence of Strategic-Form Games 51 2.4 Reduced Normal Representations 54 2.5 Elimination of Dominated Strategies 57 2.6 Multiagent Representations 61 2.7 Common Knowledge 63 2.8 Bayesian Games 67 2.9 Modeling Games with Incomplete Information 74 Exercises 83 3 Equilibria of Strategic-Form Games (cid:9) 3.1 (cid:9) Domination and Rationalizability 88 3.2 Nash Equilibrium 91 xi 1 37 88 (cid:9) (cid:9) (cid:9)
null
null
null
null
viii (cid:9) Contents 3.3 Computing Nash Equilibria 99 3.4 Significance of Nash Equilibria 105 3.5 The Focal-Point Effect 108 3.6 The Decision-Analytic Approach to Games 114 3.7 Evolution, Resistance, and Risk Dominance 117 3.8 Two-Person Zero-Sum Games 122 3.9 (cid:9) 3.10 Purification of Randomized Strategies in Equilibria 129 3.11 Auctions 132 3.12 Proof of Existence of Equilibrium 136 3.13 Infinite Strategy Sets 140 Bayesian Equilibria 127 Exercises 148 4 Sequential Equilibria of Extensive - Form Games (cid:9) 154 4.1 (cid:9) Mixed Strategies and Behavioral Strategies 154 4.2 (cid:9) 4.3 (cid:9) Equilibria in Behavioral Strategies 161 Sequential Rationality at Information States with Positive Probability 163 4.4 Consistent Beliefs and Sequential Rationality at All Information States 168 4.5 Computing Sequential Equilibria 177 4.6 Subgame-Perfect Equilibria 183 4.7 Games with Perfect Information 185 4.8 Adding Chance Events with Small Probability 187 4.9 Forward Induction 190 4.10 Voting and Binary Agendas 196 4.11 Technical Proofs 202 Exercises 208 5 Refinements of Equilibrium in Strategic Form (cid:9) 213 Introduction 213 Perfect Equilibria 216 Existence of Perfect and Sequential Equilibria 221 Proper Equilibria 222 Persistent Equilibria 230 Stable Sets of Equilibria 232 5.1 (cid:9) 5.2 (cid:9) 5.3 (cid:9) 5.4 (cid:9) 5.5 (cid:9) 5.6 (cid:9) 5.7 Generic Properties 239 5.8 Conclusions 240 Exercises 242 6 Games with Communication (cid:9) 244 Contracts and Correlated Strategies 244 6.
null
null
null
null
5 (cid:9) 5.6 (cid:9) 5.7 Generic Properties 239 5.8 Conclusions 240 Exercises 242 6 Games with Communication (cid:9) 244 Contracts and Correlated Strategies 244 6.1 (cid:9) 6.2 Correlated Equilibria 249 6.3 Bayesian Games with Communication 258 6.4 Bayesian Collective-Choice Problems and Bayesian Bargaining Problems 263
null
null
null
null
Contents (cid:9) ix 6.5 Trading Problems with Linear Utility 271 6.6 General Participation Constraints for Bayesian Games with Contracts 281 6.7 Sender-Receiver Games 283 6.8 Acceptable and Predominant Correlated Equilibria 288 6.9 Communication in Extensive-Form and Multistage Games 294 Exercises 299 Bibliographic Note 307 7 Repeated Games (cid:9) 308 7.1 The Repeated Prisoners' Dilemma 308 7.2 A General Model of Repeated Games 310 7.3 Stationary Equilibria of Repeated Gaines with Complete State Information and Discounting 317 7.4 Repeated Games with Standard Information: Examples 323 7.5 General Feasibility Theorems for Standard Repeated Games 331 7.6 Finitely Repeated Games and the Role of Initial Doubt 337 7.7 Imperfect Observability of Moves 342 7.8 Repeated Games in Large Decentralized Groups 349 7.9 Repeated Games with Incomplete Information 352 7.10 Continuous Time 361 7.11 Evolutionary Simulation of Repeated Games 364 Exercises 365 8 Bargaining and Cooperation in Two-Person Games (cid:9) 370 8.1 Noncooperative Foundations of Cooperative Game Theory 370 8.2 Two-Person Bargaining Problems and the Nash Bargaining Solution 375 8.3 Interpersonal Comparisons of Weighted Utility 381 8.4 Transferable Utility 384 8.5 Rational Threats 385 8.6 Other Bargaining Solutions 390 8.7 An Alternating-Offer Bargaining Game 394 8.8 An Alternating-Offer Game with Incomplete Information 399 8.9 A Discrete Alternating-Offer Game 403 8.10 Renegotiation 408 Exercises 412 9 Coalitions in Cooperative Games (cid:9) 417 Introduction to Coalitional Analysis 417 9.1 (cid:9) 9.2 Characteristic Functions with Transferable Utility 422 9.3 The Core 427 9.
null
null
null
null
1 (cid:9) 9.2 Characteristic Functions with Transferable Utility 422 9.3 The Core 427 9.4 The Shapley Value 436 9.5 Values with Cooperation Structures 444 9.6 Other Solution Concepts 452 9.7 Coalitional Games with Nontransferable Utility 456
null
null
null
null
x (cid:9) Contents 9.8 Cores without Transferable Utility 462 9.9 Values without Transferable Utility 468 Exercises 478 Bibliographic Note 481 10 Cooperation under Uncertainty (cid:9) 483 10.1 Introduction 483 10.2 Concepts of Efficiency 485 10.3 An Example 489 10.4 Ex Post Inefficiency and Subsequent Offers 493 10.5 Computing Incentive-Efficient Mechanisms 497 10.6 Inscrutability and Durability 502 10.7 Mechanism Selection by an Informed Principal 509 10.8 Neutral Bargaining Solutions 515 10.9 Dynamic Matching Processes with Incomplete Information 526 Exercises 534 Bibliography Index 539 553
null
null
null
null
Preface Game theory has a very general scope, encompassing questions that are basic to all of the social sciences. It can offer insights into any economic, political, or social situation that involves individuals who have different goals or preferences. However, there is a fundamental unity and co- herent methodology that underlies the large and growing literature on game theory and its applications. My goal in this book is to convey both the generality and the unity of game theory. I have tried to present some of the most important models, solution concepts, and results of game theory, as well as the methodological principles that have guided game theorists to develop these models and solutions. This book is written as a general introduction to game theory, in- tended for both classroom use and self-study. It is based on courses that I have taught at Northwestern University, the University of Chicago, and the University of Paris—Dauphine. I have included here, however, somewhat more cooperative game theory than I can actually cover in a first course. I have tried to set an appropriate balance between non- cooperative and cooperative game theory, recognizing the fundamental primacy of noncooperative game theory but also the essential and com- plementary role of the cooperative approach. The mathematical prerequisite for this book is some prior exposure to elementary calculus, linear algebra, and probability, at the basic un- dergraduate level. It is not as important to know the theorems that may be covered in such mathematics courses as it is to be familiar with the basic ideas and notation of sets, vectors, functions, and limits. Where more advanced mathematics is used, I have given a short, self-contained explanation of the mathematical ideas.
null
null
null
null
xii (cid:9) Preface In every chapter, there are some topics of a more advanced or spe- cialized nature that may be omitted without loss of subsequent compre- hension. I have not tried to "star" such sections or paragraphs. Instead, I have provided cross-references to enable a reader to skim or pass over sections that seem less interesting and to return to them if they are needed later in other sections of interest. Page references for the im- portant definitions are indicated in the index. In this introductory text, I have not been able to cover every major topic in the literature on game theory, and I have not attempted to assemble a comprehensive bibliography. I have tried to exercise my best judgment in deciding which topics to emphasize, which to mention briefly, and which to omit; but any such judgment is necessarily subjec- tive and controversial, especially in a field that has been growing and changing as rapidly as game theory. For other perspectives and more references to the vast literature on game theory, the reader may consult some of the other excellent survey articles and books on game theory, which include Aumann (1987b) and Shubik (1982). A note of acknowledgment must begin with an expression of my debt to Robert Aumann, John Harsanyi, John Nash, Reinhard Selten, and Lloyd Shapley, whose writings and lectures taught and inspired all of us who have followed them into the field of game theory. I have bene- fited greatly from long conversations with Ehud Kalai and Robert Weber about game theory and, specifically, about what should be covered in a basic textbook on game theory. Discussions with Bengt Holmstrom, Paul Milgrom, and Mark Satterthwaite have also substantially influenced the development of this book. Myrna Wooders, Robert Marshall, Dov Mon- derer, Gregory Pollock, Leo Simon, Michael Chwe, Gordon Green, Akihiko Matsui, Scott Page, and Eun Soo Park read parts of the manu- script and gave many valuable comments.
null
null
null
null
Myrna Wooders, Robert Marshall, Dov Mon- derer, Gregory Pollock, Leo Simon, Michael Chwe, Gordon Green, Akihiko Matsui, Scott Page, and Eun Soo Park read parts of the manu- script and gave many valuable comments. In writing the book, I have also benefited from the advice and suggestions of Lawrence Ausubel, Raymond Deneckere, Itzhak Gilboa, Ehud Lehrer, and other colleagues in the Managerial Economics and Decision Sciences department at Northwestern University. The final manuscript was ably edited by Jodi Simpson, and was proofread by Scott Page, Joseph Riney, Ricard Torres, Guangsug Hahn, Jose Luis Ferreira, loannis Tournas, Karl Schlag, Keuk-Ryoul Yoo, Gordon Green, and Robert Lapson. This book and related research have been supported by fellowships from the John Simon Guggenheim Memorial Foundation and the Alfred P. Sloan
null
null
null
null
Preface (cid:9) xiii Foundation, and by grants from the National Science Foundation and the Dispute Resolution Research Center at Northwestern University. Last but most, I must acknowledge the steady encouragement of my wife, my children, and my parents, all of whom expressed a continual faith in a writing project that seemed to take forever. Evanston, Illinois December 1990
null
null
null
null
Game Theory
null
null
null
null
