id
int64
673k
4.14M
tag
stringlengths
1
39.7k
cite
stringlengths
1
8.39k
fullcite
stringlengths
1
50.9k
summary
stringlengths
1
47k
spoken
stringlengths
1
13.9k
fulltext
stringlengths
1
138k
textLength
float64
0
138k
markup
stringlengths
10
139k
pocket
stringlengths
1
863
hat
stringlengths
1
5.45k
block
stringlengths
1
16.5k
bucketId
int64
37
1.65M
duplicateCount
int64
1
3.81k
fileId
int64
14k
129k
filePath
stringlengths
60
188
roundId
int64
565k
915k
side
stringclasses
2 values
tournament
stringlengths
1
62
round
stringclasses
34 values
opponent
stringlengths
1
57
judge
stringlengths
1
87
report
stringlengths
1
612k
opensourcePath
stringlengths
48
176
caselistUpdatedAt
float64
teamId
int64
48.4k
77.9k
teamName
stringlengths
3
5
teamDisplayName
stringlengths
8
31
notes
float64
debater1First
stringclasses
164 values
debater1Last
stringclasses
183 values
debater2First
stringclasses
151 values
debater2Last
stringclasses
186 values
schoolId
int64
18.7k
26.1k
schoolName
stringclasses
306 values
schoolDisplayName
stringclasses
306 values
state
float64
chapterId
float64
caselistId
int64
1k
1.04k
caselistName
stringclasses
10 values
caselistDisplayName
stringclasses
10 values
year
int64
2.01k
2.02k
event
stringclasses
2 values
level
stringclasses
2 values
teamSize
int64
1
2
740,905
Modern medicine is built on the grave of Hippocrates – a constant deference to the words promised by each practicing physician –
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Modern medicine is built on the grave of Hippocrates – a constant deference to the words promised by each practicing physician – </h4>
null
1AC
null
430,038
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,906
The illegality of PAS bars women from the transgressive act of death in the name of futurity and life preservation, allowing gendered norms to dominate end-of-life care. This regime of medicalization keeps suffering women alive to sustain patriarchal values. Diane Raymond explains
null
Diane, professor of Gender Studies at Simmons College, Ph.D in philosophy from NYU, “’Fatal practices’: A feminist analysis of physician-assisted suicide and Euthanasia” Hypatia Spring 1999. Vol. 14:2 SJE
Wolf extends her argument against PAS by grounding the examples just discussed in a gendered context where passivity have been the normative ideal. Wolf oversimplifies and overgeneralizes that history. Many cultures equated suicide with courage and thereby framed the practice as male. Wolf's ascription of suicide as a "woman's solution" might be as inaccurate and overly monolithic a description of ancient Greek practice and ideology as it appears of the present, where statistics show that older white men kill themselves at a rate five times higher than the national average the slippage in Wolf's argument from self-sacrifice to suicide makes the argument suspect; rather than conflating the two, one might argue that, given that women's historical role has been to endure selflessly all forms of labor and abuse suicide may for women be the ultimate transgressive act. even if we agree that popular discussions of PAS and euthanasia "may be animated by gendered logic all that follows is the more modest conclusion that we must interrogate that logic before making a normative judgment about the practice. if there is any gendered difference in end-of-life treatments, it is that men are undertreated and women are overtreated the superficial inconsistency between men's end-of-life treatments and their greater access to earlier treatment options might instead reflect a pattern consistent with patriarchal ideology, namely that we hold to a higher standard of quality of life for men than for women. gender ideology, in valorizing female passivity, may actively collude with the medical profession in keeping dying, suffering women alive. one can agree wholeheartedly with Wolf's claim that "the very meaning of the patient's request for death is socially constructed" (1996, 299) while rejecting her understanding of that meaning or being willing to entertain multiple interpretations.
Wolf oversimplifies and overgeneralizes that history. Many cultures equated suicide with courage and framed the practice as male Wolf's ascription of suicide as a "woman's solution" might be inaccurate and overly monolithic the slippage in Wolf's argument from self-sacrifice to suicide makes the argument suspect; rather than conflating the two given that women's historical role has been to endure selflessly all forms of labor and abuse suicide may for women be the ultimate transgressive act. even if discussions of PAS may be animated by gendered logic all that follows is that we must interrogate that logic before making a normative judgment about the practice men are undertreated and women are overtreated. the inconsistency between men's end-of-life treatments and their greater access to earlier treatment options might reflect patriarchal ideology that we hold to a higher standard of quality of life for men than for women gender ideology may actively collude with the medical profession in keeping suffering women alive
In the section "Gender in Cases, Images, and Practices," Wolf extends her argument against PAS by grounding the examples just discussed in a gendered context where female self-sacrifice and passivity have been the normative ideal. That insight leads her to explore the historical and cultural background of suicide and its ideology, suggestively using Greek tragedy, the nineteenth-century cult of True Womanhood, and Carol Gilligan's research to confirm that self-sacrifice has traditionally been associated with women and regarded thereby as a feminine virtue. Yet, while there is no doubt as to the misogynistic history of women's constrained choices, Wolf oversimplifies and overgeneralizes that history. Many cultures--the Stoic, for example--equated suicide with courage and thereby framed the practice as male. The Greek tradition of soldiers throwing themselves on their swords rather than be taken as slaves, the Japanese ritual of hara-kiri, the examples of Hemingway, Kohlberg, and numerous others--these easily recoverable cases suggest that suicide can be seen as part of a masculinist ideology or at least not unproblematically feminine. 10 While a more in-depth analysis would probably reveal much divergence even in ancient Greek practice, Wolf's ascription of suicide as a "woman's solution" (Wolf 1996, 289) might be as inaccurate and overly monolithic a description of ancient Greek practice and ideology as it appears of the present, where statistics show that older white men kill themselves at a rate five times higher than the national average (National Center for Health Statistics Report 1987). Given patriarchal ideology's equation of masculinity with strength and power, men's heightened inability to cope with aging and illness makes sense intuitively. Further, women's lived experiences with multiple forms of dependence and interdependence--pregnancy, childrearing, and so forth--may mitigate some of the anxiety associated with aging, dependence on others, and decreasing physical autonomy.¶ Further, the slippage in Wolf's argument from self-sacrifice (a "feminine not masculine virtue" [1996, 289]) to suicide makes the argument suspect; rather than conflating the two, one might argue that, given that women's historical role has been to endure selflessly all forms of labor and abuse, particularly in the domestic sphere, suicide may for women be the ultimate transgressive act. One need not, however, go that far or make men's behavior normative to challenge Wolf's argument. For even if we agree that popular discussions of PAS and euthanasia "may be animated by unacknowledged images that give the practices a certain gendered logic and felt correctness" (Wolf 1996, 289), all that follows is the more modest conclusion that we must interrogate that logic before making a normative judgment about the practice. The gender ideology fleshed out in Wolf's analysis may lead, as suggested earlier, to great reluctance, not eagerness, to allow PAS or euthanasia for women. Indeed, some evidence suggests that if there is any gendered difference in end-of-life treatments, it is that men are undertreated and women are overtreated. Steven Miles and Allison August, for example, have examined a number of judicial decisions relating to withdrawal of treatment at end-of-life and find a pattern of acceding to male patients' wishes over females'. They note that women are held to higher evidentiary standards when requests to die are examined, and they remark on the ways in which gendered language in judicial treatments of these cases tends to rob women of their agency. Women and not men, for example, are routinely infantilized by referring to them by their first names ("Debbie" and "Diane" fit this pattern); and men's statements about end-of-life treatment are held to reflect "mature, rational choice" while women's are seen as "unreflective, emotional, or immature" (Miles and August 1990, 87). Karen Quinlan's comments to her mother were thereby dismissed as a "wish" or personal "distaste" and not a genuine expression of her values. In another case, a woman's repeated comments regarding her desire not to be kept on life support were trivialized as no "more than immediate reaction to the unsettling experience of seeing or hearing of another unnecessarily prolonged death" (in Miles and August 1990, 88). Courts seem even to discount women's advance directives, preferring instead to appoint family members as decision-makers for the incompetent woman; in one case, the Court empowered a woman's husband/guardian to make the decision "for" her, despite the fact that she had been an active member of the state's "Euthanasia Council." Women's "overtreatment" at end-of-life may seem odd considering men's greater access to earlier interventions, including more standard diagnostic procedures like angiograms and more "exotic" treatments like organ transplants. But the superficial inconsistency between men's end-of-life treatments and their greater access to earlier treatment options might instead reflect a pattern consistent with patriarchal ideology, namely that we hold to a higher standard of quality of life for men than for women. If such is the case, then gender ideology, in valorizing female passivity, may actively collude with the medical profession in keeping dying, suffering women alive. Likewise, ideological constructions of masculinity as inextricably aligned with agency, activity, and transcendence might lead to respect for men's medical directives--formal and informal--as well as to gendered distinctions on quality-of-life issues. Those unfamiliar with the ravages of persistent vegetative state (PVS) may picture the comatose or PVS patient as a comfortable "sleeping beauty" waiting for her miraculous awakening; such gendered imagery may help to account for the resistance to withdrawal of life support in the classic Quinlan and Cruzan cases, and the willingness of the Georgia Supreme Court to grant the physicians of Larry McAfee, a C-2 quadriplegic (a non-terminal condition), permission to provide him with the drugs necessary for him to be free of pain when his respirator was disconnected. Wolf's analysis of cultural ideology, while extremely suggestive, needs elaboration and nuance. Further, in the course of that extended analysis we should not be surprised by gaps and inconsistencies, for culture is never monolithic or fixed, and cultural practices do not follow consistently or irresistibly even the most hegemonic ideology. Thus, one can agree wholeheartedly with Wolf's claim that "the very meaning of the patient's request for death is socially constructed" (1996, 299) while rejecting her understanding of that meaning or being willing to entertain multiple interpretations.
6,765
<h4>The illegality of PAS bars women from the transgressive act of death in the name of futurity and life preservation, allowing gendered norms to dominate end-of-life care. This regime of medicalization keeps suffering women alive to sustain patriarchal values. Diane Raymond explains </h4><p>Diane, professor of Gender Studies at Simmons College, Ph.D in philosophy from NYU, “’Fatal practices’: A feminist analysis of physician-assisted suicide and Euthanasia” Hypatia Spring 1999. Vol. 14:2 SJE</p><p>In the section "Gender in Cases, Images, and Practices," <u>Wolf extends her argument against PAS by grounding the examples just discussed in a gendered context where</u> female self-sacrifice and<u> passivity have been the normative ideal.</u> That insight leads her to explore the historical and cultural background of suicide and its ideology, suggestively using Greek tragedy, the nineteenth-century cult of True Womanhood, and Carol Gilligan's research to confirm that self-sacrifice has traditionally been associated with women and regarded thereby as a feminine virtue. Yet, while there is no doubt as to the misogynistic history of women's constrained choices, <u><strong><mark>Wolf oversimplifies and overgeneralizes that history.</strong></mark> <mark>Many cultures</u></mark>--the Stoic, for example--<u><mark>equated suicide with courage</mark> <mark>and</mark> thereby <mark>framed the practice as male</mark>.</u> The Greek tradition of soldiers throwing themselves on their swords rather than be taken as slaves, the Japanese ritual of hara-kiri, the examples of Hemingway, Kohlberg, and numerous others--these easily recoverable cases suggest that suicide can be seen as part of a masculinist ideology or at least not unproblematically feminine. 10 While a more in-depth analysis would probably reveal much divergence even in ancient Greek practice, <u><mark>Wolf's ascription of suicide as a "woman's solution"</u></mark> (Wolf 1996, 289) <u><mark>might</mark> <mark>be</mark> as <mark>inaccurate and overly monolithic</mark> a description of ancient Greek practice and ideology as it appears of the present, where statistics show that older white men kill themselves at a rate five times higher than the national average</u> (National Center for Health Statistics Report 1987). Given patriarchal ideology's equation of masculinity with strength and power, men's heightened inability to cope with aging and illness makes sense intuitively. Further, women's lived experiences with multiple forms of dependence and interdependence--pregnancy, childrearing, and so forth--may mitigate some of the anxiety associated with aging, dependence on others, and decreasing physical autonomy.¶ Further, <u><mark>the slippage in Wolf's argument from self-sacrifice</u></mark> (a "feminine not masculine virtue" [1996, 289]) <u><mark>to suicide makes the argument suspect; rather than conflating the two</mark>, one might argue that, <mark>given that women's historical role has been to endure selflessly all forms of labor and abuse</u></mark>, particularly in the domestic sphere, <u><strong><mark>suicide may for women be the ultimate transgressive act.</u></strong></mark> One need not, however, go that far or make men's behavior normative to challenge Wolf's argument. For <u><mark>even if</mark> we agree that popular <mark>discussions of PAS</mark> and euthanasia "<mark>may be animated by</u></mark> unacknowledged images that give the practices a certain <u><mark>gendered logic</u></mark> and felt correctness" (Wolf 1996, 289), <u><mark>all that follows is </mark>the more modest conclusion <mark>that we must <strong>interrogate that logic</strong> before making a normative judgment about the practice</mark>. </u>The gender ideology fleshed out in Wolf's analysis may lead, as suggested earlier, to great reluctance, not eagerness, to allow PAS or euthanasia for women. Indeed, some evidence suggests that <u>if there is any gendered difference in end-of-life treatments, it is that <mark>men are undertreated and women are overtreated</u>.</mark> Steven Miles and Allison August, for example, have examined a number of judicial decisions relating to withdrawal of treatment at end-of-life and find a pattern of acceding to male patients' wishes over females'. They note that women are held to higher evidentiary standards when requests to die are examined, and they remark on the ways in which gendered language in judicial treatments of these cases tends to rob women of their agency. Women and not men, for example, are routinely infantilized by referring to them by their first names ("Debbie" and "Diane" fit this pattern); and men's statements about end-of-life treatment are held to reflect "mature, rational choice" while women's are seen as "unreflective, emotional, or immature" (Miles and August 1990, 87). Karen Quinlan's comments to her mother were thereby dismissed as a "wish" or personal "distaste" and not a genuine expression of her values. In another case, a woman's repeated comments regarding her desire not to be kept on life support were trivialized as no "more than immediate reaction to the unsettling experience of seeing or hearing of another unnecessarily prolonged death" (in Miles and August 1990, 88). Courts seem even to discount women's advance directives, preferring instead to appoint family members as decision-makers for the incompetent woman; in one case, the Court empowered a woman's husband/guardian to make the decision "for" her, despite the fact that she had been an active member of the state's "Euthanasia Council." Women's "overtreatment" at end-of-life may seem odd considering men's greater access to earlier interventions, including more standard diagnostic procedures like angiograms and more "exotic" treatments like organ transplants. But <u><mark>the</mark> superficial <mark>inconsistency between men's end-of-life treatments and their greater access to earlier treatment options might</mark> instead <mark>reflect</mark> a pattern consistent with <mark>patriarchal ideology</mark>, namely <mark>that we hold to a <strong>higher standard of quality of life for men than for women</strong></mark>.</u> If such is the case, then <u><strong><mark>gender ideology</mark>, in valorizing female passivity, <mark>may actively collude with the medical profession in keeping</mark> dying, <mark>suffering women alive</mark>.</u></strong> Likewise, ideological constructions of masculinity as inextricably aligned with agency, activity, and transcendence might lead to respect for men's medical directives--formal and informal--as well as to gendered distinctions on quality-of-life issues. Those unfamiliar with the ravages of persistent vegetative state (PVS) may picture the comatose or PVS patient as a comfortable "sleeping beauty" waiting for her miraculous awakening; such gendered imagery may help to account for the resistance to withdrawal of life support in the classic Quinlan and Cruzan cases, and the willingness of the Georgia Supreme Court to grant the physicians of Larry McAfee, a C-2 quadriplegic (a non-terminal condition), permission to provide him with the drugs necessary for him to be free of pain when his respirator was disconnected. Wolf's analysis of cultural ideology, while extremely suggestive, needs elaboration and nuance. Further, in the course of that extended analysis we should not be surprised by gaps and inconsistencies, for culture is never monolithic or fixed, and cultural practices do not follow consistently or irresistibly even the most hegemonic ideology. Thus, <u>one can agree wholeheartedly with Wolf's claim that "the very meaning of the patient's request for death is socially constructed" (1996, 299) while rejecting her understanding of that meaning or being willing to entertain multiple interpretations.</p></u>
null
null
null
430,002
5
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,907
Footnoting DA
Der Derian 95
Der Derian 95 (James, Professor of Political Science – University of Massachusetts, International Theory: Critical Investigations, p. 374)
A stop-gap solution is to supplement the gambit with a facile gesture. The IR theorist will note the 'essentially contested' nature of realism - duly backed up with a footnote and then get down to business as usual using realism as the best language to reflect a self-same phenomenon. This amounts to an intellectual plea of nolo-contendere: in exchange for not contesting the IR 'perp' gets off easy, to then turn around and commit worse epistemological crimes
A stop-gap solution is to supplement the gambit with a facile gesture. The IR theorist will note the contested' nature of realism with a footnote and then business as usual This amounts to an intellectual plea of nolo-contendere the IR 'perp' gets off easy, to commit worse epistemological crimes
But what happens - as seems to be the case to this observer - when the 'we' fragments, 'realism' takes on prefixes and goes plural, the meaning of meaning itself is up for grabs? A stop-gap solution is to supplement the definitional gambit with a facile gesture. The IR theorist, mindful of a creeping pluralism, will note the 'essentially contested' nature of realism - duly backed up with a footnote to W. B. Gallie or W E. Connolly - and then get down to business as usual, that is, using realism as the best language to reflect a self-same phenomenon. This amounts to an intellectual plea of nolo-contendere: in exchange for not contesting the charge that the meaning of realism is contestable, the IR 'perp' gets off easy, to then turn around and commit worse epistemological crimes. In honor of the most notorious benefactor of nolo-contendere in recent American legal history, we might call this the 'Spiro-ette effect' in International Relations.
954
<h4>Footnoting DA</h4><p><u><strong>Der Derian 95</u></strong> (James, Professor of Political Science – University of Massachusetts, International Theory: Critical Investigations, p. 374)</p><p>But what happens - as seems to be the case to this observer - when the 'we' fragments, 'realism' takes on prefixes and goes plural, the meaning of meaning itself is up for grabs? <u><mark>A stop-gap solution is to supplement the</u></mark> definitional <u><mark>gambit with a facile gesture. The IR theorist</u></mark>, mindful of a creeping pluralism, <u><mark>will note the</mark> 'essentially <mark>contested' nature of realism</mark> - duly backed up <mark>with a footnote</u></mark> to W. B. Gallie or W E. Connolly - <u><mark>and then</mark> get down to <mark>business as usual</u></mark>, that is, <u>using realism as the best language to reflect a self-same phenomenon. <mark>This amounts to an intellectual plea of nolo-contendere</mark>: in exchange for not contesting</u> the charge that the meaning of realism is contestable, <u><mark>the IR 'perp' gets off easy, to</mark> then turn around and <mark>commit worse epistemological crimes</u></mark>. In honor of the most notorious benefactor of nolo-contendere in recent American legal history, we might call this the 'Spiro-ette effect' in International Relations.</p>
2NC
K
Perm
224,576
30
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,908
The idea that subjects should be maximally reciprocal destroys the possibility for individual value
Robinson 12
Robinson 12
Baudrillard sees communication and sociality being corrupted into sign-values to be consumed. The loss of genuine, spontaneous, reciprocal human relations is covered up by the standardised production of signs of social warmth and participation. it simulates intimacy. These simulated signs are what now counts as abstract ‘interpersonal skills’. such false sociality is shot through with the flaws of the mode of production, including aggression and frustration. It turns into an entire value-system dressed-up as functionality. It has a constant repressive effect, pacifying social relations. The act of conforming to a model is presented as narcissistic self-assertion through small signified differences. People think they are creating themselves when in fact they are consuming themselves femininity and masculinity are models which govern, rather than express, women and men such models shape how people see each other People set up signs of happiness in the hope that happiness will alight on them. There is a ‘fun system’ of enforced enjoyment, which imposes a duty to happiness and denies any right not to be happy. Consumption is a institution and a system of values with functions of social integration and control. The anarchic consumer is a thing of the past. People are pressured to consume in standard ways this pressure destroys enjoyment from the inside. Consumption is haunted by its inner puritanism, rendering it compulsive and limitless. At the same time as socialising people, it atomises people into private consumption. They mark conformity with the code, not individuality. The system is based on abolishing real difference so as to usher in a process of differentiation Excessive social contact due to urbanism leads to psychological pauperisation. People gain an increased need for objects as signifiers of differentiation Consumption excludes the possibility of enjoyment. because consumption is always collective whereas enjoyment is personal. The disappearance of altruistic forms of integration leads to an expanded role for state repression. Atomisation leads to bureaucratic control, disguised as freedom. The ‘people’ are glorified as long as they do not try to exercise their putative sovereignty on a political or social stage, and instead stick to consuming. Competition leads to generalised fatigue Such fatigue is really a resistance, akin to a slowdown by workers or boredom in school. Such resistance becomes habitual and ‘grows into’ people’s It is a partial revolt necessary to prevent total breakdown, which is instantly available as a source of discontent in crisis situations. The real social effect of the pursuit of system-promoted goals is an exhausting rat-race. The system of unstable, precarious employment creates generalised insecurity and generalised competition for status. The constant treadmill of work leaves some on the scrapheap and others successful but exhausted. the ideology of consumption lulls people into believing that they are affluent, fulfilled, happy and liberated. Baudrillard writes of the production of a new kind of character-armoured subject: the sociometric individual. Sociability is mis-perceived as something personal, while being rendered simply functional. Instead of being autonomous, people display marks of ‘personalisation’. A person transformed is at home everywhere and nowhere – able to display superficial intimacy, but belonging nowhere. Rather than conformity, the system demands of such people that they be maximally sociable and maximally compatible with others across a wide range of situations. Such people are part of an enforced mobilisation, always available as calculable and accountable units for use in political and sociometric planning. They become psychologically dependent on gaining approval, and lose individual transcendental aspirations. This leads to a new social morality. Ideology and individual values are replaced relativity, receptivity, agreement and anxious communication, all of which render people programmable. Baudrillard’s critique extends to politics. The contradiction between ‘services’ and democratic ideology leads to an entire simulation of absent reciprocity. A superficial layer of minimal communication is used to paper over the hostility and social distance which are everywhere. This layer is ‘functional’ enough to personalise and pacify power, but is stripped of every affective and psychological aspect. People can demand signs of sociability and sincerity. But the signs only reproduce the mistrust. They have become empty signs in a closed system, which no longer convey real trust.
The loss of genuine relations is covered up by signs of participation. These simulated signs now count as skills It has a constant repressive effect, pacifying social relations. a ‘fun system’ of enforced enjoyment, which imposes a duty to happiness and denies any right not to be happy. Consumption is social control. it atomises people into private consumption They mark conformity with the code, not individuality. Consumption excludes the possibility of enjoyment. because consumption is always collective whereas enjoyment is personal. Atomisation leads to bureaucratic control, disguised as freedom. people’ are glorified as long as they do not try to exercise their sovereignty and consum The effect of the pursuit of system-promoted goals is an exhausting rat-race. The treadmill of work lulls people into believing that they are liberated. A person transformed is at home everywhere and nowhere but belonging nowhere. individual values are replaced which render people programmable. an simulation of absent reciprocity. A superficial layer of minimal communication is used to paper over the hostility and social distance everywhere
(Andrew, Political Theorist, Activist Based in the UK and research fellow affiliated to the Centre for the Study of Social and Global Justice (CSSGJ), University of Nottingham, April 14, 2012, “Jean Baudrillard: Critique of Alienation – Draft 1,” http://ceasefiremagazine.co.uk/in-theory-baudrillard-3/ Baudrillard also sees communication and sociality being corrupted into sign-values to be consumed. This occurs through the consumption of ‘services’ based on sociability. The loss of genuine, spontaneous, reciprocal human relations (which require a symbolic dimension) is covered up by the standardised production of signs of social warmth and participation. As with the smile of the salesman, receptionist or PR executive, or the “have a nice day” of McDonald’s, it simulates intimacy. These simulated signs are what now counts as abstract ‘interpersonal skills’. In practice, Baudrillard observes, such false sociality is shot through with the flaws of the mode of production, including aggression and frustration. It turns into an entire value-system dressed-up as functionality. It has a constant repressive effect, pacifying social relations. The act of conforming to a model is presented as narcissistic self-assertion through small signified differences. People think they are creating themselves when in fact they are consuming themselves, or their images. For example, femininity and masculinity are models which govern, rather than express, women and men. Baudrillard believes that such models shape how people see each other, regardless of whether people actually conform to them. Similarly, sites such as holiday resorts are constructed as planned communities and total environments realising a particular ideal of abstract happiness. These sites replace distinct elements with homogeneous ones. People set up signs of happiness in the hope that happiness will alight on them. There is a ‘fun system’ of enforced enjoyment, which imposes a duty (not a right) to happiness and denies any right not to be happy. Consumption is a morality, an institution and a system of values with functions of social integration and control. The anarchic consumer, free to consume or not, is a thing of the past. People are now pressured to consume in standard ways and even to seek out new experiences. Yet this pressure destroys enjoyment from the inside. Consumption is haunted by its inner puritanism, rendering it compulsive and limitless. It is both lived as an affirmative myth, and endured as a kind of social adaptation to a new collective regime. At the same time as socialising people, it atomises people into private consumption. Beauty products and the like often claim to be drawing out an inherent personality, or recovering one which has been lost. In fact they are products of the industrial mass-production of systematic differences. These differences are derived from a model and are only artificially diversified. They mark conformity with the code, not individuality. Baudrillard writes of ‘monopoly concentration of the production of differences’. The system is based on abolishing real difference (and for instance nature) so as to usher in a process of differentiation (and naturalisation, etc). Difference within the code is based on the smallest marginal difference, used as a sign of hierarchy. Excessive social contact due to urbanism leads to psychological pauperisation. People gain an increased need for objects as signifiers of differentiation. Consumption actually excludes the possibility of enjoyment. This is because consumption is always collective, at least indirectly, whereas enjoyment is personal. The disappearance of altruistic forms of integration leads to an expanded role for state repression. Atomisation leads to bureaucratic control, disguised as freedom. Credit is used to condition people into capitalistic forms of action. The ‘people’ or consumers are glorified as long as they do not try to exercise their putative sovereignty on a political or social stage, and instead stick to consuming. Consumer goods are experienced as miraculous, because their production is concealed. They seem as if they come from technology, progress or growth. In fact we have only the signs of affluence, coexisting with ever more impoverished social relations. Competition, generalised across social life as consumption as well as production is ranked, leads to generalised fatigue. Such fatigue is really a resistance, akin to a slowdown by workers or boredom in school. Such resistance, as the only resistance available, becomes habitual and ‘grows into’ people’s bodies. It is a partial revolt necessary to prevent total breakdown, which is also instantly available as a source of discontent in crisis situations. The real social effect of the pursuit of system-promoted goals is an exhausting rat-race. The system of unstable, precarious employment creates generalised insecurity and generalised competition for status. The constant treadmill of work, retraining and status-competition leaves some on the scrapheap and others successful but exhausted. But the ideology of consumption lulls people into believing that they are affluent, fulfilled, happy and liberated. Baudrillard writes of the production of a new kind of character-armoured subject: the sociometric individual. Sociability is mis-perceived as something personal, while in fact being rendered simply functional. Instead of being autonomous, people display marks of ‘personalisation’. A person thus transformed is at home everywhere and nowhere – able to display superficial intimacy, but belonging nowhere. Social action is subordinated to the pursuit of status. Rather than conformity, the system demands of such people that they be maximally sociable and maximally compatible with others across a wide range of situations. Such people are part of an enforced mobilisation, always available as calculable and accountable units for use in political and sociometric planning. They become psychologically dependent on gaining approval, and lose individual transcendental aspirations. This in turn leads to a new social morality. Ideology and individual values are replaced in this morality with relativity, receptivity, agreement and anxious communication, all of which render people programmable. Baudrillard’s critique also extends to politics. The contradiction between ‘services’ and democratic ideology leads to an entire simulation of absent reciprocity. A superficial layer of minimal communication is used to paper over the hostility and social distance which are everywhere. This layer is ‘functional’ enough to personalise and pacify power, but is stripped of every affective and psychological aspect. Instead it is constructed from the calculated model of an ideal relationship. People can no longer trust themselves or each other. It is for this reason that they demand signs of sociability and sincerity. But the signs only reproduce the mistrust. They have become empty signs in a closed system, which no longer convey real trust. The welfare state is criticised as a way to portray an exchange society as if it were a service society, giving back what it takes from workers. Equality and democracy conceal the real system of discrimination, based on whether or not one can decode consumer goods. Furthermore, the system conditions people to constantly want a little more than they have. The system produces the needs it satisfies (through advertising and demand management), produces only for its own needs, and hides behind the alibi of individual needs (inventing an idea of economic man to prop itself up). It rests on real needs being misrecognised. And it produces needs which it then refuses to satisfy, instead using them as inducements to conformity.
7,778
<h4>The idea that subjects should be maximally reciprocal destroys the possibility for individual value</h4><p><strong>Robinson 12</strong> </p><p>(Andrew, Political Theorist, Activist Based in the UK and research fellow affiliated to the Centre for the Study of Social and Global Justice (CSSGJ), University of Nottingham, April 14, 2012, “Jean Baudrillard: Critique of Alienation – Draft 1,” http://ceasefiremagazine.co.uk/in-theory-baudrillard-3/</p><p><u><strong>Baudrillard</u></strong> also <u><strong>sees communication and sociality being corrupted into sign-values to be consumed. </u></strong> This occurs through the consumption of ‘services’ based on sociability. <u><strong><mark>The loss of genuine</mark>, spontaneous, reciprocal human <mark>relations</u></strong></mark> (which require a symbolic dimension) <u><strong><mark>is covered up by</mark> the standardised production of <mark>signs of </mark>social warmth and <mark>participation.</u></strong></mark> As with the smile of the salesman, receptionist or PR executive, or the “have a nice day” of McDonald’s, <u><strong>it simulates intimacy.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>These simulated signs</mark> are what <mark>now count</mark>s <mark>as</mark> abstract ‘interpersonal <mark>skills</mark>’.</u></strong> In practice, Baudrillard observes, <u><strong>such false sociality is shot through with the flaws of the mode of production, including aggression and frustration.</u></strong> <u><strong>It turns into an entire value-system dressed-up as functionality. <mark>It has a constant repressive effect, pacifying social relations.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>The act of conforming to a model is presented as narcissistic self-assertion through small signified differences.</u></strong> <u><strong>People think they are creating themselves when in fact they are consuming themselves</u></strong>, or their images. For example, <u><strong>femininity and masculinity are models which govern, rather than express, women and men</u></strong>. Baudrillard believes that <u><strong>such models shape how people see each other</u></strong>, regardless of whether people actually conform to them. Similarly, sites such as holiday resorts are constructed as planned communities and total environments realising a particular ideal of abstract happiness. These sites replace distinct elements with homogeneous ones. <u><strong>People set up signs of happiness in the hope that happiness will alight on them.</u></strong> <u><strong>There is <mark>a ‘fun system’ of enforced enjoyment, which imposes a duty</u></strong></mark> (not a right) <u><strong><mark>to happiness and denies any right not to be happy.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>Consumption is</mark> a</u></strong> morality, an <u><strong>institution and a system of values with functions of <mark>social </mark>integration and <mark>control.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>The anarchic consumer</u></strong>, free to consume or not, <u><strong>is a thing of the past.</u></strong> <u><strong>People are</u></strong> now <u><strong>pressured to consume in standard ways</u></strong> and even to seek out new experiences. Yet <u><strong>this pressure destroys enjoyment from the inside.</u></strong> <u><strong>Consumption is haunted by its inner puritanism, rendering it compulsive and limitless.</u></strong> It is both lived as an affirmative myth, and endured as a kind of social adaptation to a new collective regime. <u><strong>At the same time as socialising people, <mark>it atomises people into private consumption</mark>. </u></strong>Beauty products and the like often claim to be drawing out an inherent personality, or recovering one which has been lost. In fact they are products of the industrial mass-production of systematic differences. These differences are derived from a model and are only artificially diversified. <u><strong><mark>They mark conformity with the code, not individuality.</u></strong></mark> Baudrillard writes of ‘monopoly concentration of the production of differences’. <u><strong>The system is based on abolishing real difference</u></strong> (and for instance nature) <u><strong>so as to usher in a process of differentiation</u></strong> (and naturalisation, etc). Difference within the code is based on the smallest marginal difference, used as a sign of hierarchy. <u><strong>Excessive social contact due to urbanism leads to psychological pauperisation.</u></strong> <u><strong>People gain an increased need for objects as signifiers of differentiation</u></strong>. <u><strong><mark>Consumption</u></strong></mark> actually <u><strong><mark>excludes the possibility of enjoyment.</u></strong></mark> This is <u><strong><mark>because consumption is always collective</u></strong></mark>, at least indirectly, <u><strong><mark>whereas enjoyment is personal. </mark>The disappearance of altruistic forms of integration leads to an expanded role for state repression.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>Atomisation leads to bureaucratic control, disguised as freedom.</u></strong></mark> Credit is used to condition people into capitalistic forms of action. <u><strong>The ‘<mark>people’</u></strong></mark> or consumers <u><strong><mark>are glorified as long as they do not try to exercise their</mark> putative <mark>sovereignty</mark> on a political or social stage, <mark>and </mark>instead stick to <mark>consum</mark>ing.</u></strong> Consumer goods are experienced as miraculous, because their production is concealed. They seem as if they come from technology, progress or growth. In fact we have only the signs of affluence, coexisting with ever more impoverished social relations. <u><strong>Competition</u></strong>, generalised across social life as consumption as well as production is ranked, <u><strong>leads to generalised fatigue</u></strong>. <u><strong>Such fatigue is really a resistance, akin to a slowdown by workers or boredom in school.</u></strong> <u><strong>Such resistance</u></strong>, as the only resistance available, <u><strong>becomes habitual and ‘grows into’ people’s</u></strong> bodies. <u><strong>It is a partial revolt necessary to prevent total breakdown, which is </u></strong>also <u><strong>instantly available as a source of discontent in crisis situations.<mark> The </mark>real social <mark>effect of the pursuit of system-promoted goals is an exhausting rat-race.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>The system of unstable, precarious employment creates generalised insecurity and generalised competition for status.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>The </mark>constant <mark>treadmill of work</u></strong></mark>, retraining and status-competition <u><strong>leaves some on the scrapheap and others successful but exhausted.</u></strong> But <u><strong>the ideology of consumption <mark>lulls people into believing that they are</mark> affluent, fulfilled, happy and <mark>liberated.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>Baudrillard writes of the production of a new kind of character-armoured subject: the sociometric individual.</u></strong> <u><strong>Sociability is mis-perceived as something personal, while</u></strong> in fact <u><strong>being rendered simply functional. Instead of being autonomous, people display marks of ‘personalisation’. <mark>A person</u></strong></mark> thus <u><strong><mark>transformed is at home everywhere and nowhere </mark>– able to display superficial intimacy, <mark>but belonging nowhere.</u></strong></mark> Social action is subordinated to the pursuit of status. <u><strong>Rather than conformity, the system demands of such people that they be maximally sociable and maximally compatible with others across a wide range of situations.</u></strong> <u><strong>Such people are part of an enforced mobilisation, always available as calculable and accountable units for use in political and sociometric planning.</u></strong> <u><strong>They become psychologically dependent on gaining approval, and lose individual transcendental aspirations.</u></strong> <u><strong>This</u></strong> in turn <u><strong>leads to a new social morality.</u></strong> <u><strong>Ideology and <mark>individual values are replaced</mark> </u></strong>in this morality with <u><strong>relativity, receptivity, agreement and anxious communication, all of <mark>which render people programmable.</mark> Baudrillard’s critique</u></strong> also <u><strong>extends to politics.</u></strong> <u><strong>The contradiction between ‘services’ and democratic ideology leads to <mark>an </mark>entire <mark>simulation of absent reciprocity. A superficial layer of minimal communication is used to paper over the hostility and social distance</mark> which are <mark>everywhere</mark>. This layer is ‘functional’ enough to personalise and pacify power, but is stripped of every affective and psychological aspect.</u></strong> Instead it is constructed from the calculated model of an ideal relationship. <u><strong>People</u></strong> <u><strong>can</u></strong> no longer trust themselves or each other. It is for this reason that they <u><strong>demand signs of sociability and sincerity. But the signs only reproduce the mistrust.</u></strong> <u><strong>They have become empty signs in a closed system, which no longer convey real trust. </u></strong>The welfare state is criticised as a way to portray an exchange society as if it were a service society, giving back what it takes from workers. Equality and democracy conceal the real system of discrimination, based on whether or not one can decode consumer goods. Furthermore, the system conditions people to constantly want a little more than they have. The system produces the needs it satisfies (through advertising and demand management), produces only for its own needs, and hides behind the alibi of individual needs (inventing an idea of economic man to prop itself up). It rests on real needs being misrecognised. And it produces needs which it then refuses to satisfy, instead using them as inducements to conformity.</p>
2AC
FW
AT: Limits
430,039
3
16,993
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
564,698
A
NDT
3
UTD LO
Heidt, Shook, Lundberg
1AC PAS genealogy- same assimilar to USC PAS 1AC 1NC T- Framework K- Szaz Medicalization of death 2NR T
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,909
*Bernie Madoff also caused Know Your Customer requirements that your evidence complains about
Economist 14
Economist 14 The Economist, 1/11/14, “Know your customer, or else…” http://www.economist.com/blogs/schumpeter/2014/01/jpmorgan-chase-and-madoff-case
A consequence of the Madoff case will be that all banks will need to be far tougher on their clients—and not just crooks America’s Bank Secrecy Act requires reporting anything that could have “a high degree of usefulness in criminal, tax or regulatory investigations Should a checking account mean a bank must know all? The Madoff settlement suggests, strongly, that the answer is yes. say goodbye to financial privacy. There could be other consequences adding armies to monitor transactions and pass them on to regulators Banks will become less like an efficient coffee shop competing with new products and more like airports, with oppressive security
A consequence of the Madoff case will be that all banks will need to be far tougher on their clients—and not just crooks. America requires reporting anything that could have “a high degree of usefulness in criminal, tax or regulatory investigations Should a checking account mean a bank must know all? The Madoff settlement suggests, strongly, that the answer is yes. say goodbye to financial privacy
“JPMORGAN as an institution failed and failed miserably,” said Preet Bharara, New York’s federal attorney, when explaining earlier this week a $1.7 billion settlement in the case of the bank’s failure to detect horrendous fraud of Bernard Madoff (pictured). A more intellectually honest announcement might have included indignation about the various government enforcement agencies which were explicitly and repeatedly warned of Mr Madoff’s scam by, among others, another major bank—and then utterly blew inspections without any individual or entity facing censure. A consequence of the Madoff case will be that all banks will need to be far tougher on their clients—and not just crooks. The 40 plus pages released along with the settlement do not make for easy reading, but the government’s case is built around two components. One is the relationship of Mr Madoff with JPMorgan Chase’s investment office in London. At times it invested with Mr Madoff through “feeder” funds, but never directly. It ultimately developed concerns about how these generated returns, and alerted British authorities. Less well known, JPMorgan’s primary relationship with Mr Madoff in America was two large checking accounts. Which raises the question whether, because of these checking accounts, JPMorgan had an obligation to alert American authorities as well? In agreeing to the settlement, JPMorgan has said it should have—though it was not in a position to argue (the simple issuance of a criminal indictment would have been devastating, regardless of whether it succeeded in court). The government’s case rests on the notion that America’s Bank Secrecy Act requires reporting anything that could have “a high degree of usefulness in criminal, tax or regulatory investigations.” Given the expansiveness of America’s laws, that could be almost anything. The government’s information document cites the report sent to British authorities, which says that “the investment performance achieved…appear to be too good to be true—meaning that it probably is.” If that is the standard, American regulatory agencies should be prepared for an electronic tsunami of alerts. There is, apparently, no penalty for over-reporting. The government statement is scathing about JPMorgan’s misunderstanding of Mr Madoff’s business. Banks are required to know their customers, but to what extent? Successful investment-management firms are often secretive about their approach, and rightly so: it is, after all, their secret sauce. Most businesses are complex. Should a checking account in America mean a company must spill all, or even that a bank must know all? The Madoff settlement suggests, strongly, that the answer is yes. So say goodbye to financial privacy. The government will see all. There could be lots of other consequences. Beyond adding armies to monitor transactions and pass them on to regulators, banks will start firing clients because they happen to do business in newly suspect categories. The reasons may not be explained. They may not even be understood by the bank employee relaying the news to the fired customer. Among them will be pursuing business activities abroad in places thought to have activities that violate American law. Or it could be because of a relationship with a politician (making a bank liable to accusations of politically-induced lending) or because of employment with a government of a country that is accused of money laundering. The Madoff settlement will be just one reason for this worrying trend, but it is an important one. The payment of a $1.7 billion for having a toxic client will mean the imposition of rules everywhere. And because they are rules, they won’t merely cover toxic clients. For non-crooks, these will seem arbitrary. Banks will become less like an efficient coffee shop competing with new products and more like airports, with oppressive security. The Madoff settlement may not be JPMorgan’s biggest, but it will have large implications—and not just for the bank. We will all pay.
4,019
<h4>*Bernie Madoff also caused Know Your Customer requirements that your evidence complains about</h4><p><u><strong>Economist 14</u></strong> The Economist, 1/11/14, “Know your customer, or else…” http://www.economist.com/blogs/schumpeter/2014/01/jpmorgan-chase-and-madoff-case</p><p>“JPMORGAN as an institution failed and failed miserably,” said Preet Bharara, New York’s federal attorney, when explaining earlier this week a $1.7 billion settlement in the case of the bank’s failure to detect horrendous fraud of Bernard Madoff (pictured). A more intellectually honest announcement might have included indignation about the various government enforcement agencies which were explicitly and repeatedly warned of Mr Madoff’s scam by, among others, another major bank—and then utterly blew inspections without any individual or entity facing censure. <u><mark>A consequence of the Madoff case will be that all banks will need to be far tougher on their clients—and not just crooks</u>.</mark> The 40 plus pages released along with the settlement do not make for easy reading, but the government’s case is built around two components. One is the relationship of Mr Madoff with JPMorgan Chase’s investment office in London. At times it invested with Mr Madoff through “feeder” funds, but never directly. It ultimately developed concerns about how these generated returns, and alerted British authorities. Less well known, JPMorgan’s primary relationship with Mr Madoff in America was two large checking accounts. Which raises the question whether, because of these checking accounts, JPMorgan had an obligation to alert American authorities as well? In agreeing to the settlement, JPMorgan has said it should have—though it was not in a position to argue (the simple issuance of a criminal indictment would have been devastating, regardless of whether it succeeded in court). The government’s case rests on the notion that <u><mark>America</mark>’s Bank Secrecy Act <mark>requires reporting anything that could have “a high degree of usefulness in criminal, tax or regulatory investigations</u></mark>.” Given the expansiveness of America’s laws, that could be almost anything. The government’s information document cites the report sent to British authorities, which says that “the investment performance achieved…appear to be too good to be true—meaning that it probably is.” If that is the standard, American regulatory agencies should be prepared for an electronic tsunami of alerts. There is, apparently, no penalty for over-reporting. The government statement is scathing about JPMorgan’s misunderstanding of Mr Madoff’s business. Banks are required to know their customers, but to what extent? Successful investment-management firms are often secretive about their approach, and rightly so: it is, after all, their secret sauce. Most businesses are complex. <u><mark>Should a checking account</u></mark> in America <u><mark>mean</u></mark> a company must spill all, or even that <u><mark>a bank must know all? The Madoff settlement suggests, strongly, that the answer is yes.</u></mark> So <u><mark>say goodbye to financial privacy</mark>.</u> The government will see all. <u>There could be</u> lots of <u>other consequences</u>. Beyond <u>adding armies to monitor transactions and pass them on to regulators</u>, banks will start firing clients because they happen to do business in newly suspect categories. The reasons may not be explained. They may not even be understood by the bank employee relaying the news to the fired customer. Among them will be pursuing business activities abroad in places thought to have activities that violate American law. Or it could be because of a relationship with a politician (making a bank liable to accusations of politically-induced lending) or because of employment with a government of a country that is accused of money laundering. The Madoff settlement will be just one reason for this worrying trend, but it is an important one. The payment of a $1.7 billion for having a toxic client will mean the imposition of rules everywhere. And because they are rules, they won’t merely cover toxic clients. For non-crooks, these will seem arbitrary. <u>Banks will become less like an efficient coffee shop competing with new products and more like airports, with oppressive security</u>. The Madoff settlement may not be JPMorgan’s biggest, but it will have large implications—and not just for the bank. We will all pay.</p>
1NR
Banks
2NC Alt Cause
430,040
3
16,987
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round1.docx
564,729
N
NDT
1
Harvard DH
Eric Short, Chris Thiele, Dan Stout
1ac was online gambling with econ and china advantages 1nc was security edelman and case 2nc was security 1nr was case 2nr was security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round1.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,910
Terrorist can’t cross the border through cartel routes and the status quo solves
Powell 11 Texas-from-2341185.php>)
Powell 11 – Houston Chronicle writer (Stewart M., “Are Potential Terrorists Crossing into Texas From Mexico?”, 12/2/11; < http://www.chron.com/news/houston-texas/article/Are-potential-terrorists-crossing-into-Texas-from-2341185.php>)
Yet despite these dire possibilities - including Perry's contention that Hamas and Hezbollah are working in Mexico to come to the U.S. - experts say such Iranian-financed factions are not crossing the southwest border. The last thing these organizations want is to start out at the border with a high profile criminal act that gets attention They want to be as unobtrusive as possible." Federal law enforcement agents picked up 445,000 border crossers last year. But only 13 Iranians were taken into custody, No credible cases The number of Iranians apprehended by U.S. Border Patrol "has been historically minimal," said a Department of Homeland Security official. "No credible terrorist threat has been identified, however DHS carefully monitors any potential threats along the Southwest border and responds accordingly."
experts say Iranian factions are not crossing the border. organizations want to be unobtrusive as possible The number apprehended by U.S. Border Patrol "has been historically minimal No credible terrorist threat has been identified DHS carefully monitors any potential threats along the border and responds accordingly
Pakistani officials told Texas' Republican Congressman Michael McCaul on a recent visit to Karachi that potential operatives from Pakistan, Iran, al-Qaida, the Taliban and the Haqqani network can obtain visas for Mexico from Mexican diplomatic outposts in Pakistan far more easily than getting them for the United States, making Mexico a perfect way station. Yet despite these dire possibilities - including Perry's contention that Hamas and Hezbollah are working in Mexico to come to the U.S. - experts say such Iranian-financed factions are not crossing the southwest border. They point instead to the 327 airports and border crossings in the United States where legitimate or forged passports might be used the same way that 19 hijackers gained access to carry out the 9/11 attacks. "The last thing these organizations want is to start out at the border with a high profile criminal act that gets attention," says James Carafano, a West Point graduate and retired Army lieutenant colonel handling security affairs at the Heritage Foundation. "They want to be as unobtrusive as possible." Federal law enforcement agents picked up 445,000 border crossers last year. But only 13 Iranians were taken into custody, a fraction of the 663 "special interest aliens" from 35 countries detained along the southwestern border for special U.S. scrutiny. None of the Iranians - indeed none of the 663 "special interest aliens" - has faced federal prosecution on terror-related charges, according to federal officials. No credible cases The number of Iranians apprehended by U.S. Border Patrol "has been historically minimal," said a Department of Homeland Security official. "No credible terrorist threat has been identified, however DHS carefully monitors any potential threats along the Southwest border and responds accordingly."
1,822
<h4>Terrorist can’t cross the border through cartel routes and the status quo solves</h4><p><u><strong>Powell 11</u> </strong>– Houston Chronicle writer (Stewart M., “Are Potential Terrorists Crossing into Texas From Mexico?”, 12/2/11; < http://www.chron.com/news/houston-texas/article/Are-potential-terrorists-crossing-into-<u><strong>Texas-from-2341185.php>)</p><p></u></strong>Pakistani officials told Texas' Republican Congressman Michael McCaul on a recent visit to Karachi that potential operatives from Pakistan, Iran, al-Qaida, the Taliban and the Haqqani network can obtain visas for Mexico from Mexican diplomatic outposts in Pakistan far more easily than getting them for the United States, making Mexico a perfect way station. <u><strong>Yet despite these dire possibilities - including Perry's contention that Hamas and Hezbollah are working in Mexico to come to the U.S. - <mark>experts say</mark> such <mark>Iranian</mark>-financed <mark>factions are not crossing the</mark> southwest <mark>border.</mark> </u></strong>They point instead to the 327 airports and border crossings in the United States where legitimate or forged passports might be used the same way that 19 hijackers gained access to carry out the 9/11 attacks. "<u><strong>The last thing these <mark>organizations</mark> want is to start out at the border with a high profile criminal act that gets attention</u></strong>," says James Carafano, a West Point graduate and retired Army lieutenant colonel handling security affairs at the Heritage Foundation. "<u><strong>They <mark>want to be</mark> as <mark>unobtrusive as possible</mark>." Federal law enforcement agents picked up 445,000 border crossers last year. But only 13 Iranians were taken into custody,</u></strong> a fraction of the 663 "special interest aliens" from 35 countries detained along the southwestern border for special U.S. scrutiny. None of the Iranians - indeed none of the 663 "special interest aliens" - has faced federal prosecution on terror-related charges, according to federal officials. <u><strong>No credible cases <mark>The number</mark> of Iranians <mark>apprehended by U.S. Border Patrol "has been historically minimal</mark>," said a Department of Homeland Security official. "<mark>No credible terrorist threat has been identified</mark>, however <mark>DHS carefully monitors any potential threats along the</mark> Southwest <mark>border and responds accordingly</mark>."</p></u></strong>
1NR
Cartels
No Cartel Terror
296,348
3
16,989
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Round2.docx
564,705
N
Kentucky
2
Mary Washington SY
Rebecca Steiner
1ac was marihuana legalization with advantages of cartels and econ 1nc was t legalization security kritik gop bad midterms da the marijuana word pic and case 2nc was security 1nr was t and case 2nr was security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Round2.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,911
“I SWEAR by Apollo the physician, I will keep this Oath…
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>“I SWEAR by Apollo the physician, I will keep this Oath… </h4>
null
1AC
null
430,041
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,912
The spread of biopolitics based on securing a vital community forms and categorizes discursive identities based on sexuality as a means of social control – Marc Spindelman describes how one such identity trope is manifested in PAS discourses through the figure of the gay man with AIDS whose sexuality damned him into seeking death – only rejecting sex as truth overcomes this form of biopower – Thomas Roach explains
null
Thomas J., Ph.D, professor at Professor of English and Cultural Studies at Bryant University’s Center for Cultural Studies, “Sense and Sexuality: Foucault, Wojnarowicz, and Biopower.” Nebula, Vol. 6:3, Fall 2009 SJE
biopower encourages an art of living: thou shalt live a good life as devised by state informed¶ expert knowledge The family, medicine, psychiatry, education, and employers¶ cooperate with state apparatuses to ensure a uniform standard of living, to produce subjectivities that secure a “vital population.” secularized,¶ techniques of pastoral power function under biopower to ensure a worldly salvation of health, security,¶ sufficient wealth, and citizenship sexuality is the central dispositif deployed by the modern state and capital¶ to manage life directly, the site at which biopower’s individuating and totalizing techniques converge sexuality is mobilized as a hermeneutic of desire to reveal the truth of the subject and fasten¶ it to an identity. The¶ discursive link between sexual desire and self-identity—that is, "sexuality"—is thus implemented as a means of social control, deterring movements of collective revolt and imprisoning bodies and pleasures In order to resist the biopolitical administration of life the link between sex and¶ truth must be broken.
biopower encourages an art of living a good life as devised by state knowledge medicine education cooperate with state apparatuses to ensure a uniform standard of living, to produce subjectivities that secure a “vital population.” secularized,¶ techniques function under biopower to ensure a worldly salvation of health, security wealth, and citizenship sexuality is the central dispositif deployed by the state and capital¶ to manage life directly, the site at which biopower’s individuating and totalizing techniques converge. sexuality is mobilized to reveal the truth of the subject and fasten¶ it to an identity. The¶ discursive link between sexual desire and self-identity sexuality is implemented as a means of social control, In order to resist the biopolitical administration of life the link between sex and¶ truth must be broken.
At the risk of rehearsing the familiar story of biopower's conceptual life, I begin by doing so for¶ two reasons: first, to emphasize the centrality of sexuality in Foucault's rendering of the concept; and¶ second, to show precisely how Hardt and Negri desexualize it. Foucault begins his account in the¶ seventeenth century when a "power over life" emerges as a tendency alongside an earlier, overtly repressive, penal form of power that disciplined subjects through juridical systems. In contrast to a¶ negative form of freedom predicated upon "thou shalt not," which found its logical conclusion in public¶ spectacles of death, biopower encourages an art of living: thou shalt live a good life as devised by state informed¶ expert knowledge; thou shalt do what is best for you, which conveniently coincides with what¶ is best for biopolitical administration. The family, medicine, psychiatry, education, and employers¶ cooperate with state apparatuses to ensure a uniform standard of living, to produce subjectivities and¶ forms of life that secure a “vital population.” A docile subject is produced when procedures of¶ totalization combine with techniques of individualization, or, in Foucault’s vocabulary, when the¶ anatomo-politics of the body and the biopolitics of the population become two poles in the art of¶ governance. These poles correspond chronologically to different historical moments: the anatomopolitics¶ of the body, “the first to be formed it seems […] centered on the body as a machine: its¶ disciplining, the optimization of its capabilities, the extortion of its forces," while the biopolitics of the¶ population, “formed somewhat later, focused on the species body, the body imbued with the mechanics¶ of life and serving as the basis of the biological processes.”6¶ The anatomo-politics of the body and the¶ biopolitics of the population play two roles in the operation of biopower: the former, analytical,¶ concerning the individual, the latter, quantitative, concerning the population. In an essay entitled "The¶ Subject and Power" we learn that biopower derives from a form of power implemented in archaic¶ Christian institutions—what Foucault designates pastoral power.7¶ Christian pastoral power promised¶ individuals salvation in the afterlife while anchoring one’s earthly life in a community of believers. Its¶ efficacy lay in its ability to govern a population both as individuals and as a mass. Now secularized,¶ techniques of pastoral power function under biopower to ensure a worldly salvation of health, security,¶ sufficient wealth, and citizenship (334-5). On Foucault's view, sexuality is the central dispositif deployed by the modern state and capital¶ to manage life directly, the site at which biopower’s individuating and totalizing techniques converge.¶ In the psychiatrization and medicalization of sexuality the individual becomes legible, recordable,¶ disciplined: sexuality is mobilized as a hermeneutic of desire to reveal the truth of the subject and fasten¶ it to an identity. At the same time this marker of individuality becomes useful in administering a social¶ totality. Techniques of the state such as the population census, fertility rates, and statistics of life¶ expectancy appeal to this hermeneutic to organize individual subjects into a manageable whole. The¶ discursive link between sexual desire and self-identity—that is, "sexuality"—is thus implemented as a means of social control, deterring movements of collective revolt and imprisoning bodies and pleasures.¶ In order to resist the biopolitical administration of life, according to Foucault, the link between sex and¶ truth must be broken.
3,664
<h4>The spread of biopolitics based on securing a vital community forms and categorizes discursive identities based on sexuality as a means of social control – Marc Spindelman describes how one such identity trope is manifested in PAS discourses through the figure of the gay man with AIDS whose sexuality damned him into seeking death – only rejecting sex as truth overcomes this form of biopower – Thomas Roach explains</h4><p>Thomas J., Ph.D, professor at Professor of English and Cultural Studies at Bryant University’s Center for Cultural Studies, “Sense and Sexuality: Foucault, Wojnarowicz, and Biopower.” Nebula, Vol. 6:3, Fall 2009 SJE </p><p><u><strong> </p><p></u></strong>At the risk of rehearsing the familiar story of biopower's conceptual life, I begin by doing so for¶ two reasons: first, to emphasize the centrality of sexuality in Foucault's rendering of the concept; and¶ second, to show precisely how Hardt and Negri desexualize it. Foucault begins his account in the¶ seventeenth century when a "power over life" emerges as a tendency alongside an earlier, overtly repressive, penal form of power that disciplined subjects through juridical systems. In contrast to a¶ negative form of freedom predicated upon "thou shalt not," which found its logical conclusion in public¶ spectacles of death, <u><mark>biopower encourages an art of living</mark>: thou shalt live <mark>a good life as devised by state</mark> informed¶ expert <mark>knowledge</u></mark>; thou shalt do what is best for you, which conveniently coincides with what¶ is best for biopolitical administration. <u>The family, <mark>medicine</mark>, psychiatry, <mark>education</mark>, and employers¶ <mark>cooperate with state apparatuses to ensure a uniform standard of living, to produce subjectivities </u></mark>and¶ forms of life <u><strong><mark>that secure a “vital population.”</u></strong></mark> A docile subject is produced when procedures of¶ totalization combine with techniques of individualization, or, in Foucault’s vocabulary, when the¶ anatomo-politics of the body and the biopolitics of the population become two poles in the art of¶ governance. These poles correspond chronologically to different historical moments: the anatomopolitics¶ of the body, “the first to be formed it seems […] centered on the body as a machine: its¶ disciplining, the optimization of its capabilities, the extortion of its forces," while the biopolitics of the¶ population, “formed somewhat later, focused on the species body, the body imbued with the mechanics¶ of life and serving as the basis of the biological processes.”6¶ The anatomo-politics of the body and the¶ biopolitics of the population play two roles in the operation of biopower: the former, analytical,¶ concerning the individual, the latter, quantitative, concerning the population. In an essay entitled "The¶ Subject and Power" we learn that biopower derives from a form of power implemented in archaic¶ Christian institutions—what Foucault designates pastoral power.7¶ Christian pastoral power promised¶ individuals salvation in the afterlife while anchoring one’s earthly life in a community of believers. Its¶ efficacy lay in its ability to govern a population both as individuals and as a mass. Now <u><mark>secularized,¶ techniques </mark>of pastoral power <mark>function under biopower to ensure a worldly salvation of health, security</mark>,¶ sufficient <mark>wealth, and citizenship</u></mark> (334-5). On Foucault's view, <u><mark>sexuality is the central dispositif deployed by the </mark>modern <mark>state and capital¶ to manage life directly, the site at which biopower’s individuating and totalizing techniques converge</u>.</mark>¶ In the psychiatrization and medicalization of sexuality the individual becomes legible, recordable,¶ disciplined: <u><mark>sexuality is mobilized</mark> as a hermeneutic of desire <strong><mark>to reveal the truth of the subject and fasten¶ it to an identity.</u></strong></mark> At the same time this marker of individuality becomes useful in administering a social¶ totality. Techniques of the state such as the population census, fertility rates, and statistics of life¶ expectancy appeal to this hermeneutic to organize individual subjects into a manageable whole. <u><mark>The¶ discursive link between sexual desire and self-identity</mark>—that is, "<mark>sexuality</mark>"—<mark>is</mark> thus <mark>implemented as a means of social control,</mark> deterring movements of collective revolt and imprisoning bodies and pleasures</u>.¶ <u><strong><mark>In order to resist the biopolitical administration of life</u></strong></mark>, according to Foucault,<u><strong> <mark>the link between sex and¶ truth must be broken.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
null
430,006
3
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,913
Depoliticization DA: Their government focused problem-solving approach depoliticizes politics and reduces it to calculations, constraining debate
Peker 06
Peker 06
Efe, Sessional Instructor of Sociology @ Simon Fraser U. Linkopings Universitet. “Following 9/11: George W. Bush’s Discursive Re-articulation of American Social Identity” This is to say that politics is about the rooted organizations of the administrative structure, and the relevant discourse that is established through a consolidated dominant ideology; which create subjects that do not question or look for solutions elsewhere but the boundaries of a particular system. The problem-solving approaches of politics, takes the world as it finds it, with the prevailing social and power relationships and the institutions into which they are organized, as the given framework for action. Edkins terms the process depoliticization referring to the limitation of political action to the calculable, the instrumental, especially in the modern Western democracies: the total domination of rational calculability and planning, the triumph of instrumental reason rationality in the form of such obedience swallows up everything, even the freedom to think”.
politics is about the rooted organizations of the administrative structure, and discourse established through dominant ideology; which create subjects that do not question or look for solutions elsewhere but the boundaries of a particular system problem-solving takes the world as it finds it, with the prevailing social and power relationships and the institutions into which they are organized, as the given framework for action the limitation of political action to the calculable domination of rational calculability and planning rationality in the form of such obedience swallows up everything, even the freedom to think”.
Efe, Sessional Instructor of Sociology @ Simon Fraser U. Linkopings Universitet. “Following 9/11: George W. Bush’s Discursive Re-articulation of American Social Identity” In her work Poststructuralism and International Relations, Jenny Edkins emphasizes a distinction between what she terms politics and the political. Politics, according to her, has got to do with elections, political parties, the doings of governments and parliaments, the state apparatus, and in the case of international politics, treaties, international agreements, diplomacy, wars, institutions of which states are members… and the actions of statesmen and – women.” This is to say that politics is about the rooted organizations of the administrative structure, and the relevant discourse that is established through a consolidated dominant ideology; which create subjects that do not question or look for solutions elsewhere but the boundaries of a particular system. The problem-solving approaches of politics, as Cox puts it, takes the world as it finds it, with the prevailing social and power relationships and the institutions into which they are organized, as the given framework for action. Edkins terms the process depoliticization or technologization, each of which referring to the limitation of political action to the calculable, the instrumental, especially in the modern Western democracies: the total domination of rational calculability and planning, the triumph of instrumental reason, as Simon Critchley interprets it. The philosophy of this world is essentially rationalistic, Max Horkheimer utters in The End of Reason, and warns us: “rationality in the form of such obedience swallows up everything, even the freedom to think”.
1,724
<h4><u>Depoliticization DA: </u><strong>Their government focused problem-solving approach depoliticizes politics and reduces it to calculations, constraining debate</h4><p>Peker 06</p><p><u>Efe, Sessional Instructor of Sociology @ Simon Fraser U. Linkopings Universitet. “Following 9/11: George W. Bush’s Discursive Re-articulation of American Social Identity” </p><p></u></strong>In her work Poststructuralism and International Relations, Jenny Edkins emphasizes a distinction between what she terms politics and the political. Politics, according to her, has got to do with elections, political parties, the doings of governments and parliaments, the state apparatus, and in the case of international politics, treaties, international agreements, diplomacy, wars, institutions of which states are members… and the actions of statesmen and – women.” <u><strong>This is to say that <mark>politics is about the rooted organizations of the administrative structure, and</mark> the relevant <mark>discourse</mark> that is <mark>established through</mark> a consolidated <mark>dominant ideology; which create subjects that do not question or look for solutions elsewhere but the boundaries of a particular system</mark>. The <mark>problem-solving</mark> approaches of politics, </u></strong>as Cox puts it, <u><strong><mark>takes the world as it finds it, with the prevailing social and power relationships and the institutions into which they are organized, as the given framework for action</mark>.</u></strong> <u><strong>Edkins terms the process depoliticization</u></strong> or technologization, each of which <u><strong>referring to <mark>the limitation of political action to the calculable</mark>, the instrumental, especially in the modern Western democracies: the total <mark>domination of rational calculability and planning</mark>, the triumph of instrumental reason</u></strong>, as Simon Critchley interprets it. The philosophy of this world is essentially rationalistic, Max Horkheimer utters in The End of Reason, and warns us: “<u><strong><mark>rationality in the form of such obedience swallows up everything, even the freedom to think”.</p></u></strong></mark>
2AC
FW
AT: Gov Edu Best
422,051
2
16,993
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
564,698
A
NDT
3
UTD LO
Heidt, Shook, Lundberg
1AC PAS genealogy- same assimilar to USC PAS 1AC 1NC T- Framework K- Szaz Medicalization of death 2NR T
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,914
*Here’s more evidence - It’s resilient and rising in popularity
Senechal, their author 14 , Senior Policy Manager, Executive Secretary, ICC Banking Commission, the United Nations, the World Trade Organization, the G20 and many other intergovernmental bodies, both international and regional, are kept in touch with the views of international business through ICC, “2014: Rethinking Trade and Finance,” google scholar)
Senechal, their author 14 – (2014, collaborative production of the International Chamber of Commerce, edited by Thierry Senechal, Senior Policy Manager, Executive Secretary, ICC Banking Commission, the United Nations, the World Trade Organization, the G20 and many other intergovernmental bodies, both international and regional, are kept in touch with the views of international business through ICC, “2014: Rethinking Trade and Finance,” google scholar)
Trade finance will never go away It will continue to evolve with market requirements and technological progress. It will become more standardized - over the next few years. The popularity of trade finance securitization will have gained momentum. As world trade continues to grow, a more fluid secondary market will enable banks to meet the ever growing requirements of end users, supporting economic development globally. There is already evidence of ample demand amongst institutional investors.
Trade finance will never go away. It will continue to evolve with market requirements and tech progress. It will become more standardized over the next few years. The popularity of trade finance will gain momentum. As world trade continues to grow, a more fluid secondary market will enable banks to meet the ever growing requirements of end users, supporting economic development globally. There is already evidence of ample demand
> DANI COTTI: Trade finance will never go away. It will continue to evolve with market requirements and technological progress. It will become more standardized - along with many financial instruments - over the next few years. The popularity of trade finance securitization will have gained momentum. As world trade continues to grow, a more fluid secondary market will enable banks to meet the ever growing requirements of end users, supporting economic development globally. There is already evidence of ample demand amongst institutional investors.
552
<h4>*Here’s more evidence - It’s resilient and rising in popularity</h4><p><u><strong>Senechal, their author 14</u></strong> – (2014, collaborative production of the International Chamber of Commerce, edited by Thierry Senechal<u><strong>, Senior Policy Manager, Executive Secretary, ICC Banking Commission, the United Nations, the World Trade Organization, the G20 and many other intergovernmental bodies, both international and regional, are kept in touch with the views of international business through ICC, “2014: Rethinking Trade and Finance,” google scholar)</p><p></u></strong>> DANI COTTI: <u><strong><mark>Trade finance will never go away</u></strong>. <u>It will continue to evolve with market requirements and tech</mark>nological <mark>progress. It will become <strong>more standardized</strong></mark> </u>- along with many financial instruments <u>- <mark>over the next few years. The <strong>popularity</strong> of trade finance</mark> securitization <mark>will</mark> have <strong><mark>gain</strong></mark>ed <strong><mark>momentum</strong>. As world trade continues to grow, a more fluid <strong>secondary market</strong> will enable banks to meet the ever growing requirements of end users, <strong>supporting economic development globally</strong>. There is already evidence of ample demand</mark> amongst institutional investors.</p></u>
1NR
Banks
2NC Trade Finance Resilient
430,042
3
16,987
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round1.docx
564,729
N
NDT
1
Harvard DH
Eric Short, Chris Thiele, Dan Stout
1ac was online gambling with econ and china advantages 1nc was security edelman and case 2nc was security 1nr was case 2nr was security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round1.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,915
US masks its interests under the guise of saving mexico which demonstrates a form of benign imperialism which causes violence
Jalbert 13
Jalbert 13 (Elie Jalbert, BA honors in anthropology at Concordia University, “Emergency as Security: Liberal Empire at Home and Abroad,” pp 31-2, GENDER MODIFIED) gz
U.S. history is fraught with contradiction. There seems to have¶ been a persistent divide between its represented self-image and its¶ actions in the world It has promoted its¶ exceptional nature and asserted its difference from all previous¶ empires, advocating fundamental human rights and opportunity¶ for all, though its society has been one of profound segregation¶ with a foreign policy more often than not brutal,¶ repressive, and indeed essentially imperialistic a foreign policy that then in turn transformed domestic¶ policy by importing its policing practices back home Founded on the genocide of its Indigenous¶ population, the U.S. has defined its brave and free persona by glorifying¶ its revolution that shook off the empire’s grip, yet has been¶ leading a global counterinsurgent “War on Terrorism” that defines¶ resistance as a threat that must be eliminated the contrast of a projected benign history¶ of the quest for freedom and rights with the reality of American¶ ascent to global domination there is “an almost pathological tendency to confuse¶ American ideal with historical political reality,” and a constant¶ tension between “liberty and power, freedom and authority, contract¶ and coercion, and law and violence this sense of exceptionalism to be underpinned by¶ a Spencerian theory of social evolution that presents American industry¶ as the pinnacle of [humanity’s] ever ascending rise to perfection This “social Darwinism” that applied biological notions of survival¶ of the fittest to human society provided legitimacy for rapacious¶ and competitive social and economic practices by presenting them¶ as a natural and normal continuation of evolution toward complexity reminiscent of the Malthusian arguments discussed earlier,¶ that rooted their reasoning in the laws of nature so as to give them¶ an air of inevitability
U.S. history is fraught with contradiction between its self-image and its¶ actions It has asserted its difference from all previous¶ empires, advocating human rights and opportunity though its society has been one of profound segregation with a foreign policy brutal,¶ repressive, and imperialistic importing its policing practices back home Founded on the genocide of its Indigenous¶ population, the U.S. defined its persona by glorifying¶ its revolution yet has been¶ leading a “War on Terrorism” that defines¶ resistance as a threat that must be eliminated there is “a pathological tendency to confuse¶ American ideal with historical reality this sense of exceptionalism presents American industry¶ as the pinnacle of [humanity’s] perfection.¶ This “social Darwinism” that applied survival¶ of the fittest to human society provided legitimacy for rapacious practices by presenting them¶ as a natural continuation of evolution reminiscent of Malthusian arguments that rooted their reasoning in the laws of nature to give them¶ an air of inevitability.
U.S. history is fraught with contradiction. There seems to have¶ been a persistent divide between its represented self-image and its¶ actions in the world. It has viewed itself as a land of the free,¶ where individuals have free reign to maximize their wealth and¶ pursue happiness without the constraints of government inhibiting¶ their freedom, while ignoring the way in which government typically¶ enforced the rights of one group over another (McCaull, 1976)¶ and provided the infrastructure and investments that made development¶ possible (Novak, 2008; Limerick, 2012). It has promoted its¶ exceptional nature and asserted its difference from all previous¶ empires, advocating fundamental human rights and opportunity¶ for all, though its society has been one of profound segregation¶ (Perlstein, 2006), with a foreign policy more often than not brutal,¶ repressive, and indeed essentially imperialistic (Chomsky, 1998;¶ McCoy, 2009)—a foreign policy that then in turn transformed domestic¶ policy by importing its policing practices back home (McCoy¶ & Scarano, 2009; Chomsky, 1999; De Genova, 2010; Steinmetz,¶ 2005, pp. 357–361). Founded on the genocide of its Indigenous¶ population, the U.S. has defined its brave and free persona by glorifying¶ its revolution that shook off the empire’s grip, yet has been¶ leading a global counterinsurgent “War on Terrorism” that defines¶ resistance as a threat that must be eliminated.¶ One such contradiction—the contrast of a projected benign history¶ of the quest for freedom and rights with the reality of American¶ ascent to global domination—is discussed by Novak (2008). In¶ addressing what he calls the “myth of the ‘weak’ American state”,¶ he shows how there is “an almost pathological tendency to confuse¶ American ideal with historical political reality,” and a constant¶ tension between “liberty and power, freedom and authority, contract¶ and coercion, and law and violence” (Novak, 2008, p. 754). In¶ the author’s view, the myth of an American weak state has its¶ roots in an exceptionalist view of the U.S as being a new world exempted¶ from previous political histories by a “so-called ‘natural’¶ development of individualism, private rights, civil society, free labour,¶ and a free economy” (Novak, 2008, pp. 754–755). McCaull¶ (1976) considers this sense of exceptionalism to be underpinned by¶ a Spencerian theory of social evolution that presents American industry¶ as the pinnacle of man’s [humanity’s] ever ascending rise to perfection.¶ This “social Darwinism” that applied biological notions of survival¶ of the fittest to human society provided legitimacy for rapacious¶ and competitive social and economic practices by presenting them¶ as a natural and normal continuation of evolution toward complexity.¶ Spencer’s theory was thus co-opted by American industrialists¶ as a powerful “scientific” tool of laissez faire capitalism legitimation,¶ reminiscent of the Malthusian arguments discussed earlier,¶ that rooted their reasoning in the laws of nature so as to give them¶ an air of inevitability.
3,072
<h4>US masks its interests under the guise of saving mexico which demonstrates a form of benign imperialism which causes violence</h4><p><u><strong>Jalbert 13</u></strong> (Elie Jalbert, BA honors in anthropology at Concordia University, “Emergency as Security: Liberal Empire at Home and Abroad,” pp 31-2, GENDER MODIFIED) gz </p><p><u><mark>U.S. history is fraught with contradiction</mark>. There seems to have¶ been a persistent divide <mark>between its</mark> represented <mark>self-image and its¶ actions</mark> in the world</u>. It has viewed itself as a land of the free,¶ where individuals have free reign to maximize their wealth and¶ pursue happiness without the constraints of government inhibiting¶ their freedom, while ignoring the way in which government typically¶ enforced the rights of one group over another (McCaull, 1976)¶ and provided the infrastructure and investments that made development¶ possible (Novak, 2008; Limerick, 2012). <u><mark>It has</mark> promoted its¶ exceptional nature and <mark>asserted its difference from all previous¶ empires, advocating</mark> fundamental <mark>human rights and opportunity</mark>¶ for all, <mark>though its society has been one of profound <strong>segregation</strong></mark>¶ </u>(Perlstein, 2006), <u><mark>with a foreign policy</mark> more often than not <strong><mark>brutal,¶ repressive</strong>, and</mark> indeed essentially <strong><mark>imperialistic</u></strong></mark> (Chomsky, 1998;¶ McCoy, 2009)—<u>a foreign policy that then in turn transformed domestic¶ policy by <strong><mark>importing its policing practices</strong> back home</u></mark> (McCoy¶ & Scarano, 2009; Chomsky, 1999; De Genova, 2010; Steinmetz,¶ 2005, pp. 357–361). <u><strong><mark>Founded on the genocide of its Indigenous¶ population</strong>, the U.S.</mark> has <mark>defined its</mark> brave and free <mark>persona by glorifying¶ its revolution</mark> that shook off the empire’s grip, <mark>yet has been¶ leading a</mark> global counterinsurgent <mark>“War on Terrorism” that <strong>defines¶ resistance as a threat that must be eliminated</u></strong></mark>.¶ One such contradiction—<u>the contrast of a projected benign history¶ of the quest for freedom and rights with the reality of American¶ ascent to <strong>global domination</u></strong>—is discussed by Novak (2008). In¶ addressing what he calls the “myth of the ‘weak’ American state”,¶ he shows how <u><mark>there is “<strong>a</mark>n almost <mark>pathological tendency</strong> to confuse¶ American ideal with historical</mark> political <mark>reality</mark>,” and a constant¶ tension between “<strong>liberty and power</strong>, <strong>freedom and authority</strong>, <strong>contract¶ and coercion</strong>, and <strong>law and violence</u></strong>” (Novak, 2008, p. 754). In¶ the author’s view, the myth of an American weak state has its¶ roots in an exceptionalist view of the U.S as being a new world exempted¶ from previous political histories by a “so-called ‘natural’¶ development of individualism, private rights, civil society, free labour,¶ and a free economy” (Novak, 2008, pp. 754–755). McCaull¶ (1976) considers <u><mark>this sense of exceptionalism</mark> to be underpinned by¶ a Spencerian theory of social evolution that <mark>presents American industry¶ as the <strong>pinnacle of </u></strong></mark>man’s<u><strong> <mark>[humanity’s]</mark> ever ascending rise to <mark>perfection</u></strong>.¶ <u>This “<strong>social Darwinism</strong>” that applied</mark> biological notions of <mark>survival¶ of the fittest to human society provided legitimacy for rapacious</mark>¶ and competitive social and economic <mark>practices by presenting them¶ as a natural</mark> and normal <mark>continuation of evolution</mark> toward complexity</u>.¶ Spencer’s theory was thus co-opted by American industrialists¶ as a powerful “scientific” tool of laissez faire capitalism legitimation,¶ <u><mark>reminiscent of</mark> the <strong><mark>Malthusian arguments</strong></mark> discussed earlier,¶ <mark>that rooted their reasoning in the laws of nature</mark> so as <mark>to give them¶ an air of inevitability</u>.</p></mark>
2NC
K
Link – Mexico
91,443
4
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,916
Terrorism will not cause extinction
Kato ‘8
Kato ‘8
It is encouraging to see the emergence of a new strategic discussion within the United States that recognizes the fact that nonstate actors such as al Qaeda "do not pose an existential threat" to the United States Al Qaeda possesses neither the strategic vision nor the capability to topple the existing world order and U.S. predominance
nonstate actors such as al Qaeda "do not pose an existential threat" Al Qaeda possesses neither the vision nor t capability to topple the world order and U.S. predominance
(Yoichi, bureau chief of the American General Bureau of the Asahi Shimbun, “Return from 9/11 PTSD to Global Leader,” Washington Quarterly, Fall 2008, lexis) The administration has become a prisoner to the newly emergent threats that it faces. It is therefore encouraging to see the emergence of a new strategic discussion within the United States that recognizes the fact that nonstate actors such as al Qaeda "do not pose an existential threat" to the United States. 4 Al Qaeda rejects the expansion of U.S. values, especially in the Middle East, and has proven that it can inflict enormous pain on the United States and its friends and allies and disrupt regions and the globe through terrorist attacks. Yet, it possesses neither the strategic vision nor the capability to topple the existing world order and U.S. predominance. Overreactions based on the overestimation of such threats were the fundamental reasons underlying the failure of the current U.S. strategy. A calm and objective reassessment of the threats and challenges must be the first step toward restoration of the U.S. reputation.
1,099
<h4><strong>Terrorism will not cause extinction </h4><p>Kato ‘8</p><p></strong>(Yoichi, bureau chief of the American General Bureau of the Asahi Shimbun, “Return from 9/11 PTSD to Global Leader,” Washington Quarterly, Fall 2008, lexis) </p><p>The administration has become a prisoner to the newly emergent threats that it faces. <u><strong>It is</u></strong> therefore <u><strong>encouraging to see the emergence of a new strategic discussion within the United States that recognizes the fact that <mark>nonstate actors such as al Qaeda "do not pose an existential threat" </mark>to the United States</u></strong>. <strong>4</strong> <u><strong><mark>Al Qaeda</u></strong> </mark>rejects the expansion of U.S. values, especially in the Middle East, and has proven that it can inflict enormous pain on the United States and its friends and allies and disrupt regions and the globe through terrorist attacks. Yet, it <u><strong><mark>possesses neither the</mark> strategic <mark>vision nor t</mark>he <mark>capability to topple the </mark>existing <mark>world order and U.S. predominance</u></strong></mark>. Overreactions based on the overestimation of such threats were the fundamental reasons underlying the failure of the current U.S. strategy. A calm and objective reassessment of the threats and challenges must be the first step toward restoration of the U.S. reputation.</p>
1NR
Cartels
No Nuke Terror
430,043
1
16,989
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Round2.docx
564,705
N
Kentucky
2
Mary Washington SY
Rebecca Steiner
1ac was marihuana legalization with advantages of cartels and econ 1nc was t legalization security kritik gop bad midterms da the marijuana word pic and case 2nc was security 1nr was t and case 2nr was security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Round2.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,917
Legalization of prostitution means government regulation
Jacobson ‘14
Jacobson ‘14
four legal responses to prostitution have arisen: complete criminalization, legalization, complete decriminalization, and partial decriminalization Complete criminalization makes both the sale and purchase of sex illegal. Legalization makes both the sale and purchase of sex legal but brings it under heavy government regulation Complete decriminalization removes criminal punishment and sanction for the purchase and sale of sex, whereas partial decriminalization continues to make the purchase of sex illegal while decriminalizing the sale of sex
four legal responses to prostitution have arisen complete criminalization legalization complete decriminalization, and partial decriminalization Legalization makes both the sale and purchase of sex legal but brings it under heavy government regulation.
[Brynn, J.D. Candidate. Seattle University School of Law, 2014; B.A., Political Science, University of Washington, 2010. “Addressing the Tension Between the Dual Identities of the American Prostitute: Criminal and Victim; How Problem-Solving Courts Can Help.” 37 Seattle Univ. L. R. 1023. ETB] Prostitution and its legal status are the subject of a heated global debate. n7 Currently, prostitution is illegal everywhere in the United States except Nevada, where it is legal in several counties. n8 An important consideration of that debate is how prostitution laws affect law enforcement's ability to identify and prosecute sex traffickers, or "pimps" as they are commonly known. n9 To date, there is still no uniform approach to trafficking prosecutions in the United States, and many states continue to criminalize the acts of prostitutes while failing to enforce criminal laws against those who exploit them. n10 As a result of this debate, four legal responses to prostitution have arisen: complete criminalization, legalization, complete decriminalization, and partial decriminalization. n11 Complete criminalization makes both the sale and purchase of sex illegal. n12 Legalization makes both the sale and purchase of sex legal but brings it under heavy government regulation. n13 Complete decriminalization removes criminal punishment and sanction for the purchase and sale of sex, whereas partial decriminalization continues to make the purchase of sex illegal while decriminalizing the sale of sex. n14 Based on a utilitarian analysis, which recognizes the value of these four theories, this Comment reaches the conclusion that any scheme of legalization or decriminalization is not the optimal solution to the problem of prostitution because it leaves victims in a worse situation than they are currently in and subjects them to further exploitation. This Comment argues for continued criminalization for prostitution in the United States. An appropriate way to deal with women arrested for prostitution is to set up a problem-solving court, similar to a drug court, which would provide a multidisciplinary approach to helping those trapped in prostitution.
2,167
<h4><u><strong>Legalization of prostitution means government regulation</h4><p>Jacobson ‘14</p><p></u></strong>[Brynn, J.D. Candidate. Seattle University School of Law, 2014; B.A., Political Science, University of Washington, 2010. “Addressing the Tension Between the Dual Identities of the American Prostitute: Criminal and Victim; How Problem-Solving Courts Can Help.” 37 Seattle Univ. L. R. 1023. ETB]</p><p>Prostitution and its legal status are the subject of a heated global debate. n7 Currently, prostitution is illegal everywhere in the United States except Nevada, where it is legal in several counties. n8 An important consideration of that debate is how prostitution laws affect law enforcement's ability to identify and prosecute sex traffickers, or "pimps" as they are commonly known. n9 To date, there is still no uniform approach to trafficking prosecutions in the United States, and many states continue to criminalize the acts of prostitutes while failing to enforce criminal laws against those who exploit them. n10 As a result of this debate, <u><mark>four legal responses to prostitution have arisen</mark>: <mark>complete</mark> <mark>criminalization</mark>, <mark>legalization</mark>, <mark>complete decriminalization, and partial decriminalization</u></mark>. n11 <u>Complete criminalization makes both the sale and purchase of sex illegal.</u> n12 <u><mark>Legalization makes both the sale and purchase of sex legal but brings it under <strong>heavy</strong> government regulation</u>.</mark> n13 <u>Complete decriminalization removes criminal punishment and sanction for the purchase and sale of sex, whereas partial decriminalization continues to make the purchase of sex illegal while decriminalizing the sale of sex</u>. n14 Based on a utilitarian analysis, which recognizes the value of these four theories, this Comment reaches the conclusion that any scheme of legalization or decriminalization is not the optimal solution to the problem of prostitution because it leaves victims in a worse situation than they are currently in and subjects them to further exploitation. This Comment argues for continued criminalization for prostitution in the United States. An appropriate way to deal with women arrested for prostitution is to set up a problem-solving court, similar to a drug court, which would provide a multidisciplinary approach to helping those trapped in prostitution.</p>
1NC
null
Off
429,723
7
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,918
I will follow that system of regimen which… I consider for the benefit of my patients, and abstain from whatever is deleterious…
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>I will follow that system of regimen which… I consider for the benefit of my patients, and abstain from whatever is deleterious…</h4>
null
1AC
null
430,044
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,919
Status quo justifications for PAS are based on a notion of autonomy which upholds a neoliberal notion of rights and individuation – our project consists of a disruption of those illusory forms of subjectivity – Scott Shershow, when discussing the right to die, posits two important questions: first, “can the political and legal concepts of “rights” or “freedom” apply to something that, so to speak, marks the very limit of all rights and all freedom?” and second “can one really conceive of a right to that which comes inescapably to all whether they like it or not?”
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Status quo justifications for PAS are based on a notion of autonomy which upholds a neoliberal notion of rights and individuation – our project consists of a disruption of those illusory forms of subjectivity – Scott Shershow, when discussing the right to die, posits two important questions: first, “can the political and legal concepts of “rights” or “freedom” apply to something that, so to speak, marks the very limit of all rights and all freedom?” and second “can one really conceive of a right to that which comes inescapably to all whether they like it or not?”<u><strong> </h4></u></strong>
null
null
null
430,045
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,920
Deliberative democracy is a floating signifier that can be filled with any number of ideologies. The result is the exploitative violence of an alienated capitalist society.
Dean 07
Dean 07 Jodi Dean Ph.D., Columbia M.A., Columbia, B.A., PrincetonThe Democratic Deadlock, Theory & Event, 10:4, Project Muse | © 2007
The Left, although seemingly opposed to the Bush administration, also appeals to democracy as that which it wishes to restore, redeem, or reach. Why does the Left continue to appeal to democracy to accept this horizon is to accept an impoverished political field, a diminishment of aspirations to something better. We accept the limitation of democracy, convinced that this is as good as it gets. constitutional democracies privilege the wealthy. They exclude, exploit, and oppress the poor. Despite democracy's inability to represent justice in the social field left political theorists continue to appeal to arrangements that can be filled in, by fundamentalisms, nationalisms, populisms, and conservatisms diametrically opposed to progressive visions of social and economic equality. We proceed as if democracy were already the solution to contemporary political problems rather than symptomatic of them.
Why does the Left continue to appeal to democracy We accept the limitation of democracy, convinced that this is as good as it gets. constitutional democracies privilege the wealthy. They exclude, exploit, and oppress the poor. Despite democracy's inability to represent justice in the social field that theorists continue to appeal to arrangements that can be filled in, by fundamentalisms, nationalisms, populisms, and conservatisms diametrically opposed to progressive visions of social and economic equality . We proceed as if democracy were already the solution to contemporary political problems rather than symptomatic of them
A commonplace of media punditry in the middle years of the first decade of the twenty-first century concerns the deep divide in American politics. Whether in terms of political parties, red states and blue states, support or opposition to US militarism in Afghanistan and Iraq, or the ongoing culture war between the religious right and the secular left, the United States is depicted as a nation split in its fundamental ethico-political self-understanding. This depiction is misleading. It occludes the way these seeming opponents continue to appeal to democracy. Thus, the administration of George W. Bush presents itself as actively engaged in bringing democracy to the Middle East, as encouraging countries throughout the world to strengthen their democratic institutions. The Left, although seemingly opposed to the Bush administration, also appeals to democracy as that which it wishes to restore, redeem, or reach. Why does the Left continue to appeal to democracy? Is democracy, as Slavoj Žižek asks, the ultimate horizon of political thought?1 For Žižek, to accept this horizon is to accept an impoverished political field, a diminishment of aspirations to something better. We accept the limitation of democracy, convinced that this is as good as it gets. Real existing constitutional democracies privilege the wealthy. They exclude, exploit, and oppress the poor. Crucial determinants of our lives and conditions remain outside the frame of political deliberation and response. The expansion and intensification of networked communications that was supposed to enhance democratic participation integrates and consolidates communicative capitalism.2 Nevertheless, we on the Left continue to present our political hopes as aspirations to democracy. Despite democracy's inability to represent justice in the social field that has emerged in the incompatibility between the global neoliberal economy and states' willingness to retain the promise of social security and collective welfare, left political and cultural theorists continue to appeal to arrangements that can be filled in, substantialized, by fundamentalisms, nationalisms, populisms, and conservatisms diametrically opposed to progressive visions of social and economic equality. Continuing to appeal to democracy, we fail to emphasize the divisions necessary for politics, divisions that should lead us to organize against the interests of corporations and their stockholders, against the values of the fundamentalists and the individualists, and on behalf of collectivist arrangements designed to redistribute benefits and opportunities more equitably. We proceed as if democracy were already the solution to contemporary political problems rather than symptomatic of them.