1 Decision-Theoretic Foundations 1.1 Game Theory, Rationality, and Intelligence Game theory can be defined as the study of mathematical models of conflict and cooperation between intelligent rational decision-makers. Game theory provides general mathematical techniques for analyzing situations in which two or more individuals make decisions that will influence one another's welfare. As such, game theory offers insights of fundamental importance for scholars in all branches of the social sciences, as well as for practical decision-makers. The situations that game theorists study are not merely recreational activities, as the term "game" might unfortunately suggest. "Conflict analysis" or "interactive decision theory" might be more descriptively accurate names for the subject, but the name "game theory" seems to be here to stay. Modern game theory may be said to begin with the work of Zermelo (1913), Borel (1921), von Neumann (1928), and the great seminal book of von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944). Much of the early work on game theory was done during World War II at Princeton, in the same intellectual community where many leaders of theoretical physics were also working (see Morgenstern, 1976). Viewed from a broader perspec- tive of intellectual history, this propinquity does not seem coincidental. Much of the appeal and promise of game theory is derived from its position in the mathematical foundations of the social sciences. In this century, great advances in the most fundamental and theoretical branches of the physical sciences have created a nuclear dilemma that threatens the survival of our civilization. People seem to have learned more about how to design physical systems for exploiting radioactive materials than about how to create social systems for moderating human
null
null
null
null
2 (cid:9) 1 • Decision-Theoretic Foundations behavior in conflict. Thus, it may be natural to hope that advances in the most fundamental and theoretical branches of the social sciences might be able to provide the understanding that we need to match our great advances in the physical sciences. This hope is one of the moti- vations that has led many mathematicians and social scientists to work in game theory during the past 50 years. Real proof of the power of game theory has come in recent years from a prolific development of important applications, especially in economics. Game theorists try to understand conflict and cooperation by studying quantitative models and hypothetical examples. These examples may be unrealistically simple in many respects, but this simplicity may make the fundamental issues of conflict and cooperation easier to see in these examples than in the vastly more complicated situations of real life. Of course, this is the method of analysis in any field of inquiry: to pose one's questions in the context of a simplified model in which many of the less important details of reality are ignored. Thus, even if one is never involved in a situation in which people's positions are as clearly defined as those studied by game theorists, one can still come to under- stand real competitive situations better by studying these hypothetical examples. In the language of game theory, a game refers to any social situation involving two or more individuals. The individuals involved in a game may be called the players. As stated in the definition above, there are two basic assumptions that game theorists generally make about players: they are rational and they are intelligent. Each of these adjectives is used here in a technical sense that requires some explanation. A decision-maker is rational if he makes decisions consistently in pur- suit of his own objectives. In game theory, building on the fundamental results of decision theory, we assume that each player's objective is to maximize the expected value of his own payoff, which is measured in some utility scale. The idea that a rational decision-maker should make decisions that will maximize his expected utility payoff goes back at least to Bernoulli (1738), but the modern justification of this idea is due to von Neumann and Morgenstern (1947).
null
null
null
null
The idea that a rational decision-maker should make decisions that will maximize his expected utility payoff goes back at least to Bernoulli (1738), but the modern justification of this idea is due to von Neumann and Morgenstern (1947). Using remarkably weak as- sumptions about how a rational decision-maker should behave, they showed that for any rational decision-maker there must exist some way of assigning utility numbers to the various possible outcomes that he cares about, such that he would always choose the option that maximizes
null
null
null
null
1.1 Rationality and Intelligence (cid:9) 3 his expected utility. We call this result the expected-utility maximization theorem. It should be emphasized here that the logical axioms that justify the expected-utility maximization theorem are weak consistency assump- tions. In derivations of this theorem, the key assumption is generally a sure-thing or substitution axiom that may be informally paraphrased as follows: "If a decision-maker would prefer option 1 over option 2 when event A occurs, and he would prefer option 1 over option 2 when event A does not occur, then he should prefer option 1 over option 2 even before he learns whether event A will occur or not." Such an assump- tion, together with a few technical regularity conditions, is sufficient to guarantee that there exists some utility scale such that the decision- maker always prefers the options that give the highest expected utility value. Consistent maximizing behavior can also be derived from models of evolutionary selection. In a universe where increasing disorder is a physical law, complex organisms (including human beings and, more broadly speaking, social organizations) can persist only if they behave in a way that tends to increase their probability of surviving and repro- ducing themselves. Thus, an evolutionary-selection argument suggests that individuals may tend to maximize the expected value of some measure of general survival and reproductive fitness or success (see Maynard Smith, 1982). In general, maximizing expected utility payoff is not necessarily the same as maximizing expected monetary payoff, because utility values are not necessarily measured in dollars and cents. A risk-averse individ- ual may get more incremental utility from an extra dollar when he is poor than he would get from the same dollar were he rich. This obser- vation suggests that, for many decision-makers, utility may be a nonlin- ear function of monetary worth. For example, one model that is com- monly used in decision analysis stipulates that a decision-maker's utility payoff from getting x dollars would be u(x) = 1 — e', for some number c that represents his index of risk aversion (see Pratt, 1964).
null
null
null
null
More gener- ally, the utility payoff of an individual may depend on many variables besides his own monetary worth (including even the monetary worths of other people for whom he feels some sympathy or antipathy). When there is uncertainty, expected utilities can be defined and com- puted only if all relevant uncertain events can be assigned probabilities,
null
null
null
null
4 (cid:9) 1 • Decision-Theoretic Foundations which quantitatively measure the likelihood of each event. Ramsey (1926) and Savage (1954) showed that, even where objective probabili- ties cannot be assigned to some events, a rational decision-maker should be able to assess all the subjective probability numbers that are needed to compute these expected values. In situations involving two or more decision-makers, however, a spe- cial difficulty arises in the assessment of subjective probabilities. For example, suppose that one of the factors that is unknown to some given individual 1 is the action to be chosen by some other individual 2. To assess the probability of each of individual 2's possible choices, individual 1 needs to understand 2's decision-making behavior, so 1 may try to imagine himself in 2's position. In this thought experiment, 1 may realize that 2 is trying to rationally solve a decision problem of her own and that, to do so, she must assess the probabilities of each of l's possible choices. Indeed, 1 may realize that 2 is probably trying to imagine herself in l's position, to figure out what 1 will do. So the rational solution to each individual's decision problem depends on the solution to the other individual's problem. Neither problem can be solved with- out understanding the solution to the other. Thus, when rational deci- sion-makers interact, their decision problems must be analyzed together, like a system of equations. Such analysis is the subject of game theory. When we analyze a game, as game theorists or social scientists, we say that a player in the game is intelligent if he knows everything that we know about the game and he can make any inferences about the situ- ation that we can make. In game theory, we generally assume that players are intelligent in this sense. Thus, if we develop a theory that describes the behavior of intelligent players in some game and we believe that this theory is correct, then we must assume that each player in the game will also understand this theory and its predictions. For an example of a theory that assumes rationality but not intelli- gence, consider price theory in economics.
null
null
null
null
For an example of a theory that assumes rationality but not intelli- gence, consider price theory in economics. In the general equilibrium model of price theory, it is assumed that every individual is a rational utility-maximizing decision-maker, but it is not assumed that individuals understand the whole structure of the economic model that the price theorist is studying. In price-theoretic models, individuals only perceive and respond to some intermediating price signals, and each individual is supposed to believe that he can trade arbitrary amounts at these prices, even though there may not be anyone in the economy actually willing to make such trades with him.
null
null
null
null
1.2 • Basic Concepts (cid:9) 5 Of course, the assumption that all individuals are perfectly rational and intelligent may never be satisfied in any real-life situation. On the other hand, we should be suspicious of theories and predictions that are not consistent with this assumption. If a theory predicts that some individuals will be systematically fooled or led into making costly mis- takes, then this theory will tend to lose its validity when these individuals learn (from experience or from a published version of the theory itself ) to better understand the situation. The importance of game theory in the social sciences is largely derived from this fact. 1.2 Basic Concepts of Decision Theory The logical roots of game theory are in Bayesian decision theory. In- deed, game theory can be viewed as an extension of decision theory (to the case of two or more decision-makers), or as its essential logical fulfillment. Thus, to understand the fundamental ideas of game theory, one should begin by studying decision theory. The rest of this chapter is devoted to an introduction to the basic ideas of Bayesian decision theory, beginning with a general derivation of the expected utility max- imization theorem and related results. At some point, anyone who is interested in the mathematical social sciences should ask the question, Why should I expect that any simple quantitative model can give a reasonable description of people's behav- ior? The fundamental results of decision theory directly address this question, by showing that any decision-maker who satisfies certain in- tuitive axioms should always behave so as to maximize the mathematical expected value of some utility function, with respect to some subjective probability distribution. That is, any rational decision-maker's behavior should be describable by a utility function, which gives a quantitative characterization of his preferences for outcomes or prizes, and a subjec- tive probability distribution, which characterizes his beliefs about all rele- vant unknown factors. Furthermore, when new information becomes available to such a decision-maker, his subjective probabilities should be revised in accordance with Bayes's formula. There is a vast literature on axiomatic derivations of the subjective probability, expected-utility maximization, and Bayes's formula, begin- ning with Ramsey (1926), von Neumann and Morgenstern (1947), and Savage (1954).