2,747
<h4><strong>Deliberative democracy is a floating signifier that can be filled with any number of ideologies. The result is the exploitative violence of an alienated capitalist society. </h4><p>Dean 07</p><p></strong>Jodi Dean Ph.D., Columbia M.A., Columbia, B.A., PrincetonThe Democratic Deadlock, Theory & Event, 10:4, Project Muse | ©<u><strong> 2007</p><p></u></strong>A commonplace of media punditry in the middle years of the first decade of the twenty-first century concerns the deep divide in American politics. Whether in terms of political parties, red states and blue states, support or opposition to US militarism in Afghanistan and Iraq, or the ongoing culture war between the religious right and the secular left, the United States is depicted as a nation split in its fundamental ethico-political self-understanding. This depiction is misleading. It occludes the way these seeming opponents continue to appeal to democracy. Thus, the administration of George W. Bush presents itself as actively engaged in bringing democracy to the Middle East, as encouraging countries throughout the world to strengthen their democratic institutions. <u><strong>The Left, although seemingly opposed to the Bush administration, also appeals to democracy as that which it wishes to restore, redeem, or reach. <mark>Why does the Left continue to appeal to democracy</u></strong></mark>? Is democracy, as Slavoj Žižek asks, the ultimate horizon of political thought?1 For Žižek, <u><strong>to accept this horizon is to accept an impoverished political field, a diminishment of aspirations to something better. <mark>We accept the limitation of democracy, convinced that this is as good as it gets</strong>.</u></mark> Real existing <u><strong><mark>constitutional democracies privilege the wealthy. They exclude, exploit, and oppress the poor.</strong></mark> </u>Crucial determinants of our lives and conditions remain outside the frame of political deliberation and response. The expansion and intensification of networked communications that was supposed to enhance democratic participation integrates and consolidates communicative capitalism.2 Nevertheless, we on the Left continue to present our political hopes as aspirations to democracy. <u><strong><mark>Despite democracy's inability to represent justice in the social field</strong> </u>that</mark> has emerged in the incompatibility between the global neoliberal economy and states' willingness to retain the promise of social security and collective welfare, <u><strong>left political</strong> </u>and cultural<u> <strong><mark>theorists continue to appeal to arrangements that can be filled in,</strong></mark> </u>substantialized, <u><strong><mark>by fundamentalisms, nationalisms, populisms, and conservatisms diametrically opposed to progressive visions of social and economic equality</mark>. </u></strong>Continuing to appeal to democracy, we fail to emphasize the divisions necessary for politics, divisions that should lead us to organize against the interests of corporations and their stockholders, against the values of the fundamentalists and the individualists, and on behalf of collectivist arrangements designed to redistribute benefits and opportunities more equitably<mark>.<u> <strong>We proceed as if democracy were already the solution to contemporary political problems rather than symptomatic of them</mark>.</p></u></strong>
2AC
FW
AT: Gov Edu Best
430,046
1
16,993
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
564,698
A
NDT
3
UTD LO
Heidt, Shook, Lundberg
1AC PAS genealogy- same assimilar to USC PAS 1AC 1NC T- Framework K- Szaz Medicalization of death 2NR T
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,921
That is a form of ideological alarmism which masks US involvement in terrorist construction – our evidence cites their internal link author
Longmire 14
Sylvia Longmire 14, Senior lecturer @ Air Force Special Operations School's Dynamics of International Terrorism with MA @ USF in Latin America studies, consultant/Analyst/SME on Mexico's drug war and border security issues retired Air Force captain and former Special Agent with the Air Force Office of Special Investigations, “Avoiding Sensationalism And Fiction In Drug War Reporting”, February 28th, AB
There is a lot of daily drama surrounding Mexico’s drug war reporting on cartel happenings of our border tends to turn sensational to grab headlines generate buzz, or spark controversy to increase readership an overblown and alarmist article can simply be the result of a misinformed an article from World Politics Review titled, “Strategic Horizons: All Options Bad If Mexico’s Drug Violence Expands to U.S.” from a writer with a strong professional background that would lead readers to some very wrong conclusions. The “shock factor” began when I read, “Americans must face the possibility that the [Mexican] conflict may also expand northward, This statement is to suck readers in with the notion that Mexican drug cartels could possibly engage in terrorist activity The writer, Steven Metz, expands on this thought by saying The Zetas already have a substantial connection to Hezbollah Since Hezbollah is a close ally or proxy of Iran, it might some day attempt to strike the United States in retribution for American action against Tehran Unfortunately for Metz this information is flat-out wrong not enough people understand the corporate and profit-maximizing interests of cartels any government or law enforcement attention brought upon them by such associations would crush their business operations Drug cartels have less of an interest in working with Hezbollah than our government does Hezbollah and a cartel have two very different goals Hezbollah has a fundamentalist mentality that involves a hatred of the West Los Zetas just want to make money and need a stable government apparatus that they can manipulate Nieto is pulling away from bilateral cooperation to prove that Mexico can handle its own affairs Mexico is not on the verge of collapse despite insurgency It has the 13th largest economy in the world, a strong military, free and fair elections and a broken but existent justice system Somalia it is not. It is very true that cartels have a widespread prese However, the dramatic “possibilities” that Metz outlines in this piece are alarmist and not based on solid or reliable facts—merely conjecture read any report about Mexico’s drug war with a discerning eye for facts, sources, and anything that sounds even remotely outrageous or sensational This is how we writers are held accountable, how we propagate facts, and how we restrain fiction
reporting on cartel happenings tends to turn sensational to grab headlines an overblown and alarmist article can be misinformed that lead readers to wrong conclusions This statement is to suck readers in with the notion that cartels could engage in terrorist activity Metz expands saying Zetas connect to Hezbollah it might strike the U S this information is flat-out wrong not enough people understand the profit interests of cartels any government attention would crush their business operations Drug cartels have less of an interest in working with Hezbollah than our government does Hezbollah and a cartel have two very different goals. Hezbollah has a fundamentalist mentality Zetas just want to make money, and a government they can manipulate Mexico is not on the verge of collapse, despite insurgency It has the 13th largest economy a strong military free fair elections and a broken but existent justice system the dramatic “possibilities Metz outlines are alarmist and not based on facts merely conjecture read any report about Mexico’s drug war with a discerning eye for anything that sounds even remotely sensational
There is a lot of daily drama surrounding Mexico’s drug war. In fact, I often refer to the frequent changes of command, violent territory grabs, and back-room deals between former rivals as something akin to As the Narco-World Turns. As a result of that, I believe that some reporting on cartel happenings on both sides of our southwest border tends to turn sensational, either to grab headlines, generate buzz, or spark controversy in an attempt to increase readership. In some cases, an overblown and alarmist article can simply be the result of a misinformed writer. On February 20, 2014, an associate of mine brought to my attention an article from World Politics Review titled, “Strategic Horizons: All Options Bad If Mexico’s Drug Violence Expands to U.S.” I read this article with interest because I assumed it would address border violence spillover and cartel activities within the US. It did, but unfortunately, it wasn’t long before I was shaking my head with disappointment. Here was another article from a writer with a strong professional background that would inevitably lead readers to some very wrong conclusions. The “shock factor” treatment began in the first paragraph when I read, “Americans must face the possibility that the [Mexican] conflict may also expand northward, with inter-gang warfare, assassinations of government officials and outright terrorism in the United States.” This statement is sure to suck readers in, particularly with the notion that Mexican drug cartels could possibly engage in terrorist activity in the US. The writer, Steven Metz, expands on this thought by saying, “The Zetas already have a substantial connection to Hezbollah, based on collaborative narco-trafficking and arms smuggling…Since Hezbollah is a close ally or proxy of Iran, it might some day attempt to strike the United States in retribution for American action against Tehran. If so, it would likely attempt to exploit its connection with the Zetas, pulling the narco-traffickers into a transnational proxy war.” Unfortunately for Metz and his readers, this information is flat-out wrong. I devoted an entire chapter in my forthcoming book, Border Insecurity, to laying out the facts and fiction surrounding the potential (or lack thereof) for cartels and terrorist groups to work together. It seems that not enough people understand the corporate and profit-maximizing interests of cartels, and how any government or law enforcement attention brought upon them by such associations would crush their business operations. Drug cartels have almost less of an interest in working with Hezbollah than our government does in seeing them do so. This isn’t to say that terrorist groups and drug trafficking organizations don’t have several things in common, like selling drugs to raise money and using a variety of avenues to launder their ill-gotten proceeds. It’s well known that groups like the PKK in Turkey, the Taliban in Afghanistan, and the Lashkar-e-Taiba in South Asia all benefit tremendously from their involvement in the drug trade. However, Hezbollah and a cartel like Los Zetas have two very different goals. Hezbollah has a fundamentalist and Islamist mentality that involves a deep hatred of the West and a desire to spread radical Islam throughout the world. Los Zetas and their rivals just want to make money, and need a stable government apparatus that they can simply manipulate, not control or take over. The statement that “…using the U.S. military against the cartels on Mexican soil could weaken the Mexican government or even cause its collapse…” also demonstrates a deep misunderstanding of the dynamic between our two governments, as well as a highly exaggerated view of what it would take to collapse the Mexican government. It’s true that our relationship with our neighbor to the south is delicate and complicated due to over a century of meddling in Latin America’s affairs. However, the US Department of Defense is extremely aware of Mexico’s desire to assert its sovereignty. Current Mexican President Enrique Peña Nieto is pulling away from bilateral cooperation in a likely attempt to prove that Mexico can handle its own affairs—a contrast to his predecessor Felipe Calderón, who drew considerable heat for allowing US drones to fly in Mexico in 2009 in order to provide imagery in support of counterdrug operations. Mexico is not on the verge of collapse, despite a criminal insurgency that has affected many parts of the country. It has the 13th largest economy in the world, a strong military, free and relatively fair elections in a functioning democracy, and a broken but existent justice system. Somalia or Sudan, it is not. It is very true that Mexican cartels—mostly by proxy through lower-level associates and gang members—have a widespread presence in virtually every corner of the US. They supply 90 percent of the illegal drugs on our streets, and engage in violent behavior against each other, migrants, and law enforcement officers on US soil. However, the dramatic “possibilities” that Metz outlines in this piece are alarmist and not based on solid or reliable facts—merely conjecture. The problem is that there is a lot more material out there like this. People will read these articles and assume they are true, then express anger that our government can’t even begin to address this apocalyptic threat. I am solidly in the camp that our government does not give nearly enough credence and attention to the national security threat posed by Mexican cartels, nor does it come close to validating the security concerns of many border residents. However, that doesn’t excuse anyone from publishing information that is not thoroughly researched and based on more than blog “reports” with no obvious author. It’s a disservice to readers, and I encourage you to read any report about Mexico’s drug war or border security—yes, even mine—with a discerning eye for facts, sources, and anything that sounds even remotely outrageous or sensational. This is how we writers are held accountable, how we propagate facts, and how we restrain fiction.
6,102
<h4>That is a form of ideological alarmism which masks US involvement in terrorist construction – our evidence cites their internal link author</h4><p>Sylvia <u><strong>Longmire 14</u></strong>, Senior lecturer @ Air Force Special Operations School's Dynamics of International Terrorism with MA @ USF in Latin America studies, consultant/Analyst/SME on Mexico's drug war and border security issues retired Air Force captain and former Special Agent with the Air Force Office of Special Investigations, “Avoiding Sensationalism And Fiction In Drug War Reporting”, February 28th, AB </p><p><u>There is a lot of daily drama surrounding Mexico’s drug war</u>. In fact, I often refer to the frequent changes of command, violent territory grabs, and back-room deals between former rivals as something akin to As the Narco-World Turns. As a result of that, I believe that some <u><strong><mark>reporting</strong> on cartel happenings</u></mark> on both sides <u>of our</u> southwest <u>border <strong><mark>tends to turn</mark> <mark>sensational</u></strong></mark>, either <u><mark>to grab headlines</u></mark>, <u>generate buzz, or spark controversy</u> in an attempt <u>to increase readership</u>. In some cases, <u><strong><mark>an overblown and alarmist article</u></strong> <u>can</mark> simply <mark>be</mark> the result of a <mark>misinformed</u></mark> writer. On February 20, 2014, an associate of mine brought to my attention <u>an article from World Politics Review titled, “Strategic Horizons: All Options Bad If Mexico’s Drug Violence Expands to U.S.”</u> I read this article with interest because I assumed it would address border violence spillover and cartel activities within the US. It did, but unfortunately, it wasn’t long before I was shaking my head with disappointment. Here was another article <u>from a writer with a strong professional background <mark>that</mark> would</u> inevitably <u><strong><mark>lead readers to</strong></mark> some very <strong><mark>wrong conclusions</strong></mark>. The “shock factor”</u> treatment <u>began</u> in the first paragraph <u>when I read, “Americans must face the possibility that the [Mexican] conflict may also expand northward,</u> with inter-gang warfare, assassinations of government officials and outright terrorism in the United States.” <u><mark>This statement</u> <u>is</u></mark> sure <u><mark>to suck readers in</u></mark>, particularly <u><mark>with the notion that</mark> Mexican drug <mark>cartels could</mark> possibly <mark>engage in terrorist activity</u></mark> in the US. <u>The writer, Steven <mark>Metz</mark>, <mark>expands</mark> on this thought by <mark>saying</u></mark>, “<u>The <mark>Zetas</mark> already have a substantial <mark>connect</mark>ion <mark>to Hezbollah</u></mark>, based on collaborative narco-trafficking and arms smuggling…<u>Since Hezbollah is a close ally or proxy of Iran, <mark>it</mark> <mark>might</mark> some day attempt to <mark>strike the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates in retribution for American action against Tehran</u>. If so, it would likely attempt to exploit its connection with the Zetas, pulling the narco-traffickers into a transnational proxy war.” <u>Unfortunately for Metz</u> and his readers, <u><strong><mark>this information is flat-out wrong</u></strong></mark>. I devoted an entire chapter in my forthcoming book, Border Insecurity, to laying out the facts and fiction surrounding the potential (or lack thereof) for cartels and terrorist groups to work together. It seems that <u><strong><mark>not enough people</mark> <mark>understand the</strong> </mark>corporate and <strong><mark>profit</strong></mark>-maximizing <strong><mark>interests of cartels</u></strong></mark>, and how <u><mark>any</u></mark> <u><mark>government</mark> or law enforcement <mark>attention</mark> brought upon them by such associations <mark>would <strong>crush their business operations</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong><mark>Drug cartels have</u></strong></mark> almost <u><strong><mark>less of an interest in working with Hezbollah than our government does</u></strong></mark> in seeing them do so. This isn’t to say that terrorist groups and drug trafficking organizations don’t have several things in common, like selling drugs to raise money and using a variety of avenues to launder their ill-gotten proceeds. It’s well known that groups like the PKK in Turkey, the Taliban in Afghanistan, and the Lashkar-e-Taiba in South Asia all benefit tremendously from their involvement in the drug trade. However, <u><strong><mark>Hezbollah and a cartel</u></strong></mark> like Los Zetas <u><strong><mark>have two very different goals</u></strong>.</mark> <u><mark>Hezbollah has a fundamentalist</u></mark> and Islamist <u><mark>mentality</u></mark> <u>that involves a</u> deep <u>hatred of the West</u> and a desire to spread radical Islam throughout the world. <u>Los <strong><mark>Zetas</u></strong></mark> and their rivals <u><strong><mark>just want to make money</u></strong>, <u>and <strong></mark>need <mark>a</mark> stable <mark>government</mark> apparatus</u></strong> <u>that <mark>they can</mark> </u>simply <u><mark>manipulate</u></mark>, not control or take over. The statement that “…using the U.S. military against the cartels on Mexican soil could weaken the Mexican government or even cause its collapse…” also demonstrates a deep misunderstanding of the dynamic between our two governments, as well as a highly exaggerated view of what it would take to collapse the Mexican government. It’s true that our relationship with our neighbor to the south is delicate and complicated due to over a century of meddling in Latin America’s affairs. However, the US Department of Defense is extremely aware of Mexico’s desire to assert its sovereignty. Current Mexican President Enrique Peña <u>Nieto is pulling away from bilateral cooperation</u> in a likely attempt <u>to prove that Mexico can handle its own affairs</u>—a contrast to his predecessor Felipe Calderón, who drew considerable heat for allowing US drones to fly in Mexico in 2009 in order to provide imagery in support of counterdrug operations. <u><strong><mark>Mexico is not on the verge of collapse</u></strong>, <u>despite</u></mark> a criminal <u><mark>insurgency</u></mark> that has affected many parts of the country. <u><mark>It has the 13th largest economy</mark> in the world, <mark>a strong military</mark>, <mark>free</mark> and </u>relatively <u><mark>fair elections</u></mark> in a functioning democracy, <u><mark>and a broken but existent justice system</u></mark>. <u>Somalia</u> or Sudan, <u>it is not. It is very true that</u> Mexican <u>cartels</u>—mostly by proxy through lower-level associates and gang members—<u>have a widespread prese</u>nce in virtually every corner of the US. They supply 90 percent of the illegal drugs on our streets, and engage in violent behavior against each other, migrants, and law enforcement officers on US soil. <u>However, <strong><mark>the dramatic “possibilities</mark>”</strong> that <mark>Metz outlines</mark> in this piece <strong><mark>are alarmist</mark> <mark>and not based on</mark> solid or reliable <mark>facts</strong></mark>—<mark>merely conjecture</u></mark>. The problem is that there is a lot more material out there like this. People will read these articles and assume they are true, then express anger that our government can’t even begin to address this apocalyptic threat. I am solidly in the camp that our government does not give nearly enough credence and attention to the national security threat posed by Mexican cartels, nor does it come close to validating the security concerns of many border residents. However, that doesn’t excuse anyone from publishing information that is not thoroughly researched and based on more than blog “reports” with no obvious author. It’s a disservice to readers, and I encourage you to <u><strong><mark>read any report about Mexico’s drug war</u></strong></mark> or border security—yes, even mine—<u><strong><mark>with a discerning eye for</mark> facts, sources, and <mark>anything that sounds even remotely </mark>outrageous or <mark>sensational</u></strong></mark>. <u>This is how we writers are held accountable, how we propagate facts, and how we restrain fiction</u>.</p>
2NC
K
Link – Mexico
49,950
17
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,922
Royal votes neg – the next page says decline disincentivizes saber rattling
Royal, their author, 10
Royal, their author, 10—director of Cooperative Threat Reduction at the U.S. Department of Defense (Jedediah, “Economic Integration, Economic Signaling and the Problem of Economic Crises”, published in Economics of War and Peace: Economic, Legal and Political Perspectives, ed. Goldsmith and Brauer, p. 217, google books)
There is another trend at play. Economic crises fragment regimes A decrease in cohesion at the leadership level reduces the ability of the state to coalesce a strong political base required to undertake costly balancing measures Schweller builds on earlier studies that link fragmentation with decisions not to balance against rising threats Where cohesion is strong, states are more likely to balance unstable regimes that rule over polities will be constrained in their ability to adapt to systemic incentives they will be least likely to enact costly policies even when their nation's survival is at stake
Economic crises fragment regimes A decrease in cohesion at the leadership reduces the ability to coalesce a political base required to undertake costly balancing studies link fragmentation with decisions not to balance unstable regimes they will be least likely to enact costly policies even when their nation's survival is at stake
There is, however, another trend at play. Economic crises tend to fragment regimes and divide polities. A decrease in cohesion at the political leadership level and at the electorate level reduces the ability of the state to coalesce a sufficiently strong political base required to undertake costly balancing measures such as economic costly signals. Schweller (2006) builds on earlier studies (sec, e.g., Christensen, 1996; Snyder, 2000) that link political fragmentation with decisions not to balance against rising threats or to balance only in minimal and ineffective ways to demonstrate a tendency for states to 'underbalance'. Where political and social cohesion is strong, states are more likely to balance against rising threats in effective and costly ways. However, 'unstable and fragmented regimes that rule over divided polities will be significantly constrained in their ability to adapt to systemic incentives; they will be least likely to enact bold and costly policies even when their nation's survival is at stake and they are needed most' (Schweller, 2006, p. 130).
1,084
<h4>Royal votes neg – the next page says decline disincentivizes<strong> saber rattling</h4><p><u>Royal, their author, 10</u></strong>—director of Cooperative Threat Reduction at the U.S. Department of Defense (Jedediah, “Economic Integration, Economic Signaling and the Problem of Economic Crises”, published in Economics of War and Peace: Economic, Legal and Political Perspectives, ed. Goldsmith and Brauer, p. 217, google books) </p><p><u>There is</u>, however, <u>another trend at play. <mark>Economic crises</u></mark> tend to <u><mark>fragment regimes</u></mark> and divide polities. <u><mark>A decrease in cohesion at the</u></mark> political <u><mark>leadership</mark> level</u> and at the electorate level <u><strong><mark>reduces the ability</strong></mark> of the state <mark>to coalesce a</u></mark> sufficiently <u>strong <mark>political base <strong>required to undertake costly balancing</mark> measures</u></strong> such as economic costly signals. <u>Schweller</u> (2006) <u>builds on earlier <mark>studies</u></mark> (sec, e.g., Christensen, 1996; Snyder, 2000) <u>that <mark>link</u></mark> political <u><mark>fragmentation with decisions <strong>not to balance</strong></mark> against rising threats</u> or to balance only in minimal and ineffective ways to demonstrate a tendency for states to 'underbalance'. <u>Where</u> political and social <u>cohesion is strong, states are more likely to balance</u> against rising threats in effective and costly ways. However, '<u><mark>unstable</u></mark> and fragmented <u><mark>regimes</mark> that rule over</u> divided <u>polities will be</u> significantly <u>constrained in their ability to adapt to systemic incentives</u>; <u><mark>they will be least likely to enact</u></mark> bold and <u><mark>costly policies <strong>even when their nation's survival is at stake</u></strong></mark> and they are needed most' (Schweller, 2006, p. 130).</p>
1NR
Banks
2NC Trade Finance Resilient
80,564
25
16,987
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round1.docx
564,729
N
NDT
1
Harvard DH
Eric Short, Chris Thiele, Dan Stout
1ac was online gambling with econ and china advantages 1nc was security edelman and case 2nc was security 1nr was case 2nr was security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round1.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,923
Empirics prove
Zakaria 9
Zakaria 9 Zakaria, PhD Poli Sci @ Harvard, Editor of Newsweek, 12/12/’9¶ (Fareed, “The Secrets of Stability,” Newsweek, http://www.newsweek.com/id/226425)
there's a fundamental reason why we have not faced global collapse It is the same reason that we weathered the crash of 87 recession of 92 the Asian crisis of 97 the Russian default of 98, and the tech-bubble collapse of 2000. The global economic system is more resilient than we think. The world is characterized by major forces for stability The first is great-power peace. the world's major powers have not competed with each other in geomilitary terms. by historical standards the globe is free of friction The number of people who have died as a result of conflicts has declined sharply Peace is like oxygen, Harvard's Nye has written. The peace that flowed from the end of the Cold War was accompanied by the discrediting of socialism. The world was left with a sole superpower but also a single workable economic model capitalism albeit with many variants This consensus enabled the expansion of the global economy almost all countries were participants. everyone is invested in the same system. Today while nations might face an economic crisis, no one is suggesting that they abandon free-market capitalism around the world you see the opposite there have been few successful electoral appeals for socialism or a rejection of the current framework Center-right parties have prospered in recent elections
we weathered the 87 recession of 92 the Asian crisis of 97 the Russian default of 98 and the tech-bubble collapse of 2000 The global economic system is more resilient than we think. The world is characterized by major forces for stability the world's major powers have not competed in geomilitary terms by historical standards the globe is free of friction The world was left with a single workable economic model albeit with many variants almost all countries were participants everyone is invested in the same system while nations might face an economic crisis, no one is suggesting that they abandon free-market capitalism around the world you see the opposite there have been few appeals for socialism Center-right parties have prospered
Beyond all this, though, I believe there's a fundamental reason why we have not faced global collapse in the last year. It is the same reason that we weathered the stock-market crash of 1987, the recession of 1992, the Asian crisis of 1997, the Russian default of 1998, and the tech-bubble collapse of 2000. The current global economic system is inherently more resilient than we think. The world today is characterized by three major forces for stability, each reinforcing the other and each historical in nature.¶ The first is the spread of great-power peace. Since the end of the Cold War, the world's major powers have not competed with each other in geomilitary terms. There have been some political tensions, but measured by historical standards the globe today is stunningly free of friction between the mightiest nations. This lack of conflict is extremely rare in history. You would have to go back at least 175 years, if not 400, to find any prolonged period like the one we are living in. The number of people who have died as a result of wars, civil conflicts, and terrorism over the last 30 years has declined sharply (despite what you might think on the basis of overhyped fears about terrorism). And no wonder—three decades ago, the Soviet Union was still funding militias, governments, and guerrillas in dozens of countries around the world. And the United States was backing the other side in every one of those places. That clash of superpower proxies caused enormous bloodshed and instability: recall that 3 million people died in Indochina alone during the 1970s. Nothing like that is happening today.¶ Peace is like oxygen, Harvard's Joseph Nye has written. When you don't have it, it's all you can think about, but when you do, you don't appreciate your good fortune. Peace allows for the possibility of a stable economic life and trade. The peace that flowed from the end of the Cold War had a much larger effect because it was accompanied by the discrediting of socialism. The world was left with a sole superpower but also a single workable economic model—capitalism—albeit with many variants from Sweden to Hong Kong.¶ This consensus enabled the expansion of the global economy; in fact, it created for the first time a single world economy in which almost all countries across the globe were participants. That means everyone is invested in the same system. Today, while the nations of Eastern Europe might face an economic crisis, no one is suggesting that they abandon free-market capitalism and return to communism. In fact, around the world you see the opposite: even in the midst of this downturn, there have been few successful electoral appeals for a turn to socialism or a rejection of the current framework of political economy. Center-right parties have instead prospered in recent elections throughout the West.
2,849
<h4>Empirics prove</h4><p><u><strong>Zakaria 9</p><p></u></strong>Zakaria, PhD Poli Sci @ Harvard, Editor of Newsweek, 12/12/’9¶ (Fareed, “The Secrets of Stability,” Newsweek, http://www.newsweek.com/id/226425)</p><p>Beyond all this, though, I believe <u>there's a fundamental reason why we have not faced global collapse</u> in the last year. <u>It is the same reason that <mark>we weathered the</u></mark> stock-market <u>crash of</u> 19<u><mark>87</u></mark>, the <u><mark>recession of</u></mark> 19<u><mark>92</u></mark>, <u><mark>the Asian crisis of</u></mark> 19<u><mark>97</u></mark>, <u><mark>the Russian default of</u></mark> 19<u><mark>98</mark>, <mark>and the tech-bubble collapse of 2000</mark>. <mark>The</u></mark> current <u><mark>global economic system is</u></mark> inherently <u><mark>more resilient than we think.</u> <u>The world</u></mark> today <u><mark>is characterized by</u></mark> three <u><mark>major forces for stability</u></mark>, each reinforcing the other and each historical in nature.¶ <u>The first is</u> the spread of <u>great-power peace.</u> Since the end of the Cold War, <u><mark>the world's major powers have not competed</mark> with each other <mark>in geomilitary terms</mark>.</u> There have been some political tensions, but measured <u><mark>by historical standards the globe</u></mark> today <u><mark>is</u></mark> stunningly <u><mark>free of friction</u></mark> between the mightiest nations. This lack of conflict is extremely rare in history. You would have to go back at least 175 years, if not 400, to find any prolonged period like the one we are living in. <u>The number of people who have died as a result of </u>wars, civil <u>conflicts</u>, and terrorism over the last 30 years <u>has declined sharply</u> (despite what you might think on the basis of overhyped fears about terrorism). And no wonder—three decades ago, the Soviet Union was still funding militias, governments, and guerrillas in dozens of countries around the world. And the United States was backing the other side in every one of those places. That clash of superpower proxies caused enormous bloodshed and instability: recall that 3 million people died in Indochina alone during the 1970s. Nothing like that is happening today.¶ <u>Peace is like oxygen, Harvard's</u> Joseph <u>Nye has written.</u> When you don't have it, it's all you can think about, but when you do, you don't appreciate your good fortune. Peace allows for the possibility of a stable economic life and trade. <u>The peace that flowed from the</u> <u>end of the Cold War</u> had a much larger effect because it <u>was accompanied by the discrediting of socialism.</u> <u><mark>The world was left with</mark> a</u> <u>sole superpower but also <mark>a single workable economic model</u></mark>—<u>capitalism</u>—<u><mark>albeit with many variants</u></mark> from Sweden to Hong Kong.¶ <u>This consensus enabled the expansion of the global economy</u>; in fact, it created for the first time a single world economy in which <u><mark>almost all countries</u></mark> across the globe <u><mark>were participants</mark>.</u> That means <u><mark>everyone is invested in the same system</mark>.</u> <u>Today</u>, <u><mark>while</u></mark> the <u><mark>nations</u></mark> of Eastern Europe <u><mark>might face an economic crisis, no one is suggesting that they abandon free-market capitalism</u></mark> and return to communism. In fact, <u><mark>around the world you see the opposite</u></mark>: even in the midst of this downturn, <u><mark>there have been few</mark> successful electoral <mark>appeals for</u></mark> a turn to <u><mark>socialism</mark> or a rejection of the current framework</u> of political economy. <u><mark>Center-right parties have</u></mark> instead <u><mark>prospered</mark> in recent elections</u> throughout the West.</p>
1NR
Econ
Resilient
73,430
105
16,989
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Round2.docx
564,705
N
Kentucky
2
Mary Washington SY
Rebecca Steiner
1ac was marihuana legalization with advantages of cartels and econ 1nc was t legalization security kritik gop bad midterms da the marijuana word pic and case 2nc was security 1nr was t and case 2nr was security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Round2.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,924
They legalize for some forms of prostitution but decrim for independent contractors – that’s a voter
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>They legalize for some forms of prostitution but decrim for independent contractors – that’s a voter</h4>
1NC
null
Off
430,047
1
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,925
I will give no deadly medicine to any one if asked, nor suggest any such counsel…
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>I will give no deadly medicine to any one if asked, nor suggest any such counsel…</h4>
null
1AC
null
430,048
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,926
Our affirmation of a right to die through PAS entails a recognition of the impossibility of liberalism – death inevitably reaches all of us so the juxtaposition of the project of “rights” with death’s seduction demonstrates the futility and brokenness of the liberal project of autonomy – the paradox of asserting a right to die combined with a process of countermemory constitutes an unstable bomb which destroys the conditions of possibility for liberalism’s death control – Ben Golder explains that
2011 SJE
Ben Golder, Ph.D, Professor at the University of New South Wales (Sydney, Australia), “Foucault’s Critical¶ (Yet Ambivalent)¶ Affirmation:¶ Three Figures of Rights,”Social And Legal Studies, 2011 SJE
Foucault diverges from orthodox liberal articulations of the ‘right to die’ Foucault’s deployment of the ‘right to die’ is intended to contest the forms of subjectivity produced and required by that very ‘juridico-medical authority’. Under contemporary conditions of bio-politics the medically-aware subject is enjoined to police his or her own health such that ‘[r]easonable individuals have been eager participants in this modern project of death deferral’ Under these conditions the standard liberal resort to the dignity of the individual and the autonomous terms under which that individual can exit life do nothing to contest the terms under which that life is bio-politically lived and invested by the institutions of medical power. By contrast, Foucault’s interventions on the ‘right to die’ (read alongside his wider critique of biopolitics) actually entail a ‘fundamental challenge to the juridico-medical complex of modernity’ The deployment of rights is intended to reflect back, as it were, upon the politicization of life. Foucault’s assertion of a ‘right to die’ is thus intended to problematize the subjective pre-suppositions of medicalized bio-politics (obedience to discourses of death-deferral and medical self-management) by opening up a different perspective upon death in life – that is, the preparation of one’s own death as an aesthetic project The crux of the difference between the Foucaultian and the liberal articulations of the ‘right to die’ thus resides in life’s preparation for death and, through this late modern melete thanatou, the consequent ‘enlightenment’ in life ‘by focussing on controlling one’s death [the] liberal perspective does not foster critical reflection upon those convictions by which one lives one’s life, and leaves unchallenged the role of medical authority in shaping those convictions orthodox liberal articulations of the ‘right to die work to reinforce a bio-political medical apparatus. Such an approach leaves unquestioned (indeed, performatively reinforces) the respective roles of law, state and medicine, whereas Foucault’s aesthetic, de-medicalized, anti-statist discourse seeks to subvert or avoid these relations.
Foucault diverges from orthodox liberal articulations of the ‘right to die’. Foucault’s deployment of the ‘right to die’ is intended to contest the forms of subjectivity produced and required by that very ‘juridico-medical authority’. Under contemporary conditions of bio-politics the standard liberal resort to the dignity of the individual and the autonomous terms under which that individual can exit life do nothing to contest the terms under which that life is bio-politically lived and invested by the institutions of medical power. By contrast, Foucault’s interventions on the ‘right to die’ (read alongside his wider critique of biopolitics) actually entail a ‘fundamental challenge to the juridico-medical complex of modernity’ The deployment of rights is intended to reflect back, as it were, upon the politicization of life. Foucault’s assertion of a ‘right to die’ is intended to problematize the subjective pre-suppositions of medicalized bio-politics by opening up a different perspective upon death in life the preparation of one’s own death as an aesthetic project ‘by focussing on controlling one’s death [the] liberal perspective does not foster critical reflection upon those convictions by which one lives one’s life, and leaves unchallenged the role of medical authority in shaping those convictions’ orthodox liberal articulations of the ‘right to die’ , work to reinforce a bio-political medical apparatus Such an approach leaves unquestioned (indeed,¶ performatively reinforces) the respective roles of law, state and medicine, whereas¶ Foucault’s aesthetic, de-medicalized, anti-statist discourse seeks to subvert or avoid¶ these relations.
In a recent article on this topic, Thomas Tierney neatly illustrates how Foucault diverges from orthodox liberal articulations of the ‘right to die’. In order to do this, Tier- ney reads Foucault’s comments on the ‘right to die’ against the famous intervention of the ‘Dream Team’ (a collection of six eminent liberal/libertarian philosophers, to wit: Ronald Dworkin, Thomas Nagel, Robert Nozick, John Rawls, TM Scanlon and Judith Jarvis Johnson) in their amicus curiae brief in the 1997 US Supreme Court case on assisted suicide, Washington v Glucksberg (see Dworkin et al. 1997). Whereas the latter is ‘concerned with providing to individuals enough control over their deaths so they can avoid a painful and/or degrading demise, while simultaneously maintaining the integrity of juridico-medical authority that is aimed at preserving life’, (Tierney, 2006: 626), Foucault’s deployment of the ‘right to die’ is intended to contest the forms of subjectivity produced and required by that very ‘juridico-medical authority’. Under contemporary conditions of bio-politics, that which Tierney calls the ‘juridico-medical order of mod- ernity’, the medically-aware subject is enjoined to police his or her own health such that ‘[r]easonable individuals have been eager participants in this modern project of death deferral’ (Tierney, 2006: 614, 615; see also Thompson, 2004). Under these conditions the standard liberal resort to the dignity of the individual and the autonomous terms under which that individual can exit life do nothing to contest the terms under which that life is bio-politically lived and invested by the institutions of medical power. By contrast, Foucault’s interventions on the ‘right to die’ (read alongside his wider critique of biopolitics) actually entail a ‘fundamental challenge to the juridico-medical complex of modernity’ (Tierney, 2006: 631) by ‘rais[ing] unsettling questions about the very nature of modern subjects’ (Tierney, 2006: 605). The deployment of rights is intended to reflect back, as it were, upon the politicization of life. Foucault’s assertion of a ‘right to die’ is thus intended to problematize the subjective pre-suppositions of medicalized bio-politics (obedience to discourses of death-deferral and medical self-management) by opening up a different perspective upon death in life – that is, the preparation of one’s own death as an aesthetic project (cf. Foucault, 1983: 237). ‘It is quite inconceivable that we not be given the chance’, Foucault writes elsewhere, ‘to prepare ourselves with all the passion, intensity and detail that we wish, including the little extras that we have been dreaming about for such a long time’ (Foucault, 1996: 296–297), that is to make of suicide ‘a fathomless pleasure whose patient and relentless preparation will enlighten all of your life’ (1996: 296). The crux of the difference between the Foucaultian and the liberal articulations of the ‘right to die’ thus resides in life’s preparation for death and, through this late modern melete thanatou, the consequent ‘enlightenment’ in life (read, for Foucault: the disruption of bio-politicized subjectivity). In contrast, ‘by focussing on controlling one’s death [the] liberal perspective does not foster critical reflection upon those convictions by which one lives one’s life, and leaves unchallenged the role of medical authority in shaping those convictions’ (Tierney, 2006: 632). For all its insistence upon the manner of death needing to reflect autonomous decisions concerning the value of life itself (which would seemingly import some critical perspective upon that life), orthodox liberal articulations of the ‘right to die’, like that of the ‘Dream Team’, work to reinforce a bio-political medical apparatus. The liberal narrative reinscribes the death- bound subject of bio-politics in a milieu of suffering (see the pathos-laden conclusion to Dworkin et al., 1997) from which medicine cannot save her and it thus calls upon law¶ and the state to balance the interests of the individual’s dignity against the state’s¶ (bio-political) interest in preserving life. Such an approach leaves unquestioned (indeed,¶ performatively reinforces) the respective roles of law, state and medicine, whereas¶ Foucault’s aesthetic, de-medicalized, anti-statist discourse seeks to subvert or avoid¶ these relations.
4,349
<h4>Our affirmation of a right to die through PAS entails a recognition of the impossibility of liberalism – death inevitably reaches all of us so the juxtaposition of the project of “rights” with death’s seduction demonstrates the futility and brokenness of the liberal project of autonomy – the paradox of asserting a right to die combined with a process of countermemory constitutes an unstable bomb which destroys the conditions of possibility for liberalism’s death control – Ben Golder explains that</h4><p>Ben Golder, Ph.D, Professor at the University of New South Wales (Sydney, Australia), “Foucault’s Critical¶ (Yet Ambivalent)¶ Affirmation:¶ Three Figures of Rights,”Social And Legal Studies, <u><strong><mark>2011 SJE</p><p></u></strong></mark>In a recent article on this topic, Thomas Tierney neatly illustrates how <u><mark>Foucault diverges from orthodox liberal articulations of the ‘right to die’</u>.</mark> In order to do this, Tier- ney reads Foucault’s comments on the ‘right to die’ against the famous intervention of the ‘Dream Team’ (a collection of six eminent liberal/libertarian philosophers, to wit: Ronald Dworkin, Thomas Nagel, Robert Nozick, John Rawls, TM Scanlon and Judith Jarvis Johnson) in their amicus curiae brief in the 1997 US Supreme Court case on assisted suicide, Washington v Glucksberg (see Dworkin et al. 1997). Whereas the latter is ‘concerned with providing to individuals enough control over their deaths so they can avoid a painful and/or degrading demise, while simultaneously maintaining the integrity of juridico-medical authority that is aimed at preserving life’, (Tierney, 2006: 626), <u><strong><mark>Foucault’s deployment of the ‘right to die’ is intended to contest the forms of subjectivity produced and required by that very ‘juridico-medical authority’.</strong> Under contemporary conditions of bio-politics</u></mark>, that which Tierney calls the ‘juridico-medical order of mod- ernity’, <u>the medically-aware subject is enjoined to police his or her own health such that ‘[r]easonable individuals have been eager participants in this modern project of death deferral’</u> (Tierney, 2006: 614, 615; see also Thompson, 2004). <u>Under these conditions <mark>the standard liberal resort to the dignity of the individual and the autonomous terms under which that individual can exit life do nothing to contest the terms under which that life is bio-politically lived and invested by the institutions of medical power. By contrast, <strong>Foucault’s interventions on the ‘right to die’ (read alongside his wider critique of biopolitics) actually entail a ‘fundamental challenge to the juridico-medical complex of modernity’</u></strong></mark> (Tierney, 2006: 631) by ‘rais[ing] unsettling questions about the very nature of modern subjects’ (Tierney, 2006: 605). <u><mark>The deployment of rights is intended to reflect back, as it were, upon the politicization of life. Foucault’s assertion of a ‘right to die’ is</mark> thus <strong><mark>intended to problematize the subjective pre-suppositions of medicalized bio-politics</strong></mark> (obedience to discourses of death-deferral and medical self-management) <strong><mark>by opening up a different perspective upon death in life</strong></mark> – that is, <mark>the preparation of one’s own death as an aesthetic project</u></mark> (cf. Foucault, 1983: 237). ‘It is quite inconceivable that we not be given the chance’, Foucault writes elsewhere, ‘to prepare ourselves with all the passion, intensity and detail that we wish, including the little extras that we have been dreaming about for such a long time’ (Foucault, 1996: 296–297), that is to make of suicide ‘a fathomless pleasure whose patient and relentless preparation will enlighten all of your life’ (1996: 296). <u>The crux of the difference between the Foucaultian and the liberal articulations of the ‘right to die’ thus resides in life’s preparation for death and, through this late modern melete thanatou, the consequent ‘enlightenment’ in life </u>(read, for Foucault: the disruption of bio-politicized subjectivity). In contrast, <u><mark>‘by focussing on controlling one’s death [the] liberal perspective does not foster critical reflection upon those convictions by which one lives one’s life, and leaves unchallenged the role of medical authority in shaping those convictions</u>’</mark> (Tierney, 2006: 632). For all its insistence upon the manner of death needing to reflect autonomous decisions concerning the value of life itself (which would seemingly import some critical perspective upon that life), <u><mark>orthodox liberal articulations of the ‘right to die</u>’</mark>, like that of the ‘Dream Team’<mark>, <u>work to</mark> <mark>reinforce a bio-political medical apparatus</mark>. </u>The liberal narrative reinscribes the death- bound subject of bio-politics in a milieu of suffering (see the pathos-laden conclusion to Dworkin et al., 1997) from which medicine cannot save her and it thus calls upon law¶ and the state to balance the interests of the individual’s dignity against the state’s¶ (bio-political) interest in preserving life. <u><strong><mark>Such an approach leaves unquestioned (indeed,</u></strong>¶<u><strong> performatively reinforces) the respective roles of law, state and medicine, whereas</u></strong>¶<u><strong> Foucault’s aesthetic, de-medicalized, anti-statist discourse seeks to subvert or avoid</u></strong>¶<u><strong> these relations.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
null
430,013
7
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,927
Ethos of Betterment DA: their claims about skills and problem solving reinforce an understanding of education which frames subjects as units of rationality to be bettered – this dispassionate construction dooms millions to suffer and reentrenches neoliberalism which makes it a double turn with cap
Mourad 01
Mourad 01
103, Number 5, October 2001, pp. 739–759) The tacit, unchallenged belief is that through education, the human being must be made into something better than it was or would be absent a formal education. There are all kinds of versions of this subject and of what it should become qualified professional, good citizen, “leader,” independent actor, critical thinker, change agent, knowledgeable person. In all cases, the subject before education is viewed to be, like the subject before civilization, something in need of being made competent—and safe—in the mind of the educator It must be resolved, or contained in some way; and this is done immediately by rendering the student a rule follower – a follower of the social order, both in and out of the classroom. Or the student must be rendered a challenger of the social order, in favor of an order that overcomes oppression—to become a competent comrade. The individual must be taught how to be an individual in accordance with this balance. Being an individual means being “free”—it means being “self-determined,” it means competing, and it means obeying the law the remedy tends to be to provide the person with an opportunity to become competent This situation reflects that the logic of formal education and the state, is not predicated upon a recognition that the human being is susceptible to suffering or that the state’s reason for being should be to care for people. We talk about equipping children and adults to “solve problems.” Yet, problems do not fall from the sky; they do not exist as such until a human being gives them a name In contrast, the concept of contention suggests that the practical role of reason should be used to understand the human being as subject to suffering and to act accordingly as moral agents. That is very different from an educational philosophy, policy, and practice that views reason as an instrument by which to overcome obstacles and to conform to the social order it is commonly expressed that we live in a “complex world must “learn how to learn,” in order to “succeed in a world of rapid change.” One must be an “active learner” or else Why? The individual must be acted upon and rendered into an entity that engages reality in the ways that are deemed just by many educators, lawmakers, and others with a stake in the perpetuation of the given social order. This philosophy of improvement is not necessarily consistent with enhancement of living. It often has the opposite effect The modern idea that anyone can be rational leads quickly to the idea that everyone is responsible for being wholly rational, as that word is understood according to the social order. The perpetuation of the given social order in education as elsewhere is about gaining advantage and retaining power It is about cultural politics and about marginalization of various groups and about class and about socializing children to believe in capitalism as if it is a natural law. these major problems are symptoms of something more basic It is about the intense pressures on people to think and act in ways that serve broader interests that are not at all concerned with their well-being in a variety of contexts including psychological, social, economic, political, and cultural It is no answer to ground pedagogy in the notion of “building community.” The idea that something must be built implies that something must be made better in order for it to be tolerated. “community” carries with it the prerequisite that one be made competent to be a member this ethos of betterment through competency will inevitably fail to fulfill the dreams of reformers and revolutionaries. It does not consider the human being as an entity to care for but rather as something to be equipped with skills and knowledge in order to improve itself. This failure is not only because there are millions of children and adults that live in poverty in the wealthiest countries in human history. It is because the state of mind that can tolerate such suffering is the same state that advances and maintains the ethos of civility as betterment, rather than civility as caring for people because they are subject to suffering. The alternative is intended to address an unacceptable state of contemporary Western civilization, namely, its repetitive and even escalating incidence of disregard for suffering and harm in many forms, despite intellectual, social, medical, legal, educational, scientific, and technological “progress.” We have had two hundred years of modern educational principles, and two hundred years of profound suffering along with them The problem of the individual calls for a new formulation and for a proper response one that cares for the individual rather than makes it competent. The “modern project” of betterment through competency and opportunity must be challenged and replaced by an emotionally intelligent ethos that expressly and fundamentally acknowledges suffering and limitation in philosophy, policy, and practice.
The belief is that the human must be made into something better than it was absent a formal education good citizen critical thinker, change agent It must be resolved by rendering the student a rule follower to become competent The individual must be taught how to be an individual Being an individual means obeying the law We talk about equipping children and adults to “solve problems.” One must be an “active learner” or else The individual must be rendered into an entity that engages reality in ways are deemed just by educators, lawmakers, and others with a stake in the perpetuation of the given social order The idea that anyone can be rational leads to the idea that everyone is responsible for being wholly rational The perpetuation of the given social order in education is about retaining power socializing children to believe in capitalism “community” carries with it the prerequisite that one be made competent to be a member It does not consider the human as an entity to care for but something to be equipped with skills millions live in poverty in the wealthiest countries the state of mind that can tolerate such suffering is the same state that advances the ethos of civility as betterment, rather than caring for people betterment through competency must be replaced by an ethos that acknowledges suffering
(Roger Jr., Director of Institutional Research at Washtenaw College and teaches at the University of Michigan. His academic credentials include a Ph.D. in Higher Education, M.A. in Philosophy of Education, and J.D. in Law, all from the University of Michigan. He is the author of Postmodern Philosophical Critique and the Pursuit of Knowledge in Higher Education ~Westport: Greenwood, 1997! and several recent journal publications on epistemological, ethical, and legal issues pertaining to the nature and structure of institutionally organized education and its relation to the social good, “Education After Foucault: The Question of Civility” Teachers College Record Volume 103, Number 5, October 2001, pp. 739–759) EDUCATION FOR IMPROVEMENT, OR “KICKING THE DOG” Too many lost names too many rules to the game Better find a focus or you’re out of the picture.48 The idea that the fundamental issue of the just civil state is to find the right balance between preserving individual freedom and constraining individual threat has served as a tacit foundation within which belief and debate about educational philosophy, policy, and practice develop. This statement is not intended to suggest that there is some direct and specific historical connection that can be unequivocally demonstrated to exist between foundational political theory and mainstream educational theories and practices. However, I want to propose that there is a compatibility between them that has important consequences for a new critique of organized formal education. In the remainder of this paper, my aim is to argue that the tenor of the theories that I have summarized is endemic in the ordinary ways that we think about and engage in organized education. How is the idea of the basic human being that is posed as the fundamental social, political, and pedagogic problem for modern civilization, this human being that must be managed in order to keep it from harming itself and others, played out in educational presuppositions? The tacit, unchallenged belief is that through education, the human being must be made into something better than it was or would be absent a formal education. There are all kinds of versions of this subject and of what it should become: potential achiever, qualified professional, good citizen, “leader,” independent actor, critical thinker, change agent, knowledgeable person. In all cases, the subject before education is viewed to be, like the subject before civilization, something in need of being made competent—and safe—in the mind of the educator. From this vantage point, the pedagogic relationship between teacher and student, between competent adult and incompetent child ~or adult!, contains within it a possibility that it seeks to overcome, namely, a rejection of the socialization program of the former by the latter. There is an implicit conflict between individuals as soon as the student walks into the school or college classroom door from outside the civility that the teacher would have that student become. It must be resolved, or contained in some way; and this is done immediately by rendering the student a rule follower – a follower of the social order, both in and out of the classroom. Or the student must be rendered a challenger of the social order, in favor of an order that overcomes oppression—to become a competent comrade. The individual must be taught how to be an individual in accordance with this balance. Being an individual means being “free”—it means being “self-determined,” it means competing, and it means obeying the law. This is the case, even if the teaching is done with kindness and sensitivity. The responsibility for dealing with suffering and limitation lies almost solely with this individual, not the state. In fact, if suffering is viewed at all, it tends to be viewed as something that is good for the individual to endure or to fight in order to overcome it. Limitation is not acknowledged, unless the individual is deemed disadvantaged in some way, and the remedy tends to be to provide the person with an opportunity to become competent. Is it any wonder that parents of children with disabilities, aided by many educators, often must fight for educational and other services? This situation simply reflects that the basic logic of organized formal education and, more generally, the state, is not predicated upon a recognition that the human being is susceptible to suffering or that the state’s reason for being should be to care for people. If caring for its inhabitants were the basic purpose of the civil state, then there would be no need to fight for this recognition. Is it any wonder that the education of the ordinary child is mainly training for a far-off, abstract future that is destined to be better than life at present? Why must school be about overcoming anything? We talk about equipping children and adults to “solve problems.” Yet, problems do not fall from the sky; they do not exist as such until a human being gives them a name. In contrast, the concept of contention suggests that the practical role of reason should be used to understand the human being as subject to suffering and to act accordingly as moral agents. That is very different from an educational philosophy, policy, and practice that views reason as an instrument by which to overcome obstacles and to conform to the social order. It may be argued that modern education is about reason, about how to think and live reasonably and, therefore, how to live well and to care for oneself and for others. Yet it is commonly expressed that we live in a “complex world” and that children and adults must “learn how to learn,” in order to “succeed in a world of rapid change.” The question that needs to be asked is: Why should a person have to? In effect, education expects the human being to have an unlimited ability to think and act with reason sufficient to cope with increasingly complex situations that require individual intellect to adequately recognize, evaluate, and prioritize alternative courses of action, consider their consequences, and make good decisions. For the most part, the increasing complexity of civil society and the multiplicity of factors that intellect is expected to deal with in different situations are not questioned in education. Is this what education is rightly about? Education is as much about the use of intelligence to avoid suffering and feelings of limitation and about fending off feelings of fear as it is about learning. It is about acting upon other people and upon the civil order to deal with perceived threats. One must be an “active learner” or else. Why? The individual must be acted upon and rendered into an entity that engages reality in the ways that are deemed just by many educators, lawmakers, and others with a stake in the perpetuation of the given social order. Thus, the individual is exhorted to “do your best,” “make an effort,” “earn a grade,” “be motivated,” “work hard,” “overcome obstacles,” “achieve.” Why should education be about any of these things? Unfortunately, the culture of scholarship is thoroughly consistent with these precepts. When we question them, we challenge the ends that they serve but not the ideas themselves. We believe that education is rightly about improvement. This philosophy of improvement is not necessarily consistent with enhancement of living. It often has the opposite effect. How is this result justified? Certainly, it can feel good to accomplish something or to overcome obstacles. Does that mean that adversity should be a positive value of the civil state? The modern idea, beginning with Descartes and established through Lockean empiricism ~and made pedagogic by Rousseau’s Emile!, that anyone can be rational leads quickly to the idea that everyone is responsible for being wholly rational, as that word is understood according to the social order. The perpetuation of the given social order in education as elsewhere is about gaining advantage and retaining power. It is about cultural politics and about marginalization of various groups and about class and about socializing children to believe in capitalism as if it is a natural law. Yet under the analysis that I have made here, these major problems are symptoms of something more basic. The more basic problem that I have emphasized here is inextricable from the problem of the just civil state. It is about the intense pressures on people to think and act in ways that serve broader interests that are not at all concerned with their well-being in a variety of contexts including psychological, social, economic, political, and cultural. It is no answer to ground pedagogy in the notion of “building community.” The idea that something must be built implies that something must be made better in order for it to be tolerated. Moreover, “community” carries with it the prerequisite that one be made competent to be a member— again, the presumption that something must be done to the person to make it better in some way. I do not mean to say that educators have bad intent. I do mean that this ethos of betterment through competency will inevitably fail to fulfill the dreams of reformers and revolutionaries. It does not consider the human being as an entity to care for but rather as something to be equipped with skills and knowledge in order to improve itself. This failure is not only because there are millions of children and adults that live in poverty in the wealthiest countries in human history. It is because the state of mind that can tolerate such suffering is the same state that advances and maintains the ethos of civility as betterment, rather than civility as caring for people because they are subject to suffering. The alternative that I have only introduced in a very abbreviated way under the rubric that I called “contention” is intended to be pragmatic in the ways that Foucault and Richard Rorty are pragmatic in their respective approaches to the subject of the state.49 It is intended to address an unacceptable state of contemporary Western civilization, namely, its repetitive and even escalating incidence of disregard for suffering and harm in many forms, despite intellectual, social, medical, legal, educational, scientific, and technological “progress.” We have had two hundred years of modern educational principles, and two hundred years of profound suffering along with them. The problem of the individual calls for a new formulation and for a proper response—one that cares for the individual rather than makes it competent. The “modern project” of betterment through competency and opportunity must be challenged and replaced by an emotionally intelligent ethos that expressly and fundamentally acknowledges suffering and limitation in philosophy, policy, and practice.
10,916
<h4><u>Ethos of Betterment DA</u><strong>: their claims about skills and problem solving reinforce an understanding of education which frames subjects as units of rationality to be bettered – this dispassionate construction dooms millions to suffer and reentrenches neoliberalism which makes it a double turn with cap</h4><p>Mourad 01 </p><p></strong>(Roger Jr., Director of Institutional Research at Washtenaw College and teaches at the University of Michigan. His academic credentials include a Ph.D. in Higher Education, M.A. in Philosophy of Education, and J.D. in Law, all from the University of Michigan. He is the author of Postmodern Philosophical Critique and the Pursuit of Knowledge in Higher Education ~Westport: Greenwood, 1997! and several recent journal publications on epistemological, ethical, and legal issues pertaining to the nature and structure of institutionally organized education and its relation to the social good, “Education After Foucault: The Question of Civility” Teachers College Record Volume<u><strong> 103, Number 5, October 2001, pp. 739–759)</p><p></u></strong>EDUCATION FOR IMPROVEMENT, OR “KICKING THE DOG” Too many lost names too many rules to the game Better find a focus or you’re out of the picture.48 The idea that the fundamental issue of the just civil state is to find the right balance between preserving individual freedom and constraining individual threat has served as a tacit foundation within which belief and debate about educational philosophy, policy, and practice develop. This statement is not intended to suggest that there is some direct and specific historical connection that can be unequivocally demonstrated to exist between foundational political theory and mainstream educational theories and practices. However, I want to propose that there is a compatibility between them that has important consequences for a new critique of organized formal education. In the remainder of this paper, my aim is to argue that the tenor of the theories that I have summarized is endemic in the ordinary ways that we think about and engage in organized education. How is the idea of the basic human being that is posed as the fundamental social, political, and pedagogic problem for modern civilization, this human being that must be managed in order to keep it from harming itself and others, played out in educational presuppositions? <u><strong><mark>The </mark>tacit, unchallenged <mark>belief is that</mark> through education, <mark>the human </mark>being <mark>must be made into something better than it was</mark> or would be <mark>absent a formal education</mark>.</u></strong> <u><strong>There are all kinds of versions of this subject and of what it should become</u></strong>: potential achiever, <u><strong>qualified professional, <mark>good citizen</mark>, “leader,” independent actor, <mark>critical thinker, change agent</mark>, knowledgeable person. In all cases, the subject before education is viewed to be, like the subject before civilization, something in need of being made competent—and safe—in the mind of the educator</u></strong>. From this vantage point, the pedagogic relationship between teacher and student, between competent adult and incompetent child ~or adult!, contains within it a possibility that it seeks to overcome, namely, a rejection of the socialization program of the former by the latter. There is an implicit conflict between individuals as soon as the student walks into the school or college classroom door from outside the civility that the teacher would have that student become. <u><strong><mark>It must be resolved</mark>, or contained in some way; and this is done immediately <mark>by rendering the student a rule follower</mark> – a follower of the social order, both in and out of the classroom. Or the student must be rendered a challenger of the social order, in favor of an order that overcomes oppression—<mark>to become </mark>a <mark>competent </mark>comrade.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>The individual must be taught how to be an individual</mark> in accordance with this balance. <mark>Being an individual means </mark>being “free”—it means being “self-determined,” it means competing, and it means <mark>obeying the law</u></strong></mark>. This is the case, even if the teaching is done with kindness and sensitivity. The responsibility for dealing with suffering and limitation lies almost solely with this individual, not the state. In fact, if suffering is viewed at all, it tends to be viewed as something that is good for the individual to endure or to fight in order to overcome it. Limitation is not acknowledged, unless the individual is deemed disadvantaged in some way, and <u><strong>the remedy tends to be to provide the person with an opportunity to become competent</u></strong>. Is it any wonder that parents of children with disabilities, aided by many educators, often must fight for educational and other services? <u><strong>This situation </u></strong>simply <u><strong>reflects</u></strong> <u><strong>that the </u></strong>basic <u><strong>logic of </u></strong>organized <u><strong>formal education and</u></strong>, more generally, <u><strong>the state, is not predicated upon a recognition that the human being is susceptible to suffering or that the state’s reason for being should be to care for people.</u></strong> If caring for its inhabitants were the basic purpose of the civil state, then there would be no need to fight for this recognition. Is it any wonder that the education of the ordinary child is mainly training for a far-off, abstract future that is destined to be better than life at present? Why must school be about overcoming anything? <u><strong><mark>We talk about equipping children and adults to “solve problems.”</mark> Yet, problems do not fall from the sky; they do not exist as such until a human being gives them a name</u></strong>. <u><strong>In contrast, the concept of contention suggests that the practical role of reason should be used to understand the human being as subject to suffering and to act accordingly as moral agents.</u></strong> <u><strong>That is</u></strong> <u><strong>very different from an educational philosophy, policy, and practice that views reason as an instrument by which to overcome obstacles and to conform to the social order</u></strong>. It may be argued that modern education is about reason, about how to think and live reasonably and, therefore, how to live well and to care for oneself and for others. Yet <u><strong>it is commonly expressed that we live in a “complex world</u></strong>” and that children and adults <u><strong>must “learn how to learn,” in order to “succeed in a world of rapid change.”</u></strong> The question that needs to be asked is: Why should a person have to? In effect, education expects the human being to have an unlimited ability to think and act with reason sufficient to cope with increasingly complex situations that require individual intellect to adequately recognize, evaluate, and prioritize alternative courses of action, consider their consequences, and make good decisions. For the most part, the increasing complexity of civil society and the multiplicity of factors that intellect is expected to deal with in different situations are not questioned in education. Is this what education is rightly about? Education is as much about the use of intelligence to avoid suffering and feelings of limitation and about fending off feelings of fear as it is about learning. It is about acting upon other people and upon the civil order to deal with perceived threats. <u><strong><mark>One must be an “active learner” or else</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Why?</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>The individual must be</mark> acted upon and <mark>rendered into an entity that engages reality in </mark>the <mark>ways </mark>that <mark>are deemed just by</mark> many <mark>educators, lawmakers, and others with a stake in the perpetuation of the given social order</mark>.</u></strong> Thus, the individual is exhorted to “do your best,” “make an effort,” “earn a grade,” “be motivated,” “work hard,” “overcome obstacles,” “achieve.” Why should education be about any of these things? Unfortunately, the culture of scholarship is thoroughly consistent with these precepts. When we question them, we challenge the ends that they serve but not the ideas themselves. We believe that education is rightly about improvement. <u><strong>This philosophy of improvement is not necessarily consistent with enhancement of living. It often has the opposite effect</u></strong>. How is this result justified? Certainly, it can feel good to accomplish something or to overcome obstacles. Does that mean that adversity should be a positive value of the civil state? <u><strong><mark>The </mark>modern <mark>idea</u></strong></mark>, beginning with Descartes and established through Lockean empiricism ~and made pedagogic by Rousseau’s Emile!, <u><strong><mark>that anyone can be rational leads </mark>quickly <mark>to the idea that everyone is responsible for being wholly rational</mark>, as that word is understood according to the social order. <mark>The perpetuation of the given social order in education</mark> as elsewhere <mark>is about</mark> gaining advantage and <mark>retaining power</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>It is about cultural politics and about marginalization of various groups and about class and about <mark>socializing children to believe in capitalism</mark> as if it is a natural law.</u></strong> Yet under the analysis that I have made here, <u><strong>these major problems are symptoms of something more basic</u></strong>. The more basic problem that I have emphasized here is inextricable from the problem of the just civil state. <u><strong>It is about the intense pressures on people to think and act in ways that serve broader interests that are not at all concerned with their well-being in a variety of contexts including psychological, social, economic, political, and cultural</u></strong>. <u><strong>It is no answer to ground pedagogy in the notion of “building community.” The idea that something must be built implies that something must be made better in order for it to be tolerated.</u></strong> Moreover, <u><strong><mark>“community” carries with it the prerequisite that one be made competent to be a member</u></strong></mark>— again, the presumption that something must be done to the person to make it better in some way. I do not mean to say that educators have bad intent. I do mean that <u><strong>this ethos of betterment through competency will inevitably fail to fulfill the dreams of reformers and revolutionaries.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>It does not consider the human </mark>being <mark>as an entity to care for but </mark>rather as <mark>something to be</mark> <mark>equipped with skills </mark>and knowledge in order to improve itself. This failure is not only because there are <mark>millions</mark> of children and adults that <mark>live in poverty in the wealthiest countries </mark>in human history. It is because <mark>the state of mind that can tolerate such suffering is the same state that advances </mark>and maintains <mark>the ethos of civility as betterment, rather than </mark>civility as <mark>caring for people </mark>because they are subject to suffering.</u></strong> <u><strong>The alternative</u></strong> that I have only introduced in a very abbreviated way under the rubric that I called “contention” is intended to be pragmatic in the ways that Foucault and Richard Rorty are pragmatic in their respective approaches to the subject of the state.49 It <u><strong>is intended to address an unacceptable state of contemporary Western civilization, namely, its repetitive and even escalating incidence of disregard for suffering and harm in many forms, despite intellectual, social, medical, legal, educational, scientific, and technological “progress.” We have had two hundred years of modern educational principles, and two hundred years of profound suffering along with them</u></strong>. <u><strong>The problem of the individual calls for a new formulation and for a proper response</u></strong>—<u><strong>one that cares for the individual rather than makes it competent. The “modern project” of <mark>betterment through competency</mark> and opportunity <mark>must be</mark> challenged and <mark>replaced by an </mark>emotionally intelligent <mark>ethos that</mark> expressly and fundamentally <mark>acknowledges suffering </mark>and limitation in philosophy, policy, and practice.</p></u></strong>
2AC
FW
AT: Decisionmaking
134,537
27
16,993
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
564,698
A
NDT
3
UTD LO
Heidt, Shook, Lundberg
1AC PAS genealogy- same assimilar to USC PAS 1AC 1NC T- Framework K- Szaz Medicalization of death 2NR T
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,928
Second this constant drive for intervention causes global war
Duffield 8
Duffield 8 (Mark Duffield, emeritus professor of politics at the University of Bristol, 2008, “Global Civil War: The Non-Insured, International Containment and Post-Interventionary Society,” Journal of Refugee Studies Volume 21 Issue 2)
you cannot have development or security without containing the circulation of underdeveloped life the origins of this nexus can be traced to decolonization decolonization publicly signalled the generic division of humankind into insured and non-insured species-life. It foregrounded the coexistence of a developed life, supported by the welfare bureaucracies associated with social insurance, with an underdeveloped life expected to be self-reliant decolonization also called forth a volatile world of peoples having, for the first time, the potential to circulate globally containment has deepened and extended to constitute a virtual global ban on the free movement of spontaneous or non-managed migration Spurred by the threat of terrorism, such concerns have now been generalized to include the critical energy, transport and service infrastructures of mass consumer society. The international security architecture that emerged with decolonization interconnects the containment of irregular migration with measures to integrate migrant communities already settled within consumer society and, at the same time, state-led development initiatives to improve the self-reliance and stasis of underdeveloped life in situ. This episodic architecture has deepened with each crisis of global circulation. It marks out a terrain of a global civil war, or rather tableau of wars, which is being fought on and between the modalities of life itself Through their associated modalities of circulation—and the need to police them—global civil war connects the livelihood conflicts of the global South with threats to critical infrastructure in the North the radical interdependence of world events has placed a renewed emphasis on the need for social cohesion at home while, at the same time, urging a fresh wave of intervention abroad to reconstruct weak and fragile states, or remove rogue ones. What is at stake in this war is the West's ability to contain and manage international poverty while maintaining the ability of mass society to live and consume beyond its means there is a real possibility that this disastrous formula for sharing the world with others will be defended to the death Reflected within the globalization of containment, imposing and maintaining this putative life-style has become increasingly violent and coercive. we are all involved in this war; it cannot be escaped since it mobilizes societies as a whole, including policy makers and academics
you cannot have development without containing underdeveloped life this nexus can be traced to the division of humankind into insured and non-insured species-life. It foregrounded the coexistence of a developed life with an underdeveloped life expected to be self-reliant security interconnects containment of migration with measures to integrate migrant communities within consumer society to improve the self-reliance of underdeveloped life in situ It marks a terrain of a global civil war fought on and between the modalities of life itself global civil war connects livelihood conflicts of the global South with threats in the North the need for social cohesion at home while urging intervention abroad this disastrous formula will be defended to the death we are all involved in this war since it mobilizes societies as a whole
This essay began with the proposition that to complete the nexus between development and security, the term containment needs to be included; in the sense that you cannot have development or security without containing the circulation of underdeveloped life. Rather than emerging with the end of the Cold War, or even less convincingly with 9/11, the origins of this nexus can be traced to decolonization. While its constituent parts have an even longer history, decolonization publicly signalled the generic division of humankind into insured and non-insured species-life. It foregrounded the coexistence of a developed life, supported by the welfare bureaucracies associated with social insurance, with an underdeveloped life expected to be self-reliant. While the former was secure within the juridico-political framework of the nation-state, the latter was synonymous with deficient but aspiring states. As an appendage of this new world of states, decolonization also called forth a volatile world of peoples having, for the first time, the potential to circulate globally. In meeting this threat, since the 1960s, the resilience of consumer society has been regularly scored in terms of the ability of effective states to contain the circulatory effects of the permanent crisis of self-reliance, including political instability and the mobile poverty of irregular migration. In the intervening decades, containment has deepened and extended to constitute a virtual global ban on the free movement of spontaneous or non-managed migration. This necessity was first articulated in terms of the risks posed to community cohesion and the finite resources of the welfare state. Spurred by the threat of terrorism, such concerns have now been generalized to include the critical energy, transport and service infrastructures of mass consumer society. The international security architecture that emerged with decolonization interconnects the containment of irregular migration with measures to integrate migrant communities already settled within consumer society and, at the same time, state-led development initiatives to improve the self-reliance and stasis of underdeveloped life in situ. This episodic architecture has deepened with each crisis of global circulation. It marks out a terrain of a global civil war, or rather tableau of wars, which is being fought on and between the modalities of life itself. Through their associated modalities of circulation—and the need to police them—global civil war connects the livelihood conflicts of the global South with threats to critical infrastructure in the North. Since the end of the Cold War, the radical interdependence of world events has placed a renewed emphasis on the need for social cohesion at home while, at the same time, urging a fresh wave of intervention abroad to reconstruct weak and fragile states, or remove rogue ones. What is at stake in this war is the West's ability to contain and manage international poverty while maintaining the ability of mass society to live and consume beyond its means. Supported by the massed ranks of career politicians and big business, there is a real possibility that this disastrous formula for sharing the world with others will be defended to the death. Certainly, that a large part of humanity is deemed to be self-reliant and potentially sustainable—if limited to basic needs—must give hope to many in the environmental lobby. As a lived reality, however, it is less convincing. Reflected within the globalization of containment, imposing and maintaining this putative life-style has become increasingly violent and coercive. In one way or another, we are all involved in this war; it cannot be escaped since it mobilizes societies as a whole, including policy makers and academics. Because this war is being conducted in our name, however, we have a right as citizens to decide where we agree and disagree, and at what point, or over which issues, we need to establish our own terms of engagement.
4,009
<h4>Second this constant drive for intervention causes global war</h4><p><u><strong>Duffield 8</u></strong> (Mark Duffield, emeritus professor of politics at the University of Bristol, 2008, “Global Civil War: The Non-Insured, International Containment and Post-Interventionary Society,” Journal of Refugee Studies<u> Volume 21 Issue 2)</p><p></u>This essay began with the proposition that to complete the nexus between development and security, the term containment needs to be included; in the sense that <u><mark>you cannot have development </mark>or security <mark>without containing</mark> the <strong>circulation of <mark>underdeveloped life</u></strong></mark>. Rather than emerging with the end of the Cold War, or even less convincingly with 9/11, <u>the origins of <mark>this nexus can be traced to </mark>decolonization</u>. While its constituent parts have an even longer history, <u>decolonization publicly signalled <mark>the</mark> generic <mark>division of humankind into insured and non-insured species-life. It foregrounded the coexistence of a developed life</mark>, supported by the welfare bureaucracies associated with social insurance, <mark>with an <strong>underdeveloped life expected to be self-reliant</u></strong></mark>. While the former was secure within the juridico-political framework of the nation-state, the latter was synonymous with deficient but aspiring states. As an appendage of this new world of states, <u>decolonization also called forth a volatile world of peoples having, for the first time, the potential to circulate globally</u>. In meeting this threat, since the 1960s, the resilience of consumer society has been regularly scored in terms of the ability of effective states to contain the circulatory effects of the permanent crisis of self-reliance, including political instability and the mobile poverty of irregular migration. In the intervening decades, <u>containment has deepened and extended to constitute a virtual global ban on the free movement of spontaneous or non-managed migration</u>. This necessity was first articulated in terms of the risks posed to community cohesion and the finite resources of the welfare state. <u>Spurred by the threat of terrorism, such concerns have now been generalized to include the critical energy, transport and service infrastructures of mass consumer society.</p><p>The international <mark>security </mark>architecture that emerged with decolonization <mark>interconnects</mark> the <mark>containment of </mark>irregular <mark>migration with measures to integrate migrant communities</mark> already settled <mark>within consumer society</mark> and, at the same time, state-led development initiatives <mark>to improve the self-reliance</mark> and stasis <mark>of underdeveloped life in situ</mark>. This episodic architecture has deepened with each crisis of global circulation. <mark>It marks</mark> out <mark>a terrain of a <strong>global civil war</strong></mark>, or rather tableau of wars, which is being <strong><mark>fought on and between the modalities of life itself</u></strong></mark>. <u>Through their associated modalities of circulation—and the need to police them—<strong><mark>global civil war connects </mark>the <mark>livelihood conflicts of the global South with threats</mark> to critical infrastructure <mark>in the North</u></strong></mark>. Since the end of the Cold War, <u>the radical interdependence of world events has placed a renewed emphasis on <mark>the need for social cohesion at home while</mark>, at the same time, <mark>urging</mark> a <strong>fresh wave of <mark>intervention abroad</strong></mark> to reconstruct weak and fragile states, or remove rogue ones. What is at stake in this war is the West's ability to contain and manage international poverty while maintaining the ability of mass society to live and consume beyond its means</u>. Supported by the massed ranks of career politicians and big business, <u>there is a real possibility that <strong><mark>this disastrous formula</mark> for sharing the world with others <mark>will be defended to the death</u></strong></mark>. Certainly, that a large part of humanity is deemed to be self-reliant and potentially sustainable—if limited to basic needs—must give hope to many in the environmental lobby. As a lived reality, however, it is less convincing. <u>Reflected within the <strong>globalization of containment</strong>, imposing and maintaining this putative life-style has become <strong>increasingly violent and coercive</strong>.</u> In one way or another, <u><strong><mark>we are all involved in this war</strong></mark>; it cannot be escaped <mark>since it mobilizes societies as a whole</mark>, including policy makers and academics</u>. Because this war is being conducted in our name, however, we have a right as citizens to decide where we agree and disagree, and at what point, or over which issues, we need to establish our own terms of engagement.</p>
2NC
K
Link – Mexico
429,900
5
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,929
They say causality models but diversionary theory fails those
Fravel ‘10
Fravel ‘10 (M. Taylor, Associate Professor of Political Science and member of the Security Studies Program at MIT, “The Limits of Diversion: Rethinking Internal and External Conflict” 26 Oct. 2010 dspace.mit.edu/openaccess-disseminate/1721.1/59524‎) BSH
The diversionary hypothesis offers one of the most powerful alternatives to rationalist explanations of war based on the state as a unitary actor. The cases investigated in this article, raise doubts about the strength of the diversionary hypothesis as well as the empirical validity of arguments based on diversionary mechanisms hypothesis fails to pass two most likely tests external security challenges and bargaining over disputed territory better explain decision making. The historical record offers stronger evidence for a standard realist model and the dynamics of coercive diplomacy. the research design used in this article weakens confidence in the strength of diversionary arguments. Diversion as a principal or primary source of some conflicts may be much less frequent than scholars assert. If diversion cannot account for these decisions, it is unclear what the hypothesis can in fact explain. At the most general level of analysis, the lack of support for the diversion hypothesis complements quantitative studies of diversion that do not identify a systematic and significant relationship between domestic politics and aggressive foreign policies In addition, the research design used in this article raises questions about studies that do provide empirical support for diversion because it demonstrates that despite the presence of domestic unrest underlying causal mechanisms of diversion may not account for the decisions to use force. the rally effect that leaders enjoy from an international crisis is generally brief in duration and unlikely to change permanently a public’s overall satisfaction with its leaders. Diversionary action should produce the largest rally effect against the most powerful target because such action would reflect a leader’s skills through coercing a superior opponent Although the odds of victory increase when targeting weaker states, success should have a much more muted effect on domestic support , weak or embattled leaders can choose from a wide range of policy options to strengthen their standing at home Weak leaders can also seek to deepen cooperation with other states if they believe it will strengthen their position at home The findings carry implications for future empirical tests of the diversionary hypothesis and the broader relationship between internal and external confli given the common view within the field of international relations that some past conflicts are best explained by diversionary motives, additional case studies are needed to test diversionary claims against plausible alternative explanations in analysis of German decision making before 1914 Copeland finds leadership statements that disconfirm the diversionary hypothesis although smoking-gun evidence in leadership statements may be impossible to find, scholars can use case study methods to test diversionary arguments against alternative explanations. scholars can trace changes in the domestic political environment with foreign policy decision making to identify a clear relationship between domestic political strife and plans to threaten or use force findings also underscore the importance of including appropriate international-level variables in quantitative models of diversion. The inclusion of such variables not only ensures that appropriate scope conditions for the diversionary use of force are present, but they can also control for alternative explanations driven by changes in a state’s international environment Those studies that do include such variables use them as controls for a state’s ability to engage in diversionary behavior such as relative capabilities and major power status or opportunity structures for diversion such as an enduring rivalry or ongoing crisis. few studies include variables that measure a state’s threat environment or other states’ efforts to change the status quo, actions that might also account for dispute escalation. In current models, indicators of domestic conflict are usually included as a separate variable If, the effect of domestic strife is conditional, then diversionary factors are perhaps more appropriately modeled as a multiplicative interaction term Diversion itself, however, may have its limits.
cases raise doubts about the diversionary hypothesis as well as empirical validity the lack of support for the diversion hypothesis complements studies that do not identify a significant relationship between domestic politics and aggressive foreign policies, the research design used in this article raises questions about studies that do provide empirical support for diversion the rally effect is generally brief in duration and unlikely to change satisfaction with leaders. Weak leaders can also seek to deepen cooperation leadership statements disconfirm the diversionary hypothesis findings underscore the importance of including appropriate variables in quantitative models of diversion few studies include variables that measure actions that might also account for dispute escalation.
The diversionary hypothesis offers one of the most powerful alternatives to rationalist explanations of war based on the state as a unitary actor. Strong empirical support for diversion would identify a more complete set of causal mechanisms underlying international conflict. The cases investigated in this article, however, raise doubts about the strength of the diversionary hypothesis as well as the empirical validity of arguments based on diversionary mechanisms, such as Mansfield and Snyder’s theory about democratization and war.126 In Argentina and Turkey, the hypothesis fails to pass two most likely tests. In neither case was domestic unrest a necessary condition for the use of force as proponents of diversionary theory must demonstrate. Instead, external security challenges and bargaining over disputed territory better explain Argentine and Turkish decision making. The historical record, including leadership statements and reasoning, offers stronger evidence for a standard realist model and the dynamics of coercive diplomacy. Drawing definitive conclusions about diversion from just two cases is impossible. Nevertheless, the modified most likely research design used in this article weakens confidence in the strength of diversionary arguments. Diversion as a principal or primary source of some conflicts may be much less frequent than scholars assert. These two episodes should be among the easiest cases for diversion to explain. Not only did embattled leaders escalate disputes into crises and then use force, but scholars have also viewed these cases as being best explained by diversionary mechanisms. If diversion cannot account for these decisions, it is unclear what the hypothesis can in fact explain. My findings have several implications for the literature on diversionary war theory. At the most general level of analysis, the lack of support for the diversion hypothesis in Argentina and Turkey complements those quantitative studies of diversion that do not identify a systematic and significant relationship between domestic politics and aggressive foreign policies, including the use of force.127 In addition, the modified most likely research design used in this article raises questions about those quantitative studies that do provide empirical support for diversion because it demonstrates that despite the presence of domestic unrest, the underlying causal mechanisms of diversion may not account for the decisions to use force. The lack of support for diversion raises a simple but important question: why is diversion less frequent than commonly believed, despite its plausible intuition? Although further research is required, several factors should be considered. First, the rally effect that leaders enjoy from an international crisis is generally brief in duration and unlikely to change permanently a public’s overall satisfaction with its leaders.128 George H. W. Bush, for example, lost his reelection bid after successful prosecution of the 1991 Gulf War. Winston Churchill fared no better after the Allied victory in World War II.129 Leaders have little reason to conclude that a short-term rally will address what are usually structural sources of domestic dissatisfaction. 127 Second, a selection effect may prevent embattled leaders from choosing diversion. Diversionary action should produce the largest rally effect against the most powerful target because such action would reflect a leader’s skills through coercing a superior opponent. At the same time, leaders should often be deterred from challenging stronger targets, as the imbalance of military forces increases the risk of defeat and thus the probability of losing office at home. Although the odds of victory increase when targeting weaker states, success should have a much more muted effect on domestic support, if any, because victory would have been expected.130 Third, weak or embattled leaders can choose from a wide range of policy options to strengthen their standing at home. Although scholars such as Oakes and Gelpi have noted that embattled leaders can choose repression or economic development in addition to diversionary action, the range of options is even greater and carries less risk than the failure of diversion. Weak leaders can also seek to deepen cooperation with other states if they believe it will strengthen their position at home. Other studies, for example, have demonstrated that political unrest facilitated détente among the superpowers in the early 1970s, China’s concessions in its many territorial disputes, support for international financial liberalization, and the formation of regional organizations such as the Association of Southeast Asian States and the Gulf Cooperation Council.131 The findings from these two cases also carry implications for future empirical tests of the diversionary hypothesis and the broader relationship between internal and external conflict. To start, given the common view within the field of international relations that some past conflicts are best explained by diversionary motives, additional case studies are needed to test diversionary claims against plausible alternative explanations. In other cases that scholars have cast as diversionary, for example, evidence exists that casts doubt upon the hypothesis. Historian Arno Mayer, among others, is often cited as providing support for diversion through his argument that domestic crises accounted for key decisions leading to the outbreak of World War I (as well as other conflicts) in Europe.132 Yet in his analysis of German decision making before 1914, Dale Copeland finds leadership statements that disconfirm the diversionary hypothesis. As early as 1905-06, for instance, Admiral Tirpitz concluded that war in Europe would only “cause chaos at home,” not increase societal cohesion.133 Similarly, the 1904-05 Russo-Japanese war is often mentioned as another example of diversion. One of the key pieces of evidence to support his claim comes from a memoir of a Russian official, Count Sergei Witte, who quotes V. K. Pleve, minister of the interior at the time, as stating that “we need a little victorious war to stem the tide of revolution.”134 Geoffrey Blainey notes, however, numerous problems with this statement as evidence of Russian decision making: the quote appeared in a memoir that was penned eight years later, Witte and Pleve were rivals, and Witte in other parts of the memoir that analyzes the war includes no other statements that would support a diversionary explanation.135 These two examples suggest that a thorough audit of other diversionary cases would be helpful. In addition, although smoking-gun evidence in leadership statements may be impossible to find, scholars can use case study methods to test diversionary arguments against alternative explanations. In particular, scholars can trace changes in the domestic political environment with foreign policy decision making to identify a clear relationship between domestic political strife and plans to threaten or use force. Scholars can also examine leadership statements for evidence consistent with diversion, such as concern about their domestic political standing or the anticipated effects of an external conflict on domestic politics. At the same time, my findings also underscore the importance of including appropriate international-level variables in quantitative models of diversion. The inclusion of such variables not only ensures that appropriate scope conditions for the diversionary use of force are present, but they can also control for alternative explanations driven by changes in a state’s international environment. In some cross-national studies, for example, international-level variables are excluded.136 Those studies that do include such variables use them as controls for a state’s ability to engage in diversionary behavior such as relative capabilities and major power status or opportunity structures for diversion such as an enduring rivalry or ongoing crisis.137 Very few studies include variables that measure a state’s threat environment or other states’ efforts to change the status quo, actions that might also account for dispute escalation.138 Finally, even though external security challenges explain the Argentine and Turkish decisions better than diversion, the presence of domestic unrest in both episodes suggests a new avenue for research on the relationship between internal and external conflict. Drawing upon Hein Goemans’ study of war termination, leaders with low levels of public support may have additional incentives to use force when confronting external security threats than leaders with comparatively high levels of support.139 If weak leaders fail to defend their states’ interests abroad, they are even more likely to face punishment at home. In this way, the degree of domestic support that a leader enjoys might function as an intervening or mediating variable that increases the magnitude of the incentive to use force when threatened or challenged by another state. This possible effect, however, is not a diversionary one, as domestic unrest does not create an independent incentive for leaders to deflect attention abroad through the use of force. If the effect of domestic conflict is to magnify or enlarge existing incentives for escalation created by the international environment, new specifications of quantitative models of diversion should also be considered. In current models, indicators of domestic conflict are usually included as a separate variable, suggesting that diversionary factors exert linear additive effects on the odds of conflict. If, however, the effect of domestic strife is conditional, then diversionary factors are perhaps more appropriately modeled as a multiplicative interaction term.140 New specifications might account for the mixed results that past quantitative tests have revealed. Diversion itself, however, may have its limits.
9,962
<h4>They say causality models but diversionary theory fails those</h4><p><u><strong>Fravel ‘10</u></strong> (M. Taylor, Associate Professor of Political Science and member of the Security Studies Program at MIT, “The Limits of Diversion: Rethinking Internal and External Conflict” 26 Oct. 2010 dspace.mit.edu/openaccess-disseminate/1721.1/59524‎) BSH</p><p><u>The diversionary hypothesis offers one of the most powerful alternatives to rationalist explanations of war based on the state as a unitary actor. </u>Strong empirical support for diversion would identify a more complete set of causal mechanisms underlying international conflict. <u>The <mark>cases </mark>investigated in this article,</u> however, <u><mark>raise doubts about </mark>the strength of <mark>the diversionary hypothesis as well as</mark> the <mark>empirical validity </mark>of arguments based on diversionary mechanisms</u>, such as Mansfield and Snyder’s theory about democratization and war.126 In Argentina and Turkey, the <u>hypothesis fails to pass two most likely tests</u>. In neither case was domestic unrest a necessary condition for the use of force as proponents of diversionary theory must demonstrate. Instead, <u>external security challenges and bargaining over disputed territory better explain </u>Argentine and Turkish <u>decision making. The historical record</u>, including leadership statements and reasoning, <u>offers stronger evidence for a standard realist model and the dynamics of coercive diplomacy.</u> Drawing definitive conclusions about diversion from just two cases is impossible. Nevertheless, <u>the</u> modified most likely <u>research design used in this article weakens confidence in the strength of diversionary arguments. Diversion as a principal or primary source of some conflicts may be much less frequent than scholars assert.</u> These two episodes should be among the easiest cases for diversion to explain. Not only did embattled leaders escalate disputes into crises and then use force, but scholars have also viewed these cases as being best explained by diversionary mechanisms. <u>If diversion cannot account for these decisions, it is unclear what the hypothesis can in fact explain. </u>My findings have several implications for the literature on diversionary war theory. <u>At the most general level of analysis, <mark>the lack of support for the diversion hypothesis</u></mark> in Argentina and Turkey <u><mark>complements</u></mark> those <u>quantitative <mark>studies</mark> of diversion <mark>that do not identify a</mark> systematic and <mark>significant relationship between domestic politics and aggressive foreign policies</u>,</mark> including the use of force.127 <u>In addition, <mark>the</u></mark> modified most likely <u><mark>research design used in this article raises questions</mark> <mark>about</mark> </u>those quantitative <u><mark>studies that do provide empirical support for diversion</mark> because it demonstrates that despite the presence of domestic unrest</u>, the <u>underlying causal mechanisms of diversion may not account for the decisions to use force. </u>The lack of support for diversion raises a simple but important question: why is diversion less frequent than commonly believed, despite its plausible intuition? Although further research is required, several factors should be considered. First, <u><strong><mark>the rally effect </mark>that leaders enjoy from an international crisis <mark>is generally brief in duration and unlikely to change </mark>permanently a public’s overall <mark>satisfaction with </mark>its <mark>leaders.</u></strong></mark>128 George H. W. Bush, for example, lost his reelection bid after successful prosecution of the 1991 Gulf War. Winston Churchill fared no better after the Allied victory in World War II.129 Leaders have little reason to conclude that a short-term rally will address what are usually structural sources of domestic dissatisfaction. 127 Second, a selection effect may prevent embattled leaders from choosing diversion. <u>Diversionary action should produce the largest rally effect against the most powerful target because such action would reflect a leader’s skills through coercing a superior opponent</u>. At the same time, leaders should often be deterred from challenging stronger targets, as the imbalance of military forces increases the risk of defeat and thus the probability of losing office at home. <u>Although the odds of victory increase when targeting weaker states, success should have a much more muted effect on domestic support</u>, if any, because victory would have been expected.130 Third<u>, weak or embattled leaders can choose from a wide range of policy options to strengthen their standing at home</u>. Although scholars such as Oakes and Gelpi have noted that embattled leaders can choose repression or economic development in addition to diversionary action, the range of options is even greater and carries less risk than the failure of diversion. <u><mark>Weak leaders can also seek to deepen cooperation</mark> with other states if they believe it will strengthen their position at home</u>. Other studies, for example, have demonstrated that political unrest facilitated détente among the superpowers in the early 1970s, China’s concessions in its many territorial disputes, support for international financial liberalization, and the formation of regional organizations such as the Association of Southeast Asian States and the Gulf Cooperation Council.131 <u>The findings</u> from these two cases also <u>carry implications for future empirical tests of the diversionary hypothesis and the broader relationship between internal and external confli</u>ct. To start, <u>given the common view within the field of international relations that some past conflicts are best explained by diversionary motives, additional case studies are needed to test diversionary claims against plausible alternative explanations</u>. In other cases that scholars have cast as diversionary, for example, evidence exists that casts doubt upon the hypothesis. Historian Arno Mayer, among others, is often cited as providing support for diversion through his argument that domestic crises accounted for key decisions leading to the outbreak of World War I (as well as other conflicts) in Europe.132 Yet <u>in </u>his <u>analysis of German decision making before 1914</u>, Dale <u>Copeland finds <mark>leadership statements</mark> that <mark>disconfirm the diversionary hypothesis</u></mark>. As early as 1905-06, for instance, Admiral Tirpitz concluded that war in Europe would only “cause chaos at home,” not increase societal cohesion.133 Similarly, the 1904-05 Russo-Japanese war is often mentioned as another example of diversion. One of the key pieces of evidence to support his claim comes from a memoir of a Russian official, Count Sergei Witte, who quotes V. K. Pleve, minister of the interior at the time, as stating that “we need a little victorious war to stem the tide of revolution.”134 Geoffrey Blainey notes, however, numerous problems with this statement as evidence of Russian decision making: the quote appeared in a memoir that was penned eight years later, Witte and Pleve were rivals, and Witte in other parts of the memoir that analyzes the war includes no other statements that would support a diversionary explanation.135 These two examples suggest that a thorough audit of other diversionary cases would be helpful. In addition, <u>although smoking-gun evidence in leadership statements may be impossible to find, scholars can use case study methods to test diversionary arguments against alternative explanations.</u> In particular, <u>scholars can trace changes in the domestic political environment with foreign policy decision making to identify a clear relationship between domestic political strife and plans to threaten or use force</u>. Scholars can also examine leadership statements for evidence consistent with diversion, such as concern about their domestic political standing or the anticipated effects of an external conflict on domestic politics. At the same time, my <u><mark>findings</mark> also <mark>underscore the importance of including appropriate</mark> international-level <mark>variables in quantitative models of diversion</mark>.</u> <u>The inclusion of such variables not only ensures that appropriate scope conditions for the diversionary use of force are present, but they can also control for alternative explanations driven by changes in a state’s international environment</u>. In some cross-national studies, for example, international-level variables are excluded.136 <u>Those studies that do include such variables use them as controls for a state’s ability to engage in diversionary behavior such as relative capabilities and major power status or opportunity structures for diversion such as an enduring rivalry or ongoing crisis.</u>137 Very <u><strong><mark>few studies include variables that measure</strong></mark> a state’s threat environment or other states’ efforts to change the status quo, <strong><mark>actions that might also account for dispute escalation.</u></strong></mark>138 Finally, even though external security challenges explain the Argentine and Turkish decisions better than diversion, the presence of domestic unrest in both episodes suggests a new avenue for research on the relationship between internal and external conflict. Drawing upon Hein Goemans’ study of war termination, leaders with low levels of public support may have additional incentives to use force when confronting external security threats than leaders with comparatively high levels of support.139 If weak leaders fail to defend their states’ interests abroad, they are even more likely to face punishment at home. In this way, the degree of domestic support that a leader enjoys might function as an intervening or mediating variable that increases the magnitude of the incentive to use force when threatened or challenged by another state. This possible effect, however, is not a diversionary one, as domestic unrest does not create an independent incentive for leaders to deflect attention abroad through the use of force. If the effect of domestic conflict is to magnify or enlarge existing incentives for escalation created by the international environment, new specifications of quantitative models of diversion should also be considered. <u>In current models, indicators of domestic conflict are usually included as a separate variable</u>, suggesting that diversionary factors exert linear additive effects on the odds of conflict. <u>If,</u> however, <u>the effect of domestic strife is conditional, then diversionary factors are perhaps more appropriately modeled as a multiplicative interaction term</u>.140 New specifications might account for the mixed results that past quantitative tests have revealed. <u>Diversion itself, however, may have its limits.</p></u>
1NR
Banks
2NC Trade Finance Resilient
63,453
50
16,987
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round1.docx
564,729
N
NDT
1
Harvard DH
Eric Short, Chris Thiele, Dan Stout
1ac was online gambling with econ and china advantages 1nc was security edelman and case 2nc was security 1nr was case 2nr was security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round1.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,930
Neg ground - they spike out of links to why regulating prostitution is bad
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Neg ground - they spike out of links to why regulating prostitution is bad</h4>
1NC
null
Off
430,049
1
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,931
With purity and with holiness I will pass my life and practice my Art.”