null
null
null
null
There is a vast literature on axiomatic derivations of the subjective probability, expected-utility maximization, and Bayes's formula, begin- ning with Ramsey (1926), von Neumann and Morgenstern (1947), and Savage (1954). Other notable derivations of these results have been offered by Herstein and Milnor (1953), Luce and Raiffa (1957), An-
null
null
null
null
6 (cid:9) 1 • Decision-Theoretic Foundations scombe and Aumann (1963), and Pratt, Raiffa, and Schlaiffer (1964); for a general overview, see Fishburn (1968). The axioms used here are mainly borrowed from these earlier papers in the literature, and no attempt is made to achieve a logically minimal set of axioms. (In fact, a number of axioms presented in Section 1.3 are clearly redundant.) Decisions under uncertainty are commonly described by one of two models: a probability model or a state-variable model. In each case, we speak of the decision-maker as choosing among lotteries, but the two models differ in how a lottery is defined. In a probability model, lotteries are probability distributions over a set of prizes. In a state-variable model, lotteries are functions from a set of possible states into a set of prizes. Each of these models is most appropriate for a specific class of appli- cations. A probability model is appropriate for describing gambles in which the prizes will depend on events that have obvious objective probabili- ties; we refer to such events as objective unknowns. These gambles are the "roulette lotteries" of Anscombe and Aumann (1963) or the "risks" of Knight (1921). For example, gambles that depend on the toss of a fair coin, the spin of a roulette wheel, or the blind draw of a ball out of an urn containing a known population of identically sized but dif- ferently colored balls all could be adequately described in a probability model. An important assumption being used here is that two objective unknowns with the same probability are completely equivalent for de- cision-making purposes. For example, if we describe a lottery by saying that it "offers a prize of $100 or $0, each with probability 1/2," we are assuming that it does not matter whether the prize is determined by tossing a fair coin or by drawing a ball from an urn that contains 50 white and 50 black balls. On the other hand, many events do not have obvious probabilities; the result of a future sports event or the future course of the stock market are good examples.
null
null
null
null
On the other hand, many events do not have obvious probabilities; the result of a future sports event or the future course of the stock market are good examples. We refer to such events as subjective un- knowns. Gambles that depend on subjective unknowns correspond to the "horse lotteries" of Anscombe and Aumann (1963) or the "uncer- tainties" of Knight (1921). They are more readily described in a state- variable model, because these models allow us to describe how the prize will be determined by the unpredictable events, without our having to specify any probabilities for these events. Here we define our lotteries to include both the probability and the state-variable models as special cases. That is, we study lotteries in which
null
null
null
null
1.2 Basic Concepts (cid:9) 7 the prize may depend on both objective unknowns (which may be di- rectly described by probabilities) and subjective unknowns (which must be described by a state variable). (In the terminology of Fishburn, 1970, we are allowing extraneous probabilities in our model.) Let us now develop some basic notation. For any finite set Z, we let A(Z) denote the set of probability distributions over the set Z. That is, (1.1) (cid:9) A(Z) = {q:Z (cid:9) RI (cid:9) yEZ q(y) = 1 and q(z) (cid:9) 0, Vz E Z}. (Following common set notation, "I" in set braces may be read as "such that.") Let X denote the set of possible prizes that the decision-maker could ultimately get. Let 11 denote the set of possible states, one of which will be the true state of the world. To simplify the mathematics, we assume that X and 11 are both finite sets. We define a lottery to be any function f that specifies a nonnegative real number f(xIt), for every prize x in X and every state t in CI, such that IxEx f(x I t) = 1 for every t in 11. Let L denote the set of all such lotteries. That is, L = {f:11 ---> A(X)}. For any state t in 11 and any lottery f in L, f(.1t) denotes the probability distribution over X designated by f in state t. That is, ./-(' I (cid:9) = (f(x t)),,Ex E A(X). Each number f(x I t) here is to be interpreted as the objective condi- tional probability of getting prize x in lottery f if t is the true state of the world. (Following common probability notation, "1" in parentheses may be interpreted here to mean "given.")
null
null
null
null
(Following common probability notation, "1" in parentheses may be interpreted here to mean "given.") For this interpretation to make sense, the state must be defined broadly enough to summarize all subjective unknowns that might influence the prize to be received. Then, once a state has been specified, only objective probabilities will remain, and an objective probability distribution over the possible prizes can be calculated for any well-defined gamble. So our formal definition of a lottery allows us to represent any gamble in which the prize may depend on both objective and subjective unknowns. A prize in our sense could be any commodity bundle or resource allocation. We are assuming that the prizes in X have been defined so that they are mutually exclusive and exhaust the possible consequences of the decision-maker's decisions. Furthermore, we assume that each
null
null
null
null
• • 8 (cid:9) 1 Decision-Theoretic Foundations prize in X represents a complete specification of all aspects that the decision-maker cares about in the situation resulting from his decisions. Thus, the decision-maker should be able to assess a preference ordering over the set of lotteries, given any information that he might have about the state of the world. The information that the decision-maker might have about the true state of the world can be described by an event, which is a nonempty subset of a We let El, denote the set of all such events, so that = IS I S C SZ and S 01. For any two lotteries f and g in L and any event S in (cid:9) we write f (cid:9) g iff the lottery f would be at least as desirable as g, in the opinion of the decision-maker, if he learned that the true state of the world was in the set S. (Here iff means "if and only if.") That is, f g iff the decision-maker would be willing to choose the lottery f when he has to choose between f and g and he knows only that the event S has occurred. Given this relation we define relations (>s) and (— s) so that f — s g iff f g and g f; f >, g iff f g and g f s g means that the decision-maker would be indifferent That is, f between f and g, if he had to choose between them after learning S; and f >, g means that he would strictly prefer f over g in this situation. We may write >, and — for >n, and —n, respectively. That is, when no conditioning event is mentioned, it should be assumed that we are referring to prior preferences before any states in ft are ruled out by observations.
null
null
null
null
We may write >, and — for >n, and —n, respectively. That is, when no conditioning event is mentioned, it should be assumed that we are referring to prior preferences before any states in ft are ruled out by observations. Notice the assumption here that the decision-maker would have well- defined preferences over lotteries conditionally on any possible event in a In some expositions of decision theory, a decision-maker's condi- tional preferences are derived (using Bayes's formula) from the prior preferences that he would assess before making any observations; but such derivations cannot generate rankings of lotteries conditionally on events that have prior probability 0. In game-theoretic contexts, this omission is not as innocuous as it may seem. Kreps and Wilson (1982) have shown that the characterization of a rational decision-maker's be- liefs and preferences after he observes a zero-probability event may be crucial in the analysis of a game. For any number a such that 0 5- a 5_ 1, and for any two lotteries f and g in L, of + (1 — a)g denotes the lottery in L such that
null
null
null
null
1.3 • Axioms (cid:9) 9 (af + (1 — a)g)(x1t) = af(x1t) + (1 — a)g(x1t), Vx E X, Vt E To interpret this definition, suppose that a ball is going to be drawn from an urn in which a is the proportion of black balls and 1 — a is the proportion of white balls. Suppose that if the ball is black then the decision-maker will get to play lottery f and if the ball is white then the decision-maker will get to play lottery g. Then the decision-maker's ultimate probability of getting prize x if t is the true state is af(x I t) + (1 — a)g(xjt). Thus, of + (1 — a)g represents the compound lottery that is built up from f and g by this random lottery-selection process. For any prize x, we let [x] denote the lottery that always gives prize x for sure. That is, for every state t, (1.2) (cid:9) [x](ylt) = 1 if y = x, [x](ylt) = 0 if y (cid:9) x. Thus, a[x] + (1 — u)[y] denotes the lottery that gives either prize x or prize y, with probabilities a and 1 — a, respectively. 1.3 Axioms Basic properties that a rational decision-maker's preferences may be expected to satisfy can be presented as a list of axioms. Unless otherwise stated, these axioms are to hold for all lotteries e, f, g, and h in L, for all events S and T in E, and for all numbers a and 13 between 0 and 1. Axioms 1.1A and 1.1B assert that preferences should always form a complete transitive order over the set of lotteries. AXIOM 1. 1A (COMPLETENESS). f g or g s f. AXIOM 1. 1B (TRANSITIVITY).
null
null
null
null
AXIOM 1. 1A (COMPLETENESS). f g or g s f. AXIOM 1. 1B (TRANSITIVITY). If f zs g and g (cid:9) h then f -?-s h. It is straightforward to check that Axiom 1.1B implies a number of other transitivity results, such as if f — s g and g — s h then f— s h; and if f >s g and g h then f>, h. Axiom 1.2 asserts that only the possible states are relevant to the decision-maker, so, given an event S, he would be indifferent between two lotteries that differ only in states outside S. AXIOM 1.2 (RELEVANCE). If f(•1 t) = g(•It) Vt E S, then f — s g. Axiom 1.3 asserts that a higher probability of getting a better lottery is always better.
null
null
null
null
10 (cid:9) 1 • Decision-Theoretic Foundations AXIOM 1.3 (MONOTONICITY). If f >s h and 0 5_ 13<a51, then of + (1 — a)h >s I3f + ( 1 — (3)h. Building on Axiom 1.3, Axiom 1.4 asserts that -yf + (1 — y)h gets better in a continuous manner as y increases, so any lottery that is ranked between f and h is just as good as some randomization between f and h. AXIOM 1.4 (CONTINUITY). If f (cid:9) some number y such that 0 -y s 1 and g — s -yf + (1 — -y)h. g and g (cid:9) h, then there exists The substitution axioms (also known as independence or sure-thing axioms) are probably the most important in our system, in the sense that they generate strong restrictions on what the decision-maker's pref- erences must look like even without the other axioms. They should also be very intuitive axioms. They express the idea that, if the decision- maker must choose between two alternatives and if there are two mu- tually exclusive events, one of which must occur, such that in each event he would prefer the first alternative, then he must prefer the first alternative before he learns which event occurs. (Otherwise, he would be expressing a preference that he would be sure to want to reverse after learning which of these events was true!) In Axioms 1.5A and 1.5B, these events are objective randomizations in a random lottery- selection process, as discussed in the preceding section. In Axioms 1.6A and 1.6B, these events are subjective unknowns, subsets of f/. AXIOM 1.5A (OBJECTIVE SUBSTITUTION).
null
null
null
null
In Axioms 1.6A and 1.6B, these events are subjective unknowns, subsets of f/. AXIOM 1.5A (OBJECTIVE SUBSTITUTION). If e f and g >s h and 0 s a (cid:9) 1, then ae + (1 — a)g (cid:9) of + (1 — a)h. AXIOM 1.5B (STRICT OBJECTIVE SUBSTITUTION). If e >s f h and 0 < a 5_ 1, then ae + (1 — a)g >s of + (1 — a)h. and g (cid:9) AXIOM 1.6A (SUBJECTIVE SUBSTITUTION). If f g and f g and S fl T = 0, then f' suT g. AXIOM 1.6B (STRICT SUBJECTIVE SUBSTITUTION). If f >s g and f >T g and S fl T = 0, then f >suT g.
null
null
null
null
1.3 Axioms (cid:9) 11 To fully appreciate the importance of the substitution axioms, we may find it helpful to consider the difficulties that arise in decision theory when we try to drop them. For a simple example, suppose an individual would prefer x over y, but he would also prefer .5[y]+ .5[z] over .5[x] + .5[z], in violation of substitution. Suppose that w is some other prize that he would consider better than .5[x] + .5[z] and worse than .5[y] + .5[z]. That is, x > y but .5[y] + .5[z] > [w] > .5[x] + .5[z]. Now consider the following situation. The decision-maker must first decide whether to take prize w or not. If he does not take prize w, then a coin will be tossed. If it comes up Heads, then he will get prize z; and if it comes up Tails, then he will get a choice between prizes x and y. What should this decision-maker do? He has three possible decision- making strategies: (1) take w, (2) refuse w and take x if Tails, (3) refuse w and take y if Tails. If he follows the first strategy, then he gets the lottery [w]; if he follows the second, then he gets the lottery .5[x] + .5[z]; and if he follows the third, then he gets the lottery .5[y] + .5[z]. Because he likes .5[y] + .5[z] best among these lotteries, the third strategy would be best for him, so it may seem that he should refuse w. However, if he refuses w and the coin comes up Tails, then his pref- erences stipulate that he should choose x instead of y. So if he refuses w, then he will actually end up with z if Heads or x if Tails. But this lottery .5[x] + .5[z] is worse than w. So we get the contradictory conclu- sion that he should have taken w in the first place.
null
null
null
null
But this lottery .5[x] + .5[z] is worse than w. So we get the contradictory conclu- sion that he should have taken w in the first place. Thus, if we are to talk about "rational" decision-making without sub- stitution axioms, then we must specify whether rational decision-makers are able to commit themselves to follow strategies that they would sub- sequently want to change (in which case "rational" behavior would lead to .5[y] + .5[z] in this example). If they cannot make such commitments, then we must also specify whether they can foresee their future incon- stancy (in which case the outcome of this example should be [w]) or not (in which case the outcome of this example should be .5[x]+ .5[z]). If none of these assumptions seem reasonable, then to avoid this dilemma we must accept substitution axioms as a part of our definition of ration- ality. Axiom 1.7 asserts that the decision-maker is never indifferent between all prizes. This axiom is just a regularity condition, to make sure that there is something of interest that could happen in each state.
null
null
null
null
12 (cid:9) 1 Decision-Theoretic Foundations AXIOM 1.7 (INTEREST). For every state t in S2, there exist prizes y and z in X such that [y] >m [z]. Axiom 1.8 is optional in our analysis, in the sense that we can state a version of our main result with or without this axiom. It asserts that the decision-maker has the same preference ordering over objective gam- bles in all states of' the world. If this axiom fails, it is because the same prize might be valued differently in different states. AXIOM 1.8 (STATE NEUTRALITY). For any two states r and t in ft if f(lr) = f(.It) and g(.Ir) = g(.1t) and f Z'{r} g, then f (cid:9) g. 1.4 The Expected-Utility Maximization Theorem A conditional-probability function on 11 is any function p:!, ---> A(I),) that specifies nonnegative conditional probabilities p(tIS) for every state t in f2 and every event S, such that p(tIS) = 0 if t 0 S, and (cid:9) Nrls) = 1. rES Given any such conditional-probability function, we may write p(RIS) = (cid:9) p(rIs), VR C SZ, VS ( E. >ER A utility function can be any function from X x 11 into the real numbers R. A utility function u:X x SZ —> R is state independent iff it does not actually depend on the state, so there exists some function U:X —> R such that u(x4) = U(x) for all x and t. Given any such conditional-probability function p and any utility func- tion u and given any lottery f in L and any event S in we let E p(u( f )IS) denote the expected utility value of the prize determined by f, when p(.IS) is the probability distribution for the true state of the world.
null
null
null
null
That is, E p(u( f )1 S) =- (cid:9) p(tIS) (cid:9) u(x,t)f(x1t). THEOREM 1.1. Axioms I.1AB, 1.2, 1.3, 1.4, 1.5AB, 1.6AB, and 1.7 are jointly satisfied if and only if there exists a utility function u:X X SI —) R and a conditional-probability function A(1-1) such that
null
null
null
null
1.4 • Expected-Utility Maximization Theorem (cid:9) 13 (1.3) (cid:9) (1.4) (cid:9) max u(x,t) = 1 and min u(x,t) = 0, bit E sEX (cid:9) xEX p(R1T) = p(Rjs)p(siT), VR, VS, and VT such that RCSCTCfland SOO; (1.5) (cid:9) f (cid:9) g if and only if E p(u( f )IS) (cid:9) E p(u(g)IS), Vf,g E L, VS E Furthermore, given these Axioms 1.1AB-1.7, Axiom 1.8 is also satisfied if and only if conditions (1.3)—(1.5) here can be satisfied with a state-independent utility function. In this theorem, condition (1.3) is a normalization condition, asserting that we can choose our utility functions to range between 0 and 1 in every state. (Recall that X and Cl are assumed to be finite.) Condition (1.4) is a version of Bayes's formula, which establishes how conditional probabilities assessed in one event must be related to conditional prob- abilities assessed in another. The most important part of the theorem is condition (1.5), however, which asserts that the decision-maker always prefers lotteries with higher expected utility. By condition (1.5), once we have assessed u and p, we can predict the decision-maker's optimal choice in any decision-making situation. He will choose the lottery with the highest expected utility among those available to him, using his subjective probabilities conditioned on whatever event in Cl he has ob- served. Notice that, with X and Cl finite, there are only finitely many utility and probability numbers to assess. Thus, the decision-maker's preferences over all of the infinitely many lotteries in L can be com- pletely characterized by finitely many numbers.
null
null
null
null
Notice that, with X and Cl finite, there are only finitely many utility and probability numbers to assess. Thus, the decision-maker's preferences over all of the infinitely many lotteries in L can be com- pletely characterized by finitely many numbers. To apply this result in practice, we need a procedure for assessing the utilities u(x,t) and the probabilities p(t1s), for all x, t, and S. As Raiffa (1968) has emphasized, such procedures do exist, and they form the basis of practical decision analysis. To define one such assessment pro- cedure, and to prove Theorem 1.1, we begin by defining some special lotteries, using the assumption that the decision-maker's preferences satisfy Axioms 1.1AB-1.7. Let a, be a lottery that gives the decision-maker one of the best prizes in every state; and let ao be a lottery that gives him one of the worst prizes in every state. That is, for every state t, a1(y1t) = 1 = ao(z1t) for some prizes y and z such that, for every x in X, y x z. Such best
null
null
null
null
14 (cid:9) 1 • Decision-Theoretic Foundations and worst prizes can be found in every state because the preference relation (....{,}) forms a transitive ordering over the finite set X. For any event S in E•„ let bs denote the lottery such that bs(.1t) = a,(.1t) if t E S, b5(.1t) = a„(•1t) if t 0 S. That is, bs is a "bet on S" that gives the best possible prize if S occurs and gives the worst possible prize otherwise. For any prize x and any state t, let c„,, be the lottery such that r) = [x](. I r) if r = t, c,,,(• I r) = ao • I r) if r (cid:9) t. That is, co is the lottery that always gives the worst prize, except in state t, when it gives prize x. We can now define a procedure to assess the utilities and probabilities that satisfy the theorem, given preferences that satisfy the axioms. For each x and t, first ask the decision-maker, "For what number 13 would you be indifferent between [x] and Ba, + (1 — 13)a, if you knew that t was the true state of the world?" By the continuity axiom, such a number must exist. Then let u(x,t) equal the number that he specifies, such that [x] —{,} u(x,t)a, + (1 — u(x,t))ao. For each t and 5, ask the decision-maker, "For what number y would you be indifferent between b{,} and ya, + (1 — y)ao if you knew that the true state was in S?" Again, such a number must exist, by the continuity axiom. (The subjective substitution axiom guarantees that b{1} ?s a0.) Then let p(tls) equal the number that he specifies, such a, that b{,} (cid:9) p(tIS)a, + (1 — p(t1S))ao.