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>With purity and with holiness I will pass my life and practice my Art.”</h4>
null
1AC
null
430,050
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,932
Suicide as escape is a necessary transgression within the cycle of eternal recurrence. Accepting death through the option for suicide imparts meaning onto life’s suffering – Paul Loeb explains
null
Paul, Dr. of philosophy at University of Puget Sound, Ph.D from Cal Berkeley, “Suicide, Meaning, and Redemption,” Nietzsche on Time and History, Ed. Manuel Dries, p. 163-189 SJE
eternal recurrence, which Nietzsche describes as ‘the highest formula of affirmation that is at all attainable’ turns out to be the new counter-ideal and the means whereby the human can for the first time will a life-affirming meaning for its past and thereby for its entire existence However, this invocation of eternal recurrence does nothing whatsoever to eliminate the irreversibility of time the human has nostalgically willed the return, and even eternal repetition, of its most treasured and joyous past moments When Nietzsche describes eternal recurrence as the highest formulation of life-affirmation that is at all attainable, his point is not that the human animal should aim to will this eternal recurrence and thereby achieve the highest life-affirmation possible his point is that the human can never will this and that therefore the human can never achieve such life-affirmation. Nietzsche found himself unable to will his life’s eternal recurrence. rather than conferring meaning upon the human animal’s past, the thought of eternal recurrence actually multiplies and intensifies the meaninglessness of this past to a new and devastating degree. Eternal recurrence, he writes, is the most extreme form of nihilism because it is the ‘thought of existence as it is, without meaning or goal, but inevitably recurring, without any finale into nothingness’ everything becomes and recurs eternally— escape is impossible the thought of death as escape keeps humans from giving in to their pre-existing death-wish by imparting meaning to life’s suffering and offering the hope of a different or better life.
eternal recurrence Nietzsche describes as ‘the¶ highest affirmation attainable’ the counter-ideal and means whereby the human can will a life-affirming meaning for its past However, invocation of eternal recurrence does not eliminate the irreversibility of time , the human has willed the eternal repetition, of its most joyous past moments When Nietzsche describes eternal recurrence as the highest¶ formulation of life-affirmation his point is not that¶ the human should aim to will this eternal recurrence his point i the human can never will this and that therefore the human can never achieve such life-affirmation. the thought of eternal recurrence multiplies and intensifies the meaninglessness of this past everything becomes and recurs eternally— escape¶ is impossible the thought of death as escape¶ keeps humans from giving in to their pre-existing death-wish by imparting¶ meaning to life’s suffering and offering the hope of a different or¶ better life.
Although Zarathustra does not explicitly introduce his teaching of eternal¶ recurrence in his redemption speech, he obviously points in this direction¶ when he concludes by asking how the creative will might be taught to will¶ backwards so that it might will something higher than any reconciliation¶ with time. According to the consensus reading I have been concerned to¶ criticize, what Zarathustra means by this is that my affirmation of my present¶ state should teach me how to ‘will backwards’—that is, to will the¶ exact repetition of my entire past. And I would not be able to will in this¶ way unless I had successfully redescribed my past as directed inevitably¶ towards my present state. As Nehamas writes: ‘If I am even for a moment¶ such as I would want to be again, then I would accept all my past actions,¶ which, essential to and constitutive of the self I want to repeat, are now¶ newly redescribed’ (1985, p. 160, my emphasis). Or, as Julian Young¶ writes, the key is to ‘“write” my life so that I not merely like it, but like it¶ so much that I can will its recurrence for ever and ever, down to every last¶ detail’ (2003, p. 91), and to do this we must be able to see the kind of personal¶ providence in things that Nietzsche describes in Gay Science 277.¶ Hence eternal recurrence, which Nietzsche describes in Ecce Homo as ‘the¶ highest formula of affirmation that is at all attainable’ (EH III Z 1), turns¶ out to be the new counter-ideal and the means whereby the human animal¶ can for the first time will a life-affirming meaning for its past and thereby¶ for its entire existence.¶ However, this invocation of eternal recurrence does nothing whatsoever¶ to eliminate the kind of self-deception pointed out by Nietzsche himself¶ in Gay Science 277. Saying to my past, ‘Thus I will it to be repeated’,¶ or, ‘Thus I will it to be repeated eternally’, does not add any¶ more meaning to my past than saying to it merely, ‘Thus I will it.’ Just as¶ my present willing can do nothing whatsoever to direct my past inevitably¶ towards my present state, so too my present willing can do nothing whatsoever¶ to ensure the repetition of my vanished past. Indeed, this is precisely¶ Nietzsche’s point about the irreversibility of time: ever since its¶ acquisition of a faculty of memory, the human animal has nostalgically¶ willed the return, and even eternal repetition, of its most treasured and¶ joyous past moments. The problem is not that the human animal has never¶ before willed this, and that it should start doing so now. The problem, rather,¶ is that the human animal has always willed this, and that this willing¶ has been of no avail whatsoever. Indeed, it is precisely this impotence, this¶ confrontation with the immovable stone ‘it was’, that has caused the human¶ animal to find its existence and suffering devoid of meaning, to take revenge on life, to formulate the ascetic ideal, and to live its life against¶ life.¶ When, therefore, Nietzsche describes eternal recurrence as the highest¶ formulation of life-affirmation that is at all attainable, his point is not that¶ the human animal should aim to will this eternal recurrence and thereby¶ achieve the highest life-affirmation possible.12 Instead, his point is that the human animal can never will this and that therefore the human animal can never achieve such life-affirmation. Indeed, no matter how strong and healthy¶ he deemed himself, perhaps the strongest and healthiest of all of his¶ contemporaries, Nietzsche found himself unable to will his life’s eternal¶ recurrence. Writing in his notebooks in 1883, Nietzsche exclaims: ‘I do not¶ want life again. How have I borne it? What has made me endure the sight?¶ the vision of the superhuman who affirms life. I have tried to affirm it¶ myself —alas!’ (Nachlaß November 1882–February 1883, KSA 10,¶ 4[81]).13¶ So, rather than conferring meaning upon the human animal’s past, the thought of eternal recurrence actually multiplies and intensifies the meaninglessness of this past to a new and devastating degree. This is why Nietzsche¶ writes in his 1887 notes that the thought of eternal recurrence builds¶ upon the nihilism that follows the demise of the ascetic ideal—that is, upon¶ the most paralysing thought of ‘continuing with an “in vain”, without aim¶ and purpose’. Eternal recurrence, he writes, is the most extreme form of¶ nihilism because it is the ‘thought of existence as it is, without meaning or¶ goal, but inevitably recurring, without any finale into nothingness’ (Nachla߶ Summer 1886–Autumn 1887, KSA 12, 5[71], my emphasis). It is not¶ just the thought of meaninglessness, but the thought of meaninglessness¶ eternally. Previously the human animal sought solace in the idea of death¶ and nothingness as an escape from the meaninglessness of its life and suffering.¶ But the thought of eternal recurrence closes off all such escape and¶ condemns the human animal to eternal meaninglessness. As Nietzsche¶ writes in his 1883 notes: ‘everything becomes and recurs eternally— escape¶ is impossible!” (Nachlaß Winter 1883–1884, KSA 10, 24[7]).14¶ Nor can it be replied to this that, because death no longer affords an escape¶ to life’s suffering, there is actually less point to suicide. For in the third essay of the Genealogy Nietzsche argues that the thought of death as escape¶ keeps humans from giving in to their pre-existing death-wish by imparting¶ meaning to life’s suffering and offering the hope of a different or¶ better life. Because eternal recurrence undermines both this meaning and¶ this hope, nothing remains to keep humans from giving in to their inherent¶ suicidal instincts.
5,651
<h4>Suicide as escape is a necessary transgression within the cycle of eternal recurrence. Accepting death through the option for suicide imparts meaning onto life’s suffering – Paul Loeb explains</h4><p>Paul, Dr. of philosophy at University of Puget Sound, Ph.D from Cal Berkeley, “Suicide, Meaning, and Redemption,” Nietzsche on Time and History, Ed. Manuel Dries, p. 163-189 SJE</p><p>Although Zarathustra does not explicitly introduce his teaching of eternal¶ recurrence in his redemption speech, he obviously points in this direction¶ when he concludes by asking how the creative will might be taught to will¶ backwards so that it might will something higher than any reconciliation¶ with time. According to the consensus reading I have been concerned to¶ criticize, what Zarathustra means by this is that my affirmation of my present¶ state should teach me how to ‘will backwards’—that is, to will the¶ exact repetition of my entire past. And I would not be able to will in this¶ way unless I had successfully redescribed my past as directed inevitably¶ towards my present state. As Nehamas writes: ‘If I am even for a moment¶ such as I would want to be again, then I would accept all my past actions,¶ which, essential to and constitutive of the self I want to repeat, are now¶ newly redescribed’ (1985, p. 160, my emphasis). Or, as Julian Young¶ writes, the key is to ‘“write” my life so that I not merely like it, but like it¶ so much that I can will its recurrence for ever and ever, down to every last¶ detail’ (2003, p. 91), and to do this we must be able to see the kind of personal¶ providence in things that Nietzsche describes in Gay Science 277.¶ Hence <u><mark>eternal recurrence</mark>, which <mark>Nietzsche</u> <u>describes</u></mark> in Ecce Homo <u><mark>as ‘the</u>¶<u> highest</mark> formula of <mark>affirmation</mark> that is at all <mark>attainable’</mark> </u>(EH III Z 1), <u>turns</u>¶<u> out to be <mark>the</mark> <strong>new <mark>counter-ideal</strong> and</mark> the <strong><mark>means whereby the human</strong></mark> </u>animal¶<u> <strong><mark>can</strong></mark> for the first time <strong><mark>will a life-affirming meaning</strong> for its past</mark> and thereby</u>¶<u> for its entire existence</u>.¶ <u><mark>However, <strong></mark>this <mark>invocation of eternal recurrence does not</strong></mark>hing whatsoever</u>¶<u> to <strong><mark>eliminate the</u></strong></mark> kind of self-deception pointed out by Nietzsche himself¶ in Gay Science 277. Saying to my past, ‘Thus I will it to be repeated’,¶ or, ‘Thus I will it to be repeated eternally’, does not add any¶ more meaning to my past than saying to it merely, ‘Thus I will it.’ Just as¶ my present willing can do nothing whatsoever to direct my past inevitably¶ towards my present state, so too my present willing can do nothing whatsoever¶ to ensure the repetition of my vanished past. Indeed, this is precisely¶ Nietzsche’s point about the <u><strong><mark>irreversibility of time</u></strong></mark>: ever since its¶ acquisition of a faculty of memory<mark>, <u>the human</u></mark> animal <u><mark>has</mark> nostalgically</u>¶<u> <mark>willed the</mark> return, and even <mark>eternal repetition, of its most</mark> treasured and</u>¶<u> <mark>joyous past moments</u></mark>. The problem is not that the human animal has never¶ before willed this, and that it should start doing so now. The problem, rather,¶ is that the human animal has always willed this, and that this willing¶ has been of no avail whatsoever. Indeed, it is precisely this impotence, this¶ confrontation with the immovable stone ‘it was’, that has caused the human¶ animal to find its existence and suffering devoid of meaning, to take revenge on life, to formulate the ascetic ideal, and to live its life against¶ life.¶ <u><mark>When</u></mark>, therefore, <u><mark>Nietzsche describes eternal recurrence as the highest</u>¶<u> formulation of life-affirmation</mark> that is at all attainable, <mark>his point is not that</u>¶<u> the human</mark> animal <mark>should aim to will this eternal recurrence</mark> and thereby</u>¶<u> achieve the highest life-affirmation possible</u>.12 Instead, <u><mark>his point i</mark>s that <strong><mark>the human</mark> </u></strong>animal<u><strong> <mark>can never will this and that therefore the human </u></strong></mark>animal<u><strong><mark> can never achieve such life-affirmation.</u></strong></mark> Indeed, no matter how strong and healthy¶ he deemed himself, perhaps the strongest and healthiest of all of his¶ contemporaries, <u>Nietzsche found himself unable to will his life’s eternal</u>¶<u> recurrence.</u> Writing in his notebooks in 1883, Nietzsche exclaims: ‘I do not¶ want life again. How have I borne it? What has made me endure the sight?¶ the vision of the superhuman who affirms life. I have tried to affirm it¶ myself —alas!’ (Nachlaß November 1882–February 1883, KSA 10,¶ 4[81]).13¶ So, <u>rather than conferring meaning upon the human animal’s past, <strong><mark>the thought of eternal recurrence</mark> actually <mark>multiplies and intensifies the meaninglessness of this past</strong></mark> to a new and devastating degree.</u> This is why Nietzsche¶ writes in his 1887 notes that the thought of eternal recurrence builds¶ upon the nihilism that follows the demise of the ascetic ideal—that is, upon¶ the most paralysing thought of ‘continuing with an “in vain”, without aim¶ and purpose’. <u>Eternal recurrence, he writes, is the most extreme form of</u>¶<u> nihilism because it is the ‘thought of existence as it is, without meaning or</u>¶<u> goal, but inevitably recurring, without any finale into nothingness’</u> (Nachla߶ Summer 1886–Autumn 1887, KSA 12, 5[71], my emphasis). It is not¶ just the thought of meaninglessness, but the thought of meaninglessness¶ eternally. Previously the human animal sought solace in the idea of death¶ and nothingness as an escape from the meaninglessness of its life and suffering.¶ But the thought of eternal recurrence closes off all such escape and¶ condemns the human animal to eternal meaninglessness. As Nietzsche¶ writes in his 1883 notes: ‘<u><mark>everything becomes and recurs eternally— escape</u>¶<u> is impossible</u></mark>!” (Nachlaß Winter 1883–1884, KSA 10, 24[7]).14¶ Nor can it be replied to this that, because death no longer affords an escape¶ to life’s suffering, there is actually less point to suicide. For in the third essay of the Genealogy Nietzsche argues that <u><strong><mark>the thought of death as escape</u></strong>¶<u><strong> keeps humans from giving in to their pre-existing death-wish by imparting</u></strong>¶<u><strong> meaning to life’s suffering and offering the hope of a different or</u></strong>¶<u><strong> better life.</u></strong></mark> Because eternal recurrence undermines both this meaning and¶ this hope, nothing remains to keep humans from giving in to their inherent¶ suicidal instincts.</p>
null
null
null
430,014
3
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,933
Their testing standards are nonfalsifiable
Mutz 8
Mutz 8 (Diana, Department of Political Science and Annenberg School, University of Pennsylvania, “Is Deliberative Democracy a Falsifiable Theory?” Annual Review of Political Science Vol. 11: 521-538)
Falsifiability is probably the single most intransigent issue in getting normative theory and empirical research to speak to one another in the realm of deliberative theory. Several problems conspire to make deliberative theory elusive in this respect. For some theorists, deliberation is simply defined as intrinsically good. Obviously, such a claim renders empirical research irrelevant But even without the assumption of intrinsic goodness, more complex problems hinder the interaction between empirical studies and political theory deliberation falls short on many of the standards deemed essential to good social science theory Beyond the general issue of falsifiability, deliberative theory falls short of meeting three requirements for productive social theory that are enumerated in virtually any textbook: clearly defined concepts; specification of logical relationships among concepts within the theory; consistency between hypotheses and evidence accumulated to date. When theories cannot meet these three criteria, they are generally unproductive in advancing our understanding of the phenomenon of interest. when empirical researchers attempt to translate deliberative theory into these terms they discover a great deal of conceptual ambiguity as to what should qualify as deliberation. Moreover, the definitions offered by theorists frequently conflate causes (criteria defining deliberation) and effects (its beneficial consequences). Second, the tests of deliberative theory do not develop well-specified explanations for the relationships between deliberation and its many proposed benefits. Third, deliberative theory is inconsistent with much of what is already known about political discourse in group contexts. Many of the hypotheses that flow from the deliberative framework are not well-grounded in either previous theory or empirical evidence
Falsifiability is the single most intransigent issue in getting empirical research in the realm of deliberative theory. deliberation is defined as intrinsically good such a claim renders empirical research irrelevant Beyond falsifiability, deliberative theory falls short of meeting three requirements for theory that are enumerated in virtually any textbook: clearly defined concepts logical relationships among concepts consistency between hypotheses and evidence definitions offered by theorists frequently conflate causes (criteria defining deliberation) and effects (its beneficial consequences). tests do not develop explanations for the relationships between deliberation and its proposed benefits deliberative theory is inconsistent with what is already known about political discourse the deliberative framework are not grounded in empirical evidence
Falsifiability is probably the single most intransigent issue in getting normative theory and empirical research to speak to one another in the realm of deliberative theory. Several problems conspire to make deliberative theory elusive in this respect. For some theorists, deliberation is simply defined as intrinsically good. Obviously, such a claim renders empirical research irrelevant (see, e.g., Stokes 1998). But even without the assumption of intrinsic goodness, more complex problems hinder the interaction between empirical studies and political theory. It is difficult to envision an empirical test that might produce evidence construed by theorists and empiricists alike as disconfirming the claims of deliberative theory. This is because deliberation falls short on many of the standards deemed essential to good social science theory, at least as the theory is currently construed. Beyond the general issue of falsifiability, deliberative theory falls short of meeting three requirements for productive social theory that are enumerated in virtually any textbook: 1. clearly defined concepts; 2. specification of logical relationships among concepts within the theory; 3. consistency between hypotheses and evidence accumulated to date. It is, of course, unfair to criticize a normative theory for lacking the characteristics required of productive social science theory. But criticism is not my main purpose. Instead, I want to take seriously the admonition that the two subfields should talk to one another. To make a dialogue possible, this normative theory must be translated into the terminology of empirical social science and must then be subjected to the standards of theory testing within the social science tradition. It is crucial to address these three problems in order to accumulate useful empirical evidence on the potential of deliberative democracy. Social scientists generally define “theory” as a set of interrelated statements intended to explain and/or make predictions about some aspect of social life. Toward those ends, a good theory is supposed to have well-defined constructs of general theoretical interest. It is supposed to describe logical associations among these constructs (which are most often causal associations), and it should allow for connections between the theoretical constructs and observable entities. When theories cannot meet these three criteria, they are generally unproductive in advancing our understanding of the phenomenon of interest.2 What happens when empirical researchers attempt to translate deliberative theory into these terms? First, as Thompson points out, they discover a great deal of conceptual ambiguity as to what should qualify as deliberation. Moreover, the definitions offered by theorists frequently conflate causes (criteria defining deliberation) and effects (its beneficial consequences). Second, the tests of deliberative theory offered to date typically do not develop well-specified explanations for the relationships between deliberation and its many proposed benefits. Third, deliberative theory is inconsistent with much of what is already known about political discourse in group contexts. Many, though not all, of the hypotheses that flow from the deliberative framework are not well-grounded in either previous theory or empirical evidence.
3,336
<h4>Their testing standards are nonfalsifiable</h4><p><strong>Mutz 8</strong> (Diana, Department of Political Science and Annenberg School, University of Pennsylvania, “Is Deliberative Democracy a Falsifiable Theory?” Annual Review of Political Science Vol. 11: 521-538)</p><p><u><strong><mark>Falsifiability is </mark>probably <mark>the single most intransigent issue in getting </mark>normative theory and <mark>empirical research </mark>to speak to one another <mark>in the realm of deliberative theory.</mark> Several problems conspire to make deliberative theory elusive in this respect. For some theorists, <mark>deliberation is </mark>simply <mark>defined as intrinsically good</mark>. Obviously, <mark>such a claim renders empirical research irrelevant</u></strong> </mark>(see, e.g., Stokes 1998). <u><strong>But even without the assumption of intrinsic goodness, more complex problems hinder the interaction between empirical studies and political theory</u></strong>. It is difficult to envision an empirical test that might produce evidence construed by theorists and empiricists alike as disconfirming the claims of deliberative theory. This is because <u><strong>deliberation falls short on many of the standards deemed essential to good social science theory</u></strong>, at least as the theory is currently construed. <u><strong><mark>Beyond </mark>the general issue of <mark>falsifiability, deliberative theory falls short of meeting three requirements for </mark>productive social <mark>theory</u></strong> <u><strong>that are enumerated in virtually any textbook: </u></strong></mark>1. <u><strong><mark>clearly defined concepts</mark>; </u></strong>2. <u><strong>specification of <mark>logical relationships among concepts </mark>within the theory;</u></strong> 3. <u><strong><mark>consistency between hypotheses and evidence </mark>accumulated to date.</u></strong> It is, of course, unfair to criticize a normative theory for lacking the characteristics required of productive social science theory. But criticism is not my main purpose. Instead, I want to take seriously the admonition that the two subfields should talk to one another. To make a dialogue possible, this normative theory must be translated into the terminology of empirical social science and must then be subjected to the standards of theory testing within the social science tradition. It is crucial to address these three problems in order to accumulate useful empirical evidence on the potential of deliberative democracy. Social scientists generally define “theory” as a set of interrelated statements intended to explain and/or make predictions about some aspect of social life. Toward those ends, a good theory is supposed to have well-defined constructs of general theoretical interest. It is supposed to describe logical associations among these constructs (which are most often causal associations), and it should allow for connections between the theoretical constructs and observable entities. <u><strong>When theories cannot meet these three criteria, they are generally unproductive in advancing our understanding of the phenomenon of interest.</u></strong>2 What happens <u><strong>when empirical researchers attempt to translate deliberative theory into these terms</u></strong>? First, as Thompson points out, <u><strong>they discover a great deal of conceptual ambiguity as to what should qualify as deliberation. Moreover, the <mark>definitions offered by theorists frequently conflate causes (criteria defining deliberation) and effects (its beneficial consequences). </mark>Second, the <mark>tests </mark>of deliberative theory</u></strong> offered to date typically <u><strong><mark>do not develop </mark>well-specified <mark>explanations for the relationships between deliberation and its </mark>many <mark>proposed benefits</mark>. Third, <mark>deliberative theory is inconsistent with </mark>much of <mark>what is already known about political discourse </mark>in group contexts. Many</u></strong>, though not all, <u><strong>of the hypotheses that flow from <mark>the deliberative framework are not </mark>well-<mark>grounded in </mark>either previous theory or <mark>empirical evidence</u></strong></mark>.</p>
2AC
FW
AT: Decisionmaking
94,266
27
16,993
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
564,698
A
NDT
3
UTD LO
Heidt, Shook, Lundberg
1AC PAS genealogy- same assimilar to USC PAS 1AC 1NC T- Framework K- Szaz Medicalization of death 2NR T
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,934
Those turn the entire case and cause more structural violence
Mercille 14
Mercille 14 (Julien Mercille, PhD in geography from UCLA, lecturer at the School of Geography, Planning & Environmental Policy at the University College Dublin, March 2014, “The Media-Entertainment Industry and the “War on Drugs” in Mexico,” Latin American Perspectives Volume 41 Number 2) gz
neoliberal reforms have contributed to increasing the size of the industry reforms such as NAFTA pushed more Mexicans toward the drug industry, both to find work and out of desperation. Neoliberalism has had largely negative consequences for the majority of Mexicans. Whereas before reforms were implemented the economy grew at a rate of 3.5 percent between 1960 and 1979 this dropped to a meager 0.1 percent in the 1980s and 1.6 percent from 1992 to 2007. NAFTA has not led to job growth or wage increases: for example, in Juárez, the average wage decreased from US$4.50 a day to US$3.70 the manufacturing sector has added some 500,000 to 600,000 net jobs, but they have been offset by a loss of around 2.3 million jobs in agriculture because of cheaper corn imports from subsidized U.S. agrobusinesses. This has forced farmers to leave their land and either migrate to the United States or move to cities in Mexico’s North, where many have become cheap labor in U.S. manufactures many Mexicans had little choice but to participate in drug trafficking, often as low-level dealers, to make ends meet Finally, the social dislocation and unemployment caused by neoliberal reforms has increased Mexicans’ use of drugs to alleviate suffering, thereby enlarging the market Who in their right mind would turn down a chance to consume drugs in a city of poverty, filth, violence, and despair?”
NAFTA pushed more Mexicans toward the drug industry to find work out of desperation Whereas before reforms the economy grew at 3.5 percent this dropped to a meager 0.1 percent NAFTA has not led to job growth or wage increases average wage decreased from 4.50 to 3.70 manufacturing has added 500,000 jobs, but they have been offset by a loss of 2.3 million in agriculture because of cheaper corn from U.S. agrobusinesses many had little choice but to participate in drug trafficking as low-level dealers, to make ends meet neoliberal reforms has increased Mexicans’ use of drugs to alleviate suffering enlarging the market
Since the 1980s, neoliberal reforms have contributed to increasing the size of the industry (although there are other causes as well) (Watt and Zepeda, 2012). First, drug smuggling has been facilitated by larger trade flows across the U.S.-Mexico border. Cartels started shipping cocaine, cannabis, crystal meth, and heroin on trucks going to the United States (Bowden, 2010). Second, reforms such as NAFTA pushed more Mexicans toward the drug industry, both to find work and out of desperation. Neoliberalism has had largely negative consequences for the majority of Mexicans. Whereas before reforms were implemented the economy grew at a rate of 3.5 percent between 1960 and 1979 (annual per capita rate), this dropped to a meager 0.1 percent in the 1980s and 1.6 percent from 1992 to 2007. NAFTA has not led to job growth or wage increases: for example, in Juárez, the average wage decreased from US$4.50 a day to US$3.70. Since NAFTA went into effect, the manufacturing sector has added some 500,000 to 600,000 net jobs, but they have been offset by a loss of around 2.3 million jobs in agriculture because of cheaper corn imports from subsidized U.S. agrobusinesses. This has forced farmers to leave their land and either migrate to the United States or move to cities in Mexico’s North, where many have become cheap labor in U.S. manufactures (maquiladoras). The size of the informal economy, in which workers face worse conditions, has increased from 53 percent of the workforce in 1992 to 57 percent in 2004 (Bowden, 2010: 98; Faux, 2006: 40; Zepeda, Wise, and Gallagher, 2009). Consequently, many Mexicans had little choice but to participate in drug trafficking, often as low-level dealers, to make ends meet. The supply of laborers for the cartels increased again around 2000 as maquiladoras faced competition from China’s and India’s cheaper labor. Some companies located in Mexico moved to Asia, leading to further layoffs. Finally, the social dislocation and unemployment caused by neoliberal reforms has increased Mexicans’ use of drugs to alleviate suffering, thereby enlarging the market. Charles Bowden (2010: 55), a veteran analyst of Mexico, speaking of Juárez, asks, “Who in their right mind would turn down a chance to consume drugs in a city of poverty, filth, violence, and despair?”
2,307
<h4>Those turn the entire case and cause more structural violence</h4><p><u><strong>Mercille 14</u></strong> (Julien Mercille, PhD in geography from UCLA, lecturer at the School of Geography, Planning & Environmental Policy at the University College Dublin, March 2014, “The Media-Entertainment Industry and the “War on Drugs” in Mexico,” Latin American Perspectives<u> Volume 41 Number 2) gz</p><p></u>Since the 1980s, <u>neoliberal reforms have contributed to increasing the size of the industry</u> (although there are other causes as well) (Watt and Zepeda, 2012). First, drug smuggling has been facilitated by larger trade flows across the U.S.-Mexico border. Cartels started shipping cocaine, cannabis, crystal meth, and heroin on trucks going to the United States (Bowden, 2010). Second, <u>reforms such as <mark>NAFTA <strong>pushed more Mexicans toward the drug industry</strong></mark>, both <mark>to find work</mark> and <mark>out of desperation</mark>. Neoliberalism has had largely negative consequences for the majority of Mexicans. <mark>Whereas before reforms</mark> were implemented <mark>the economy grew at</mark> a rate of <mark>3.5 percent</mark> between 1960 and 1979</u> (annual per capita rate), <u><mark>this dropped to <strong>a meager 0.1 percent</strong> </mark>in the 1980s and 1.6 percent from 1992 to 2007. <strong><mark>NAFTA has not led to job growth or wage increases</strong></mark>: for example, in Juárez, the <mark>average wage decreased <strong>from</mark> US$<mark>4.50</mark> a day <mark>to</mark> US$<mark>3.70</u></strong></mark>. Since NAFTA went into effect, <u>the <mark>manufacturing</mark> sector <mark>has added</mark> some <mark>500,000</mark> to 600,000 net <mark>jobs, but they have been offset by a loss of</mark> around <strong><mark>2.3 million</mark> jobs <mark>in agriculture </strong>because of cheaper corn</mark> imports <mark>from</mark> subsidized <mark>U.S. agrobusinesses</mark>. This has forced farmers to leave their land and either migrate to the United States or move to cities in Mexico’s North, where many have become cheap labor in U.S. manufactures</u> (maquiladoras). The size of the informal economy, in which workers face worse conditions, has increased from 53 percent of the workforce in 1992 to 57 percent in 2004 (Bowden, 2010: 98; Faux, 2006: 40; Zepeda, Wise, and Gallagher, 2009). Consequently, <u><mark>many</mark> Mexicans <mark>had little choice but to participate in drug trafficking</mark>, often <mark>as low-level dealers, to make ends meet</u></mark>. The supply of laborers for the cartels increased again around 2000 as maquiladoras faced competition from China’s and India’s cheaper labor. Some companies located in Mexico moved to Asia, leading to further layoffs. <u>Finally, the social dislocation and unemployment caused by <mark>neoliberal reforms has <strong>increased Mexicans’ use of drugs to alleviate suffering</strong></mark>, thereby <mark>enlarging the market</u></mark>. Charles Bowden (2010: 55), a veteran analyst of Mexico, speaking of Juárez, asks, “<u>Who in their right mind would turn down a chance to consume drugs in a city of poverty, filth, violence, and despair?”</p></u>
2NC
K
Link – Mexico
429,899
5
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,935
Global economy resilient
Zakaria 9
Zakaria 9
One year ago, the world seemed as if it might be coming apart. The global financial system was crumbling Pundits whose bearishness had been vindicated predicted we were doomed to cascading failures country after country. Others predicted economic shocks would lead to political instability and violence One year later, how much has the world really changed? Wall Street is home to two fewer investment banks There was some turmoil in Moldova But overall, things look nothing like they did in the 1930s. predictions of collapse have not materialized at all.¶ governments, having learned the lessons of the Great Depression, were determined not to repeat the same mistakes once this crisis hit. By expanding state support for the economy they buffered the worst of the damage social safety nets that cushioned the pain felt by many things are nowhere near as bad as in the 1930s, when governments played a tiny role in national economies.¶ interventions may be fueling some bubbles Yet these rallies also demonstrate the return of confidence, and confidence is a powerful economic force. why we have not faced global collapse It is the same reason that we weathered the market crash of 87, the recession of 92, the Asian crisis of 97 the Russian default of 98, and the tech-bubble collapse The global economic system is inherently more resilient than we think
Pundits predicted we were doomed to cascading failures Others predicted shocks would lead to instability One year later, how much has the world changed? Wall Street is home to two fewer investment banks There was some turmoil in Moldova But things look nothing like the 30s governments, having learned the lessons of the Great Depression were determined not to repeat the same mistakes By expanding state support they buffered the worst of the damage social safety nets cushioned the pain the reason that we weathered the market crash of 87, the recession of 92, the Asian crisis of 97, the Russian default of 98, and the tech-bubble collapse The global economic system is resilient
PhD in pol sci from Harvard. Editor of Newsweek, BA from Yale, PhD in pol sci, Harvard. He serves on the board of Yale University, The Council on Foreign Relations, The Trilateral Commission, and Shakespeare and Company. Named "one of the 21 most important people of the 21st Century" (Fareed, The Secrets of Stability, 12 December 2009, http://www.fareedzakaria.com/articles/articles.html) One year ago, the world seemed as if it might be coming apart. The global financial system, which had fueled a great expansion of capitalism and trade across the world, was crumbling. All the certainties of the age of globalization—about the virtues of free markets, trade, and technology—were being called into question. Faith in the American model had collapsed. The financial industry had crumbled. Once-roaring emerging markets like China, India, and Brazil were sinking. Worldwide trade was shrinking to a degree not seen since the 1930s.¶ Pundits whose bearishness had been vindicated predicted we were doomed to a long, painful bust, with cascading failures in sector after sector, country after country. In a widely cited essay that appeared in The Atlantic this May, Simon Johnson, former chief economist of the International Monetary Fund, wrote: "The conventional wisdom among the elite is still that the current slump 'cannot be as bad as the Great Depression.' This view is wrong. What we face now could, in fact, be worse than the Great Depression."¶ Others predicted that these economic shocks would lead to political instability and violence in the worst-hit countries. At his confirmation hearing in February, the new U.S. director of national intelligence, Adm. Dennis Blair, cautioned the Senate that "the financial crisis and global recession are likely to produce a wave of economic crises in emerging-market nations over the next year." Hillary Clinton endorsed this grim view. And she was hardly alone. Foreign Policy ran a cover story predicting serious unrest in several emerging markets.¶ Of one thing everyone was sure: nothing would ever be the same again. Not the financial industry, not capitalism, not globalization.¶ One year later, how much has the world really changed? Well, Wall Street is home to two fewer investment banks (three, if you count Merrill Lynch). Some regional banks have gone bust. There was some turmoil in Moldova and (entirely unrelated to the financial crisis) in Iran. Severe problems remain, like high unemployment in the West, and we face new problems caused by responses to the crisis—soaring debt and fears of inflation. But overall, things look nothing like they did in the 1930s. The predictions of economic and political collapse have not materialized at all.¶ A key measure of fear and fragility is the ability of poor and unstable countries to borrow money on the debt markets. So consider this: the sovereign bonds of tottering Pakistan have returned 168 percent so far this year. All this doesn't add up to a recovery yet, but it does reflect a return to some level of normalcy. And that rebound has been so rapid that even the shrewdest observers remain puzzled. "The question I have at the back of my head is 'Is that it?' " says Charles Kaye, the co-head of Warburg Pincus. "We had this huge crisis, and now we're back to business as usual?"¶ This revival did not happen because markets managed to stabilize themselves on their own. Rather, governments, having learned the lessons of the Great Depression, were determined not to repeat the same mistakes once this crisis hit. By massively expanding state support for the economy—through central banks and national treasuries—they buffered the worst of the damage. (Whether they made new mistakes in the process remains to be seen.) The extensive social safety nets that have been established across the industrialized world also cushioned the pain felt by many. Times are still tough, but things are nowhere near as bad as in the 1930s, when governments played a tiny role in national economies.¶ It's true that the massive state interventions of the past year may be fueling some new bubbles: the cheap cash and government guarantees provided to banks, companies, and consumers have fueled some irrational exuberance in stock and bond markets. Yet these rallies also demonstrate the return of confidence, and confidence is a very powerful economic force. When John Maynard Keynes described his own prescriptions for economic growth, he believed government action could provide only a temporary fix until the real motor of the economy started cranking again—the animal spirits of investors, consumers, and companies seeking risk and profit.¶ Beyond all this, though, I believe there's a fundamental reason why we have not faced global collapse in the last year. It is the same reason that we weathered the stock-market crash of 1987, the recession of 1992, the Asian crisis of 1997, the Russian default of 1998, and the tech-bubble collapse of 2000. The current global economic system is inherently more resilient than we think. The world today is characterized by three major forces for stability, each reinforcing the other and each historical in nature.
5,167
<h4><u><strong>Global economy resilient </h4><p>Zakaria</u> 9 </p><p></strong>PhD in pol sci from Harvard. Editor of Newsweek, BA from Yale, PhD in pol sci, Harvard. He serves on the board of Yale University, The Council on Foreign Relations, The Trilateral Commission, and Shakespeare and Company. Named "one of the 21 most important people of the 21st Century" (Fareed, The Secrets of Stability, 12 December 2009, http://www.fareedzakaria.com/articles/articles.html)</p><p><u>One year ago, the world seemed as if it might be coming apart. The global financial system</u>, which had fueled a great expansion of capitalism and trade across the world, <u>was crumbling</u>. All the certainties of the age of globalization—about the virtues of free markets, trade, and technology—were being called into question. Faith in the American model had collapsed. The financial industry had crumbled. Once-roaring emerging markets like China, India, and Brazil were sinking. Worldwide trade was shrinking to a degree not seen since the 1930s.¶ <u><mark>Pundits</mark> whose bearishness had been vindicated <mark>predicted we were doomed to</u></mark> a long, painful bust, with <u><mark>cascading failures</u></mark> in sector after sector, <u>country after country.</u> In a widely cited essay that appeared in The Atlantic this May, Simon Johnson, former chief economist of the International Monetary Fund, wrote: "The conventional wisdom among the elite is still that the current slump 'cannot be as bad as the Great Depression.' This view is wrong. What we face now could, in fact, be worse than the Great Depression."¶ <u><mark>Others predicted</u></mark> that these <u>economic <mark>shocks would lead to</mark> political</u> <u><mark>instability</mark> and violence</u> in the worst-hit countries. At his confirmation hearing in February, the new U.S. director of national intelligence, Adm. Dennis Blair, cautioned the Senate that "the financial crisis and global recession are likely to produce a wave of economic crises in emerging-market nations over the next year." Hillary Clinton endorsed this grim view. And she was hardly alone. Foreign Policy ran a cover story predicting serious unrest in several emerging markets.¶ Of one thing everyone was sure: nothing would ever be the same again. Not the financial industry, not capitalism, not globalization.¶ <u><mark>One year later, how much has the world </mark>really <mark>changed?</u></mark> Well, <u><mark>Wall Street is home to two fewer investment banks</u></mark> (three, if you count Merrill Lynch). Some regional banks have gone bust. <u><mark>There was some turmoil in Moldova</u></mark> and (entirely unrelated to the financial crisis) in Iran. Severe problems remain, like high unemployment in the West, and we face new problems caused by responses to the crisis—soaring debt and fears of inflation. <u><mark>But</mark> overall, <mark>things look nothing like</mark> they did in <mark>the</mark> 19<mark>30s</mark>.</u> The <u>predictions of</u> economic and political <u>collapse have not materialized at all.¶ </u>A key measure of fear and fragility is the ability of poor and unstable countries to borrow money on the debt markets. So consider this: the sovereign bonds of tottering Pakistan have returned 168 percent so far this year. All this doesn't add up to a recovery yet, but it does reflect a return to some level of normalcy. And that rebound has been so rapid that even the shrewdest observers remain puzzled. "The question I have at the back of my head is 'Is that it?' " says Charles Kaye, the co-head of Warburg Pincus. "We had this huge crisis, and now we're back to business as usual?"¶ This revival did not happen because markets managed to stabilize themselves on their own. Rather, <u><mark>governments, having learned the lessons of the Great Depression</mark>, <mark>were determined not to repeat the same mistakes</mark> once this crisis hit. <mark>By</u></mark> massively <u><mark>expanding</u> <u>state support</mark> for the economy</u>—through central banks and national treasuries—<u><mark>they buffered the worst of the damage</u></mark>. (Whether they made new mistakes in the process remains to be seen.) The extensive <u><mark>social safety nets</mark> that</u> have been established across the industrialized world also <u><mark>cushioned the pain</mark> felt by many</u>. Times are still tough, but <u>things are nowhere near as bad as in the 1930s, when governments played a tiny role in national economies.¶ </u>It's true that the massive state <u>interventions</u> of the past year <u>may be fueling some</u> new <u>bubbles</u>: the cheap cash and government guarantees provided to banks, companies, and consumers have fueled some irrational exuberance in stock and bond markets. <u>Yet</u> <u>these rallies also</u> <u>demonstrate the return of confidence, and confidence is a</u> very <u>powerful economic force.</u> When John Maynard Keynes described his own prescriptions for economic growth, he believed government action could provide only a temporary fix until the real motor of the economy started cranking again—the animal spirits of investors, consumers, and companies seeking risk and profit.¶ Beyond all this, though, I believe there's a fundamental reason <u>why we have not faced global collapse</u> in the last year. <u>It is <mark>the</mark> same <mark>reason that we weathered the</mark> </u>stock-<u><mark>market crash of</mark> </u>19<u><mark>87, the recession of</u></mark> 19<u><mark>92, the Asian crisis of</u></mark> 19<u><mark>97</u>, <u>the Russian default of</u></mark> 19<u><mark>98, and the tech-bubble collapse</u></mark> of 2000. <u><mark>The</u></mark> current <u><mark>global economic system is</mark> inherently more <mark>resilient</mark> than we think</u>. The world today is characterized by three major forces for stability, each reinforcing the other and each historical in nature.</p>
1NR
Banks
2NC Trade Finance Resilient
73,430
105
16,987
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round1.docx
564,729
N
NDT
1
Harvard DH
Eric Short, Chris Thiele, Dan Stout
1ac was online gambling with econ and china advantages 1nc was security edelman and case 2nc was security 1nr was case 2nr was security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round1.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,936
Purity and Holiness become the conditions for treatment, resting on the imperative to preserve life which always subordinates a patient’s desire to the health of the body politic –
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Purity and Holiness become the conditions for treatment, resting on the imperative to preserve life which always subordinates a patient’s desire to the health of the body politic – </h4>
null
1AC
null
430,051
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,937
Bidirectionality – they affirm both legalization and decrim which is neg ground
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Bidirectionality – they affirm both legalization and decrim which is neg ground</h4>
1NC
null
Off
430,052
1
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,938
Political subjects under the state are ahistorical fabrications of being – our praxis of counter-memory exposes the illusion of subjectivity and, through a process of cutting, opens up space for radical becoming. Michael Clifford explains
ondon, Great Britain. pp. 134-7
Michael, Associate Professor of Philosophy with the Institute for the Humanities and the Department of Philosophy and Religion at Mississippi State University, 2001, “Political Genealogy After Foucault”. Routledge, London, Great Britain. pp. 134-7
counter-memory is very close to the Nietzschean idea of “active forgetfulness” Counter-memory consists of essentially forgetting who we are. It is a forgetfulness of essence, of necessity, of the moral and ontological obligations that bind us to an identity. Counter-memory holds us at a remove, a distance, from ourselves; not in the traditional sense of self reflection, but of wrenching the self—this identity—apart, through an incision, a cutting that makes the self stand naked and strange before us across an unbridgeable divide, a gap of difference. The self, as a coherent identity, becomes foreign through counter-memory. We cannot remember what it was that compelled us to act, believe, be a given way. Counter-memory dissolves this compulsion, this determination, this subjection. The power of identity is suspended through a forgetfulness of its necessity—a freedom is opened within the space of a difference that no identity can constrain. Counter-memory bears directly on processes of subjectivation “Counter-discourses” anticipate a subjectival freedom of open possibilities by opposing themselves to the discourses of truth through which we recognize ourselves as subjects. These counter-discourses, the discourses of genealogy, lift the burdensome obligations imposed on us by such a recognition. counter-memory always takes the form of a transgression. Yet there is freedom in this refusal, Counter-memory counters, or suspends, the power of identity through genealogical accounts of its constitution. Genealogy effects “the systematic dissociation of identity” by revealing its radical contingency, its historicality and utter lack of essentiality. The purpose of genealogy is not to discover the roots of our identity, but to commit itself to its dissipation.” Genealogical critique is an exposition of our history as subjects that has the effect of disposing subjectival constraints by exposing the contingency of their imposition Wherever “the self fabricates a coherent identity,” genealogy puts into play a subversive counter-analysis that “permits the dissociation of the self Genealogy disturbs, fragments, displaces the unity of subjectivity. It cuts through the oppressive, assimilating density of Truth and discovers in this beguiling haze that subjectivity is nothing more than a colorful mask. Behind it there is no essential identity, no unified spirit or will, no naked subject stripped of its colorful dress. there is only a matrix of intersecting lines and heterogenous congruities, an arbitrary and historically contingent complex of discursive and nondiscursive practices. Unity is a mask for an interplay of anonymous forces and historical accidents that permits us to identify subjects identity—is imposed on subjects as the mask of their fabrication. Subjectivity is the carceral and incarcerating expression of this imposition, of the limitations drawn around us by discourses of truth and practices of individualization; but seen through the “differential knowledge” of genealogy, the identity of subjectivity collapses Counter-memory through genealogical critique is a transgression of limits. As such, it opens onto a possibility of freedom. genealogy gives “new impetus, as far and wide as possible, to the undefined work of freedom.” It is not a freedom against the office of government, but against governmentality—against a rationality that imprisons us in the cellular space of our own self-government. the freedom of/through counter-memory is a form of mimetic play with the notion of positive freedom whereby citizenship is unwrapped like a cloak from the politicized body. by exposing the nonessentiality of the limits imposed on us through the constitution of a self, it opens the possibility of going beyond those limits. a kind of fracture, at once an open space and a breaking free of the constraining power inherent in identity and identification. Freedom, concrete freedom, is a space of possible transformation. Even the most violent forms of resistance against subjection accomplish nothing if they do not gain this freedom, do not open a space of possible transformation—which means nothing more, and nothing less, than the possibility of being otherwise what is being required here is not a freedom to transform ourselves in accordance with some global or teleological model of a more “genuine” form of subjectivity. Rather, the freedom opened by counter-memory is a freedom of permanent transformation, of always being able to become other than what we are.
Counter-memory consists of forgetting who we are a forgetfulness of essence, of necessity, of moral and ontological obligations that bind us to an identity Counter-memory holds us at a distance, from ourselves wrenching the self apart, through an incision, a cutting that makes the self stand naked and strange The self becomes foreign We cannot remember what it was that compelled us to act, believe, be a given way. Counter-memory dissolves this compulsion, this determination, this subjection identity is suspended through forgetfulness of its necessity Counter-discourses” anticipate a subjectival freedom by opposing discourses of truth the discourses of genealogy, lift obligations imposed on us by such a recognition counter-memory takes the form of a transgression there is freedom in refusal Counter-memory suspends identity through genealogical accounts of its constitution The purpose of genealogy is not to discover the roots of our identity, but to commit to its dissipation Genealogical critique is an exposition of our history as subjects disposing subjectival constraints by exposing contingency Genealogy cuts through the oppressive density of Truth and discovers that subjectivity is nothing more than a colorful mask there is no essential identity, no unified spirit or will, no naked subject stripped of its colorful dress only a matrix of intersecting lines and heterogenous congruities Subjectivity is the carceral and incarcerating expression of this imposition but seen through the “differential knowledge” of genealogy, the identity of subjectivity collapses It is not a freedom against the government, but against governmentality a rationality that imprisons us in the cellular space of our own self-government a form of mimetic play with the notion of positive freedom whereby citizenship is unwrapped from the politicized body Even the most violent forms of resistance accomplish nothing if they do not open a space of possible transformation a freedom of permanent transformation, of always being able to become other than what we are
Foucault’s counter-memory is very close to the Nietzschean idea of “active forgetfulness” (aktive Vergesslichkeit).21 Counter-memory consists of essentially forgetting who we are. It is a forgetfulness of essence, of necessity, of the moral and ontological obligations that bind us to an identity. There is freedom in forgetfulness. Counter-memory holds us at a remove, a distance, from ourselves; not in the traditional sense of self reflection, but of wrenching the self—this identity—apart, through an incision, a cutting that makes the self stand naked and strange before us across an unbridgeable divide, a gap of difference. Counter-memory dislodges the propriety of our-selves. The self, as a coherent identity, becomes foreign through counter-memory. We cannot remember what it was that compelled us to act, believe, be a given way. Counter-memory dissolves this compulsion, this determination, this subjection. The power of identity is suspended through a forgetfulness of its necessity—a freedom is opened within the space of a difference that no identity can constrain. This difference always plays outside the limits, outside any delimitation of being. Counter-memory thrusts us into this uncharted world, where a memory makes no sense, where play is the order of the day, where lightening and chance disintegrate the heavy and solid, the identical. Counter-memory bears directly on processes of subjectivation, on the techniques of the self through which we constitute for ourselves an identity. “Counter-discourses” anticipate a subjectival freedom of open possibilities by opposing themselves to the discourses of truth through which we recognize ourselves as subjects.22 These counter-discourses, the discourses of genealogy, lift the burdensome obligations imposed on us by such a recognition. As a forgetfulness of these obligations, counter-memory always takes the form of a transgression. It invites condemnation even as it refuses to be held accountable. Yet there is freedom in this refusal, in this transgression—for those who have the stomach for it.23 There is always an essential risk involved in refusing, in forgetting, one’s identity.24 Counter-memory is not a form of consciousness. It is nothing, really, except the effect of a certain kind of description of ourselves, a description of the historical ontology of ourselves as subjects. This description has been closed off and denied by power/knowledge relations, excluded and made peripheral by certain dominant discourses and entrenched scientific-philosophical enterprises that bind us to a conception of what we are in truth. Counter-memory counters, or suspends, the power of identity through genealogical accounts of its constitution. Genealogy effects “the systematic dissociation of identity” by revealing its radical contingency, its historicality and utter lack of essentiality. The purpose of genealogy, says Foucault, “is not to discover the roots of our identity, but to commit itself to its dissipation.”25 Genealogical critique is an exposition of our history as subjects that has the effect of disposing subjectival constraints by exposing the contingency of their imposition. Genealogy turns the firm posture of the self-identical subject into the mere posing of a pretentious display. Genealogy proceeds through “dissension” and “disparity.” Wherever “the self fabricates a coherent identity,” genealogy puts into play a subversive counter-analysis that “permits the dissociation of the self, its recognition and displacement as an empty synthesis.”26 Genealogy disturbs, fragments, displaces the unity of subjectivity. It cuts through the oppressive, assimilating density of Truth and discovers in this beguiling haze that subjectivity is nothing more than a colorful mask. Who we are, what we are, is a mask displayed for public viewing and examination, for person-al subjection and ethical subjugation. Genealogy cuts through this mask, only to make another discovery. Behind it there is no essential identity, no unified spirit or will, no naked subject stripped of its colorful dress. Rather, there is only a matrix of intersecting lines and heterogenous congruities, an arbitrary and historically contingent complex of discursive and nondiscursive practices. Asserts Foucault, “If the genealogist refuses to extend his faith in metaphysics, if he listens to history, he finds that there is ‘something altogether different’ behind things; not a timeless and essential secret, but the secret that they have no essence or that their essence was fabricated in a piecemeal fashion from alien forms.”27 Contrary to what René Descartes or John Locke would contend, unity (whether of consciousness proper or the continuity of personal experience) is not the essence of subjectivity. Unity is a mask for an interplay of anonymous forces and historical accidents that permits us to identify subjects, to identify ourselves, as specific human beings. Unity—identity—is imposed on subjects as the mask of their fabrication. Subjectivity is the carceral and incarcerating expression of this imposition, of the limitations drawn around us by discourses of truth and practices of individualization; but seen through the “differential knowledge” of genealogy, the identity of subjectivity collapses. Counter-memory through genealogical critique is a transgression of limits. As such, it opens onto a possibility of freedom. Genealogy permits us “to separate out, from the contingency that has made us what we are, the possibility of no longer being, doing, thinking what we are, do, or think.” In this sense, genealogy gives “new impetus, as far and wide as possible, to the undefined work of freedom.”28 The freedom offered by counter-memory is a kind of parodic reversal of negative freedom: it is not a freedom from interference, but for it—for disruption, for displacement, for violating those inviolable spheres of liberty that serve as the limits of our subjection. It is not a freedom for individuality, but from it—a freedom from individualization, from the practices and discourses which bind us to our own identity as individuals. It is not a freedom against the office of government, but against governmentality—against a rationality that imprisons us in the cellular space of our own self-government. At the same time, the freedom of/through counter-memory is a form of mimetic play with the notion of positive freedom whereby citizenship is unwrapped like a cloak from the politicized body. In simple terms, it can be said that genealogy “enables one to get free of oneself.”29 That is, by exposing the nonessentiality of the limits imposed on us through the constitution of a self, it opens the possibility of going beyond those limits.30 This opening is a kind of fracture, at once an open space and a breaking free of the constraining power inherent in identity and identification. In this sense, genealogy opens up “a space of concrete freedom, i.e., of possible transformation.”31 This notion of fracture allows us to define freedom more precisely, to gauge whether or not a genuine space of freedom has been opened for us. Freedom, concrete freedom, is a space of possible transformation. Unless we are free to transform ourselves, to be other than the identity dictated for us by some extraneous rationality, we have no freedom. Even the most violent forms of resistance against subjection accomplish nothing if they do not gain this freedom, do not open a space of possible transformation—which means nothing more, and nothing less, than the possibility of being otherwise. Something very like this point is made by Dennis Altman with regard to the Stonewall riots of 1969 and the militant Gay Liberation Front that emerged from them in the early 1970s. In one of the seminal texts of what would later become known as Queer Theory, Altman rails against the limited vision of a political movement that sought for gay and lesbian people little more than an expansion of rights and the “liberal tolerance” of the homophile community: “Homosexuals can win acceptance as distinct from tolerance only by a transformation of society, one that is based on a ‘new human’ who is able to accept the multifaceted and varied nature of his or her sexual identity. That such a society can be founded is the gamble upon which gay and women’s liberation are based; like all radical movements they hold to an optimistic view of human nature, above all to its mutability.”32 This requirement that we are only genuinely free if we able to transform ourselves is recalcitrant.33 It is crucial to understand, however, that what is being required here is not a freedom to transform ourselves in accordance with some global or teleological model of a more “genuine” form of subjectivity. This freedom does not consist (as it does in On Liberty) in replacing one form of subjectivity for another that is supposedly “truer” or more fulfilling to human nature. Not only is this illusory and unobtainable, it would also amount to a cancellation of freedom, a reimposition of subjectival limitations and expectations. Rather, the freedom opened by counter-memory is a freedom of permanent transformation, of always being able to become other than what we are.
9,241
<h4>Political subjects under the state are ahistorical fabrications of being – our praxis of counter-memory exposes the illusion of subjectivity and, through a process of cutting, opens up space for radical becoming. Michael Clifford explains</h4><p>Michael, Associate Professor of Philosophy with the Institute for the Humanities and the Department of Philosophy and Religion at Mississippi State University, 2001, “Political Genealogy After Foucault”. Routledge, L<u><strong>ondon, Great Britain. pp. 134-7</p><p></u></strong>Foucault’s <u>counter-memory is very close to the Nietzschean idea of “active forgetfulness”</u> (aktive Vergesslichkeit).21 <u><mark>Counter-memory consists of</mark> essentially <mark>forgetting who we are</mark>. It is <mark>a forgetfulness of essence, of necessity, of</mark> the <mark>moral and ontological obligations that bind us to an identity</mark>.</u> There is freedom in forgetfulness. <u><mark>Counter-memory holds us at</mark> a remove, <mark>a distance, from ourselves</mark>; not in the traditional sense of self reflection, but of <mark>wrenching the self</mark>—this identity—<mark>apart, through an incision, a cutting that makes the self stand naked and strange</mark> before us across an unbridgeable divide, a gap of difference.</u> Counter-memory dislodges the propriety of our-selves. <u><mark>The self</mark>, as a coherent identity, <mark>becomes foreign</mark> through counter-memory. <mark>We cannot remember what it was that compelled us to act, believe, be a given way. Counter-memory dissolves this compulsion, this determination, this subjection</mark>. The power of <mark>identity is suspended through</mark> a <mark>forgetfulness of its necessity</mark>—a freedom is opened within the space of a difference that no identity can constrain.</u> This difference always plays outside the limits, outside any delimitation of being. Counter-memory thrusts us into this uncharted world, where a memory makes no sense, where play is the order of the day, where lightening and chance disintegrate the heavy and solid, the identical. <u>Counter-memory bears directly on processes of subjectivation</u>, on the techniques of the self through which we constitute for ourselves an identity. <u>“<mark>Counter-discourses” anticipate a subjectival freedom</mark> of open possibilities <mark>by opposing</mark> themselves to the <mark>discourses of truth</mark> through which we recognize ourselves as subjects.</u>22 <u>These counter-discourses, <mark>the discourses of genealogy, lift</mark> the burdensome <mark>obligations imposed on us by such a recognition</mark>.</u> As a forgetfulness of these obligations, <u><mark>counter-memory</mark> always <mark>takes the form of a transgression</mark>.</u> It invites condemnation even as it refuses to be held accountable. <u>Yet <mark>there is freedom in</mark> this <mark>refusal</mark>,</u> in this transgression—for those who have the stomach for it.23 There is always an essential risk involved in refusing, in forgetting, one’s identity.24 Counter-memory is not a form of consciousness. It is nothing, really, except the effect of a certain kind of description of ourselves, a description of the historical ontology of ourselves as subjects. This description has been closed off and denied by power/knowledge relations, excluded and made peripheral by certain dominant discourses and entrenched scientific-philosophical enterprises that bind us to a conception of what we are in truth. <u><mark>Counter-memory</mark> counters, or <mark>suspends</mark>, the power of <mark>identity through genealogical accounts of its constitution</mark>. Genealogy effects “the systematic dissociation of identity” by revealing its radical contingency, its historicality and utter lack of essentiality. <mark>The purpose of genealogy</u></mark>, says Foucault, “<u><mark>is not to discover the roots of our identity, but to commit </mark>itself <mark>to its dissipation</mark>.”</u>25 <u><mark>Genealogical critique is</mark> <mark>an exposition of our history as subjects</mark> that has the effect of <mark>disposing subjectival constraints by exposing</mark> the <mark>contingency</mark> of their imposition</u>. Genealogy turns the firm posture of the self-identical subject into the mere posing of a pretentious display. Genealogy proceeds through “dissension” and “disparity.” <u>Wherever “the self fabricates a coherent identity,” genealogy puts into play a subversive counter-analysis that “permits the dissociation of the self</u>, its recognition and displacement as an empty synthesis.”26 <u><mark>Genealogy</mark> disturbs, fragments, displaces the unity of subjectivity. It <mark>cuts through the oppressive</mark>, assimilating <mark>density of Truth and discovers</mark> in this beguiling haze <mark>that subjectivity is nothing more than a colorful mask</mark>.</u> Who we are, what we are, is a mask displayed for public viewing and examination, for person-al subjection and ethical subjugation. Genealogy cuts through this mask, only to make another discovery. <u>Behind it <mark>there is no essential identity, no unified spirit or will, no naked subject stripped of its colorful dress</mark>.</u> Rather, <u>there is <mark>only a matrix of intersecting lines and heterogenous congruities</mark>, an arbitrary and historically contingent complex of discursive and nondiscursive practices.</u> Asserts Foucault, “If the genealogist refuses to extend his faith in metaphysics, if he listens to history, he finds that there is ‘something altogether different’ behind things; not a timeless and essential secret, but the secret that they have no essence or that their essence was fabricated in a piecemeal fashion from alien forms.”27 Contrary to what René Descartes or John Locke would contend, unity (whether of consciousness proper or the continuity of personal experience) is not the essence of subjectivity. <u>Unity is a mask for an interplay of anonymous forces and historical accidents that permits us to identify subjects</u>, to identify ourselves, as specific human beings. Unity—<u>identity—is imposed on subjects as the mask of their fabrication.</u> <u><mark>Subjectivity is the carceral and incarcerating expression of this imposition</mark>, of the limitations drawn around us by discourses of truth and practices of individualization; <mark>but seen through the “differential knowledge” of genealogy, the identity of subjectivity collapses</u></mark>. <u>Counter-memory through genealogical critique is a transgression of limits. As such, it opens onto a possibility of freedom.</u> Genealogy permits us “to separate out, from the contingency that has made us what we are, the possibility of no longer being, doing, thinking what we are, do, or think.” In this sense, <u>genealogy gives “new impetus, as far and wide as possible, to the undefined work of freedom.”</u>28 The freedom offered by counter-memory is a kind of parodic reversal of negative freedom: it is not a freedom from interference, but for it—for disruption, for displacement, for violating those inviolable spheres of liberty that serve as the limits of our subjection. It is not a freedom for individuality, but from it—a freedom from individualization, from the practices and discourses which bind us to our own identity as individuals. <u><mark>It is not a freedom against the</mark> office of <mark>government, but against governmentality</mark>—against <mark>a rationality that imprisons us in the cellular space of our own self-government</mark>.</u> At the same time, <u>the freedom of/through counter-memory is <mark>a form of mimetic play with the notion of positive freedom whereby citizenship is unwrapped</mark> like a cloak <mark>from the politicized body</mark>.</u> In simple terms, it can be said that genealogy “enables one to get free of oneself.”29 That is, <u>by exposing the nonessentiality of the limits imposed on us through the constitution of a self, it opens the possibility of going beyond those limits.</u>30 This opening is <u>a kind of fracture, at once an open space and a breaking free of the constraining power inherent in identity and identification.</u> In this sense, genealogy opens up “a space of concrete freedom, i.e., of possible transformation.”31 This notion of fracture allows us to define freedom more precisely, to gauge whether or not a genuine space of freedom has been opened for us. <u>Freedom, concrete freedom, is a space of possible transformation.</u> Unless we are free to transform ourselves, to be other than the identity dictated for us by some extraneous rationality, we have no freedom. <u><mark>Even the most violent forms of resistance</mark> against subjection <mark>accomplish nothing if they do not</mark> gain this freedom, do not <mark>open a space of possible transformation</mark>—which means nothing more, and nothing less, than the possibility of being otherwise</u>. Something very like this point is made by Dennis Altman with regard to the Stonewall riots of 1969 and the militant Gay Liberation Front that emerged from them in the early 1970s. In one of the seminal texts of what would later become known as Queer Theory, Altman rails against the limited vision of a political movement that sought for gay and lesbian people little more than an expansion of rights and the “liberal tolerance” of the homophile community: “Homosexuals can win acceptance as distinct from tolerance only by a transformation of society, one that is based on a ‘new human’ who is able to accept the multifaceted and varied nature of his or her sexual identity. That such a society can be founded is the gamble upon which gay and women’s liberation are based; like all radical movements they hold to an optimistic view of human nature, above all to its mutability.”32 This requirement that we are only genuinely free if we able to transform ourselves is recalcitrant.33 It is crucial to understand, however, that <u>what is being required here is not a freedom to transform ourselves in accordance with some global or teleological model of a more “genuine” form of subjectivity.</u> This freedom does not consist (as it does in On Liberty) in replacing one form of subjectivity for another that is supposedly “truer” or more fulfilling to human nature. Not only is this illusory and unobtainable, it would also amount to a cancellation of freedom, a reimposition of subjectival limitations and expectations. <u>Rather, the freedom opened by counter-memory is <mark>a freedom of permanent transformation, of always being able to become other than what we are</mark>.</p></u>
null
null
null
221,971
16
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,939
Their notion of agonistic respect is a life-denying destruction of the agon. Fairness doesn’t come from the judge but from unfeterred contestation of will – only by challenging the rules of the game can we make this possible
Siemens 13
Siemens 13 Herman Siemens teaches modern philosophy at Leiden University in the Netherlands and is president of the Friedrich Nietzsche Society of Great Britain. He is a chief editor and contributor to the ongoing ‘Nietzsche Dictionary’ project, based at Radboud University of Nijmegen and Leiden. 2013. Nietzsche and Political Thought, pp. 85-92 Gender modified
political agonisms exhibit two formal features that bear directly on Nietzsche’s concept of the agon The first is the open-ended, counter-final character no results are permanent, all settlements remain open to contestation the agon can only work and thrive where a plurality of antagonistic ‘forces are engaged in an inconclusive, open-ended contestation of victory The other formal element concerns the scope of contestation. Contestation does not just take place within a specific political-legal-institutional order, but also over the very terms of that order; political agonism does not just follow a set of rules and procedures but is also contestation over those very rules, procedures and criteria. This formal characteristic coheres with the agon as game, The measure or standard of victory is not given or fixed independently of each contest; it is the actual issue of contestation, so that the agonal antagonist does not just want to win; his [their] ambition is to determine what counts as winning, so that you have a contest of judgements of victory or a contestation of justice of the very standard or measure of victory. Nietzsche was suspicious of modern mass democracies for promoting mediocrity democracy actually ruined the agon The entire praxis of democracy becomes with time an inauthentic agon in which despicable speech, sycophancy etc. come to the foreground In advancing a concept of democratic politics as struggle any agonistic theory of democracy must in one way or other confront the problem of limits or measure: How to contain political struggle so that it remains this side of mutual annihilation? the almost all agonists appeal to some form of respect ‘agonistic respect’ for the other as a legitimate opponent they appeal to self-restraint on the part of the agonist guided by a certain attitude, disposition or ethos. Hatab’s is a ‘soft,’ altogether sanitized interpretation of the Will to Power that dissolves the dynamic of creation-destruction there is a tension between the agon and the Will to Power, one that can be traced to the moment of limits in the agon: in precluding injury divides the agon against life as Will to Power the reciprocity and interdependence of enmity Hatab and Connolly have two things in common Both approach the question of limits from the position of the subject and the kind of ethos or attitude that must be adopted for political antagonism to remain this side of mutual destruction. Both start from the subject’s insight into the reciprocity and interdependence implied by relations of antagonism or enmity, and derive from it an acknowledgement or respect for the antagonist or enemy; that is, the attitude or ethos that limits or contains the subject’s antagonism. Both of these points are, I believe, deeply problematic and can be criticized from a Nietzschean perspective there is no talk of ‘respect,’ let alone respect for one’s enemy, much less ‘empathy.’ to value enmity is by no means the same as respecting ones enemy one values the enemy for the resistance or opposition it offers one, not for the specificity of its content. The late Nietzsche develops a relational ontology of tension, attraction-repulsion, action-resistance among forces there is something amiss with the attempt to think agonistic interaction and the question of limits from the subject-position each particular capacity, force or genius can only become what it is through antagonistic striving against others. This social ontology makes antagonistic relations essential to the forging of identities in agonal action. However, these relations also act as a medium of resistance that cuts subjective intentions off from resulting action or interaction, so that the identity -the ‘who’ -disclosed in agonal action is not the result of a wilful purpose, but the product of relations of tension that are dynamic and unpredictable in nature At stake is a resolutely relational social ontology that is conditional upon an equilibrium of sorts the agonal play of forces By ‘equality of power,’ Nietzsche does not mean a judgement made from an external standpoint the concept of ‘equilibrium’ cannot be understood from the subject-position, the standpoint of the single antagonists or powers as their conscious goal. For the antagonists do not aim at equilibrium; rather, each strives for supremacy to be the best. Equilibrium is an ‘intersubjective’ or relational phenomenon, a function of the relations between forces striving for supremacy each wants to be the best, yet an equilibrium is, or can be, achieved; each is tempted to excess and hubris, yet limits or measure can be achieved. the limit on action is determined not by the players’ goals, interests or disposition; rather it is the contingent result of dynamic relations that emerge between social forces competing for supremacy the social ontology of tension and the relational concept of equilibrium point to the impossibility of realizing agonal interaction from the subject-position, by adopting a specific attitude or ethos By inserting a disjunction between the subjects’ dispositions and the measured character of their agonal interaction, it frees up the phenomenology of agonal agency from the overriding need to locate sources of measure or self-restraint in an ethos of respect. ‘respect’ cannot really be felt and cannot be relied on to really motivate or limit agonal action. What can be felt are ambition, hatred: the passions that are the real springs of the agon. agonal interaction is motivated by hatred, rather than respect, and that Nietzsche’s concept of agonal hatred combines antagonism with an affirmation of the other that far exceeds ‘agonistic respect.’
the agon can only thrive where a plurality of antagonistic ‘forces are engaged in an open-ended contestation Contestation does not just take place within a political-legal-institutional order, but also over the very terms of that order agonism does not just follow rules but is contestation over those very rules The measure of victory is not given it is the actual issue of contestation the agonal antagonist want to determine what counts as winning modern mass democracies promot mediocrity democracy ruined the agon the appeal to agonistic respect’ is a ‘soft,’ sanitized Will to Power that dissolves the dynamic of creation-destruction that can be traced to the moment of limits in the agon: precluding injury divides the agon against life as Will to Power there is no talk of ‘respect,’ for one’s enemy to value enmity is by no means the same as respecting ones enemy one values the enemy for resistance not for its content By ‘equality of power,’ Nietzsche does not mean a judgement made from an external standpoint the antagonists do not aim at equilibrium; rather, each strives for supremacy Equilibrium is intersubjective’ the limit is determined not by the players’ goals rather it is the contingent result of dynamic relations that emerge between social forces competing for supremacy the relational concept of equilibrium point to the impossibility of realizing agonal interaction from the subject-position, by adopting a specific attitude respect’ cannot really be felt and cannot be relied on to limit agonal action. What can be felt are ambition, hatred: the real springs of the agon. agonal interaction is motivated by hatred an affirmation of the other that far exceeds ‘agonistic respect.
These political agonisms exhibit two formal features that bear directly on Nietzsche’s concept of the agon in Homers Contest (Homers Wettkampf, HC): 1. The first is the open-ended, counter-final character of agonism: no results are permanent, all settlements remain open to contestation, so that contestation is incessant, continuous. In HC, this is implied by the exclusion of the ‘hervorragende Individuum’ from Nietzsche’s account of agon; that is, the conclusive victor who cannot be challenged. This implies that the agon can only work and thrive where a plurality of antagonistic ‘forces (Krafte) or “geniuses”’ are engaged in an inconclusive, open-ended contestation of victory (HC, KSA 1, 789). The agon admits mastery between the contests temporary, intermittent victors like the Olympic champion or the winner of the contest of tragedies this year. The emergence of an absolute victor kills the agon. 2. The other formal element concerns the scope of contestation. Contestation does not just take place within a specific political-legal-institutional order, but also over the very terms of that order; political agonism does not just follow a set of rules and procedures but is also contestation over those very rules, procedures and criteria. This formal characteristic coheres with the anomalous character of agon as game, as described by Nietzsche in HC and MA 170.12 The measure or standard of victory is not given or fixed independently of each contest; it is the actual issue of contestation, so that the agonal antagonist does not just want to win; his [their] ambition is to determine what counts as winning, so that you have a contest of judgements of victory or a contestation of justice of the very standard or measure of victory. Despite these formal convergences, Nietzsche’s account of the agon in Homers Contest does not translate well into democratic practices. This is (1) because the text presents not a recipe for action or recommendation, but a highly stylized, not to say idealized model of the agon focused on martial, artistic, athletic and pedagogic practices, rather than politics. In other, more realist contexts Nietzsche can be highly critical of the Greek agon for its practical consequences, such as stifling lesser talents, and inhibiting the emergence of the individual.13 This suggests that, in taking inspiration from Nietzsche’s idealized model of the agon in Homer’s Contest, agonistic theorists offer highly idealized accounts of democratic practices which ignore the practical difficulties of real agonistic interaction. Furthermore (2), the relation between the agon and democracy is tenuous at best for Nietzsche. Like his colleague at Basel, Jacob Burckhardt, he was suspicious of modern mass democracies for promoting mediocrity. Both opposed the agon practised by Greek aristocrats not just to modern culture but also to later Greek democracy.14 By disrupting one-to-one relations and introducing the ‘masses’ into the equation, democracy actually ruined the agon for Burckhardt, who writes of fifth century Greece: ‘The entire praxis of democracy becomes with time an inauthentic agon in which despicable speech, sycophancy etc. come to the foreground.’15 To relate the agon to democratic practices in affirmative ways, as do political agonists like Hatab, Owen and Connolly, is therefore is to oppose, rather than succeed to Nietzsche. So how exactly do they situate the agon in democracy? In Hatab’s case it begins with the claim that there are deep compatibilities between Nietzsche’s thought and democracy, or at least: democracy under a certain description. They concern not just (1) the notion of agon, but also (2) perspectivism and the open category of interpretation (in place of foundationalist claims to absolute, objective knowledge, and (3) the Nietzschean suspicion of the underlying power-claims at stake in moral and cognitive claims.16 In his 1995 book A Nietzschean Defense of Democracy, he argues that Nietzsche opens the possibility of redescribing democracy in nonmetaphysical terms that incorporate critical insights of postmodernism and enable us to dispense with a positive concept of equality, with its irreducibly metaphysical/ theological foundations. That is to say, Hatab takes one aspect of Nietzsche’s critique of democracy on board: the critique of equality, but argues that we can theorize democracy without a substantive concept of equality. In place of equality, he proposes an ethos of agonistic respect for opponents, grounded in Will to Power (I shall return to this below). Connolly and Owen advance a perfectionist version of agonistic democratic theory. Their question is how to ‘ennoble’ democracy, and both argue against Nietzsche that the kinds of nobility of character and culture he advanced are better anchored and expressed in democratic practices than he imagined. Nietzschean nobility, glossed by Connolly in terms of self-experimentation, grace and plurality, exhibits traits that he contends are appropriate to our fast-paced world.17 Indeed, in Connolly’s view, Nietzsche offers unique constructive resources for rethinking key democratic ideas in a present that seems to be outpacing slow pace of democratic deliberation, as well as the ideals bequeathed by classical democrats such as Rousseau, Tocqueville, Mill, or even contemporaries like Rawls or Habermas. In all three cases we are clearly dealing with appropriations, rather than interpretations of Nietzsche. Their concern is not to interpret his texts in a way that does justice to their specificity, but to take from them and adapt what is needed for their own ‘post-Nietzschean’ democratic projects.18 But the question of interpretation remains: whether what they take from Nietzsche most notably the affirmative notion of antagonism is adequate as an interpretation of his thought. In Section 1 of this Chapter I examine what divides Nietzsche’s conception of the agon from the notions of antagonism at work in agonistic theory, in order to highlight some of the weaknesses in the latter that emerge out of these differences. Section 2 will then turn to the question of what constructive alternatives, if any, his philosophy of conflict has to offer. Against ‘respect’ In advancing a concept of democratic politics as antagonism, struggle and disagreement, any agonistic theory of democracy must in one way or other confront the problem of limits or measure: How to contain political struggle so that it remains this side of mutual annihilation? In HC this is the question of the relation between the Wett-kampf and the Vernichtungs-kampf, between the ‘good’ and the ‘evil Eris.’ As part of their response, almost all agonists (Hatab, Owen, Connolly, Mouffe) appeal to some form of respect ‘agonistic respect’ for the other as a legitimate opponent. That is to say, they appeal to self-restraint on the part of the agonist guided by a certain attitude, disposition or ethos. In what follows, two examples will be considered. 4 1. The first is Hatab. In dispensing with a substantive notion of equality, Hatab tries to replace it with an ethos of equal regard 19 and agonistic respect. 20 This ethos is supposedly derived from the antagonists’ insight into their agonistic interdependence, which in turn is presented by Hatab as a consequence of Nietzsche’s Will to Power: [T]he will to power expresses an agonistic force-field, wherein any achievement or production of meaning is constituted by an overcoming of some opposing force. Consequently, my Other is always implicated in my nature; the annulment of my Other would be the annulment of myself. [. . .] This is why Nietzsche often speaks of the need to affirm our opponents as opponents, since they figure in our selfdevelopment.21 and upon this Hatab builds his concept of agonistic respect. Agonistic respect is a consequence of my insight into the reciprocity and interdependence of antagonistic forces. Since ‘the annulment of my Other would be the annulment of myself’ (or again: ‘The elimination or degradation of the Other would be self-defeating’),22 I am bound to affirm my opponent as opponent. Hatab’s analysis involves a curious, psychologistic translation of the Will to Power onto the plane of the subjective self-awareness. But I am not a Will to Power, and others are not opposing Wills to Power. We are all derivative, provisional unities resulting from the infinitely complex, pre-conscious, subject-less organizations of Wills to Power. Furthermore, Hatab’s is a ‘soft,’ altogether sanitized interpretation of the Will to Power that dissolves the dynamic of creation-destruction, the activity of expansion through incorporation or functionalization of opposing Will to Power complexes, and the logic of exploitation. In Nietzsche’s thought there is a tension between the agon and the Will to Power, one that can be traced to the moment of measure or limits in the agon: in precluding injury and exploitation it divides the agon against life as Will to Power, insofar as Will to Power includes injury and exploitation.23 This tension is overlooked by Hatab, who effectively reads agonal restraint back into the ‘logic’ of the Will to Power. Finally, one can question whether the Will to Power allows for the kind of recognition or acknowledgement of the Other that supposedly motivates agonistic self-restraint. Hegelian dialectics may allow for acknowledgement of the Other in its particular content, but it is unclear whether the logic of exploitation in power-relations implies any more than the instrumental valuation by one power-complex of the resistance offered by another as means for its own expansion.24 2. In the case of Connolly, one can see even more clearly than in Hatab that agonistic politics is based on an ontology of struggle and power that is quite alien to Nietzsche. Connolly’s point of departure is a theory of identity, supposedly informed by Nietzsche and Foucault. In a world of flux without design, he argues, any life-form or self, in order to subsist as a unity, needs an identity ‘to organise and resist the chaos of raw sensibility.’25 Yet life, understood as an excess of energy propelling possibilities into being, ‘exceeds any purpose or identity to which people already conform; for every way of life, settled practice or fixed identity produces difference in and around itself in the very process of specifying itself.’26 Life, therefore, ‘provides a precondition for identity while resisting [because exceeding HS] the completion of any form of identity’ (ibid.). This account of identity-formation, conceived as a process of ‘constituting’ or ‘producing’ difference, rests on a post-structuralist logic of the ‘constitutive outside.’27 In Nietzsche’s ontology of life, by contrast, difference like activity is a precondition (or presupposition) for (thinking) identity as a life-process. It is only by virtue of differential relations with other forces, in the very process of confronting the resistance they offer, that any derivative identity is possible. Identity, understood as the process whereby a complex or organization of Wills to Power is formed, does not produce difference; rather it seeks out resistance and difference in order to expand by commanding and incorporating that which resists it.28 It is not therefore Nietzsche’s concept of diversity and difference to which Connolly’s agonistic politics of identity and difference is hospitable. Connolly’s post-structuralist theory of identity is designed to address adequately and affirm the specific character of pluralism in late modern democracies; what he calls ‘the paradox of difference that haunts social life in late modern democracies.’29 Identity (personal, group, collective) ‘is defined and specified by the way it constitutes difference: identity needs difference to be, but difference threatens the security and certainty of self-identity.’30 Connolly’s question is, then: How best to respond to this paradox politically? The paradigmatic response, he maintains, is to deny the constitutive role of the other and to seek the self-certainty of identity through closure against the other; that is, by defining the other as evil or (in the case of deliberative theory) irrational, while making claims to absolute truth and value for oneself.31 Connolly’s agonistic alternative to this response turns on the need to acknowledge the contingency and incompleteness of identity, and its constitutive dependence on difference and opposition. What is needed instead, he argues, are identities that can affirm themselves without denying their constructed, relational, paradoxical character; only this will allow for a pluralization of identities appropriate to our contemporary world. The hope is that insight into our agonistic dependence on the other can act as an incentive towards ‘agonistic respect,’ which he characterizes as an ‘empathy for what we are not,’ a ‘care for difference.’32 For Connolly, agonistic respect is a ‘civic virtue,’ one that goes as far as ‘deep respect’ by which he means that ‘those who bestow it acknowledge the dignity of those who embrace different sources of respect’ that they ‘honor different final sources.’33 Yet Connolly insists that none of this excludes contesting other sources of respect, and he enlists Nietzsche’s ‘spiritualisation of enmity’ (Vergeistigung der Feindschaft) in order to explicate this peculiar agonistic empathy. He appeals in specific to Nietzsche’s ‘pathos of distance’ and refers to TI Antinature 3 as a key source: The spiritualisation of sensuality is called love: it is a great triumph over Christianity. Another triumph is our spiritualisation of enmity. It consists in profoundly grasping the value of having enemies [. . .] The church has at all times wanted the destruction of its enemies: we, we immoralists and anti-Christians, see that it is to our advantage that the church exists. . . . In the domain of politics as well enmity has become more spiritual nowadays much cleverer, much more thoughtful, much more considerate [schonender]. Almost every party grasps that its interest in self-preservation lies in the opposition party not losing its powers [. . .] (TI Antinature 3, KSA 6, 84) According to Connolly, this passage illustrates how our insight into the reciprocity and interdependence of enmity leads to an agonistic respect for our enemies. Despite significant differences in their approaches, Hatab and Connolly have two things in common. 1. Both approach the question of limits from the position of the subject and the kind of ethos or attitude that must be adopted for political antagonism to remain this side of mutual destruction. 2. Both theorists start from the subject’s insight into the reciprocity and interdependence implied by relations of antagonism or enmity, and derive from it an acknowledgement or respect for the antagonist or enemy; that is, the attitude or ethos that limits or contains the subject’s antagonism. Both of these points are, I believe, deeply problematic and can be criticized from a Nietzschean perspective. To begin with the second point: In Nietzsche’s passage on the spiritualization of enmity, used by Connolly to support his notion of agonistic respect, there is no talk of ‘respect,’ let alone respect for one’s enemy, much less ‘empathy.’ Nietzsche writes of a deep understanding, i.e. acknowledgement of the ‘the value of having enemies’; but to value enmity is by no means the same as respecting ones enemy a la Connolly. In Nietzsche’s formulation, what is valued (not respected) are relations of enmity (not the enemy), and to value relations of enmity implies only that one values the enemy for the resistance or opposition it offers one, not for the specificity of its content. The same difficulty afflicts Hatab’s account, as we have seen, since it is the opposition of the other, the resistance it offers, that is constitutive of my Will to Power or perspective, and not its specific content. Both accounts raise the same question: Does the interdependence of antagonistic relations imply any more than the instrumental value of the antagonistic other?34 This concern is completely missed if ‘the value of enmity’ is allowed to slide into ‘respect for the enemy.’ Nietzsche’s emphasis on relations of enmity is by no means confined to this text. The late Nietzsche writes of ‘the relational character of all occurrence’ (Relations-charakter alles Geschehens: KSA 11, 26[36], 157) and develops a relational ontology of tension, attraction-repulsion, action-resistance among forces without substance to describe it. This suggests that there is something amiss with the first point shared by Hatab and Connolly: their attempt to think agonistic interaction and the question of limits from the subject-position. This suspicion is confirmed when we consider that for the young Nietzsche who authored Homers Contest, it was clear that the agon became important and effective as an institution in a context where the Greeks could not rely on self-restraint. What drew Nietzsche to the Greek agon was the way it conjugated a heroic pathos, the temptation to hubris and excess (Obermass) on the part of the subjects, with measured, creative conflict in the relations between them: Wonderful process, how the generalized struggle [Kampf] of all Greeks gradually comes to acknowledge one Sikh in all domains: where does this come from? The contest unleashes the individual: and at the same time, it restrains [or tames: bandigt] the individual according to eternal laws. (KSA 7, 16[22], 402) If we ask with Nietzsche how this was possible, one clue lies in the social ontology of tension presupposed by the agon. In Homers Contest he describes the principle of Greek pedagogy as the view that: ‘Every gift [talent, capacity: Begabung] must unfold [or flourish: sich entfalten] through contestation, this is what Hellenic popular pedagogy dictates’ (HC, KSA 1, 789). This implies that each particular capacity, force or genius can only become what it is (‘sich entfalten’) through antagonistic striving [Gegenstreben] against others. This social ontology makes antagonistic relations essential to the forging of identities in agonal action. However, these relations also act as a medium of resistance that cuts subjective intentions off from resulting action or interaction, so that the identity -the ‘who’ -disclosed in agonal action is not the result of a wilful purpose, but the product of relations of tension that are dynamic and unpredictable in nature.35 At stake is a resolutely relational social ontology that is conditional upon an equilibrium of sorts among a plurality of forces or geniuses: the agonal play of forces (Wettspiel der Krafte), Nietzsche writes, presupposes that in a natural order of things, there are always several geniuses who stimulate each other reciprocally to deeds, as they also hold each other reciprocally within the limits of measure (HC, KSA 1, 789)36 These relations of mutual stimulation and mutual restraint are best understood with reference to the concept of equilibrium (ungefahres Gleichgewicht) among more-or-less equal powers, proposed in Human, All Too Human as the origin of justice and anticipated in the Nachlass note cited above (KSA 7, 16[22], 402) on the agonal origins of 8(Kh in Greece.37 By ‘equality of power,’ Nietzsche does not mean a quantitative measure of objective magnitudes, nor a judgement made from an external standpoint, but the expression of an estimated correspondence between powers, where each power judges itself (as equal) in relation to another power.38 Unlike the measure of equality, however, the concept of ‘equilibrium’ cannot be understood from the subject-position, the standpoint of the single antagonists or powers as their conscious goal. For the antagonists do not aim at equilibrium; rather, each strives for supremacy (Obermacht) – to be the best. Equilibrium is, then, an ‘intersubjective’ or relational phenomenon, a function of the relations between more-or-less equal forces, each striving for supremacy. So once again, the relational concept of equilibrium inserts a radical disjunction between the subject-position of the antagonists their desires, intentions and claims – and the qualities of their resulting agonal interaction: each wants to be the best, yet an equilibrium is, or can be, achieved; each is tempted to excess and hubris, yet limits or measure can be achieved. The relational sense of the agon means that the measure or limit on action is determined not by the players’ goals, interests or disposition; rather it is the contingent result of dynamic relations that emerge between social forces competing for supremacy. Both the social ontology of tension and the relational concept of equilibrium point to the impossibility of realizing agonal interaction from the subject-position, by adopting a specific attitude or ethos. 3 Rethinking agonistic theory: Nietzsche’s constructive alternatives Nietzsche’s relational concept of agonal interaction also has significant consequences for the phenomenology of agonal agency. By inserting a disjunction between the subjects’ dispositions (intentions, desires, claims, etc.) and the measured character of their agonal interaction, it frees up the phenomenology of agonal agency from the overriding need to locate sources of measure or self-restraint in an ethos of respect. One of the problems with ‘respect’ is that it cannot really be felt and, as such cannot be relied on to really motivate or limit agonal action. What can be felt, as Nietzsche points out repeatedly, are envy, jealousy, ambition, hatred: the passions that are the real springs of the agon. Nietzsche’s relational concept of agonal interaction opens the space for a much richer, realist account of the subject’s dispositions, a phenomenology of enmity that brings the antagonism back into agonism and corrects the emphasis on empathy and reciprocal constitution in agonistic respect. In the following section I argue that agonal interaction is motivated by hatred, rather than respect, and that Nietzsche’s concept of agonal hatred combines antagonism with an affirmation of the other that far exceeds ‘agonistic respect.’ This forms part of my broader claim that Nietzsche’s phenomenology of enmity houses invaluable constructive resources for agonistic democratic theory.