null
null
null
null
Then let p(tls) equal the number that he specifies, such a, that b{,} (cid:9) p(tIS)a, + (1 — p(t1S))ao. In the proof of Theorem 1.1, we show that defining u and p in this way does satisfy the conditions of the theorem. Thus, finitely many questions suffice to assess the probabilities and utilities that completely character- ize the decision-maker's preferences. Proof of Theorem 1.1. Let p and u be as constructed above. First, we derive condition ( 1.5) from the axioms. The relevance axiom and the definition of u(x,t) implies that, for every state r,
null
null
null
null
1.4 .Expected-Utility Maximization Theorem (cid:9) 15 u(x,t)b{, } + (1 - u(x,t))ao. Then subjective substitution implies that, for every event S, s u(x,t)b{,} + (1 - u(x,t))ao. Axioms 1.5A and 1.5B together imply that f (cid:9) g if and only if ( 1 (cid:9) i ) f + (1 1 (cid:9) 1,—(1-1 ) ao (cid:9) 1 (cid:9) (4-1-1 ) g + (1 - 47) %. 1 (Here, 111,1 denotes the number of states in the set SZ.) Notice that 1 (cid:9) (pi)f + (1 (cid:9) 1 (cid:9) ao = (TO /51 xx f(xl 1 But, by repeated application of the objective substitution axiom, ( (cid:9) ( I (cid:9) s , (cid:9) %-s (cid:9) 'Ell xEX f(X10kU(X,t)b{ t} + (1 — U(X,Oad Efix10(24x,o(p(tis)a, ,E xEX + (1 — p(tIS))aO ) + ( 1 - u(x,t))ao) (1+1-i) (cid:9) f(xl t)u(x,t)p(t I S)a, 1 - E E f(xjou(x,00ls)/Ifil)ao + ( tES1 xEX = (Ep(U(PIS)/10ai + (1 (cid:9) (Ep(U(f)1S)/11/1))a0• Similarly, (1/InOg + (1 - (1/111j))ao -s (Ep(u(g)IS)/Ifil)a l + (1 - (Ep(u(g)15')/Ifil))ao• Thus, by transitivity, f (cid:9) g if and only if
null
null
null
null
16 (cid:9) 1 • Decision-Theoretic Foundations (Ep(u(f )1 S)/1,111)a, + (1 — (Ep(u(f )1S)/IniDao (Ei (it(g)1S)/ini)a l + (1 — (Ep(u(g)IS)/ini))ao• But by monotonicity, this final relation holds if and only if E p(u(f)1S) (cid:9) E p(u(g)IS), because interest and strict subjective substitution guarantee that a, >5 ao. Thus, condition (1.5) is satisfied. Next, we derive condition (1.4) from the axioms. For any events R and S, (IRS) bR (cid:9) (1 (cid:9) E RI) 'ER (I (cid:9) b{,} a° (cid:9) (p(ds)a, + (1 — p(ris))a) (IR' I)E ,ER = ( )(P(R1s)a, + (1 — P(RiS))ao) (cid:9) I R ' ( 1 IR' I a' by objective substitution. Ri is the number of states in the set R.) Then, using Axioms 1.5A and 1.5B, we get b, s p(RIS)a, + (1 — p(RIS))ao. By the relevance axiom, bs —, a, and, for any r not in S, (cid:9) — 5 a,. So the above formula implies (using monotonicity and interest) that p(riS) = 0 if r S, and p(sls) = 1. Thus, p is a conditional-probability function, as defined above. Now, suppose that R CSC T. Using b, — s a, again, we get b„ (cid:9) p(RIS)b, + (1 — p(RIS))ao.
null
null
null
null
Now, suppose that R CSC T. Using b, — s a, again, we get b„ (cid:9) p(RIS)b, + (1 — p(RIS))ao. Furthermore, because b„, bs, and a, all give the same worst prize outside 5, relevance also implies b„ --r\s p(Ris)b, + (1 — p(RIS))ao. (Here T\S = {ti t E T, t 0 S}.) So, by subjective and objective substitution, bR T P(R I WS + ( 1 — P(R I S))aO p(R1s)(p(sIT)a, + (1 — p(siT))ao) + (1 — p(RIS))a() = p(RIS)p(SIT)a, + (1 — p(Ris)p(siT))ao. (cid:9)
null
null
null
null
1.4 • Expected-Utility Maximization Theorem (cid:9) 17 p(RIT)a, + (1 — p(RiT))ao. Also, a, >7- a0, so monotonicity But b, (cid:9) implies that p(R1T) = p(Ris)p(sIT). Thus, Bayes's formula (1.4) follows from the axioms. If y is the best prize and z is the worst prize in state t, then [y] {t} a, and [z] a,), so that u(y,t) = 1 and u(z,t) = 0 by monotonicity. So the range condition (1.3) is also satisfied by the utility function that we have constructed. If state neutrality is also given, then the decision-maker will give us the same answer when we assess u(x,t) as when we assess u(x,r) for any other state r (because [x] —{,} Pa, + (1 — (3)a, implies [x] pa, + (1 — p)a(), and monotonicity and interest guarantee that his answer is unique). So Axiom 1.8 implies that u is state-independent. To complete the proof of the theorem, it remains to show that the existence of functions u and p that satisfy conditions (1.3)—(1.5) in the theorem is sufficient to imply all the axioms (using state independence only for Axiom 1.8). If we use the basic mathematical properties of the expected-utility formula, verification of the axioms is straightforward. To illustrate, we show the proof of one axiom, subjective substitution, and leave the rest as an exercise for the reader. Suppose that f (cid:9) g and f (cid:9) E p(u(g)1S) and E p(u( f )IT) (cid:9) g and S fl T = 0. By (1.5), E p(u(f)IS) E p(u(g)IT).
null
null
null
null
By (1.5), E p(u(f)IS) E p(u(g)IT). But Bayes's formula (1.4) implies that Ep(u(f)1S U T) = p(tis U T)f(x1t)u(x,t) r = E E p(ths)p(sis U T)f(x1t)u(x,t) /ES vEX + (cid:9) E POI nP(TIs U T)f(xlt)u(x,t) 1E7' vEX = p(SIS U T)E p(u( f )1 S) + pals U T)E p(u( f )1S) and Ep(u(g)1S U T) = p(SIS U T)Ep(u(g)IS) + pals U T)E p(u(g)IS). So Ep(u(f)IS U T) Ep(u(g)IS U T) and f z.sur g. •
null
null
null
null
18 (cid:9) 1 Decision-Theoretic Foundations 1.5 Equivalent Representations When we drop the range condition (1.3), there can be more than one pair of utility and conditional-probability functions that represent the same decision-maker's preferences, in the sense of condition (1.5). Such equivalent representations are completely indistinguishable in terms of their decision-theoretic properties, so we should be suspicious of any theory of economic behavior that requires distinguishing between such equivalent representations. Thus, it may be theoretically important to be able to recognize such equivalent representations. Given any subjective event S, when we say that a utility function v and a conditional-probability function q represent the preference order- ing we mean that, for every pair of lotteries f and g, Eq(v(f)IS) Eq(v(g)IS) if and only if f (cid:9) g. THEOREM 1.2. Let S in EI be any given subjective event. Suppose that the decision-maker's preferences satisfy Axioms 1.1AB through 1.7, and let u and p be utility and conditional-probability functions satisfying (1.3)—(1.5) in Theorem 1.1. Then v and q represent the preference ordering >s if and only if there exists a positive number A and a function B:S —> R such that q(tIS)v(x,t) = Ap(tIS)u(x,t) + B(t), Vt E S, Nix E X. Proof. Suppose first that A and 13(•) exist as described in the theorem.
null
null
null
null
Suppose first that A and 13(•) exist as described in the theorem. Then, for any lottery f, E q(v( f )1 S) (cid:9) f(xlt)q(tIS)v(x,t) IES xEX = (cid:9) E focloop(o)u(x,t) + B(0) IES xEX = AEIf(Xlop(tis)u(x,t) + (cid:9) B(t) (cid:9) foclo tES xEX (cid:9) tES (cid:9) xEX = AE p (u(f)IS) + (cid:9) B(t), because E„,„ f(x I = 1. So expected v-utility with respect to q is an increasing linear function of expected u-utility with respect to p, because A > 0. Thus, Ea(v(f)IS) (cid:9) Ep(u(g)IS), and so v and q together represent the same preference ordering over lotteries as u and p. Eg(v(g)IS) if and only if Ep(u(f)IS)
null
null
null
null
1.5 • Equivalent Representations (cid:9) 19 Conversely, suppose now that v and q represent the same preference ordering as u and p. Pick any prize x and state t, and let X = E q(v(cx t)I S) — E q(v(ao)IS) ' E q(v (a 1) I S) — E q(v(ao)I S) Then, by the linearity of the expected -value operator, Eq(v(ka, + (1 — X)a,) I S) = E q(v(a0)1 S) + X(E q(v(a 01 S) — E q(v(a0)1 S)) = E q(v(c ,t)I S) , so cx,, —, Xa, + (1 — X.)a,. In the proof of Theorem 1.1, we constructed u and p so that c„,, - - s u(x ,t)b{,} + (1 — u(x ,t))ao —s u(x,t)(P(ti S)al + (1 — P(tIS))a,) + (1 — u(x ,t))ao —s POI S)u(x ,t)c t 1 + (1 — p(t1s)u(x,t))ao. The monotonicity axiom guarantees that only one randomization be- tween a, and a, can be just as good as c„,„ so X = p(t1s)u(x,t). But c,, differs from a, only in state t, where it gives prize x instead of the worst prize, so Eq(v(c„,)1 5) — Eq(v(ao) I S) = q(t I S) (v(x a) — min v(z,t)) .
null
null
null
null
zEX Thus, going back to the definition of X, we get p(tis)u(x,t) .--- q(t I S)(v(x a) — min v(z,t)) zEX E q(v(a 1)1 S) — E q(v(a0)I S) Now let A = E q(v (a 01 S) — E q(v (601 S) , and let B(t)' = q(tI S) min v(z,t). zEX
null
null
null
null
20 (cid:9) 1 • Decision-Theoretic Foundations Then Ap(tIS)u(x,t) + B(t) = q(tIS)v(x,t). Notice that A is independent of x and t and that B(t) is independent of x. In addition, A > 0, because a, >s a, implies Eq(v(a,)IS) > E ,(v (a 0)1S). n It is easy to see from Theorem 1.2 that more than one probability distribution can represent the decision-maker's beliefs given some event S. In fact, we can make the probability distribution q(• IS) almost any- thing and still satisfy the equation in Theorem 1.2, as long as we make reciprocal changes in v, to keep the left-hand side of the equation the same. The way to eliminate this indeterminacy is to assume Axiom 1.8 and require utility functions to be state independent. THEOREM 1.3. Let S in 5, be any given subjective event. Suppose that the decision-maker's preferences satisfy Axioms 1.IAB through 1.8, and let u and p be the state-independent utility function and the conditional-probability function, respectively, that satisfy conditions (1.3)—(1.5) in Theorem 1.1. Let v be a state- independent utility function, let q be a conditional-probability function, and suppose that v and q represent the preference ordering Then q(11S) = (cid:9) Vt E S, and there exist numbers A and C such that A > 0 and v(x) = Au(x) + C, Vx E X. (For simplicity, we can write v(x) and u(x) here, instead of v(x,t) and u(x,t), because both functions are state independent.) Proof. Let A = ,(v(a S) — from the proof of Theorem 1.2, q(v(ao) I S), and let C = minzExv(z).
null
null
null
null
Proof. Let A = ,(v(a S) — from the proof of Theorem 1.2, q(v(ao) I S), and let C = minzExv(z). Then, Ap(t1S)u(x) + q(tIS)C = q(tIS)v(x), Vx E X, Vt E S. Summing this equation over all t in S, we get Au(x) + C = v(x). Then, substituting this equation back, and letting x be the best prize so u(x) = 1, we get Ap(o) + q(tIS)C = Aq(t1S) + q(tIS)C. Because A > 0, we get p(tis) = q(tIS). n
null
null
null
null
1.6 • Bayesian Conditional-Probability Systems (cid:9) 21 1.6 Bayesian Conditional-Probability Systems We define a Bayesian conditional-probability system (or simply a conditional- probability system) on the finite set f2 to be any conditional-probability function p on SI that satisfies condition (1.4) (Bayes's formula). That is, if p is a Bayesian conditional-probability system on 12, then, for every S that is a nonempty subset of SI, p(.Is) is a probability distribution over ,i/ such that p(sIs) = 1 and p(RIT) = p(Rls)p(sIT), VR C S, VT D S. We let L1*(0) denote the set of all Bayesian conditional-probability sys- tems on Cl. For any finite set Z, we let A°(Z) denote the set of all probability distributions on Z that assign positive probability to every element in Z, so (1.6) (cid:9) AV) = {q E A(Z)lq(z) > 0, Vz E Z}. Any probability distribution fi in A°(.11) generates a conditional-proba- bility system p in A*(a) by the formula p(tIs) — p if t E S, P (r) rES p(tIs) = 0 if t (cid:9) S. The conditional-probability systems that can be generated in this way from distributions in A°(C2) do not include all of 0*(f2), but any other Bayesian conditional-probability system in A*(f2) can be expressed as the limit of conditional-probability systems generated in this way. This fact is asserted by the following theorem. For the proof, see Myerson (1986b). THEOREM 1 . 4 .
null
null
null
null
This fact is asserted by the following theorem. For the proof, see Myerson (1986b). THEOREM 1 . 4 . The probability function p is a Bayesian conditional-prob- ability system in if and only if there exists a sequence of probability distributions {fik },7_, in A°(S2) such that, for every nonempty subset S of Cl and every t in Cl, *(Cl) A fik(t) PO's) = lim E fik(r) if t E S, rES p(tIs) = 0 if tlf S.
null
null
null
null
22 (cid:9) 1 Decision-Theoretic Foundations 1.7 Limitations of the Bayesian Model We have seen how expected-utility maximization can be derived from axioms that seem intuitively plausible as a characterization of rational preferences. Because of this result, mathematical social scientists have felt confident that mathematical models of human behavior that are based on expected-utility maximization should have a wide applicability and relevance. This book is largely motivated by such confidence. It is important to try to understand the range of applicability of expected-utility maximization in real decision-making. In considering this question, we must remember that any model of decision-making can be used either descriptively or prescriptively. That is, we may use a model to try to describe and predict what people will do, or we may use a model as a guide to apply to our own (or our clients') decisions. The predictive validity of a model can be tested by experimental or empirical data. The prescriptive validity of a decision model is rather harder to test; one can only ask whether a person who understands the model would feel that he would be making a mistake if he did not make decisions according to the model. Theorem 1.1, which derives expected-utility maximization from in- tuitive axioms, is a proof of the prescriptive validity of expected-utility maximization, if any such proof is possible. Although other models of decision-making have been proposed, few have been able to challenge the logical appeal of expected-utility maximization for prescriptive pur- poses. There is, of course, a close relationship between the prescriptive and predictive roles of any decision-making model. If a model is prescrip- tively valid for a decision-maker, then he diverges from the model only when he is making a mistake. People do make mistakes, but they try not to. When a person has had sufficient time to learn about a situation and think clearly about it, we can expect that he will make relatively few mistakes. Thus, we can expect expected-utility maximization to be predictively accurate in many situations.
null
null
null
null
When a person has had sufficient time to learn about a situation and think clearly about it, we can expect that he will make relatively few mistakes. Thus, we can expect expected-utility maximization to be predictively accurate in many situations. However, experimental research on decision-making has revealed some systematic violations of expected-utility maximization (see Allais and Hagen, 1979; Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; and Kahneman, Slovic, and Tversky, 1982). This research has led to suggestions of new models of decision-making that may have greater descriptive accuracy (see Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; and Machina, 1982). We discuss
null
null
null
null
1.7 • Limitations of the Bayesian Model (cid:9) 23 here three of the best-known examples in which people often seem to violate expected-utility maximization: one in which utility functions seem inapplicable, one in which subjective probability seems inapplica- ble, and one in which any economic model seems inapplicable. Consider first a famous paradox, due to M. Allais (see Allais and Hagen, 1979). Let X = {$12 million, $1 million, $0}, and let = .10[$12 million] + .90[$0], f2 = .11[$1 million] + .89[$0], f3 = [$1 million], f, = .10[$12 million] + .89[$1 million] + .01[$0]. Many people will express the preferences f, > f2 and f3 > f4. (Recall that no subscript on > means that we are conditioning on D..) Such people may feel that $12 million is substantially better than $1 million, so the slightly higher probability of winning in f2 compared with f, is not worth the lower prize. On the other hand, they would prefer to take the sure $1 million in f3, rather than accept a probability .01 of getting nothing in exchange for a probability .10 of increasing the prize to $12 million in f,. Such preferences cannot be accounted for by any utility function. To prove this, notice that .5f, + .5f3 = .05[$12 million] + .5[$1 million] + .45[$0] = .5f2 Thus, the common preferences f, > f2 and f3 > f4 must violate the strict objective substitution axiom. Other paradoxes have been generated that challenge the role of subjective probability in decision theory, starting with a classic paper by Ellsberg (1961).
null
null
null
null
Other paradoxes have been generated that challenge the role of subjective probability in decision theory, starting with a classic paper by Ellsberg (1961). For a simple example of this kind, due to Raiffa (1968), let X = {—$100,$100}, let SZ = {A,N}, and let bA($1001A) = 1 = bA(—$1001N), b,(—$1001A) = 1 = bN($100IN). That is, bA is a $100 bet in which the decision-maker wins if A occurs, and bN is a $100 bet in which the decision-maker wins if N occurs. Suppose that A represents the state in which the American League will win the next All-Star game (in American baseball) and that N represents
null
null
null
null
24 (cid:9) 1 • Decision-Theoretic Foundations the state in which the National League will win the next All-Star game. (One of these two leagues must win the All-Star game, because the rules of baseball do not permit ties.) Many people who feel that they know almost nothing about American baseball express the preferences .5[$100] + .5[—$100] > 6, and .5[$100] + .5[ —$100] > b„,. That is, they would strictly prefer to bet $100 on Heads in a fair coin toss than to bet $100 on either league in the All- Star game. Such preferences cannot be accounted for by any subjective probability distribution over II At least one state in I/ must have prob- ability greater than or equal to .5, and the bet on the league that wins in that state must give expected utility that is at least as great as the bet on the fair coin toss. To see it another way, notice that .506, + .506, = .5[$100] + .5[—$100] = .50(.5[$100] + .5[—$100]) + .50(.5[$100] + .5[—$100]), so the common preferences expressed above must violate the strict objective substitution axiom. To illustrate the difficulty of constructing a model of decision-making that is both predictively accurate and prescriptively appealing, Kahne- man and Tversky (1982) have suggested the following example. In Situation A, you are arriving at a theatrical performance, for which you have bought a pair of tickets that cost $40. You suddenly realize that your tickets have fallen out of your pocket and are lost. You must decide whether to buy a second pair of tickets for $40 (there are some similar seats still available) or simply go home. In Situation B, you are arriving at a theatrical performance for which a pair of tickets costs $40. You did not buy tickets in advance, but you put $40 in your pocket when you left home. You suddenly realize that the $40 has fallen out of your pocket and is lost.
null
null
null
null
You did not buy tickets in advance, but you put $40 in your pocket when you left home. You suddenly realize that the $40 has fallen out of your pocket and is lost. You must decide whether to buy a pair of tickets for $40 with your charge card (which you still have) or simply go home. As Kahneman and Tversky (1982) report, most people say that they would simply go home in Situation A but would buy the tickets in Situation B. However, in each of these situations, the final outcomes resulting from the two options are, on the one hand, seeing the perfor- mance and being out $80 and, on the other hand, missing the perfor- mance and being out $40. Thus, it is impossible to account for such behavior in any economic model that assumes that the levels of monetary
null
null
null
null
1.7 • Limitations of the Bayesian Model (cid:9) 25 wealth and theatrical consumption are all that should matter to the decision-maker in these situations. Any analytical model must derive its power from simplifying assump- tions that enable us to see different situations as analytically equivalent, but such simplifying assumptions are always questionable. A model that correctly predicts the common behavior in this example must draw distinctions between situations on the basis of fine details in the order of events that have no bearing on the final outcome. Such distinctions, however, would probably decrease the normative appeal of the model if it were applied for prescriptive purposes. (What would you think of a consultant who told you that you should make a point of behaving differently in Situations A and B?) The explanatory power of expected-utility maximization can be ex- tended to explain many of its apparent contradictions by the analysis of salient perturbations. A perturbation of a given decision problem is any other decision problem that is very similar to it (in some sense). For any given decision problem, we say that a perturbation is salient if people who actually face the given decision problem are likely to act as if they think that they are in this perturbation. A particular perturbation of a decision problem may be salient when people find the decision problem to be hard to understand and the perturbation is more like the kind of situations that they commonly experience. If we can predict the salient perturbation of an individual's decision problem, then the decision that maximizes his expected utility in this salient perturbation may be a more accurate prediction of his behavior. For example, let us reconsider the problem of betting on the All-Star game.