22,377
<h4>Their notion of agonistic respect is a life-denying destruction of the agon. Fairness doesn’t come from the judge but from unfeterred contestation of will – only by challenging the rules of the game can we make this possible</h4><p><strong>Siemens 13</strong> </p><p>Herman Siemens teaches modern philosophy at Leiden University in the Netherlands and is president of the Friedrich Nietzsche Society of Great Britain. He is a chief editor and contributor to the ongoing ‘Nietzsche Dictionary’ project, based at Radboud University of Nijmegen and Leiden. 2013. Nietzsche and Political Thought, pp. 85-92 Gender modified</p><p>These <u><strong>political agonisms exhibit two formal features that bear directly on Nietzsche’s concept of the agon</u></strong> in Homers Contest (Homers Wettkampf, HC): 1. <u><strong>The first is the open-ended, counter-final character</u></strong> of agonism: <u><strong>no results are permanent, all settlements remain open to contestation</u></strong>, so that contestation is incessant, continuous. In HC, this is implied by the exclusion of the ‘hervorragende Individuum’ from Nietzsche’s account of agon; that is, the conclusive victor who cannot be challenged. This implies that <u><strong><mark>the agon can only</mark> work and <mark>thrive where a plurality of antagonistic ‘forces</u></strong></mark> (Krafte) or “geniuses”’ <u><strong><mark>are engaged in an </mark>inconclusive, <mark>open-ended contestation</mark> of victory </u></strong>(HC, KSA 1, 789). The agon admits mastery between the contests temporary, intermittent victors like the Olympic champion or the winner of the contest of tragedies this year. The emergence of an absolute victor kills the agon. 2. <u><strong>The other formal element concerns the scope of contestation. <mark>Contestation does not just take place within a </mark>specific <mark>political-legal-institutional order, but also over the very terms of that order</mark>; political <mark>agonism does not just follow</mark> a set of <mark>rules</mark> and procedures <mark>but is</mark> also <mark>contestation over those very rules</mark>, procedures and criteria. This formal characteristic coheres with the</u></strong> anomalous character of <u><strong>agon as game,</u></strong> as described by Nietzsche in HC and MA 170.12 <u><strong><mark>The measure</mark> or standard <mark>of victory is not given</mark> or fixed independently of each contest; <mark>it is the actual issue of contestation</mark>, so that <mark>the agonal antagonist</mark> does not just <mark>want to</mark> win; his [their] ambition is to <mark>determine what counts as winning</mark>, so that you have a contest of judgements of victory or a contestation of justice of the very standard or measure of victory. </u></strong>Despite these formal convergences, Nietzsche’s account of the agon in Homers Contest does not translate well into democratic practices. This is (1) because the text presents not a recipe for action or recommendation, but a highly stylized, not to say idealized model of the agon focused on martial, artistic, athletic and pedagogic practices, rather than politics. In other, more realist contexts Nietzsche can be highly critical of the Greek agon for its practical consequences, such as stifling lesser talents, and inhibiting the emergence of the individual.13 This suggests that, in taking inspiration from Nietzsche’s idealized model of the agon in Homer’s Contest, agonistic theorists offer highly idealized accounts of democratic practices which ignore the practical difficulties of real agonistic interaction. Furthermore (2), the relation between the agon and democracy is tenuous at best for <u><strong>Nietzsche</u></strong>. Like his colleague at Basel, Jacob Burckhardt, he <u><strong>was suspicious of <mark>modern mass democracies</mark> for <mark>promot</mark>ing <mark>mediocrity</u></strong></mark>. Both opposed the agon practised by Greek aristocrats not just to modern culture but also to later Greek democracy.14 By disrupting one-to-one relations and introducing the ‘masses’ into the equation, <u><strong><mark>democracy </mark>actually <mark>ruined the agon</u></strong></mark> for Burckhardt, who writes of fifth century Greece: ‘<u><strong>The entire praxis of democracy becomes with time an inauthentic agon in which despicable speech, sycophancy etc. come to the foreground</u></strong>.’15 To relate the agon to democratic practices in affirmative ways, as do political agonists like Hatab, Owen and Connolly, is therefore is to oppose, rather than succeed to Nietzsche. So how exactly do they situate the agon in democracy? In Hatab’s case it begins with the claim that there are deep compatibilities between Nietzsche’s thought and democracy, or at least: democracy under a certain description. They concern not just (1) the notion of agon, but also (2) perspectivism and the open category of interpretation (in place of foundationalist claims to absolute, objective knowledge, and (3) the Nietzschean suspicion of the underlying power-claims at stake in moral and cognitive claims.16 In his 1995 book A Nietzschean Defense of Democracy, he argues that Nietzsche opens the possibility of redescribing democracy in nonmetaphysical terms that incorporate critical insights of postmodernism and enable us to dispense with a positive concept of equality, with its irreducibly metaphysical/ theological foundations. That is to say, Hatab takes one aspect of Nietzsche’s critique of democracy on board: the critique of equality, but argues that we can theorize democracy without a substantive concept of equality. In place of equality, he proposes an ethos of agonistic respect for opponents, grounded in Will to Power (I shall return to this below). Connolly and Owen advance a perfectionist version of agonistic democratic theory. Their question is how to ‘ennoble’ democracy, and both argue against Nietzsche that the kinds of nobility of character and culture he advanced are better anchored and expressed in democratic practices than he imagined. Nietzschean nobility, glossed by Connolly in terms of self-experimentation, grace and plurality, exhibits traits that he contends are appropriate to our fast-paced world.17 Indeed, in Connolly’s view, Nietzsche offers unique constructive resources for rethinking key democratic ideas in a present that seems to be outpacing slow pace of democratic deliberation, as well as the ideals bequeathed by classical democrats such as Rousseau, Tocqueville, Mill, or even contemporaries like Rawls or Habermas. In all three cases we are clearly dealing with appropriations, rather than interpretations of Nietzsche. Their concern is not to interpret his texts in a way that does justice to their specificity, but to take from them and adapt what is needed for their own ‘post-Nietzschean’ democratic projects.18 But the question of interpretation remains: whether what they take from Nietzsche most notably the affirmative notion of antagonism is adequate as an interpretation of his thought. In Section 1 of this Chapter I examine what divides Nietzsche’s conception of the agon from the notions of antagonism at work in agonistic theory, in order to highlight some of the weaknesses in the latter that emerge out of these differences. Section 2 will then turn to the question of what constructive alternatives, if any, his philosophy of conflict has to offer. Against ‘respect’ <u><strong>In advancing a concept of democratic politics as</u></strong> antagonism, <u><strong>struggle</u></strong> and disagreement, <u><strong>any agonistic theory of democracy must in one way or other confront the problem of limits or measure: How to contain political struggle so that it remains this side of mutual annihilation?</u></strong> In HC this is the question of the relation between the Wett-kampf and the Vernichtungs-kampf, between <u><strong><mark>the</u></strong></mark> ‘good’ and the ‘evil Eris.’ As part of their response, <u><strong>almost all agonists</u></strong> (Hatab, Owen, Connolly, Mouffe) <u><strong><mark>appeal to</mark> some form of respect ‘<mark>agonistic respect’</mark> for the other as a legitimate opponent</u></strong>. That is to say, <u><strong>they appeal to self-restraint on the part of the agonist guided by a certain attitude, disposition or ethos.</u></strong> In what follows, two examples will be considered. 4 1. The first is Hatab. In dispensing with a substantive notion of equality, Hatab tries to replace it with an ethos of equal regard 19 and agonistic respect. 20 This ethos is supposedly derived from the antagonists’ insight into their agonistic interdependence, which in turn is presented by Hatab as a consequence of Nietzsche’s Will to Power: [T]he will to power expresses an agonistic force-field, wherein any achievement or production of meaning is constituted by an overcoming of some opposing force. Consequently, my Other is always implicated in my nature; the annulment of my Other would be the annulment of myself. [. . .] This is why Nietzsche often speaks of the need to affirm our opponents as opponents, since they figure in our selfdevelopment.21 and upon this Hatab builds his concept of agonistic respect. Agonistic respect is a consequence of my insight into the reciprocity and interdependence of antagonistic forces. Since ‘the annulment of my Other would be the annulment of myself’ (or again: ‘The elimination or degradation of the Other would be self-defeating’),22 I am bound to affirm my opponent as opponent. Hatab’s analysis involves a curious, psychologistic translation of the Will to Power onto the plane of the subjective self-awareness. But I am not a Will to Power, and others are not opposing Wills to Power. We are all derivative, provisional unities resulting from the infinitely complex, pre-conscious, subject-less organizations of Wills to Power. Furthermore, <u><strong>Hatab’s <mark>is a ‘soft,’</mark> altogether <mark>sanitized </mark>interpretation of the <mark>Will to Power that dissolves the dynamic of creation-destruction</u></strong></mark>, the activity of expansion through incorporation or functionalization of opposing Will to Power complexes, and the logic of exploitation. In Nietzsche’s thought <u><strong>there is a tension between the agon and the Will to Power, one <mark>that can be traced to the moment of</u></strong></mark> measure or <u><strong><mark>limits in the agon:</mark> in <mark>precluding injury</u></strong></mark> and exploitation it <u><strong><mark>divides the agon against life as Will to Power</u></strong></mark>, insofar as Will to Power includes injury and exploitation.23 This tension is overlooked by Hatab, who effectively reads agonal restraint back into the ‘logic’ of the Will to Power. Finally, one can question whether the Will to Power allows for the kind of recognition or acknowledgement of the Other that supposedly motivates agonistic self-restraint. Hegelian dialectics may allow for acknowledgement of the Other in its particular content, but it is unclear whether the logic of exploitation in power-relations implies any more than the instrumental valuation by one power-complex of the resistance offered by another as means for its own expansion.24 2. In the case of Connolly, one can see even more clearly than in Hatab that agonistic politics is based on an ontology of struggle and power that is quite alien to Nietzsche. Connolly’s point of departure is a theory of identity, supposedly informed by Nietzsche and Foucault. In a world of flux without design, he argues, any life-form or self, in order to subsist as a unity, needs an identity ‘to organise and resist the chaos of raw sensibility.’25 Yet life, understood as an excess of energy propelling possibilities into being, ‘exceeds any purpose or identity to which people already conform; for every way of life, settled practice or fixed identity produces difference in and around itself in the very process of specifying itself.’26 Life, therefore, ‘provides a precondition for identity while resisting [because exceeding HS] the completion of any form of identity’ (ibid.). This account of identity-formation, conceived as a process of ‘constituting’ or ‘producing’ difference, rests on a post-structuralist logic of the ‘constitutive outside.’27 In Nietzsche’s ontology of life, by contrast, difference like activity is a precondition (or presupposition) for (thinking) identity as a life-process. It is only by virtue of differential relations with other forces, in the very process of confronting the resistance they offer, that any derivative identity is possible. Identity, understood as the process whereby a complex or organization of Wills to Power is formed, does not produce difference; rather it seeks out resistance and difference in order to expand by commanding and incorporating that which resists it.28 It is not therefore Nietzsche’s concept of diversity and difference to which Connolly’s agonistic politics of identity and difference is hospitable. Connolly’s post-structuralist theory of identity is designed to address adequately and affirm the specific character of pluralism in late modern democracies; what he calls ‘the paradox of difference that haunts social life in late modern democracies.’29 Identity (personal, group, collective) ‘is defined and specified by the way it constitutes difference: identity needs difference to be, but difference threatens the security and certainty of self-identity.’30 Connolly’s question is, then: How best to respond to this paradox politically? The paradigmatic response, he maintains, is to deny the constitutive role of the other and to seek the self-certainty of identity through closure against the other; that is, by defining the other as evil or (in the case of deliberative theory) irrational, while making claims to absolute truth and value for oneself.31 Connolly’s agonistic alternative to this response turns on the need to acknowledge the contingency and incompleteness of identity, and its constitutive dependence on difference and opposition. What is needed instead, he argues, are identities that can affirm themselves without denying their constructed, relational, paradoxical character; only this will allow for a pluralization of identities appropriate to our contemporary world. The hope is that insight into our agonistic dependence on the other can act as an incentive towards ‘agonistic respect,’ which he characterizes as an ‘empathy for what we are not,’ a ‘care for difference.’32 For Connolly, agonistic respect is a ‘civic virtue,’ one that goes as far as ‘deep respect’ by which he means that ‘those who bestow it acknowledge the dignity of those who embrace different sources of respect’ that they ‘honor different final sources.’33 Yet Connolly insists that none of this excludes contesting other sources of respect, and he enlists Nietzsche’s ‘spiritualisation of enmity’ (Vergeistigung der Feindschaft) in order to explicate this peculiar agonistic empathy. He appeals in specific to Nietzsche’s ‘pathos of distance’ and refers to TI Antinature 3 as a key source: The spiritualisation of sensuality is called love: it is a great triumph over Christianity. Another triumph is our spiritualisation of enmity. It consists in profoundly grasping the value of having enemies [. . .] The church has at all times wanted the destruction of its enemies: we, we immoralists and anti-Christians, see that it is to our advantage that the church exists. . . . In the domain of politics as well enmity has become more spiritual nowadays much cleverer, much more thoughtful, much more considerate [schonender]. Almost every party grasps that its interest in self-preservation lies in the opposition party not losing its powers [. . .] (TI Antinature 3, KSA 6, 84) According to Connolly, this passage illustrates how our insight into <u><strong>the reciprocity and interdependence of enmity</u></strong> leads to an agonistic respect for our enemies. Despite significant differences in their approaches, <u><strong>Hatab and Connolly have two things in common</u></strong>. 1. <u><strong>Both approach the question of limits from the position of the subject and the kind of ethos or attitude that must be adopted for political antagonism to remain this side of mutual destruction.</u></strong> 2. <u><strong>Both</u></strong> theorists <u><strong>start from the subject’s insight into the reciprocity and interdependence implied by relations of antagonism or enmity, and derive from it an acknowledgement or respect for the antagonist or enemy; that is, the attitude or ethos that limits or contains the subject’s antagonism. Both of these points are, I believe, deeply problematic and can be criticized from a Nietzschean perspective</u></strong>. To begin with the second point: In Nietzsche’s passage on the spiritualization of enmity, used by Connolly to support his notion of agonistic respect, <u><strong><mark>there is no talk of ‘respect,’</mark> let alone respect <mark>for one’s enemy</mark>, much less ‘empathy.’</u></strong> Nietzsche writes of a deep understanding, i.e. acknowledgement of the ‘the value of having enemies’; but <u><strong><mark>to value enmity is by no means the same as respecting ones enemy</u></strong></mark> a la Connolly. In Nietzsche’s formulation, what is valued (not respected) are relations of enmity (not the enemy), and to value relations of enmity implies only that <u><strong><mark>one values the enemy for</mark> the <mark>resistance</mark> or opposition it offers one, <mark>not for</mark> the specificity of <mark>its content</mark>.</u></strong> The same difficulty afflicts Hatab’s account, as we have seen, since it is the opposition of the other, the resistance it offers, that is constitutive of my Will to Power or perspective, and not its specific content. Both accounts raise the same question: Does the interdependence of antagonistic relations imply any more than the instrumental value of the antagonistic other?34 This concern is completely missed if ‘the value of enmity’ is allowed to slide into ‘respect for the enemy.’ Nietzsche’s emphasis on relations of enmity is by no means confined to this text. <u><strong>The late Nietzsche</u></strong> writes of ‘the relational character of all occurrence’ (Relations-charakter alles Geschehens: KSA 11, 26[36], 157) and <u><strong>develops a relational ontology of tension, attraction-repulsion, action-resistance among forces</u></strong> without substance to describe it. This suggests that <u><strong>there is something amiss with the</u></strong> first point shared by Hatab and Connolly: their <u><strong>attempt to think agonistic interaction and the question of limits from the subject-position</u></strong>. This suspicion is confirmed when we consider that for the young Nietzsche who authored Homers Contest, it was clear that the agon became important and effective as an institution in a context where the Greeks could not rely on self-restraint. What drew Nietzsche to the Greek agon was the way it conjugated a heroic pathos, the temptation to hubris and excess (Obermass) on the part of the subjects, with measured, creative conflict in the relations between them: Wonderful process, how the generalized struggle [Kampf] of all Greeks gradually comes to acknowledge one Sikh in all domains: where does this come from? The contest unleashes the individual: and at the same time, it restrains [or tames: bandigt] the individual according to eternal laws. (KSA 7, 16[22], 402) If we ask with Nietzsche how this was possible, one clue lies in the social ontology of tension presupposed by the agon. In Homers Contest he describes the principle of Greek pedagogy as the view that: ‘Every gift [talent, capacity: Begabung] must unfold [or flourish: sich entfalten] through contestation, this is what Hellenic popular pedagogy dictates’ (HC, KSA 1, 789). This implies that <u><strong>each particular capacity, force or genius can only become what it is</u></strong> (‘sich entfalten’) <u><strong>through antagonistic striving</u></strong> [Gegenstreben] <u><strong>against others. This social ontology makes antagonistic relations essential to the forging of identities in agonal action. However, these relations also act as a medium of resistance that cuts subjective intentions off from resulting action or interaction, so that the identity -the ‘who’ -disclosed in agonal action is not the result of a wilful purpose, but the product of relations of tension that are dynamic and unpredictable in nature</u></strong>.35 <u><strong>At stake is a resolutely relational social ontology that is conditional upon an equilibrium of sorts</u></strong> among a plurality of forces or geniuses: <u><strong>the agonal play of forces</u></strong> (Wettspiel der Krafte), Nietzsche writes, presupposes that in a natural order of things, there are always several geniuses who stimulate each other reciprocally to deeds, as they also hold each other reciprocally within the limits of measure (HC, KSA 1, 789)36 These relations of mutual stimulation and mutual restraint are best understood with reference to the concept of equilibrium (ungefahres Gleichgewicht) among more-or-less equal powers, proposed in Human, All Too Human as the origin of justice and anticipated in the Nachlass note cited above (KSA 7, 16[22], 402) on the agonal origins of 8(Kh in Greece.37 <u><strong><mark>By ‘equality of power,’ Nietzsche does not mean</u></strong></mark> a quantitative measure of objective magnitudes, nor <u><strong><mark>a judgement made from an external standpoint</u></strong></mark>, but the expression of an estimated correspondence between powers, where each power judges itself (as equal) in relation to another power.38 Unlike the measure of equality, however, <u><strong>the concept of ‘equilibrium’ cannot be understood from the subject-position, the standpoint of the single antagonists or powers as their conscious goal. For <mark>the antagonists do not aim at equilibrium; rather, each strives for supremacy</u></strong></mark> (Obermacht) – <u><strong>to be the best. <mark>Equilibrium is</u></strong></mark>, then, <u><strong>an ‘<mark>intersubjective’</mark> or relational phenomenon, a function of the relations between</u></strong> more-or-less equal <u><strong>forces</u></strong>, each <u><strong>striving for supremacy</u></strong>. So once again, the relational concept of equilibrium inserts a radical disjunction between the subject-position of the antagonists their desires, intentions and claims – and the qualities of their resulting agonal interaction: <u><strong>each wants to be the best, yet an equilibrium is, or can be, achieved; each is tempted to excess and hubris, yet limits or measure can be achieved.</u></strong> The relational sense of the agon means that <u><strong><mark>the</u></strong></mark> measure or <u><strong><mark>limit </mark>on action <mark>is determined not by the players’ goals</mark>, interests or disposition; <mark>rather it is the contingent result of dynamic relations that emerge between social forces competing for supremacy</u></strong></mark>. Both <u><strong>the social ontology of tension and <mark>the relational concept of equilibrium point to the impossibility of realizing agonal interaction from the subject-position, by adopting a specific attitude</mark> or ethos</u></strong>. 3 Rethinking agonistic theory: Nietzsche’s constructive alternatives Nietzsche’s relational concept of agonal interaction also has significant consequences for the phenomenology of agonal agency. <u><strong>By inserting a disjunction between the subjects’ dispositions</u></strong> (intentions, desires, claims, etc.) <u><strong>and the measured character of their agonal interaction, it frees up the phenomenology of agonal agency from the overriding need to locate sources of measure or self-restraint in an ethos of respect. </u></strong>One of the problems with <u><strong>‘<mark>respect’</u></strong></mark> is that it <u><strong><mark>cannot really be felt and</u></strong></mark>, as such <u><strong><mark>cannot be relied on to</mark> really motivate or <mark>limit agonal action. What can be felt</u></strong></mark>, as Nietzsche points out repeatedly, <u><strong><mark>are</u></strong></mark> envy, jealousy, <u><strong><mark>ambition, hatred:</mark> the passions that are <mark>the real springs of the agon.</u></strong></mark> Nietzsche’s relational concept of agonal interaction opens the space for a much richer, realist account of the subject’s dispositions, a phenomenology of enmity that brings the antagonism back into agonism and corrects the emphasis on empathy and reciprocal constitution in agonistic respect. In the following section I argue that <u><strong><mark>agonal interaction is motivated by hatred</mark>, rather than respect, and that Nietzsche’s concept of agonal hatred combines antagonism with <mark>an affirmation of the other that far exceeds ‘agonistic respect.</mark>’</u></strong> This forms part of my broader claim that Nietzsche’s phenomenology of enmity houses invaluable constructive resources for agonistic democratic theory.</p>
2AC
FW
AT: Agonism
222,086
4
16,993
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
564,698
A
NDT
3
UTD LO
Heidt, Shook, Lundberg
1AC PAS genealogy- same assimilar to USC PAS 1AC 1NC T- Framework K- Szaz Medicalization of death 2NR T
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,940
Their methodology is flawed and Eurocentric---war per capita is a terrible metric—the past two centuries have been exceptionally violent and the trend is only increasing---your role should be to look at the enabling conditions for violence and not rest your faith in our luck so far
Braumoeller 13
Bear F. Braumoeller 13, The Ohio State University Department of Political Science, August 27, “Is War Disappearing?” http://www.braumoeller.info/wp-content/uploads/2013/08/Is-War-Disappearing.pdf
A spate of recent research1 strongly suggests that war and violence are on the decline and have been for decades or centuries Pinker argues that, as a result of pacification, civilization, and the “humanitarian revolution there has been a decline in the propensity of humans to use violence against one another The decline-of-war thesis seems implausible , if for no other reason that the 20th century was spectacularly bloody by any standard The response is that the World Wars was a fluke The primary evidence for the decline of war is taken to be, not the “anomalous” World Wars, but the seventy-year “Long Peace” that followed There are two problems with this argument The first is that it’s often possible to point to one person who lit the fuse that led to war: the Napoleonic Wars are called that for a reason. That’s not the same thing as arguing that that individual was both necessary and sufficient for the onset of war—an extremely ambitious claim that is unlikely to withstand scrutiny World War II may have been begun by Hitler but the ground was made fertile for him by the punitive peace of World War I the crushing terms of German reparations The Allies took these steps knowing that there was a risk of substantial backlash The second, and more serious, problem is that it attributes the occurrence of war to chance without exploring the role of chance in the occurrence of peace. most scholars see both processes as irreducibly probabilistic One can cite any number of peaceful periods that could just as easily have exploded into war During the Cuban Missile Crisis the U S conveyed its intention to use practice depth charges to force Soviet submarines to surface but the Soviet Union failed to inform the four Foxtrot-class submarines in the area of that fact On October 27, a trapped Foxtrot submarine very nearly used its nuclear weapon against the American Navy: doing so required consensus among the captain, the second in command, and the political officer, and only one of the three refused to endorse a nuclear response we can take a rough stab at assessing which of these two events was more anomalous If we look at the record of Great Power wars we ênd an average of about two per century prior to the 20th century Having two such wars in the 20th century, therefore, is far from anomalous it’s more or less what we’d expect The Long Peace is only slightly less likely to have happened by chance than the two World Wars World War II was the bloodiest conflict in modern human history subsequent conflicts have been impressively costly the claim that human violence is on the decline requires qualification Authors who make it typically note that the number of people available to be killed in war has increased considerably so the appropriate metric is war deaths per capita Is this a reasonable metric Not really War deaths per capita accurately reflects the average citizen’s risk from death in war, but it’s not immediately obvious how that quantity is related to human war-proneness A decrease in war deaths per capita means that population is outpacing war deaths There may be fewer people exposed to risk of death from war the individual risk may have decreased due to other factors combat medicine, for example and so on. Moreover, population growth is exponential and exponential growth defies human imagination more than 1 in 20 people who have ever lived, from 50,000 B.C. to the present, are alive at this moment We should hardly be surprised that deaths from war cannot keep up the best way to gauge the warlikeness of nations would be to measure the frequency with which they run the risk of war Initiating a war, or issuing a threat that creates the risk of war is indicative of the willingness in the worst case, to spill quite a bit of blood that willingness is the best indicator of the propensity of the state to engage in violent conflict trends in conflicts are the most reliable indicator of the propensity of states to fight wars Pinker offers little justifcation for examining only Great Powers and European states save that they “offer a circumscribed but consequential theater in which we can look at historical trends in war.” None of the proponents of the decline-in-warfare thesis suggests that it should be an exclusively European or Great-Power phenomenon Indeed, quite the opposite we should examine Brecke’s data in order to see what the the long-term trends in warfare look like in the international system as a whole we need look no farther than the working paper that Pinker cites Brecke’s graph of trends suggest that conflict in the last two centuries has been more prevalent than ever before fine-grained data from the industry-standard Correlates of War Militarized Interstate Dispute dataset lead us to a similar conclusion many states in the international system are not “politically relevant” to one another: conflict between them is unlikely for purely geographic reasons, and we should account for that fact when attempting to draw inferences about the onset of war and its causes. as of this writing there is little consensus in the literature regarding how exactly to measure political relevance The simplest rule to apply is contiguity: Only neighboring pairs of states, or states separated by less than 150 miles of water, are treated as potential combatants the downward trend has clearly reversed itself: the overall trend is slightly upward and has held steady at a higher rate during the Cold War than in previous periods. Even if we add another condition—that any dyad containing a Great Power is politically relevant—we still find that around a quarter of all militarized disputes in the postwar period occurred between “politically irrelevant” states we are faced with a surprisingly stark result not only does the inclination to fight not decrease, it actually increases, What does decrease is the ability of potential combatants to reach each other. the trends are far from what one would expect if the decline-of-war thesis could hold water. More important, the model gives us an important metric a measure of political relevance—that we can use to draw conclusions about the raw data Although the period from the 1960s to the present does exhibit a decline in conflict the drop is fairly modest and the result is a rate of conflict not too different from the average across the past two centuries There is certainly no suggestion of a general downward trend in rates of conflict initiation a more reasonable characterization would be a cyclical alternation of more-warlike and less-warlike periods. that’s not to say that an upswing will inevitably follow the current lull: indeed, the general trend more closely resembles a random walk than a steady decline per-capita deaths from war is a misleading and irrelevant statistic to use in answering this question because it has no foundation in a coherent account of how wars actually happen I argue instead that we should be examining uses of force that have the potential to become wars because such actions are indicative of a willingness to use considerable violence even if that willingness is not realized. An initial glance suggested that the propensity to use force is going up rather than down This trend is plausibly an artifact of the division of the world into a larger number of political units At the same time, those units are on average smaller, weaker, and more distant I therefore examine a new metric—uses of force per relevant dyad— that controls for both trends simultaneously. The results bear little resemblance to a decline in violence over time. A more reasonable characterization might be a semi-random oscillation pattern of that nature offers little basis to conclude that war is on the decline or to conclude much of anything at all about its likely future direction
the 20th century was spectacularly bloody by any standard. The response evidence for the decline of war is taken to be the seventy-year “Long Peace” that followed this argument attributes the occurrence of war to chance without exploring the role of chance in the occurrence of peace One can cite any number of peaceful periods that could easily have exploded into war. the Cuban Missile Crisis The Long Peace is only slightly less likely to have happened by chance than the two World Wars Authors note that the appropriate metric is war deaths per capita it’s not obvious how that quantity is related to war-proneness.7 population is outpacing war deaths population growth is exponential We should hardly be surprised that deaths from war cannot keep up the best way to gauge warlikeness would be to measure the frequency with which they run the risk of war Pinker offers little justifcation for examining only Great Powers and European states conflict in the last two centuries has been more prevalent than ever before. data from the Correlates of War lead us to a similar conclusion the overall trend is upward trends are far from what one would expect if the decline-of-war thesis could hold water There is certainly no suggestion of a downward trend in rates of conflict initiation the propensity to use force is going up I examine a new metric—uses of force per relevant dyad— that controls for both trends simultaneously The results bear little resemblance to a decline in violence over time
Introduction A spate of recent research1 strongly suggests, contra popular perception, that war and violence are on the decline and have been for decades or centuries. Steven Pinker (2011) argues that, as a result of an irregularly overlapping set of processes— pacification, civilization, and the “humanitarian revolution”—there has been an across-the-board decline in the propensity of humans to use violence against one another, both individually and collectively. Along the same lines, John Mueller (2004) argues both that ideational changes—a growing distaste for the institution of warfare—and political ones, in the form of more capable political institutions, have resulted in a general decline in warfare. Pinker’s book, in particular, has been heralded in the mainstream press: one fairly typical review concludes that it is “supremely important…. Pinker convincingly demonstrates that there has been a dramatic decline in violence, and he is persuasive about the causes of that decline.” (Singer, 2011) Exploring these arguments is interesting for three reasons. First, and most obviously, we wish to know whether war is, in fact, disappearing. Second, to the conëict studies community, this question is a thrown gauntlet: if we cannot answer this simple question in a compelling manner, how can we hope to explain the causes of war? Finally, answering the question convincingly requires us to understand both the nature of war and how it should be measured. Those issues, I argue, are more complicated than most people realize. In this sketch of a paper, I offer some preliminary thoughts on how to go about answering these questions about the nature of war and its proper measurement. I leave aside for the moment arguments about the changing nature of war, such as Mueller’s contention that most modern wars are policing wars that are prompted by bandits and thugs.2 I also leave aside civil war, which has its own dynamics and merits separate exploration. I focus more narrowly on the argument that the frequency of interstate war, whatever the reason for its employment, has gone down. I highlight a primary, heretofore unaccounted-for driver of changes in warlike behavior, namely, simple geography: as the world has divided itself into smaller, weaker, and more distant political units, fewer and fewer of those units are able (or willing) to reach each other to engage in combat. At the same time, those political units are far more numerous, so the number of opportunities for conëict has increased dramatically. Existing studies of the decline of war have ignored these two trends. I control for them and ênd, on balance, that no net trend toward a decrease in war is evident. If anything, the opposite is true. Chance, Peace, and War The decline-of-war thesis seems implausible on the surface, if for no other reason that the 20th century was spectacularly bloody by any standard. The response of its proponents, essentially, is that one or both of the two World Wars in that century was a fluke—a statistical anomaly. Mueller (2004, 2), for example, calls World War II “a spectacular anachronism, fabricated almost single-handedly by history’s supreme atavism, Adolf Hitler.” Pinker (2011, 208-9) also points to Hitler, as well as to Gavrilo Princip, and argues that each was a necessary condition for his respective war. The primary evidence for the decline of war is taken to be, not the “anomalous” World Wars, but the nearly seventy-year “Long Peace” that followed them.3 There are two problems with this argument. The first is that it’s often possible to point to one person who, more than others, lit the fuse that led to war: the Napoleonic Wars are called that for a reason. That’s not the same thing as arguing that that individual was both necessary and sufficient for the onset of war—an extremely ambitious claim that is unlikely to withstand scrutiny.4 World War II may have been begun by Hitler, but the ground was made fertile for him by the punitive peace of World War I and the crushing terms of German reparations. The Allies took these steps knowing full well that there was a risk of substantial backlash: although no one could have foreseen Hitler, some hypernationalist response leading to a Great Power war was hardly out of the question. The second, and more serious, problem with the argument is that it attributes the occurrence of war to chance without exploring the role of chance in the occurrence of peace. In fact, most scholars see both processes as irreducibly probabilistic. One can cite any number of peaceful periods that could just as easily have exploded into war. During the Cuban Missile Crisis, for example, the United States conveyed its intention to use practice depth charges to force Soviet submarines near the quarantine line to surface, but the Soviet Union failed to inform the four Foxtrot-class submarines in the area of that fact. The Soviets, for their part, failed to convey the fact that their submarines were armed with nuclear-tipped torpedoes. On October 27, a trapped Foxtrot submarine very nearly used its nuclear weapon against the American Navy: doing so required consensus among the captain, the second in command, and the political officer, and only one of the three—Vasili Arkhipov—refused to endorse a nuclear response (Roberts, 2012). If we give the role that chance plays the same credit in peace that we give it in war, we can take a rough stab at assessing which of these two events—the two World Wars, or the “long peace” that followed—was more anomalous. If we look at the record of Great Power wars over the past êve centuries (Levy, 1983; Goldstein, 1988, 146), we ênd an average of about two per century prior to the 20th century. Having two such wars in the 20th century, therefore, is far from anomalous; it’s more or less what we’d expect given what we’ve seen in the past. More surprising, perhaps, is the fact that the seventy years of peace that have passed since the end of World War II are hardly anomalous either. More formally, let’s take the probability of a systemic war breaking out in any given year, based on historical precedent, to be 0.02.5 We can calculate the probability of seeing k “successes” (wars) in n “trials” (years) given an underlying probability of success p by examining the probability mass function of a binomial distribution, P r(X = k) = ( n k ) p k (1 p) (nk) Figure 1 uses this function to compare the probability of observing no wars in the 70 years since World War II with the probabilities of observing one, two, three, or more wars in the same time period, if nothing has changed—that is, if the probability of systemic war has not deviated from its historical average of two per century. As we can see, although the most likely outcome is a single war during that time period, an absence of wars is far from improbable. Figure 2 takes a look at how these same probabilities change over the course of 250 years. As the Figure demonstrates, for nearly 50 years, peace is the most likely outcome. A single war then becomes more likely, but not much more; and at no point are one or two wars all that much more a likely outcome than none at all. These Figures answer our question about the improbability of World Wars I and II, relative to the Long Peace. If there has been no change in the underlying propensity for systemic war over time, the probability of seeing two wars in the 20th century–that is, the probability that two of the 100 one-year periods contained in the century will see the onset of general war—is 27.3%. By contrast, the probability of observing seven continuous decades of peace—zero wars in fourteen êve-year trials, with a probability of “success” of 0.02—is 24.3%. The Long Peace is only slightly less likely to have happened by chance than the two World Wars. How many years of peace would we have to see before we could conclude that the long-term average no longer applies? We can examine the conêdence intervals of the binomial distribution to answer this question. These intervals delimit the plausible values of p, the probability of Great Power war, given n years of peace. As Figure 3 shows, although the range of plausible values narrows quickly for the êrst half-century or so, it would still take about 150 years of uninterrupted peace for us to reject conclusively the hypothesis that the underlying probability of systemic war remains unchanged.6 Now that I’ve addressed a few points about how much we can, or can’t, infer about the long-term probability of systemic war from the World Wars and the Long Peace, I will turn to a thornier issue—the nature of war and its implications for measurement—before addressing the question of whether or not the use of force more generally is in fact in decline. The (Mis)measure of War World War II was the bloodiest conflict in modern human history, and subsequent conflicts have been impressively costly, so on its surface the claim that human violence is on the decline requires qualification. Authors who make it typically note that the number of people available to be killed in war has increased considerably, so the appropriate metric is not absolute number of war deaths, but rather, war deaths per capita. Pinker (2011, 51), for example, notes that “[t]he number of deaths per 100,000 people per year is the standard measure of homicide rates, and I will use it as the yardstick of violence throughout the book.” Is this a reasonable metric to use when examining the argument that war is disappearing over time? Not really. War deaths per capita accurately reflects the average citizen’s risk from death in war, but it’s not immediately obvious how that quantity is related to human war-proneness.7 A decrease in war deaths per capita means that population is outpacing war deaths—nothing more, nothing less. There may be fewer people exposed to risk of death from war; the individual risk may have decreased due to other factors (combat medicine, for example); and so on. Moreover, population growth is exponential, and exponential growth defies human imagination: more than 1 in 20 people who have ever lived, from 50,000 B.C. to the present, are alive at this moment (Curtin, 2007). We should hardly be surprised that deaths from war cannot keep up. More generally, we cannot infer any direct relationship between individual-level characteristics and state bellicosity for one simple reason: the logic of individual action in the context of a domestic political hierarchy does not, in any straightforward manner, map to the logic of state action in the context of international anarchy (Waltz, 1959, 1979). As Kant argued in Perpetual Peace, the problem of achieving order can be solved even by a race of intelligent devils; similarly, Jervis (1978) shows that war may occur even between states that desire peace. The behavior of states does not, in any uncomplicated way, reëect the nature of individual humans: to argue that it does is to commit logical as well as ecological fallacies. Therefore, we cannot point to a change in the rate of death from war (or even the number of deaths from war) as evidence that people are becoming more peaceful. How, then, can we understand whether states are becoming more peaceful? In order to understand whether something is changing, we must êrst understand how to measure it; in order to measure it, we must understand what it is. To answer this question, therefore, we need to begin by exploring the fundamental nature of war. What Is War? If our goal is to understand war, we should start with the writings of Carl von Clausewitz (1832/1976). Clausewitz described two different understandings of war— absolute war, which he likened to “a duel on a larger scale” (75), and “real war, or the sort of war that we actually observe, which he described as “a continuation of political intercourse, with the addition of other means.” (605) The distinction is puzzling at êrst, especially given Clausewitz’s claim that absolute wars rarely if ever occur. The logic of Clausewitz’s models of war, and their relationship to one another, have been usefully ëeshed out by modern theorists. First, Fearon (1995) asked the question of why a rational state would êght at all, given the inevitable costs of doing so and the availability of a costless negotiated settlement. In Fearon’s model of warfare, the process that leads to war is a process of negotiation. When actors cannot credibly commit to a settlement or one actor has private information (about its capabilities or resolve, say) and an incentive to misrepresent that information, then war occurs; otherwise, rational actors should be able to reach a negotiated settlement. Wagner (2000) pushes this logic further by arguing that negotiation continues during war—that, in fact, war is a form of costly negotiation, Clausewitz’s “continuation of political intercourse, with the addition of other means.” War begins due to a lack of information, and êghting reveals the information needed to arrive at a settlement. In a simple example, a state with an incentive to bluff, or pretend to be stronger than it is, will soon have its weakness revealed on the battleêeld and be forced to accept a settlement that reëects its weakness. Wagner also addresses the question of how Clausewitz’s “real war” is related to “absolute war.” Absolute war comprises a process, not of êghting to reveal information, but of êghting to defeat the opponent’s military and hold its civilian population hostage.8 The outcome of absolute war, war to the bitter end, is the hypothetical about which real war provides information. In order for absolute war to play that role, though, there must be some chance that it will be realized—that is, some possibility that war will change relative capabilities more rapidly, or more effectively, than it provides information about them. This intuition is captured well by Smith and Stam (2004), who describe a bargaining game in which states êght in order to conquer “forts” (analogous to territory or strategic assets). If one side captures all of the assets, the other is left defenseless and must yield. The act of êghting over such assets both tilts the balance this way and that and, in the process, gives the players more information about their relative capabilities. A settlement can occur either as the result of increased information or as a result of military defeat. From this perspective, decision makers terminate wars when their estimates of one another’s capabilities converge.9 Those estimates are inëuenced by the efficacy of their military forces: a side that loses êve, ten, or êfteen battles in a row should begin to suspect that it has made a mistake. Implications What empirical implications can we glean from this account of war that can help us to answer the question of whether war is on the decline? First, information, not attrition, is the goal of conflict. This fact drives a stake into the heart of the wardeaths-per-capita metric, since there is no direct or obvious connection between changes in estimates of relative capabilities and size of total population. Decision makers glean information as a result of the outcome of a series of battles; their relative losses influence those estimates. Although an informative loss might be more costly in modern warfare than it was 200 years ago, that change is likely due to changes in technology, not to changes in the size of the civilian population. Simply put, the outcomes of ten tank battles are probably costlier than the outcomes of ten equally informative cavalry battles; but either should be as informative to the leader of a country of a million as it is to the leader of a country of ten million. Second, conflict initiation, and even the “bargaining” that might lead to initiation, is a gamble. Leaders cannot know whether their opponents will fold or stand firm until they do one or the other. If they stand êrm, leaders cannot know whether their divergent beliefs will be resolved by the outcome of a few skirmishes, a weekslong conëict, or a major war. As Pinker (2011, 192) himself puts it, “When the iron dice begin to roll (as the German chancellor Theobald von Bethmann-Hollweg put it on the eve of World War I), the unlucky outcomes can be far worse than our primitive imaginations foresee.” Indeed, Tuchman (1962, ch. 9) documents the fact that political elites in the capitols of the Great Powers believed nearly unanimously that the conëict begun in 1914 would last no more than a few weeks, or possibly a couple of months at the outside. This fact, too, undercuts the war-deaths-per-capita metric: if the scale of a war is uncontrollable, except by surrender, and therefore unknowable a priori, it cannot reëect the magnitude of the human propensity for violence that led to war. When the first bullets fly, no decision maker can know how many people will die; so their intent cannot be measured by the number of people who actually do die, whether a thousand or a million. The only reasonable metric is the willingness to “roll the dice” in the first place. These two conclusions help us to resolve the dilemma that Pinker (2011, 210) outlines: “[W]arlike” can refer to two different things. It can refer to how likely people are to go to war, or it can refer to how many people are killed when they do. Imagine two rural counties with the same size population. One of them has a hundred teenage arsonists who delight in setting forest êres. But the forests are in isolated patches, so each êre dies out before doing much damage. The other county has just two arsonists, but its forests are connected, so that a small blaze is likely to spread, as they say, like wildêre. Which county has the worse forest êre problem? One could argue it either way. As far as the amount of reckless depravity is concerned, the êrst county is worse; as far as the risk of serious damage is concerned, the second is. Given the fact that that states êght in order to gain information, not to produce attrition of one another’s general populations, and given that the intentions of leaders who risk war cannot be inferred from the magnitude of the war that results, we are in a situation in which, to continue Pinker’s analogy, when forests are randomly distributed in each village and the arsonists set êres without knowing how far they will spread, the village with more arsonists is the village with the worse problem. Accordingly, the best way to gauge the warlikeness of nations would be to measure the frequency with which they run the risk of war. Initiating a war, or issuing a threat that creates the risk of war, is indicative of the willingness, in the worst case, to spill quite a bit of blood; that willingness is the best indicator of the propensity of the state to engage in violent conflict; and the individual conëict incident, or militarized dispute, is the most reliable objective indicator of that willingness.10 War and Numbers The preceding discussion leads to the conclusion that trends in conflicts of any kind are probably the most reliable indicator of the propensity of states to fight wars. The question then becomes, what can we discern from trends in conëict? At first glance, trends in conëict would seem to support the disappearance-ofwar thesis. In his Figure 5.17, reproduced here as Figure 4, Pinker (2011, 222-231) uses data on the number of conëicts per year from Peter Brecke’s “conëict catalog”11 to demonstrate that war among European powers is on the decline. An earlier Figure (5.13, not presented here) does the same for Great Power wars. Nevertheless, Pinker offers little justifcation for examining only Great Powers and European states, save that they “offer a circumscribed but consequential theater in which we can look at historical trends in war.” None of the proponents of the decline-in-warfare thesis suggests that it should be an exclusively European or Great-Power phenomenon. Indeed, quite the opposite. Pinker (2011, ch. 4, esp. at 134) explicitly makes reference to his “humanitarian revolution” as a worldwide phenomenon, while Mueller (2004), who largely focuses on war between developed states, explicitly (6; 83) notes that the same trends are evident in less-developed parts of the world. To begin, then, we should examine Brecke’s data in order to see what the the long-term trends in warfare look like in the international system as a whole. To do so, we need look no farther than the working paper that Pinker cites (Brecke, 1999), which does just this. Brecke’s graph of trends in the international system— reproduced here as Figure 5—suggest that conflict in the last two centuries has been more prevalent than ever before. More fine-grained data from the industry-standard Correlates of War Militarized Interstate Dispute (MID) dataset lead us to a similar conclusion. MARKED In Figure 6, I calculate the number of uses of force12 per year and graph them against time. Given the volatility of the series, I also add a lowess line through the center of the data to capture the central tendency of the data. The result is precisely the opposite of what one would expect if war were on the decline: uses of force held more or less steady through the êrst World War but then increased steadily thereafter. The problem with this graph, and the previous ones, is straightforward: no correction is made for the number of interaction opportunities in the international system. Especially during the êrst two thirds of the twentieth century, the number of independent states in the system grew dramatically, and the number of opportunities for conëict rose accordingly: in a world of two states, only one pair of states can go to war; in a world of four states, there are six possible axes of conëict; and so on. To correct for this issue, in Figure 7 I divide the number of uses of force in a given year by the number of pairs of states (or dyads) present in the international system. In this graph, we can see precisely the sort of relationship that we would expect to see if war were dwindling: a steady decline through both centuries, interrupted by brief surges around the time of the two World Wars.13 Although Figure 7 would seem to be an improvement on Figure 6, it is not without its own problems. Counting every pair of states in the international system as a potential conëict dyad is ambitious, to say the least. The overwhelming majority of the states in the international system lack the ability to project power beyond their own region, at best; most, in the absence of outside assistance, are limited to conëict with their neighbors. Moreover, the scope of states’ political interests tends roughly to correspond to the scope of their inëuence. A clash between Bolivia and Botswana is highly unlikely, both because they are distant and weak and because the politics of each is largely irrelevant to the other. In short, as Maoz and Russett (1993) memorably put it, many states in the international system are not “politically relevant” to one another: conflict between them is unlikely for purely geographic reasons, and we should account for that fact when attempting to draw inferences about the onset of war and its causes. Unfortunately, as of this writing there is little consensus in the literature regarding how exactly to measure, or control for, political relevance (Braumoeller and Carson, 2011, 292-293). The simplest rule to apply is contiguity: Only neighboring pairs of states, or states separated by less than 150 miles of water, are treated as potential combatants. If we apply this rule and reexamine the use of force over time (Figure 8), the downward trend has clearly reversed itself: though there is a fair bit of noise, the overall trend is slightly upward and has held steady at a higher rate during the Cold War than in previous periods. Clearly, assuming that conëict can only occur between neighboring states is overcompensating for political relevance. Even if we add another condition—that any dyad containing a Great Power is politically relevant—we still find that around a quarter of all militarized disputes in the postwar period occurred between “politically irrelevant” states. Other assumptions—including pairs of states that are separated by up to 400 miles, for example—do not solve the problem, though they do reduce the percentage of excluded disputes by a bit (Benson, 2005, 115-116). At this point, we face a serious dilemma. Controlling for the number of pairs of states in the international system tentatively suggests that war is indeed on the decline, but controlling for the number of contiguous states leads to the opposite conclusion. Neither answer is satisfactory, because neither controls for the correct number of states. What we need is a theoretically motivated measure of political relevance that allows for shades of grey—that is, for situations in which distance and weakness renders conëict improbable, not impossible. In the next section, I describe a statistical model of the use of force that allows me to estimate, empirically, the political relevance of any pair of states in the international system. The measure is not perfect, but I argue that it represents the state of the art at present. I also include in the model two sets of variables designed to allow me to capture the main arguments implicated in the decline-of-war literature—the humanitarian revolution, and the trend toward better and more coherent governance—so that I can examine the contribution of each to changes, if any, in the average propensity of states to êght over time. Modeling War and Peace My main goal in constructing a statistical model of war and peace is to generate an estimate of political relevance that I can then use to construct a reasonable metric of the warlikeness of states—conëict incidents per politically relevant dyad. That, in turn, will help us to answer the question of whether international war is disappearing. As a side beneêt, we can use the statistical model to measure the contributions of a variety of factors to the probability of conëict initiation. To preview, the model will have three main components. The êrst will be a model of the warlikeness of states—that is, their general propensity to use force to settle disputes. The theoretical model of war outlined above gives us some general expectations about the sorts of situations in which we should expect to see states resort to violence—namely, those in which there is a fair bit of uncertainty about relative capabilities and, therefore, about the outcome. If the decline-of-war theorists are correct, we should ênd that the propensity to êght based on such calculations is in decline. More than that, however: We should ênd that the propensity to use force to settle disputes is in decline even when controlling for other factors that are known to blunt it. Two of these—regime type and political irrelevance—are the second and third components of the model. Democratic political regimes are known to be peaceful in their dealings with one another; their inëuence should be controlled for because both Pinker and Mueller point to a change in ideas, not institutions, as the source of paciêcation. Political irrelevance—greater distances between weaker states—makes war less possible, not less desirable: its effects are not unlike those of putting bellicose siblings in different rooms for a “time out.” Distance decreases the opportunity to êght, whether or not states are willing to do so. If the decline-of-war theorists are correct and humans desire less conëict than they had in previous decades, warlikeness should decrease even when distance is controlled for. Warlikeness The êrst thing that we need is a measure of warlikeness, or the conëict propensity of states. The most obvious culprit, given the theoretical explanation of war that we use above, is uncertainty. The bargaining model of war described above leads us to expect that war will be more likely when states are more uncertain about the balance of power. Regardless of the issue at stake, uncertainty can cause a challenger to the status quo to demand too much, or cause a defender to underestimate the challenger’s willingness to êght. As uncertainty increases, so does the potential for misunderstandings like these to lead to war. Unfortunately, there is no good measure of the uncertainty in states’ calculations about one another’s capabilities. However, as intuition suggests (and Reed (2003) demonstrates), uncertainty is highest when states’ capabilities are relatively evenly matched. When capabilities are mismatched, by contrast, the likely outcome of a conëict is clear enough to forestall it. Therefore, we can use the difference in capabilities of states as a proxy for the propensity of states to engage in conëict as a result of uncertainty about the likely outcome of that conëict. The advantages of this model of warlikeness are twofold: it follows cleanly from the bargaining model of war described above, and the logic applies to any impetus toward conëict—territorial issues, ideology, hegemony, or what have you. H1a: Uncertainty, as captured by similarity of capabilities, increases the propensity of states to engage in conëict. Using this baseline model of warlikeness, we can ascertain both whether increased uncertainty leads to an increase in the propensity to use force and whether that propensity has become less prevalent over time. What we can’t do is ascertain whether, as decline-of-war theorists argue, the propensity to êght has declined over time despite unchanging levels of uncertainty. To do that, we need to include a second variable: Time. H1b: Over time, the propensity of states to initiate conëict has declined. Including time in the equation ensures that we can capture secular declines in warlikeness over time, for whatever reason. Any variable implicated in the decline-ofwar literature must, of necessity, be highly correlated with the passage of time. Time is, therefore, a useful proxy, even if it fails to capture the precise quantity of interest.14 Governance, Good and Bad These hypotheses are subject to a caveat. Over the last three decades, scholars have arrived at a near-consensus that relations among democratic states are largely if not entirely exempt from the pressures that lead most states to war (Doyle, 1983a,b; Russett, 1993). While these êndings do suggest that the impetus to go to war has been substantially reduced in the case of a subset of states, they cannot speak to the overall proclivity of states to êght: if democracies are substantially more likely to êght nondemocracies than nondemocracies are to êght one another, the systemic implication of low-to-intermediate levels of democratization might be more war, not less. Nevertheless, among democracies the relationship between uncertainty and war should be substantially mitigated. H2a: Joint democracy decreases the impact of the similarity of capabilities on the probability of conëict. Along the same lines, Mueller (2004), who argues that democracy is more likely to be a result of peace than the cause of it (2, 167-169), suggests that “capable government…is ultimately the most promising method for the long-term control, and even potentially for the eradication, of most of the remnants of war.” (3) This is so because of the decrease it produces in organized criminality, which Mueller sees as a primary source of the “policing wars” that dominate organized international uses of force today. H2b: Capable governance decreases the impact of the similarity of capabilities on the probability of conëict. Political Relevance Finally, these generalizations only hold among states that are politically relevant to one another: in the Botswana-Bolivia dyad, for example, relative capabilities and regime type are largely immaterial. We therefore need to specify a ênal condition: H3: Political irrelevance decreases the impact of the similarity of capabilities and of regime type on the probability of conëict. Measurement To test these hypotheses, I utilize a range of variables from the Correlates of War Militarized Interstate Dispute (MID) project,15 aggregated by EUGene (Bennett and Stam, 2000), as well as more up-to-date data from the Polity project. To measure the difference in capabilities between state i and state j, I begin with the standard Correlates of War capabilities measure, cap, and create the index Capability Difference = jcapi capjj capi + capj (1) For time, I measure the number of years since 1815. For regime type, I use the standard Polity measures of democracy (i.e., democracy-anocracy) for states i and j, as well as their product. In addition, I create a new variable, Anocracyi or j, that equals one if the democracy score of either state lies between 3 and -3 and zero otherwise. This variable captures the argument that poor governance, rather than governance of a particular sort, creates an impetus to war. To capture the concept of political relevance, I include three variables: the Correlates of War capability score of the strongest state; the log of the inter-capital distance between states i and j; and a dummy variable indicating whether the dyad contains at least one major power, as deêned by the COW project. Analysis Given the fundamentally interactive nature of the hypotheses—political relevance and regime type moderate the impact of uncertainty on the use of force—I utilize Boolean logit (Braumoeller, 2003) to test the hypotheses. In a nutshell, in contrast to standard logit analysis, in which Pr(y = 1) = (X ); (2) Boolean logit posits the existence of three latent dependent variables—y u , or the dyad’s propensity to use force; y r , the pacifying effects of regime type; and y pr, the degree to which political relevance permits states to use force in the êrst place. It then assigns separate vectors of independent variables to each latent dependent variable: Pr(y u = 1) = (X ) (3) Pr(y r = 1) = (Z ) (4) Pr(y pr = 1) = (W ) (5) Finally, it speciêes the interactive manner in which the combination of latent dependent variables contributes to the observed dependent variable, the use of force: Pr(y = 1) = Pr(y u = 1) Pr(y r = 1) Pr(y pr = 1) (6) In this case, because the theory speciêes a conjunctural relationship among the latent variables, the result resembles a standard multiplicative interaction, except that vectors of independent variables rather than individual variables are interacting with one another. The technique has two advantages from the point of view of this study. First, we can use it to create predictions, or estimates, of the unmeasured latent dependent variables. In particular, we can simply compute (W ) in order to produce a continuous metric of political relevance—a function of distance, capabilities, and Great Power status that is bounded at 0 and 1. This variable will provide a much richer and more nuanced measure of political relevance than simple measures of contiguity.Put another way: Most measures of political relevance assume a strict relationship between Great Power status and/or contiguity, on the one hand, and political relevance, on the other. Rather than assuming such a relationship, this technique allows us to estimate it. The second advantage is that we can use the results to capture three distinct quantities that reëect conëict propensity, regime type, and political relevance, and chart those separate quantities over time. To do so, we average the value of the latent dependent variable across all units in the system in each year. Changes in those averages over time are indicative of how much or how little the propensity for conëict and the pacifying effects of regime type and political irrelevance have changed across the system over time. Table 1 contains the results of the Boolean logit analysis.16 As anticipated, simi- larity of capabilities—our indicator of uncertainty—increases the probability of conëict, as does the absence of coherent government on the part of at least one of the states in the dyad, while joint democracy decreases it. As one might anticipate, political relevance increases with the capabilities of the strongest actor and with the presence of a major power in the dyad, and decreases with distance. Most surprising, though, is the coefficient on the time variable, which reëects a modest but signiêcant increase in the propensity to êght over time. These results allow us to break apart the different components of conëict initiation to see whether, on average, any of them has declined over time. Figure 9 does exactly this by charting the mean within-sample predicted value for each of the y over time. While there is little change in the pacifying effects of regime type,17 there is a signiêcant increase over time in warlikeness, or the propensity to use force to resolve disputes. This propensity dips a bit during the long and relatively peaceful 19th century, but it increases steadily through the 20th. At the same time, we can see a clear and dramatic decrease in average political relevance across the entire period, as the world is increasingly divided up into states that are smaller, weaker, and farther apart. Discussion The goal of the above analysis was to separate three trends over time: the propensity to initiate conëict in situations of uncertainty, as the bargaining model of war suggests states will do; the pacifying effects of political regime type; and the pseudo-pacifying effects of the trend toward smaller, weaker, and more distant states. Having done so, we are faced with a surprisingly stark result: not only does the inclination to fight not decrease, it actually increases, slowly but steadily. What does decrease, quite dramatically, is the ability of potential combatants to reach each other. No model of conflict initiation is perfect, of course, and this one is surely far from it: the macro-level variables make inference particularly challenging. Even so, the trends are far from what one would expect if the decline-of-war thesis could hold water. More important, the model gives us an important metric—a measure of political relevance—that we can use to draw conclusions about the raw data. Recall that, in Figure 8, we looked at uses of force per politically relevant dyad, but the measure of political relevance that we used was a very imperfect one. A much improved measure of political relevance can be had by calculating the predicted value of y pr using the above variables W and coefficients . As a quick check of surface validity, I plot political relevance from the perspective of four countries—the United States, the United Kingdom, Egypt, and Chile—in the year 1993 in Figure 10. The plots correspond roughly to intuition: to the United States, most of the world is mostly relevant, with only the most distant parts slightly less so, while the United Kingdom displays a more regional pattern. Egypt’s politically relevant neighborhood is more constrained still, extending through much of the Middle East and including the more powerful states of Europe, while Chile primarily sees neighbors and Great Powers as its politically relevant cohort. There is room to quibble, of course, but the results represent a considerable improvement over the standard way of doing things, which suggests that all states are equally relevant to Great Powers and non-Great Powers are only relevant to their neighbors. With this more nuanced measure of political relevance, we can get a much better sense of trends in the use of force controlling for capabilities and distance. I turn to this task in the next section. War and Political Relevance The final step in this exercise is to measure the frequency of conëict initiation controlling for the political relevance of dyads. Our measure of conëicts per dyad was simply the number of uses of force in a given year, divided by the number of extant dyads in that year. Conëicts per contiguous dyad was equal to the number of uses of force divided by the number of contiguous (directly or within 150 miles by water) dyads. In order to create a measure of systemic warlikeness, I divide the number of uses of force in the system in a given year by the sum of the political-relevance scores for all dyads in the system. This measure assumes, êrst, that the political-relevance measure is reasonably accurate, and second, that we should on average expect half as many conëicts from a dyad with a political relevance score of 0.5 as we would expect from a dyad with a political relevance score of 1. Given that the estimator that was used to derive the measure incorporates exactly this assumption, it would seem not to be too unrealistic. Figure 11 illustrates the result—the ênal overall metric of warlikeness from 1816– 2001. Although the period from the 1960s to the present does exhibit a decline in conflict, the drop is fairly modest, and the result is a rate of conflict not too different from the average across the past two centuries. There is certainly no suggestion of a general downward trend in rates of conflict initiation; a more reasonable characterization would be a cyclical alternation of more-warlike (1850s, 1910s, 1940-90) and less-warlike periods. Of course, that’s not to say that an upswing will inevitably follow the current lull: indeed, the general trend more closely resembles a random walk than a steady decline. We might be tempted to derive meaning from the postCold War cluster of lower-conëict years, and in time we may conclude that they’re more than a ëuke; but as Pinker himself puts it, “events that occur at random seem to come in clusters, because it would take a nonrandom process to space them out.” (Pinker, 2011, 203) Conclusion In this paper, I set out to explore the claim that there has been an overall decline in the propensity of states to use violence against one another in international relations. I’ve argued that per-capita deaths from war is a misleading and irrelevant statistic to use in answering this question, because it has no foundation in a coherent account of how wars actually happen. I argue instead that we should be examining uses of force that have the potential to become wars, because such actions are indicative of a willingness to use considerable violence even if that willingness is not realized. An initial glance at uses of force per year suggested that the propensity to use force is going up rather than down. This trend is plausibly an artifact of the division of the world into a larger number of political units with a larger number of conëict opportunities. At the same time, those units are on average smaller, weaker, and more distant. I therefore examine a new metric—uses of force per relevant dyad— that controls for both trends simultaneously. The results bear little resemblance to a decline in violence over time. A more reasonable characterization might be a semi-random oscillation, with more and less conëictual periods alternating across irregular periods. A pattern of that nature offers little basis to conclude that war is on the decline—or indeed, to conclude much of anything at all about its likely future direction.
43,176
<h4>Their methodology is flawed and Eurocentric---war per capita is a terrible metric—the past two centuries have been exceptionally violent and the trend is only increasing---your role should be to look at the <u>enabling</u> conditions for violence and not rest your faith in our luck so far </h4><p>Bear F. <u><strong>Braumoeller 13</u></strong>, The Ohio State University Department of Political Science, August 27, “Is War Disappearing?” http://www.braumoeller.info/wp-content/uploads/2013/08/Is-War-Disappearing.pdf</p><p>Introduction <u>A spate of recent research1</u> <u>strongly suggests</u>, contra popular perception, <u>that war and violence are on the decline and have been for decades or centuries</u>. Steven <u>Pinker </u>(2011) <u>argues that, as a result of</u> an irregularly overlapping set of processes— <u>pacification, civilization, and the “humanitarian revolution</u>”—<u>there has been a</u>n across-the-board <u>decline in the propensity of humans to use violence against one another</u>, both individually and collectively. Along the same lines, John Mueller (2004) argues both that ideational changes—a growing distaste for the institution of warfare—and political ones, in the form of more capable political institutions, have resulted in a general decline in warfare. Pinker’s book, in particular, has been heralded in the mainstream press: one fairly typical review concludes that it is “supremely important…. Pinker convincingly demonstrates that there has been a dramatic decline in violence, and he is persuasive about the causes of that decline.” (Singer, 2011) Exploring these arguments is interesting for three reasons. First, and most obviously, we wish to know whether war is, in fact, disappearing. Second, to the conëict studies community, this question is a thrown gauntlet: if we cannot answer this simple question in a compelling manner, how can we hope to explain the causes of war? Finally, answering the question convincingly requires us to understand both the nature of war and how it should be measured. Those issues, I argue, are more complicated than most people realize. In this sketch of a paper, I offer some preliminary thoughts on how to go about answering these questions about the nature of war and its proper measurement. I leave aside for the moment arguments about the changing nature of war, such as Mueller’s contention that most modern wars are policing wars that are prompted by bandits and thugs.2 I also leave aside civil war, which has its own dynamics and merits separate exploration. I focus more narrowly on the argument that the frequency of interstate war, whatever the reason for its employment, has gone down. I highlight a primary, heretofore unaccounted-for driver of changes in warlike behavior, namely, simple geography: as the world has divided itself into smaller, weaker, and more distant political units, fewer and fewer of those units are able (or willing) to reach each other to engage in combat. At the same time, those political units are far more numerous, so the number of opportunities for conëict has increased dramatically. Existing studies of the decline of war have ignored these two trends. I control for them and ênd, on balance, that no net trend toward a decrease in war is evident. If anything, the opposite is true. Chance, Peace, and War <u>The decline-of-war thesis seems implausible</u> on the surface<u>, if for no other reason that <mark>the 20th century was <strong>spectacularly bloody by any standard</u></strong>. <u>The response</mark> </u>of its proponents, essentially, <u>is that</u> one or both of <u>the </u>two <u>World Wars</u> in that century <u>was a fluke</u>—a statistical anomaly. Mueller (2004, 2), for example, calls World War II “a spectacular anachronism, fabricated almost single-handedly by history’s supreme atavism, Adolf Hitler.” Pinker (2011, 208-9) also points to Hitler, as well as to Gavrilo Princip, and argues that each was a necessary condition for his respective war. <u>The primary <mark>evidence for the decline of war is taken to be</mark>, not the “anomalous” World Wars, but <mark>the</u></mark> nearly <u><mark>seventy-year “Long Peace” that followed</u></mark> them.3 <u>There are two problems with <mark>this argument</u></mark>. <u>The first is that it’s often possible to point to one person who</u>, more than others, <u>lit the fuse that led to war: the Napoleonic Wars are called that for a reason.</u> <u><strong>That’s not the same thing as arguing that that individual was both necessary and sufficient for the onset of war—an extremely ambitious claim that is unlikely to withstand scrutiny</u></strong>.4 <u>World War II may have been begun by Hitler</u>, <u>but the ground was made fertile for him by the punitive peace of World War I</u> and <u>the crushing terms of German reparations</u>. <u>The Allies took these steps</u> <u>knowing </u>full well <u>that there was a risk of substantial backlash</u>: although no one could have foreseen Hitler, some hypernationalist response leading to a Great Power war was hardly out of the question. <u>The second, and more serious, problem</u> with the argument <u>is that it <strong><mark>attributes the occurrence of war to chance without exploring the role of chance in the occurrence of peace</mark>.</u></strong> In fact, <u>most scholars see both processes as irreducibly probabilistic</u>. <u><mark>One can cite any number of peaceful periods that could </mark>just as <mark>easily have <strong>exploded into war</u></strong>. <u></mark>During <mark>the Cuban Missile Crisis</u></mark>, for example, <u>the U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates <u>conveyed its intention to use practice depth charges to force Soviet submarines</u> near the quarantine line <u>to surface</u>, <u>but the Soviet Union failed to inform the four Foxtrot-class submarines in the area of that fact</u>. The Soviets, for their part, failed to convey the fact that their submarines were armed with nuclear-tipped torpedoes. <u>On October 27, a trapped Foxtrot submarine</u> <u>very nearly used its nuclear weapon against the American Navy: doing so required consensus among the captain, the second in command, and the political officer, and only one of the three</u>—Vasili Arkhipov—<u>refused to endorse a nuclear response</u> (Roberts, 2012). If we give the role that chance plays the same credit in peace that we give it in war, <u>we can take a rough stab at assessing which of these two events</u>—the two World Wars, or the “long peace” that followed—<u>was more anomalous</u>. <u>If we look at the record of Great Power wars</u> over the past êve centuries (Levy, 1983; Goldstein, 1988, 146), <u>we ênd an average of about two per century prior to the 20th century</u>. <u>Having two such wars in the 20th century, therefore, <strong>is far from anomalous</u></strong>; <u>it’s more or less what we’d expect</u> given what we’ve seen in the past. More surprising, perhaps, is the fact that the seventy years of peace that have passed since the end of World War II are hardly anomalous either. More formally, let’s take the probability of a systemic war breaking out in any given year, based on historical precedent, to be 0.02.5 We can calculate the probability of seeing k “successes” (wars) in n “trials” (years) given an underlying probability of success p by examining the probability mass function of a binomial distribution, P r(X = k) = ( n k ) p k (1 p) (nk) Figure 1 uses this function to compare the probability of observing no wars in the 70 years since World War II with the probabilities of observing one, two, three, or more wars in the same time period, if nothing has changed—that is, if the probability of systemic war has not deviated from its historical average of two per century. As we can see, although the most likely outcome is a single war during that time period, an absence of wars is far from improbable. Figure 2 takes a look at how these same probabilities change over the course of 250 years. As the Figure demonstrates, for nearly 50 years, peace is the most likely outcome. A single war then becomes more likely, but not much more; and at no point are one or two wars all that much more a likely outcome than none at all. These Figures answer our question about the improbability of World Wars I and II, relative to the Long Peace. If there has been no change in the underlying propensity for systemic war over time, the probability of seeing two wars in the 20th century–that is, the probability that two of the 100 one-year periods contained in the century will see the onset of general war—is 27.3%. By contrast, the probability of observing seven continuous decades of peace—zero wars in fourteen êve-year trials, with a probability of “success” of 0.02—is 24.3%. <u><strong><mark>The Long Peace is only slightly less likely to have happened by chance than the two World Wars</u></strong></mark>. How many years of peace would we have to see before we could conclude that the long-term average no longer applies? We can examine the conêdence intervals of the binomial distribution to answer this question. These intervals delimit the plausible values of p, the probability of Great Power war, given n years of peace. As Figure 3 shows, although the range of plausible values narrows quickly for the êrst half-century or so, it would still take about 150 years of uninterrupted peace for us to reject conclusively the hypothesis that the underlying probability of systemic war remains unchanged.6 Now that I’ve addressed a few points about how much we can, or can’t, infer about the long-term probability of systemic war from the World Wars and the Long Peace, I will turn to a thornier issue—the nature of war and its implications for measurement—before addressing the question of whether or not the use of force more generally is in fact in decline. The (Mis)measure of War <u><strong>World War II was the bloodiest conflict in modern human history</u></strong>, and <u>subsequent conflicts have been impressively costly</u>, so on its surface <u><strong>the claim that human violence is on the decline requires qualification</u></strong>. <u><mark>Authors</mark> who make it typically <mark>note that</mark> the number of people available to be killed in war has increased considerably</u>, <u>so <mark>the appropriate metric is</u></mark> not absolute number of war deaths, but rather, <u><mark>war deaths per capita</u></mark>. Pinker (2011, 51), for example, notes that “[t]he number of deaths per 100,000 people per year is the standard measure of homicide rates, and I will use it as the yardstick of violence throughout the book.” <u>Is this a reasonable metric</u> to use when examining the argument that war is disappearing over time? <u><strong>Not really</u></strong>. <u>War deaths per capita accurately reflects the average citizen’s risk from death in war,</u> <u><strong>but <mark>it’s not</mark> immediately <mark>obvious how that quantity is related to </mark>human <mark>war-proneness</u></strong>.7 <u></mark>A decrease in war deaths per capita means that <mark>population is outpacing war deaths</u></mark>—nothing more, nothing less. <u>There may be fewer people exposed to risk of death from war</u>; <u>the individual risk may have decreased due to other factors</u> (<u>combat medicine, for example</u>); <u>and so on.</u> <u>Moreover, <mark>population growth is exponential</u></mark>, <u>and exponential growth defies human imagination</u>: <u>more than 1 in 20 people who have ever lived, from 50,000 B.C. to the present, are alive at this moment</u> (Curtin, 2007). <u><strong><mark>We should hardly be surprised that deaths from war cannot keep up</u></strong></mark>. More generally, we cannot infer any direct relationship between individual-level characteristics and state bellicosity for one simple reason: the logic of individual action in the context of a domestic political hierarchy does not, in any straightforward manner, map to the logic of state action in the context of international anarchy (Waltz, 1959, 1979). As Kant argued in Perpetual Peace, the problem of achieving order can be solved even by a race of intelligent devils; similarly, Jervis (1978) shows that war may occur even between states that desire peace. The behavior of states does not, in any uncomplicated way, reëect the nature of individual humans: to argue that it does is to commit logical as well as ecological fallacies. Therefore, we cannot point to a change in the rate of death from war (or even the number of deaths from war) as evidence that people are becoming more peaceful. How, then, can we understand whether states are becoming more peaceful? In order to understand whether something is changing, we must êrst understand how to measure it; in order to measure it, we must understand what it is. To answer this question, therefore, we need to begin by exploring the fundamental nature of war. What Is War? If our goal is to understand war, we should start with the writings of Carl von Clausewitz (1832/1976). Clausewitz described two different understandings of war— absolute war, which he likened to “a duel on a larger scale” (75), and “real war, or the sort of war that we actually observe, which he described as “a continuation of political intercourse, with the addition of other means.” (605) The distinction is puzzling at êrst, especially given Clausewitz’s claim that absolute wars rarely if ever occur. The logic of Clausewitz’s models of war, and their relationship to one another, have been usefully ëeshed out by modern theorists. First, Fearon (1995) asked the question of why a rational state would êght at all, given the inevitable costs of doing so and the availability of a costless negotiated settlement. In Fearon’s model of warfare, the process that leads to war is a process of negotiation. When actors cannot credibly commit to a settlement or one actor has private information (about its capabilities or resolve, say) and an incentive to misrepresent that information, then war occurs; otherwise, rational actors should be able to reach a negotiated settlement. Wagner (2000) pushes this logic further by arguing that negotiation continues during war—that, in fact, war is a form of costly negotiation, Clausewitz’s “continuation of political intercourse, with the addition of other means.” War begins due to a lack of information, and êghting reveals the information needed to arrive at a settlement. In a simple example, a state with an incentive to bluff, or pretend to be stronger than it is, will soon have its weakness revealed on the battleêeld and be forced to accept a settlement that reëects its weakness. Wagner also addresses the question of how Clausewitz’s “real war” is related to “absolute war.” Absolute war comprises a process, not of êghting to reveal information, but of êghting to defeat the opponent’s military and hold its civilian population hostage.8 The outcome of absolute war, war to the bitter end, is the hypothetical about which real war provides information. In order for absolute war to play that role, though, there must be some chance that it will be realized—that is, some possibility that war will change relative capabilities more rapidly, or more effectively, than it provides information about them. This intuition is captured well by Smith and Stam (2004), who describe a bargaining game in which states êght in order to conquer “forts” (analogous to territory or strategic assets). If one side captures all of the assets, the other is left defenseless and must yield. The act of êghting over such assets both tilts the balance this way and that and, in the process, gives the players more information about their relative capabilities. A settlement can occur either as the result of increased information or as a result of military defeat. From this perspective, decision makers terminate wars when their estimates of one another’s capabilities converge.9 Those estimates are inëuenced by the efficacy of their military forces: a side that loses êve, ten, or êfteen battles in a row should begin to suspect that it has made a mistake. Implications What empirical implications can we glean from this account of war that can help us to answer the question of whether war is on the decline? First, information, not attrition, is the goal of conflict. This fact drives a stake into the heart of the wardeaths-per-capita metric, since there is no direct or obvious connection between changes in estimates of relative capabilities and size of total population. Decision makers glean information as a result of the outcome of a series of battles; their relative losses influence those estimates. Although an informative loss might be more costly in modern warfare than it was 200 years ago, that change is likely due to changes in technology, not to changes in the size of the civilian population. Simply put, the outcomes of ten tank battles are probably costlier than the outcomes of ten equally informative cavalry battles; but either should be as informative to the leader of a country of a million as it is to the leader of a country of ten million. Second, conflict initiation, and even the “bargaining” that might lead to initiation, is a gamble. Leaders cannot know whether their opponents will fold or stand firm until they do one or the other. If they stand êrm, leaders cannot know whether their divergent beliefs will be resolved by the outcome of a few skirmishes, a weekslong conëict, or a major war. As Pinker (2011, 192) himself puts it, “When the iron dice begin to roll (as the German chancellor Theobald von Bethmann-Hollweg put it on the eve of World War I), the unlucky outcomes can be far worse than our primitive imaginations foresee.” Indeed, Tuchman (1962, ch. 9) documents the fact that political elites in the capitols of the Great Powers believed nearly unanimously that the conëict begun in 1914 would last no more than a few weeks, or possibly a couple of months at the outside. This fact, too, undercuts the war-deaths-per-capita metric: if the scale of a war is uncontrollable, except by surrender, and therefore unknowable a priori, it cannot reëect the magnitude of the human propensity for violence that led to war. When the first bullets fly, no decision maker can know how many people will die; so their intent cannot be measured by the number of people who actually do die, whether a thousand or a million. The only reasonable metric is the willingness to “roll the dice” in the first place. These two conclusions help us to resolve the dilemma that Pinker (2011, 210) outlines: “[W]arlike” can refer to two different things. It can refer to how likely people are to go to war, or it can refer to how many people are killed when they do. Imagine two rural counties with the same size population. One of them has a hundred teenage arsonists who delight in setting forest êres. But the forests are in isolated patches, so each êre dies out before doing much damage. The other county has just two arsonists, but its forests are connected, so that a small blaze is likely to spread, as they say, like wildêre. Which county has the worse forest êre problem? One could argue it either way. As far as the amount of reckless depravity is concerned, the êrst county is worse; as far as the risk of serious damage is concerned, the second is. Given the fact that that states êght in order to gain information, not to produce attrition of one another’s general populations, and given that the intentions of leaders who risk war cannot be inferred from the magnitude of the war that results, we are in a situation in which, to continue Pinker’s analogy, when forests are randomly distributed in each village and the arsonists set êres without knowing how far they will spread, the village with more arsonists is the village with the worse problem. Accordingly, <u><mark>the best way to gauge</mark> the <mark>warlikeness</mark> of nations</u> <u><strong><mark>would be to measure the frequency with which they run the risk of war</u></strong></mark>. <u>Initiating a war, or issuing a threat</u> <u>that creates the risk of war</u>, <u>is indicative of the willingness</u>, <u>in the worst case, to spill quite a bit of blood</u>; <u>that willingness is the best indicator of the propensity of the state to engage in violent conflict</u>; and the individual conëict incident, or militarized dispute, is the most reliable objective indicator of that willingness.10 War and Numbers The preceding discussion leads to the conclusion that <u>trends in conflicts</u> of any kind <u>are</u> probably <u>the most reliable indicator of the propensity of states to fight wars</u>. The question then becomes, what can we discern from trends in conëict? At first glance, trends in conëict would seem to support the disappearance-ofwar thesis. In his Figure 5.17, reproduced here as Figure 4, Pinker (2011, 222-231) uses data on the number of conëicts per year from Peter Brecke’s “conëict catalog”11 to demonstrate that war among European powers is on the decline. An earlier Figure (5.13, not presented here) does the same for Great Power wars. Nevertheless, <u><strong><mark>Pinker offers little justifcation for examining only Great Powers and European states</u></strong></mark>, <u>save that they “offer a circumscribed but consequential theater in which we can look at historical trends in war.”</u> <u>None of the proponents of the decline-in-warfare thesis suggests that it should be an exclusively European or Great-Power phenomenon</u>. <u><strong>Indeed, quite the opposite</u></strong>. Pinker (2011, ch. 4, esp. at 134) explicitly makes reference to his “humanitarian revolution” as a worldwide phenomenon, while Mueller (2004), who largely focuses on war between developed states, explicitly (6; 83) notes that the same trends are evident in less-developed parts of the world. To begin, then, <u>we should examine Brecke’s data in order to see what the the long-term trends in warfare look like in the international system as a whole</u>. To do so, <u>we need look no farther than the working paper that Pinker cites</u> (Brecke, 1999), which does just this. <u>Brecke’s graph of trends</u> in the international system— reproduced here as Figure 5—<u><strong>suggest that <mark>conflict in the last two centuries has been more prevalent than ever before</u></strong>.</mark> More <u>fine-grained <mark>data from the </mark>industry-standard <mark>Correlates of War</mark> Militarized Interstate Dispute</u> (MID) <u>dataset <strong><mark>lead us to a similar conclusion</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>MARKED</p><p> In Figure 6, I calculate the number of uses of force12 per year and graph them against time. Given the volatility of the series, I also add a lowess line through the center of the data to capture the central tendency of the data. The result is precisely the opposite of what one would expect if war were on the decline: uses of force held more or less steady through the êrst World War but then increased steadily thereafter. The problem with this graph, and the previous ones, is straightforward: no correction is made for the number of interaction opportunities in the international system. Especially during the êrst two thirds of the twentieth century, the number of independent states in the system grew dramatically, and the number of opportunities for conëict rose accordingly: in a world of two states, only one pair of states can go to war; in a world of four states, there are six possible axes of conëict; and so on. To correct for this issue, in Figure 7 I divide the number of uses of force in a given year by the number of pairs of states (or dyads) present in the international system. In this graph, we can see precisely the sort of relationship that we would expect to see if war were dwindling: a steady decline through both centuries, interrupted by brief surges around the time of the two World Wars.13 Although Figure 7 would seem to be an improvement on Figure 6, it is not without its own problems. Counting every pair of states in the international system as a potential conëict dyad is ambitious, to say the least. The overwhelming majority of the states in the international system lack the ability to project power beyond their own region, at best; most, in the absence of outside assistance, are limited to conëict with their neighbors. Moreover, the scope of states’ political interests tends roughly to correspond to the scope of their inëuence. A clash between Bolivia and Botswana is highly unlikely, both because they are distant and weak and because the politics of each is largely irrelevant to the other. In short, as Maoz and Russett (1993) memorably put it, <u>many states in the international system are not “politically relevant” to one another: conflict between them is unlikely for purely geographic reasons, and we should account for that fact when attempting to draw inferences about the onset of war and its causes. </u>Unfortunately, <u>as of this writing there is little consensus in the literature regarding how exactly to measure</u>, or control for, <u>political relevance</u> (Braumoeller and Carson, 2011, 292-293). <u>The simplest rule to apply is contiguity: Only neighboring pairs of states, or states separated by less than 150 miles of water, are treated as potential combatants</u>. If we apply this rule and reexamine the use of force over time (Figure 8), <u><strong>the downward trend has clearly reversed itself:</u></strong> though there is a fair bit of noise, <u><strong><mark>the overall trend is</mark> slightly <mark>upward</mark> and has held steady at a higher rate during the Cold War than in previous periods. </u></strong>Clearly, assuming that conëict can only occur between neighboring states is overcompensating for political relevance. <u>Even if we add another condition—that any dyad containing a Great Power is politically relevant—we still find that around a quarter of all militarized disputes in the postwar period occurred between “politically irrelevant” states</u>. Other assumptions—including pairs of states that are separated by up to 400 miles, for example—do not solve the problem, though they do reduce the percentage of excluded disputes by a bit (Benson, 2005, 115-116). At this point, we face a serious dilemma. Controlling for the number of pairs of states in the international system tentatively suggests that war is indeed on the decline, but controlling for the number of contiguous states leads to the opposite conclusion. Neither answer is satisfactory, because neither controls for the correct number of states. What we need is a theoretically motivated measure of political relevance that allows for shades of grey—that is, for situations in which distance and weakness renders conëict improbable, not impossible. In the next section, I describe a statistical model of the use of force that allows me to estimate, empirically, the political relevance of any pair of states in the international system. The measure is not perfect, but I argue that it represents the state of the art at present. I also include in the model two sets of variables designed to allow me to capture the main arguments implicated in the decline-of-war literature—the humanitarian revolution, and the trend toward better and more coherent governance—so that I can examine the contribution of each to changes, if any, in the average propensity of states to êght over time. Modeling War and Peace My main goal in constructing a statistical model of war and peace is to generate an estimate of political relevance that I can then use to construct a reasonable metric of the warlikeness of states—conëict incidents per politically relevant dyad. That, in turn, will help us to answer the question of whether international war is disappearing. As a side beneêt, we can use the statistical model to measure the contributions of a variety of factors to the probability of conëict initiation. To preview, the model will have three main components. The êrst will be a model of the warlikeness of states—that is, their general propensity to use force to settle disputes. The theoretical model of war outlined above gives us some general expectations about the sorts of situations in which we should expect to see states resort to violence—namely, those in which there is a fair bit of uncertainty about relative capabilities and, therefore, about the outcome. If the decline-of-war theorists are correct, we should ênd that the propensity to êght based on such calculations is in decline. More than that, however: We should ênd that the propensity to use force to settle disputes is in decline even when controlling for other factors that are known to blunt it. Two of these—regime type and political irrelevance—are the second and third components of the model. Democratic political regimes are known to be peaceful in their dealings with one another; their inëuence should be controlled for because both Pinker and Mueller point to a change in ideas, not institutions, as the source of paciêcation. Political irrelevance—greater distances between weaker states—makes war less possible, not less desirable: its effects are not unlike those of putting bellicose siblings in different rooms for a “time out.” Distance decreases the opportunity to êght, whether or not states are willing to do so. If the decline-of-war theorists are correct and humans desire less conëict than they had in previous decades, warlikeness should decrease even when distance is controlled for. Warlikeness The êrst thing that we need is a measure of warlikeness, or the conëict propensity of states. The most obvious culprit, given the theoretical explanation of war that we use above, is uncertainty. The bargaining model of war described above leads us to expect that war will be more likely when states are more uncertain about the balance of power. Regardless of the issue at stake, uncertainty can cause a challenger to the status quo to demand too much, or cause a defender to underestimate the challenger’s willingness to êght. As uncertainty increases, so does the potential for misunderstandings like these to lead to war. Unfortunately, there is no good measure of the uncertainty in states’ calculations about one another’s capabilities. However, as intuition suggests (and Reed (2003) demonstrates), uncertainty is highest when states’ capabilities are relatively evenly matched. When capabilities are mismatched, by contrast, the likely outcome of a conëict is clear enough to forestall it. Therefore, we can use the difference in capabilities of states as a proxy for the propensity of states to engage in conëict as a result of uncertainty about the likely outcome of that conëict. The advantages of this model of warlikeness are twofold: it follows cleanly from the bargaining model of war described above, and the logic applies to any impetus toward conëict—territorial issues, ideology, hegemony, or what have you. H1a: Uncertainty, as captured by similarity of capabilities, increases the propensity of states to engage in conëict. Using this baseline model of warlikeness, we can ascertain both whether increased uncertainty leads to an increase in the propensity to use force and whether that propensity has become less prevalent over time. What we can’t do is ascertain whether, as decline-of-war theorists argue, the propensity to êght has declined over time despite unchanging levels of uncertainty. To do that, we need to include a second variable: Time. H1b: Over time, the propensity of states to initiate conëict has declined. Including time in the equation ensures that we can capture secular declines in warlikeness over time, for whatever reason. Any variable implicated in the decline-ofwar literature must, of necessity, be highly correlated with the passage of time. Time is, therefore, a useful proxy, even if it fails to capture the precise quantity of interest.14 Governance, Good and Bad These hypotheses are subject to a caveat. Over the last three decades, scholars have arrived at a near-consensus that relations among democratic states are largely if not entirely exempt from the pressures that lead most states to war (Doyle, 1983a,b; Russett, 1993). While these êndings do suggest that the impetus to go to war has been substantially reduced in the case of a subset of states, they cannot speak to the overall proclivity of states to êght: if democracies are substantially more likely to êght nondemocracies than nondemocracies are to êght one another, the systemic implication of low-to-intermediate levels of democratization might be more war, not less. Nevertheless, among democracies the relationship between uncertainty and war should be substantially mitigated. H2a: Joint democracy decreases the impact of the similarity of capabilities on the probability of conëict. Along the same lines, Mueller (2004), who argues that democracy is more likely to be a result of peace than the cause of it (2, 167-169), suggests that “capable government…is ultimately the most promising method for the long-term control, and even potentially for the eradication, of most of the remnants of war.” (3) This is so because of the decrease it produces in organized criminality, which Mueller sees as a primary source of the “policing wars” that dominate organized international uses of force today. H2b: Capable governance decreases the impact of the similarity of capabilities on the probability of conëict. Political Relevance Finally, these generalizations only hold among states that are politically relevant to one another: in the Botswana-Bolivia dyad, for example, relative capabilities and regime type are largely immaterial. We therefore need to specify a ênal condition: H3: Political irrelevance decreases the impact of the similarity of capabilities and of regime type on the probability of conëict. Measurement To test these hypotheses, I utilize a range of variables from the Correlates of War Militarized Interstate Dispute (MID) project,15 aggregated by EUGene (Bennett and Stam, 2000), as well as more up-to-date data from the Polity project. To measure the difference in capabilities between state i and state j, I begin with the standard Correlates of War capabilities measure, cap, and create the index Capability Difference = jcapi capjj capi + capj (1) For time, I measure the number of years since 1815. For regime type, I use the standard Polity measures of democracy (i.e., democracy-anocracy) for states i and j, as well as their product. In addition, I create a new variable, Anocracyi or j, that equals one if the democracy score of either state lies between 3 and -3 and zero otherwise. This variable captures the argument that poor governance, rather than governance of a particular sort, creates an impetus to war. To capture the concept of political relevance, I include three variables: the Correlates of War capability score of the strongest state; the log of the inter-capital distance between states i and j; and a dummy variable indicating whether the dyad contains at least one major power, as deêned by the COW project. Analysis Given the fundamentally interactive nature of the hypotheses—political relevance and regime type moderate the impact of uncertainty on the use of force—I utilize Boolean logit (Braumoeller, 2003) to test the hypotheses. In a nutshell, in contrast to standard logit analysis, in which Pr(y = 1) = (X ); (2) Boolean logit posits the existence of three latent dependent variables—y u , or the dyad’s propensity to use force; y r , the pacifying effects of regime type; and y pr, the degree to which political relevance permits states to use force in the êrst place. It then assigns separate vectors of independent variables to each latent dependent variable: Pr(y u = 1) = (X ) (3) Pr(y r = 1) = (Z ) (4) Pr(y pr = 1) = (W ) (5) Finally, it speciêes the interactive manner in which the combination of latent dependent variables contributes to the observed dependent variable, the use of force: Pr(y = 1) = Pr(y u = 1) Pr(y r = 1) Pr(y pr = 1) (6) In this case, because the theory speciêes a conjunctural relationship among the latent variables, the result resembles a standard multiplicative interaction, except that vectors of independent variables rather than individual variables are interacting with one another. The technique has two advantages from the point of view of this study. First, we can use it to create predictions, or estimates, of the unmeasured latent dependent variables. In particular, we can simply compute (W ) in order to produce a continuous metric of political relevance—a function of distance, capabilities, and Great Power status that is bounded at 0 and 1. This variable will provide a much richer and more nuanced measure of political relevance than simple measures of contiguity.Put another way: Most measures of political relevance assume a strict relationship between Great Power status and/or contiguity, on the one hand, and political relevance, on the other. Rather than assuming such a relationship, this technique allows us to estimate it. The second advantage is that we can use the results to capture three distinct quantities that reëect conëict propensity, regime type, and political relevance, and chart those separate quantities over time. To do so, we average the value of the latent dependent variable across all units in the system in each year. Changes in those averages over time are indicative of how much or how little the propensity for conëict and the pacifying effects of regime type and political irrelevance have changed across the system over time. Table 1 contains the results of the Boolean logit analysis.16 As anticipated, simi- larity of capabilities—our indicator of uncertainty—increases the probability of conëict, as does the absence of coherent government on the part of at least one of the states in the dyad, while joint democracy decreases it. As one might anticipate, political relevance increases with the capabilities of the strongest actor and with the presence of a major power in the dyad, and decreases with distance. Most surprising, though, is the coefficient on the time variable, which reëects a modest but signiêcant increase in the propensity to êght over time. These results allow us to break apart the different components of conëict initiation to see whether, on average, any of them has declined over time. Figure 9 does exactly this by charting the mean within-sample predicted value for each of the y over time. While there is little change in the pacifying effects of regime type,17 there is a signiêcant increase over time in warlikeness, or the propensity to use force to resolve disputes. This propensity dips a bit during the long and relatively peaceful 19th century, but it increases steadily through the 20th. At the same time, we can see a clear and dramatic decrease in average political relevance across the entire period, as the world is increasingly divided up into states that are smaller, weaker, and farther apart. Discussion The goal of the above analysis was to separate three trends over time: the propensity to initiate conëict in situations of uncertainty, as the bargaining model of war suggests states will do; the pacifying effects of political regime type; and the pseudo-pacifying effects of the trend toward smaller, weaker, and more distant states. Having done so, <u>we are faced with a surprisingly stark result</u>: <u><strong>not only does the inclination to fight not decrease, it actually increases,</u></strong> slowly but steadily. <u>What does decrease</u>, quite dramatically, <u>is the ability of potential combatants to reach each other. </u>No model of conflict initiation is perfect, of course, and this one is surely far from it: the macro-level variables make inference particularly challenging. Even so, <u><strong>the <mark>trends are far from what one would expect if the decline-of-war thesis could hold water</mark>. </strong>More important, the model gives us an important metric</u>—<u>a measure of political relevance—that we can use to draw conclusions about the raw data</u>. Recall that, in Figure 8, we looked at uses of force per politically relevant dyad, but the measure of political relevance that we used was a very imperfect one. A much improved measure of political relevance can be had by calculating the predicted value of y pr using the above variables W and coefficients . As a quick check of surface validity, I plot political relevance from the perspective of four countries—the United States, the United Kingdom, Egypt, and Chile—in the year 1993 in Figure 10. The plots correspond roughly to intuition: to the United States, most of the world is mostly relevant, with only the most distant parts slightly less so, while the United Kingdom displays a more regional pattern. Egypt’s politically relevant neighborhood is more constrained still, extending through much of the Middle East and including the more powerful states of Europe, while Chile primarily sees neighbors and Great Powers as its politically relevant cohort. There is room to quibble, of course, but the results represent a considerable improvement over the standard way of doing things, which suggests that all states are equally relevant to Great Powers and non-Great Powers are only relevant to their neighbors. With this more nuanced measure of political relevance, we can get a much better sense of trends in the use of force controlling for capabilities and distance. I turn to this task in the next section. War and Political Relevance The final step in this exercise is to measure the frequency of conëict initiation controlling for the political relevance of dyads. Our measure of conëicts per dyad was simply the number of uses of force in a given year, divided by the number of extant dyads in that year. Conëicts per contiguous dyad was equal to the number of uses of force divided by the number of contiguous (directly or within 150 miles by water) dyads. In order to create a measure of systemic warlikeness, I divide the number of uses of force in the system in a given year by the sum of the political-relevance scores for all dyads in the system. This measure assumes, êrst, that the political-relevance measure is reasonably accurate, and second, that we should on average expect half as many conëicts from a dyad with a political relevance score of 0.5 as we would expect from a dyad with a political relevance score of 1. Given that the estimator that was used to derive the measure incorporates exactly this assumption, it would seem not to be too unrealistic. Figure 11 illustrates the result—the ênal overall metric of warlikeness from 1816– 2001. <u>Although the period from the 1960s to the present does exhibit a decline in conflict</u>, <u>the drop is fairly modest</u>, <u>and the result is a rate of conflict not too different from the average across the past two centuries</u>. <u><strong><mark>There is certainly no suggestion of a</mark> general <mark>downward trend in rates of conflict initiation</u></strong></mark>; <u>a more reasonable characterization would be a cyclical alternation of more-warlike</u> (1850s, 1910s, 1940-90) <u>and less-warlike periods.</u> Of course, <u>that’s not to say that an upswing will inevitably follow the current lull: indeed, the general trend more closely resembles a random walk than a steady decline</u>. We might be tempted to derive meaning from the postCold War cluster of lower-conëict years, and in time we may conclude that they’re more than a ëuke; but as Pinker himself puts it, “events that occur at random seem to come in clusters, because it would take a nonrandom process to space them out.” (Pinker, 2011, 203) Conclusion In this paper, I set out to explore the claim that there has been an overall decline in the propensity of states to use violence against one another in international relations. I’ve argued that <u><strong>per-capita deaths from war is a misleading and irrelevant statistic to use in answering this question</u></strong>, <u>because it has no foundation in a coherent account of how wars actually happen</u>. <u>I argue instead that we should be examining uses of force that have the potential to become wars</u>, <u>because such actions are indicative of a willingness to use considerable violence even if that willingness is not realized. An initial glance</u> at uses of force per year <u><strong>suggested that <mark>the propensity to use force is going up</mark> rather than down</u></strong>. <u>This trend is plausibly an artifact of the division of the world into a larger number of political units</u> with a larger number of conëict opportunities. <u>At the same time, those units are on average smaller, weaker, and more distant</u>. <u><mark>I</mark> therefore <mark>examine a new metric—uses of force per relevant dyad— that controls for both trends simultaneously</mark>. <strong><mark>The results bear little resemblance to a decline in violence over time</strong></mark>. A more reasonable characterization might be a semi-random oscillation</u>, with more and less conëictual periods alternating across irregular periods. A <u><strong>pattern of that nature offers little basis to conclude that war is on the decline</u></strong>—<u><strong>or </u></strong>indeed, <u><strong>to conclude much of anything at all about its likely future direction</u></strong>.</p>