null
null
null
null
For example, let us reconsider the problem of betting on the All-Star game. To get a decision-maker to express his preference ordering (.--11) over fb,, 6,, .5[$100] + .5[—$100]}, we must ask him, for each pair in this set, which bet would he choose if this pair of bet-options were offered to him uninformatively, that is, in a manner that does not give him any new information about the true state in I. That is, when we ask him whether he would prefer to bet $100 on the American League or on a fair coin toss, we are assuming that the mere fact of offering this option to him does not change his information about the All-Star game. However, people usually offer to make bets only when they have some special information or beliefs. Thus, when someone who knows little about baseball gets an offer from another person to bet on the American League, it is usually because the other person has information suggesting that the American League is likely to lose. In such situations,
null
null
null
null
26 (cid:9) 1 Decision-Theoretic Foundations an opportunity to bet on one side of the All-Star game should (by Bayes's formula) make someone who knows little about baseball decrease his subjective probability of the event that this side will win, so he may well prefer to bet on a fair coin toss. We can try to offer bets uninformatively in controlled experiments, and we can even tell our experimental sub- jects that the bets are being offered uninformatively, but this is so unnatural that the experimental subjects may instead respond to the salient perturbation in which we would only offer baseball bets that we expected the subject to lose. 1.8 Domination Sometimes decision-makers find subjective probabilities difficult to as- sess. There are fundamental theoretical reasons why this should be particularly true in games. In a game situation, the unknown environ- ment or "state of the world" that confronts a decision-maker may in- clude the outcome of decisions that are to be made by other people. Thus, to assess his subjective probability distribution over this state space, the decision-maker must think about everything that he knows about other people's decision-making processes. To the extent that these other people are concerned about his own decisions, his beliefs about their behavior may be based at least in part on his beliefs about what they believe that he will do himself. So assessing subjective probabilities about others' behavior may require some understanding of the pre- dicted outcome of his own decision-making process, part of which is his probability assessment itself. The resolution of this seeming paradox is the subject of game theory, to be developed in the subsequent chapters of this book. Sometimes, however, it is possible to say that some decision-options could not possibly be optimal for a decision-maker, no matter what his beliefs may be. In this section, before turning from decision theory to game theory, we develop some basic results to show when such proba- bility-independent statements can be made. Consider a decision-maker who has a state-dependent utility function u:X x SZ --> R and can choose any x in X. That is, let us reinterpret X as the set of decision-options available to the decision-maker.
null
null
null
null
Consider a decision-maker who has a state-dependent utility function u:X x SZ --> R and can choose any x in X. That is, let us reinterpret X as the set of decision-options available to the decision-maker. If his subjective probability of each state t in Si were p(t) (that is, p(t) = 0111), Vt E 14), then the decision-maker would choose some particular y in X only if
null
null
null
null
1.8 Domination (cid:9) 27 (1.7) (cid:9) E p(t)u(y,t) (cid:9) E p(t)u(x,t), vx E X. (En (cid:9) tEO Convexity is an important property of many sets that arise in math- ematical economics. A set of vectors is convex iff, for any two vectors p and q and any number X between 0 and 1, if p is in the set and q is in the set then the vector Xp + (1 — X)q must also be in the set. Geomet- rically, convexity means that, for any two points in the set, the whole line segment between them must also be contained in the set. THEOREM 1.5. Given u:X X (cid:9) in A(n) such that y is optimal is convex. R and given y in X, the set of all p Proof. Suppose that y would be optimal for the decision-maker with beliefs p and q. Let X be any number between 0 and 1, and let r = Xp + (1 — X)q. Then for any x in X E r(t)u(y,t) = X E p(ou(y,t) + (1 — X) E q(t)u(y,t) tEll (cid:9) t(f2 X (cid:9) p(t)u(x,t) + (1 — X) E q(t)u(x,t) rE0 (cid:9) (En E r(t)u(x,t). tES1 So y is optimal for beliefs r. n For example, suppose X = {a,13,)/}, f = {01 ,02}, and the utility func- tion u is as shown in Table 1.1. With only two states, p(01 ) = 1 — p(02).
null
null
null
null
With only two states, p(01 ) = 1 — p(02). The decision a is optimal for the decision-maker iff the following two inequalities are both satisfied: 8p(01 ) + 1(1 — p(01 )) (cid:9) 5p(0,) + 3(1 — p(01 )) 8p(01 ) + 1(1 — p(01 )) > 4p(01 ) + 7(1 — p(01 )). Table 1.1 Expected utility payoffs for states 0, and 02 Decision a (cid:9) e, (cid:9) 8 (cid:9) 5 (cid:9) 4 (cid:9) 02 1 3 7 (cid:9)
null
null
null
null
28 (cid:9) 1 Decision-Theoretic Foundations The first of these inequalities asserts that the expected utility payoff from a must be at least as much as from p, and the second asserts that the expected utility payoff from a must be at least as much as from y. By straightforward algebra, these inequalities imply that a is optimal when p(01) 0.6. Similarly, decision y would be optimal iff 4p(01) + 7(1 — p(01 )) > 8p(01 ) + 1(1 — p(01 )) 4p(01 ) + 7(1 — P(0I)) > 5p(01) + 3(1 — PA% and these two inequalities are both satisfied when p(01) lc 0.6. Decision 13 would be optimal iff 8p(01 ) + 1(1 — p(01 )) 5p(01 ) + 3(1 — p(01 )) 5p(01) + 3(1 — p(01)) > 4p(0 1 ) + 7(1 — p(0,)), but there is no value of p(0,) that satisfies both of these inequalities. Thus, each decision is optimal over some convex interval of probabili- ties, except that the interval where 13 is optimal is the empty set. Thus, even without knowing p, we can conclude that 0 cannot possibly be the optimal decision for the decision-maker. Such a decision-option that could never be optimal, for any set of beliefs, is said to be strongly dominated. Recognizing such dominated options may be helpful in the analysis of decision problems. Notice that a would be best if the decision-maker were sure that the state was 0,, and y would be best if the decision- maker were sure that the state was 02, so it is easy to check that neither a nor -y is dominated in this sense. Option 13 is a kind of intermediate decision, in that it is neither best nor worst in either column of the payoff table. However, such intermediate decision-options are not nec- essarily dominated.
null
null
null
null
Option 13 is a kind of intermediate decision, in that it is neither best nor worst in either column of the payoff table. However, such intermediate decision-options are not nec- essarily dominated. For example, if the utility payoffs from decision 13 were changed to 6 in both states, then 13 would be the optimal decision whenever 5/7 p(01 ) 1/3. On the other hand, if the payoffs from decision 13 were changed to 3 in both states, then it would be obvious that 13 could never be optimal, because choosing y would always be better than choosing 13. There is another way to see that 13 is dominated, for the original payoff table shown above. Suppose that the decision-maker considered the following randomized strategy for determining his decision: toss a coin, and choose a if it comes out Heads, and choose y if it comes out
null
null
null
null
1.8 Domination (cid:9) 29 Tails. We may denote this strategy by .5[a] + .5[y], because it gives a probability of .5 to a and -y each. If the true state were 01, then this randomized strategy would give the decision-maker an expected utility payoff of .5 x 8 + .5 x 4 = 6, which is better than the payoff of 5 that he would get from 13. (Recall that, because these payoffs are utilities, higher expected values are always more preferred by the decision- maker.) If the true state were 02, then this randomized strategy would give an expected payoff of .5 x 1 + .5 x 7 = 4, which is better than the payoff of 3 that he would get from 13. So no matter what the state may be, the expected payoff from .5[a] + .5[y] is strictly higher than the payoff from 13. Thus, we may argue that the decision-maker would be irrational to choose 13 because, whatever his beliefs about the state might be, he would get a higher expected payoff from the randomized strategy .5[a] + .5[-A than from choosing 13. We may say that 13 is strongly dominated by the randomized strategy .5[a] + .5[y]. In general, a randomized strategy is any probability distribution over the set of decision options X. We may denote such a randomized strategy in general by o- = (cr(x))xEx, where o-(x) represents the probability of choosing x. Given the utility function u:X x SZ —> R, we may say that a decision option y in X is strongly dominated by a randomized strategy o- in A(X) such that (1.8) (cid:9) xEX cr(x)u(x,t) > u(y,t), Vt E That is, y is strongly dominated by o- if, no matter what the state might be, o- would always be strictly better than y under the expected-utility criterion. We have now used the term "strongly dominated" in two different senses. The following theorem asserts that they are equivalent.
null
null
null
null
We have now used the term "strongly dominated" in two different senses. The following theorem asserts that they are equivalent. THEOREM 1.6. Given u:X x f/ —> R, where X and ft are nonempty finite sets, and given any y in X, there exists a randomized strategy o- in A(X) such that y is strongly dominated by cr, in the sense of condition (1.8), if and only if there does not exist any probability distribution p in A(11) such that y is optimal in the sense of condition (1.7). The proof is deferred to Section 1.9. Theorem 1.6 gives us our first application of the important concept of a randomized strategy. Notice, however, that this result itself does
End of preview.
YAML Metadata Warning: empty or missing yaml metadata in repo card (https://huggingface.co/docs/hub/datasets-cards)