2NC
K
A2: getting better
204,417
7
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,941
Voter for fairness and education
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Voter for fairness and education</h4>
1NC
null
Off
430,053
1
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,942
The medicalized order by which the sovereign controls the process of both living and dying rests on the anxiety of life-preserving communities to define themselves in opposition to whatever threatens vitality - This increasing sovereign power over death founded in community leads to the ultimate exclusion –creates a state of exception in which life is entirely controlled by the state, rendering life bare and providing the foundation for mobilization of war – that’s Bayatrizi
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The medicalized order by which the sovereign controls the process of both living and dying rests on the anxiety of life-preserving communities to define themselves in opposition to whatever threatens vitality - This increasing sovereign power over death founded in community leads to the ultimate exclusion –creates a state of exception in which life is entirely controlled by the state, rendering life bare and providing the foundation for mobilization of war – that’s Bayatrizi</h4>
Case
null
null
430,054
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,943
“Health” comes to mean the absence of death, that specter which haunts the terrain of the medical, to be banished in every instance – this banishment of death is thus the precondition for political intelligibility and personhood
null
Illich 94
Physicians in the Hippocratic tradition were pledged to restore health but forbidden to use their skills to deal with death. They had to accept nature's power to dissolve the healing contract between the patient and his physician.¶ coming alive in the womb and the personal struggle to die defined the extreme boundaries between which a subject of medical care could be conceived.¶ Physicians are taught to consider themselves responsible for lives from the moment the egg is fertilized through the time of organ harvest. They have become the socially responsible professional manager not of a patient, but of a life Physicians have become the bureaucrats of the brave new biocracy that rules from womb to tomb. bio-ethics has sought to create the semblance of a moral discourse that roots personhood in the "scientific ability" of bioethicists to determine who is a person and who is not through qualitative evaluation of "a life." "A life" is amenable to management, to improvement and to evaluation in a way which is unthinkable when we speak of "a person." The transmogrification of a person into "a life" is a lethal operation The Christian West has given birth to a radically other kind of human condition within the "technological system" A new role opens for mythmaking, moralizing, legitimating institutions We seem to need a Linus blanket, some prestigious fetish that we can drag around to feel like defenders of sacred values. "Life" has become this blanket: it has come to constitute an essential referent in current ecological, medical, legal, political and ethical discourse. life as a property, as a value, a national resource, a right, is a Western notion which shares its Christian ancestry with other key verities defining secular society. The notion of a human life as a distinct entity which can be professionally and legally protected has been torturously constructed through a legal-medical-religious-scientific discourse The concept of life does not exist in Greco-Roman antiquity: bios means the course of a destiny and zoe something close to the brilliance of aliveness. In Hebrew, the concept is utterly theocentric, an implication of God's breath.¶ "What is life?" is not a perennial question, but the pop-science counterfoil to scientific research reports on reproduction, physiology, heredity, organization, evolution and morphogenesis With the scientific revolution a mechanistic model comes to dominate perception it raised the nagging question: How to explain the existence of living forms in a dead cosmos? The notion of substantive life thus appears as a kind of mindless shibboleth to fill a void.¶ For over a century now it has become customary to speak about the "conservation of life" as the ultimate motive of human action and social organization. bioethicists they demand that we recognize that there is a deep difference between having a life and merely being alive. The proven ability to exercise this act of possession or appropriation is turned into the criterion for personhood and for the existence of a legal subject.¶
Physicians in the Hippocratic tradition were forbidden to use their skills to deal with death Physicians are taught to consider themselves responsible for lives from the moment the egg is fertilized through the time of organ harvest not a patient, but a life Physicians have become the bureaucrats of the brave new biocracy that rules from womb to tomb. bio-ethics roots personhood in the "scientific ability" to determine who is a person and who is not through qualitative evaluation of "a life." "A life" is amenable to management improvement evaluation The transmogrification of a person into "a life" is a lethal operation We seem to need a Linus blanket we can drag around to feel like defenders of sacred values. "Life" has become this blanket: an essential referent in current ecological, medical, legal, political and ethical discourse. life as a property a value, a national resource, a right, is a Western notion been torturously constructed through a legal-medical-religious-scientific discourse a mechanistic model comes to dominate perception it raised the nagging question: How to explain the existence of living forms in a dead cosmos? The notion of substantive life thus appears as a mindless shibboleth to fill a void it has become customary to speak about the "conservation of life" as the ultimate motive of human action and social organization. there is a deep difference between having a life and merely being alive ability to exercise this act of possession or appropriation is turned into the criterion for personhood and for the existence of a legal subject
Ivan, Ph.D from the University of Salzburg, “BRAVE NEW BIOCRACY: HEALTH CARE FROM WOMB TO TOMB,” New Perspectives Quarterly, Winter 1994, Vol. 11, Issue 1, http://brandon.multics.org/library/Ivan%20Illich/against_life.html SJE Physicians in the Hippocratic tradition were pledged to restore the balance -- or "health" -- of their patient's constitution but forbidden to use their skills to deal with death. They had to accept nature's power to dissolve the healing contract between the patient and his physician.¶ When the Hippocratic signs indicated to the physician that the patient had entered into agony, the "atrium between life and death," he had to withdraw from what was now a deathbed. Both quickening -- coming alive in the womb -- and agony -- the personal struggle to die -- defined the extreme boundaries between which a subject of medical care could be conceived.¶ In our world, these boundaries have been obliterated. By the early 20th century, the physician came to be perceived as society's appointed tutor of any person who, having been placed in a patient role, lost his own competence.¶ Physicians are taught today to consider themselves responsible for lives from the moment the egg is fertilized through the time of organ harvest. They have become the socially responsible professional manager not of a patient, but of a life from sperm to worm. Physicians have become the bureaucrats of the brave new biocracy that rules from womb to tomb. In societies confused by the technological prowess that enables us to transgress all traditional boundaries of coming to life and dying, the new discipline of bio-ethics has emerged to mediate between pop-science and law. It has sought to create the semblance of a moral discourse that roots personhood in the "scientific ability" of bioethicists to determine who is a person and who is not through qualitative evaluation of the fetish, "a life."¶ What I fear is that the abstract, secular notion of "a life" will be sacralized, thereby making it possible that this spectral entity will progressively replace the notion of a "person" in which the humanism of Western individualism is anchored. "A life" is amenable to management, to improvement and to evaluation in a way which is unthinkable when we speak of "a person." The transmogrification of a person into "a life" is a lethal operation, as dangerous as reaching out for the tree of life in the time of Adam and Eve.¶ The churches -- one of the most important agencies for defining moral issues in public life -- bear a particular responsibility as a lost civilization turns to them for guidance on such issues as abortion, euthanasia, organ transplants, embryo cloning and eugenics.¶ "A life" is the most powerful idol the church has had to face in the course of its history. More than the ideology of empire or feudal order, more than nationalism or progress, more than gnosticism or Enlightenment, the acceptance of "life" as a God given reality lends itself to a new corruption of the Christian faith.¶ The Christian West has given birth to a radically other kind of human condition unlike anything before it. Only within the matrix which Jacques Ellul calls the "technological system" has this new type of human condition come to full fruition. A new role opens for mythmaking, moralizing, legitimating institutions, a role which cannot quite be understood in terms of old religions, but which some churches rush in to fill.¶ The new technological society is singularly incapable of generating myths to which people can form deep and rich attachments. Yet, for its rudimentary maintenance it needs agencies which create and legitimate fetishes to which epistemic sentimentality can attach itself.¶ We seem to need a Linus blanket, some prestigious fetish that we can drag around to feel like defenders of sacred values. "Life" has become this blanket: it has come to constitute an essential referent in current ecological, medical, legal, political and ethical discourse. Consistently, those who use it forget that the notion has a history. It is a Western notion, ultimately the result of a perversion of the Christian message.¶ When the Lord announced to Martha "I am Life," he did not say "I am a Life." He says "I am Life" tout court. This Life has its historical roots in the revelation that one human person, Jesus, is also God. This one Life is the substance of Martha's faith. In the Christian tradition, we hope to receive this Life as a gift; and we hope to share it. We know that this Life was given to us on the Cross and we cannot seek it except on the via crucis.¶ This Life is gratuitous, beyond and above having been born and living. But, as Augustine and Luther constantly stress, it is a gift without which being alive would be dust.¶ Life in the Christian tradition is personal to the point of being one person, both revealed and promised in John 19. It is something profoundly other than the life which appears as substantive in all the headlines about abortion or euthanasia in American newspapers.¶ At first sight, the two have nothing in common. On the one side, the Bible says: Emmanuel, Godman, Incarnation. On the other, the term is used to impute substance to a process for which the physician assumes responsibility, which technologies prolong and atomic armaments protect; a substance which has standing in court, can be wrongfully given, and about whose destruction without due process or beyond the needs of national defense or industrial growth the so-called pro-life organizations are incensed.¶ However, at closer inspection, life as a property, as a value, a national resource, a right, is a Western notion which shares its Christian ancestry with other key verities defining secular society. The notion of a human life as a distinct entity which can be professionally and legally protected has been torturously constructed through a legal-medical-religious-scientific discourse whose roots go far back into theology.¶ The emotional and conceptual connotations of life in Hindu, Buddhist or Islamic traditions are utterly distinct from those evident in the current debate on this subject in Western democracies.¶ In the United States, the politicized pro-life movements are sponsored mainly by Christian denominations.¶ It is for this reason that it is mainly up to the churches to de-mystify "life." The Christian churches now face an ugly temptation: to cooperate in the social creation of a fetish which, in a theological perspective, is the perversion of revealed Life into an idol.¶ The History of a Life¶ Biblical scholars are well aware of the limited correspondence between the Hebrew word for blood, dam, for breath, ruah, and the Greek term we would render as soul, namely, psyche. Neither comes anywhere near the meaning of the substantive, life. The concept of life does not exist in Greco-Roman antiquity: bios means the course of a destiny and zoe something close to the brilliance of aliveness. In Hebrew, the concept is utterly theocentric, an implication of God's breath.¶ Life as a substantive notion appears two thousand years later, along with the science that purports to study it. The term biology was coined early in the 19th century by Jean-Baptiste Lamarck. He was reacting to the baroque progress in botany and zoology which tended to reduce these two disciplines to the status of mere classification. By inventing a new term, he also named a new field of study, "the science of life."¶ Lamarck's genius confronted the tradition of distinct vegetable and animal ensoulment, along with the consequent division of nature into three kingdoms: mineral, vegetable and animal. He postulated the existence of life that distinguishes living beings from inorganic matter not by visible structure but by organization. Since Lamarck, biology searches for the "stimulating cause of organization" and its localization in tissue cells, protoplasm, the genetic code or morphogenetic fields.¶ "What is life?" is, therefore, not a perennial question, but the pop-science counterfoil to scientific research reports on a mixed bag of phenomena such as reproduction, physiology, heredity, organization, evolution and, more recently, feedback and morphogenesis.¶ Life appears during the Napoleonic wars as a postulate which is meant to lead the new biologists beyond the competing descriptive studies of mechanists, vitalists and materialists. Then, as morphological, physiological and genetic studies became more precise toward the middle of the 19th century, life and its evolution become the hazy and unintended by-products reflecting in ordinary discourse an increasingly abstract and formal kind of scientific terminology.¶ THE DEATH OF NATURE | A thread which runs back to Anaxagoras (500-428BC) links a number of otherwise profoundly distinct philosophical systems: the theme of nature's aliveness. This idea of nature's sensitive responsiveness found its constant expression well into the 16th century in animistic and idealistic, gnostic and hylomorphic versions. In these variations, nature is experienced as the matrix from which all things are born. In the long period between Augustine and Scotus this birthing power of nature was rooted in the world's being contingent on the incessant creative will of God.¶ By the 13th century, and especially in the Franciscan school of theology, the world's being is seen as contingent not merely on God's creation, but also on the graceful sharing of his own being, his life. Whatever is brought from possibility (de potentia) into the necessity of its own existence thrives by its miraculous sharing of God's own intimacy, for which there is no better word than -- His life.¶ With the scientific revolution, contingency-rooted thought fades and a mechanistic model comes to dominate perception. Caroline Merchant argues that the resulting "death of nature" has been the most far-reaching event in changing men's vision and perception of the universe. But it also raised the nagging question: How to explain the existence of living forms in a dead cosmos? The notion of substantive life thus appears not as a direct answer to this question, but as a kind of mindless shibboleth to fill a void.¶ LIFE AS PROPERTY | The ideology of possessive individualism progressively affected the way life could be talked about as a property. Since the 19th century, the legal construction of society increasingly reflects a new philosophical radicalism in the perception of the self. The result is a break with the ethics which had informed western history since Greek antiquity, clearly expressed by the shift of concern from the good to values. Society is now organized on the utilitarian assumption that man is born needy, and needed values are by definition scarce. It becomes axiomatic that the possession of life is then interpreted as the supreme value. Homo economicus becomes the referent for ethical reflection. Living is equated with a struggle for survival or, more radically, with a competition for life. For over a century now it has become customary to speak about the "conservation of life" as the ultimate motive of human action and social organization. Today, some bioethicists go even further. While up to now the law implied that a person was alive, they demand that we recognize that there is a deep difference between having a life and merely being alive. The proven ability to exercise this act of possession or appropriation is turned into the criterion for personhood and for the existence of a legal subject.¶ During this same period, homo economicus was surreptitiously taken as the emblem and analogue for all living beings. A mechanistic anthropomorphism has gained currency. Bacteria are imagined to mimic "economic" behavior and to engage in internecine competition for the scarce oxygen available in their environment. A cosmic struggle among ever more complex forms of life has become the anthropic foundational myth of the scientific age.¶
11,975
<h4><strong>“Health” comes to mean the absence of death, that specter which haunts the terrain of the medical, to be banished in every instance – this banishment of death is thus the precondition for political intelligibility and personhood</h4><p></strong>Illich 94</p><p>Ivan, Ph.D from the University of Salzburg, “BRAVE NEW BIOCRACY: HEALTH CARE FROM WOMB TO TOMB,” New Perspectives Quarterly, Winter 1994, Vol. 11, Issue 1, http://brandon.multics.org/library/Ivan%20Illich/against_life.html SJE</p><p><u><strong><mark>Physicians in the Hippocratic tradition were</mark> pledged to restore</u></strong> the balance -- or "<u><strong>health</u></strong>" -- of their patient's constitution <u><strong>but <mark>forbidden to use their skills to deal with death</mark>. They had to accept nature's power to dissolve the healing contract between the patient and his physician.¶</u></strong> When the Hippocratic signs indicated to the physician that the patient had entered into agony, the "atrium between life and death," he had to withdraw from what was now a deathbed. Both quickening -- <u><strong>coming alive in the womb</u></strong> -- <u><strong>and</u></strong> agony -- <u><strong>the personal struggle to die</u></strong> -- <u><strong>defined the extreme boundaries between which a subject of medical care could be conceived.¶</u></strong> In our world, these boundaries have been obliterated. By the early 20th century, the physician came to be perceived as society's appointed tutor of any person who, having been placed in a patient role, lost his own competence.¶ <u><strong><mark>Physicians are taught</u></strong></mark> today <u><strong><mark>to consider themselves responsible for lives from the moment the egg is fertilized through the time of organ harvest</mark>. They have become the socially responsible professional manager <mark>not </mark>of <mark>a patient, but </mark>of <mark>a life</u></strong></mark> from sperm to worm. <u><strong><mark>Physicians have become the bureaucrats of the brave new biocracy that rules from womb to tomb.</u></strong></mark> In societies confused by the technological prowess that enables us to transgress all traditional boundaries of coming to life and dying, the new discipline of <u><strong><mark>bio-ethics</u></strong></mark> has emerged to mediate between pop-science and law. It <u><strong>has sought to create the semblance of a moral discourse that <mark>roots personhood in the "scientific ability"</mark> of bioethicists <mark>to determine who is a person and who is not through qualitative evaluation of</u></strong></mark> the fetish, <u><strong><mark>"a life."</u></strong></mark>¶ What I fear is that the abstract, secular notion of "a life" will be sacralized, thereby making it possible that this spectral entity will progressively replace the notion of a "person" in which the humanism of Western individualism is anchored. <u><strong><mark>"A life" is amenable to management</mark>, to <mark>improvement</mark> and to <mark>evaluation</mark> in a way which is unthinkable when we speak of "a person." <mark>The transmogrification of a person into "a life" is a lethal operation</u></strong></mark>, as dangerous as reaching out for the tree of life in the time of Adam and Eve.¶ The churches -- one of the most important agencies for defining moral issues in public life -- bear a particular responsibility as a lost civilization turns to them for guidance on such issues as abortion, euthanasia, organ transplants, embryo cloning and eugenics.¶ "A life" is the most powerful idol the church has had to face in the course of its history. More than the ideology of empire or feudal order, more than nationalism or progress, more than gnosticism or Enlightenment, the acceptance of "life" as a God given reality lends itself to a new corruption of the Christian faith.¶ <u><strong>The Christian West has given birth to a radically other kind of human condition</u></strong> unlike anything before it. Only <u><strong>within</u></strong> the matrix which Jacques Ellul calls <u><strong>the "technological system"</u></strong> has this new type of human condition come to full fruition. <u><strong>A new role opens for mythmaking, moralizing, legitimating institutions</u></strong>, a role which cannot quite be understood in terms of old religions, but which some churches rush in to fill.¶ The new technological society is singularly incapable of generating myths to which people can form deep and rich attachments. Yet, for its rudimentary maintenance it needs agencies which create and legitimate fetishes to which epistemic sentimentality can attach itself.¶ <u><strong><mark>We seem to need a Linus blanket</mark>, some prestigious fetish that <mark>we can drag around to feel like defenders of sacred values. "Life" has become this blanket: </mark>it has come to constitute <mark>an essential referent in current ecological, medical, legal, political and ethical discourse.</u></strong></mark> Consistently, those who use it forget that the notion has a history. It is a Western notion, ultimately the result of a perversion of the Christian message.¶ When the Lord announced to Martha "I am Life," he did not say "I am a Life." He says "I am Life" tout court. This Life has its historical roots in the revelation that one human person, Jesus, is also God. This one Life is the substance of Martha's faith. In the Christian tradition, we hope to receive this Life as a gift; and we hope to share it. We know that this Life was given to us on the Cross and we cannot seek it except on the via crucis.¶ This Life is gratuitous, beyond and above having been born and living. But, as Augustine and Luther constantly stress, it is a gift without which being alive would be dust.¶ Life in the Christian tradition is personal to the point of being one person, both revealed and promised in John 19. It is something profoundly other than the life which appears as substantive in all the headlines about abortion or euthanasia in American newspapers.¶ At first sight, the two have nothing in common. On the one side, the Bible says: Emmanuel, Godman, Incarnation. On the other, the term is used to impute substance to a process for which the physician assumes responsibility, which technologies prolong and atomic armaments protect; a substance which has standing in court, can be wrongfully given, and about whose destruction without due process or beyond the needs of national defense or industrial growth the so-called pro-life organizations are incensed.¶ However, at closer inspection, <u><strong><mark>life as a property</mark>, as <mark>a value, a national resource, a right, is a Western notion</mark> which shares its Christian ancestry with other key verities defining secular society. The notion of a human life as a distinct entity which can be professionally and legally protected has <mark>been torturously constructed through a legal-medical-religious-scientific discourse</u></strong></mark> whose roots go far back into theology.¶ The emotional and conceptual connotations of life in Hindu, Buddhist or Islamic traditions are utterly distinct from those evident in the current debate on this subject in Western democracies.¶ In the United States, the politicized pro-life movements are sponsored mainly by Christian denominations.¶ It is for this reason that it is mainly up to the churches to de-mystify "life." The Christian churches now face an ugly temptation: to cooperate in the social creation of a fetish which, in a theological perspective, is the perversion of revealed Life into an idol.¶ The History of a Life¶ Biblical scholars are well aware of the limited correspondence between the Hebrew word for blood, dam, for breath, ruah, and the Greek term we would render as soul, namely, psyche. Neither comes anywhere near the meaning of the substantive, life. <u><strong>The concept of life does not exist in Greco-Roman antiquity: bios means the course of a destiny and zoe something close to the brilliance of aliveness. In Hebrew, the concept is utterly theocentric, an implication of God's breath.¶</u></strong> Life as a substantive notion appears two thousand years later, along with the science that purports to study it. The term biology was coined early in the 19th century by Jean-Baptiste Lamarck. He was reacting to the baroque progress in botany and zoology which tended to reduce these two disciplines to the status of mere classification. By inventing a new term, he also named a new field of study, "the science of life."¶ Lamarck's genius confronted the tradition of distinct vegetable and animal ensoulment, along with the consequent division of nature into three kingdoms: mineral, vegetable and animal. He postulated the existence of life that distinguishes living beings from inorganic matter not by visible structure but by organization. Since Lamarck, biology searches for the "stimulating cause of organization" and its localization in tissue cells, protoplasm, the genetic code or morphogenetic fields.¶ <u><strong>"What is life?" is</u></strong>, therefore, <u><strong>not a perennial question, but the pop-science counterfoil to scientific research reports on</u></strong> a mixed bag of phenomena such as <u><strong>reproduction, physiology, heredity, organization, evolution and</u></strong>, more recently, feedback and <u><strong>morphogenesis</u></strong>.¶ Life appears during the Napoleonic wars as a postulate which is meant to lead the new biologists beyond the competing descriptive studies of mechanists, vitalists and materialists. Then, as morphological, physiological and genetic studies became more precise toward the middle of the 19th century, life and its evolution become the hazy and unintended by-products reflecting in ordinary discourse an increasingly abstract and formal kind of scientific terminology.¶ THE DEATH OF NATURE | A thread which runs back to Anaxagoras (500-428BC) links a number of otherwise profoundly distinct philosophical systems: the theme of nature's aliveness. This idea of nature's sensitive responsiveness found its constant expression well into the 16th century in animistic and idealistic, gnostic and hylomorphic versions. In these variations, nature is experienced as the matrix from which all things are born. In the long period between Augustine and Scotus this birthing power of nature was rooted in the world's being contingent on the incessant creative will of God.¶ By the 13th century, and especially in the Franciscan school of theology, the world's being is seen as contingent not merely on God's creation, but also on the graceful sharing of his own being, his life. Whatever is brought from possibility (de potentia) into the necessity of its own existence thrives by its miraculous sharing of God's own intimacy, for which there is no better word than -- His life.¶ <u><strong>With the scientific revolution</u></strong>, contingency-rooted thought fades and <u><strong><mark>a mechanistic model comes to dominate perception</u></strong></mark>. Caroline Merchant argues that the resulting "death of nature" has been the most far-reaching event in changing men's vision and perception of the universe. But <u><strong><mark>it</u></strong></mark> also <u><strong><mark>raised the nagging question: How to explain the existence of living forms in a dead cosmos?</mark> <mark>The notion of substantive life thus appears</u></strong></mark> not as a direct answer to this question, but <u><strong><mark>as a</mark> kind of <mark>mindless shibboleth to fill a void</mark>.¶</u></strong> LIFE AS PROPERTY | The ideology of possessive individualism progressively affected the way life could be talked about as a property. Since the 19th century, the legal construction of society increasingly reflects a new philosophical radicalism in the perception of the self. The result is a break with the ethics which had informed western history since Greek antiquity, clearly expressed by the shift of concern from the good to values. Society is now organized on the utilitarian assumption that man is born needy, and needed values are by definition scarce. It becomes axiomatic that the possession of life is then interpreted as the supreme value. Homo economicus becomes the referent for ethical reflection. Living is equated with a struggle for survival or, more radically, with a competition for life. <u><strong>For over a century now <mark>it has become customary to speak about the "conservation of life" as the ultimate motive of human action and social organization.</u></strong></mark> Today, some <u><strong>bioethicists</u></strong> go even further. While up to now the law implied that a person was alive, <u><strong>they demand that we recognize that <mark>there is a deep difference between having a life and merely being alive</mark>. The proven <mark>ability to exercise this act of possession or appropriation is turned into the criterion for personhood and for the existence of a legal subject</mark>.¶</u></strong> During this same period, homo economicus was surreptitiously taken as the emblem and analogue for all living beings. A mechanistic anthropomorphism has gained currency. Bacteria are imagined to mimic "economic" behavior and to engage in internecine competition for the scarce oxygen available in their environment. A cosmic struggle among ever more complex forms of life has become the anthropic foundational myth of the scientific age.¶ </p>
null
1AC
null
430,055
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,944
Democracy doesn’t solve war
Mueller 9—pol sci prof and IR, Ohio State. Widely-recognized expert on terrorism threats in foreign policy. AB from U Chicago, MA in pol sci from UCLA and PhD in pol sci from UCLA (John, Faulty Correlation, Foolish Consistency, Fatal Consequence: Democracy, Peace, and Theory in the Middle East, 15 June 2007, http://psweb.sbs.ohio-state.edu/faculty/jmueller/KENT2.PDF)
Mueller 9—pol sci prof and IR, Ohio State. Widely-recognized expert on terrorism threats in foreign policy. AB from U Chicago, MA in pol sci from UCLA and PhD in pol sci from UCLA (John, Faulty Correlation, Foolish Consistency, Fatal Consequence: Democracy, Peace, and Theory in the Middle East, 15 June 2007, http://psweb.sbs.ohio-state.edu/faculty/jmueller/KENT2.PDF)
there has been a burgeoning discussion about the connection between democracy and war democracies have almost never, gotten into war with each other This relationship seems more correlative than causal, While democracy and war aversion have taken the same trajectory they have been substantially out of synchronization with each other: the movement toward democracy began about 200 years ago, but the movement against war began 100 years ago ( it is often asserted democracies are peaceful because they apply their domestic penchant for compromise to the international arena But authoritarian regimes also develop compromise developed democracies have not adopted a pacifist approach, particularly after a version of that approach failed so to prevent World War II they were willing to subvert or threaten and apply military force when threats appeared to loom during the Cold War developed democracies hardly needed democracy to decide that war among them was a bad idea Thus, while democracy and war aversion have often been promoted by the same advocates, the relationship does not seem to be a causal one. democracies will fight one another various warlike sentiments could be found in Yugoslavia or in India and then-democratic Pakistan The important consideration does not seem to be "whether a country is democratic but whether its ruling coalition is committed to conflict resolution countries of Latin America have engaged in very few wars without being democratic the long peace enjoyed by developed countries since World War II includes not only democracies, but the more important one between authoritarian east Associated with speculations has been a tendency to emboss the grubby gimmick with something of a mystique. the correlation between democracy and war aversion has also been elevated into a causal relationship.
democracy began 200 years ago, but the movement against war began 100 years ago authoritarian regimes also develop compromise democracies apply force when threats appear democracies hardly needed democracy to decide war was a bad idea the relationship does not seem causal warlike sentiments could be found in Yugoslavia India and Pakistan The consideration is whether its ruling coalition is committed to conflict resolution Latin America engaged in few wars without being democratic
In the last couple of decades there has been a burgeoning and intriguing discussion about the connection between democracy and war aversion.7 Most notable has been the empirical observation that democracies have never, or almost never, gotten into a war with each other. This relationship seems more correlative than causal, however. Like many important ideas over the last few centuries, the idea that war is undesirable and inefficacious and the idea that democracy is a good form of government have largely followed the same trajectory: they were embraced first in northern Europe and North America and then gradually, with a number of traumatic setbacks, became more accepted elsewhere. In this view, the rise of democracy not only is associated with the rise of war aversion, but also with the decline of slavery, religion, capital punishment, and cigarette smoking, and with the growing acceptance of capitalism, scientific methodology, women's rights, environmentalism, abortion, and rock music.8 While democracy and war aversion have taken much the same trajectory, however, they have been substantially out of synchronization with each other: the movement toward democracy began about 200 years ago, but the movement against war really began only about 100 years ago (Mueller 1989, 2004). Critics of the democracy/peace connection often cite examples of wars or near-wars between democracies. Most of these took place before World War I--that is, before war aversion had caught on.9 A necessary, logical connection between democracy and war aversion, accordingly, is far from clear. Thus, it is often asserted that democracies are peaceful because they apply their domestic penchant for peaceful compromise (something, obviously, that broke down in the United States in 1861) to the international arena or because the structure of democracy requires decision-makers to obtain domestic approval.10 But authoritarian regimes must also necessarily develop skills at compromise in order to survive, and they all have domestic constituencies that must be serviced such as the church, the landed gentry, potential urban rioters, the nomenklatura, the aristocracy, party members, the military, prominent business interests, the police or secret police, lenders of money to the exchequer, potential rivals for the throne, the sullen peasantry.11 Since World War I, the democracies in the developed world have been in the lead in rejecting war as a methodology. Some proponents of the democracy-peace connection suggest that this is because the democratic norm of non-violent conflict resolution has been externalized to the international arena. However, developed democracies have not necessarily adopted a pacifist approach, particularly after a version of that approach failed so spectacularly to prevent World War II from being forced upon them. In addition, they were willing actively to subvert or to threaten and sometimes apply military force when threats appeared to loom during the Cold War contest. At times this approach was used even against regimes that had some democratic credentials such as in Iran in 1953, Guatemala in 1954, Chile in 1973, and perhaps Nicaragua in the 1980s (Rosato 2003, 590-91). And, they have also sometimes used military force in their intermittent efforts to police the post-Cold War world (Mueller 2004, chs. 7, 8). It is true that they have warred little or not at all against each other--and, since there were few democracies outside the developed world until the last quarter of the twentieth century, it is this statistical regularity that most prominently informs the supposed connection between democracy and peace. However, the developed democracies hardly needed democracy to decide that war among them was a bad idea.12 In addition, they also adopted a live-and-let-live approach toward a huge number of dictatorships and other non-democracies that did not seem threatening during the Cold War--in fact, they often aided and embraced such regimes if they seemed to be on the right side in the conflict with Communism. Moreover, the supposed penchant for peaceful compromise of democracies has not always served them well when confronted with civil war situations, particularly ones involving secessionist demands. The process broke down into civil warfare in democratic Switzerland in 1847 and savagely so in the United States in 1861. Democracies have also fought a considerable number of wars to retain colonial possessions--six by France alone since World War II--and these, as James Fearon and David Laitin suggest, can in many respects be considered essentially to be civil wars (2003, 76). To be sure, democracies have often managed to deal with colonial problems peacefully, mostly by letting the colonies go. But authoritarian governments have also done so: the Soviet Union, for example, withdrew from his empire in Eastern Europe and then dissolved itself, all almost entirely without violence. Thus, while democracy and war aversion have often been promoted by the same advocates, the relationship does not seem to be a causal one. And when the two trends are substantially out of step today, democracies will fight one another. Thus, it is not at all clear that telling the elected hawks in the Jordanian parliament that Israel is a democracy will dampen their hostility in the slightest. And various warlike sentiments could be found in the elected parliaments in the former Yugoslavia in the early 1990s or in India and then-democratic Pakistan when these two countries engaged in armed conflict in 1999. If Argentina had been a democracy in 1982 when it seized the Falkland Islands (a very popular undertaking), it is unlikely that British opposition to the venture would have been much less severe. "The important consideration," observes Miriam Fendius Elman after surveying the literature on the subject, does not seem to be "whether a country is democratic or not, but whether its ruling coalition is committed to peaceful methods of conflict resolution." As she further points out, the countries of Latin America and most of Africa have engaged in very few international wars even without the benefit of being democratic (for a century before its 1982 adventure, Argentina, for example, fought none at all) (1997, 484, 496). (Interestingly, although there has also been scarcely any warfare between Latin American states for over 100 years or among Arab ones or European ones for more that 50--in all cases whether democratic or not--this impressive phenomenon has inspired remarkably few calls for worldwide Arab colonialism or for the systematic transplant of remaining warlike states to Latin America or Europe.) And, of course, the long peace enjoyed by developed countries since World War II includes not only the one that has prevailed between democracies, but also the even more important one between the authoritarian east and the democratic west. Even if there is some connection, whether causal or atmospheric, between democracy and peace, it cannot explain this latter phenomenon. Democracy and the democratic peace become mystiques: the role of philosophers and divines Democracy has been a matter of debate for several millennia as philosophers and divines have speculated about what it is, what it might become, and what it ought to be. Associated with these speculations has been a tendency to emboss the grubby gimmick with something of a mystique. Of particular interest for present purposes is the fanciful notion that democracy does not simply express and aggregate preferences, but actually somehow creates (or should create) them. In addition, the (rough) correlation between democracy and war aversion has also been elevated into a causal relationship.
7,745
<h4>Democracy doesn’t solve war </h4><p><strong>Mueller 9<u>—pol sci prof and IR, Ohio State. Widely-recognized expert on terrorism threats in foreign policy. AB from U Chicago, MA in pol sci from UCLA and PhD in pol sci from UCLA (John, Faulty Correlation, Foolish Consistency, Fatal Consequence: Democracy, Peace, and Theory in the Middle East, 15 June 2007, http://psweb.sbs.ohio-state.edu/faculty/jmueller/KENT2.PDF)</p><p></u></strong>In the last couple of decades <u><strong>there has been a</u></strong> <u><strong>burgeoning</u></strong> and intriguing <u><strong>discussion about the connection between democracy and war</u></strong> aversion.7 Most notable has been the empirical observation that <u><strong>democracies have </u></strong>never, or <u><strong>almost never, gotten into</u></strong> a <u><strong>war with each other</u></strong>. <u><strong>This relationship seems more correlative than causal,</u></strong> however. Like many important ideas over the last few centuries, the idea that war is undesirable and inefficacious and the idea that democracy is a good form of government have largely followed the same trajectory: they were embraced first in northern Europe and North America and then gradually, with a number of traumatic setbacks, became more accepted elsewhere. In this view, the rise of democracy not only is associated with the rise of war aversion, but also with the decline of slavery, religion, capital punishment, and cigarette smoking, and with the growing acceptance of capitalism, scientific methodology, women's rights, environmentalism, abortion, and rock music.8 <u><strong>While democracy and war aversion have taken </u></strong>much <u><strong>the same</u></strong> <u><strong>trajectory</u></strong>, however, <u><strong>they have been substantially out of synchronization with each other: the movement toward <mark>democracy began </mark>about <mark>200 years ago,</mark> <mark>but the movement against</u></strong> <u><strong>war</u></strong></mark> really <u><strong><mark>began</u></strong></mark> only about <u><strong><mark>100 years ago</mark> (</u></strong>Mueller 1989, 2004). Critics of the democracy/peace connection often cite examples of wars or near-wars between democracies. Most of these took place before World War I--that is, before war aversion had caught on.9 A necessary, logical connection between democracy and war aversion, accordingly, is far from clear. Thus, <u><strong>it is often asserted</u></strong> that <u><strong>democracies are peaceful because they apply their domestic penchant for</u></strong> peaceful <u><strong>compromise</u></strong> (something, obviously, that broke down in the United States in 1861) <u><strong>to the international arena</u></strong> or because the structure of democracy requires decision-makers to obtain domestic approval.10 <u><strong>But <mark>authoritarian regimes</u></strong></mark> must <u><strong><mark>also</u></strong></mark> necessarily <u><strong><mark>develop</u></strong></mark> skills at <u><strong><mark>compromise</u></strong></mark> in order to survive, and they all have domestic constituencies that must be serviced such as the church, the landed gentry, potential urban rioters, the nomenklatura, the aristocracy, party members, the military, prominent business interests, the police or secret police, lenders of money to the exchequer, potential rivals for the throne, the sullen peasantry.11 Since World War I, the democracies in the developed world have been in the lead in rejecting war as a methodology. Some proponents of the democracy-peace connection suggest that this is because the democratic norm of non-violent conflict resolution has been externalized to the international arena. However, <u><strong>developed <mark>democracies </mark>have not</u></strong> necessarily <u><strong>adopted a pacifist approach, particularly after a version of that approach failed so</u></strong> spectacularly <u><strong>to prevent World War II</u></strong> from being forced upon them. In addition, <u><strong>they were willing </u></strong>actively <u><strong>to subvert</u></strong> <u><strong>or</u></strong> to <u><strong>threaten</u></strong> <u><strong>and</u></strong> sometimes <u><strong><mark>apply </mark>military <mark>force when threats appear</mark>ed to loom during the Cold War </u></strong>contest. At times this approach was used even against regimes that had some democratic credentials such as in Iran in 1953, Guatemala in 1954, Chile in 1973, and perhaps Nicaragua in the 1980s (Rosato 2003, 590-91). And, they have also sometimes used military force in their intermittent efforts to police the post-Cold War world (Mueller 2004, chs. 7, 8). It is true that they have warred little or not at all against each other--and, since there were few democracies outside the developed world until the last quarter of the twentieth century, it is this statistical regularity that most prominently informs the supposed connection between democracy and peace. However, the <u><strong>developed <mark>democracies hardly needed democracy to decide</mark> that <mark>war</mark> among them <mark>was a bad</mark> <mark>idea</u></strong></mark>.12 In addition, they also adopted a live-and-let-live approach toward a huge number of dictatorships and other non-democracies that did not seem threatening during the Cold War--in fact, they often aided and embraced such regimes if they seemed to be on the right side in the conflict with Communism. Moreover, the supposed penchant for peaceful compromise of democracies has not always served them well when confronted with civil war situations, particularly ones involving secessionist demands. The process broke down into civil warfare in democratic Switzerland in 1847 and savagely so in the United States in 1861. Democracies have also fought a considerable number of wars to retain colonial possessions--six by France alone since World War II--and these, as James Fearon and David Laitin suggest, can in many respects be considered essentially to be civil wars (2003, 76). To be sure, democracies have often managed to deal with colonial problems peacefully, mostly by letting the colonies go. But authoritarian governments have also done so: the Soviet Union, for example, withdrew from his empire in Eastern Europe and then dissolved itself, all almost entirely without violence. <u><strong>Thus, while democracy and war aversion have often been promoted by the same advocates, <mark>the relationship does not seem </mark>to be a <mark>causal </mark>one.</u></strong> And when the two trends are substantially out of step today, <u><strong>democracies will fight one another</u></strong>. Thus, it is not at all clear that telling the elected hawks in the Jordanian parliament that Israel is a democracy will dampen their hostility in the slightest. And <u><strong>various <mark>warlike sentiments could be found in</u></strong></mark> the elected parliaments in the former <u><strong><mark>Yugoslavia</u></strong></mark> in the early 1990s <u><strong>or in <mark>India and </mark>then-democratic <mark>Pakistan</u></strong></mark> when these two countries engaged in armed conflict in 1999. If Argentina had been a democracy in 1982 when it seized the Falkland Islands (a very popular undertaking), it is unlikely that British opposition to the venture would have been much less severe. "<u><strong><mark>The </mark>important <mark>consideration</u></strong></mark>," observes Miriam Fendius Elman after surveying the literature on the subject, <u><strong>does not seem to be "whether a country <mark>is</mark> democratic</u></strong> or not, <u><strong>but <mark>whether its ruling coalition is</u></strong> <u><strong>committed to</u></strong></mark> peaceful methods of <u><strong><mark>conflict resolution</u></strong></mark>." As she further points out, the <u><strong>countries of<mark> Latin America</u></strong></mark> and most of Africa <u><strong>have <mark>engaged in </mark>very <mark>few</u></strong></mark> international <u><strong><mark>wars </u></strong></mark>even <u><strong><mark>without</u></strong></mark> the benefit of <u><strong><mark>being democratic</u></strong></mark> (for a century before its 1982 adventure, Argentina, for example, fought none at all) (1997, 484, 496). (Interestingly, although there has also been scarcely any warfare between Latin American states for over 100 years or among Arab ones or European ones for more that 50--in all cases whether democratic or not--this impressive phenomenon has inspired remarkably few calls for worldwide Arab colonialism or for the systematic transplant of remaining warlike states to Latin America or Europe.) And, of course, <u><strong>the long peace enjoyed by developed countries since World War II includes not only</u></strong> the one that has prevailed between <u><strong>democracies, but</u></strong> also <u><strong>the</u></strong> even <u><strong>more important one between</u></strong> the <u><strong>authoritarian east</u></strong> and the democratic west. Even if there is some connection, whether causal or atmospheric, between democracy and peace, it cannot explain this latter phenomenon. Democracy and the democratic peace become mystiques: the role of philosophers and divines Democracy has been a matter of debate for several millennia as philosophers and divines have speculated about what it is, what it might become, and what it ought to be. <u><strong>Associated with </u></strong>these <u><strong>speculations has been a tendency to emboss the grubby gimmick with something of a mystique.</u></strong> Of particular interest for present purposes is the fanciful notion that democracy does not simply express and aggregate preferences, but actually somehow creates (or should create) them. In addition, <u><strong>the</u></strong> (rough) <u><strong>correlation between democracy and war aversion has also been elevated into a causal relationship.</p></u></strong>
1AR
FW
AT: Agonism
154,421
9
16,993
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
564,698
A
NDT
3
UTD LO
Heidt, Shook, Lundberg
1AC PAS genealogy- same assimilar to USC PAS 1AC 1NC T- Framework K- Szaz Medicalization of death 2NR T
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round3.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,945
backwads
Szentes 8
Szentes 8 Tamás Szentes 8, Professor Emeritus at the Corvinus University of Budapest. “Globalisation and prospects of the world society” 4/22/08 http://www.eadi.org/fileadmin/Documents/Events/exco/Glob.___prospects_-_jav..pdf
human society can survive only in a lasting real peace arms race and militarisation have escalated many “invisible wars” are suffered by the poor manifested in mass misery, poverty, unemployment, homelessness, starvation epidemics and poor health conditions, exploitation and oppression racial discrimination organised injustice and in the degradation of human environment the “war against Nature and large-scale pollution of our environment Behind “invisible wars” we find striking international and intrasociety inequities and distorted development patterns which tend to generate social as well as international tensions paving the way for unrest and “visible” wars The prerequisites of a lasting peace involve not only demilitarisation, but also a and elimination of the roots of violence, of the causes of “invisible wars”, of the structural and institutional bases of inequalities, exploitation and oppression Peace requires a process of emancipation peace cannot be safeguarded in one part of the world when some others suffer visible or invisible wars no ecological balance can be ensured, unless the deep international development gap and intra-society inequalities are substantially reduced the question is not about “sustainability of development” but about the “sustainability of human life”, i.e. survival of [hu]mankind we live in an almost permanent crisis The narrow-minded, election-oriented, selfish behaviour motivated by thirst for power and wealth, paves the way for the final, last catastrophe Under the circumstances provided by rapidly progressing science and technological revolutions, human society cannot survive unless such profound intra-society and international inequalities prevailing today are soon eliminated Earth can no longer afford to have two parts: the rich, privileged on the one hand, and the poor, deprived on the other
“invisible wars” are suffered by the poor manifested in mass , poverty starvation and oppression, and degradation of environment Behind “invisible wars” we find striking international inequities which generate social as well as international tensions paving the way for “visible” wars The prerequisites of a lasting peace involve demilitarisation and elimination of the causes of “invisible wars”, of structural bases of oppression peace cannot be safeguarded when some suffer invisible wars no ecological balance can be ensured, unless inequalities are reduced. the question is about the survival of [hu]mankind we live in permanent cris selfish behaviour paves the way for the final catastrophe human society cannot survive unless intra-society and international inequalities are eliminated
It’ s a common place that human society can survive and develop only in a lasting real peace. Without peace countries cannot develop. Although since 1945 there has been no world war, but --numerous local wars took place, --terrorism has spread all over the world, undermining security even in the most developed and powerful countries, --arms race and militarisation have not ended with the collapse of the Soviet bloc, but escalated and continued, extending also to weapons of mass destruction and misusing enormous resources badly needed for development, --many “invisible wars” are suffered by the poor and oppressed people, manifested in mass misery, poverty, unemployment, homelessness, starvation and malnutrition, epidemics and poor health conditions, exploitation and oppression, racial and other discrimination, physical terror, organised injustice, disguised forms of violence, the denial or regular infringement of the democratic rights of citizens, women, youth, ethnic or religious minorities, etc., and last but not least, in the degradation of human environment, which means that --the “war against Nature”, i.e. the disturbance of ecological balance, wasteful management of natural resources, and large-scale pollution of our environment, is still going on, causing also losses and fatal dangers for human life. Behind global terrorism and “invisible wars” we find striking international and intrasociety inequities and distorted development patterns , which tend to generate social as well as international tensions, thus paving the way for unrest and “visible” wars. It is a commonplace now that peace is not merely the absence of war. The prerequisites of a lasting peace between and within societies involve not only - though, of course, necessarily - demilitarisation, but also a systematic and gradual elimination of the roots of violence, of the causes of “invisible wars”, of the structural and institutional bases of large-scale international and intra-society inequalities, exploitation and oppression. Peace requires a process of social and national emancipation, a progressive, democratic transformation of societies and the world bringing about equal rights and opportunities for all people, sovereign participation and mutually advantageous co-operation among nations. It further requires a pluralistic democracy on global level with an appropriate system of proportional representation of the world society, articulation of diverse interests and their peaceful reconciliation, by non-violent conflict management, and thus also a global governance with a really global institutional system. Under the contemporary conditions of accelerating globalisation and deepening global interdependencies in our world, peace is indivisible in both time and space. It cannot exist if reduced to a period only after or before war, and cannot be safeguarded in one part of the world when some others suffer visible or invisible wars. Thus, peace requires, indeed, a new, demilitarised and democratic world order, which can provide equal opportunities for sustainable development. “Sustainability of development” (both on national and world level) is often interpreted as an issue of environmental protection only and reduced to the need for preserving the ecological balance and delivering the next generations not a destroyed Nature with overexhausted resources and polluted environment. However, no ecological balance can be ensured, unless the deep international development gap and intra-society inequalities are substantially reduced. Owing to global interdependencies there may exist hardly any “zero-sum-games”, in which one can gain at the expense of others, but, instead, the “negative-sum-games” tend to predominate, in which everybody must suffer, later or sooner, directly or indirectly, losses. Therefore, the actual question is not about “sustainability of development” but rather about the “sustainability of human life”, i.e. survival of [hu]mankind – because of ecological imbalance and globalised terrorism. When Professor Louk de la Rive Box was the president of EADI, one day we had an exchange of views on the state and future of development studies. We agreed that development studies are not any more restricted to the case of underdeveloped countries, as the developed ones (as well as the former “socialist” countries) are also facing development problems, such as those of structural and institutional (and even system-) transformation, requirements of changes in development patterns, and concerns about natural environment. While all these are true, today I would dare say that besides (or even instead of) “development studies” we must speak about and make “survival studies”. While the monetary, financial, and debt crises are cyclical, we live in an almost permanent crisis of the world society, which is multidimensional in nature, involving not only economic but also socio-psychological, behavioural, cultural and political aspects. The narrow-minded, election-oriented, selfish behaviour motivated by thirst for power and wealth, which still characterise the political leadership almost all over the world, paves the way for the final, last catastrophe. One cannot doubt, of course, that great many positive historical changes have also taken place in the world in the last century. Such as decolonisation, transformation of socio-economic systems, democratisation of political life in some former fascist or authoritarian states, institutionalisation of welfare policies in several countries, rise of international organisations and new forums for negotiations, conflict management and cooperation, institutionalisation of international assistance programmes by multilateral agencies, codification of human rights, and rights of sovereignty and democracy also on international level, collapse of the militarised Soviet bloc and system-change3 in the countries concerned, the end of cold war, etc., to mention only a few. Nevertheless, the crisis of the world society has extended and deepened, approaching to a point of bifurcation that necessarily puts an end to the present tendencies, either by the final catastrophe or a common solution. Under the circumstances provided by rapidly progressing science and technological revolutions, human society cannot survive unless such profound intra-society and international inequalities prevailing today are soon eliminated. Like a single spacecraft, the Earth can no longer afford to have a 'crew' divided into two parts: the rich, privileged, wellfed, well-educated, on the one hand, and the poor, deprived, starving, sick and uneducated, on the other. Dangerous 'zero-sum-games' (which mostly prove to be “negative-sum-games”) can hardly be played any more by visible or invisible wars in the world society. Because of global interdependencies, the apparent winner becomes also a loser. The real choice for the world society is between negative- and positive-sum-games: i.e. between, on the one hand, continuation of visible and “invisible wars”, as long as this is possible at all, and, on the other, transformation of the world order by demilitarisation and democratization. No ideological or terminological camouflage can conceal this real dilemma any more, which is to be faced not in the distant future, by the next generations, but in the coming years, because of global terrorism soon having nuclear and other mass destructive weapons, and also due to irreversible changes in natural environment.
7,503
<h4><u><strong>backwads</h4><p>Szentes 8</p><p></u></strong>Tamás Szentes 8, Professor Emeritus at the Corvinus University of Budapest. “Globalisation and prospects of the world society” 4/22/08 http://www.eadi.org/fileadmin/Documents/Events/exco/Glob.___prospects_-_jav..pdf</p><p>It’ s a common place that <u>human society can survive</u> and develop <u>only in a lasting real peace</u>. Without peace countries cannot develop. Although since 1945 there has been no world war, but --numerous local wars took place, --terrorism has spread all over the world, undermining security even in the most developed and powerful countries, --<u>arms race and militarisation have</u> not ended with the collapse of the Soviet bloc, but <u>escalated</u> and continued, extending also to weapons of mass destruction and misusing enormous resources badly needed for development, --<u>many <mark>“invisible wars” are suffered by the poor</u></mark> and oppressed people, <u><mark>manifested in mass </mark>misery<mark>, poverty</mark>, unemployment, homelessness, <mark>starvation</u></mark> and malnutrition, <u>epidemics and poor health conditions,</u> <u>exploitation <mark>and oppression</u>,</mark> <u>racial</u> and other <u>discrimination</u>, physical terror, <u>organised injustice</u>, disguised forms of violence, the denial or regular infringement of the democratic rights of citizens, women, youth, ethnic or religious minorities, etc., <u><mark>and</u></mark> last but not least, <u>in the <mark>degradation of </mark>human <mark>environment</u></mark>, which means that --<u><strong>the “war against Nature</u></strong>”, i.e. the disturbance of ecological balance, wasteful management of natural resources, <u>and large-scale pollution of our environment</u>, is still going on, causing also losses and fatal dangers for human life. <u><mark>Behind</mark> </u>global terrorism and <u><mark>“invisible wars” we find striking international </mark>and intrasociety <mark>inequities</mark> and distorted development patterns</u> , <u><mark>which</mark> tend to <strong><mark>generate social as well as international tensions</u></strong></mark>, thus <u><strong><mark>paving the way for</strong></mark> unrest and <strong><mark>“visible” wars</u></strong></mark>. It is a commonplace now that peace is not merely the absence of war. <u><mark>The <strong>prerequisites</strong> of a <strong>lasting peace</u></strong></mark> between and within societies <u><mark>involve </mark>not only</u> - though, of course, necessarily - <u><mark>demilitarisation</mark>, but also a</u> systematic <u><mark>and</u></mark> gradual <u><mark>elimination of the</mark> roots of violence, of the <mark>causes of “invisible wars”, of</mark> the <mark>structural</mark> and institutional <mark>bases of</u></mark> large-scale international and intra-society <u>inequalities,</u> <u>exploitation and <mark>oppression</u></mark>. <u><strong>Peace requires a process of</u></strong> social and national <u><strong>emancipation</u></strong>, a progressive, democratic transformation of societies and the world bringing about equal rights and opportunities for all people, sovereign participation and mutually advantageous co-operation among nations. It further requires a pluralistic democracy on global level with an appropriate system of proportional representation of the world society, articulation of diverse interests and their peaceful reconciliation, by non-violent conflict management, and thus also a global governance with a really global institutional system. Under the contemporary conditions of accelerating globalisation and deepening global interdependencies in our world, <u><mark>peace</mark> </u>is indivisible in both time and space. It cannot exist if reduced to a period only after or before war, and <u><mark>cannot be safeguarded</mark> in one part of the world <mark>when some</mark> others <mark>suffer</mark> visible or <mark>invisible wars</u></mark>. Thus, peace requires, indeed, a new, demilitarised and democratic world order, which can provide equal opportunities for sustainable development. “Sustainability of development” (both on national and world level) is often interpreted as an issue of environmental protection only and reduced to the need for preserving the ecological balance and delivering the next generations not a destroyed Nature with overexhausted resources and polluted environment. However, <u><mark>no ecological balance can be ensured, unless</mark> the deep international development gap and intra-society <mark>inequalities are </mark>substantially <mark>reduced</u>.</mark> Owing to global interdependencies there may exist hardly any “zero-sum-games”, in which one can gain at the expense of others, but, instead, the “negative-sum-games” tend to predominate, in which everybody must suffer, later or sooner, directly or indirectly, losses. Therefore, <u><mark>the</u></mark> actual <u><mark>question is </mark>not about “sustainability of development” but</u> rather <u><strong><mark>about the </mark>“sustainability of human life”,</u></strong> <u><strong>i.e. <mark>survival of [hu]mankind</u></strong></mark> – because of ecological imbalance and globalised terrorism. When Professor Louk de la Rive Box was the president of EADI, one day we had an exchange of views on the state and future of development studies. We agreed that development studies are not any more restricted to the case of underdeveloped countries, as the developed ones (as well as the former “socialist” countries) are also facing development problems, such as those of structural and institutional (and even system-) transformation, requirements of changes in development patterns, and concerns about natural environment. While all these are true, today I would dare say that besides (or even instead of) “development studies” we must speak about and make “survival studies”. While the monetary, financial, and debt crises are cyclical, <u><mark>we live in</mark> an</u> <u>almost <strong><mark>permanent cris</mark>is</u></strong> of the world society, which is multidimensional in nature, involving not only economic but also socio-psychological, behavioural, cultural and political aspects. <u>The narrow-minded, election-oriented, <mark>selfish behaviour </mark>motivated by thirst for power and wealth,</u> which still characterise the political leadership almost all over the world, <u><mark>paves the way for the final</mark>, last <mark>catastrophe</u></mark>. One cannot doubt, of course, that great many positive historical changes have also taken place in the world in the last century. Such as decolonisation, transformation of socio-economic systems, democratisation of political life in some former fascist or authoritarian states, institutionalisation of welfare policies in several countries, rise of international organisations and new forums for negotiations, conflict management and cooperation, institutionalisation of international assistance programmes by multilateral agencies, codification of human rights, and rights of sovereignty and democracy also on international level, collapse of the militarised Soviet bloc and system-change3 in the countries concerned, the end of cold war, etc., to mention only a few. Nevertheless, the crisis of the world society has extended and deepened, approaching to a point of bifurcation that necessarily puts an end to the present tendencies, either by the final catastrophe or a common solution. <u>Under the circumstances provided by rapidly progressing science and technological revolutions, <strong><mark>human society cannot survive unless</strong></mark> such profound <strong><mark>intra-society and international inequalities</strong></mark> prevailing today <strong><mark>are</strong></mark> soon <strong><mark>eliminated</u></strong></mark>. Like a single spacecraft, the <u><strong>Earth can no longer afford to have</u></strong> a 'crew' divided into <u>two parts: the rich, privileged</u>, wellfed, well-educated, <u>on the one hand, and the poor, deprived</u>, starving, sick and uneducated, <u>on the other</u>. Dangerous 'zero-sum-games' (which mostly prove to be “negative-sum-games”) can hardly be played any more by visible or invisible wars in the world society. Because of global interdependencies, the apparent winner becomes also a loser. The real choice for the world society is between negative- and positive-sum-games: i.e. between, on the one hand, continuation of visible and “invisible wars”, as long as this is possible at all, and, on the other, transformation of the world order by demilitarisation and democratization. No ideological or terminological camouflage can conceal this real dilemma any more, which is to be faced not in the distant future, by the next generations, but in the coming years, because of global terrorism soon having nuclear and other mass destructive weapons, and also due to irreversible changes in natural environment.</p>
2NC
K
A2: war t/struct
912
269
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,946
The legalization of prostitution ensures a violent sovereign apparatus tailoring exclusionary policies towards individuals resulting in increased social control and micro fascism - this card is long but on fire
Scoular 10 , Vol. 37, No. 1, March, [AB]
Jane Scoular 10, Professor of Law at University of Strathclyde, “What's Law Got to Do With it? How and Why Law Matters in the Regulation of Sex Work,” Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 37, No. 1, March, [AB]
1. Norms legal strategies for the governance of sex work share regulatory ambitions Empirical evidence points to two parallel processes in which prostitution becomes a target for the state's wider efforts to responsibilize citizens, while simultaneously maintaining spaces for the operation of the capitalist economy. Processes of licensing and exiting operate to normalize particular forms of citizenship and sexual activity which enhance a broader structure of consumption, rendering deviant those who cannot through poverty, race, immigration status or health meet these increasingly restricted norms of citizenship, and marginalizing unproductive spaces. the normalization of other forms of commercial sex business reveal a shared set of underlying economic and cultural interests; the excision of class and racial Others from gentrifying inner cities the facilitation of the post-industrial service sector, and the creation of clean urban spaces in which middle-class men can safely indulge in recreational commercial sexual consumption. This normative order is established via a continuum of regulatory mechanisms Law has no privilege in this system but it does play a vital role in authorizing other forms of knowledge, helping to shape content, and empowering a group of regulatory agents in exercising diffuse power 2. Authorizations Examining extended forms of governance enlighten us more about what law is doing than the statute book despite differences at a sovereign level in prostitution policy law authorizes and operates though quasi-legal forums exiting programmes, rehabilitation schemes, and licensing boards and techniques fines which an extended group of regulatory agents exercise normalizing power all the little judges of conduct exercise petty powers of adjudication in `the bureaucratic workings of our over-governed existence These forums feature a hybridization of legal and non-legal authority. The state's role appears to recede but it may actually be augmented by a wider range of control mechanisms and forms of professional intervention that may be even more pervasive than the previous systems. Licensing decision making operates to reaffirm the dividing lines between legitimate and illegitimate forms of commercial sex. This ensures that the wider structures of governmentality fit with local conditions while appearing to comply with the liberal objection to state interference. the apparent increased `protection' promised by reforms results in the increased policing of many women's lives. 3. Subjectifications Foucault's observation in The Dangerous Individual is that law in normalizing societies is increasingly concerned with lives rather than with acts This is evident in the current preoccupation with particular subjects and spaces of sex work and the operationalizing of forms of governance to save, empower, responsibilize, and ethically reconstruct individuals – all testament to law's increasing normalizing ambitions as it acts alongside other discourses to construct `the fabric of the modern subject'. In doing so it operates not ideologically but through a process of subjectification encouraging self-projects in ways that align with the diverse objectives of legislation both licensing and exiting operate to encourage subjects to perform as `self-governing, rational actors' required by the wider context of neo-liberalism and to identify those who cannot self-manage or who resist normalization in order that they be excluded. when we ask what law is doing with regard to the types of subjectifications it encourages, we see that while it decriminalizes selling sex it replaces this with a system of welfare and therapeutic interventions which operate to support wider systems of neo-liberal governance contemporary forms of governance operate through these techniques of responsibilization prostitution must be viewed in the wider context of neo-liberalism in which welfare states are retracting and being replaced by systems of private insurance thus leading to increasing conditionality in citizenship and penalty for those who cannot meet their terms/manage risks In this context social exclusion is not tackled by structural change but via individual re-education abolitionist systems promote forms of self-governance which require active citizens to self-regulate according to the norms of the family and the market Those who act responsibly by adopting appropriate lifestyles via work and norms of sexuality are offered inclusion those who do not or cannot are further excluded having failed to meet the increasingly normalized terms of citizenship in late-capitalist societies. Research suggests that legalized systems create a industry as the costs and norms of compliance are too onerous for most individuals and small brothel owners to bear it overwhelmingly favours profitable sex businesses Alongside this the system of licensing encourages workers to self- regulate their behaviour in the interests of public health promotion to conform to certain modes of working in order to meet the conditions of registration Inclusion is offered to those who 'can perform the rituals of middle class society' This 'ideal' typifies the rational subjects encouraged by these processes as law operates alongside practices such as public health to create and 101 maintain a 'responsible prostitution population'. it operates to identify and exclude those who cannot meet the increasingly conditional nature of citizenship for example, migrants, the underage, and drug-users all of whom are not incorporated within the framework of regulatory protection. the moral engineering of advanced liberal governance has co-opted feminist concerns into techniques of governance and control Whether based on a recognition of sex workers' inherent agency or victimhood, social exclusion is being used as leverage for increased control rather than for increased social justice Empowerment operates to sanction forms of self-governance that support neo-liberal interests the proliferation of state-sponsored programmes of empowerment must be treated with critical caution as even while they are utilizing the vocabulary of radical politics their promise of emancipation may be merely rhetorical as they 'endeavour to operationalise the self-governing capacity of the governed in the pursuit of governmental objectives' both processes identify those who cannot perform rendering them vulnerable to exclusion or banishment.
prostitution becomes a target for the state's wider efforts to responsibilize citizens licensing and exiting normalize particular forms of citizenship and sexual activity rendering deviant those who cannot through poverty, race, immigration status or health the normalization of commercial sex reveal the excision of class and racial Others from gentrifying inner cities Law does play a vital role in authorizing knowledge helping to shape regulatory agents in exercising power despite differences in prostitution policy law authorizes and operates though quasi-legal forums exiting programmes rehabilitation schemes, and licensing and techniques which extended regulatory agents normalizing power The state appears to recede but it may be augmented by wider control mechanisms and professional intervention that may be even more pervasive than previous systems. Licensing operates to reaffirm the dividing lines between legitimate and illegitimate forms of sex. This ensures wider structures of governmentality appear to comply with the liberal objection to state interference increased `protection' results in increased policing law is concerned with lives rather than acts evident in sex work and the operationalizing of governance to save empower responsibilize and reconstruct individuals it operates through subjectification encouraging self-projects that align with objectives of legislation licensing and exiting operate to encourage subjects to perform as `self-governing, rational actors' required to identify those who resist normalization in order that they be excluded. law replaces this with interventions to support neo-liberal governance governance operate through responsibilization prostitution must be viewed in the context of states being replaced by private insurance leading to conditionality in citizenship and penalty for those who cannot meet terms social exclusion is not tackled by structural change but via individual re-education abolitionist systems promote self-governance which require citizens to self-regulate according to the norms of the family and market legalized systems create costs of compliance too onerous for individuals it favours profitable businesses licensing encourages workers to self- regulate in the interests of public health This 'ideal' typifies rational subjects as law operates alongside practices such as health to create a 'responsible prostitution population'. it operates to exclude those migrants underage drug-users not incorporated within protection liberal governance co-opted feminist concerns into techniques of control state programmes of empowerment must be treated with critical caution their promise of emancipation may be merely rhetorical as they operationalise self-governing in the pursuit of governmental objectives' both processes identify those who cannot perform rendering them vulnerable to banishment
1. Norms By examining what law is doing in both cases, it becomes apparent that despite the difference in rhetoric, legal strategies for the governance of sex work share a number of similarities in terms of their regulatory ambitions. Empirical evidence points to two parallel processes in which prostitution becomes a target for the state's wider efforts to responsibilize citizens, while simultaneously maintaining spaces for the operation of the capitalist economy. Processes of licensing and exiting operate to normalize particular forms of citizenship and sexual activity which enhance a broader structure of consumption, rendering deviant those who cannot through poverty, race, immigration status or health meet these increasingly restricted norms of citizenship, and marginalizing unproductive spaces. As Bernstein notes: both the state policing of the street-level sex trade and the normalization of other forms of commercial sex business reveal a shared set of underlying economic and cultural interests; the excision of class and racial Others from gentrifying inner cities, the facilitation of the post-industrial service sector, and the creation of clean and shiny urban spaces in which middle-class men can safely indulge in recreational commercial sexual consumption.86 This normative order is established not through law as such but via a continuum of regulatory mechanisms of which it forms part. Law has no privilege in this system but it does play a vital role in authorizing other forms of knowledge, helping to shape content, and empowering a much wider group of regulatory agents in exercising more diffuse forms of power. 2. Authorizations Examining the extended forms of governance operating in this area may enlighten us more about what law is doing than the statute book. Thus, in the context of Sweden and the Netherlands, despite differences at a sovereign level in prostitution policy, law authorizes and operates though a number of quasi-legal forums (john schools, exiting programmes, rehabilitation schemes, and licensing boards) and techniques (anti-social behaviour orders, fines, rehabilitation orders, licenses) in which an extended group of regulatory agents exercise normalizing power: `all the little judges of conduct [who] exercise their petty powers of adjudication and enforcement'87 in what Valverde and Rose call `the bureaucratic workings of our over-governed existence'.88 These forums feature a hybridization of legal and non-legal authority. The state's role appears to recede but it may actually be augmented by a wider range of control mechanisms and forms of professional intervention that may be even more pervasive than the previous systems. Licensing decision making is devolved to a wider group, yet operates to reaffirm the dividing lines between legitimate and illegitimate forms of commercial sex. Indeed, it may be more useful than direct control as delegated authority refines law more minutely in response to shifting realities on the ground and employs a wider group of authorities in its realization. This ensures that the wider structures of governmentality fit with local conditions while appearing to comply with the liberal objection to state interference. Thus, in the case of the Netherlands, while street sex work has not been outlawed it has been made more and more difficult, as a number of municipalities in closing their tippelzones have dispensed with their previous assumed duties to provide safe places for street sex work. Similarly the economic and racial segregation apparent in indoor settings appears distant and accidental as it is effected by powers exercised by diverse groups. In Sweden decriminalization premised on exiting may actually signal a wider range of control mechanisms and forms of professional intervention which are even more pervasive than the previous system of fines. Thus, the apparent increased `protection' promised by reforms results in the increased policing of many women's lives.89 3. Subjectifications There is a question which is essential in the Modern Tribunal, but which would have had a strange ring to it 150 years [ago]: `Who are You?'90 Foucault's observation in The Dangerous Individual is that law in normalizing societies is increasingly concerned with lives rather than with acts. This is evident in the current preoccupation with particular subjects and spaces of sex work and the operationalizing of forms of governance to save, empower, responsibilize, and ethically reconstruct individuals – all testament to law's increasing normalizing ambitions as it acts alongside other discourses to construct `the fabric of the modern subject'.91 In doing so it operates not ideologically, as there is always resistance, nor through the simple imputation of legal consciousness,92 but through a process of subjectification, encouraging self-projects in ways that align with the diverse objectives of legislation.93 Thus, if we examine the continuities in the projects of self-governance promoted in each jurisdiction, we begin to see that the commonly accepted opposition between victim and agent may not be as marked when viewed through a governmental lens. Thus, through parallel forms of subjectification, both licensing and exiting operate to encourage subjects to perform as `self-governing, rational actors' required by the wider context of neo-liberalism and to identify those who cannot self-manage or who resist normalization in order that they be excluded. Thus when we look to Sweden and ask what law is doing with regard to the types of subjectifications it encourages, we see that while it decriminalizes selling sex (due to women's assumed victimhood), it replaces this with a system of welfare and therapeutic interventions which operate to support wider systems of neo-liberal governance. Despite being heralded as a 'renewed welfare approach', which in any event is not necessarily benign, as my previous work with Maggie O'Neill 94 points out, contemporary forms of governance operate through these techniques of responsibilization. Techniques of 'exiting' women from prostitution must be viewed in the wider context of neo-liberalism in which welfare states, including the much renowned Swedish system, are retracting and being replaced by systems of private insurance, thus leading to increasing conditionality in citizenship and penalty for those who cannot meet their terms/manage risks. In this context social exclusion is not tackled by structural change but via individual re-education, re-training, and entry into legitimate economies and relationships. By prioritizing 'exiting' as a means of facilitating social inclusion rather than offering recognition, rights or redistribution to sex workers as a group, abolitionist systems promote forms of self-governance which require active citizens to self-regulate according to the norms of the family and the market. Those who act responsibly by adopting appropriate lifestyles via work and norms of sexuality are offered inclusion, those who do not or cannot and instead remain in sex work (which retains its criminal label) are further excluded, having failed to meet the increasingly normalized terms of citizenship in late-capitalist societies. The increased focus on male clients involves the promotion of similar individuating modes of governance. Despite the rhetoric of gender equality, the increased punitiveness towards (some) purchasers represents no more than the shifting of the 'whore stigma' to a new deviant group. Respon- sibility becomes increasingly narrowed to client motives and individual sexual ethics, which are pathologized rather than explained in relation to their historical specificity and to the social and economic institutions that themselves structure the relations of gender domination. When action is taken through criminalization, or via the quasi-legal forums of john schools and name-and-shame campaigns, it typically operates on 'a lower-tier of male heterosexual practices' or to 're-gender sexual stigma in certain middle class fractions' , leaving the more mainstream corporate and private market untouched. The system of regulationism in the Netherlands encourages similar forms of self-governance and produces analogous exclusions. Research suggests that legalized systems create a two-tiered (if not more) industry, as the costs and norms of compliance are too onerous for most individuals and small brothel owners to bear. Thus, it overwhelmingly favours profitable sex businesses which, as Brents and Hausbeck note, can now hardly be described as 'other' to late-capitalist industries. Alongside this, the system of licensing encourages workers to self- regulate their behaviour in the interests of public health promotion, to conform to certain modes of working in order to meet the conditions of registration. Inclusion is offered to those who 'can perform the rituals of middle class society' with all of the typical exclusions based on age, status, race, health, and class that this entails. This point is well illustrated in an advert which followed the decriminalization of brothels in New South Wales: . tall, blonde and stylish, she recently completed her tertiary marketing course and is looking for employment in the field . She provides her own condoms ... and comes complete with a medical certificate. This 'ideal' typifies the rational subjects encouraged by these processes, as law operates alongside practices, such as public health, to create and 101 maintain what Scott calls a 'responsible prostitution population'. The low take-up rate in the Netherlands indicates that very few can conform to this responsibilized model, meaning that while licensing can offer some increased improvement in the working conditions for a small section of workers, it also operates to identify and exclude those who cannot meet the increasingly conditional nature of citizenship, for example, migrants, the underage, and drug-users, all of whom are not incorporated within the framework of regulatory protection. Thus in both systems, the moral engineering of advanced liberal governance has co-opted feminist concerns into techniques of governance and control. Whether based on a recognition of sex workers' inherent agency or victimhood, social exclusion is being used as leverage for increased control rather than for increased social justice. Empowerment simply operates to sanction forms of self-governance that support neo-liberal interests. As Cruikshank notes, the recent proliferation of state-sponsored programmes of empowerment must be treated with critical caution, as even while they are utilizing the vocabulary of radical politics, their promise of emancipation may be merely rhetorical as they 'endeavour to operationalise the self-governing capacity of the governed in the pursuit of governmental objectives'. Yet what both processes do well is to identify those who cannot perform, rendering them vulnerable to exclusion or banishment.
10,992
<h4>The legalization of prostitution ensures a violent sovereign apparatus tailoring exclusionary policies towards individuals resulting in increased social control and micro fascism - this card is long but on fire</h4><p>Jane<u><strong> Scoular 10</u></strong>, Professor of Law at University of Strathclyde, “What's Law Got to Do With it? How and Why Law Matters in the Regulation of Sex Work,” Journal of Law and Society<u><strong>, Vol. 37, No. 1, March, [AB] </p><p>1. Norms </u></strong>By examining what law is doing in both cases, it becomes apparent that despite the difference in rhetoric, <u>legal strategies for the governance of sex work share</u> a number of similarities in terms of their <u><strong>regulatory ambitions</u></strong>. <u><strong>Empirical evidence</strong> points to two parallel processes in which <strong><mark>prostitution becomes a target</strong> for the state's</mark> <strong><mark>wider efforts to responsibilize citizens</strong></mark>, while simultaneously maintaining spaces for the operation of the capitalist economy. Processes of <mark>licensing and exiting </mark>operate to <strong><mark>normalize particular forms of citizenship and sexual activity</strong></mark> which enhance a broader structure of consumption, <strong><mark>rendering deviant those who cannot</strong> through <strong>poverty, race, immigration status or health</strong></mark> meet these increasingly <strong>restricted norms of citizenship</strong>, and <strong>marginalizing unproductive spaces.</u></strong> As Bernstein notes: both the state policing of the street-level sex trade and <u><mark>the <strong>normalization of</strong></mark> other forms of <strong><mark>commercial sex</strong></mark> business <mark>reveal</mark> a shared set of underlying economic and cultural interests; <strong><mark>the excision of class and racial Others</strong> from <strong>gentrifying inner cities</u></strong></mark>, <u>the facilitation of the post-industrial service sector, and the creation of clean</u> and shiny <u>urban spaces in which middle-class men can safely indulge in recreational commercial sexual consumption.</u>86 <u><strong>This normative order is established</u></strong> not through law as such but <u><strong>via a continuum of regulatory mechanisms</u></strong> of which it forms part. <u><strong><mark>Law</u></strong></mark> <u>has no privilege in this system but it <mark>does play a <strong>vital role</strong> in authorizing</mark> other forms of <mark>knowledge</mark>, <mark>helping to shape</mark> content, and empowering a</u> much wider <u>group of <mark>regulatory agents in exercising</mark> </u>more <u>diffuse</u> forms of<u> <mark>power</u></mark>. <u><strong>2. Authorizations </strong>Examining</u> the <u><strong>extended forms of governance</u></strong> operating in this area may <u>enlighten us <strong>more about what law is doing than the statute</strong> book</u>. Thus, in the context of Sweden and the Netherlands, <u><strong><mark>despite differences</strong> </mark>at a sovereign level <mark>in prostitution policy</u></mark>, <u><mark>law authorizes and operates though</u></mark> a number of <u><strong><mark>quasi-legal forums</u></strong></mark> (john schools, <u><mark>exiting programmes</mark>, <mark>rehabilitation schemes, and licensing</mark> boards</u>) <u><strong><mark>and techniques</u></strong></mark> (anti-social behaviour orders, <u>fines</u>, rehabilitation orders, licenses) in <u><mark>which</u></mark> <u>an <mark>extended</mark> group of <strong><mark>regulatory agents</u></strong></mark> <u>exercise <strong><mark>normalizing power</u></strong></mark>: `<u>all the <strong>little judges of conduct</u></strong> [who] <u>exercise</u> their <u><strong>petty powers of adjudication</u></strong> and enforcement'87 <u>in</u> what Valverde and Rose call <u>`the bureaucratic workings of our over-governed existence</u>'.88 <u>These forums feature a <strong>hybridization of legal and non-legal authority</strong>. <strong><mark>The state</mark>'s role <mark>appears to recede but it may</mark> actually <mark>be augmented by</mark> a <mark>wider</mark> range of <mark>control mechanisms and</mark> forms of <mark>professional intervention that may be even more pervasive than</mark> the <mark>previous systems.</mark> </strong><mark>Licensing</mark> decision making</u> is devolved to a wider group, yet <u><mark>operates to <strong>reaffirm the dividing lines</strong> between <strong>legitimate and illegitimate forms of</strong> </mark>commercial <strong><mark>sex</strong>.</mark> </u>Indeed, it may be more useful than direct control as delegated authority refines law more minutely in response to shifting realities on the ground and employs a wider group of authorities in its realization. <u><mark>This ensures</mark> that the <strong><mark>wider structures of governmentality</strong> </mark>fit with local conditions while <strong><mark>appear</mark>ing <mark>to comply with the liberal objection to state interference</strong></mark>.</u> Thus, in the case of the Netherlands, while street sex work has not been outlawed it has been made more and more difficult, as a number of municipalities in closing their tippelzones have dispensed with their previous assumed duties to provide safe places for street sex work. Similarly the economic and racial segregation apparent in indoor settings appears distant and accidental as it is effected by powers exercised by diverse groups. In Sweden decriminalization premised on exiting may actually signal a wider range of control mechanisms and forms of professional intervention which are even more pervasive than the previous system of fines. Thus, <u>the <strong>apparent <mark>increased `protection'</strong> </mark>promised by reforms <strong><mark>results in</mark> the <mark>increased policing</u></strong></mark> <u>of many women's lives.</u>89 <u><strong>3. Subjectifications </u></strong>There is a question which is essential in the Modern Tribunal, but which would have had a strange ring to it 150 years [ago]: `Who are You?'90 <u>Foucault's observation in The Dangerous Individual is that <mark>law</mark> in normalizing societies <mark>is</mark> increasingly <mark>concerned with lives rather than</mark> with <mark>acts</u></mark>. <u>This is <mark>evident in</mark> the current preoccupation with particular subjects and spaces of <mark>sex work and the <strong>operationalizing</mark> of forms <mark>of governance</strong></mark> <mark>to <strong>save</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>empower</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>responsibilize</strong></mark>, <mark>and</mark> ethically <mark>reconstruct individuals</mark> – all <strong>testament to law's</strong> increasing <strong>normalizing ambitions</strong> as it acts alongside other discourses to construct `the fabric of the modern subject'.</u>91 <u>In doing so<mark> it operates</mark> not ideologically</u>, as there is always resistance, nor through the simple imputation of legal consciousness,92 <u>but</u> <u><mark>through</mark> a process of <mark>subjectification</u></mark>, <u><strong><mark>encouraging self-projects</strong></mark> in ways <mark>that align with</mark> the diverse <strong><mark>objectives of legislation</u></strong></mark>.93 Thus, if we examine the continuities in the projects of self-governance promoted in each jurisdiction, we begin to see that the commonly accepted opposition between victim and agent may not be as marked when viewed through a governmental lens. Thus, through parallel forms of subjectification, <u>both <mark>licensing and exiting operate to</mark> <strong><mark>encourage subjects</strong> to perform as `<strong>self-governing, rational actors'</strong> required</mark> by the wider context of neo-liberalism and <mark>to identify those</mark> who cannot self-manage or <mark>who <strong>resist normalization</strong> in order that <strong>they be excluded.</u></strong></mark> Thus <u>when we</u> look to Sweden and <u>ask what <mark>law</mark> is doing with regard to the types of subjectifications it encourages, we see that while it decriminalizes selling sex</u> (due to women's assumed victimhood), <u>it <strong><mark>replaces this</strong></mark> <mark>with</mark> a system of <strong>welfare and therapeutic <mark>interventions</u></strong></mark> <u>which operate <mark>to support</mark> wider systems of <mark>neo-liberal governance</u></mark>. Despite being heralded as a 'renewed welfare approach', which in any event is not necessarily benign, as my previous work with Maggie O'Neill 94 points out, <u><strong>contemporary forms of <mark>governance operate through</mark> these techniques of <mark>responsibilization</u></strong></mark>. Techniques of 'exiting' women from <u><mark>prostitution <strong>must be viewed in the</mark> wider <mark>context</strong> of</u></mark> <u>neo-liberalism in which welfare <mark>states</u></mark>, including the much renowned Swedish system, <u>are retracting and <mark>being <strong>replaced by</mark> systems of <mark>private insurance</u></strong></mark>, <u>thus <mark>leading to</mark> <strong>increasing <mark>conditionality in citizenship</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>and</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>penalty for those who cannot meet</mark> their <mark>terms</mark>/manage risks</u></strong>. <u>In this context <strong><mark>social exclusion is not tackled by structural change but via individual re-education</u></strong></mark>, re-training, and entry into legitimate economies and relationships. By prioritizing 'exiting' as a means of facilitating social inclusion rather than offering recognition, rights or redistribution to sex workers as a group, <u><strong><mark>abolitionist systems promote</strong></mark> forms of <mark>self-governance which require</mark> active <mark>citizens to <strong>self-regulate according to the norms of the family and</mark> the <mark>market</u></strong></mark>. <u>Those who act responsibly by adopting appropriate lifestyles via work and norms of sexuality are offered inclusion</u>, <u>those who do not or cannot</u> and instead remain in sex work (which retains its criminal label) <u><strong>are further excluded</u></strong>, <u>having failed to meet the increasingly <strong>normalized terms of citizenship</strong> in late-capitalist societies. </u>The increased focus on male clients involves the promotion of similar individuating modes of governance. Despite the rhetoric of gender equality, the increased punitiveness towards (some) purchasers represents no more than the shifting of the 'whore stigma' to a new deviant group. Respon- sibility becomes increasingly narrowed to client motives and individual sexual ethics, which are pathologized rather than explained in relation to their historical specificity and to the social and economic institutions that themselves structure the relations of gender domination. When action is taken through criminalization, or via the quasi-legal forums of john schools and name-and-shame campaigns, it typically operates on 'a lower-tier of male heterosexual practices' or to 're-gender sexual stigma in certain middle class fractions' , leaving the more mainstream corporate and private market untouched. The system of regulationism in the Netherlands encourages similar forms of self-governance and produces analogous exclusions. <u>Research suggests that <mark>legalized systems create</mark> a</u> two-tiered (if not more) <u>industry</u>, <u>as the <mark>costs</mark> and norms <mark>of compliance</mark> are <mark>too onerous for</mark> most <mark>individuals</mark> and small brothel owners to bear</u>. Thus, <u><mark>it</mark> overwhelmingly <mark>favours</mark> <mark>profitable</mark> sex <mark>businesses</u></mark> which, as Brents and Hausbeck note, can now hardly be described as 'other' to late-capitalist industries. <u>Alongside this</u>, <u>the system of <mark>licensing encourages workers to <strong>self- regulate</mark> their behaviour</u></strong> <u><mark>in the interests of <strong>public health</mark> promotion</u></strong>, <u>to conform to certain modes of working in order to meet the conditions of registration</u>. <u><strong>Inclusion is offered to those who 'can perform the rituals of middle class society'</u></strong> with all of the typical exclusions based on age, status, race, health, and class that this entails. This point is well illustrated in an advert which followed the decriminalization of brothels in New South Wales: . tall, blonde and stylish, she recently completed her tertiary marketing course and is looking for employment in the field . She provides her own condoms ... and comes complete with a medical certificate. <u><mark>This 'ideal' typifies</mark> the <strong><mark>rational subjects</strong></mark> encouraged by these processes</u>, <u><mark>as</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>law operates alongside practices</u></strong></mark>, <u><mark>such as</mark> public <mark>health</u></mark>, <u><mark>to create</mark> and 101 maintain </u>what Scott calls <u><mark>a <strong>'responsible prostitution population'.</u></strong></mark> The low take-up rate in the Netherlands indicates that very few can conform to this responsibilized model, meaning that while licensing can offer some increased improvement in the working conditions for a small section of workers, <u><mark>it</u></mark> also <u><mark>operates to</mark> <strong>identify and <mark>exclude those</u></strong></mark> <u>who cannot meet the increasingly <strong>conditional nature of citizenship</u></strong>, <u>for example, <mark>migrants</mark>, the <mark>underage</mark>, and <mark>drug-users</u></mark>, <u>all of whom are <strong><mark>not incorporated within</mark> the framework of regulatory <mark>protection</strong></mark>. </u>Thus in both systems, <u>the moral engineering of advanced <strong><mark>liberal governance</mark> has <mark>co-opted feminist concerns</strong></mark> <mark>into <strong>techniques of</mark> governance and <mark>control</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Whether based on a recognition of</strong> sex workers' inherent <strong>agency</strong> or victimhood, <strong>social exclusion is being used</strong> as leverage for <strong>increased control rather than for increased social justice</u></strong>. <u>Empowerment</u> simply <u>operates to <strong>sanction forms of self-governance</strong> that support neo-liberal interests</u>. As Cruikshank notes, <u>the</u> recent <u>proliferation of <strong><mark>state</mark>-sponsored <mark>programmes of empowerment</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>must be <strong>treated with critical caution</u></strong></mark>, <u>as</u> <u><strong>even while they are utilizing</strong> the <strong>vocabulary of radical politics</u></strong>, <u><mark>their</mark> <strong><mark>promise of emancipation</strong> may be <strong>merely</mark> <mark>rhetorical</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>as they </mark>'endeavour to <strong><mark>operationalise</mark> the <mark>self-governing</mark> capacity</u></strong> <u>of the governed <mark>in the <strong>pursuit of</mark> <mark>governmental objectives'</u></strong></mark>. Yet what <u><mark>both</mark> <mark>processes</u></mark> do well is to <u><strong><mark>identify those who cannot perform</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong><mark>rendering them vulnerable</mark> <mark>to</mark> exclusion or <mark>banishment</mark>. </p></u></strong>
1NC
null
Off
429,913
13
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,947
The aff is a genealogical investigation that takes place through the affirmation of a right to die – Golder says that ruptures biopolitical control and medicalization of life in the realm of physician assisted suicide – it renders the law inoperative by turning its biopolitical enforcement mechanism in on itself
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The aff is a genealogical investigation that takes place through the affirmation of a right to die – Golder says that ruptures biopolitical control and medicalization of life in the realm of physician assisted suicide – it renders the law inoperative by turning its biopolitical enforcement mechanism in on itself</h4>
Case
null
null
430,056
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,948
GOP Majority would cut Obama EPA Regs
The Hill, 9/6
The Hill, 9/6
Republican Senate candidate Dan Sullivan blamed Obama and Senate Democrats for locking up the country's energy resources , vowing that a GOP-controlled Senate would be the best fix The Obama-Reid agenda has locked up America’s natural resources, burdened small businesses throughout the country with an avalanche of regulations and suffocated job growth through a complete disrespect for the rule of law He added that the Environmental Protection Agency, and Washington, D.C., are trying to "dictate how we manage our state-owned lands. That could all change, he explains, if voters put him, and fellow Republicans in charge If Republicans win the Senate in November, Sullivan says the GOP will make energy a priority. A Republican Senate would approve Keystone XL pipeline jobs, because Canada is our neighbor and ally," We’ll authorize more offshore development, because it’s good for coastal states and the rest of the country. We’ll seize the opportunity to expand our energy trade, because that will benefit our nation, and others who need energy – like Ukraine Republicans won't stop there, they will also work to block the administration's carbon pollution proposal for existing power plants, and other regulations the EPA is trying to finalize by next year
Sullivan blamed Obama and Senate Democrats for locking up the country's energy resources vowing that a GOP-controlled Senate would be the best fix He added that the E P A are trying to "dictate how we manage our state-owned lands That could all change if voters put Republicans in charge If Republicans win the Senate he GOP will make energy a priority Republicans will block the administration's carbon pollution proposal and other regulations the EPA is trying to finalize
[Laura Barron-Lopez, “Senate hopeful: GOP-majority would squash Obama's climate agenda” The Hill, http://thehill.com/policy/energy-environment/216827-senate-hopeful-gop-majority-would-squash-obamas-climate-agenda, CBE] Republican Senate candidate Dan Sullivan (Alaska) blamed President Obama and Senate Democrats for locking up the country's energy resources in the party's weekly address, vowing that a GOP-controlled Senate would be the best fix. Sullivan, who is challenging Sen. Mark Begich (D-Alaska) this year, worries for his three teenage daughters, who he claims won't be able to take advantage of the state's wealth of oil, natural gas, hydropower, and more, if the administration's regulatory agenda continues unchecked. "The Obama-Reid agenda has locked up America’s natural resources, burdened small businesses throughout the country with an avalanche of regulations and suffocated job growth through a complete disrespect for the rule of law," Sullivan said during the address on Saturday. He added that the Environmental Protection Agency, and Washington, D.C., are trying to "dictate how we manage our state-owned lands." That could all change, he explains, if voters put him, and fellow Republicans in charge. "The American Dream is resilient," he said. "All we need is new leadership in Washington to make it happen once again." If Republicans win the Senate in November, Sullivan says the GOP will make energy a priority. "A Republican Senate would approve Keystone XL pipeline jobs, because Canada is our neighbor and ally," Sullivan said. “We’ll authorize more offshore development, because it’s good for coastal states and the rest of the country. We’ll seize the opportunity to expand our energy trade, because that will benefit our nation, and others who need energy – like Ukraine," he added. Republicans won't stop there, they will also work to block the administration's carbon pollution proposal for existing power plants, and other regulations the EPA is trying to finalize by next year. Sullivan accused the administration and Democrats of being "stuck in the last century" tied to a system of "burdensome federal regulations" that is "stifling" the nation.
2,187
<h4><u><strong>GOP Majority would cut Obama EPA Regs</h4><p>The Hill, 9/6</p><p></u></strong>[Laura Barron-Lopez, “Senate hopeful: GOP-majority would squash Obama's climate agenda” The Hill, http://thehill.com/policy/energy-environment/216827-senate-hopeful-gop-majority-would-squash-obamas-climate-agenda, CBE]</p><p><u>Republican Senate candidate Dan <mark>Sullivan</u></mark> (Alaska) <u><mark>blamed</u></mark> President <u><mark>Obama</u></mark> <u><mark>and</u> <u>Senate Democrats for locking up the country's energy resources</u></mark> in the party's weekly address<u>, <mark>vowing that a GOP-controlled Senate would be the best fix</u></mark>. Sullivan, who is challenging Sen. Mark Begich (D-Alaska) this year, worries for his three teenage daughters, who he claims won't be able to take advantage of the state's wealth of oil, natural gas, hydropower, and more, if the administration's regulatory agenda continues unchecked. "<u>The Obama-Reid agenda has locked up America’s natural resources, burdened small businesses throughout the country with an avalanche of regulations and suffocated job growth through a complete disrespect for the rule of law</u>," Sullivan said during the address on Saturday. <u><mark>He added that the E</mark>nvironmental <mark>P</mark>rotection <mark>A</mark>gency, and Washington, D.C., <mark>are trying to "dictate how we manage our state-owned lands</mark>.</u>" <u><mark>That could all change</mark>, he explains, <mark>if voters put</mark> him, and fellow <mark>Republicans in charge</u></mark>. "The American Dream is resilient," he said. "All we need is new leadership in Washington to make it happen once again." <u><mark>If Republicans win the Senate</mark> in November, Sullivan says t<mark>he GOP will make energy a priority</mark>. </u>"<u>A Republican Senate would approve Keystone XL pipeline jobs, because Canada is our neighbor and ally,"</u> Sullivan said. “<u>We’ll authorize more offshore development, because it’s good for coastal states and the rest of the country. We’ll seize the opportunity to expand our energy trade, because that will benefit our nation, and others who need energy – like Ukraine</u>," he added. <u><mark>Republicans</mark> won't stop there, they <mark>will</mark> also work to <mark>block the administration's carbon pollution proposal</mark> for existing power plants, <mark>and other regulations the EPA is trying to finalize</mark> by next year</u>. Sullivan accused the administration and Democrats of being "stuck in the last century" tied to a system of "burdensome federal regulations" that is "stifling" the nation.</p>
2NC
DA
IL
429,530
6
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,949
The medical industrial complex claims itself a savior, concealing its true nature as a nemesis – an epidemic that destroys more than it heals –bureaucratization has ushered in a culture of overtreatment and deferral of malpractice, resulting in the spread of iatrogenic disease and proliferation of suffering
null
Illich 76
during the¶ last century doctors have affected epidemics no more profoundly than priests¶ during earlier times. Epidemics are not modified any more by the rituals performed in¶ medical clinics than by those customary at religious shrines Tuberculosis consumption Cholera, dysentery, and¶ typhoid peaked and dwindled outside the physician's control. By the time¶ their etiology was understood and their therapy had become specific, these diseases¶ had lost much of their virulence and hence their social importance. by far the most¶ important factor was a higher host-resistance due to better nutrition In England, by the middle¶ of the nineteenth century, infectious epidemics had been replaced by major¶ malnutrition syndromes These peaked and¶ vanished, to be replaced by the diseases of early childhood When these declined, the modern¶ epidemics took over: coronary heart disease, emphysema, bronchitis, obesity,¶ hypertension, cancer we have no complete explanation for¶ the genesis of these changes. the professional practice¶ of physicians cannot be credited with the elimination of old forms of mortality or¶ morbidity, nor should it be blamed for the increased expectancy of life For more than a century, analysis of disease trends¶ has shown that the environment is the primary determinant of the state of general health of any population. food water air sociopolitical equality play¶ the decisive role in determining how healthy grown-ups feel and at what age adults¶ tend to die Some modern techniques have also effected changes in¶ general health, but to a lesser degree this does not consign soap, pincers,¶ vaccination needles, delousing preparations, or condoms to the category of "medical¶ equipment. shifts in mortality from younger to older groups can¶ be explained by the incorporation of these procedures and devices into the layman's¶ culture.¶ the specifically medical treatment of people is never significantly related to a decline in the compound disease burden or to a rise in life expectancy Neither¶ the proportion of doctors in a population nor the clinical tools at their disposal nor¶ the number of hospital beds is a causal factor in the striking changes in over-all¶ patterns of disease. new techniques redefine but do not reduce morbidity. The¶ fact that the doctor population is higher where certain diseases have become rare¶ has little to do with the doctors' ability to control or eliminate them. It simply¶ means that doctors deploy themselves as they like, medical technology has combined with egalitarian rhetoric to create the impression that contemporary medicine is highly effective procedures which are applicable to widespread diseases are usually very¶ inexpensive and require a minimum of skills and services most of today's skyrocketing medical¶ expenditures are destined for the kind of diagnosis and treatment whose¶ effectiveness is doubtful. The rising rate of venereal¶ disease is due to new mores, not to ineffectual medicine. The reappearance of¶ malaria is due to pesticide-resistant mosquitoes and not new drugs for most infections medicine can show no comparable results The effectiveness of medical intervention in combatting noninfectious diseases is¶ even more questionable survival rates for cancer 90 percent of the cases—have¶ remained virtually unchanged over the last twenty-five years. The pain, dysfunction, disability, and anguish resulting from technical medical¶ intervention now rival the morbidity due to traffic and industrial accidents and even war-related activities, and make the impact of medicine one of the most rapidly spreading epidemics of our time. only¶ modern malnutrition injures more people than iatrogenic disease clinical iatrogenic¶ disease comprises all clinical conditions for which remedies, physicians, or¶ hospitals are the pathogens, or "sickening" agents. Medicines have always been potentially poisonous, but their unwanted sideeffects¶ have increased with their power and widespread use. Some take the wrong drug;¶ others get an old or a contaminated batch, and others a counterfeit others take¶ several drugs in dangerous combinations Some drugs are addictive, others mutilating, and¶ others mutagenic In some patients, antibiotics alter the normal bacterial flora and induce¶ a superinfection Other drugs contribute to the breeding of drug-resistant strains of bacteria. Subtle kinds of poisoning thus have spread even faster Unnecessary surgery is standard treatment of nonexistent diseases¶ and are on the increase the number of children disabled in Massachusetts¶ through the treatment of cardiac non-disease exceeds the number of children under¶ effective treatment for real cardiac disease. With the transformation of the doctor from an artisan exercising a¶ skill on personally known individuals into a technician applying scientific rules to¶ classes of patients, malpractice acquired an anonymous, almost respectable status. . In¶ a complex technological hospital, negligence becomes "random human error" or¶ "system breakdown," callousness becomes "scientific detachment," and¶ incompetence becomes "a lack of specialized equipment." in malpractice¶ cases, doctors are vulnerable only to the charge of having acted against the medical code 7 percent of all patients suffer compensable injuries while hospitalized Moreover, the frequency of reported accidents in¶ hospitals is higher than in all industries but mines and high-rise construction.¶ Half of these episodes result from complications¶ of drug therapy one in ten from diagnostic procedures
during the¶ last century doctors have affected epidemics no more profoundly than priests Tuberculosis consumption Cholera, dysentery typhoid peaked and dwindled outside the physician's control. the most¶ important factor was a higher host-resistance due to better nutrition modern¶ epidemics took over: coronary heart disease, emphysema, bronchitis, obesity,¶ hypertension, cancer the professional practice¶ of physicians cannot be credited with the elimination of old forms of mortality or¶ morbidity, nor should it be blamed for the increased expectancy of life disease trends show that the environment is the primary determinant of the state of general¶ health of any population shifts in mortality from younger to older groups can¶ be explained by the incorporation of these procedures and devices into the layman's¶ culture the specifically medical treatment of people is never significantly related¶ to a decline in the compound disease burden or to a rise in life expectancy doctors deploy themselves as they like medical technology has combined with egalitarian rhetoric to create the impression that contemporary medicine is highly effective procedures applicable to widespread diseases are inexpensive and require a minimum of skills most of today's skyrocketing medical¶ expenditures are destined for the kind of diagnosis and treatment whose¶ effectiveness is doubtful survival rates for cancer 90 percent of cases have¶ remained unchanged over the last twenty-five years anguish resulting from technical medical¶ intervention rival the morbidity due to traffic accidents and war and make the impact of medicine one of the most rapidly¶ spreading epidemics of our time. only¶ malnutrition injures more than iatrogenic disease Medicines unwanted sideeffects¶ have increased Some take the wrong drug;¶ others get a contaminated batch, and others a counterfeit others take dangerous combinations drugs are addictive mutilating mutagenic In some patients, antibiotics alter the normal bacterial and induce¶ a superinfection Other drugs contribute to the breeding of drug-resistant strains of bacteria. Subtle kinds of poisoning thus have spread even faster Unnecessary surgery is standard treatment of nonexistent diseases¶ and are on the increase With the transformation of the doctor from an artisan to a technician malpractice acquired an anonymous respectable status negligence becomes "random human error" callousness becomes "scientific detachment," in malpractice cases, doctors are vulnerable only to the charge of having acted¶ against the medical code 7 percent of all patients suffer compensable injuries while hospitalized Half of these episodes result from complications¶ of drug therapy
Ivan, Ph.D from the University of Salzburg, Medical Nemesis, 1976 p. 95-96 SJE The study of the evolution of disease patterns provides evidence that during the¶ last century doctors have affected epidemics no more profoundly than did priests¶ during earlier times. Epidemics came and went, imprecated by both but touched by¶ neither. They are not modified any more decisively by the rituals performed in¶ medical clinics than by those customary at religious shrines.8 Discussion of the¶ future of health care might usefully begin with the recognition of this fact. The infections that prevailed at the outset of the industrial age illustrate how¶ medicine came by its reputation.9 Tuberculosis, for instance, reached a peak over¶ two generations. In New York in 1812, the death rate was estimated to be higher¶ than 700 per 10,000; by 1882, when Koch first isolated and cultured the bacillus, it¶ had already declined to 370 per 10,000. The rate was down to 180 when the first¶ sanatorium was opened in 1910, even though "consumption" still held second place¶ in the mortality tables,10 After World War II, but before antibiotics became routine,¶ it had slipped into eleventh place with a rate of 48. Cholera, dysentery, and¶ typhoid similarly peaked and dwindled outside the physician's control. By the time¶ their etiology was understood and their therapy had become specific, these diseases¶ had lost much of their virulence and hence their social importance. The combined¶ death rate from scarlet fever, diphtheria, whooping cough, and measles among¶ children up to fifteen shows that nearly 90 percent of the total decline in mortality¶ between 1860 and 1965 had occurred before the introduction of antibiotics and¶ widespread immunization.13 In part this recession may be attributed to improved¶ housing and to a decrease in the virulence of micro-organisms, but by far the most¶ important factor was a higher host-resistance due to better nutrition. In poor¶ countries today, diarrhea and upper-respiratory-tract infections occur more¶ frequently, last longer, and lead to higher mortality where nutrition is poor, no¶ matter how much or how little medical care is available.14 In England, by the middle¶ of the nineteenth century, infectious epidemics had been replaced by major¶ malnutrition syndromes, such as rickets and pellagra. These in turn peaked and¶ vanished, to be replaced by the diseases of early childhood and, somewhat later, by¶ an increase in duodenal ulcers in young men. When these declined, the modern¶ epidemics took over: coronary heart disease, emphysema, bronchitis, obesity,¶ hypertension, cancer (especially of the lungs), arthritis, diabetes, and so-called¶ mental disorders. Despite intensive research, we have no complete explanation for¶ the genesis of these changes.15 But two things are certain: the professional practice¶ of physicians cannot be credited with the elimination of old forms of mortality or¶ morbidity, nor should it be blamed for the increased expectancy of life spent in¶ suffering from the new diseases. For more than a century, analysis of disease trends¶ has shown that the environment is the primary determinant of the state of general¶ health of any population.16 Medical geography,17 the history of diseases,18 medical¶ anthropology,19 and the social history of attitudes towards illness20 have shown that¶ food,21 water,22 and air,23 in correlation with the level of sociopolitical equality24 and¶ the cultural mechanisms that make it possible to keep the population stable,25 play¶ the decisive role in determining how healthy grown-ups feel and at what age adults¶ tend to die. As the older causes of disease recede, a new kind of malnutrition is¶ becoming the most rapidly expanding modern epidemic.26 One-third of humanity¶ survives on a level of undernourishment which would formerly have been lethal,¶ while more and more rich people absorb ever greater amounts of poisons and¶ mutagens in their food. Some modern techniques, often developed with the help of doctors, and optimally¶ effective when they become part of the culture and environment or when they are¶ applied independently of professional delivery, have also effected changes in¶ general health, but to a lesser degree. Among these can be included contraception,¶ smallpox vaccination of infants, and such nonmedical health measures as the treatment of water and sewage, the use of soap and scissors by midwives, and some¶ antibacterial and insecticidal procedures. The importance of many of these¶ practices was first recognized and stated by doctors—often courageous dissidents¶ who suffered for their recommendations28—but this does not consign soap, pincers,¶ vaccination needles, delousing preparations, or condoms to the category of "medical¶ equipment." The most recent shifts in mortality from younger to older groups can¶ be explained by the incorporation of these procedures and devices into the layman's¶ culture.¶ In contrast to environmental improvements and modern nonprofessional health¶ measures, the specifically medical treatment of people is never significantly related¶ to a decline in the compound disease burden or to a rise in life expectancy. Neither¶ the proportion of doctors in a population nor the clinical tools at their disposal nor¶ the number of hospital beds is a causal factor in the striking changes in over-all¶ patterns of disease. The new techniques for recognizing and treating such¶ conditions as pernicious anemia and hypertension, or for correcting congenital¶ malformations by surgical intervention, redefine but do not reduce morbidity. The¶ fact that the doctor population is higher where certain diseases have become rare¶ has little to do with the doctors' ability to control or eliminate them.30 It simply¶ means that doctors deploy themselves as they like, more so than other¶ professionals, and that they tend to gather where the climate is healthy, where the¶ water is clean, and where people are employed and can pay for their services. Useless Medical Treatment¶ Awe-inspiring medical technology has combined with egalitarian rhetoric to create the impression that contemporary medicine is highly effective. Undoubtedly,¶ during the last generation, a limited number of specific procedures have become¶ extremely useful. But where they are not monopolized by professionals as tools of¶ their trade, those which are applicable to widespread diseases are usually very¶ inexpensive and require a minimum of personal skills, materials, and custodial¶ services from hospitals. In contrast, most of today's skyrocketing medical¶ expenditures are destined for the kind of diagnosis and treatment whose¶ effectiveness at best is doubtful. To make this point I will distinguish between¶ infectious and noninfectious diseases.¶ In the case of infectious diseases, chemotherapy has played a significant role in¶ the control of pneumonia, gonorrhea, and syphilis. Death from pneumonia, once¶ the "old man's friend," declined yearly by 5 to 8 percent after sulphonamides and¶ antibiotics came on the market. Syphilis, yaws, and many cases of malaria and¶ typhoid can be cured quickly and easily. The rising rate of venereal¶ disease is due to new mores, not to ineffectual medicine. The reappearance of¶ malaria is due to the development of pesticide-resistant mosquitoes and not to any¶ lack of new antimalarial drugs. Immunization has almost wiped out paralytic¶ poliomyelitis, a disease of developed countries, and vaccines have certainly contributed to the decline of whooping cough and measles,34 thus seeming to¶ confirm the popular belief in "medical progress." 35 But for most other infections,¶ medicine can show no comparable results. Drug treatment has helped to reduce¶ mortality from tuberculosis, tetanus, diphtheria, and scarlet fever, but in the total¶ decline of mortality or morbidity from these diseases, chemotherapy played a minor¶ and possibly insignificant role.36 Malaria, leishmaniasis, and sleeping sickness¶ indeed receded for a time under the onslaught of chemical attack, but are now on¶ the rise again.37¶ The effectiveness of medical intervention in combatting noninfectious diseases is¶ even more questionable. In some situations and for some conditions, effective¶ progress has indeed been demonstrated: the partial prevention of caries through¶ fluoridation of water is possible, though at a cost not fully understood.38¶ Replacement therapy lessens the direct impact of diabetes, though only in the short¶ run.39 Through intravenous feeding, blood transfusions, and surgical techniques,¶ more of those who get to the hospital survive trauma, but survival rates for the most¶ common types of cancer—those which make up 90 percent of the cases—have¶ remained virtually unchanged over the last twenty-five years. This fact has¶ consistently been clouded by announcements from the American Cancer Society¶ reminiscent of General Westmoreland's proclamations from Vietnam. On the other¶ hand, the diagnostic value of the Papanicolaou vaginal smear test has been proved:¶ if the tests are given four times a year, early intervention for cervical cancer¶ demonstrably increases the five-year survival rate. Some skin-cancer treatment is¶ highly effective. But there is little evidence of effective treatment of most other¶ cancers.40 The five-year survival rate in breast-cancer cases is 50 percent, regardless¶ of the frequency of medical check-ups and regardless of the treatment used.41 Nor is¶ there evidence that the rate differs from that among untreated women. Although¶ practicing doctors and the publicists of the medical establishment stress the¶ importance of early detection and treatment of this and several other types of¶ cancer, epidemiologists have begun to doubt that early intervention can alter the¶ rate of survival.42 Surgery and chemotherapy for rare congenital and rheumatic¶ heart disease have increased the chances for an active life for some of those who¶ suffer from degenerative conditions.43 The medical treatment of common¶ cardiovascular disease44 and the intensive treatment of heart disease,45 however, are¶ effective only when rather exceptional circumstances combine that are outside the¶ physician's control. The drug treatment of high blood pressure is effective and¶ warrants the risk of side-effects in the few in whom it is a malignant condition; it¶ represents a considerable risk of serious harm, far outweighing any proven benefit,¶ for the 10 to 20 million Americans on whom rash artery-plumbers are trying to foist¶ it.46¶ Doctor-Inflicted Injuries¶ Unfortunately, futile but otherwise harmless medical care is the least important of¶ the damages a proliferating medical enterprise inflicts on contemporary society.¶ The pain, dysfunction, disability, and anguish resulting from technical medical¶ intervention now rival the morbidity due to traffic and industrial accidents and even war-related activities, and make the impact of medicine one of the most rapidly¶ spreading epidemics of our time. Among murderous institutional torts, only¶ modern malnutrition injures more people than iatrogenic disease in its various¶ manifestations.47 In the most narrow sense, iatrogenic disease includes only¶ illnesses that would not have come about if sound and professionally recommended¶ treatment had not been applied.48 Within this definition, a patient could sue his¶ therapist if the latter, in the course of his management, failed to apply a¶ recommended treatment that, in the physician's opinion, would have risked making¶ him sick. In a more general and more widely accepted sense, clinical iatrogenic¶ disease comprises all clinical conditions for which remedies, physicians, or¶ hospitals are the pathogens, or "sickening" agents. I will call this plethora of¶ therapeutic side-effects clinical iatrogenesis. They are as old as medicine itself,49¶ and have always been a subject of medical studies.50¶ Medicines have always been potentially poisonous, but their unwanted sideeffects¶ have increased with their power and widespread use.52 Every twenty-four to¶ thirty-six hours, from 50 to 80 percent of adults in the United States and the United¶ Kingdom swallow a medically prescribed chemical. Some take the wrong drug;¶ others get an old or a contaminated batch, and others a counterfeit;53 others take¶ several drugs in dangerous combinations;54 and still others receive injections with¶ improperly sterilized syringes.55 Some drugs are addictive, others mutilating, and¶ others mutagenic, although perhaps only in combination with food coloring or¶ insecticides. In some patients, antibiotics alter the normal bacterial flora and induce¶ a superinfection, permitting more resistant organisms to proliferate and invade the¶ host. Other drugs contribute to the breeding of drug-resistant strains of bacteria. Subtle kinds of poisoning thus have spread even faster than the bewildering variety¶ and ubiquity of nostrums.57 Unnecessary surgery is a standard procedure.58¶ Disabling nondiseases result from the medical treatment of nonexistent diseases¶ and are on the increase:59 the number of children disabled in Massachusetts¶ through the treatment of cardiac non-disease exceeds the number of children under¶ effective treatment for real cardiac disease.60¶ Doctor-inflicted pain and infirmity have always been a part of medical practice.61¶ Professional callousness, negligence, and sheer incompetence are age-old forms of¶ malpractice.62 With the transformation of the doctor from an artisan exercising a¶ skill on personally known individuals into a technician applying scientific rules to¶ classes of patients, malpractice acquired an anonymous, almost respectable status.63¶ What had formerly been considered an abuse of confidence and a moral fault can¶ now be rationalized into the occasional breakdown of equipment and operators. In¶ a complex technological hospital, negligence becomes "random human error" or¶ "system breakdown," callousness becomes "scientific detachment," and¶ incompetence becomes "a lack of specialized equipment." The depersonalization of¶ diagnosis and therapy has changed malpractice from an ethical into a technical¶ problem.64¶ In 1971, between 12,000 and 15,000 malpractice suits were lodged in United¶ States courts. Less than half of all malpractice claims were settled in less than¶ eighteen months, and more than 10 percent of such claims remain unsettled for over six years. Between 16 and 20 percent of every dollar paid in malpractice¶ insurance went to compensate the victim; the rest was paid to lawyers and medical¶ experts.65 In such cases, doctors are vulnerable only to the charge of having acted¶ against the medical code, of the incompetent performance of prescribed treatment,¶ or of dereliction out of greed or laziness. The problem, however, is that most of the¶ damage inflicted by the modern doctor does not fall into any of these categories.66 It¶ occurs in the ordinary practice of well-trained men and women who have learned to¶ bow to prevailing professional judgment and procedure, even though they know (or¶ could and should know) what damage they do.¶ The United States Department of Health, Education, and Welfare calculates that 7 percent of all patients suffer compensable injuries while hospitalized, though few of¶ them do anything about it. Moreover, the frequency of reported accidents in¶ hospitals is higher than in all industries but mines and high-rise construction.¶ Accidents are the major cause of death in American children. In proportion to the¶ time spent there, these accidents seem to occur more often in hospitals than in any¶ other kind of place. One in fifty children admitted to a hospital suffers an accident¶ which requires specific treatment.67 University hospitals are relatively more¶ pathogenic, or, in blunt language, more sickening. It has also been established that¶ one out of every five patients admitted to a typical research hospital acquires an¶ iatrogenic disease, sometimes trivial, usually requiring special treatment, and in¶ one case in thirty leading to death. Half of these episodes result from complications¶ of drug therapy; amazingly, one in ten comes from diagnostic procedures.68 Despite¶ good intentions and claims to public service, a military officer with a similar record¶ of performance would be relieved of his command, and a restaurant or amusement¶ center would be closed by the police. No wonder that the health industry tries to¶ shift the blame for the damage caused onto the victim, and that the dope-sheet of a¶ multinational pharmaceutical concern tells its readers that "iatrogenic disease is¶ almost always of neurotic origin."
16,711
<h4><strong>The medical industrial complex claims itself a savior, concealing its true nature as a nemesis – an epidemic that destroys more than it heals –bureaucratization has ushered in a culture of overtreatment and deferral of malpractice, resulting in the spread of iatrogenic disease and proliferation of suffering</h4><p></strong>Illich 76</p><p>Ivan, Ph.D from the University of Salzburg, Medical Nemesis, 1976 p. 95-96 SJE</p><p>The study of the evolution of disease patterns provides evidence that <u><strong><mark>during the¶ last century doctors have affected epidemics no more profoundly than</u></strong></mark> did <u><strong><mark>priests</mark>¶ during earlier times. Epidemics</u></strong> came and went, imprecated by both but touched by¶ neither. They <u><strong>are not modified any more</u></strong> decisively <u><strong>by the rituals performed in¶ medical clinics than by those customary at religious shrines</u></strong>.8 Discussion of the¶ future of health care might usefully begin with the recognition of this fact. The infections that prevailed at the outset of the industrial age illustrate how¶ medicine came by its reputation.9 <u><strong><mark>Tuberculosis</u></strong></mark>, for instance, reached a peak over¶ two generations. In New York in 1812, the death rate was estimated to be higher¶ than 700 per 10,000; by 1882, when Koch first isolated and cultured the bacillus, it¶ had already declined to 370 per 10,000. The rate was down to 180 when the first¶ sanatorium was opened in 1910, even though "<u><strong><mark>consumption</u></strong></mark>" still held second place¶ in the mortality tables,10 After World War II, but before antibiotics became routine,¶ it had slipped into eleventh place with a rate of 48. <u><strong><mark>Cholera, dysentery</mark>, and¶ <mark>typhoid</mark> </u></strong>similarly <u><strong><mark>peaked and dwindled outside the physician's control.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>By the time¶ their etiology was understood and their therapy had become specific, these diseases¶ had lost much of their virulence and hence their social importance.</u></strong> The combined¶ death rate from scarlet fever, diphtheria, whooping cough, and measles among¶ children up to fifteen shows that nearly 90 percent of the total decline in mortality¶ between 1860 and 1965 had occurred before the introduction of antibiotics and¶ widespread immunization.13 In part this recession may be attributed to improved¶ housing and to a decrease in the virulence of micro-organisms, but <u><strong>by far <mark>the most¶ important factor was a higher host-resistance due to better nutrition</u></strong></mark>. In poor¶ countries today, diarrhea and upper-respiratory-tract infections occur more¶ frequently, last longer, and lead to higher mortality where nutrition is poor, no¶ matter how much or how little medical care is available.14 <u><strong>In England, by the middle¶ of the nineteenth century, infectious epidemics had been replaced by major¶ malnutrition syndromes</u></strong>, such as rickets and pellagra. <u><strong>These</u></strong> in turn <u><strong>peaked and¶ vanished, to be replaced by the diseases of early childhood</u></strong> and, somewhat later, by¶ an increase in duodenal ulcers in young men. <u><strong>When these declined, the <mark>modern¶ epidemics took over: coronary heart disease, emphysema, bronchitis, obesity,¶ hypertension, cancer</u></strong></mark> (especially of the lungs), arthritis, diabetes, and so-called¶ mental disorders. Despite intensive research, <u><strong>we have no complete explanation for¶ the genesis of these changes.</u></strong>15 But two things are certain: <u><strong><mark>the professional practice¶ of physicians cannot be credited with the elimination of old forms of mortality or¶ morbidity, nor should it be blamed for the increased expectancy of life</u></strong></mark> spent in¶ suffering from the new diseases. <u><strong>For more than a century, analysis of <mark>disease trends</mark>¶ has <mark>show</mark>n <mark>that the environment is the primary determinant of the state of general</u></strong>¶<u><strong> health of any population</mark>.</u></strong>16 Medical geography,17 the history of diseases,18 medical¶ anthropology,19 and the social history of attitudes towards illness20 have shown that¶ <u><strong>food</u></strong>,21 <u><strong>water</u></strong>,22 and <u><strong>air</u></strong>,23 in correlation with the level of <u><strong>sociopolitical equality</u></strong>24 and¶ the cultural mechanisms that make it possible to keep the population stable,25 <u><strong>play¶ the decisive role in determining how healthy grown-ups feel and at what age adults¶ tend to die</u></strong>. As the older causes of disease recede, a new kind of malnutrition is¶ becoming the most rapidly expanding modern epidemic.26 One-third of humanity¶ survives on a level of undernourishment which would formerly have been lethal,¶ while more and more rich people absorb ever greater amounts of poisons and¶ mutagens in their food. <u><strong>Some modern techniques</u></strong>, often developed with the help of doctors, and optimally¶ effective when they become part of the culture and environment or when they are¶ applied independently of professional delivery, <u><strong>have also effected changes in¶ general health, but to a lesser degree</u></strong>. Among these can be included contraception,¶ smallpox vaccination of infants, and such nonmedical health measures as the treatment of water and sewage, the use of soap and scissors by midwives, and some¶ antibacterial and insecticidal procedures. The importance of many of these¶ practices was first recognized and stated by doctors—often courageous dissidents¶ who suffered for their recommendations28—but <u><strong>this does not consign soap, pincers,¶ vaccination needles, delousing preparations, or condoms to the category of "medical¶ equipment.</u></strong>" The most recent <u><strong><mark>shifts in mortality from younger to older groups can¶ be explained by the incorporation of these procedures and devices into the layman's¶ culture</mark>.¶ </u></strong>In contrast to environmental improvements and modern nonprofessional health¶ measures, <u><strong><mark>the specifically medical treatment of people is never significantly related</u></strong>¶<u><strong> to a decline in the compound disease burden or to a rise in life expectancy</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Neither¶ the proportion of doctors in a population nor the clinical tools at their disposal nor¶ the number of hospital beds is a causal factor in the striking changes in over-all¶ patterns of disease.</u></strong> The <u><strong>new techniques</u></strong> for recognizing and treating such¶ conditions as pernicious anemia and hypertension, or for correcting congenital¶ malformations by surgical intervention, <u><strong>redefine but do not reduce morbidity. The¶ fact that the doctor population is higher where certain diseases have become rare¶ has little to do with the doctors' ability to control or eliminate them.</u></strong>30 <u><strong>It simply¶ means that <mark>doctors deploy themselves as they like</mark>,</u></strong> more so than other¶ professionals, and that they tend to gather where the climate is healthy, where the¶ water is clean, and where people are employed and can pay for their services. Useless Medical Treatment¶ Awe-inspiring <u><strong><mark>medical technology has combined with egalitarian rhetoric to create the impression that contemporary medicine is highly effective</u></strong></mark>. Undoubtedly,¶ during the last generation, a limited number of specific <u><strong><mark>procedures</u></strong></mark> have become¶ extremely useful. But where they are not monopolized by professionals as tools of¶ their trade, those <u><strong>which are <mark>applicable to widespread diseases are</mark> usually very¶ <mark>inexpensive and require a minimum of</u></strong></mark> personal <u><strong><mark>skills</u></strong></mark>, materials, <u><strong>and</u></strong> custodial¶ <u><strong>services</u></strong> from hospitals. In contrast, <u><strong><mark>most of today's skyrocketing medical¶ expenditures are destined for the kind of diagnosis and treatment whose¶ effectiveness</u></strong></mark> at best <u><strong><mark>is doubtful</mark>.</u></strong> To make this point I will distinguish between¶ infectious and noninfectious diseases.¶ In the case of infectious diseases, chemotherapy has played a significant role in¶ the control of pneumonia, gonorrhea, and syphilis. Death from pneumonia, once¶ the "old man's friend," declined yearly by 5 to 8 percent after sulphonamides and¶ antibiotics came on the market. Syphilis, yaws, and many cases of malaria and¶ typhoid can be cured quickly and easily. <u><strong>The rising rate of venereal¶ disease is due to new mores, not to ineffectual medicine. The reappearance of¶ malaria is due to</u></strong> the development of <u><strong>pesticide-resistant mosquitoes and not</u></strong> to any¶ lack of <u><strong>new</u></strong> antimalarial <u><strong>drugs</u></strong>. Immunization has almost wiped out paralytic¶ poliomyelitis, a disease of developed countries, and vaccines have certainly contributed to the decline of whooping cough and measles,34 thus seeming to¶ confirm the popular belief in "medical progress." 35 But <u><strong>for most</u></strong> other <u><strong>infections</u></strong>,¶ <u><strong>medicine can show no comparable results</u></strong>. Drug treatment has helped to reduce¶ mortality from tuberculosis, tetanus, diphtheria, and scarlet fever, but in the total¶ decline of mortality or morbidity from these diseases, chemotherapy played a minor¶ and possibly insignificant role.36 Malaria, leishmaniasis, and sleeping sickness¶ indeed receded for a time under the onslaught of chemical attack, but are now on¶ the rise again.37¶ <u><strong>The effectiveness of medical intervention in combatting noninfectious diseases is¶ even more questionable</u></strong>. In some situations and for some conditions, effective¶ progress has indeed been demonstrated: the partial prevention of caries through¶ fluoridation of water is possible, though at a cost not fully understood.38¶ Replacement therapy lessens the direct impact of diabetes, though only in the short¶ run.39 Through intravenous feeding, blood transfusions, and surgical techniques,¶ more of those who get to the hospital survive trauma, but <u><strong><mark>survival rates for</mark> </u></strong>the most¶ common types of <u><strong><mark>cancer</u></strong></mark>—those which make up <u><strong><mark>90 percent of</mark> the <mark>cases</mark>—<mark>have¶ remained</mark> virtually <mark>unchanged over the last twenty-five years</mark>.</u></strong> This fact has¶ consistently been clouded by announcements from the American Cancer Society¶ reminiscent of General Westmoreland's proclamations from Vietnam. On the other¶ hand, the diagnostic value of the Papanicolaou vaginal smear test has been proved:¶ if the tests are given four times a year, early intervention for cervical cancer¶ demonstrably increases the five-year survival rate. Some skin-cancer treatment is¶ highly effective. But there is little evidence of effective treatment of most other¶ cancers.40 The five-year survival rate in breast-cancer cases is 50 percent, regardless¶ of the frequency of medical check-ups and regardless of the treatment used.41 Nor is¶ there evidence that the rate differs from that among untreated women. Although¶ practicing doctors and the publicists of the medical establishment stress the¶ importance of early detection and treatment of this and several other types of¶ cancer, epidemiologists have begun to doubt that early intervention can alter the¶ rate of survival.42 Surgery and chemotherapy for rare congenital and rheumatic¶ heart disease have increased the chances for an active life for some of those who¶ suffer from degenerative conditions.43 The medical treatment of common¶ cardiovascular disease44 and the intensive treatment of heart disease,45 however, are¶ effective only when rather exceptional circumstances combine that are outside the¶ physician's control. The drug treatment of high blood pressure is effective and¶ warrants the risk of side-effects in the few in whom it is a malignant condition; it¶ represents a considerable risk of serious harm, far outweighing any proven benefit,¶ for the 10 to 20 million Americans on whom rash artery-plumbers are trying to foist¶ it.46¶ Doctor-Inflicted Injuries¶ Unfortunately, futile but otherwise harmless medical care is the least important of¶ the damages a proliferating medical enterprise inflicts on contemporary society.¶ <u><strong>The pain, dysfunction, disability, and <mark>anguish resulting from technical medical¶ intervention</mark> now <mark>rival the morbidity due to traffic</mark> and industrial <mark>accidents and</mark> even <mark>war</mark>-related activities, <mark>and make the impact of medicine one of the most rapidly</u></strong>¶<u><strong> spreading epidemics of our time.</u></strong></mark> Among murderous institutional torts, <u><strong><mark>only¶ </mark>modern <mark>malnutrition injures more </mark>people <mark>than iatrogenic disease</u></strong></mark> in its various¶ manifestations.47 In the most narrow sense, iatrogenic disease includes only¶ illnesses that would not have come about if sound and professionally recommended¶ treatment had not been applied.48 Within this definition, a patient could sue his¶ therapist if the latter, in the course of his management, failed to apply a¶ recommended treatment that, in the physician's opinion, would have risked making¶ him sick. In a more general and more widely accepted sense, <u><strong>clinical iatrogenic¶ disease comprises all clinical conditions for which remedies, physicians, or¶ hospitals are the pathogens, or "sickening" agents.</u></strong> I will call this plethora of¶ therapeutic side-effects clinical iatrogenesis. They are as old as medicine itself,49¶ and have always been a subject of medical studies.50¶ <u><strong><mark>Medicines</mark> have always been potentially poisonous, but their <mark>unwanted sideeffects¶ have increased</mark> with their power and widespread use.</u></strong>52 Every twenty-four to¶ thirty-six hours, from 50 to 80 percent of adults in the United States and the United¶ Kingdom swallow a medically prescribed chemical. <u><strong><mark>Some take the wrong drug;¶ others get</mark> an old or <mark>a contaminated batch, and others a counterfeit</u></strong></mark>;53 <u><strong><mark>others take</mark>¶ several drugs in <mark>dangerous combinations</u></strong></mark>;54 and still others receive injections with¶ improperly sterilized syringes.55 <u><strong>Some <mark>drugs are addictive</mark>, others <mark>mutilating</mark>, and¶ others <mark>mutagenic</u></strong></mark>, although perhaps only in combination with food coloring or¶ insecticides. <u><strong><mark>In some patients, antibiotics alter the normal bacterial</mark> flora <mark>and induce¶ a superinfection</u></strong></mark>, permitting more resistant organisms to proliferate and invade the¶ host. <u><strong><mark>Other drugs contribute to the breeding of drug-resistant strains of bacteria.</u></strong> <u><strong>Subtle kinds of poisoning thus have spread even faster</u></strong></mark> than the bewildering variety¶ and ubiquity of nostrums.57 <u><strong><mark>Unnecessary surgery is</mark> </u></strong>a <u><strong><mark>standard</u></strong></mark> procedure.58¶ Disabling nondiseases result from the medical <u><strong><mark>treatment of nonexistent diseases¶ and are on the increase</u></strong></mark>:59 <u><strong>the number of children disabled in Massachusetts¶ through the treatment of cardiac non-disease exceeds the number of children under¶ effective treatment for real cardiac disease.</u></strong>60¶ Doctor-inflicted pain and infirmity have always been a part of medical practice.61¶ Professional callousness, negligence, and sheer incompetence are age-old forms of¶ malpractice.62 <u><strong><mark>With the transformation of the doctor from an artisan</mark> exercising a¶ skill on personally known individuals in<mark>to a technician</mark> applying scientific rules to¶ classes of patients, <mark>malpractice acquired an anonymous</mark>, almost <mark>respectable status</mark>.</u></strong>63¶ What had formerly been considered an abuse of confidence and a moral fault can¶ now be rationalized into the occasional breakdown of equipment and operators<u><strong>. In¶ a complex technological hospital, <mark>negligence becomes "random human error"</mark> or¶ "system breakdown," <mark>callousness becomes "scientific detachment,"</mark> and¶ incompetence becomes "a lack of specialized equipment."</u></strong> The depersonalization of¶ diagnosis and therapy has changed malpractice from an ethical into a technical¶ problem.64¶ In 1971, between 12,000 and 15,000 malpractice suits were lodged in United¶ States courts. Less than half of all malpractice claims were settled in less than¶ eighteen months, and more than 10 percent of such claims remain unsettled for over six years. Between 16 and 20 percent of every dollar paid <u><strong><mark>in malpractice</mark>¶ </u></strong>insurance went to compensate the victim; the rest was paid to lawyers and medical¶ experts.65 In such <u><strong><mark>cases, doctors are vulnerable only to the charge of having acted</u></strong>¶<u><strong> against the medical code</u></strong></mark>, of the incompetent performance of prescribed treatment,¶ or of dereliction out of greed or laziness. The problem, however, is that most of the¶ damage inflicted by the modern doctor does not fall into any of these categories.66 It¶ occurs in the ordinary practice of well-trained men and women who have learned to¶ bow to prevailing professional judgment and procedure, even though they know (or¶ could and should know) what damage they do.¶ The United States Department of Health, Education, and Welfare calculates that <u><strong><mark>7 percent of all patients suffer compensable injuries while hospitalized</u></strong></mark>, though few of¶ them do anything about it. <u><strong>Moreover, the frequency of reported accidents in¶ hospitals is higher than in all industries but mines and high-rise construction.¶ </u></strong>Accidents are the major cause of death in American children. In proportion to the¶ time spent there, these accidents seem to occur more often in hospitals than in any¶ other kind of place. One in fifty children admitted to a hospital suffers an accident¶ which requires specific treatment.67 University hospitals are relatively more¶ pathogenic, or, in blunt language, more sickening. It has also been established that¶ one out of every five patients admitted to a typical research hospital acquires an¶ iatrogenic disease, sometimes trivial, usually requiring special treatment, and in¶ one case in thirty leading to death. <u><strong><mark>Half of these episodes result from complications¶ of drug therapy</u></strong></mark>; amazingly, <u><strong>one in ten </u></strong>comes <u><strong>from diagnostic procedures</u></strong>.68 Despite¶ good intentions and claims to public service, a military officer with a similar record¶ of performance would be relieved of his command, and a restaurant or amusement¶ center would be closed by the police. No wonder that the health industry tries to¶ shift the blame for the damage caused onto the victim, and that the dope-sheet of a¶ multinational pharmaceutical concern tells its readers that "iatrogenic disease is¶ almost always of neurotic origin." </p>
null
1AC
null
201,016
2
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,950
The affirmative is built on a fantasy of legal incorporation which serves only to continue the displacement of black and trans bodies into zones of sacrifice through a presumption of personhood as property – we need to reconstruct humanity through an affirmation of the liminal spaces of not-quite-humans
Weheliye 14
Weheliye 14 (Alexander Weheliye, Associate Professor of African American Studies at Northwestern University, 2014, “Habeas Viscus: Racializing Assemblages, Biopolitics, and Black Feminist Theories of the Human,” pp 81-2) gz
We are in dire need of alternatives to the legal conception of personhood that dominates our world, and, in addition, to not lose sight of what remains outside the law, what the law cannot capture, what it cannot magically transform into the fantastic form of property ownership. the connections between transgender politics and other forms of identity- based activism that respond to structural inequalities the focus on inclusion, recognition, and equality based on a narrow legal framework (especially as it pertains to antidiscrimination and hate crime laws) not only hinders the eradication of violence against trans people and other vulnerable populations but actually creates the condition of possibility for the continued unequal “distribution of life chances If demanding recognition and inclusion remains at the center of minority politics, it will lead only to a delimited notion of personhood as property that zeroes in comparatively on only one form of subjugation at the expense of others, thus allowing for the continued existence of hierarchical differences between full humans, not- quite- humans, and nonhumans. This can be gleaned from the “successes” of the mainstream feminist, civil rights, and lesbian- gay rights movements, which facilitate the incorporation of a privileged minority into the ethnoclass of Man at the cost of the still and/or newly criminalized and disposable populations (women of color, the black poor, trans people, the incarcerated, etc To make claims for inclusion and humanity via the U.S. juridical assemblage removes from view that the law itself has been thoroughly violent in its endorsement of racial slavery, indigenous genocide, Jim Crow, the prison- industrial complex, domestic and international warfare, and so on, and that it continues to be one of the chief instruments in creating and maintaining the racializing assemblages in the world of Man Instead of appealing to legal recognition Oparah suggests counteracting the “racialized (trans)gender entrapment” within the prison- industrial complex and beyond with practices of “maroon abolition to “foreground the ways in which often overlooked African diasporic cultural and political legacies inform and undergird anti- prison work,” while also providing strategies and life worlds not exclusively centered on reforming the law a radical politics articulated from the “‘impossible’ worldview of trans political existence,” which redefines “the insistence of government agencies, social service providers, media, and many nontrans activists and nonprofiteers that the existence of trans people is impossible A relational maroon abolitionism beholden to the practices of black radicalism and that arises from the incompatibility of black trans existence with the world of Man serves as one example of how putatively abject modes of being need not be redeployed within hegemonic frameworks but can be operationalized as variable liminal territories or articulated assemblages in movements to abolish the grounds upon which all forms of subjugation are administered
We are in dire need of alternatives to legal personhood and to not lose sight of what remains outside the law, what the law cannot capture cannot transform into property ownership the focus on inclusion, recognition, and equality based on a legal framework as it pertains to antidiscrimination not only hinders the eradication of violence against trans people and other populations but creates the condition of possibility for unequal “distribution of life chances recognition and inclusion will lead only to personhood as property that zeroes in on one form of subjugation at the expense of others allowing for hierarchical differences between full humans, not- quite- humans, and nonhumans mainstream civil rights movements facilitate the incorporation of a privileged minority into Man at the cost of criminalized and disposable populations (women of color, the black poor, trans people, the incarcerated, etc the law itself has been thoroughly violent in racial slavery, indigenous genocide, Jim Crow, the prison- industrial complex, domestic and international warfare and continues to be one of the chief instruments in maintaining the racializing assemblages of Man Instead of legal recognition Oparah suggests counteracting racialized (trans)gender entrapment with maroon abolition while providing strategies and life worlds not centered on reforming the law a radical politics from the “‘impossible’ worldview of trans political existence A relational maroon abolitionism beholden to black radicalism that arises from the incompatibility of black trans existence with Man serves as how abject modes of being need not be redeployed within hegemonic frameworks but can be operationalized as liminal territories or articulated assemblages to abolish subjugation
We are in dire need of alternatives to the legal conception of personhood that dominates our world, and, in addition, to not lose sight of what remains outside the law, what the law cannot capture, what it cannot magically transform into the fantastic form of property ownership. Writing about the connections between transgender politics and other forms of identity- based activism that respond to structural inequalities, legal scholar Dean Spade shows how the focus on inclusion, recognition, and equality based on a narrow legal framework (especially as it pertains to antidiscrimination and hate crime laws) not only hinders the eradication of violence against trans people and other vulnerable populations but actually creates the condition of possibility for the continued unequal “distribution of life chances.” 22 If demanding recognition and inclusion remains at the center of minority politics, it will lead only to a delimited notion of personhood as property that zeroes in comparatively on only one form of subjugation at the expense of others, thus allowing for the continued existence of hierarchical differences between full humans, not- quite- humans, and nonhumans. This can be gleaned from the “successes” of the mainstream feminist, civil rights, and lesbian- gay rights movements, which facilitate the incorporation of a privileged minority into the ethnoclass of Man at the cost of the still and/or newly criminalized and disposable populations (women of color, the black poor, trans people, the incarcerated, etc.). 23 To make claims for inclusion and humanity via the U.S. juridical assemblage removes from view that the law itself has been thoroughly violent in its endorsement of racial slavery, indigenous genocide, Jim Crow, the prison- industrial complex, domestic and international warfare, and so on, and that it continues to be one of the chief instruments in creating and maintaining the racializing assemblages in the world of Man. Instead of appealing to legal recognition, Julia Oparah suggests counteracting the “racialized (trans)gender entrapment” within the prison- industrial complex and beyond with practices of “maroon abolition” (in reference to the long history of escaped slave contraband settlements in the Americas) to “foreground the ways in which often overlooked African diasporic cultural and political legacies inform and undergird anti- prison work,” while also providing strategies and life worlds not exclusively centered on reforming the law. 24 Relatedly, Spade calls for a radical politics articulated from the “‘impossible’ worldview of trans political existence,” which redefines “the insistence of government agencies, social service providers, media, and many nontrans activists and nonprofiteers that the existence of trans people is impossible.” 25 A relational maroon abolitionism beholden to the practices of black radicalism and that arises from the incompatibility of black trans existence with the world of Man serves as one example of how putatively abject modes of being need not be redeployed within hegemonic frameworks but can be operationalized as variable liminal territories or articulated assemblages in movements to abolish the grounds upon which all forms of subjugation are administered.
3,270
<h4>The affirmative is built on a fantasy of legal incorporation which serves only to continue the displacement of black and trans bodies into zones of sacrifice through a presumption of personhood as property – we need to reconstruct humanity through an affirmation of the liminal spaces of not-quite-humans</h4><p><u><strong>Weheliye 14</u></strong> (Alexander Weheliye, Associate Professor of African American Studies at Northwestern University, 2014, “Habeas Viscus: Racializing Assemblages, Biopolitics, and Black Feminist Theories of the Human,” pp 81-2) gz</p><p><u><mark>We are in dire need of <strong>alternatives to</mark> the <mark>legal</mark> conception of <mark>personhood</strong></mark> that dominates our world, <mark>and</mark>, in addition, <mark>to not lose sight of what remains <strong>outside the law</strong>, what the law <strong>cannot capture</strong></mark>, what it <mark>cannot</mark> magically <mark>transform into</mark> the fantastic form of <strong><mark>property ownership</strong></mark>.</u> Writing about <u>the connections between transgender politics and other forms of identity- based activism that respond to structural inequalities</u>, legal scholar Dean Spade shows how <u><mark>the <strong>focus on inclusion, recognition, and equality</strong> based on a</mark> narrow <strong><mark>legal framework</strong></mark> (especially <mark>as it pertains to <strong>antidiscrimination</strong></mark> and hate crime laws) <mark>not only <strong>hinders the eradication of violence against trans people and other</mark> vulnerable <mark>populations</strong> but</mark> actually <strong><mark>creates the condition of possibility</strong> for</mark> the continued <strong><mark>unequal “distribution of life chances</u></strong></mark>.” 22 <u>If demanding <strong><mark>recognition and inclusion</strong></mark> remains at the center of minority politics, it <mark>will lead only to </mark>a delimited notion of <strong><mark>personhood as property</strong> that zeroes in</mark> comparatively <mark>on</mark> only <mark>one form of subjugation at <strong>the expense of others</strong></mark>, thus <mark>allowing for</mark> the continued existence of <strong><mark>hierarchical differences</strong> between full humans, not- quite- humans, and nonhumans</mark>. This can be gleaned from the “successes” of the <strong><mark>mainstream</mark> feminist, <mark>civil rights</mark>, and lesbian- gay rights <mark>movements</strong></mark>, which <mark>facilitate the</mark> <strong><mark>incorporation of a privileged minority into</mark> the ethnoclass of <mark>Man</strong> at the cost of</mark> the still and/or newly <strong><mark>criminalized and disposable populations</strong> (women of color, the black poor, trans people, the incarcerated, etc</u></mark>.). 23 <u>To make claims for inclusion and humanity via the U.S. <strong>juridical assemblage</strong> removes from view that <strong><mark>the law itself has been thoroughly violent</strong> in</mark> its endorsement of <strong><mark>racial slavery</strong>, <strong>indigenous genocide</strong>, <strong>Jim Crow</strong>, the <strong>prison- industrial complex</strong>, <strong>domestic and international warfare</strong></mark>, and so on, <mark>and</mark> that it <mark>continues to be one of the chief instruments in</mark> creating and <strong><mark>maintaining the racializing assemblages</mark> in the world <mark>of Man</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>Instead of</mark> appealing to <mark>legal recognition</u></mark>, Julia <u><mark>Oparah suggests counteracting</mark> the “<mark>racialized (trans)gender entrapment</mark>” within the prison- industrial complex and beyond <mark>with</mark> practices of “<strong><mark>maroon abolition</u></strong></mark>” (in reference to the long history of escaped slave contraband settlements in the Americas) <u>to “foreground the ways in which often overlooked African diasporic cultural and political legacies inform and undergird anti- prison work,” <mark>while</mark> also <mark>providing strategies and life worlds <strong>not</mark> exclusively <mark>centered on reforming the law</u></strong></mark>. 24 Relatedly, Spade calls for <u><mark>a radical politics</mark> articulated <mark>from the <strong>“‘impossible’ worldview of trans political existence</strong></mark>,” which redefines “the insistence of government agencies, social service providers, media, and many nontrans activists and nonprofiteers that the existence of trans people is impossible</u>.” 25 <u><mark>A <strong>relational maroon abolitionism</strong> beholden to</mark> the practices of <mark>black radicalism</mark> and <mark>that arises from the <strong>incompatibility of black trans existence with</mark> the world of <mark>Man</strong> serves as</mark> one example of <mark>how</mark> putatively <mark>abject modes of being <strong>need not be redeployed within hegemonic frameworks</strong> but can be operationalized as</mark> <strong>variable <mark>liminal territories or articulated assemblages</strong></mark> in movements <mark>to <strong>abolish </mark>the grounds</strong> upon which all forms of <mark>subjugation</mark> are administered</u>.</p>
1NC
null
Off
313,349
69
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,951
The 1AC’s act of countermemory through genealogy is key to dismantling notions of liberal subjecthood the current medicalized order relies on – it’s a process of cutting away what makes us subjects in order to open space for transformation
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The 1AC’s act of countermemory through genealogy is key to dismantling notions of liberal subjecthood the current medicalized order relies on – it’s a process of cutting away what makes us subjects in order to open space for transformation</h4>
Case
null
null
430,057
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,952
This isn’t just theory – for-profit enterprises control medical resource allocation and the rate of iatrogenic disease is higher than ever
Biley 10
Biley 10
Thirty years after the publication of Medical Nemesis, the work would appear accurately prophetic malnutrition and infectious disease are more important A few simple, inexpensive approaches such as immunization is most appropriate only a few people worldwide¶ have access to truly beneficial medical interventions. these are given¶ lower priorities than sophisticated medical technology , a system was created that: “brought in the entrepreneurial forces and put greater control in self serving institutions Since then, the driving force has been to “profit” from health care ”Managed care” has¶ been largely motivated by the recognition of those outside medicine of the potential profit¶ from an expanding “market There has been an expansion of medicine into a wide range¶ of personal and societal spheres including diet weight baldness sexual potency influence and power¶ has shifted…to for-profit organisations Empirical evidence to support the increasing medicalisation of life and medical iatrogenesis is so extensive that it is almost overwhelming. One review found evidence of significant risk from just about all areas of health care. In acute hospital care¶ adverse events occurred in 3.7% of all cases and 69% were attributable to medical error from a one year sample of 325 patients, 12.6% of patients had been admitted as a result of “iatrogenic disease”
Medical Nemesis would appear accurately prophetic malnutrition and infectious disease are more important simple, inexpensive approaches such as immunization is most appropriate only a few have access to beneficial medical interventions these…are given¶ lower priorities than sophisticated medical technology a system was created that: “brought in entrepreneurial forces and put greater control in self serving institutions the driving force has been to “profit” from health care There has been an expansion of medicine into a wide range¶ of personal and societal spheres diet weight baldness sexual potency power¶ has shifted…to for-profit organisations Empirical evidence to support the increasing medicalisation of life and medical iatrogenesis is so¶ extensive that it is almost overwhelming In hospital care¶ adverse events occurred in 3.7% of all cases and 69% were attributable to medical error.¶ from a one year sample of 325 12.6% of patients had been¶ admitted as a result of “iatrogenic disease
Francis, Ph.D in Medical Humanities from University of Wales College of Medicine, professor of Nursing at Seton Hall University, “The ‘Sickening’ Search for Health: Ivan Illich’s revised thoughts on the medicalization of life and medical iatrogenesis,” The International Journal of Healing and Caring, Vol. 10:2, May 2010 SJE Thirty years after the publication of Medical Nemesis, the work would appear to have been, to a far¶ greater extent, accurately prophetic. For instance, in a recent article Barnet states (2003, p. 276):¶ “…malnutrition and infectious disease, including typhoid, malaria, dysentery, cholera and¶ now AIDS, Ebola and SARS, are more important issues. A few simple, inexpensive approaches such as immunization, simple antibiotics and intravenous fluids with the means¶ to administer them, are often what is most appropriate. Yet only a few people worldwide¶ have access to truly beneficial medical interventions. Unfortunately, these…are often given¶ lower priorities than sophisticated medical technology”. Barnet goes on to say that, at least in the U.S and from the time of the health reforms of the 90’s, a system was created that: “brought in the entrepreneurial forces and put greater control in self serving institutions…¶ Since then, the driving force has been to “profit” from health care... ”Managed care” has¶ been largely motivated by the recognition of those outside medicine of the potential profit¶ from an expanding “market”… There has been an expansion of medicine into a wide range¶ of personal and societal spheres including not only diet, weight reduction, exercise but¶ more recently baldness and sexual potency… Many of the conditions that are identified as¶ illnesses are the result of modern distortions of human activity… The influence and power¶ has shifted…to for-profit organisations” (p. 282).¶ Empirical evidence to support the increasing medicalisation of life and medical iatrogenesis is so¶ extensive that it is almost overwhelming. One review of medical errors (Weingart et al., 2000)¶ found evidence of significant risk from just about all areas of health care. In acute hospital care¶ adverse events occurred in 3.7% of all cases and 69% of these were attributable to medical error.¶ In intensive care units, medical practitioners made 1.7 errors per patient day. In out-patient care,¶ 18% of patients experienced drug-related complications.¶ Patients are not only likely to encounter errors while they are hospitalized in intensive care units,¶ but they are in some cases hospitalized in the first place as a result of medical error. For instance,¶ Trunet et al. (1980) found that from a one year sample of 325 patients, 12.6% of patients had been¶ admitted as a result of “iatrogenic disease” [sic, author’s own emphasis], which was life-threatening¶ in one case in every twenty, and fatal in eight cases.¶ Finally, post-discharge statistics reveal the longer-term dangers of medical care. For example, it¶ was found in a study of 400 discharged patients that 76 experienced adverse events following¶ discharge, of which 23 were thought to be preventable, and 3% resulted in permanent disability¶ (Forster et al., 2003).
3,180
<h4><strong>This isn’t just theory – for-profit enterprises control medical resource allocation and the rate of iatrogenic disease is higher than ever </h4><p>Biley 10</p><p></strong>Francis, Ph.D in Medical Humanities from University of Wales College of Medicine, professor of Nursing at Seton Hall University, “The ‘Sickening’ Search for Health: Ivan Illich’s revised thoughts on the medicalization of life and medical iatrogenesis,” The International Journal of Healing and Caring, <strong>Vol. 10:2, May 2010 SJE</p><p><u>Thirty years after the publication of <mark>Medical Nemesis</mark>, the work <mark>would appear</u></strong></mark> to have been, to a far¶ greater extent, <u><strong><mark>accurately prophetic</u></strong></mark>. For instance, in a recent article Barnet states (2003, p. 276):¶ “…<u><strong><mark>malnutrition and infectious disease</u></strong></mark>, including typhoid, malaria, dysentery, cholera and¶ now AIDS, Ebola and SARS, <u><strong><mark>are more important</u></strong></mark> issues. <u><strong>A few <mark>simple, inexpensive approaches such as immunization</u></strong></mark>, simple antibiotics and intravenous fluids with the means¶ to administer them, are often what <u><strong><mark>is most appropriate</u></strong></mark>. Yet <u><strong><mark>only a few</mark> people worldwide¶ <mark>have access to</mark> truly <mark>beneficial medical interventions</mark>.</u></strong> Unfortunately, <u><strong><mark>these</u></strong>…<u><strong>are</u></strong></mark> often <u><strong><mark>given¶ lower</mark> <mark>priorities than sophisticated medical technology</u></strong></mark>”. Barnet goes on to say that, at least in the U.S and from the time of the health reforms of the 90’s<u><strong>, <mark>a system was created that: “brought in</mark> the <mark>entrepreneurial forces and put greater control in self serving institutions</u></strong></mark>…¶ <u><strong>Since then, <mark>the driving force has been to “profit” from health care</u></strong></mark>... <u><strong>”Managed care” has¶ been largely motivated by the recognition of those outside medicine of the potential profit¶ from an expanding “market</u></strong>”… <u><strong><mark>There has been an expansion of medicine into a wide range¶ of personal and societal spheres </mark>including </u></strong>not only <u><strong><mark>diet</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong><mark>weight</u></strong></mark> reduction, exercise but¶ more recently <u><strong><mark>baldness</u></strong></mark> and <u><strong><mark>sexual potency</u></strong></mark>… Many of the conditions that are identified as¶ illnesses are the result of modern distortions of human activity… The <u><strong>influence and <mark>power¶ has shifted…to for-profit organisations</u></strong></mark>” (p. 282).¶ <u><strong><mark>Empirical evidence to support the increasing medicalisation of life and medical iatrogenesis is so</u></strong>¶<u><strong> extensive that it is almost overwhelming</mark>. One review</u></strong> of medical errors (Weingart et al., 2000)¶<u><strong> found evidence of significant risk from just about all areas of health care. <mark>In</mark> acute <mark>hospital care¶ adverse events occurred in 3.7% of all cases and 69%</u></strong></mark> of these <u><strong><mark>were attributable to medical error</u></strong>.¶</mark> In intensive care units, medical practitioners made 1.7 errors per patient day. In out-patient care,¶ 18% of patients experienced drug-related complications.¶ Patients are not only likely to encounter errors while they are hospitalized in intensive care units,¶ but they are in some cases hospitalized in the first place as a result of medical error. For instance,¶ Trunet et al. (1980) found that <u><strong><mark>from a one year sample of 325</mark> patients, <mark>12.6% of patients had been</u></strong>¶<u><strong> admitted as a result of “iatrogenic disease</mark>”</u></strong> [sic, author’s own emphasis], which was life-threatening¶ in one case in every twenty, and fatal in eight cases.¶ Finally, post-discharge statistics reveal the longer-term dangers of medical care. For example, it¶ was found in a study of 400 discharged patients that 76 experienced adverse events following¶ discharge, of which 23 were thought to be preventable, and 3% resulted in permanent disability¶ (Forster et al., 2003). </p>
null
1AC
null
430,058
2
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,953
No risk of protectionism
Kim 13
Kim 13 Soo Yeon Kim, of the National University of Singapore, associate professor of music at Nazareth College of Rochester, New York, Fellow of the Transatlantic Academy, based at the German Marshall Fund of the United States, The Monkey Cage, January 30, 2013, " Protectionism During Recessions: Is This Time Different?", http://themonkeycage.org/blog/2013/01/30/protectionism-during-recessions-is-this-time-different/
There is widespread agreement regarding the critical role of international institutions as “firewalls” against protectionism during recession institutions have served as conveyors of information and mechanisms of commitment and socialization information enhances the transparency and accountability of states’ trade policies, and mitigate uncertainty when it is running high the WTO and PTAs also lock in commitments to liberal trade through legal obligations that make defections costly institutions also propagate important norms such as commitment to liberal trading and cooperative economic behavior states have not resorted to large-scale protectionism during this recession scholarship also indicates that governments are likely to employ policy substitutes, opting for monetary autonomy when facing trade policy constraints, for example, due to membership in a preferential trade agreement Protectionist policies are not adopted by governments in a political vacuum to adopt trade defense measures such as anti-dumping duties, governments first conduct investigations Such investigations are initiated when firms apply for them “firms are central,” and over the years the export-dependent, multinational firm has evolved in tandem with the increasing complexity of the international supply chain. Today’s firm is not only heavily export-dependent but equally import-dependent in its reliance on intermediate inputs The extensive international supply chain thus often puts exporting and importing firms on the same side of the political debate
There is widespread agreement regarding international institutions as “firewalls” against protectionism institutions have served as conveyors of information and mechanisms of commitment and socialization the WTO and PTAs lock in commitments that make defections costly institutions propagate norms scholarship indicates governments are likely to employ policy substitutes, opting for monetary autonomy for example Protectionist policies are initiated when firms apply for them the multinational firm has evolved Today’s firm is not only heavily export-dependent but equally import-dependent international supply chain often puts firms on the same side of the political debate
The Great Recession of 2008: Who Resisted Protectionism? There is widespread agreement regarding the critical role of international institutions as “firewalls” against protectionism during this recession. Economic and non-economic international institutions have served as conveyors of information and mechanisms of commitment and socialization. Their informational function enhances the transparency and accountability of states’ trade policies, and they mitigate uncertainty when it is running high. Specialized international institutions devoted to trade, such as the WTO and preferential trade agreements (PTAs), also lock in commitments to liberal trade through legal obligations that make defections costly, thus creating accountability in the actions of its members. Equally important, international institutions are also arenas of socialization that help propagate important norms MARKED such as the commitment to the liberal trading system and cooperative economic behavior. In this connection, the degree to which a particular country was embedded in the global network of economic and non-economic international institutions has been found to be strongly correlated with fewer instances of protectionist trade measures. Information provided to date by international institutions, with the exception of the GTA project, largely agree that states have not resorted to large-scale protectionism during this recession, in spite of the fact that the “great trade collapse” at the beginning of the current crisis was steeper and more sudden than that of its Great Depression predecessor. The WTO Secretariat, in addition to its regular individual reports on members’ trade policies under the Trade Policy Review Mechanism (TPRM), has issued more than a dozen reports on member states’ trade policies during the crisis. At the request of the G-20 countries, which pledged not to adopt protectionist trade measures at the onset of the crisis in 2008, the WTO, the OECD, and UNCTAD have produced joint reports on the trade and investment measures of the world’s largest trading states. They, too, find that G-20 countries had largely adhered to their commitment not to raise trade and investment barriers. In the World Bank’s Temporary Trade Barriers (TTB) project, an important and unique data collection that includes information on pre-crisis and crisis trade policy behavior, Bown finds that temporary trade barriers such as safeguards, countervailing and antidumping duties saw only a slight increase of usage by developed countries, in the neighborhood of 4%. In contrast, emerging market economies were the heavy users of TTBs, whose usage rose by almost 40% between 2008 and 2009. As scholarly insights accumulate on the current recession and its impact on protectionism (or lack thereof), two questions emerge for further research. First, to what extent have governments employed policy substitutes that have the same effect as trade protectionism? International institutions may appear to have been successful in preventing protectionism, but governments may well have looked elsewhere to defend national economies. This question can be seen in the broader context of the “open economy trilemma,” in which governments may achieve only two of three macroeconomic policy objectives: stable exchange rates, stable prices, and open trade. Irwin argues that governments that abandoned the gold standard during the Great Depression were less protectionist, and their economies also suffered less from the recession. Existing scholarship also indicates that governments are likely to employ policy substitutes, opting for monetary autonomy when facing trade policy constraints, for example, due to membership in a preferential trade agreement. Moreover, at the time of writing, the International Monetary Fund (IMF) has announced that it has dropped its objections to capital controls, albeit cautiously and only under certain conditions, thus potentially providing another policy alternative for governments to achieve economic stability during this crisis. Future research may further extend the application to policy substitutes that are deployed during economic downturns. Finally, why did firms not push for more protection? Protectionist policies are not adopted by governments in a political vacuum. In order to adopt trade defense measures such as anti-dumping duties, governments first conduct investigations to assess the extent of injury. Such investigations are initiated when firms apply for them through the domestic political process. If indeed governments did not appeal extensively or unusually to protectionist trade policies, the explanation to a significant degree lies in firm behavior. A distinguished body of research exists in this area that is due for a revisit in the age of extensive international supply chains, from Schattschneider’s classic examination of the domestic pressures that led to the Smoot-Hawley Act to Helen Milner’s study of export-dependent firms that resisted protectionism during the crisis of the 1920s and the 1970s. Milner rightly pointed out that “firms are central,” and over the years the export-dependent, multinational firm has evolved in tandem with the increasing complexity of the international supply chain. Today’s firm is not only heavily export-dependent but equally import-dependent in its reliance on intermediate inputs, whether through intra-firm trade or from foreign firms. The extensive international supply chain thus often puts exporting and importing firms on the same side of the political debate, especially when they are members of large multinational firms. Moreover, the study of firm-level behavior must extend beyond the developed world to consider firms in emerging market economies, which have been the heavy users of trade defense measures during the current recession. How the internationalization of production, driven by investment and trade in intermediate goods, restrained multinational firms from pushing for more protection remains an important question for further research.
6,070
<h4><u><strong>No risk of protectionism</h4><p>Kim 13</p><p></strong>Soo Yeon Kim, of the National University of Singapore, associate professor of music at Nazareth College of Rochester, New York, Fellow of the Transatlantic Academy, based at the German Marshall Fund of the United States, The Monkey Cage, January 30, 2013, " Protectionism During Recessions: Is This Time Different?", http://themonkeycage.org/blog/2013/01/30/protectionism-during-recessions-is-this-time-different/</p><p></u>The Great Recession of 2008: Who Resisted Protectionism? <u><mark>There is widespread agreement regarding</mark> the critical role of <mark>international institutions as “firewalls” against protectionism</mark> during</u> this <u>recession</u>. Economic and non-economic international <u><mark>institutions have served as conveyors of information and mechanisms of commitment and socialization</u></mark>. Their <u>information</u>al function <u>enhances the transparency and accountability of states’ trade policies, and</u> they <u>mitigate uncertainty when it is running high</u>. Specialized international institutions devoted to trade, such as <u><mark>the WTO and</u></mark> preferential trade agreements (<u><mark>PTAs</u></mark>), <u>also <mark>lock in commitments</mark> to liberal trade through legal obligations <mark>that make defections costly</u></mark>, thus creating accountability in the actions of its members. Equally important, international <u><mark>institutions</u></mark> are <u>also</u> arenas of socialization that help <u><mark>propagate</mark> important <mark>norms</mark> </p><p></u>MARKED</p><p><u>such as</u> the <u>commitment to</u> the <u>liberal trading</u> system <u>and cooperative economic behavior</u>. In this connection, the degree to which a particular country was embedded in the global network of economic and non-economic international institutions has been found to be strongly correlated with fewer instances of protectionist trade measures. Information provided to date by international institutions, with the exception of the GTA project, largely agree that <u>states have not resorted to large-scale protectionism during this recession</u>, in spite of the fact that the “great trade collapse” at the beginning of the current crisis was steeper and more sudden than that of its Great Depression predecessor. The WTO Secretariat, in addition to its regular individual reports on members’ trade policies under the Trade Policy Review Mechanism (TPRM), has issued more than a dozen reports on member states’ trade policies during the crisis. At the request of the G-20 countries, which pledged not to adopt protectionist trade measures at the onset of the crisis in 2008, the WTO, the OECD, and UNCTAD have produced joint reports on the trade and investment measures of the world’s largest trading states. They, too, find that G-20 countries had largely adhered to their commitment not to raise trade and investment barriers. In the World Bank’s Temporary Trade Barriers (TTB) project, an important and unique data collection that includes information on pre-crisis and crisis trade policy behavior, Bown finds that temporary trade barriers such as safeguards, countervailing and antidumping duties saw only a slight increase of usage by developed countries, in the neighborhood of 4%. In contrast, emerging market economies were the heavy users of TTBs, whose usage rose by almost 40% between 2008 and 2009. As scholarly insights accumulate on the current recession and its impact on protectionism (or lack thereof), two questions emerge for further research. First, to what extent have governments employed policy substitutes that have the same effect as trade protectionism? International institutions may appear to have been successful in preventing protectionism, but governments may well have looked elsewhere to defend national economies. This question can be seen in the broader context of the “open economy trilemma,” in which governments may achieve only two of three macroeconomic policy objectives: stable exchange rates, stable prices, and open trade. Irwin argues that governments that abandoned the gold standard during the Great Depression were less protectionist, and their economies also suffered less from the recession. Existing <u><mark>scholarship</mark> also <mark>indicates</mark> that <mark>governments are likely to employ policy substitutes, opting for monetary autonomy</mark> when facing trade policy constraints, <mark>for example</mark>, due to membership in a preferential trade agreement</u>. Moreover, at the time of writing, the International Monetary Fund (IMF) has announced that it has dropped its objections to capital controls, albeit cautiously and only under certain conditions, thus potentially providing another policy alternative for governments to achieve economic stability during this crisis. Future research may further extend the application to policy substitutes that are deployed during economic downturns. Finally, why did firms not push for more protection? <u><mark>Protectionist policies</mark> are not adopted by governments in a political vacuum</u>. In order <u>to adopt trade defense measures such as anti-dumping duties, governments first conduct investigations</u> to assess the extent of injury. <u>Such investigations <mark>are initiated when firms apply for them</u></mark> through the domestic political process. If indeed governments did not appeal extensively or unusually to protectionist trade policies, the explanation to a significant degree lies in firm behavior. A distinguished body of research exists in this area that is due for a revisit in the age of extensive international supply chains, from Schattschneider’s classic examination of the domestic pressures that led to the Smoot-Hawley Act to Helen Milner’s study of export-dependent firms that resisted protectionism during the crisis of the 1920s and the 1970s. Milner rightly pointed out that <u>“firms are central,” and over the years <mark>the</mark> export-dependent, <mark>multinational firm has evolved</mark> in tandem with the increasing complexity of the international supply chain. <mark>Today’s firm is not only heavily export-dependent but equally import-dependent</mark> in its reliance on intermediate inputs</u>, whether through intra-firm trade or from foreign firms. <u>The extensive <mark>international supply chain</mark> thus <mark>often</mark> <mark>puts</mark> exporting and importing <mark>firms on the same side of the political debate</u></mark>, especially when they are members of large multinational firms. Moreover, the study of firm-level behavior must extend beyond the developed world to consider firms in emerging market economies, which have been the heavy users of trade defense measures during the current recession. How the internationalization of production, driven by investment and trade in intermediate goods, restrained multinational firms from pushing for more protection remains an important question for further research.</p>
2NC
DA
Trade
97,311
43
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,954
Their invocation of prostitutes reminds us that they are more than criminals, they are citizens, so we act because they deserve to live MORE LIKE US through the granting of autonomy via economic freedom. This empathetic witnessing is liberalism par excellence where debate is converted into a factory where subjectivity is produced and shipped out to the dispossessed other in sardine cans
Strick 14
Strick 14
, 2014, p. 132-6] The concluding argument concerns late modern figurations of the body in pain. Spectacles of pain have proliferated in many forms in the contemporary American public sphere if indeed pain hasn't become its primary and all-pervading obsession Confessional TV shows exchange narratives of personal trauma and hurt for public intelligibility spectacles of suffering news reports narrate national-scale catastrophes There is also a proliferation of political discourse disclosing the injuries caused by contemporary forms of governing critical discourses continue to shed light on the structural violence of regimes of power identitarian movements expand public recognition of social and political injury, changing the scope of intelligibility These diverse affective readily distinguishable in neoliberal regimes Brown or Ahmed have pointed out the coopting of identitarian politics in contemporary governmental regimes These critical voices urge "[c]aution . . . against the assumption that 'speaking out' within radical politics can be separated from self-expression in neoliberal forms of governance Obama's ongoing focus on a "politics of empathy" recognition of suffering to democratic progress Academic debates have matched this capitalization on pain and compassion as necessary ingredients to the development of politics, ethics, or community making various diagnoses of America as trauma culture describe a highly disparate tension-laden field of affective discourse rather than a unified fixation on pain in contemporary Western societies Berlant has argued that these politics of affect dictate the continuous envelopment of the political in sentimental rhetoric Sentimentalism holds up the promise that subjectivity is granted in the recognition of pain Sentimental discourses "locate the human in a universal capacity to suffer They] imagine a nonhierarchical social world that is . . . 'at heart' democratic because good intentions and love flourish in it" Sentimental rhetoric produces a public sphere assembled around pain bonded by feeling with what is unspeakable: a commonality of passionate and compassionate bodily subjects a "fantasy of generality through emotional likeness the emancipatory project of democracy relies on pain suffering, and a unified politics This is true for American culture and its foundational ideas The cultural sites participate in this public sphere where oppressive hurtings and social injuries are "counted in" toward a better politics of integration, understanding, and recognition The sentimental linkage indicates a larger genealogy that dominates American culture traced back to America's emancipatory foundation as a nation freed from colonial injury and informed by a national history of successful incorporations of marginalized subjects into the national project American dolorologies has related this discourse to an apparatus of cultural technologies such as compassion and affect and pain and the materializations of race and gender they covertly enact sentimentality has long been a popular rhetorical means by which pain is advanced This connection of pain, nation, and subjectivity has led to the public sphere becoming a site of intimate "affect" exchange This transformation is visible in the proliferation of mediatized forms of confession and other articulations of traumatized selfhood We can also see a . . . collusion between liberal, capitalist forms of mass entertainment and individualist therapies, and the feminist importance of the personal the articulation of trauma is furthermore supplemented by mainstream political discourse becoming compassionate and revolving primarily around the recognition of bodies in pain
Spectacles of pain have proliferated in the public sphere—if pain hasn't become its primary obsession shows exchange narratives of trauma for public intelligibility spectacles of suffering There is political discourse disclosing injuries caused by governing critical discourses shed light on structural violence movements expand public recognition changing the scope of intelligibility diverse affective coopt identitarian politics in contemporary regimes These urge "[c]aution . . . against the assumption that 'speaking out' within radical politics can be separated from self-expression in neoliberal forms of governance Academic debates have matched this capitalization on pain as necessary to politics, ethics, or community making diagnoses of America as trauma culture describe affective discourse these politics of affect dictate the envelopment of the political in sentimental rhetoric Sentimental discourses "locate the human in a universal capacity to suffer They] imagine a nonhierarchical social 'at heart' democratic because good intentions flourish in it Sentimental rhetoric produces a public sphere assembled around pain bonded by feeling what is unspeakable fantasy through emotional likeness This is true for American culture in this public sphere, where oppressive hurtings are "counted in" toward a better politics dolorologies has related this discourse to cultural tech such as compassion and affect This connection of pain, nation, and subjectivity has led to the public sphere becoming a site of intimate "affect" exchange We can see a . . . collusion between liberal, capitalist entertainment and individualist therapies trauma is supplemented by political discourse becoming compassionate and revolving around bodies in pain
[Simon, Postdoctoral Researcher at the Center for Literary and Cultural Research Berlin, American Dolorologies, 2014, p. 132-6] The concluding argument concerns late modern figurations of the body in pain. Spectacles of pain have proliferated in many forms in the contemporary American public sphere—if indeed pain hasn't become its primary and all-pervading obsession. Confessional TV shows exchange narratives of personal trauma and hurt for public intelligibility; cinematic spectacles of suffering, from The Passion of the Christ (2004) to torture-porn favorite Hostel (2005), exhibit the body in pain for profit, thrill, and public outrage; news reports narrate national-scale catastrophes through individual testimonials of pain; reality game shows such as Survivor measure their contestants' bodily pain capacities against their resistance to (or aggressiveness in) traumatizing and abusive group dynamics. There is also a proliferation of political discourse disclosing the injuries caused by contemporary forms of governing: public movements raise consciousness for excluded and abjected forms of living, feeling, and aching in Western democracies; critical discourses continue to shed light on the structural violence of regimes of power; the interventions of identitarian movements and groups successfully expand public recognition of social and political injury, changing the scope of intelligibility in the process.¶ These diverse affective phenomena are not always readily distinguishable in neoliberal regimes. Scholars such as Wendy Brown or Sara Ahmed have pointed out the coopting of identitarian politics in contemporary governmental regimes. These critical voices urge "[c]aution . . . against the assumption that 'speaking out' and 'making visible' within so-called radical politics can be separated from the conventions of self-expression in neoliberal forms of governance" (Ahmed and Stacey 2001, 4). Bill Clinton's infamous tagline "I feel your pain" or Barack Obama's ongoing focus on a "politics of empathy"1 are only the presidential cases in point for an ongoing politics of pain that links recognition of suffering to democratic progress. Academic debates have matched this capitalization on pain and compassion as necessary ingredients to the development of politics, ethics, or community making, such as in Rosi Braidotti's call for the unification of feminist, gay, lesbian, and transgender identity politics under the label of a "community of the suffering."2 The various diagnoses of America as "wound culture" (Seltzer 1998) or "trauma culture" (Kaplan 2005), in this view, describe a highly disparate, tension-laden, and ambivalent field of affective discourse, rather than a unified or unifying fixation on pain in contemporary Western societies.¶ Lauren Berlant has argued that these politics of affect dictate the continuous envelopment of the political in sentimental rhetoric. Sentimentalism holds up the promise that subjectivity is granted in the recognition of pain and that democracy is realized as the participation in an ideal of common suffering and compassion. Sentimental discourses "locate the human in a universal capacity to suffer and romantic conventions of individual historical acts of compassion and transcendence. [They] imagine a nonhierarchical social world that is . . . 'at heart' democratic because good intentions and love flourish in it" (2008, 6). Sentimental rhetoric produces a public sphere assembled around pain bonded by feeling with what is unspeakable: a commonality of passionate and compassionate bodily subjects, or a "fantasy of generality through emotional likeness in the domain of pain" (Berlant 2008, 6).¶ These arguments suggest a fundamental link between the sentimental evocation of pain and the discourses imagined as "at heart democratic." Indeed, the emancipatory project of democracy relies on articulations of pain, the recognition of those suffering, and a unified politics as remedy of this suffering. This is certainly true for American culture and its foundational ideas of promise and exceptionalism. The cultural sites I have pointed to participate in this evocation of a public sphere, where oppressive hurtings and social injuries are "counted in" toward a better politics of integration, understanding, and recognition. The sentimental linkage of emancipation through the circulation of pain and compassion as politics indicates a larger genealogy that dominates American culture and that this book has tried to elucidate. This genealogy was traced back to America's emancipatory foundation as a nation freed from colonial injury, and informed by a national history of successful incorporations of marginalized subjects into the national project (suffrage, abolitionism). American dolorologies has related this discourse to an apparatus of cultural technologies such as compassion, testimony to oppression, and articulations of affect and pain, and the materializations of race and gender they covertly enact. My analysis concurs with Berlant's observation that the various claims to pain as identity disarticulate their marginalizing effects in a rhetoric of universalization:¶ In the liberal tradition of the United States [testimony of pain] is not simply a mode of particularizing and puncturing self-description by minorities, but a rhetoric of universality located, not in abstract categories, but in what was thought to be, simultaneously, particular and universal experience. Indeed, it would not be exaggerating to say that sentimentality has long been a popular rhetorical means by which pain is advanced, in the United States, as the true core of personhood and citizenship. (2000, 34)¶ This connection of pain, nation, and subjectivity has, on the one hand, led to the public sphere becoming more and more a site of intimate "affect" exchange. This transformation is visible in the proliferation of mediatized forms of confession, testimony, and other articulations of traumatized selfhood, such as reality TV or the culture of therapeutic discourse. These governmental forms of achieving public subjectivity through speaking pain imitate and appropriate the critical formulations of differential experience from identitarian movements, at times becoming indistinguishable from them: "We can also see a . . . collusion between liberal, capitalist forms of mass entertainment and individualist therapies, and the feminist importance of the personal" (Ahmed 2000, 12). The achievement of public visibility through the articulation of trauma and pain is furthermore supplemented by mainstream political discourse becoming compassionate and revolving primarily around the recognition of bodies in pain.3¶
6,711
<h4>Their invocation of prostitutes reminds us that they are more than criminals, they are citizens, so we act because they deserve to live MORE LIKE US through the granting of autonomy via economic freedom. This empathetic witnessing is liberalism par excellence where debate is converted into a factory where subjectivity is produced and shipped out to the dispossessed other in sardine cans </h4><p><u><strong>Strick 14</u></strong> </p><p>[Simon, Postdoctoral Researcher at the Center for Literary and Cultural Research Berlin, American Dolorologies<u>, 2014, p. 132-6]</p><p>The concluding argument concerns late modern figurations of the body in pain. <strong><mark>Spectacles of pain</strong> have proliferated in</mark> many forms in <mark>the</mark> contemporary American <mark>public sphere</u>—<u>if</mark> indeed <mark>pain hasn't become its <strong>primary</strong></mark> and <strong>all-pervading</strong> <mark>obsession</u></mark>. <u>Confessional TV <mark>shows exchange narratives of</mark> personal <mark>trauma</mark> and hurt <mark>for public intelligibility</u></mark>; cinematic <u><mark>spectacles of suffering</u></mark>, from The Passion of the Christ (2004) to torture-porn favorite Hostel (2005), exhibit the body in pain for profit, thrill, and public outrage; <u>news reports narrate national-scale catastrophes</u> through individual testimonials of pain; reality game shows such as Survivor measure their contestants' bodily pain capacities against their resistance to (or aggressiveness in) traumatizing and abusive group dynamics. <u><mark>There is</mark> also a proliferation of <mark>political discourse disclosing</mark> the <mark>injuries caused by</mark> contemporary forms of <mark>governing</u></mark>: public movements raise consciousness for excluded and abjected forms of living, feeling, and aching in Western democracies; <u><strong><mark>critical discourses</strong></mark> continue to <strong><mark>shed light</strong> on</mark> the <strong><mark>structural violence</strong></mark> of regimes of power</u>; the interventions of <u>identitarian <mark>movements</u></mark> and groups successfully <u><strong><mark>expand public recognition</strong></mark> of social and political injury, <mark>changing the scope of intelligibility</u></mark> in the process.¶ <u>These <strong><mark>diverse affective </u></strong></mark>phenomena are not always <u><strong>readily distinguishable</strong> in neoliberal regimes</u>. Scholars such as Wendy <u>Brown or</u> Sara <u>Ahmed have pointed out the <strong><mark>coopt</mark>ing of <mark>identitarian politics</strong> in <strong>contemporary</strong></mark> governmental <strong><mark>regimes</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>These </mark>critical voices <mark>urge "[c]aution . . . against the assumption that 'speaking out'</u></mark> and 'making visible' <u><mark>within</u></mark> so-called <u><mark>radical politics can be separated from</u></mark> the conventions of <u><mark>self-expression in neoliberal forms of governance</u></mark>" (Ahmed and Stacey 2001, 4). Bill Clinton's infamous tagline "I feel your pain" or Barack <u><strong>Obama's ongoing focus</strong> on a "<strong>politics of empathy</strong>"</u>1 are only the presidential cases in point for an ongoing politics of pain that links <u>recognition of suffering to democratic progress</u>. <u><strong><mark>Academic debates</u></strong> <u>have matched this <strong>capitalization</strong> on pain</mark> and compassion <mark>as <strong>necessary</mark> ingredients</strong> <mark>to</mark> the development of <strong><mark>politics</strong>, <strong>ethics</strong>, or <strong>community making</u></strong></mark>, such as in Rosi Braidotti's call for the unification of feminist, gay, lesbian, and transgender identity politics under the label of a "community of the suffering."2 The <u>various <mark>diagnoses of America as</u></mark> "wound culture" (Seltzer 1998) or "<u><mark>trauma culture</u></mark>" (Kaplan 2005), in this view, <u><mark>describe</mark> a highly disparate</u>, <u>tension-laden</u>, and ambivalent <u>field of <strong><mark>affective discourse</u></strong></mark>, <u>rather than a unified</u> or unifying <u>fixation on pain in contemporary Western societies</u>.¶ Lauren <u>Berlant has argued that <mark>these <strong>politics of affect</strong> dictate the</mark> continuous <mark>envelopment of</mark> <mark>the <strong>political</strong> in <strong>sentimental rhetoric</u></strong></mark>. <u>Sentimentalism holds up the promise that subjectivity is granted in the recognition of pain</u> and that democracy is realized as the participation in an ideal of common suffering and compassion. <u><mark>Sentimental discourses "locate the human in a universal capacity to suffer</u></mark> and romantic conventions of individual historical acts of compassion and transcendence. [<u><mark>They] imagine a nonhierarchical social</mark> world that is . . . <mark>'at heart' democratic because good intentions</mark> and love <mark>flourish in it</mark>"</u> (2008, 6). <u><mark>Sentimental rhetoric produces a public sphere</mark> <mark>assembled around pain bonded by feeling</mark> with <strong><mark>what is unspeakable</strong></mark>: a commonality of passionate and compassionate bodily subjects</u>, or <u>a "<mark>fantasy</mark> of generality <mark>through emotional likeness</u></mark> in the domain of pain" (Berlant 2008, 6).¶ These arguments suggest a fundamental link between the sentimental evocation of pain and the discourses imagined as "at heart democratic." Indeed, <u>the emancipatory project of democracy relies on</u> articulations of <u>pain</u>, the recognition of those <u>suffering, and a unified politics</u> as remedy of this suffering. <u><mark>This is</u></mark> certainly <u><mark>true for American culture</mark> and its foundational ideas</u> of promise and exceptionalism. <u>The cultural sites</u> I have pointed to <u>participate <mark>in this</u></mark> evocation of a <u><strong><mark>public sphere</u></strong>, <u>where oppressive hurtings</mark> and social injuries <mark>are "counted in" toward a better politics</mark> of integration, understanding, and recognition</u>. <u>The <strong>sentimental linkage</u></strong> of emancipation through the circulation of pain and compassion as politics <u>indicates a larger genealogy that dominates American culture</u> and that this book has tried to elucidate. This genealogy was <u>traced back to America's emancipatory foundation as a nation freed from colonial injury</u>, <u>and informed by a national history of successful incorporations of marginalized subjects into the national project</u> (suffrage, abolitionism). <u>American <mark>dolorologies has related this discourse to</mark> an apparatus of <mark>cultural tech</mark>nologies <mark>such as compassion</u></mark>, testimony to oppression, <u><mark>and</u></mark> articulations of <u><mark>affect</mark> and pain</u>, <u>and the materializations of race and gender they covertly enact</u>. My analysis concurs with Berlant's observation that the various claims to pain as identity disarticulate their marginalizing effects in a rhetoric of universalization:¶ In the liberal tradition of the United States [testimony of pain] is not simply a mode of particularizing and puncturing self-description by minorities, but a rhetoric of universality located, not in abstract categories, but in what was thought to be, simultaneously, particular and universal experience. Indeed, it would not be exaggerating to say that <u><strong>sentimentality</u></strong> <u>has long been a popular rhetorical means by which pain is advanced</u>, in the United States, as the true core of personhood and citizenship. (2000, 34)¶ <u><mark>This connection of pain, nation, and subjectivity has</u></mark>, on the one hand, <u><mark>led to the public sphere becoming</u></mark> more and more <u><mark>a site of <strong>intimate "affect" exchange</u></strong></mark>. <u>This transformation is visible in the proliferation of mediatized forms of confession</u>, testimony, <u>and other articulations of traumatized selfhood</u>, such as reality TV or the culture of therapeutic discourse. These governmental forms of achieving public subjectivity through speaking pain imitate and appropriate the critical formulations of differential experience from identitarian movements, at times becoming indistinguishable from them: "<u><mark>We can</mark> also <mark>see a . . . collusion between</mark> <strong><mark>liberal, capitalist</strong></mark> forms of mass <mark>entertainment and individualist therapies</mark>, and the feminist importance of the personal</u>" (Ahmed 2000, 12). The achievement of public visibility through <u>the articulation of <mark>trauma</u></mark> and pain <u><mark>is</mark> furthermore <mark>supplemented by</mark> mainstream <mark>political discourse <strong>becoming compassionate</strong></mark> <mark>and revolving</mark> primarily <mark>around</mark> the recognition of <strong><mark>bodies in pain</u></strong></mark>.3¶ </p>
1NC
null
Off
98,587
104
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,955
Iatrogenesis is not just clinical but social, resulting in the displacement of populations and legitimizing ableist and capitalist violence – only an act which exposes the limits to professional dominance solves, rendering the radical monopoly self-destructive
null
Illich 76
**we modified some ableist stuff social iatrogenesis can escalate from an adventitious feature into an inherent characteristic of the medical system. When biomedical intervention crosses a critical threshold iatrogenesis turns from error into an incurable perversion of medical practice. when autonomy degenerates into a radical monopoly social iatrogenesis becomes¶ the main product of the medical organization when hospitals draft all those who are in critical condition, they impose on society a new form of dying social monopoly (stultifies) the output of nonmarketable use-values. Radical monopolies impose a society-wide substitution¶ of commodities for use-values by reshaping the milieu and by "appropriating" those¶ of its general characteristics which have enabled people so far to cope on their own. The malignant spread of medicine turns mutual care and self-medication into misdemeanors or felonies Just as clinical iatrogenesis becomes medically incurable when it reaches a critical intensity and then can be reversed only by a decline of the enterprise, so can social iatrogenesis be reversed only by political action that retrenches professional dominance. A radical monopoly feeds on itself. Iatrogenic medicine reinforces a morbid¶ society in which social control of the population by the medical system turns into a¶ principal economic activity. It serves to legitimize social arrangements into which many people do not fit. It labels the handicapped as unfit and breeds ever new¶ categories of patients. People who are angered, sickened, and impaired by their industrial labor and leisure can escape only into a life under medical supervision and are disqualified from political struggle for a healthier world. that diagnosis often serves as a means of turning political complaints¶ against the stress of growth into demands for more therapies that are just more of¶ its costly and stressful outputs awareness of the degree to which iatrogenic ill-health is politically communicated would shake the foundations of medical power much more profoundly than any catalogue of medicine's technical faults.
social iatrogenesis can escalate When biomedical intervention crosses a critical threshold autonomy degenerates into a radical monopoly social iatrogenesis becomes¶ the main product of the medical organization when hospitals draft all those who are in critical condition, they impose on society a new form of dying social monopoly (stultifies) the output of nonmarketable use-values. Radical monopolies impose society-wide substitution¶ of commodities for use-values by "appropriating" those¶ of its general characteristics which have enabled people so far to cope on their own The malignant spread of medicine turns mutual care and self-medication into misdemeanors or felonies as clinical iatrogenesis can be reversed only by a decline of the enterprise, so can social iatrogenesis be reversed only by political action that retrenches professional dominance. A radical monopoly feeds on itself. Iatrogenic medicine reinforces a morbid¶ society in which social control of the population by the medical system turns into a¶ principal economic activity. It serves to legitimize social arrangements into which¶ many people do not fit. It labels the handicapped as unfit and breeds ever new¶ categories of patients. People who are sickened, and impaired by labor can escape only into a life under medical supervision and are disqualified from political struggle that diagnosis often serves as a means of turning political complaints¶ against growth into demands for more costly and stressful outputs awareness of iatrogenic ill-health would shake the foundations of medical power
Ivan, Ph.D from the University of Salzburg, “BRAVE NEW BIOCRACY: HEALTH CARE FROM WOMB TO TOMB,” New Perspectives Quarterly, Winter 1994, Vol. 11, Issue 1, http://brandon.multics.org/library/Ivan%20Illich/against_life.html SJE **we modified some ableist stuff Like its clinical counterpart, social iatrogenesis can escalate from an adventitious feature into an inherent characteristic of the medical system. When the intensity7 of¶ biomedical intervention crosses a critical threshold, clinical iatrogenesis turns from error, accident, or fault into an incurable perversion of medical practice. In the same way, when professional autonomy degenerates into a radical monopoly and people are rendered impotent to cope with their milieu, social iatrogenesis becomes¶ the main product of the medical organization. A radical monopoly goes deeper than that of any one corporation or any one¶ government. It can take many forms. When cities are built around vehicles, they¶ devalue human feet; when schools pre-empt learning, they devalue the autodidact; when hospitals draft all those who are in critical condition, they impose on society a new form of dying. Ordinary monopolies corner the market; radical monopolies¶ disable people from doing or making things on their own. The commercial¶ monopoly restricts the flow of commodities; the more insidious social monopoly (stultifies) paralyzes the output of nonmarketable use-values. Radical monopolies impinge¶ still further on freedom and independence. They impose a society-wide substitution¶ of commodities for use-values by reshaping the milieu and by "appropriating" those¶ of its general characteristics which have enabled people so far to cope on their own.¶ Intensive education turns autodidacts into unemployables, intensive agriculture¶ destroys the subsistence farmer, and the deployment of police undermines the¶ community's self-control. The malignant spread of medicine has comparable¶ results: it turns mutual care and self-medication into misdemeanors or felonies.¶ Just as clinical iatrogenesis becomes medically incurable when it reaches a critical intensity and then can be reversed only by a decline of the enterprise, so can social iatrogenesis be reversed only by political action that retrenches professional dominance. A radical monopoly feeds on itself. Iatrogenic medicine reinforces a morbid¶ society in which social control of the population by the medical system turns into a¶ principal economic activity. It serves to legitimize social arrangements into which¶ many people do not fit. It labels the handicapped as unfit and breeds ever new¶ categories of patients. People who are angered, sickened, and impaired by their industrial labor and leisure can escape only into a life under medical supervision and are thereby seduced or disqualified from political struggle for a healthier world. Social iatrogenesis is not yet accepted as a common etiology of disease. If it were recognized that diagnosis often serves as a means of turning political complaints¶ against the stress of growth into demands for more therapies that are just more of¶ its costly and stressful outputs, the industrial system would lose one of its major¶ defenses. At the same time, awareness of the degree to which iatrogenic ill-health is politically communicated would shake the foundations of medical power much more profoundly than any catalogue of medicine's technical faults.