Loading corpus from diverse_nov13/corpus/data_corpus.jsonl

CORPUS ANALYSIS REPORT

Document Statistics:

  • Total PDF documents: 31
  • Total pages: 11890
  • Pages with errors: 0
  • Empty pages: 1082
  • Pages per document:
    • Average: 383.5
    • Minimum: 2
    • Maximum: 871

Content Statistics (words per page):

  • Minimum: 1
  • Maximum: 2,524
  • Average: 397.1
  • Median: 417.0

Words per Page Distribution:

   1.0 |████████████████████████████████████              | 923
  41.4 |█████                                             | 145
  81.7 |██████                                            | 161
 122.1 |███████                                           | 179
 162.4 |█████████                                         | 244
 202.8 |██████████████                                    | 357
 243.1 |███████████████████                               | 480
 283.4 |██████████████████████                            | 558
 323.8 |████████████████████████████████████              | 905
 364.2 |██████████████████████████████████████████        | 1053
 404.5 |██████████████████████████████████████████████████| 1250
 444.9 |███████████████████████████████████████████████   | 1178
 485.2 |██████████████████████████████████                | 873
 525.6 |█████████████████████████                         | 641
 565.9 |███████████████████████                           | 588
 606.2 |████████████████████                              | 501
 646.6 |██████████                                        | 254
 687.0 |███████                                           | 199
 727.3 |████                                              | 113
 767.6 |███                                               | 97

Outliers > 808.0 words: 107 pages

Pages per Document Distribution:
   2.0 |██████████████                                    | 2
  88.9 |███████                                           | 1
 175.8 |███████████████████████████████████               | 5
 262.7 |██████████████████████████████████████████        | 6
 349.6 |██████████████████████████████████████████████████| 7
 436.5 |██████████████                                    | 2
 523.4 |████████████████████████████                      | 4
 610.3 |█████████████████████                             | 3
 697.2 |                                                  | 0
 784.1 |                                                  | 0

Metadata Statistics:

  • Documents with metadata: 31
  • Unique CreationDate values: 28
  • Unique GTS_PDFXVersion values: 1
  • Unique ModDate values: 27
  • Unique Producer values: 24
  • Unique Creator values: 16
  • Unique Author values: 14
  • Unique Title values: 16
  • Unique EBX_PUBLISHER values: 5
  • Unique Keywords values: 6
  • Unique Session Id values: 2
  • Unique Subject values: 3
  • Unique Trapped values: 1
  • Unique PTEX.Fullbanner values: 1

Document Details:

  • American Herbal Academy - The Native American Herbalism Encyclopedia - A Complete Medical Herbs Handbook_ Discover How to Find and Grow Forgotten Herbs a (2020, Herbalism Academy) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 167 Author: Academy, American Herbal Creator: calibre 3.48.0 [https://calibre-ebook.com]
  • Claude V. Palisca - Humanism in Italian Renaissance Musical Thought (1986, Yale University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 240 Creator: PFU ScanSnap Manager 4.1.12
  • David Griffiths - Introduction to elementary particles (1987, John Wiley & Sons Inc) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 403 Author: David Griffiths Creator: PdfCompressor 3.1.34
  • David Hoffmann - Medical Herbalism_ The Science and Practice of Herbal Medicine (2003, Inner Traditions _ Bear & Co) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 675
  • Dr Simon J. D. Prince - Computer Vision_ Models, Learning, and Inference (2012, Cambridge University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 582 Author: Prince, Simon J. D. Creator: LaTeX with hyperref package
  • Ellen Meiksins Wood - Liberty and Property_ A Social History of Western Political Thought from Renaissance to Enlightenment (2012, Verso Books) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 336 Author: Ellen Meiksins Wood
  • Jacob Burckhardt - The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 281 Creator: PScript5.dll Version 5.2.2
  • John Rewald - The History of Impressionism (1961, Museum of Modern Art) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 673 Author: Rewald, John, 1912-1994 Creator: Digitized by the Internet Archive
  • John Von Neumann, Oskar Morgenstern - Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (1966, Princeton University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 674
  • Michael Moore - Medicinal Plants of the Mountain West (2003, Museum of New Mexico Pr) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 368 Creator: PFU ScanSnap Manager 4.2.14
  • Otto Georg Von Simson - The Gothic Cathedral_ Origins of Gothic Architecture and the Medieval Concept of Order (1956, Harper & Row) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 177 Creator: Adobe Acrobat 9.4
  • Paul Oskar Kristeller, Thomas A. Brady, Heiko Augustinus Oberman - Itinerarium Italicum_ The Profile of the Italian Renaissance in the Mirror of Its European Transformations (Studies in Medieval (1975, Brill Academic Publishers) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 580
  • Risto Saarinen - Weakness of Will in Renaissance and Reformation Thought (2011, Oxford University Press, USA) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 257 Author: Saarinen, Risto.
  • Roger B. Myerson - Game Theory_ Analysis of Conflict (1997, Harvard University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 587 Creator: ImageToPDF
  • Samuel K. Cohn Jr. - Cultures of Plague_ Medical thought at the end of the Renaissance (2010) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 357
  • Stull, Roland B. - An Introduction to Boundary Layer Meteorology __ __ Front_matter (1988) [10.1007_978-94-009-3027-8_FM] - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 11
  • [American Journal of Physics 1997-may vol. 65 iss. 5] Weinberg, Steven - Post-Use Review. The Quantum Theory of Fields. Vol. I_ Foundations (1997) [10.1119_1.18603] - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 2
  • [Book 1 in the Surface Series] Alainna MacPherson - Beneath the Surface (2020) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 306 Author: Alainna MacPherson Creator: calibre (4.12.0) [https://calibre-ebook.com]
  • [Harvard Historical Studies (Book 98)] John Buckler - The Theban Hegemony, 371-362 BC (Harvard Historical Studies) (1980, Harvard University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 177 Author: Scan2Net Creator: BE4-SGS-V2
  • [Harvard Historical Studies, 88] Angeliki E. Laiou - Constantinople and the Latins_ The Foreign Policy of Andronicus II, 1282-1328 (Harvard Historical Studies) (1972, Harvard University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 399 Creator: Adobe Acrobat 8.0
  • [Harvard Historical Studies] Aurora Gómez-Galvarriato_ Aurora Gómez-Galvarriato - Industry and Revolution _ Social and Economic Change in the Orizaba Valley, Mexico (2013, Harvard University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 362 Author: someAuthor
  • [Harvard Historical Studies] David Paull Nickles - Under the Wire_ How the Telegraph Changed Diplomacy (Harvard Historical Studies) (2003, Harvard University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 272 Author: David Paull Nickles
  • [Harvard Historical Studies] Sarah Kinkel - Disciplining the Empire_ Politics, Governance, and the Rise of the British Navy (2018, Harvard University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 317 Author: Sarah Kinkel Creator: Adobe InDesign CC 2015 (Macintosh)
  • [Harvard Historical Studies_ 18] Albert Howe Lybyer - The Government of the Ottoman Empire in the Time of Suleiman the Magnificent (1913, Harvard University Press) [10.4159_harvard.9780674337053] - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 360
  • [Harvard Historical Studies_ 9] Arthur Lyon Cross - The Anglican Episcopate and the American Colonies (1902, Harvard University Press) [10.4159_harvard.9780674368910] - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 380
  • [Harvard Historical Studies_ Ser.] Meredith Martin - Dairy Queens_ The Politics of Pastoral Architecture from Catherine de' Medici to Marie-Antoinette (2011, Harvard University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 337 Author: someAuthor
  • [Harvard historical studies 118] Robert McCune Kingdon - Adultery and Divorce in Calvin's Geneva 118 (1994, Harvard University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 226 Author: Kingdon, Robert M. (Robert McCune), 1927- Creator: Internet Archive PDF 1.4.13; including mupdf and pymupdf/skimage
  • [Harvard historical studies 183] Manjapra, Kris - Age of Entanglement_ German and Indian Intellectuals Across Empire (2014, Harvard University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 455 Author: Manjapra, Kris;
  • [International Geophysics] John M. Wallace, John Michael Wallace, Peter V. Hobbs - Atmospheric Science. An Introductory Survey (2006, Academic Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 505 Author: INTEGRA Creator: Adobe Acrobat 8.1 Combine Files
  • [Quantum Field Theory and the Standard Model] Schwartz, M.D. - Quantum Field Theory and the Standard Model (2013, Cambridge University Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 871 Creator: Canon iR-ADV C5045 PDF
  • [The International Geophysics 88 89] James R. Holton - An Introduction to Dynamic Meteorology (2004, Academic Press) - libgen.li.pdf Pages: 553

================================================================================

Downloads last month
5