3,429
<h4><strong>Iatrogenesis is not just clinical but social, resulting in the displacement of populations and legitimizing ableist and capitalist violence – only an act which exposes the limits to professional dominance solves, rendering the radical monopoly self-destructive</h4><p></strong>Illich 76</p><p>Ivan, Ph.D from the University of Salzburg, “BRAVE NEW BIOCRACY: HEALTH CARE FROM WOMB TO TOMB,” New Perspectives Quarterly, Winter 1994, Vol. 11, Issue 1, http://brandon.multics.org/library/Ivan%20Illich/against_life.html SJE</p><p><u><strong>**we modified some ableist stuff</p><p></u></strong>Like its clinical counterpart, <u><strong><mark>social iatrogenesis can escalate</mark> from an adventitious feature into an inherent characteristic of the medical system. <mark>When</u></strong></mark> the intensity7 of¶ <u><strong><mark>biomedical intervention crosses a critical threshold</u></strong></mark>, clinical <u><strong>iatrogenesis turns from error</u></strong>, accident, or fault <u><strong>into an incurable perversion of medical practice.</u></strong> In the same way, <u><strong>when</u></strong> professional <u><strong><mark>autonomy degenerates into a radical monopoly</u></strong></mark> and people are rendered impotent to cope with their milieu, <u><strong><mark>social iatrogenesis becomes¶ the main product of the medical organization</u></strong></mark>. A radical monopoly goes deeper than that of any one corporation or any one¶ government. It can take many forms. When cities are built around vehicles, they¶ devalue human feet; when schools pre-empt learning, they devalue the autodidact; <u><strong><mark>when hospitals draft all those who are in critical condition, they impose on society a new form of dying</u></strong></mark>. Ordinary monopolies corner the market; radical monopolies¶ disable people from doing or making things on their own. The commercial¶ monopoly restricts the flow of commodities; the more insidious <u><strong><mark>social monopoly (stultifies)</u></strong></mark> paralyzes <u><strong><mark>the output of nonmarketable use-values. Radical monopolies</u></strong></mark> impinge¶ still further on freedom and independence. They <u><strong><mark>impose</mark> a <mark>society-wide substitution¶ of commodities for use-values by</mark> reshaping the milieu and by <mark>"appropriating" those¶ of its general characteristics which have enabled people so far to cope on their own</mark>.</u></strong>¶ Intensive education turns autodidacts into unemployables, intensive agriculture¶ destroys the subsistence farmer, and the deployment of police undermines the¶ community's self-control.<u><strong> <mark>The malignant spread of medicine</u></strong></mark> has comparable¶ results: it <u><strong><mark>turns mutual care and self-medication into misdemeanors or felonies</u></strong></mark>.¶ <u><strong>Just <mark>as clinical iatrogenesis</mark> becomes medically incurable when it reaches a critical intensity and then <mark>can be reversed only by a decline of the enterprise, so can social iatrogenesis be reversed only by political action that retrenches professional dominance. A radical monopoly feeds on itself.</u></strong> <u><strong>Iatrogenic medicine reinforces a morbid¶ society in which social control of the population by the medical system turns into a¶ principal economic activity.</u></strong> <u><strong>It serves to legitimize social arrangements into which</u></strong>¶<u><strong> many people do not fit.</u></strong> <u><strong>It labels the handicapped as unfit and breeds ever new¶ categories of patients. People who are</mark> angered, <mark>sickened, and impaired by</mark> their industrial <mark>labor</mark> and leisure <mark>can escape only into a life under medical supervision and are</u></strong></mark> thereby seduced or <u><strong><mark>disqualified from political struggle</mark> for a healthier world.</u></strong> Social iatrogenesis is not yet accepted as a common etiology of disease. If it were recognized <u><strong><mark>that diagnosis often serves as a means of turning political complaints¶ against</mark> the stress of <mark>growth into demands for more</mark> therapies that are just more of¶ its <mark>costly and stressful outputs</u></strong></mark>, the industrial system would lose one of its major¶ defenses. At the same time, <u><strong><mark>awareness of</mark> the degree to which <mark>iatrogenic ill-health</mark> is politically communicated <mark>would shake the foundations of medical power</mark> much more profoundly than any catalogue of medicine's technical faults.</p></u></strong>
null
1AC
null
430,060
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,956
Counter-interpretation – aff’s have to defend an area of the topic, have a method, and advocate change
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Counter-interpretation – aff’s have to defend an area of the topic, have a method, and advocate change</h4>
T
null
null
430,059
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,957
Trade spreads disease—conclusive evidence
Sciencedaily 11
Sciencedaily 11 Sciencedaly.com, cites study done by researchers at the UK research councils’ Rural Economy and Land use programme, June 9, “Is Free Global Trade Too Great a Threat to Food Supplies, Natural Heritage and Health?”, [http://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2011/06/110609083226.html]
null
we face a future of uncertainty, and threats to our food supplies, natural heritage, and human health, from pathogens. travel and trade exacerbates the problem academics take a look at infectious diseases They conclude that increasing trade put us at greater risk from pathogens in the future, as more exotic diseases enter the country new pathogens evolve, while existing ones develop the ability to infect new hosts spread of disease is caused by increased trade Government policy and the classification of diseases increase the risks. Farmers restocking to combat one disease may introduce another.
Researchers from the UK Research Councils' Rural Economy and Land Use Programme say that we face a future of uncertainty, and possible new threats to our food supplies, natural heritage, and even human health, from animal and plant pathogens. Human behaviour, travel and trade exacerbates the problem and we may need to reconsider our approach to free trade. We face a future of uncertainty, and possible new threats to our food supplies, natural heritage, and even human health, from animal and plant pathogens, according to researchers from the UK Research Councils' Rural Economy and Land Use Programme. In a special issue of Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, the academics take a fresh look at infectious diseases of animals and plants, from an interdisciplinary perspective. They conclude that increasing global trade may put us at greater risk from pathogens in the future, as more exotic diseases enter the country. This process is already happening, particularly in plant disease. Climate change is driving shifts in cropping patterns across the world and they may take pests and diseases with them. We are also seeing completely new pathogens evolve, while existing ones develop the ability to infect new hosts. During the 20th century the number of new fungal, bacterial and viral diseases in plants appearing in Europe rose from less than five per decade to over 20. But these problems are exacerbated by human behaviour, and understanding this could be key to helping policymakers deal with risk and uncertainty. In many cases the spread of disease is caused by increased trade, transport and travel. Trends in the international horticultural industry have been towards fewer, larger producers, supplying vast numbers of retailers. Thus, disease which begins in one location may be spread far and wide. Changes in the livestock trade have similar effects at national level. Reduction in income per animal, and the introduction of mechanisation, means that fewer farmers manage more animals per farm, and animals are moved around more frequently. They may be born in one location but sold on and reared elsewhere. Government policy and the classification of diseases may even increase the risks. Farmers restocking to combat one disease may, unwittingly, introduce another.
2,301
<h4>Trade spreads disease—conclusive evidence</h4><p><u><strong>Sciencedaily 11 </u></strong>Sciencedaly.com, cites study done by researchers at the UK research councils’ Rural Economy and Land use programme, June 9, “Is Free Global Trade Too Great a Threat to Food Supplies, Natural Heritage and Health?”, [http://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2011/06/110609083226.html]</p><p>Researchers from the UK Research Councils' Rural Economy and Land Use Programme say that <mark>we face a future of uncertainty, and</mark> possible new <mark>threats to our food supplies, natural heritage, and</mark> even <mark>human health, from </mark>animal and plant <mark>pathogens.</mark> Human behaviour, <mark>travel and trade exacerbates the problem</mark> and we may need to reconsider our approach to free trade. We face a future of uncertainty, and possible new threats to our food supplies, natural heritage, and even human health, from animal and plant pathogens, according to researchers from the UK Research Councils' Rural Economy and Land Use Programme. In a special issue of Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, the <mark>academics take a</mark> fresh <mark>look at infectious diseases </mark>of animals and plants, from an interdisciplinary perspective. <mark>They conclude that increasing</mark> global <mark>trade</mark> may <mark>put us at greater risk from pathogens in the future, as more exotic diseases enter the country</mark>. This process is already happening, particularly in plant disease. Climate change is driving shifts in cropping patterns across the world and they may take pests and diseases with them. We are also seeing completely <mark>new pathogens evolve,</mark> <mark>while existing ones develop the ability to infect new hosts</mark>. During the 20th century the number of new fungal, bacterial and viral diseases in plants appearing in Europe rose from less than five per decade to over 20. But these problems are exacerbated by human behaviour, and understanding this could be key to helping policymakers deal with risk and uncertainty. In many cases the <mark>spread of disease is caused by increased trade</mark>, transport and travel. Trends in the international horticultural industry have been towards fewer, larger producers, supplying vast numbers of retailers. Thus, disease which begins in one location may be spread far and wide. Changes in the livestock trade have similar effects at national level. Reduction in income per animal, and the introduction of mechanisation, means that fewer farmers manage more animals per farm, and animals are moved around more frequently. They may be born in one location but sold on and reared elsewhere. <mark>Government policy and the classification of diseases</mark> may even <mark>increase the risks. Farmers restocking to combat one disease may</mark>, unwittingly, <mark>introduce another.</mark> </p>
1NR
DA
Trade
303,265
2
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,958
Counter-interpretation: non-instrumental affirmation of an area of the topic
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Counter-interpretation: non-instrumental affirmation of an area of the topic</h4>
T
null
null
430,061
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,959
Ironically, there’s no room for death within the regimes of iatrogenesis legitimized by the medical sphere – instead, those who seek death are labeled deviant to the social order and doctors are encouraged to “aggressively treat” these desires – PAS is a reversal of that imperative which confuses the role of the doctor – hear it from the mouths of the physicians themselves
ANCO 07
ANCO 07
SJE Legalizing physician-assisted suicide strikes at the heart of what we do as physicians and adds ambiguity to the physician-patient relationship. The physician’s primary directive is to first, do no harm. P a s destroys the trust between the patient and doctor. the physician is relieved of his or her primary responsibility to the patient to safeguard life [R]equests for [euthanasia and PAS] tend to be guided by psychological distress psychological distress are prevalent disorders in terminally ill patients and need to be sought out and aggressively treated. assisting someone to die is unethical and unacceptable, and is fundamentally incompatible with the physician’s role as healer. Instead of participating in assisted suicide, physicians must aggressively respond to the needs of patients at the end of life. The profession’s most consistent ethical traditions have always emphasized healing and comfort and have demurred at the idea that a physician should intentionally bring about the death of any patient. Pronouncements against assisted suicide date back to the Hippocratic Oath and have formed the ethical backbone for professional opposition to the practice of physician-assisted suicide.
Legalizing p a s strikes at the heart of what we do as physicians and adds ambiguity to the physician-patient relationship. The physician’s primary directive is do no harm. P a s destroys the trust between the patient and doctor. the physician is relieved of her primary responsibility to safeguard life [R]equests for PAS] tend to be guided by psychological distress prevalent disorders in terminally ill patients and need to be sought out and aggressively treated. assisting someone to die is fundamentally incompatible with the physician’s role as healer. Instead of participating in assisted suicide, physicians must aggressively respond to the needs of patients at the end of life. The profession’s most consistent ethical traditions have emphasized healing and comfort and demurred at the idea that a physician should intentionally bring about the death of any patient. Pronouncements against assisted suicide date back to the Hippocratic Oath formed the ethical backbone for opposition
Association of Northern California Oncologists¶ and¶ Medical Oncology Association of Southern California, “Position Statement on Assisted Suicide,” 4/16/07, http://dredf.org/public-policy/assisted-suicide/position-statement-on-assisted-suicide/ SJE Legalizing physician-assisted suicide strikes at the heart of what we do as physicians and adds ambiguity to the physician-patient relationship. The physician’s primary directive is to first, do no harm. Physician-assisted suicide destroys the trust between the patient and doctor. Under the pretense of providing compassion, the physician is relieved of his or her primary responsibility to the patient – to safeguard life and to provide comfort to the suffering. It is the ultimate patient abandonment.¶ Oncologists are painfully aware of our own limitations in providing optimal palliative care in every situation. We also recognize that most members of the public, as well as many physicians in other specialties who do not treat dying patients with any regularity, do not see what we see every day in our practices. We believe that far fewer physicians would support the concept of physician-assisted suicide if they had the specific training and experience that oncologists have in dealing with these types of patients and these diagnoses. We know that cases of patients experiencing intractable physical symptoms at the end of life do exist, but this is not a justification for aid in dying. We need more research and education, not patient termination.¶ In this debate, it is critical to recognize that, contrary to belief, most patients requesting physician-assisted suicide or euthanasia do not do so because of physical symptoms such as pain or nausea. Rather, depression, psychological distress, and fear of loss of control are identified as the key end of life issues. This has been borne out in numerous studies and reports. For example, in a survey of 100 terminally ill cancer patients in a palliative care program in Edmonton, Canada, a multivariate analysis showed no correlation between physical symptoms of pain, nausea, or loss of appetite and the patient’s expressed desire or support for euthanasia/PAS. Moreover, in the same study, patients demonstrating suicidal ideation were much more likely to be suffering from depression or anxiety, but not somatic symptoms such as pain.[1] An important study from the Netherlands of a cohort of 138 cancer patients with a life expectancy of three months or less demonstrated similar findings.[2] In this study, the authors had hypothesized that patients requesting euthanasia would be unlikely to have depressed mood or affect, since it would be expected that such a request would be a well-thought out decision, particularly since euthanasia has been legal in the Netherlands since 2002. The authors expected that these patients would be more accepting of their terminal diagnosis and therefore better adjusted. What they found surprised them – depressed patients were more than four times as likely to request euthanasia as patients who were not depressed. Over 40% of depressed patients requested euthanasia. Of those who requested euthanasia, about half were depressed.¶ Prominent bioethicist Ezekiel Emanuel of the National Institutes of Health has written eloquently on this “depression thesis” in regards to euthanasia and PAS and notes¶ [R]equests for [euthanasia and PAS] tend to be guided by psychological distress rather than rational choices about a good death. This conclusion should be especially worrisome given that approximately 15% to 25% of cancer patients are depressed, and approximately 80% of requests for euthanasia or PAS come from cancer patients. When the depression thesis is juxtaposed with epidemiologic data demonstrating that, in general, suicide is approximately 30% to 50% more likely among cancer patients and that depression is a primary motivation for suicide, euthanasia and PAS look more like a method of acting on suicidal ideation than a type of termination of medical treatment.[3]¶ Depression and psychological distress are prevalent disorders in terminally ill patients and need to be sought out and aggressively treated. These can be difficult conversations between physicians and patients at the end of life, but our patients deserve this from us, and not the convenient resolution of a lethal prescription.¶ The vast majority of legitimate physician organizations oppose physician-assisted suicide. The California Medical Association (CMA) has reaffirmed its opposition to PAS five times since the 1980s, most recently at its House of Delegates in 2005 and again in 2006. In a February 15, 2007 press release, the CMA states¶ The CMA believes in humane and compassionate care for the terminally ill, including appropriate pain control and counseling for the dying and their families. But assisting someone to die is unethical and unacceptable, and is fundamentally incompatible with the physician’s role as healer.[4]¶ The American Medical Association states in its code of ethics:¶ Physician-assisted suicide is fundamentally incompatible with the physician’s role as healer, would be difficult or impossible to control, and would pose serious societal risks¶ Instead of participating in assisted suicide, physicians must aggressively respond to the needs of patients at the end of life.[5]¶ The American College of Physicians, the nation’s largest medical specialty society, states:¶ The profession’s most consistent ethical traditions have always emphasized healing and comfort and have demurred at the idea that a physician should intentionally bring about the death of any patient. Pronouncements against euthanasia and assisted suicide date back to the Hippocratic Oath and have formed the ethical backbone for professional opposition to the practice of physician-assisted suicide.
5,848
<h4><strong>Ironically, there’s no room for death within the regimes of iatrogenesis legitimized by the medical sphere – instead, those who seek death are labeled deviant to the social order and doctors are encouraged to “aggressively treat” these desires – PAS is a reversal of that imperative which confuses the role of the doctor – hear it from the mouths of the physicians themselves</h4><p>ANCO 07</p><p></strong>Association of Northern California Oncologists¶ and¶ Medical Oncology Association of Southern California, “Position Statement on Assisted Suicide,” 4/16/07, http://dredf.org/public-policy/assisted-suicide/position-statement-on-assisted-suicide/<u><strong> SJE</p><p><mark>Legalizing p</mark>hysician-<mark>a</mark>ssisted <mark>s</mark>uicide <mark>strikes at the heart of what we do as physicians and adds ambiguity to the physician-patient relationship.</u></strong> <u><strong>The physician’s primary directive is</mark> to first, <mark>do no harm. P</u></strong></mark>hysician-<u><strong><mark>a</u></strong></mark>ssisted <u><strong><mark>s</u></strong></mark>uicide <u><strong><mark>destroys the trust between the patient and doctor.</u></strong></mark> Under the pretense of providing compassion, <u><strong><mark>the physician is relieved of</mark> his or <mark>her primary responsibility</mark> to the patient</u></strong> – <u><strong><mark>to safeguard life</u></strong></mark> and to provide comfort to the suffering. It is the ultimate patient abandonment.¶ Oncologists are painfully aware of our own limitations in providing optimal palliative care in every situation. We also recognize that most members of the public, as well as many physicians in other specialties who do not treat dying patients with any regularity, do not see what we see every day in our practices. We believe that far fewer physicians would support the concept of physician-assisted suicide if they had the specific training and experience that oncologists have in dealing with these types of patients and these diagnoses. We know that cases of patients experiencing intractable physical symptoms at the end of life do exist, but this is not a justification for aid in dying. We need more research and education, not patient termination.¶ In this debate, it is critical to recognize that, contrary to belief, most patients requesting physician-assisted suicide or euthanasia do not do so because of physical symptoms such as pain or nausea. Rather, depression, psychological distress, and fear of loss of control are identified as the key end of life issues. This has been borne out in numerous studies and reports. For example, in a survey of 100 terminally ill cancer patients in a palliative care program in Edmonton, Canada, a multivariate analysis showed no correlation between physical symptoms of pain, nausea, or loss of appetite and the patient’s expressed desire or support for euthanasia/PAS. Moreover, in the same study, patients demonstrating suicidal ideation were much more likely to be suffering from depression or anxiety, but not somatic symptoms such as pain.[1] An important study from the Netherlands of a cohort of 138 cancer patients with a life expectancy of three months or less demonstrated similar findings.[2] In this study, the authors had hypothesized that patients requesting euthanasia would be unlikely to have depressed mood or affect, since it would be expected that such a request would be a well-thought out decision, particularly since euthanasia has been legal in the Netherlands since 2002. The authors expected that these patients would be more accepting of their terminal diagnosis and therefore better adjusted. What they found surprised them – depressed patients were more than four times as likely to request euthanasia as patients who were not depressed. Over 40% of depressed patients requested euthanasia. Of those who requested euthanasia, about half were depressed.¶ Prominent bioethicist Ezekiel Emanuel of the National Institutes of Health has written eloquently on this “depression thesis” in regards to euthanasia and PAS and notes¶ <u><strong><mark>[R]equests for</mark> [euthanasia and <mark>PAS] tend to be guided by psychological distress</u></strong></mark> rather than rational choices about a good death. This conclusion should be especially worrisome given that approximately 15% to 25% of cancer patients are depressed, and approximately 80% of requests for euthanasia or PAS come from cancer patients. When the depression thesis is juxtaposed with epidemiologic data demonstrating that, in general, suicide is approximately 30% to 50% more likely among cancer patients and that depression is a primary motivation for suicide, euthanasia and PAS look more like a method of acting on suicidal ideation than a type of termination of medical treatment.[3]¶ Depression and <u><strong>psychological distress are <mark>prevalent disorders in terminally ill patients and need to be sought out and aggressively treated.</u></strong></mark> These can be difficult conversations between physicians and patients at the end of life, but our patients deserve this from us, and not the convenient resolution of a lethal prescription.¶ The vast majority of legitimate physician organizations oppose physician-assisted suicide. The California Medical Association (CMA) has reaffirmed its opposition to PAS five times since the 1980s, most recently at its House of Delegates in 2005 and again in 2006. In a February 15, 2007 press release, the CMA states¶ The CMA believes in humane and compassionate care for the terminally ill, including appropriate pain control and counseling for the dying and their families. But <u><strong><mark>assisting someone to die is </mark>unethical and unacceptable, and is <mark>fundamentally incompatible with the physician’s role as healer.</u></strong></mark>[4]¶ The American Medical Association states in its code of ethics:¶ Physician-assisted suicide is fundamentally incompatible with the physician’s role as healer, would be difficult or impossible to control, and would pose serious societal risks¶ <u><strong><mark>Instead of participating in assisted suicide, physicians must aggressively respond to the needs of patients at the end of life.</u></strong></mark>[5]¶ The American College of Physicians, the nation’s largest medical specialty society, states:¶ <u><strong><mark>The profession’s most consistent ethical traditions have</mark> always <mark>emphasized healing and comfort and</mark> have <mark>demurred at the idea that a physician should intentionally bring about the death of any patient.</mark> <mark>Pronouncements against</u></strong></mark> euthanasia and <u><strong><mark>assisted suicide date back to the Hippocratic Oath</mark> and have <mark>formed the ethical backbone for</mark> professional <mark>opposition</mark> to the practice of physician-assisted suicide.</p></u></strong>
null
1AC
null
430,063
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,960
Indeed, the 1AC has failed, but it is the worst failure as it packages itself in the successful façade of subjectivity. Instead, vote neg.
All of the old
All of the old
Nothing else ever Ever tried? Ever failed? No matter. Try again. Fail again. Fail better. Halberstam 11 , Jack, “Queer Art of Failure” Duke University Press, August 2011, KB terms like serious and rigorous tend to be code words, for disciplinary correctness they signal a form of training and learning that confirms what is already known according to approved methods of knowing but they do not allow for visionary insights or flights of fancy. Training of any kind, is a way of refusing a relation to knowing, a stroll down uncharted streets in the "wrong" direction it is precisely about staying in well-lit territories and about knowing exactly which way to go before you set out. Losing is an art there are many rogue intellectuals who wander off into uncharted territories and refuse the academy because the publish-or-perish pressure of academic life keeps them tethered to conventional knowledge production and its well-traveled byways. disciplines get in the way of answers because they offer maps of thought where intuition and blind fumbling might yield better results. These alternative cultural and academic realms, the areas beside academia rather than within it, the intellectual worlds conjured by failures serve as the launching pad for alternatives precisely when the university cannot. This is not a bad time to experiment with generating new forms of knowing, since the fields that were assembled over one hundred years ago to respond to new market economies and the demand for narrow expertise are losing relevance and failing to respond either to real-world knowledge projects or student interests. do we really want to shore up the ragged boundaries of our shared interests and intellectual commitments, or mightwe rather take this opportunity to rethink the project of learning and thinking altogether? universities squash rather than promote quirky and original thought. Disciplinarity is a technique of modern power: it depends upon and deploys normalization tradition, and regularity, and it produces experts and administrative forms of gover- nance. The university structure that houses the disciplines and jealously guards their boundaries now stands at a crossroads, not of disciplinarity and interdisciplinarity, past and future, national and transnational the crossroads at which the disintegrating bandwagon of disciplines subfields, and interdisciplines has arrived offer a choice between the university as corporation and the university as a new kind of public sphere with a different investment in knowledge, in ideas, and in thought and politics. A take on disciplinarity and the university that presumes the breakdown of the disciplines and the closing of gaps between fields conventionally presumed to be separated can be found in Moten and Harney The University and the Undercommons: Seven Theses For Moten and Harney, the critical academic is not the answer to encroach- ing professionalization but an extension of it, using the same tools and legitimating strategies to become "an ally of professional education." Moten and Harney prefer to pitch their tent with the "subversive intellectuals," a maroon community of outcast thinkers who refuse, resist, and renege on the demands of "excellence," and "productivity." what does the undercommons of the university want to be? It wants to constitute an unprofessional force of fugitive knowers, with a set of intellectual practices not bound by examination systems and test scores The goal for this unprofessionalization is not to abolish Not so much the abolition of prisons but the abolition of a society that could have prisons that could have slavery not aboli- tion as the elimination ofanything but abolition as the founding of a new society" Not the elimination of anything but the founding of a new society. Why not think in terms of a different kind of society than the one that first created and then abolished slavery? The social worlds we inhabit are not inevitable A few visionary books show us the paths not taken the modern state has run roughshod over local, customary, and undisciplined forms of knowledge in order to rationalize and simplify practices that have profit as their pri- mary motivation. certain ways of seeing the world are established as normal or natural as necessary even though they are often entirely counterintuitive and socially engi- neered. I want to use his monumental study to pick up some of the discarded local knowledges that are trampled underfoot in the rush to bureaucratize and rationalize an economic order that privi- leges profit over all kinds of other motivations for being and doing. we might go with the thicket of subjugated knowledge that sprouts like weeds among the disciplinary forms of knowledge threatening always to overwhelm the cultivation and pruning of the intel- lectwith mad plant life. to "see like a state" means to accept the order of things and to internalize them; it means that we begin to deploy and think with the logic of the superiority oforderliness and that we erase and sacrifice other practices of knowledge, practices that may be less efficient, may yield less marketable results, but may be more sustaining Scott identifies "legibility" as the favored technique of high modernism for sorting, organizing, and profiting and for abstracting systems of knowledge from local knowledge practices Legibility is a condition of manipulation" He favors more practical forms of knowledge that he calls metis and that emphasize mutuality, collectivity, plasticity, diversity, and adaptability. Illegibility one way of escaping the political manipulation to which all university fields and disciplines are subject. While Scott's insight about illegibility has implications for all kinds of subjects who are manipulated precisely when they become legible and visible to the state it points to an argument for antidisciplinarity in the sense that knowledge practices that refuse the form and the content of tra- ditional canons may lead to unbounded forms of speculation, modes of thinking that ally not with rigor and order but with inspiration and unpre- dictability We may want to think about how to see unlike a state new rationales for knowledge production, different aesthetic standards for ordering or disordering space, other modes of political engagement than those conjured by the liberal imagination We may want more undisciplined knowledge, more questions and fewer answers. Disciplines qualify and disqualify, legitimate and delegitimate, reward and punish; they statically reproduce themselves and inhibit dissent "Disciplines will define not a code of law, but a code of normalization" Foucault provides a context for his own antidisciplinary thinking and declares the age of "all-encompassing and global theories" to be over, giving way to the "local character of critique" or "something resembling a sort of au- tonomous and non-centralized theoretical production, or a theoretical production that does not need a visa from some common regime to establish its validity" Foucault exhorts his students to think about and turn to "subjugated knowledges," forms of knowledge produc- tion that have been "buried or masked in functional coherences or formal systematizations" These forms of knowledge have not been lost or forgotten; they have been disqualified, rendered nonsensical naive knowledges, hierarchically inferior knowledges this is what we mean by knowledge from below. if we are to struggle against disciplines, or disciplinary power, in our search for a nondisciplin- ary power, we should not be turning to the old right of sovereignty; we should be looking to a new right that is both anti-disciplinary and eman- cipated from the principle of sovereignty this book joins forces with their "subversive intellectual" and agrees to steal from the university, to "abuse its hospitality" and to be "in but not of it" Moten and Harney's theses exhort the subversive intellectual to, worry about the university, refuse professionalization, forge a collectivity, and retreat to the external world beyond the ivied walls of the campus I would add the following Resist mastery we might in- sist upon a critique of the "all-encompassing and global theories" this resistance takes the form of invest- ing in counterintuitive modes of knowing such as failure and stupidity we might read failure as a refusal of mastery, a critique of the intuitive connections within capitalism between success and profit, and as a counterhegemonic discourse of losing. Stupidity could refer not to a lack of knowledge but to the limits of certain forms of know- ing and certain ways of inhabiting structures of knowing.
Losing is an art there are rogue intellectuals who refuse the academy alternative realms the areas beside academia rather than within it the intellectual worlds conjured by failures serve as the launching pad for alternatives precisely when the university cannot. This is not a bad time to experiment with generating new forms of knowing since fields assembled over one hundred years ago are losing relevance and failing to respond either to real-world knowledge projects or student interests. we want to rethink the project of learning and thinking altogether The university structure that houses the disciplines and guards their boundaries stands at a crossroads at which the disintegrating bandwagon of disciplines, has arrived offer a choice between the university as corporation and the university as a new public sphere with a different investment in knowledge ideas thought and politics Moten and Harney pitch their tent with the "subversive intellectuals," a community of outcast thinkers who resist the demands of "excellence," and "productivity." the undercommons wants to constitute fugitive knowers Not the elimination of anything but the founding of a new society. The social worlds we inhabit are not inevitable we might go with the thicket of subjugated knowledge that sprouts like weeds among the disciplinary forms of knowledge to "see like a state" means to accept the order of things and to internalize them we begin to deploy and think with the logic of the superiority oforderliness and that we erase and sacrifice othe practices of knowledge practices that may be less efficient but more sustaining Legibility is a condition of manipulation" He favors knowledge that emphasize mutuality collectivity diversity Illegibility one way of escaping the manipulation to which all university fields and disciplines are subject. We want to see unlike a state; new rationales for knowledge production other modes of political engagement We may want more undisciplined knowledge, more questions and fewer answers. "Disciplines will define not a code of law, but a code of normalization" Foucault exhorts his students to turn to "subjugated knowledges," that have been "buried or masked These forms of knowledge have not been lost or forgotten; they have been disqualified, rendered nonsensical Resist mastery
Nothing else ever Ever tried? Ever failed? No matter. Try again. Fail again. Fail better. Halberstam 11 Halberstam, Jack, “Queer Art of Failure” Duke University Press, August 2011, KB Any book that begins with a quote from SpongeBob SquarePants and is motored by wisdom gleaned from Fantastic Mr. Fox, Chicken Run, and Find- ing Nemo, among other animated guides to life, runs the risk of not being taken seriously. Yet this is my goal. Being taken seriously means missing out on the chance to be frivolous, promiscuous, and irrelevant. The desire to be taken seriously is precisely what compels people to follow the tried and true paths of knowledge production around which I would like to map a few detours. Indeed terms like serious and rigorous tend to be code words, in academia as well as other contexts, for disciplinary correctness; they signal a form of training and learning that confirms what is already known according to approved methods of knowing, but they do not allow for visionary insights or flights of fancy. Training of any kind, in fact, is a way of refusing a kind of Benjaminian relation to knowing, a stroll down uncharted streets in the "wrong" direction (Benjamin 1996); it is precisely about staying in well-lit territories and about knowing exactly which way to go before you set out. Like many others before me, I pro- pose that instead the goal is to lose one's way, and indeed to be prepared to lose more than one's way. Losing, we may agree with Elizabeth Bishop, is an art, and one "that is not too hard to master I thought it may look like a disaster" (2008:166—167). In the sciences, particularly physics and mathematics, there are many examples of rogue intellectuals, not all of whom are reclusive Unabomber types (although more than a few are just that), who wander off into uncharted territories and refuse the academy because the publish-or-perish pressure of academic life keeps them tethered to conventional knowledge production and its well-traveled byways. Popular mathematics books, for example, revel in stories about unconventional loners who are self- schooled and who make their own way through the world of numbers. For some kooky minds, disciplines actually get in the way of answers and theorems precisely because they offer maps of thought where intuition and blind fumbling might yield better results. In 2008, for example, The New Yorker featured a story about an oddball physicist who, like many ambitious physicists and mathematicians, was in hot pursuit of a grand theory, a "theory of everything." This thinker, Garrett Lisi, had dropped out of academic physics because string theory dominated the field at that time and he thought the answers lay elsewhere. As an outsider to the discipline, writes Benjamin Wallace-Wells, Lisi "built his theory as an outsider might, relying on a grab bag of component parts: a hand-built mathematical structure, an unconventional way ofdescribing gravity, and a mysterious mathematical entity known as E8." 1 In the end Lisi's "theory of everything" fell short of expectations, but it nonetheless yielded a whole terrain of new questions and methods. Similarly the computer scientists who pioneered new programs to produce computer-generated imagery (CGI), as many accounts of the rise of Pixar have chronicled, were academic rejects or dropouts who created independent institutes in order to explore their dreams of animated worlds.2 These alternative cultural and academic realms, the areas beside academia rather than within it, the intellectual worlds conjured by losers, failures, dropouts, and refuseniks, often serve as the launching pad for alternatives precisely when the university cannot. This is not a bad time to experiment with disciplinary transformation on behalf of the project of generating new forms of knowing, since the fields that were assembled over one hundred years ago to respond to new market economies and the demand for narrow expertise, as Foucault de- scribed them, are now losing relevance and failing to respond either to real-world knowledge projects or student interests. As the big disciplines begin to crumble like banks that have invested in bad securities we might ask more broadly, do we really want to shore up the ragged boundaries of our shared interests and intellectual commitments, or mightwe rather take this opportunity to rethink the project of learning and thinking altogether? Just as the standardized tests that the U.S. favors as a guide to intellectual advancement in high schools tend to identify peoplewho are good at standardized exams (as opposed to, say, intellectual visionaries), so in universities grades, exams, and knowledge ofcanons identify schol- ars with an aptitude for maintaining and conforming to the dictates of the discipline. This book, a stroll out of the confines of conventional knowledge and into the unregulated territories of failure, loss, and unbecoming, must make a long detour around disciplines and ordinary ways of thinking. Let me explain how universities (and by implication high schools) squash rather than promote quirky and original thought. Disciplinarity, as de- fined by Foucault (1995), is a technique of modern power: it depends upon and deploys normalization, routines, convention, tradition, and regularity, and it produces experts and administrative forms of gover- nance. The university structure that houses the disciplines and jealously guards their boundaries now stands at a crossroads, not of disciplinarity and interdisciplinarity, past and future, national and transnational; the crossroads at which the rapidly disintegrating bandwagon of disciplines, subfields, and interdisciplines has arrived offer a choice between the university as corporation and investment opportunity and the university as a new kind of public sphere with a different investment in knowledge, in ideas, and in thought and politics. A radical take on disciplinarity and the university that presumes both the breakdown of the disciplines and the closing of gaps between fields conventionally presumed to be separated can be found in a manifesto published by Fred Moten and Stefano Harney in 2004 in Social Text titled "The University and the Undercommons: Seven Theses." Their essay is a searing critique directed at the intellectual and the critical intellectual, the professional scholar and the "critical academic professionals." For Moten and Harney, the critical academic is not the answer to encroach- ing professionalization but an extension of it, using the very same tools and legitimating strategies to become "an ally of professional education." Moten and Harney prefer to pitch their tent with the "subversive intellectuals," a maroon community of outcast thinkers who refuse, resist, and renege on the demands of "rigor," "excellence," and "productivity." They tell us to "steal from the university," to "steal the enlightenment for others" (112), and to act against "what Foucault called the Conquest, the unspoken war that founded, and with the force of law refounds, society" (113). And what does the undercommons of the university want to be? It wants to constitute an unprofessional force of fugitive knowers, with a set of intellectual practices not bound by examination systems and test scores. The goal for this unprofessionalization is not to abolish; in fact Moten and Harney set the fugitive intellectual against the elimination or abolition of this, the founding or refounding of that: "Not so much the abolition of prisons but the abolition of a society that could have prisons, that could have slavery, that could have thewage, and therefore not aboli- tion as the elimination ofanything but abolition as the founding of a new society" (113). Not the elimination of anything but the founding of a new society. And why not? Why not think in terms of a different kind of society than the one that first created and then abolished slavery? The social worlds we inhabit, after all, as so many thinkers have reminded us, are not inevitable; they were not always bound to turn out this way, and what's more, in the process of producing this reality, many other realities, fields of knowledge, and ways of being have been discarded and, to cite Fou- cault again, "disqualified." A few visionary books, produced alongside disciplinary knowledge, show us the paths not taken. For example, in a book that itself began as a detour, Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed (1999), James C. Scott details the ways the modern state has run roughshod over local, customary, and undisciplined forms of knowledge in order to rationalize and simplify social, agricultural, and political practices that have profit as their pri- mary motivation. In the process, says Scott, certain ways of seeing the world are established as normal or natural, as obvious and necessary, even though they are often entirely counterintuitive and socially engi- neered. Seeing Like a State began as a study of "why the state has always seemed to be the enemy of 'people who move around,'" but quickly be- came a study of the demand by the state for legibility through the imposi- tion of methods ofstandardization and uniformity (1). While Dean Spade (2008) and other queer scholars use Scott's book to think about how we came to insist upon the documentation of gender identity on all govern- mental documentation, I want to use his monumental study to pick up some of the discarded local knowledges that are trampled underfoot in the rush to bureaucratize and rationalize an economic order that privi- leges profit over all kinds of other motivations for being and doing. In place of the Germanic ordered forest that Scott uses as a potent metaphor for the start of the modern imposition of bureaucratic order upon populations, we might go with the thicket of subjugated knowledge that sprouts like weeds among the disciplinary forms of knowledge, threatening always to overwhelm the cultivation and pruning of the intel- lectwith mad plant life. For Scott, to "see like a state" means to accept the order of things and to internalize them; it means that we begin to deploy and think with the logic of the superiority oforderliness and that we erase and indeed sacrifice other, more local practices of knowledge, practices moreover that may be less efficient, may yield less marketable results, but may also, in the long term, be more sustaining. What is at stake in arguing for the trees and against the forest? Scott identifies "legibility" as the favored technique of high modernism for sorting, organizing, and profiting from land and people and for abstracting systems of knowledge from local knowledge practices. He talks about the garden and gardeners as representative of a new spirit of intervention and order favored within high modernism, and he points to the minimalism and simplicity of Le Corbusier's urban design as part of a new commitment to symmetry and division and planning that complements authoritarian preferences for hierarchies and despises the complex and messy forms of organic profu- sion and improvised creativity. "Legibility," writes Scott, "is a condition of manipulation" (1999: 183). He favors instead, borrowing from Euro- pean anarchist thought, more practical forms of knowledge that he calls metis and that emphasize mutuality, collectivity, plasticity, diversity, and adaptability. Illegibility may in fact be one way of escaping the political manipulation to which all university fields and disciplines are subject. While Scott's insight about illegibility has implications for all kinds of subjects who are manipulated precisely when they become legible and visible to the state (undocumented workers, visible queers, racialized mi- norities), it also points to an argument for antidisciplinarity in the sense that knowledge practices that refuse both the form and the content of tra- ditional canons may lead to unbounded forms of speculation, modes of thinking that ally not with rigor and order but with inspiration and unpre- dictability. We may in fact want to think about how to see unlike a state; we may want new rationales for knowledge production, different aesthetic standards for ordering or disordering space, other modes of political engagement than those conjured by the liberal imagination. We may, ulti- mately, want more undisciplined knowledge, more questions and fewer answers. Disciplines qualify and disqualify, legitimate and delegitimate, reward and punish; most important, they statically reproduce themselves and inhibit dissent. As Foucault writes, "Disciplines will define not a code of law, but a code of normalization" (2003: 38). In a series of lectures on knowledge production given at the College de France and then published posthumously as a collection titled Society Must Be Defended, Foucault provides a context for his own antidisciplinary thinking and declares the age of "all-encompassing and global theories" to be over, giving way to the "local character of critique" or "something resembling a sort of au- tonomous and non-centralized theoretical production, or in other words a theoretical production that does not need a visa from some common regime to establish its validity" (6). These lectures coincide with the writ- ing of The History of Sexuality Volume 1, and we find the outline of his cri- tique of repressive power in these pages (Foucault, 1998). I will return to Foucault's insights about the reverse discourse in Ihe History of Sexuality later in the book, especially to the places where he implicates sexual mi- norities in the production of systems of classification, but in Society Must Be Defended his target is academic legibility and legitimation, and he de- scribes and analyzes the function of the academic in the circulation and reproduction of hegemonic structures. In place of the "all-encompassing and global theories" that the uni- versityencourages, Foucault exhorts his students to think about and turn to "subjugated knowledges," namely those forms of knowledge produc- tion that have been "buried or masked in functional coherences or formal systematizations" (2003: 7). These forms of knowledge have not simply been lost or forgotten; they have been disqualified, rendered nonsensical or nonconceptual or "insufficiently elaborated." Foucault calls them " naive knowledges, hierarchically inferior knowledges, knowledges that are below the required level of erudition or scientificity" (7) —this is what we mean by knowledge from below. In relation to the identification of "subjugated knowledges," we might ask, How do we participate in the production and circulation of "sub- jugated knowledge"? How do we keep disciplinary forms of knowledge at bay? How do we avoid precisely the "scientific" forms of knowing that relegate other modes of knowing to the redundant or irrelevant? How do we engage in and teach antidisciplinary knowledge? Foucault pro- poses this answer: "Truth to tell, if we are to struggle against disciplines, or rather against disciplinary power, in our search for a nondisciplin- ary power, we should not be turning to the old right of sovereignty; we should be looking to a new right that is both anti-disciplinary and eman- cipated from the principle of sovereignty" (2003: 40). In some sense we have to untrain ourselves so that we can read the struggles and debates back into questions that seem settled and resolved. On behalfofsuch a project, and in the spirit of the "Seven Theses" pro- posed by Moten and Harney, this book joins forces with their "subversive intellectual" and agrees to steal from the university, to, as they say, "abuse its hospitality" and to be "in but not of it" (101). Moten and Harney's theses exhort the subversive intellectual to, among other things, worry about the university, refuse professionalization, forge a collectivity, and retreat to the external world beyond the ivied walls of the campus. I would add to their theses the following. First, Resist mastery. Here we might in- sist upon a critique of the "all-encompassing and global theories" iden- tified by Foucault. In my book this resistance takes the form of invest- ing in counterintuitive modes of knowing such as failure and stupidity; we might read failure, for example, as a refusal of mastery, a critique of the intuitive connections within capitalism between success and profit, and as a counterhegemonic discourse of losing. Stupidity could refer not simply to a lack of knowledge but to the limits of certain forms of know- ing and certain ways of inhabiting structures of knowing.
16,641
<h4><u><strong>Indeed, the 1AC has failed, but it is the worst failure as it packages itself in the successful façade of subjectivity. Instead, vote neg. </h4><p>All of the old</p><p>Nothing else ever</p><p>Ever tried?</p><p>Ever failed? </p><p>No matter.</p><p>Try again. Fail again. </p><p>Fail better. </p><p>Halberstam 11</p><p></u></strong>Halberstam<u>, Jack, “Queer Art of Failure” Duke University Press, August 2011, KB</p><p></u>Any book that begins with a quote from SpongeBob SquarePants and is motored by wisdom gleaned from Fantastic Mr. Fox, Chicken Run, and Find- ing Nemo, among other animated guides to life, runs the risk of not being taken seriously. Yet this is my goal. Being taken seriously means missing out on the chance to be frivolous, promiscuous, and irrelevant. The desire to be taken seriously is precisely what compels people to follow the tried and true paths of knowledge production around which I would like to map a few detours. Indeed <u>terms like serious and rigorous tend to be code words,</u> in academia as well as other contexts, <u>for disciplinary correctness</u>; <u>they signal a form of training and learning <strong>that confirms what is already known according to approved methods of knowing</u></strong>, <u>but they do not allow for visionary insights or flights of fancy.</u> <u>Training of any kind,</u> in fact, <u>is a way of refusing a</u> kind of Benjaminian <u>relation to knowing, a stroll down uncharted streets in the "wrong" direction </u>(Benjamin 1996); <u>it is precisely about staying in well-lit territories and <strong>about knowing exactly which way to go before you set out.</u></strong> Like many others before me, I pro- pose that instead the goal is to lose one's way, and indeed to be prepared to lose more than one's way. <u><strong><mark>Losing</u></strong></mark>, we may agree with Elizabeth Bishop, <u><strong><mark>is an art</u></strong></mark>, and one "that is not too hard to master I thought it may look like a disaster" (2008:166—167). In the sciences, particularly physics and mathematics, <u><mark>there are </mark>many</u> examples of <u><mark>rogue intellectuals</u></mark>, not all of whom are reclusive Unabomber types (although more than a few are just that), <u><mark>who </mark>wander off into uncharted territories <strong>and <mark>refuse the academy</strong></mark> because the publish-or-perish pressure of academic life keeps them tethered to conventional knowledge production and its well-traveled byways.</u> Popular mathematics books, for example, revel in stories about unconventional loners who are self- schooled and who make their own way through the world of numbers. For some kooky minds, <u>disciplines</u> actually <u>get in the way of answers</u> and theorems precisely <u>because they offer maps of thought where intuition and blind fumbling might yield better results.</u> In 2008, for example, The New Yorker featured a story about an oddball physicist who, like many ambitious physicists and mathematicians, was in hot pursuit of a grand theory, a "theory of everything." This thinker, Garrett Lisi, had dropped out of academic physics because string theory dominated the field at that time and he thought the answers lay elsewhere. As an outsider to the discipline, writes Benjamin Wallace-Wells, Lisi "built his theory as an outsider might, relying on a grab bag of component parts: a hand-built mathematical structure, an unconventional way ofdescribing gravity, and a mysterious mathematical entity known as E8." 1 In the end Lisi's "theory of everything" fell short of expectations, but it nonetheless yielded a whole terrain of new questions and methods. Similarly the computer scientists who pioneered new programs to produce computer-generated imagery (CGI), as many accounts of the rise of Pixar have chronicled, were academic rejects or dropouts who created independent institutes in order to explore their dreams of animated worlds.2 <u>These</u> <u><mark>alternative</mark> cultural and academic <mark>realms</mark>, <strong><mark>the areas beside academia rather than within it</mark>,</u></strong> <u><mark>the</mark> <mark>intellectual worlds conjured by</u></mark> losers, <u><mark>failures</u></mark>, dropouts, and refuseniks, often <u><strong><mark>serve as the launching pad for alternatives precisely when the university cannot. This is not a bad time to experiment with</u></strong></mark> disciplinary transformation on behalf of the project of <u><strong><mark>generating new forms of knowing</strong></mark>, <mark>since</mark> the <mark>fields</mark> that were <mark>assembled over one hundred years</mark> <mark>ago</mark> to respond to new market economies and the demand for narrow expertise</u>, as Foucault de- scribed them, <u><mark>are</u></mark> now <u><mark>losing relevance and failing to respond either to real-world knowledge projects or student interests.</u></mark> As the big disciplines begin to crumble like banks that have invested in bad securities we might ask more broadly, <u>do <mark>we</mark> really <mark>want to</mark> shore up the ragged boundaries of our shared interests and intellectual commitments, or mightwe rather take this opportunity to <strong><mark>rethink the project of learning and thinking altogether</strong></mark>?</u> Just as the standardized tests that the U.S. favors as a guide to intellectual advancement in high schools tend to identify peoplewho are good at standardized exams (as opposed to, say, intellectual visionaries), so in universities grades, exams, and knowledge ofcanons identify schol- ars with an aptitude for maintaining and conforming to the dictates of the discipline. This book, a stroll out of the confines of conventional knowledge and into the unregulated territories of failure, loss, and unbecoming, must make a long detour around disciplines and ordinary ways of thinking. Let me explain how <u>universities</u> (and by implication high schools) <u>squash rather than promote quirky and original thought.</u> <u>Disciplinarity</u>, as de- fined by Foucault (1995), <u>is a technique of modern power: it depends upon and deploys normalization</u>, routines, convention, <u>tradition, and regularity, and it produces experts and administrative forms of gover- nance.</u> <u><mark>The university structure that houses the disciplines and</mark> jealously <mark>guards their boundaries</mark> now <mark>stands at a crossroads</mark>, not of disciplinarity and interdisciplinarity, past and future, national and transnational</u>; <u>the crossroads <mark>at which the</u></mark> rapidly <u><mark>disintegrating bandwagon of disciplines</u>, <u></mark>subfields, and interdisciplines <mark>has arrived offer a choice between the university as corporation</u></mark> and investment opportunity <u><mark>and the university as a <strong>new</mark> kind of <mark>public sphere</strong></mark> <mark>with a different investment in knowledge</mark>, in <mark>ideas</mark>, and in <mark>thought and politics</mark>. A</u> radical <u>take on disciplinarity and the university that presumes</u> both <u>the breakdown of the disciplines and the closing of gaps between fields conventionally presumed to be separated can be found in</u> a manifesto published by Fred <u>Moten and</u> Stefano <u>Harney</u> in 2004 in Social Text titled "<u>The University and the Undercommons: Seven Theses</u>." Their essay is a searing critique directed at the intellectual and the critical intellectual, the professional scholar and the "critical academic professionals." <u>For Moten and Harney, the critical academic is not the answer to encroach- ing professionalization but an extension of it, using the</u> very <u>same tools and legitimating strategies to become "an ally of professional education." <mark>Moten and Harney</mark> prefer to <mark>pitch their tent with the "subversive intellectuals," a</u></mark> <u>maroon</u> <u><mark>community of outcast thinkers who </mark>refuse,<mark> resist</mark>, and renege on <mark>the demands of</u></mark> "rigor," <u><mark>"excellence," and "productivity."</mark> </u>They tell us to "steal from the university," to "steal the enlightenment for others" (112), and to act against "what Foucault called the Conquest, the unspoken war that founded, and with the force of law refounds, society" (113). And <u>what does <mark>the undercommons</mark> of the university want to be? It <mark>wants to constitute</mark> an unprofessional force of <strong><mark>fugitive knowers</strong></mark>, with a set of intellectual practices not bound by examination systems and test scores</u>. <u>The goal for this unprofessionalization is not to abolish</u>; in fact Moten and Harney set the fugitive intellectual against the elimination or abolition of this, the founding or refounding of that: "<u>Not so much the abolition of prisons but the abolition of a society that could have prisons</u>, <u>that could have slavery</u>, that could have thewage, and therefore <u>not aboli- tion as the elimination ofanything but abolition as the founding of a new society"</u> (113). <u><strong><mark>Not the elimination of anything but the founding of a new society.</u></strong></mark> And why not? <u>Why not think in terms of a different kind of society than the one that first created and then abolished slavery? <mark>The social worlds we inhabit</u></mark>, after all, as so many thinkers have reminded us, <u><mark>are not inevitable</u></mark>; they were not always bound to turn out this way, and what's more, in the process of producing this reality, many other realities, fields of knowledge, and ways of being have been discarded and, to cite Fou- cault again, "disqualified." <u>A few visionary books</u>, produced alongside disciplinary knowledge, <u>show us the paths not taken</u>. For example, in a book that itself began as a detour, Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed (1999), James C. Scott details the ways <u>the modern state has run roughshod over local, customary, and undisciplined forms of knowledge in order to rationalize and simplify </u>social, agricultural, and political <u>practices that have profit as their pri- mary motivation.</u> In the process, says Scott, <u><strong>certain ways of seeing the world are established as normal or natural</u></strong>, <u>as</u> obvious and <u>necessary</u>, <u>even though they are often entirely counterintuitive and socially engi- neered.</u> Seeing Like a State began as a study of "why the state has always seemed to be the enemy of 'people who move around,'" but quickly be- came a study of the demand by the state for legibility through the imposi- tion of methods ofstandardization and uniformity (1). While Dean Spade (2008) and other queer scholars use Scott's book to think about how we came to insist upon the documentation of gender identity on all govern- mental documentation, <u>I want to use his monumental study to pick up some of the discarded local knowledges that are trampled underfoot in the rush to bureaucratize and rationalize an economic order that privi- leges profit over all kinds of other motivations for being and doing. </u>In place of the Germanic ordered forest that Scott uses as a potent metaphor for the start of the modern imposition of bureaucratic order upon populations, <u><strong><mark>we might go with the thicket of subjugated knowledge that sprouts like weeds among the disciplinary forms of knowledge</u></strong></mark>, <u>threatening always to overwhelm the cultivation and pruning of the intel- lectwith mad plant life.</u> For Scott, <u><strong><mark>to "see like a state" means to accept the order of things and to internalize them</strong></mark>; it means that <mark>we begin to deploy and think with the logic of the superiority oforderliness and that we erase and</mark> </u>indeed <u><mark>sacrifice othe</mark>r</u>, more local <u><mark>practices of knowledge</mark>, <mark>practices</u></mark> moreover <u><mark>that may be less efficient</mark>, may yield less marketable results, <mark>but</mark> may</u> also, in the long term, <u>be <mark>more sustaining</u></mark>. What is at stake in arguing for the trees and against the forest? <u>Scott identifies "legibility" as the favored technique of high modernism for sorting, organizing, and profiting</u> from land and people <u>and for abstracting systems of knowledge from local knowledge practices</u>. He talks about the garden and gardeners as representative of a new spirit of intervention and order favored within high modernism, and he points to the minimalism and simplicity of Le Corbusier's urban design as part of a new commitment to symmetry and division and planning that complements authoritarian preferences for hierarchies and despises the complex and messy forms of organic profu- sion and improvised creativity. "<u><strong><mark>Legibility</u></strong></mark>," writes Scott, "<u><strong><mark>is a condition of manipulation"</u></strong></mark> (1999: 183). <u><mark>He favors</u></mark> instead, borrowing from Euro- pean anarchist thought, <u>more practical forms of <mark>knowledge that</mark> he calls metis and that <mark>emphasize mutuality</mark>, <mark>collectivity</mark>, plasticity, <mark>diversity</mark>, and adaptability.</u> <u><strong><mark>Illegibility</u></strong></mark> may in fact be <u><strong><mark>one way of escaping the</mark> political <mark>manipulation to which all university fields and disciplines are subject.</u></strong></mark> <u>While Scott's insight about illegibility has implications for all kinds of subjects who are manipulated precisely when they become legible and visible to the state </u>(undocumented workers, visible queers, racialized mi- norities), <u>it</u> also <u>points to an argument for antidisciplinarity in the sense that knowledge practices that refuse</u> both <u>the form and the content of tra- ditional canons may lead to unbounded forms of speculation, modes of thinking that ally not with rigor and order but with inspiration and unpre- dictability</u>. <u><mark>We</mark> may</u> in fact <u><mark>want</mark> <mark>to</mark> think about how to <mark>see unlike a state</u>;</mark> we may want <u><mark>new rationales for knowledge production</mark>, different aesthetic standards for ordering or disordering space, <mark>other modes of political engagement</mark> than those conjured by the liberal imagination</u>. <u><strong><mark>We may</u></strong></mark>, ulti- mately, <u><strong><mark>want more undisciplined knowledge, more questions and fewer answers.</u></strong></mark> <u>Disciplines qualify and disqualify, legitimate and delegitimate, reward and punish;</u> most important, <u>they statically reproduce themselves and inhibit dissent</u>. As Foucault writes, <u><strong><mark>"Disciplines will define not a code of law, but a code of normalization"</u></strong></mark> (2003: 38). In a series of lectures on knowledge production given at the College de France and then published posthumously as a collection titled Society Must Be Defended, <u>Foucault provides a context for his own antidisciplinary thinking and declares the age of "all-encompassing and global theories" to be over, giving way to the "local character of critique" or "something resembling a sort of au- tonomous and non-centralized theoretical production, or</u> in other words <u>a theoretical production that does not need a visa from some common regime to establish its validity"</u> (6). These lectures coincide with the writ- ing of The History of Sexuality Volume 1, and we find the outline of his cri- tique of repressive power in these pages (Foucault, 1998). I will return to Foucault's insights about the reverse discourse in Ihe History of Sexuality later in the book, especially to the places where he implicates sexual mi- norities in the production of systems of classification, but in Society Must Be Defended his target is academic legibility and legitimation, and he de- scribes and analyzes the function of the academic in the circulation and reproduction of hegemonic structures. In place of the "all-encompassing and global theories" that the uni- versityencourages, <u><mark>Foucault exhorts his students to</mark> think about and <mark>turn to "subjugated knowledges,"</u></mark> namely those <u>forms of knowledge produc- tion <mark>that have been "<strong>buried or masked</strong></mark> in functional coherences or formal systematizations"</u> (2003: 7). <u><strong><mark>These forms of knowledge have not</u></strong></mark> simply <u><strong><mark>been lost or forgotten; they have been disqualified, rendered nonsensical</u></strong></mark> or nonconceptual or "insufficiently elaborated." Foucault calls them " <u>naive knowledges, hierarchically inferior knowledges</u>, knowledges that are below the required level of erudition or scientificity" (7) —<u>this is what we mean by knowledge from below. </u>In relation to the identification of "subjugated knowledges," we might ask, How do we participate in the production and circulation of "sub- jugated knowledge"? How do we keep disciplinary forms of knowledge at bay? How do we avoid precisely the "scientific" forms of knowing that relegate other modes of knowing to the redundant or irrelevant? How do we engage in and teach antidisciplinary knowledge? Foucault pro- poses this answer: "Truth to tell, <u>if we are to struggle against disciplines, or</u> rather against <u>disciplinary power, in our search for a nondisciplin- ary power, we should not be turning to the old right of sovereignty; we should be looking to a new right that is both anti-disciplinary and eman- cipated from the principle of sovereignty</u>" (2003: 40). In some sense we have to untrain ourselves so that we can read the struggles and debates back into questions that seem settled and resolved. On behalfofsuch a project, and in the spirit of the "Seven Theses" pro- posed by Moten and Harney, <u>this book joins forces with their "subversive intellectual" and agrees <strong>to steal from the university, to</u></strong>, as they say, <u><strong>"abuse its hospitality" and to be "in but not of it"</u></strong> (101). <u>Moten and Harney's theses exhort the subversive intellectual to,</u> among other things, <u>worry about the university, refuse professionalization, forge a collectivity, and retreat to the external world beyond the ivied walls of the campus</u>. <u>I would add</u> to their theses <u>the following</u>. First, <u><strong><mark>Resist mastery</u></strong></mark>. Here <u>we might in- sist upon a critique of the "all-encompassing and global theories"</u> iden- tified by Foucault. In my book <u>this resistance takes the form of invest- ing in counterintuitive modes of knowing such as failure and stupidity</u>; <u><strong>we might read failure</u></strong>, for example, <u><strong>as a refusal of mastery</strong>, a critique of the intuitive connections within capitalism between success and profit, and <strong>as a counterhegemonic discourse of losing.</u></strong> <u>Stupidity could refer not </u>simply <u>to a lack of knowledge but to the limits of certain forms of know- ing and certain ways of inhabiting structures of knowing. </p></u>
1NC
null
Off
1,240,717
97
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,961
Spread of disease causes extinction
Butler 6
Rhett Butler 6-- BS from UCSD, founder of Mongabay.com, speaker at Stanford University, UC Berkeley, UCSC, participant in the US State Department Speakers Program in Indonesia, “LOSS OF SPECIES FOR FOREST REGENERATION,” [rainforests.mongabay.com/0904.htm]
null
Disease could lead to a massive human die-off populations will continue to be menaced by diseases any disease can be incubated for enough time to allow penetration into developed countries doctor infected with the ebola can board a plane and land in London The virus could quickly spread, among the city's population every person at the airport can unknowingly carry the pathogen home to their countries
Disease can break out among humans. Although not unleashed yet, someday one of these microscopic killers could lead to a massive human die-off as deadly for our species as we have been for the species of the rainforest. Until then, local populations will continue to be menaced by mosquito-borne diseases like dengue fever, Rift Valley fever, and malaria, and water-borne diseases like cholera. Many emergent and resurgent diseases are directly linked to land alterations which bring humans in closer contact with such pathogens. For example, malaria and snailborne schistosomiasis have escalated because of the creation of artificial pools of water like dams, rice paddies, drainage ditches, irrigation canals, and puddles created by tractor treads. Malaria is a particular problem in deforested and degraded areas, though not in forested zones where there are few stagnant ground pools for mosquito breeding. These pools are most abundant in cleared regions and areas where tractors tear gashes in the earth. Malaria is already a major threat to indigenous peoples who have developed no resistance to the disease nor any access to antimalarial drugs. Malaria alone is cited as being responsible for killing an estimated 20 percent of the Yanomani in Brazil and Venezuela. Malaria—caused by unicelluar parasites transferred in the saliva of mosquitoes when they bite—is an especially frightening disease for its drug-resistant forms. Thanks to poor prescribing techniques on the part of doctors, there are now strains in Southeast Asia reputed to be resistant to more than 20 anti-malarial drugs. There is serious concern that global climate change will affect the distribution of malaria, which currently infects roughly 270 million people worldwide and kills 1-2 million a year— 430,000-680,000 children in sub-Saharan Africa alone. The outbreak of disease in the tropics does not affect only the people of those countries, since virtually any disease can be incubated for enough time to allow penetration into the temperate developed countries. For example, any Central African doctor infected with the ebola virus from a patient can board a plane and land in London within 10 hours. The virus could quickly spread, especially if airborne, among the city's population of 8 million. Additionally, every person at the airport who is exposed can unknowingly carry the pathogen home to their native countries around the world.
2,426
<h4>Spread of disease causes extinction</h4><p>Rhett <u><strong>Butler 6</u></strong>-- BS from UCSD, founder of Mongabay.com, speaker at Stanford University, UC Berkeley, UCSC, participant in the US State Department Speakers Program in Indonesia, “LOSS OF SPECIES FOR FOREST REGENERATION,” [rainforests.mongabay.com/0904.htm]</p><p><mark>Disease </mark>can break out among humans. Although not unleashed yet, someday one of these microscopic killers <mark>could lead to a massive human die-off </mark>as deadly for our species as we have been for the species of the rainforest. Until then, local <mark>populations will continue to be menaced by</mark> mosquito-borne <mark>diseases</mark> like dengue fever, Rift Valley fever, and malaria, and water-borne diseases like cholera. Many emergent and resurgent diseases are directly linked to land alterations which bring humans in closer contact with such pathogens. For example, malaria and snailborne schistosomiasis have escalated because of the creation of artificial pools of water like dams, rice paddies, drainage ditches, irrigation canals, and puddles created by tractor treads. Malaria is a particular problem in deforested and degraded areas, though not in forested zones where there are few stagnant ground pools for mosquito breeding. These pools are most abundant in cleared regions and areas where tractors tear gashes in the earth. Malaria is already a major threat to indigenous peoples who have developed no resistance to the disease nor any access to antimalarial drugs. Malaria alone is cited as being responsible for killing an estimated 20 percent of the Yanomani in Brazil and Venezuela. Malaria—caused by unicelluar parasites transferred in the saliva of mosquitoes when they bite—is an especially frightening disease for its drug-resistant forms. Thanks to poor prescribing techniques on the part of doctors, there are now strains in Southeast Asia reputed to be resistant to more than 20 anti-malarial drugs. There is serious concern that global climate change will affect the distribution of malaria, which currently infects roughly 270 million people worldwide and kills 1-2 million a year— 430,000-680,000 children in sub-Saharan Africa alone. The outbreak of disease in the tropics does not affect only the people of those countries, since virtually <mark>any disease can be incubated for enough time to allow penetration into</mark> the temperate <mark>developed countries</mark>. For example, any Central African <mark>doctor infected with the ebola</mark> virus from a patient <mark>can board a plane</mark> <mark>and land in London</mark> within 10 hours. <mark>The virus could quickly spread, </mark>especially if airborne,<mark> among the city's population</mark> of 8 million. Additionally, <mark>every person at the airport</mark> who is exposed <mark>can unknowingly carry the pathogen home to their </mark>native <mark>countries</mark> around the world.</p>
1NR
DA
Trade
274,927
4
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,962
Legalizing increases sex trafficking, multiple links:
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><u><strong>Legalizing increases sex trafficking, multiple links: </h4></u></strong>
1NC
null
Off
430,062
1
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,963
The role of the ballot is to endorse the best strategy for challenging dominant historical relationships of knowledge and power. T represents their intellectual strategy.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The role of the ballot is to endorse the best strategy for challenging dominant historical relationships of knowledge and power. T represents their intellectual strategy.</h4>
T
null
null
430,064
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,964
The bioethical imperative underlying medicalization is steeped in contradictions – that the physician has a duty to stave off that which comes inevitably to all, that health becomes an empty signifier at the moment of its address – suicide as renunciation is a demand for destruction which reveals these paradoxes and breaks the cycle of appropriating individuals into socioeconomic regimes of autonomy
null
Illich 94
SJE Agony has been corrupted by the medicalization of death.¶ Health and responsibility have been made largely impossible from a technical point of view. Adaptation to the misanthropic genetic, climatic, chemical and cultural consequences of growth is now described as health. health as an orienting behavior which requires management belong with those post-industrial conjuring formulas which suggestively connote much, but denote nothing that can be grasped as soon as health is addressed, it has already turned into a sense-destroying pathogen word husks which one can wave around, making oneself important, but which can say or do nothing In a world which worships an ontology of systems, ethical responsibility is reduced to a legitimizing formality. The poisoning of the world is not the result of an irresponsible decision, but rather of our individual presence in an unjustifiable web of interconnections. It would be politically naive, to somehow resurrect them through inclusion into a personal project; some kind of resistance is demanded. Instead of brutal self-enforcement maxims, the new health requires the smooth integration of my immune system into a socioeconomic world system. Being asked for responsibility is a demand for the destruction of sense and self. this proposed self-assignment to a system stands in stark contrast to suicide. It demands self-extinction in a world hostile to death. I favor those renunciations which an a-mortal society would label suicide I must publicly expose the idealization of "healthy" self-integration.
Agony has been corrupted by the medicalization of death Health and responsibility have been made largely impossible from a technical point of view health as an orienting behavior which requires management as soon as health is addressed, it has already turned into a sense-destroying pathogen word husks which one can wave around but which can say or do nothing In a world which worships an ontology of systems, ethical responsibility is reduced to a legitimizing formality. The poisoning of the world is the result of our individual presence in an unjustifiable web of interconnections. It would be politically naive to resurrect them through inclusion into a personal project Instead of self-enforcement maxims, the new health requires the smooth integration of my immune system into a socioeconomic world system. Being asked for responsibility is a demand for the destruction of sense and self. this proposed self-assignment to a system stands in stark contrast to suicide. It demands self-extinction in a world hostile to death. I favor those renunciations society would label suicide, I must publicly expose the idealization of "healthy" self-integration.
Ivan, Ph.D from the University of Salzburg, “BRAVE NEW BIOCRACY: HEALTH CARE FROM WOMB TO TOMB,” New Perspectives Quarterly, Winter 1994, Vol. 11, Issue 1, http://brandon.multics.org/library/Ivan%20Illich/against_life.html SJE LIFE AS ECOLOGY | Ecology can mean the study of correlations between living forms and their habitat. The term is also and increasingly used for a philosophical way of correlating all knowable phenomena. It then signifies thinking in terms of a cybernetic system which. in real time is both model and reality: A process which observes and defines, regulates and sustains itself. Within this style of thinking, life comes to be equated with the system: It is the abstract fetish that both overshadows and simultaneously constitutes it.¶ Epistemic sentimentality has its roots in this conceptual collapse of the borderline between cosmic process and substance, and the mythical embodiment of both in the fetish of life. Being conceived as a system, the cosmos is imagined in analogy to an entity which can be rationally analyzed and managed.¶ Simultaneously, this very same abstract mechanism is romantically identified with life and spoken about in hushed tones as something mysterious, polymorphic, weak, demanding tender protection.¶ In a new kind of reading, Genesis now tells how Adam and Eve were entrusted with life and the further improvement of its quality. This new Adam is potter and nurse of the Golem, his artificial creation.¶ In the sickening manufactured environment we have made for ourselves, health in the Hippocratic tradition has become an impossibility; balance has become hope-less.¶ The hope once symbolized in the mystery of the unborn has been corrupted; now there is only the legal entity of the fetus monitored on the sonogram. Agony, too, has been corrupted by the medicalization of death.¶ Dignity will not be found in the universal health care now demanded, but in hygienic autonomy and in a new found art of suffering and dying. In modern sickness I see the occasion for this discovery.¶ Health and responsibility have been made largely impossible from a technical point of view. This was not clear to me when I wrote Medical Nemesis, and perhaps was not yet the case at that time. In hindsight, it was a mistake to understand health as the quality of "survival," and as the "intensity of coping behavior."¶ Adaptation to the misanthropic genetic, climatic, chemical and cultural consequences of growth is now described as health. Neither the Galenic-Hippocratic representations of balance, nor the Enlightenment utopia of a right to "health and happiness," nor any Vedic or Chinese concepts of well-being, have anything to do with survival in a technical system.¶ "Health" as function, process, mode of communication; health as an orienting behavior which requires management -- these belong with those post-industrial conjuring formulas which suggestively connote much, but denote nothing that can be grasped. And as soon as health is addressed, it has already turned into a sense-destroying pathogen, a member of a word family which Uwe Poerksen calls plastic words, word husks which one can wave around, making oneself important, but which can say or do nothing.¶ The situation is similar with responsibility, although to demonstrate this is much more difficult. In a world which worships an ontology of systems, ethical responsibility is reduced to a legitimizing formality. The poisoning of the world is not the result of an irresponsible decision, but rather of our individual presence, as when traveling by airplane or commuting on the freeway, in an unjustifiable web of interconnections. It would be politically naive, after health and responsibility have been made technically impossible, to somehow resurrect them through inclusion into a personal project; some kind of resistance is demanded.¶ Instead of brutal self-enforcement maxims, the new health requires the smooth integration of my immune system into a socioeconomic world system. Being asked for responsibility is, when seen more clearly, a demand for the destruction of sense and self. And this proposed self-assignment to a system stands in stark contrast to suicide. It demands self-extinction in a world hostile to death. Precisely because I favor those renunciations which an a-mortal society would label suicide, I must publicly expose the idealization of "healthy" self-integration.
4,417
<h4><strong>The bioethical imperative underlying medicalization is steeped in contradictions – that the physician has a duty to stave off that which comes inevitably to all, that health becomes an empty signifier at the moment of its address – suicide as renunciation is a demand for destruction which reveals these paradoxes and breaks the cycle of appropriating individuals into socioeconomic regimes of autonomy</h4><p></strong>Illich 94</p><p>Ivan, Ph.D from the University of Salzburg, “BRAVE NEW BIOCRACY: HEALTH CARE FROM WOMB TO TOMB,” New Perspectives Quarterly, Winter 1994, Vol. 11, Issue 1, http://brandon.multics.org/library/Ivan%20Illich/against_life.html<u><strong> SJE</p><p></u></strong>LIFE AS ECOLOGY | Ecology can mean the study of correlations between living forms and their habitat. The term is also and increasingly used for a philosophical way of correlating all knowable phenomena. It then signifies thinking in terms of a cybernetic system which. in real time is both model and reality: A process which observes and defines, regulates and sustains itself. Within this style of thinking, life comes to be equated with the system: It is the abstract fetish that both overshadows and simultaneously constitutes it.¶ Epistemic sentimentality has its roots in this conceptual collapse of the borderline between cosmic process and substance, and the mythical embodiment of both in the fetish of life. Being conceived as a system, the cosmos is imagined in analogy to an entity which can be rationally analyzed and managed.¶ Simultaneously, this very same abstract mechanism is romantically identified with life and spoken about in hushed tones as something mysterious, polymorphic, weak, demanding tender protection.¶ In a new kind of reading, Genesis now tells how Adam and Eve were entrusted with life and the further improvement of its quality. This new Adam is potter and nurse of the Golem, his artificial creation.¶ In the sickening manufactured environment we have made for ourselves, health in the Hippocratic tradition has become an impossibility; balance has become hope-less.¶ The hope once symbolized in the mystery of the unborn has been corrupted; now there is only the legal entity of the fetus monitored on the sonogram. <u><strong><mark>Agony</u></strong></mark>, too, <u><strong><mark>has been corrupted by the medicalization of death</mark>.¶</u></strong> Dignity will not be found in the universal health care now demanded, but in hygienic autonomy and in a new found art of suffering and dying. In modern sickness I see the occasion for this discovery.¶ <u><strong><mark>Health and responsibility have been made largely impossible from a technical point of view</mark>.</u></strong> This was not clear to me when I wrote Medical Nemesis, and perhaps was not yet the case at that time. In hindsight, it was a mista<strong>k</strong>e to understand health as the quality of "survival," and as the "intensity of coping behavior."¶ <u><strong>Adaptation to the misanthropic genetic, climatic, chemical and cultural consequences of growth is now described as health.</u></strong> Neither the Galenic-Hippocratic representations of balance, nor the Enlightenment utopia of a right to "health and happiness," nor any Vedic or Chinese concepts of well-being, have anything to do with survival in a technical system.¶ "Health" as function, process, mode of communication; <u><strong><mark>health as an orienting behavior which requires management</u></strong></mark> -- these <u><strong>belong with those post-industrial conjuring formulas which suggestively connote much, but denote nothing that can be grasped</u></strong>. And <u><strong><mark>as soon as health is addressed, it has already turned into a sense-destroying pathogen</u></strong></mark>, a member of a word family which Uwe Poerksen calls plastic words, <u><strong><mark>word husks which one can wave around</mark>, making oneself important, <mark>but which can say or do nothing</u></strong></mark>.¶ The situation is similar with responsibility, although to demonstrate this is much more difficult. <u><strong><mark>In a world which worships an ontology of systems, ethical responsibility is reduced to a legitimizing formality. The poisoning of the world is</mark> not <mark>the result of</mark> an irresponsible decision, but rather of <mark>our individual presence</u></strong></mark>, as when traveling by airplane or commuting on the freeway, <u><strong><mark>in an unjustifiable web of interconnections. It would be politically naive</mark>,</u></strong> after health and responsibility have been made technically impossible, <u><strong><mark>to</mark> somehow <mark>resurrect them through inclusion into a personal project</mark>; some kind of resistance is demanded.</u></strong>¶ <u><strong><mark>Instead of</mark> brutal <mark>self-enforcement maxims, the new health requires the smooth integration of my immune system into a socioeconomic world system. Being asked for responsibility is</u></strong></mark>, when seen more clearly, <u><strong><mark>a demand for the destruction of sense and self.</u></strong></mark> And <u><strong><mark>this proposed self-assignment to a system stands in stark contrast to suicide. It demands self-extinction in a world hostile to death.</u></strong></mark> Precisely because <u><strong><mark>I favor those renunciations</mark> which an a-mortal <mark>society would label suicide</u></strong>, <u><strong>I must publicly expose the idealization of "healthy" self-integration.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
1AC
null
430,065
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,965
No relations impact
Leonard 12
Leonard 12 (Mark Leonard is co-founder and director of the European Council on Foreign Relations, the first pan-European think tank., 7/24/2012, "The End of the Affair", www.foreignpolicy.com/articles/2012/07/24/the_end_of_the_affair)
the Western alliance has never loomed smaller in the imagination of policymakers on either side of the Atlantic there is not a single problem in the world to be looked at primarily through a transatlantic prism Although the administration looks first to Europeans as partners it no longer sees the European theater as its core problem or seeks a partnership of equals with Europeans Europeans have never cared less about what the United States thinks Germany has led the pack Europeans who for many years were infantilized by the transatlantic alliance, either using sycophancy and self-delusion about a "special relationship" to advance their goals have finally come to realize that they can no longer outsource their security or their prosperity to Uncle Sam the ties that held the alliance together are weakening Obama's biography links him to the Pacific and Africa but not to the old continent The end of the Cold War means that Europeans no longer need American protection Obama's lack of warmth has precluded him from establishing the sorts of human relationships with European leaders that animate alliances Obama s transactional nature has led to a neglect of countries that he feels will not contribute more to the relationship Obama managed to alienate the leaders of most of Europe's big states Europe's collective nose was put out of joint by Obama's refusal to make the trip to Europe for the 2010 EU-U.S. summit Obama has reached out far too late to erase the sense that Europe matters little to this American president Underlying these superficial issues is a more fundamental divergence in the way Europe and the United States are coping with their respective declines Europeans have sought to help build a multilateral, rule-based world. however, Europeans have not put their energies into becoming a full partner on global issues Europeans have not pooled their impressive economic, political, and military resources. with the eurozone's need to resolve the euro crisis, the EU may split into two or more tiers -- making concerted action even more difficult European power is too diffuse to be much of a help or a hindrance on many issues Obama's United States thinks that the best way to safeguard American interests and values is to craft a multipartner world Obama continues to believe that he can transform rising powers by integrating them into existing institutions As relative power flows Eastward it is inevitable that the Western alliance is fading fast It was perhaps inevitable that both Europeans and Americans should fail to live up to each other's expectations of their respective roles in a post-Cold War world America is still too powerful to happily commit to a multilateral world Europe is too physically safe to be willing to match U.S. defense
the Western alliance has never loomed smaller in the imagination of policymakers on either side of the Atlantic there is not a single problem in the world to be looked at through a transatlantic prism. the ties that held the alliance together are weakening The end of the Cold War means that Europeans no longer need American protection Obama's lack of warmth has precluded him from establishing human relationships with European leaders Obama reached out too late to erase the fundamental divergence in the way Europe and the U S are coping with declines European power is too diffuse to help it is inevitable that the Western alliance is fading fast America is still too powerful Europe is too physically safe
But Obama's stellar personal ratings in Europe hide the fact that the Western alliance has never loomed smaller in the imagination of policymakers on either side of the Atlantic. Seen from Washington, there is not a single problem in the world to be looked at primarily through a transatlantic prism. Although the administration looks first to Europeans as partners in any of its global endeavors -- from dealing with Iran's nuclear program to stopping genocide in Syria -- it no longer sees the European theater as its core problem or seeks a partnership of equals with Europeans. It was not until the eurozone looked like it might collapse -- threatening to bring down the global economy and with it Obama's chances of reelection -- that the president became truly interested in Europe. Conversely, Europeans have never cared less about what the United States thinks. Germany, traditionally among the most Atlanticist of European countries, has led the pack. Many German foreign-policy makers think it was simply a tactical error for Berlin to line up with Moscow and Beijing against Washington on Libya. But there is nothing accidental about the way Berlin has systematically refused even to engage with American concerns over German policy on the euro. During the Bush years, Europeans who were unable to influence the strategy of the White House would give a running commentary on American actions in lieu of a substantive policy. They had no influence in Washington, so they complained. But now, the tables are turned, with Obama passing continual judgment on German policy while Chancellor Angela Merkel stoically refuses to heed his advice. Europeans who for many years were infantilized by the transatlantic alliance, either using sycophancy and self-delusion about a "special relationship" to advance their goals or, in the case of Jacques Chirac's France, pursuing the even more futile goal of balancing American power, have finally come to realize that they can no longer outsource their security or their prosperity to Uncle Sam. On both sides of the Atlantic, the ties that held the alliance together are weakening. On the American side, Obama's biography links him to the Pacific and Africa but not to the old continent. His personal story echoes the demographic changes in the United States that have reduced the influence of Americans of European origin. Meanwhile, on the European side, the depth of the euro crisis has crowded out almost all foreign policy from the agenda of Europe's top decision-makers. The end of the Cold War means that Europeans no longer need American protection, and the U.S. financial crisis has led to a fall in American demand for European products (although U.S. exports to Europe are at an all-time high). What's more, Obama's lack of warmth has precluded him from establishing the sorts of human relationships with European leaders that animate alliances. When asked to name his closest allies, Obama mentions non-European leaders such as Recep Tayyip Erdogan of Turkey and Lee Myung-bak of South Korea. And his transactional nature has led to a neglect of countries that he feels will not contribute more to the relationship -- within a year of being elected, Obama had managed to alienate the leaders of most of Europe's big states, from Gordon Brown to Nicolas Sarkozy to Jose Luis Rodriguez Zapatero. Americans hardly remember, but Europe's collective nose was put out of joint by Obama's refusal to make the trip to Europe for the 2010 EU-U.S. summit. More recently, Obama has reached out to allies to counteract the impression that the only way to get a friendly reception in Washington is to be a problem nation -- but far too late to erase the sense that Europe matters little to this American president. Underlying these superficial issues is a more fundamental divergence in the way Europe and the United States are coping with their respective declines. As the EU's role shrinks in the world, Europeans have sought to help build a multilateral, rule-based world. That is why it is they, rather than the Chinese or the Americans, that have pushed for the creation of institutionalized global responses to climate change, genocide, or various trade disputes. To the extent that today's world has not collapsed into the deadlocked chaos of a "G-zero," it is often due to European efforts to create a functioning institutional order. To Washington's eternal frustration, however, Europeans have not put their energies into becoming a full partner on global issues. For all the existential angst of the euro crisis, Europe is not as weak as people think it is. It still has the world's largest market and represents 17 percent of world trade, compared with 12 percent for the United States. Even in military terms, the EU is the world's No. 2 military power, with 21 percent of the world's military spending, versus 5 percent for China, 3 percent for Russia, 2 percent for India, and 1.5 percent for Brazil, according to Harvard scholar Joseph Nye. But, ironically for a people who have embraced multilateralism more than any other on Earth, Europeans have not pooled their impressive economic, political, and military resources. And with the eurozone's need to resolve the euro crisis, the EU may split into two or more tiers -- making concerted action even more difficult. As a result, European power is too diffuse to be much of a help or a hindrance on many issues. On the other hand, Obama's United States -- although equally committed to liberal values -- thinks that the best way to safeguard American interests and values is to craft a multipartner world. On the one hand, Obama continues to believe that he can transform rising powers by integrating them into existing institutions (despite much evidence to the contrary). On the other, he thinks that Europe's overrepresentation in existing institutions like the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund is a threat to the consolidation of that order. This is leading a declining America to increasingly turn against Europe on issues ranging from climate change to currencies. The most striking example came at the 2009 G-20 in Pittsburgh, when Obama worked together with the emerging powers to pressure Europeans to give up their voting power at the IMF. As Walter Russell Mead, the U.S. international relations scholar, has written, "[I]ncreasingly it will be in the American interest to help Asian powers rebalance the world power structure in ways that redistribute power from the former great powers of Europe to the rising great powers of Asia today." But the long-term consequence of the cooling of this unique alliance could be the hollowing out of the world order that the Atlantic powers have made. The big unwritten story of the last few decades is the way that a European-inspired liberal economic and political order has been crafted in the shell of the American security order. It is an order that limits the powers of states and markets and puts the protection of individuals at its core. If the United States was the sheriff of this order, the EU was its constitutional court. And now it is being challenged by the emerging powers. Countries like Brazil, China, and India are all relatively new states forged by movements of national liberation whose experience of globalization has been bound up with their new sense of nationhood. While globalization is destroying sovereignty for the West, these former colonies are enjoying it on a scale never experienced before. As a result, they are not about to invite their former colonial masters to interfere in their internal affairs. Just look at the dynamics of the United Nations Security Council on issues from Sudan to Syria. Even in the General Assembly, the balance of power is shifting: 10 years ago, China won 43 percent of the votes on human rights in the United Nations, far behind Europe's 78 percent. But in 2010-11, the EU won less than 50 percent to China's nearly 60 percent, according to research by the European Council on Foreign Relations. Rather than being transformed by global institutions, China's sophisticated multilateral diplomacy is changing the global order itself. As relative power flows Eastward, it is perhaps inevitable that the Western alliance that kept liberty's flame alight during the Cold War and then sought to construct a liberal order in its aftermath is fading fast. It was perhaps inevitable that both Europeans and Americans should fail to live up to each other's expectations of their respective roles in a post-Cold War world. After all, America is still too powerful to happily commit to a multilateral world order (as evidenced by Congress's reluctance to ratify treaties). And Europe is too physically safe to be willing to match U.S. defense spending or pool its resources. What is surprising is that the passing of this alliance has not been mourned by many on either side. The legacy of Barack Obama is that the transatlantic relationship is at its most harmonious and yet least relevant in 50 years. Ironically, it may take the election of someone who is less naturally popular on the European stage for both sides to wake up and realize just what is at stake.
9,198
<h4>No relations impact</h4><p><u><strong>Leonard 12</u></strong> (Mark Leonard is co-founder and director of the European Council on Foreign Relations, the first pan-European think tank., 7/24/2012, "The End of the Affair", www.foreignpolicy.com/articles/2012/07/24/the_end_of_the_affair)</p><p>But Obama's stellar personal ratings in Europe hide the fact that <u><mark>the Western alliance has <strong>never loomed smaller</strong></mark> <mark>in the imagination of policymakers on either side of the Atlantic</u></mark>. Seen from Washington, <u><mark>there is <strong>not a single problem in the world to be looked at</mark> primarily <mark>through a transatlantic prism</u></strong>. <u></mark>Although the administration looks first to Europeans as partners</u> in any of its global endeavors -- from dealing with Iran's nuclear program to stopping genocide in Syria -- <u>it no longer sees the European theater as its core problem or seeks a partnership of equals with Europeans</u>. It was not until the eurozone looked like it might collapse -- threatening to bring down the global economy and with it Obama's chances of reelection -- that the president became truly interested in Europe. Conversely, <u>Europeans have never cared less about what the United States thinks</u>. <u>Germany</u>, traditionally among the most Atlanticist of European countries, <u>has led the pack</u>. Many German foreign-policy makers think it was simply a tactical error for Berlin to line up with Moscow and Beijing against Washington on Libya. But there is nothing accidental about the way Berlin has systematically refused even to engage with American concerns over German policy on the euro. During the Bush years, Europeans who were unable to influence the strategy of the White House would give a running commentary on American actions in lieu of a substantive policy. They had no influence in Washington, so they complained. But now, the tables are turned, with Obama passing continual judgment on German policy while Chancellor Angela Merkel stoically refuses to heed his advice. <u>Europeans who for many years were infantilized by the transatlantic alliance, either using sycophancy and self-delusion about a "special relationship" to advance their goals</u> or, in the case of Jacques Chirac's France, pursuing the even more futile goal of balancing American power, <u>have finally come to realize that they can no longer outsource their security or their prosperity to Uncle Sam</u>. On both sides of the Atlantic, <u><strong><mark>the ties that held the alliance together are weakening</u></strong></mark>. On the American side, <u>Obama's biography links him to the Pacific and Africa but not to the old continent</u>. His personal story echoes the demographic changes in the United States that have reduced the influence of Americans of European origin. Meanwhile, on the European side, the depth of the euro crisis has crowded out almost all foreign policy from the agenda of Europe's top decision-makers. <u><mark>The end of the Cold War means that Europeans no longer need American protection</u></mark>, and the U.S. financial crisis has led to a fall in American demand for European products (although U.S. exports to Europe are at an all-time high). What's more, <u><mark>Obama's lack of warmth has precluded him from establishing</mark> the sorts of <mark>human relationships with European leaders</mark> that animate alliances</u>. When asked to name his closest allies, <u>Obama</u> mentions non-European leaders such as Recep Tayyip Erdogan of Turkey and Lee Myung-bak of South Korea. And hi<u>s</u> <u>transactional nature has led to a neglect of countries that he feels will not contribute more to the relationship</u> -- within a year of being elected, <u>Obama</u> had <u>managed to alienate the leaders of most of Europe's big states</u>, from Gordon Brown to Nicolas Sarkozy to Jose Luis Rodriguez Zapatero. Americans hardly remember, but <u>Europe's collective nose was put out of joint by Obama's refusal to make the trip to Europe for the 2010 EU-U.S. summit</u>. More recently, <u><mark>Obama</mark> has <mark>reached out</u></mark> to allies to counteract the impression that the only way to get a friendly reception in Washington is to be a problem nation -- but <u>far <mark>too late to erase the</mark> sense that Europe matters little to this American president</u>. <u>Underlying these superficial issues is a more <strong><mark>fundamental divergence</u></strong> <u>in the way</u> <u>Europe and the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>are coping with</mark> their respective <mark>declines</u></mark>. As the EU's role shrinks in the world, <u>Europeans have sought to help build a multilateral, rule-based world.</u> That is why it is they, rather than the Chinese or the Americans, that have pushed for the creation of institutionalized global responses to climate change, genocide, or various trade disputes. To the extent that today's world has not collapsed into the deadlocked chaos of a "G-zero," it is often due to European efforts to create a functioning institutional order. To Washington's eternal frustration, <u>however, Europeans have not put their energies into becoming a full partner on global issues</u>. For all the existential angst of the euro crisis, Europe is not as weak as people think it is. It still has the world's largest market and represents 17 percent of world trade, compared with 12 percent for the United States. Even in military terms, the EU is the world's No. 2 military power, with 21 percent of the world's military spending, versus 5 percent for China, 3 percent for Russia, 2 percent for India, and 1.5 percent for Brazil, according to Harvard scholar Joseph Nye. But, ironically for a people who have embraced multilateralism more than any other on Earth, <u>Europeans have not pooled their impressive economic, political, and military resources.</u> And <u>with the eurozone's need to resolve the euro crisis, the EU may split into two or more tiers -- making concerted action even more difficult</u>. As a result, <u><strong><mark>European power is too diffuse to</mark> be much of a <mark>help</mark> or a hindrance on many issues</u></strong>. On the other hand, <u>Obama's United States</u> -- although equally committed to liberal values -- <u>thinks that the best way to safeguard American interests and values is to craft a multipartner world</u>. On the one hand, <u>Obama continues to believe that he can transform rising powers by integrating them into existing institutions</u> (despite much evidence to the contrary). On the other, he thinks that Europe's overrepresentation in existing institutions like the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund is a threat to the consolidation of that order. This is leading a declining America to increasingly turn against Europe on issues ranging from climate change to currencies. The most striking example came at the 2009 G-20 in Pittsburgh, when Obama worked together with the emerging powers to pressure Europeans to give up their voting power at the IMF. As Walter Russell Mead, the U.S. international relations scholar, has written, "[I]ncreasingly it will be in the American interest to help Asian powers rebalance the world power structure in ways that redistribute power from the former great powers of Europe to the rising great powers of Asia today." But the long-term consequence of the cooling of this unique alliance could be the hollowing out of the world order that the Atlantic powers have made. The big unwritten story of the last few decades is the way that a European-inspired liberal economic and political order has been crafted in the shell of the American security order. It is an order that limits the powers of states and markets and puts the protection of individuals at its core. If the United States was the sheriff of this order, the EU was its constitutional court. And now it is being challenged by the emerging powers. Countries like Brazil, China, and India are all relatively new states forged by movements of national liberation whose experience of globalization has been bound up with their new sense of nationhood. While globalization is destroying sovereignty for the West, these former colonies are enjoying it on a scale never experienced before. As a result, they are not about to invite their former colonial masters to interfere in their internal affairs. Just look at the dynamics of the United Nations Security Council on issues from Sudan to Syria. Even in the General Assembly, the balance of power is shifting: 10 years ago, China won 43 percent of the votes on human rights in the United Nations, far behind Europe's 78 percent. But in 2010-11, the EU won less than 50 percent to China's nearly 60 percent, according to research by the European Council on Foreign Relations. Rather than being transformed by global institutions, China's sophisticated multilateral diplomacy is changing the global order itself. <u>As relative power flows Eastward</u>, <u><strong><mark>it is</mark> </u></strong>perhaps <u><strong><mark>inevitable</u></strong> <u>that the Western alliance</u></mark> that kept liberty's flame alight during the Cold War and then sought to construct a liberal order in its aftermath <u><strong><mark>is fading fast</u></strong></mark>. <u>It was perhaps inevitable that both Europeans and Americans should fail to live up to each other's expectations of their respective roles in a post-Cold War world</u>. After all, <u><mark>America is still too powerful</mark> to happily commit to a multilateral world</u> order (as evidenced by Congress's reluctance to ratify treaties). And <u><mark>Europe is too physically safe</mark> to be willing to match U.S. defense</u> spending or pool its resources. What is surprising is that the passing of this alliance has not been mourned by many on either side. The legacy of Barack Obama is that the transatlantic relationship is at its most harmonious and yet least relevant in 50 years. Ironically, it may take the election of someone who is less naturally popular on the European stage for both sides to wake up and realize just what is at stake.</p>
1NR
DA
Europe
76,718
30
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,966
We Meet – we affirm PAS
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><u><strong>We Meet – we affirm PAS </h4></u></strong>
T
null
null
430,066
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,967
So write a new oath, spit on Hippocrates’ grave, cut out your “ethical backbone” and fling it at those who constantly seek to overdetermine, overtreat, overmedicate.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>So write a new oath, spit on Hippocrates’ grave, cut out your “ethical backbone” and fling it at those who constantly seek to overdetermine, overtreat, overmedicate. </h4>
null
1AC
null
430,067
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,968
Cyber terror isn’t possible
Dunlap ‘12
Dunlap ‘12 [Maj. Gen. Charles J. Dunlap Jr. (Ret.), Professor of the Practice of Law¶ Executive Director, Center on Law, Ethics and National Security @ Duke. In Patriot Debates: Contemporary Issues in National Security Law. http://www.americanbar.org/groups/public_services/law_national_security/patriot_debates2/the_book_online/ch9/ch9_ess2.html ETB]
If the United States were as vulnerable to catastrophic attack as Baker would have us believe, al Qaeda or some extremist group certainly would have launched one by now. although cyber crime may be extensive, militarily significant cyber attacks are not so easy to conduct While popular fiction and films depict cyberattacks as easy to mount—only a few computer keystrokes needed—in reality it takes significant digital snooping to identify potential entry points and susceptible nodes and then to write and insert the proper poisonous codes. if cyber weaponry is technically difficult for the world’s foremost military to use even against Libya, one may reasonably infer that it is markedly more difficult to use against a sophisticated first-world power, even for a peer or near peer of that power.
If the U S were vulnerable al Qaeda or some group would have launched one by now cyber attacks are not easy to conduct it takes significant digital snooping to identify entry points and susceptible nodes and to write and insert the proper poisonous codes if cyber weaponry is difficult for the world’s foremost military to use against Libya it is markedly more difficult to use against a sophisticated first-world power
If, indeed, the United States were as vulnerable to catastrophic attack as Baker would have us believe, al Qaeda or some extremist group certainly would have launched one by now. In point of fact, although cyber crime may be extensive, militarily significant cyber attacks apparently are not so easy to conduct as Baker seems to think. In reporting the rejection of cyber weaponry as a means of dismantling ibyan air defenses, The New York Times noted that:¶ While popular fiction and films depict cyberattacks as easy to mount—only a few computer keystrokes needed—in reality it takes significant digital snooping to identify potential entry points and susceptible nodes in a linked network of communications systems, radars and missiles like that operated by the Libyan government, and then to write and insert the proper poisonous codes.36¶ Obviously, if cyber weaponry is technically difficult for the world’s foremost military to use even against a third-world power such as Libya, one may reasonably infer that it is markedly more difficult to use against a sophisticated first-world power, even for a peer or near peer of that power.
1,140
<h4><u><strong>Cyber terror isn’t possible</h4><p>Dunlap ‘12</p><p></u></strong>[Maj. Gen. Charles J. Dunlap Jr. (Ret.), Professor of the Practice of Law¶ Executive Director, Center on Law, Ethics and National Security @ Duke. In <u>Patriot Debates: Contemporary Issues in National Security Law</u>. http://www.americanbar.org/groups/public_services/law_national_security/patriot_debates2/the_book_online/ch9/ch9_ess2.html<u> ETB]</p><p><mark>If</u></mark>, indeed, <u><mark>the</mark> <mark>U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>were</mark> as <mark>vulnerable</mark> to catastrophic attack as Baker would have us believe, <mark>al Qaeda or some</mark> extremist <mark>group</mark> certainly <strong><mark>would have launched one by now</strong></mark>.</u> In point of fact, <u>although cyber crime may be extensive, militarily significant <mark>cyber attacks</u></mark> apparently <u><mark>are</mark> <mark>not</mark> so <mark>easy to conduct</u></mark> as Baker seems to think. In reporting the rejection of cyber weaponry as a means of dismantling ibyan air defenses, The New York Times noted that:¶ <u>While popular fiction and films depict cyberattacks as easy to mount—only a few computer keystrokes needed—in reality <mark>it takes significant digital snooping to identify</mark> potential <mark>entry points and susceptible nodes</u></mark> in a linked network of communications systems, radars and missiles like that operated by the Libyan government, <u><mark>and</mark> then <mark>to write and insert the proper poisonous codes</mark>.</u>36¶ Obviously, <u><mark>if cyber weaponry is</mark> technically <mark>difficult for the</mark> <mark>world’s foremost military to use</mark> even <mark>against</mark> </u>a third-world power such as <u><mark>Libya</mark>, one may reasonably infer that <mark>it is markedly more difficult to use against a sophisticated first-world power</mark>, even for a peer or near peer of that power.</p></u>
1NR
FBI
Cyber
430,069
1
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,969
1. Makes the US a magnet for trafficking – Netherlands proves
Raymond ‘3
Raymond ‘3 [Ph.D. Janice Raymond is a professor at the University of Massachusetts.¶ “Ten Reasons for Not Legalizing Prostitution ¶ And a Legal Response to the Demand for Prostitution.” (Published in simultaneously in hard copy in Journal of Trauma Practice, 2, 2003: ¶ pp. 315-332; and in Prostitution, Trafficking and Traumatic Stress. Melissa Farley ¶ (Ed.). Binghamton: Haworth Press, 2003. ETB]
Legalized prostitution are one of the root causes of sex trafficking 80% of women in the brothels of the Netherlands were trafficked from other countries The Netherlands has removed every legal impediment to ¶ pimping, procuring and brothels NGOs report traffickers use work permits to bring foreign women into the Dutch ¶ prostitution industry, masking the fact that women have been trafficked, by ¶ coaching them to describe themselves as independent “migrant sex workers” since lifting the ban on brothels in the Netherlands Dutch victim ¶ support organizations reported an increase in the number of victims of trafficking, the number of victims from ¶ other countries has not diminished The sheer volume of foreign women in the German prostitution industry suggests that these women were trafficked into Germany, a process euphemistically ¶ described as facilitated migration. It is almost impossible for poor women to facilitate their own migration, underwrite the costs of travel and travel documents, and set themselves up in “business” without intervention. ¶ . Noting the link between legalization of prostitution and trafficking in ¶ Australia, the US Department of State observed: “Trafficking in East Asian ¶ women for the sex trade is a growing problem…lax laws – including legalized ¶ prostitution in parts of the country – make [anti-trafficking] enforcement difficult at ¶ the working level” Legalization/decriminalization of prostitution does not control the sex ¶ industry. It expands it. ¶ ). Over the last decade, as pimping was ¶ legalized, and brothels decriminalized in the year 2000, the sex industry ¶ increased by 25% in the Netherlands Most of them are women from other countries who were probably trafficked into ¶ the Netherlands prostitution is promoted by associations of sex businesses and ¶ organizations comprised of prostitution buyers who consult and collaborate with ¶ the government to further their interests. As prostitution has been transformed into “sex work,” and pimps into ¶ entrepreneurs, so too this recommendation transforms trafficking into “voluntary ¶ migration for sex work.” the Netherlands is targeting poor ¶ women for the international sex trade to remedy the inadequacies of the free ¶ market of “sexual services.” Prostitution is thus normalized as an “option for the ¶ poor.” Legalization of prostitution in Australia, resulted in massive ¶ expansion of the sex industry Along with legalization of prostitution, other forms ¶ of sexual exploitation, such as tabletop dancing, bondage and discipline centers, ¶ peep shows, phone sex, and pornography, have all developed in much more ¶ profitable ways than before legalization Prostitution ¶ has become an integral part of the tourism boom state sponsored prostitution countries serve as magnets and, ultimately, as conduits through which significant numbers of women are trafficked to other nations (IOM) has estimated that 500,000 women and children ¶ are trafficked in Europe annually In contrast, it has been estimated ¶ that 45,000-50,000 women and children are trafficked annually into the United ¶ States
Legalized prostitution are one of the root causes of sex trafficking 80% in the Netherlands were trafficked traffickers use work permits to maski that women have been trafficked Dutch ¶ support organizations reported an increase in victims The sheer volume of foreign women in the German industry suggests these women were trafficked It is almost impossible for poor women to facilitate their own migration, underwrite the costs of travel and set up business” without intervention prostitution is promoted by sex businesses who collaborate with government to further their interests state sponsored prostitution countries serve as magnets and, conduits through which significant numbers of women are trafficked to other nations 500,000 are trafficked in Europe annually In contrast, 45,000 are trafficked into the Un S
Legalized or decriminalized prostitution industries are one of the root causes of sex trafficking. One argument for legalizing prostitution in the Netherlands was ¶ that legalization would help to end the exploitation of desperate immigrant ¶ women who had been trafficked there for prostitution. However, one report found ¶ that 80% of women in the brothels of the Netherlands were trafficked from other countries (Budapest Group, 1999)(1). In 1994, the International Organization of ¶ Migration (IOM) stated that in the Netherlands alone, “nearly 70 % of trafficked ¶ women were from CEEC [Central and Eastern European Countries]” (IOM, 1995, ¶ p. 4). The government of the Netherlands presents itself as a champion of anti-¶ trafficking policies and programs, yet it has removed every legal impediment to ¶ pimping, procuring and brothels. In the year 2000, the Dutch Ministry of Justice ¶ argued in favor of a legal quota of foreign “sex workers,” because the Dutch ¶ prostitution market demanded a variety of “bodies” (Dutting, 2001, p. 16). Also in ¶ 2000, the Dutch government sought and received a judgment from the European ¶ Court recognizing prostitution as an economic activity, thereby enabling women ¶ from the European Union and former Soviet bloc countries to obtain working ¶ permits as “sex workers” in the Dutch sex industry if they could prove that they ¶ are self employed. Non-governmental organizations (NGOs) in Europe report ¶ that traffickers use the work permits to bring foreign women into the Dutch ¶ prostitution industry, masking the fact that women have been trafficked, by ¶ coaching them to describe themselves as independent “migrant sex workers” ¶ (Personal Communication, Representative of the International Human Rights ¶ Network, 1999).¶ In the year since lifting the ban on brothels in the Netherlands, eight Dutch victim ¶ support organizations reported an increase in the number of victims of trafficking, ¶ and twelve victim support organization reported that the number of victims from ¶ other countries has not diminished (Bureau NRM, 2002, p. 75). Forty-three of ¶ the 348 municipalities (12%) in the Netherlands choose to follow a no-brothel ¶ policy, but the Minister of Justice has indicated that the complete banning of ¶ prostitution within any municipality could conflict with the federally guaranteed ¶ “right to free choice of work” (Bureau NRM, 2002, p.19). ¶ ¶ The first steps toward legalization of prostitution in Germany occurred in the ¶ 1980s. By 1993, it was widely recognized that 75% of the women in Germany’s ¶ prostitution industry were foreigners from Uruguay, Argentina, Paraguay and other countries in South America (Altink, 1993, p. 33). After the fall of the Berlin ¶ wall, 80% of the estimated 10,000 women trafficked into Germany were from ¶ Central and Eastern Europe and CIS countries (IOM. 1998a , p. 17). In 2002, ¶ prostitution in Germany was established as a legitimate job after years of being ¶ legalized in tolerance zones. Promotion of prostitution, pimping and brothels are ¶ now legal in Germany. ¶ ¶ The sheer volume of foreign women in the German prostitution industry suggests that these women were trafficked into Germany, a process euphemistically ¶ described as facilitated migration. It is almost impossible for poor women to facilitate their own migration, underwrite the costs of travel and travel documents, and set themselves up in “business” without intervention. ¶ ¶ In 1984, a Labor government in the Australian State of Victoria introduced ¶ legislation to legalize prostitution in brothels. Subsequent Australian ¶ governments expanded legalization culminating in the Prostitution Control Act of ¶ 1994. Noting the link between legalization of prostitution and trafficking in ¶ Australia, the US Department of State observed: “Trafficking in East Asian ¶ women for the sex trade is a growing problem…lax laws – including legalized ¶ prostitution in parts of the country – make [anti-trafficking] enforcement difficult at ¶ the working level” (U.S. Department of State, 2000, p. 6F). ¶ ¶ 3. Legalization/decriminalization of prostitution does not control the sex ¶ industry. It expands it. ¶ ¶ Contrary to claims that legalization and decriminalization would control the ¶ expansion of the sex industry, prostitution now accounts for 5% of the ¶ Netherlands economy (Daley, 2001, p. 4). Over the last decade, as pimping was ¶ legalized, and brothels decriminalized in the year 2000, the sex industry ¶ increased by 25% in the Netherlands (Daley, 2001, p.4). At any hour of the day, ¶ women of all ages and races, dressed in hardly anything, are put on display in ¶ the notorious windows of Dutch brothels and sex clubs and offered for sale. ¶ Most of them are women from other countries who were probably trafficked into ¶ the Netherlands (Daley, 2001, p. 4). ¶ ¶ In addition to governmental endorsement of prostitution in the Netherlands, ¶ prostitution is also promoted by associations of sex businesses and ¶ organizations comprised of prostitution buyers who consult and collaborate with ¶ the government to further their interests. These include the “Association of ¶ Operators of Relaxation Businesses,” the “Cooperating Consultation of Operators ¶ of Window Prostitution,” and the “Man/Woman and Prostitution Foundation,” a ¶ group of men who regularly use women in prostitution, and whose specific aims ¶ include “to make prostitution and the use of services of prostitutes more accepted ¶ and openly discussible,” and “to protect the interests of clients” (Bureau NRM, ¶ 2002, pp.115-16). Faced with a dwindling number of Dutch women who engage in prostitution ¶ activities and the expanding demand for more female bodies and more exotic ¶ women to service the prostitution market, the Dutch National Rapporteur on ¶ Trafficking has stated that in the future, a solution may be to “offer [to the market] ¶ prostitutes from non EU/EEA[European Union/European Economic Area] ¶ countries, who voluntarily choose to work in prostitution…” These women would ¶ be given “legal and controlled access to the Dutch market” (Bureau NRM, 2002, ¶ p. 140). As prostitution has been transformed into “sex work,” and pimps into ¶ entrepreneurs, so too this recommendation transforms trafficking into “voluntary ¶ migration for sex work.” Looking to the future, the Netherlands is targeting poor ¶ women for the international sex trade to remedy the inadequacies of the free ¶ market of “sexual services.” Prostitution is thus normalized as an “option for the ¶ poor.” ¶ ¶ Legalization of prostitution in the State of Victoria, Australia, resulted in massive ¶ expansion of the sex industry. Along with legalization of prostitution, other forms ¶ of sexual exploitation, such as tabletop dancing, bondage and discipline centers, ¶ peep shows, phone sex, and pornography, have all developed in much more ¶ profitable ways than before legalization (Sullivan & Jeffreys, 2001). Prostitution ¶ has become an integral part of the tourism and casino boom in Victoria with ¶ government-sponsored casinos authorizing the redeeming of casino chips at ¶ local brothels (Sullivan & Jeffreys, 2001). ¶ ¶ A range of state-sponsored prostitution systems exist in Austria, Denmark, ¶ Germany, the Netherlands and Switzerland. It seems likely that European state sponsored prostitution countries serve as magnets and, ultimately, as conduits through which significant numbers of women are trafficked to other European ¶ nations. Europe has a high density of women trafficked per square mile ¶ compared to North America, for example. Given the porousness of national ¶ borders facilitated by the Schengen agreement (2), it is not surprising that high ¶ numbers of trafficked women are also present in other European countries that ¶ do not have legalized or decriminalized systems of prostitution. Although ¶ accurate numbers of women trafficked are difficult to obtain, the International ¶ Organization of Migration (IOM) has estimated that 500,000 women and children ¶ are trafficked in Europe annually (IOM, 1998). In contrast, it has been estimated ¶ that 45,000-50,000 women and children are trafficked annually into the United ¶ States (Richard, 1999, p.3).
8,240
<h4>1. Makes<u><strong> the US a magnet for trafficking – Netherlands proves</h4><p></u>Raymond ‘3</p><p></strong>[Ph.D. Janice Raymond is a professor at the University of Massachusetts.¶ “Ten Reasons for Not Legalizing Prostitution ¶ And a Legal Response to the Demand for Prostitution.” (Published in simultaneously in hard copy in Journal of Trauma Practice, 2, 2003: ¶ pp. 315-332; and in Prostitution, Trafficking and Traumatic Stress. Melissa Farley ¶ (Ed.). Binghamton: Haworth Press, 2003. ETB]</p><p><u><strong><mark>Legalized</u></strong> </mark>or decriminalized <u><strong><mark>prostitution</u></strong> </mark>industries <u><strong><mark>are one of the root causes of sex trafficking</u></strong></mark>. One argument for legalizing prostitution in the Netherlands was ¶ that legalization would help to end the exploitation of desperate immigrant ¶ women who had been trafficked there for prostitution. However, one report found ¶ that <u><strong><mark>80%</strong> </mark>of women <strong><mark>in</strong> </mark>the brothels of <strong><mark>the</mark> <mark>Netherlands were trafficked</strong> </mark>from other countries</u> (Budapest Group, 1999)(1). In 1994, the International Organization of ¶ Migration (IOM) stated that in the Netherlands alone, “nearly 70 % of trafficked ¶ women were from CEEC [Central and Eastern European Countries]” (IOM, 1995, ¶ p. 4). <u>The</u> government of the <u>Netherlands</u> presents itself as a champion of anti-¶ trafficking policies and programs, yet it <u>has removed every legal impediment to ¶ pimping, procuring and</u> <u>brothels</u>. In the year 2000, the Dutch Ministry of Justice ¶ argued in favor of a legal quota of foreign “sex workers,” because the Dutch ¶ prostitution market demanded a variety of “bodies” (Dutting, 2001, p. 16). Also in ¶ 2000, the Dutch government sought and received a judgment from the European ¶ Court recognizing prostitution as an economic activity, thereby enabling women ¶ from the European Union and former Soviet bloc countries to obtain working ¶ permits as “sex workers” in the Dutch sex industry if they could prove that they ¶ are self employed. Non-governmental organizations (<u>NGOs</u>) in Europe <u>report</u> ¶ that <u><strong><mark>traffickers use</u></strong> </mark>the <u><strong><mark>work permits to</strong> </mark>bring foreign women into the Dutch ¶ prostitution industry, <strong><mark>maski</strong></mark>ng the fact<strong><mark> that women have been trafficked</strong></mark>, by ¶ coaching them to describe themselves as independent “migrant sex workers”</u> ¶ (Personal Communication, Representative of the International Human Rights ¶ Network, 1999).¶ In the year <u>since lifting the ban on brothels in the Netherlands</u>, eight <u><mark>Dutch </mark>victim <mark>¶ support organizations reported an increase in </mark>the number of <mark>victims </mark>of trafficking,</u> ¶ and twelve victim support organization reported that <u>the number of victims from ¶ other countries has not diminished</u> (Bureau NRM, 2002, p. 75). Forty-three of ¶ the 348 municipalities (12%) in the Netherlands choose to follow a no-brothel ¶ policy, but the Minister of Justice has indicated that the complete banning of ¶ prostitution within any municipality could conflict with the federally guaranteed ¶ “right to free choice of work” (Bureau NRM, 2002, p.19). ¶ ¶ The first steps toward legalization of prostitution in Germany occurred in the ¶ 1980s. By 1993, it was widely recognized that 75% of the women in Germany’s ¶ prostitution industry were foreigners from Uruguay, Argentina, Paraguay and other countries in South America (Altink, 1993, p. 33). After the fall of the Berlin ¶ wall, 80% of the estimated 10,000 women trafficked into Germany were from ¶ Central and Eastern Europe and CIS countries (IOM. 1998a , p. 17). In 2002, ¶ prostitution in Germany was established as a legitimate job after years of being ¶ legalized in tolerance zones. Promotion of prostitution, pimping and brothels are ¶ now legal in Germany. ¶ ¶ <u><mark>The sheer volume of foreign women in the German </mark>prostitution <mark>industry suggests</mark> that <mark>these women were trafficked </mark>into Germany, a process euphemistically ¶ described as facilitated migration. <strong><mark>It is almost impossible for poor women to facilitate their own migration, underwrite the costs of</mark> <mark>travel</strong> </mark>and travel documents, <strong><mark>and set</strong> </mark>themselves <strong><mark>up</strong> </mark>in “<strong><mark>business” without intervention</strong></mark>. ¶ </u>¶ In 1984, a Labor government in the Australian State of Victoria introduced ¶ legislation to legalize prostitution in brothels. Subsequent Australian ¶ governments expanded legalization culminating in the Prostitution Control Act of ¶ 1994<u>. Noting the link between legalization of prostitution and trafficking in ¶ Australia, the US Department of State observed: “Trafficking in East Asian ¶ women for the sex trade is a growing problem…lax laws – including legalized ¶ prostitution in parts of the country – make [anti-trafficking] enforcement difficult at ¶ the working level”</u> (U.S. Department of State, 2000, p. 6F). ¶ ¶ 3. <u>Legalization/decriminalization of prostitution does not control the sex ¶ industry. It expands it. ¶ </u>¶ Contrary to claims that legalization and decriminalization would control the ¶ expansion of the sex industry, prostitution now accounts for 5% of the ¶ Netherlands economy (Daley, 2001, p. 4<u>). Over the last decade, as pimping was ¶ legalized, and brothels decriminalized in the year 2000, the sex industry ¶ increased by 25% in the Netherlands</u> (Daley, 2001, p.4). At any hour of the day, ¶ women of all ages and races, dressed in hardly anything, are put on display in ¶ the notorious windows of Dutch brothels and sex clubs and offered for sale. ¶ <u>Most of them are women from other countries who were probably trafficked into ¶ the Netherlands </u>(Daley, 2001, p. 4). ¶ ¶ In addition to governmental endorsement of prostitution in the Netherlands, ¶ <u><mark>prostitution is</u> </mark>also <u><mark>promoted by </mark>associations of <mark>sex businesses </mark>and ¶ organizations comprised of prostitution buyers <mark>who </mark>consult and <mark>collaborate with </mark>¶ the <mark>government to further their interests</mark>.</u> These include the “Association of ¶ Operators of Relaxation Businesses,” the “Cooperating Consultation of Operators ¶ of Window Prostitution,” and the “Man/Woman and Prostitution Foundation,” a ¶ group of men who regularly use women in prostitution, and whose specific aims ¶ include “to make prostitution and the use of services of prostitutes more accepted ¶ and openly discussible,” and “to protect the interests of clients” (Bureau NRM, ¶ 2002, pp.115-16). Faced with a dwindling number of Dutch women who engage in prostitution ¶ activities and the expanding demand for more female bodies and more exotic ¶ women to service the prostitution market, the Dutch National Rapporteur on ¶ Trafficking has stated that in the future, a solution may be to “offer [to the market] ¶ prostitutes from non EU/EEA[European Union/European Economic Area] ¶ countries, who voluntarily choose to work in prostitution…” These women would ¶ be given “legal and controlled access to the Dutch market” (Bureau NRM, 2002, ¶ p. 140). <u>As prostitution has been transformed into “sex work,” and pimps into ¶ entrepreneurs, so too this recommendation transforms trafficking into “voluntary ¶ migration for sex work.”</u> Looking to the future, <u>the Netherlands is targeting poor ¶ women for the international sex trade to remedy the inadequacies of the free ¶ market of “sexual services.” Prostitution is thus normalized as an “option for the ¶ poor.”</u> ¶ ¶ <u>Legalization of prostitution in</u> the State of Victoria, <u>Australia, resulted in massive ¶ expansion of the sex industry</u>. <u>Along with legalization of prostitution, other forms ¶ of sexual exploitation, such as tabletop dancing, bondage and discipline centers, ¶ peep shows, phone sex, and pornography, have all developed in much more ¶ profitable ways than before legalization</u> (Sullivan & Jeffreys, 2001). <u>Prostitution ¶ has become an integral part of the tourism</u> and casino <u>boom</u> in Victoria with ¶ government-sponsored casinos authorizing the redeeming of casino chips at ¶ local brothels (Sullivan & Jeffreys, 2001). ¶ ¶ A range of state-sponsored prostitution systems exist in Austria, Denmark, ¶ Germany, the Netherlands and Switzerland. It seems likely that European <u><strong><mark>state sponsored prostitution countries serve as magnets and</strong>, </mark>ultimately, as <strong><mark>conduits </mark> <mark>through which significant numbers of women are trafficked to other</u></strong> </mark>European ¶ <u><strong><mark>nations</u></strong></mark>. Europe has a high density of women trafficked per square mile ¶ compared to North America, for example. Given the porousness of national ¶ borders facilitated by the Schengen agreement (2), it is not surprising that high ¶ numbers of trafficked women are also present in other European countries that ¶ do not have legalized or decriminalized systems of prostitution. Although ¶ accurate numbers of women trafficked are difficult to obtain, the International ¶ Organization of Migration <u>(IOM) has estimated that <strong><mark>500,000 </strong></mark>women and children ¶ <strong><mark>are trafficked in Europe annually </u></strong></mark>(IOM, 1998). <u><strong><mark>In contrast,</strong></mark> it has been estimated ¶ that <strong><mark>45,000</strong></mark>-50,000 women and children <strong><mark>are trafficked </strong></mark>annually <strong><mark>into the Un</strong></mark>ited ¶<mark> <strong>S</strong></mark>tates</u> (Richard, 1999, p.3). </p>
1NC
null
Off
431,927
40
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,970
I swear by Apollo the physician, I will provide physician-assisted suicide to whoever seeks it.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>I swear by Apollo the physician, I will provide physician-assisted suicide to whoever seeks it.</h4>
null
1AC
null
430,068
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,971
2. Criminalization is key to removing victims and prosecuting traffickers
Day ‘12
Day ‘12
. ETB] a jurisdiction that decriminalizes prostitution exacerbates the sex trafficking crisis by obstructing law enforcement's ability to identify pimps and trafficking victims, effectively remove the trafficking victim from the situation, and to successfully prosecute the pimps. the availability of shelters and support services will not motivate trafficking victims, especially those who are minors, to get help for three reason First, many trafficking victims do not consider themselves a victim of human trafficking. Second, pimps manipulate their victims to keep them from seeking help and beat the victims into submission if they otherwise fail to obey Third, police, not shelter operators, are the only agents able to identify trafficking victims and to effectively separate the victims from the enslaving control of their traffickers Even if upon arrest, law enforcement diverted trafficking victims directly into a rehabilitation center, there is nothing to encourage the trafficking victim to stay unless criminal charges are pending Simply making shelters and rehabilitation facilities available will not effectively keep trafficking victims from the psychological and physical clutches of their pimps police jurisdiction over victims through criminal prostitution laws is the only effective, recognized means to rescue trafficking victims. Decriminalization creates ideal conditions for pimps and traffickers, as it prevents the police from arresting them and keeps women and children enslaved.
a jurisdiction that decriminalizes prostitution exacerbates sex trafficking by obstructing law enforcement's ability to identify pimps and victims, many do not consider themselves a victim pimps manipulate victims to keep them from seeking help and beat the victims into submission police are the only agents able to identify victims and effectively separate the victims from their traffickers there is nothing to encourage the victim to stay unless criminal charges are pending. criminal law is the only means to rescue trafficking victims Decrimin creates ideal conditions for traffickers as it prevents the police from arresting them
[Kristina, ADDRESSING THE SEX TRAFFICKING CRISIS: HOW PROSTITUTION LAWS CAN HELP. 2 Creighton Int'l & Comp. L.J. 149. ETB] 1. Decriminalizing Acts of Prostitution Increases the Demand for Sex and Impedes on Law Enforcement's Ability to Identify Trafficking Victims and The Traffickers¶ Policies on prostitution in Western countries are changing rapidly. n115 Over the past ten years, decriminalizing and legalizing prostitution have been the most popular solutions to combat sex [*163] trafficking. n116 Many people concerned about sex trafficking victims and their need for protection understandably question whether criminalizing such victims under prostitution laws is appropriate or necessary. n117 This comes out of concern for sex trafficking victims and their need for protection, not criminalization. n118 However, a jurisdiction that decriminalizes prostitution exacerbates the sex trafficking crisis by obstructing law enforcement's ability to identify pimps and trafficking victims, effectively remove the trafficking victim from the situation, and to successfully prosecute the pimps. n119¶ Those in support of decriminalizing prostitution tend to believe that prosecuting trafficked girls is unnecessary if shelters and rehabilitation facilities are made available to them. n120 However, the [*164] availability of such shelters and support services will not motivate trafficking victims, especially those who are minors, to get help for three reasons. n121 First, many trafficking victims do not consider themselves a victim of human trafficking. n122 Second, pimps manipulate their victims to keep them from seeking help and beat the victims into submission if they otherwise fail to obey. n123 Third, police, not shelter operators, are the only agents able to identify trafficking victims and to effectively separate the victims from the enslaving control of their traffickers. n124¶ Even if upon arrest, law enforcement diverted trafficking victims directly into a rehabilitation center, there is nothing to encourage the trafficking victim to stay unless criminal charges are pending. n125 Simply making shelters and rehabilitation facilities available will not effectively keep trafficking victims from the psychological and physical clutches of their pimps. n126 Thus, police jurisdiction over victims through criminal prostitution laws is the only effective, recognized means to rescue trafficking victims. n127 Decriminalization does not help these victims because it creates ideal conditions for pimps and traffickers, as it prevents the police from arresting them and keeps women and children enslaved.
2,626
<h4>2. <u><strong>Criminalization is key to removing victims and prosecuting traffickers</h4><p>Day ‘12</p><p></u></strong>[Kristina, ADDRESSING THE SEX TRAFFICKING CRISIS: HOW PROSTITUTION LAWS CAN HELP. 2 Creighton Int'l & Comp. L.J. 149<u><strong>. ETB]</p><p></u></strong>1. Decriminalizing Acts of Prostitution Increases the Demand for Sex and Impedes on Law Enforcement's Ability to Identify Trafficking Victims and The Traffickers¶ Policies on prostitution in Western countries are changing rapidly. n115 Over the past ten years, decriminalizing and legalizing prostitution have been the most popular solutions to combat sex [*163] trafficking. n116 Many people concerned about sex trafficking victims and their need for protection understandably question whether criminalizing such victims under prostitution laws is appropriate or necessary. n117 This comes out of concern for sex trafficking victims and their need for protection, not criminalization. n118 However, <u><strong><mark>a jurisdiction that decriminalizes prostitution exacerbates</strong> </mark>the <strong><mark>sex trafficking </mark>crisis <mark>by obstructing law enforcement's ability to identify pimps and</strong> </mark>trafficking <strong><mark>victims,</mark> effectively remove the</strong> trafficking <strong>victim</strong> from the situation, <strong>and to successfully prosecute the pimps</strong>.</u> n119¶ Those in support of decriminalizing prostitution tend to believe that prosecuting trafficked girls is unnecessary if shelters and rehabilitation facilities are made available to them. n120 However, <u>the</u> [*164] <u>availability</u> <u>of</u> such <u>shelters and support services will not motivate trafficking victims, especially those who are minors, to get help for three reason</u>s. n121 <u>First, <mark>many </mark>trafficking victims <mark>do not consider themselves a victim </mark>of human trafficking.</u> n122 <u>Second, <mark>pimps manipulate</mark> their <mark>victims to keep them from seeking help and beat the victims into submission </mark>if they otherwise fail to obey</u>. n123 <u>Third, <strong><mark>police</strong></mark>, not shelter operators, <strong><mark>are the only agents able to identify</strong> </mark>trafficking <strong><mark>victims</strong> <strong>and</strong> </mark>to <strong><mark>effectively separate the</strong> <strong>victims from</strong> </mark>the enslaving control of <strong><mark>their traffickers</u></strong></mark>. n124¶ <u>Even if upon arrest, law enforcement diverted trafficking victims directly into a rehabilitation center, <mark>there is nothing to encourage the</mark> trafficking <mark>victim to stay unless criminal charges are pending</u>.</mark> n125 <u>Simply making shelters and rehabilitation facilities available will not effectively keep trafficking victims from the psychological and physical clutches of their pimps</u>. n126 Thus, <u><strong>police jurisdiction over victims through <mark>criminal</strong> </mark>prostitution <strong><mark>law</mark>s<mark> is the only </mark>effective, recognized <mark>means to rescue trafficking victims</strong></mark>.</u> n127 <u><strong><mark>Decrimin</strong></mark>alization</u> does not help these victims because it <u><strong><mark>creates ideal conditions for </strong></mark>pimps and <strong><mark>traffickers</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>as it prevents the police from arresting them</strong></mark> and keeps women and children enslaved.</p></u>
1NC
null
Off
429,937
4
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,972
United States is a linguistic referent
Valsiner ‘12
Valsiner ‘12
most of the people have had a direct or indirect impact on their life as result of acts performed by people in accordance to what the United Sates means for them Yet people are able to recognize that the United States is not a thing Nobody has ever been able to touch the United States If I forget to ask for a visa it is not the United States that will prevent me from entering, but a police officer
people have a direct impact on their life as result of acts performed by people in accordance to what the U S means the U S is not a thing Nobody has ever been able to touch the U S If I forget to ask for a visa it is not the U S that will prevent me from entering, but a police officer
Jaan The Oxford Handbook of Culture and Psychology https://books.google.com/books?id=WljI1r2e-SUC&pg=PA243&lpg=PA243&dq=%22the+united+states+means%22+people&source=bl&ots=3vBpoL9XCg&sig=Gg43ejwLbebceYvWUmn7o78jVh0&hl=en&sa=X&ei=WaioVLeoMIW1oQSPg4HYAQ&ved=0CCAQ6AEwATgK#v=onepage&q=%22the%20united%20states%20means%22%20people&f=false Maybe most of the people of the world have somehow had a direct or indirect impact on their life as result of acts performed by other people in accordance to what the United Sates means for them. And those other people, in turn, have experienced the United States in terms of the acts that other people performed in accordance with it- and so forth, in an infinite intertwining of infinite dimensionality. Yet, people are able to recognize that the United States is not a thing (as I have defined above— Namely, an entity endowed with substantial consistence. Nobody has ever been able to touch the United States or invite them to dinner. If I forget to ask for a visa, I will not be able to enter “the United States.” Yet I am aware that it is not the United States that will prevent me from entering, but someone—a frontier police officer—who will do it as if she were executing the United States will—that is, in accordance with what “the United States” means for her/him. Moreover, the frontier police officer will be able to have a commitment to her action insofar as she regards “the United States” as if it was an existing entity.
1,471
<h4><u>United States is a linguistic referent</h4><p><strong>Valsiner ‘12</p><p></u></strong>Jaan The Oxford Handbook of Culture and Psychology</p><p>https://books.google.com/books?id=WljI1r2e-SUC&pg=PA243&lpg=PA243&dq=%22the+united+states+means%22+people&source=bl&ots=3vBpoL9XCg&sig=Gg43ejwLbebceYvWUmn7o78jVh0&hl=en&sa=X&ei=WaioVLeoMIW1oQSPg4HYAQ&ved=0CCAQ6AEwATgK#v=onepage&q=%22the%20united%20states%20means%22%20people&f=false</p><p>Maybe <u><strong>most of the <mark>people</u></strong></mark> of the world <u><strong><mark>have</u></strong></mark> somehow <u><strong>had</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>a direct</mark> or indirect <mark>impact on their life as result of acts performed by</u></strong></mark> other <u><strong><mark>people</u></strong> <u><strong>in accordance to what the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>ates <mark>means</mark> for them</u></strong>. And those other people, in turn, have experienced the United States in terms of the acts that other people performed in accordance with it- and so forth, in an infinite intertwining of infinite dimensionality. <u><strong>Yet</u></strong>, <u><strong>people are able to recognize that <mark>the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>is not a thing</u></strong></mark> (as I have defined above— Namely, an entity endowed with substantial consistence. <u><strong><mark>Nobody has ever been able to touch the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates</u></strong> or invite them to dinner. <u><strong><mark>If I forget to ask for a visa</u></strong></mark>, I will not be able to enter “the United States.” Yet I am aware that <u><strong><mark>it is not the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>that will prevent me from entering, but</mark> </u></strong>someone—<u><strong><mark>a</u></strong></mark> frontier <u><strong><mark>police officer</u></strong></mark>—who will do it as if she were executing the United States will—that is, in accordance with what “the United States” means for her/him. Moreover, the frontier police officer will be able to have a commitment to her action insofar as she regards “the United States” as if it was an existing entity.</p>
T
null
null
222,110
5
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,973
No risk of cyberterror—anonymity makes it useless
Gartzke 2012
Gartzke 2012(Erik, University of California, San Diego, December 7, "The Myth of Cyberwar: Bringing War on the Internet Back Down to Earth", http://dss.ucsd.edu/~egartzke/papers/cyberwar_12062012.pdf)
the focus is on the potential for harm, while ignoring the motives and operational logic of perpetrators. If internet anonymity is awkward for targets of attacks, it is certainly also a problem for initiators. Terrorists spend as much time trying to market their exploits as they do fighting Where anonymity protects an aggressor from retribution, it also dilutes credit for the deed Just as ongoing cyber attacks from unidentified sources do not give the target a way to retaliate, they also do not give the target a ready way to accommodate an attacker's demands. Demands from an anonymous cyber warrior will tend to be ignored or reneged on, once vulnerabilities are identified and addressed it is in the interest of the attacker to “brand” its efforts in order to elicit concessions from a target. even if demands are complied with, it will be difficult for an attacker to obtain sustained compliance, given the impossibility of demonstrating future capabilities and the temporary nature of harm
If internet anonymity is awkward for targets it is certainly a problem for initiators. Terrorists spend as much time trying to market their exploits as they do fighting anonymity dilutes credit cyber attacks do not give the target a way to accommodate demands. Demands will be ignored or reneged on, once vulnerabilities are identified it is in the interest of the attacker to “brand” its efforts in order to elicit concessions it will be difficult for an attacker to obtain sustained compliance
Again the focus is on the potential for harm, while ignoring the motives and operational logic of perpetrators. If internet anonymity is awkward for targets of attacks, it is certainly also a problem for initiators. Terrorists spend as much time trying to market their exploits as they do fighting, bombing, assassinating, etc. Where anonymity protects an aggressor from retribution, it also dilutes credit for the deed. Vandals often “tag” their handiwork—creating an identity where none need exist—precisely because anonymity has both advantages and drawbacks. Internet vandals also brand their exploits, presumably in an effort to counteract, rather than maximize, anonymity. Just as ongoing cyber attacks from unidentified sources do not give the target a way to retaliate, they also do not give the target a ready way to accommodate an attacker's demands. Demands from an anonymous cyber warrior will tend to be ignored or reneged on, once vulnerabilities are identified and addressed. Demands might also come from a source that did not, or even was not capable of, mounting a cyber attack. As with the use of identifying symbols in war, it is in the interest of the attacker to “brand” its efforts in order to elicit concessions from a target. Indeed, even if demands are complied with, it will be difficult for an attacker to obtain sustained compliance, given the impossibility of demonstrating future capabilities and the temporary nature of harm. Discussion of attribution problems in cyber space also reflects a subtle but telling shift in framing. Libicki's simple calculus of deterrence, for example, involves “getting caught,” something more often characteristic of crime than war. Some aspects of international relations involve anonymity. Espionage, covert operations and certain kinds of political theft or murder function most effectively when the perpetrators are unknown, or indeed when the operations themselves remain undisclosed. Strategic or tactical advantage can also stem from anonymity and surprise in terrestrial military missions, though nations and groups often sacrifice surprise and advertise their role in contests in order to exercise advantages in the form of foreign concessions or tacit or formal admission of defeat. How does one surrender to no one in particular? The advantage of anonymity will persist for peripheral forms of warfare on the internet, just as it has played a role in terrestrial competition and conflict. But most forms of warfare or potential warfare actually invite disclosure of an initiator's identity. As I have already noted, coercion requires attribution, not of the target but by the initiator. Similarly, threats designed to elicit concessions or deter aggression are already problematic in physical space (Powell 1990, Nalebu 1991). This “credibility problem” mirrors the attribution problem and is likely to make internet aggression all the more problematic for initiators.
2,942
<h4>No risk of cyberterror—anonymity makes it useless</h4><p><u><strong>Gartzke 2012</u></strong>(Erik, University of California, San Diego, December 7, "The Myth of Cyberwar: Bringing War on the Internet Back Down to Earth", http://dss.ucsd.edu/~egartzke/papers/cyberwar_12062012.pdf)</p><p>Again <u>the focus is on the potential for harm, while ignoring the motives and operational logic of perpetrators. <mark>If internet anonymity is awkward for targets</mark> of attacks, <mark>it is certainly</mark> also <mark>a problem for initiators.</mark> <mark>Terrorists spend as much time trying to market their exploits as they do fighting</u></mark>, bombing, assassinating, etc. <u>Where <mark>anonymity</mark> protects an aggressor from retribution, it also <mark>dilutes credit</mark> for the deed</u>. Vandals often “tag” their handiwork—creating an identity where none need exist—precisely because anonymity has both advantages and drawbacks. Internet vandals also brand their exploits, presumably in an effort to counteract, rather than maximize, anonymity. <u>Just as ongoing <mark>cyber attacks</mark> from unidentified sources do not give the target a way to retaliate, they also <mark>do not give the target a</mark> ready <mark>way to accommodate</mark> an attacker's <mark>demands.</mark> <mark>Demands</mark> from an anonymous cyber warrior <mark>will</mark> tend to <mark>be ignored or reneged on, once vulnerabilities are identified</mark> and addressed</u>. Demands might also come from a source that did not, or even was not capable of, mounting a cyber attack. As with the use of identifying symbols in war, <u><mark>it is in the interest of the attacker to “brand” its efforts in order to elicit concessions</mark> from a target.</u> Indeed, <u>even if demands are complied with, <mark>it will be difficult for an attacker to obtain sustained compliance</mark>, given the impossibility of demonstrating future capabilities and the temporary nature of harm</u>. Discussion of attribution problems in cyber space also reflects a subtle but telling shift in framing. Libicki's simple calculus of deterrence, for example, involves “getting caught,” something more often characteristic of crime than war. Some aspects of international relations involve anonymity. Espionage, covert operations and certain kinds of political theft or murder function most effectively when the perpetrators are unknown, or indeed when the operations themselves remain undisclosed. Strategic or tactical advantage can also stem from anonymity and surprise in terrestrial military missions, though nations and groups often sacrifice surprise and advertise their role in contests in order to exercise advantages in the form of foreign concessions or tacit or formal admission of defeat. How does one surrender to no one in particular? The advantage of anonymity will persist for peripheral forms of warfare on the internet, just as it has played a role in terrestrial competition and conflict. But most forms of warfare or potential warfare actually invite disclosure of an initiator's identity. As I have already noted, coercion requires attribution, not of the target but by the initiator. Similarly, threats designed to elicit concessions or deter aggression are already problematic in physical space (Powell 1990, Nalebu 1991). This “credibility problem” mirrors the attribution problem and is likely to make internet aggression all the more problematic for initiators.</p>
1NR
FBI
Cyber
430,070
1
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,974
Municipalities control zoning laws for prostitution
ALLIL No Date
ALLIL No Date
ETB] A growing tendency is to segregat prostitution associated overt prostitution is shunted into specific enclaves These have usually been "low-rent" neighborhoods in or near ethnic minority or migrants' residential areas the only place where it is legally tolerated are areas whose development alternatives include weapons testing and waste dumps.
A growing tendency is to segregat prostitution associated overt prostitution is shunted into specific enclaves These have usually been "low-rent" neighborhoods in or near ethnic minority or migrants' residential areas the only place where it is legally tolerated are areas whose development alternatives include weapons testing and waste dumps.
[American Law and Legal Information Library, http://law.jrank.org/pages/1880/Prostitution-Regimes-prohibition-criminalization-regulation.html#ixzz3JKp8jdwf ETB] A growing tendency is to make use of strategies for spatially segregating prostitution and activities associated with it in order to manage or minimize perceived externalities. This echoes the long-time practice in many cities where overt prostitution is de facto shunted into specific enclaves, often called "red light districts." These have usually been "low-rent" neighborhoods, that is, low-valued land-use urban zones, in or near ethnic minority or migrants' residential areas. It is illustrative of the spatial logic of minimizing the social costs of prostitution that the only place where it is legally tolerated in the United States are certain rural counties of Nevada—areas with very low population densities whose economic development alternatives include military weapons testing sites and toxic waste dumps.
981
<h4><u><strong>Municipalities control zoning laws for prostitution</h4><p>ALLIL No Date</p><p></u></strong>[American Law and Legal Information Library, http://law.jrank.org/pages/1880/Prostitution-Regimes-prohibition-criminalization-regulation.html#ixzz3JKp8jdwf<u> ETB]</p><p><mark>A growing tendency is to</u> </mark>make use of strategies for spatially <u><mark>segregat</u></mark>ing <u><mark>prostitution</u> </mark>and activities <u><mark>associated</u> </mark>with it in order to manage or minimize perceived externalities. This echoes the long-time practice in many cities where <u><mark>overt prostitution is</u> </mark>de facto <u><mark>shunted into specific enclaves</u></mark>, often called "red light districts." <u><mark>These have usually been "low-rent" neighborhoods</u></mark>, that is, low-valued land-use urban zones, <u><mark>in or near ethnic minority or migrants' residential areas</u></mark>. It is illustrative of the spatial logic of minimizing the social costs of prostitution that <u><mark>the only place where it is legally tolerated</u> </mark>in the United States <u><mark>are</u> </mark>certain rural counties of Nevada—<u><mark>areas</u> </mark>with very low population densities <u><mark>whose</u> </mark>economic <u><mark>development alternatives include</u> </mark>military <u><mark>weapons testing</u> </mark>sites <u><mark>and</u> </mark>toxic <u><mark>waste dumps.</p></u></mark>
1NC
null
Off
429,927
2
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,975
Our affirmation of PAS is an epistemological askesis: a renunciation of responsibility over the idols of life and health as modernity has construed them – only this approach prevents the deployment of life as religiosity to subdue bodies into regimes of managerialism
Cayley 92
Cayley 92
, 1992 SJE Responsibility was a word that acquired connotations that had made it¶ into the opposite of self-limitation. How could he be responsible, he¶ asked, when health now implies “the smooth integration of my immune system into a socioeconomic world system” and¶ responsibility “an interiorization of global systems into the self I can imagine no complex of controls capable of saving us¶ from the flood of poisons, radiations, goods and services¶ which sicken humans and animals more than ever before.¶ There is no way out of this world. “Responsibility” is now an illusion. In such¶ a world, “being healthy” is reduced to a combination of¶ techniques As an alternative to responsibility, Illich proposed renunciation. courageous, disciplined, self-critical¶ renunciation accomplished in community I will call it askesis not mortification but “epistemological askesis,” a purge of those corrupting concepts that give “fictitious substances” the semblance of a sensible existence. he was imposing a painful¶ proscription only by refraining from those modes of¶ speech and action that disguise their own powerlessness can people¶ recover a sense of the surprising power of this moment, this place, this¶ person. Responsibility for health is a way of¶ warding off evil that domesticates it Life is the master concept of “a new stage of religiosity,” the primum mobile in fictitious substances Life is used as a substantive when¶ people speak of life on earth, or the appearance of a new life at¶ conception. Doctors who claim responsibility for the lives of their¶ patients speak in¶ the same sense. In this radically new discourse life loses its anchorage in persons and becomes the ultimate resource.
Responsibility acquired connotations that made it the opposite of self-limitation. How could he be responsible when health now implies “the smooth integration of my immune system into a socioeconomic world system” and¶ responsibility “an interiorization of global systems into the self There is no way out of this world. “Responsibility” is now an illusion “being healthy” is reduced to a combination of¶ techniques As an alternative to responsibility, Illich proposed renunciation courageous, disciplined, self-critical¶ renunciation accomplished in community askesis,” a purge of¶ those corrupting concepts that give “fictitious substances” the¶ semblance of a sensible existence a painful¶ proscription only by refraining from those modes of¶ speech and action that disguise their own powerlessness can people¶ recover a sense of the surprising power of this moment Life is the master concept of “a new stage of religiosity,” used as a substantive when¶ people speak of life on earth life at¶ conception. Doctors who claim responsibility for the lives of their¶ patients In this radically new discourse life loses its anchorage and becomes the ultimate resource.
David, CBC Reporter, winner of John Culkin Award for Outstanding Praxis in the Field of Media Ecology, Ivan Illich in Conversation: The Testament of Ivan Illich, 1992 SJE In a passage in Gender about Raymond Williams’s book Key¶ Words, Illich comments that “each entry conveys the surprise and¶ passion of an aging man telling us about the inconstancy of a word on¶ which his own integrity has rested.”103 Illich has known the same¶ experience. Responsibility was a word that carried considerable weight¶ in his writings until at least the time of Medical Nemesis; but, in 1990,¶ in a lecture given in Hannover, Germany, entitled “Health as One’s¶ Own Responsibility: No Thank You!,” he renounced it. In this talk he¶ argued that the word had now acquired connotations that had made it¶ into the opposite of self-limitation. How could he be responsible, he¶ asked, when health now implies “the smooth integration of my immune system into a socioeconomic world system” and¶ responsibility “an interiorization of global systems into the self, in the¶ manner of a categorical imperative.” “In a world which worships an¶ ontology of systems,” he went on, “ethical responsibility is reduced to¶ a legitimizing formality.”¶ I can imagine no complex of controls capable of saving us¶ from the flood of poisons, radiations, goods and services¶ which sicken humans and animals more than ever before.¶ There is no way out of this world. I live in a manufactured¶ reality ever further removed from creation. And I know today ¶ what that signifies, what horror threatens each of us. A few¶ decades ago, I did not yet know it. At that time, it seemed¶ possible that I could share responsibility for the re-making of¶ this manufactured world. Today, I finally know what¶ powerlessness is. “Responsibility” is now an illusion. In such¶ a world, “being healthy” is reduced to a combination of¶ techniques, protection of the environment, and adaptation to¶ the consequences of techniques, all three of which are,¶ inevitably, privileges.¶ As an alternative to responsibility, Illich proposed renunciation.¶ “We no longer have a word for courageous, disciplined, self-critical¶ renunciation accomplished in community — but that is what I am¶ talking about. I will call it askesis.” He specified that he did not mean¶ mortification but rather an “epistemological askesis,” a purge of¶ those corrupting concepts that give “fictitious substances” the¶ semblance of a sensible existence.¶ Illich did not hide the fact that he was imposing a painful¶ proscription, but he argued that only by refraining from those modes of¶ speech and action that disguise their own powerlessness can people¶ recover a sense of the surprising power of this moment, this place, this¶ person. Responsibility for health is what he calls a rain dance: a way of¶ warding off evil that at the same time domesticates it by making it¶ appear to be in the dancer’s power. Evil, for Illich, is not manageable;¶ and such things as nuclear weapons, genetic manipulation, and the¶ chemical transformation of earth and atmosphere by industrial poisons ¶ are evils, not problems. “We can suffer such evil,” he says. “We can¶ be broken by it, but we cannot make sense of it, cannot direct it.”¶ At the end of “Health as One’s Own Responsibility: No Thank¶ You!” Illich takes up the question of “life” that occupies the last¶ chapter of this book. Life, in Illich’s view, is the master concept of¶ what he calls “a new stage of religiosity,”04 the primum mobile in the¶ empyrean of fictitious substances. Two years before, he had shocked a¶ convocation of Lutheran bishops by pronouncing a solemn curse on¶ the use of this word as substantive. Life is used as a substantive when¶ people speak of life on earth, or the appearance of a new life at¶ conception. Doctors who claim responsibility for the lives of their¶ patients, and bioethicists who asses the quality of those lives, speak in¶ the same sense. In this radically new discourse, Illich says, life loses its anchorage in persons and becomes the ultimate resource.
4,066
<h4><strong>Our affirmation of PAS is an epistemological askesis: a renunciation of responsibility over the idols of life and health as modernity has construed them – only this approach prevents the deployment of life as religiosity to subdue bodies into regimes of managerialism</h4><p>Cayley 92</p><p></strong>David, CBC Reporter, winner of John Culkin Award for Outstanding Praxis in the Field of Media Ecology, Ivan Illich in Conversation: The Testament of Ivan Illich<u><strong>, 1992 SJE</p><p></u></strong>In a passage in Gender about Raymond Williams’s book Key¶ Words, Illich comments that “each entry conveys the surprise and¶ passion of an aging man telling us about the inconstancy of a word on¶ which his own integrity has rested.”103 Illich has known the same¶ experience. <u><strong><mark>Responsibility</mark> was a word that</u></strong> carried considerable weight¶ in his writings until at least the time of Medical Nemesis; but, in 1990,¶ in a lecture given in Hannover, Germany, entitled “Health as One’s¶ Own Responsibility: No Thank You!,” he renounced it. In this talk he¶ argued that the word had now <u><strong><mark>acquired connotations that</mark> had <mark>made it</mark>¶ into <mark>the opposite of self-limitation. How could he be responsible</mark>, he¶ asked, <mark>when health now implies “the smooth integration of my immune system into a socioeconomic world system” and¶ responsibility “an interiorization of global systems into the self</u></strong></mark>, in the¶ manner of a categorical imperative.” “In a world which worships an¶ ontology of systems,” he went on, “ethical responsibility is reduced to¶ a legitimizing formality.”¶ <u><strong>I can imagine no complex of controls capable of saving us¶ from the flood of poisons, radiations, goods and services¶ which sicken humans and animals more than ever before.¶ <mark>There is no way out of this world.</u></strong></mark> I live in a manufactured¶ reality ever further removed from creation. And I know today ¶ what that signifies, what horror threatens each of us. A few¶ decades ago, I did not yet know it. At that time, it seemed¶ possible that I could share responsibility for the re-making of¶ this manufactured world. Today, I finally know what¶ powerlessness is. <u><strong><mark>“Responsibility” is now an illusion</mark>. In such¶ a world, <mark>“being healthy” is reduced to a combination of¶ techniques</u></strong></mark>, protection of the environment, and adaptation to¶ the consequences of techniques, all three of which are,¶ inevitably, privileges.¶ <u><strong><mark>As an alternative to responsibility, Illich proposed renunciation</mark>.</u></strong>¶ “We no longer have a word for <u><strong><mark>courageous, disciplined, self-critical¶ renunciation accomplished in community</u></strong></mark> — but that is what I am¶ talking about. <u><strong>I will call it askesis</u></strong>.” He specified that he did <u><strong>not</u></strong> mean¶ <u><strong>mortification but</u></strong> rather an <u><strong>“epistemological <mark>askesis,” a purge of</u></strong>¶<u><strong> those corrupting concepts that give “fictitious substances” the</u></strong>¶<u><strong> semblance of a sensible existence</mark>.</u></strong>¶ Illich did not hide the fact that <u><strong>he was imposing <mark>a painful¶ proscription</u></strong></mark>, but he argued that <u><strong><mark>only by refraining from those modes of¶ speech and action that disguise their own powerlessness can people¶ recover a sense of the surprising power of this moment</mark>, this place, this¶ person. Responsibility for health is</u></strong> what he calls a rain dance: <u><strong>a way of¶ warding off evil that</u></strong> at the same time <u><strong>domesticates it</u></strong> by making it¶ appear to be in the dancer’s power. Evil, for Illich, is not manageable;¶ and such things as nuclear weapons, genetic manipulation, and the¶ chemical transformation of earth and atmosphere by industrial poisons ¶ are evils, not problems. “We can suffer such evil,” he says. “We can¶ be broken by it, but we cannot make sense of it, cannot direct it.”¶ At the end of “Health as One’s Own Responsibility: No Thank¶ You!” Illich takes up the question of “life” that occupies the last¶ chapter of this book. <u><strong><mark>Life</u></strong></mark>, in Illich’s view, <u><strong><mark>is the master concept of</u></strong></mark>¶ what he calls <u><strong><mark>“a new stage of religiosity,”</u></strong></mark>04 <u><strong>the primum mobile in</u></strong> the¶ empyrean of <u><strong>fictitious substances</u></strong>. Two years before, he had shocked a¶ convocation of Lutheran bishops by pronouncing a solemn curse on¶ the use of this word as substantive. <u><strong>Life is <mark>used as a substantive when¶ people speak of life on earth</mark>, or the appearance of a new <mark>life at¶ conception. Doctors who claim responsibility for the lives of their¶ patients</u></strong></mark>, and bioethicists who asses the quality of those lives, <u><strong>speak in¶ the same sense. <mark>In this radically new discourse</u></strong></mark>, Illich says, <u><strong><mark>life loses its anchorage</mark> in persons <mark>and becomes the ultimate resource.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
1AC
null
430,071
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,976
Legalize means to remove all restrictions
Sumner 11
Sumner 11 [L.W. Sumner (a Canadian philosopher notable for his work on normative and applied ethics, political philosophy, and the philosophy of law. Sumner is University Professor Emeritus of Law and Philosophy at the University of Toronto.) “Assisted Death: A study in Ethics and Law” Oxford University Press, pg. 165-166, CBE]
The contrast between legalization and decriminalization is frequently invoked for a number of practices that the state likes to control, including assisted death By decriminalizing a practice I mean repealing any and all criminal Statutes governing that practice Decriminalization is consistent with regulating the practice by Other, non—criminal, legal means Legalization is consistent with imposing no restrictions on it whatever—leaving it completely unregulated—or with permitting it subject to a regulatory regime.
Decrim is consistent with regulating the practice by Other, non—criminal, legal means Legalization is consistent with imposing no restrictions leaving it completely unregulated
Before we get to the main business of the chapter, a terminological note is in order. Throughout the discussion I have consistently spoken about legalizing assisted death rather than decriminalizing it. The contrast between legalization and decriminalization is frequently invoked for a number of practices that the state likes to control, including (besides assisted death) prostitution, drug use, and abortion. Despite the popularity of the distinction, however, there appears to be no common understanding of exactly what it means. So the best thing I can do is to state as clearly as possible what I mean by it. I By decriminalizing a practice I mean repealing any and all criminal Statutes governing that practice. Decriminalization is consistent with regulating (or even prohibiting) the practice by Other, non—criminal, legal means. This is the sense in which abortion has been decriminalized in Canada: the previous criminal statute regulating the practice was struck down by the Supreme Court in its 1988 Morgentaler decision and was never replaced either in whole or in part. There is, therefore, no criminal regulation of abortion in Canada today; nonetheless, the practice IS still regulated in Other ways (through provincial licensing laws, certification requirements for medical practitioners, hospital regulations concerning late-term abortions, require- ments of competent medical practice, etc.). In most other countries there is still criminal legislation governing abortion, though it may be just as liberal in its effect as the current regime in Canada; in those cases abortion has not been decriminalized, though it has been legalized. By legalizing a practice I mean making some legal provision for it i.e. not completely prohibiting it. Legalization is consistent with imposing no restrictions on it whatever—leaving it completely unregulated—or with permitting it subject to a regulatory regime. Abortion was legalized, but not decrim- inalized, in Canada in 1969 when the previous criminal statute was amended to stipulate conditions under which performing an abortion would not be an offence.
2,118
<h4><u>Legalize means to remove all restrictions</h4><p><strong>Sumner 11</p><p></u></strong>[L.W. Sumner (a Canadian philosopher notable for his work on normative and applied ethics, political philosophy, and the philosophy of law. Sumner is University Professor Emeritus of Law and Philosophy at the University of Toronto.) “Assisted Death: A study in Ethics and Law” Oxford University Press, pg. 165-166, CBE]</p><p>Before we get to the main business of the chapter, a terminological note is in order. Throughout the discussion I have consistently spoken about legalizing assisted death rather than decriminalizing it. <u>The contrast between legalization and decriminalization is frequently invoked for a number of practices that the state likes to control, including</u> (besides <u>assisted death</u>) prostitution, drug use, and abortion. Despite the popularity of the distinction, however, there appears to be no common understanding of exactly what it means. So the best thing I can do is to state as clearly as possible what I mean by it. I <u>By</u> <u>decriminalizing a practice</u> <u>I mean repealing any and all criminal Statutes governing that practice</u>. <u><strong><mark>Decrim</mark>inalization <mark>is consistent with regulating</u></strong></mark> (or even prohibiting) <u><mark>the practice by Other, non—criminal, legal means</u></mark>. This is the sense in which abortion has been decriminalized in Canada: the previous criminal statute regulating the practice was struck down by the Supreme Court in its 1988 Morgentaler decision and was never replaced either in whole or in part. There is, therefore, no criminal regulation of abortion in Canada today; nonetheless, the practice IS still regulated in Other ways (through provincial licensing laws, certification requirements for medical practitioners, hospital regulations concerning late-term abortions, require- ments of competent medical practice, etc.). In most other countries there is still criminal legislation governing abortion, though it may be just as liberal in its effect as the current regime in Canada; in those cases abortion has not been decriminalized, though it has been legalized. By legalizing a practice I mean making some legal provision for it i.e. not completely prohibiting it. <u><strong><mark>Legalization is consistent with imposing no restrictions</strong></mark> on it whatever—<mark>leaving it completely unregulated</mark>—or with permitting it subject to a regulatory regime.</u> Abortion was legalized, but not decrim- inalized, in Canada in 1969 when the previous criminal statute was amended to stipulate conditions under which performing an abortion would not be an offence. </p>
T
null
null
430,035
2
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,977
The PARADOX OF RISK makes issues of cyber security NOT resolvable by weighing the plan - there is no way to linearly predict scenarios for cyber warfare
Stevens 2013
Stevens 2013 (Tim, Department of War Studies, King's College London; Centre for Science & Security Studies; International Centre for the Study of Radicalisation; "Apocalyptic Visions: Cyber War and the Politics of Time")
Prophets who read and pronounce upon these apocalyptic signs do not restrict themselves to specific dates and times upon which terrible events will occur, so need not excuse themselves from incorrect predictions; consequently, they can never be wrong Specific vectors of ‘cyber insecurity’ may change, and timescales expand and contract, but the certainty in apocalypse remains unwavering Apocalyptic intensity’ is maintained and heightened further by making continued ‘imminent but indeterminate’ predictions, legitimising a constant state of readiness This uncertainty is shared with other forms of security, which thrive on a ‘denotative imprecision …. simultaneous appeal to the precise and the imprecise When events and scenarios converge, the narrative of cyber war gains explanatory power in its own right.
Prophets who pronounce apocalyptic signs—the do not restrict themselves to specific dates and times upon which events will occur so need not excuse themselves from incorrect predictions they can never be wrong Specific vectors of ‘cyber insecurity’ may change, timescales expand and contract the certainty in apocalypse remains unwavering. Apocalyptic intensity’ is maintained by making continued imminent predictions legitimising a constant state of readiness
Prophets who read and pronounce upon these apocalyptic signs—the ‘Cassandras of cyber warfare’ (Rid, 2012: 6)—do not, like their religious counterparts, restrict themselves to specific dates and times upon which terrible events will occur, so need not excuse themselves from incorrect predictions; consequently, they can never be wrong. However, they do have in common talents as ‘masterful bricoleurs, skilfully recasting elements and themes within the constraints of their respective traditions and reconfiguring them to formulate new, meaningful endtimes scenarios’ (Wojcik, 1997: 148). Specific vectors of ‘cyber insecurity’ may change, and timescales expand and contract, but the certainty in apocalypse remains unwavering. ‘Apocalyptic intensity’ is maintained and heightened further by making continued ‘imminent but indeterminate’ predictions, legitimising a constant state of readiness in which adherents ‘feel themselves to be standing poised on the brink of time’ (Bromley, 1997: 36). In fact, it is always ‘only a matter of time’ before a ‘cyber-apocalypse’ occurs (Gable, 2010). This uncertainty is shared with other forms of security, which thrive on a ‘denotative imprecision …. simultaneous appeal to the hard and the vacuous, the precise and the imprecise …. vague generalities about everything and nothing’ (Walker, 1997: 63). This epistemic tension is partially resolved by reading the signs of cyber war as corroboration of a deterministic ‘script’ of the future (Robbins and Palmer, 1997: 5). When events and scenarios converge, the narrative of cyber war gains explanatory power in its own right. In periods of ‘thickened history’ like this, it becomes ever more difficult to comprehend these events—‘to see the wood for the trees’, as it were—and they become part of their own causal structure (Beissinger, 2002: 27). In this case, the impression is that if cyber war is not already occurring, it very soon will be.
1,938
<h4>The PARADOX OF RISK makes issues of cyber security NOT resolvable by weighing the plan - there is no way to linearly predict scenarios for cyber warfare </h4><p><u><strong><mark>Stevens</mark> 20<mark>13</u></strong></mark> (Tim, Department of War Studies, King's College London; Centre for Science & Security Studies; International Centre for the Study of Radicalisation; "Apocalyptic Visions: Cyber War and the Politics of Time")</p><p><u><mark>Prophets who</mark> read and <mark>pronounce</mark> upon these <mark>apocalyptic signs</u>—the</mark> ‘Cassandras of cyber warfare’ (Rid, 2012: 6)—<u><mark>do not</u></mark>, like their religious counterparts, <u><mark>restrict themselves to specific dates and times upon which </mark>terrible <mark>events will occur</mark>, <mark>so need not excuse themselves from incorrect predictions</mark>; consequently, <mark>they can never be wrong</u></mark>. However, they do have in common talents as ‘masterful bricoleurs, skilfully recasting elements and themes within the constraints of their respective traditions and reconfiguring them to formulate new, meaningful endtimes scenarios’ (Wojcik, 1997: 148). <u><strong><mark>Specific vectors of ‘cyber insecurity’ may change,</mark> and <mark>timescales expand and contract</mark>, but <mark>the certainty in apocalypse remains unwavering</u></strong>.</mark> ‘<u><mark>Apocalyptic intensity’</mark> <mark>is maintained</mark> and heightened further <mark>by making</mark> <mark>continued</mark> ‘<mark>imminent</mark> but indeterminate’ <mark>predictions</mark>, <mark>legitimising a constant state of readiness</u></mark> in which adherents ‘feel themselves to be standing poised on the brink of time’ (Bromley, 1997: 36). In fact, it is always ‘only a matter of time’ before a ‘cyber-apocalypse’ occurs (Gable, 2010). <u>This uncertainty is shared with other forms of security, which thrive on a ‘denotative imprecision …. simultaneous appeal to the</u> hard and the vacuous, the <u>precise and the imprecise</u> …. vague generalities about everything and nothing’ (Walker, 1997: 63). This epistemic tension is partially resolved by reading the signs of cyber war as corroboration of a deterministic ‘script’ of the future (Robbins and Palmer, 1997: 5). <u>When events and scenarios converge, the narrative of cyber war gains explanatory power in its own right.</u> In periods of ‘thickened history’ like this, it becomes ever more difficult to comprehend these events—‘to see the wood for the trees’, as it were—and they become part of their own causal structure (Beissinger, 2002: 27). In this case, the impression is that if cyber war is not already occurring, it very soon will be.</p>
1NR
FBI
Cyber
17,846
15
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,978
That turns case
Farley ‘10
Farley ‘10 [Melissa Farley is a research and clinical psychologist at Prostitution Research & Education, a San Francisco non-profit organization. http://www.mercatornet.com/articles/view/the_real_harms_of_prostitution#sthash.6CiGViVR.dpuf ETB]
regulation of prostitution by zoning is a physical manifestation of the stigma that advocates want to avoid. Whether in Turkish genelevs or Nevada brothels
regulation of prostitution by zoning is a physical manifestation of the stigma that advocates want to avoid. Whether in Turkish genelevs or Nevada brothels
The regulation of prostitution by zoning is a physical manifestation of the same social/psychological stigma that decriminalisation advocates allegedly want to avoid. Whether in Turkish genelevs (walled-off multi-unit brothel complexes) or in Nevada brothels (ringed with barbed wire or electric fencing), women in state-zoned prostitution are physically isolated and socially rejected by the rest of society.
409
<h4><u><strong><mark>That turns case</h4><p></mark>Farley ‘10</p><p></u></strong>[Melissa Farley is a research and clinical psychologist at Prostitution Research & Education, a San Francisco non-profit organization. http://www.mercatornet.com/articles/view/the_real_harms_of_prostitution#sthash.6CiGViVR.dpuf ETB]</p><p>The <u><mark>regulation of prostitution by zoning is a physical manifestation</u> <u>of</u> <u>the</u> </mark>same social/psychological <u><mark>stigma</u> <u>that</u> </mark>decriminalisation <u><mark>advocates</u> </mark>allegedly <u><mark>want to avoid.</u> <u>Whether in Turkish genelevs</u> </mark>(walled-off multi-unit brothel complexes) <u><mark>or</u> </mark>in <u><mark>Nevada brothels</u> </mark>(ringed with barbed wire or electric fencing), women in state-zoned prostitution are physically isolated and socially rejected by the rest of society.</p>
1NC
null
Off
429,930
2
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,979
No ground loss – they still get PAS bad, the physician PIC, the slippery slope DA, ableism, and everything else that’s core lit
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>No ground loss – they still get PAS bad, the physician PIC, the slippery slope DA, ableism, and everything else that’s core lit</h4>
T
null
null
430,072
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,980
Only this total rejection of the vital imperative can deconstruct the axiomatic truths which provide the foundations for medicalization, opening the possibility for practice founded upon an ethic of care
Illich 94
Illich 94
The physician was required to take responsibility for life Biomedicine discovered its competence over "life."¶ , it is obvious that with the arrival of life and its quality the thread which linked that which is called health today with health in the past was broken. Health has become a scale on which one measures an immune system's fitness for living.¶ The reduction of a person to an immune system corresponds to the deceptive reduction of creation to a global system responsibility ends up being understood as the self-steering of an immune system. Where is the Life we have lost in living? Where is the wisdom we have lost in knowledge? Where is the knowledge we have lost in information? The concept of a life which can be reduced to a survival phase of the immune system is a caricature an idol I can imagine no complex of controls capable of saving us from the flood of poisons, radiations, goods and services which sicken humans and animals more than ever before I live in a manufactured reality ever further removed from creation. "responsibility" is an illusion.¶ In such a world, "being healthy" is reduced to a combination of the enjoyment of techniques, protection of the environment, and adaptation to the consequences of techniques, all three of which are, inevitably, privileges.¶ In order to live today, I must decisively renounce health and responsibility I must accept powerlessness, mourn that which is gone and renounce the irrecoverable. Renunciation can free one from the powerlessness which robs me of my awareness of my sense The epoch in which we live is abstract and disembodied. The certainties on which it rests are largely sense-less. And their worldwide acceptance gives them a semblance of independence from history and culture. epistemological askesis opens the path toward renouncing those axiomatic certainties on which the contemporary world view rests. I speak of critically practiced discipline. The so-called values of health and responsibility belong to these certainties. Examined in depth, one sees them as deeply sickening, disorienting phenomena. , I believe it necessary to assert the truth of the human condition: I suffer pain; I am afflicted with certain impairments; I will certainly die. we all equally face death.¶ , some of us today have come to believe that we desperately need packages, commodities, all under the label of "health," designed and delivered by a system of professionalized services. Many have forgotten common-sense ways of living that contribute to one's well-being and ability to recover from illness. Many have allowed themselves to become dependent on a self-aggrandizing technological myth the impersonal ways in which it impoverishes many while enriching a few.¶ specific situations and circumstances are "sickening," rather than that people themselves are sick. The symptoms which modern medicine attempts to treat often have little to do with the condition of our bodies; they are, rather, signals pointing to the disorders and presumptions of modern ways of working, playing and living.¶ many are mesmerized by the glitter of high-tech "solutions, " we seek to postpone death at almost any cost. I demand celebrate living rather than preserve "life" the liberty to die without diagnosis.¶ we will never eliminate pain;¶ we will not cure all disorders;¶ we will certainly die.¶ the pursuit of health may be a sickening disorder. There are no scientific, technological solutions. There is the daily task of accepting the fragility and contingency of the human situation. There are limits which must be placed on conventional "health" care. we suffer pain, we become ill, we die. But we also hope, laugh, celebrate; we know the joy of caring for one another; often we are healed and we recover by many means
Biomedicine discovered its competence over "life." Health has become a scale on which one measures an immune system's fitness for living.¶ The reduction of a person to an immune system corresponds to the deceptive reduction of creation to a global system Where is the Life we have lost in living? Where is the wisdom we have lost in knowledge? Where is the knowledge we have lost in information? The concept of a life which can be reduced to a survival phase of the immune system is a caricature an idol "responsibility" is an illusion "being healthy" is reduced to a combination of the enjoyment of techniques, protection of the environment, and adaptation to the consequences of techniques, all three of which are, inevitably, privileges.¶ In order to live today, I must decisively renounce health and responsibility. I must accept powerlessness, mourn that which is gone and renounce the irrecoverable. Renunciation can free one from the powerlessness which robs me of my awareness of my sense The epoch in which we live is disembodied. The certainties on which it rests are sense-less epistemological askesis opens the path toward renouncing those axiomatic certainties on which the contemporary world view rests. I believe it necessary to assert the truth of the human condition: I suffer I am afflicted with impairments; I will die we all equally face death Many have allowed themselves to become dependent on a self-aggrandizing technological myth the impersonal ways in which it impoverishes many while enriching a few. The symptoms which modern medicine attempts to treat often have little to do with the condition of our bodies; they are signals pointing to the disorders and presumptions of modern ways of working, playing and living. we seek to postpone death at any cost I demand celebrate living rather than preserve "life" the liberty to die without diagnosis the pursuit of health may be a sickening disorder. There are no scientific, technological solutions. There is the daily task of accepting the fragility and contingency of the human situation. There are limits which must be placed on "health" care. we suffer pain, we become ill, we die. But we also hope, laugh, celebrate; we know the joy of caring for one another; often we are healed and we recover by many means.
Ivan, Ph.D from the University of Salzburg, “BRAVE NEW BIOCRACY: HEALTH CARE FROM WOMB TO TOMB,” New Perspectives Quarterly, Winter 1994, Vol. 11, Issue 1, http://brandon.multics.org/library/Ivan%20Illich/against_life.html SJE In recent times, as I discussed earlier, the representation of the substantive concept, "life," has prominently emerged. The physician was required to take responsibility for life. Around 1979, the quality of life was suddenly before us. Biomedicine discovered its competence over "life."¶ Studying the history of well-being, the history of health, it is obvious that with the arrival of life and its quality -- which was also called health -- the thread which linked that which is called health today with health in the past was broken. Health has become a scale on which one measures an immune system's fitness for living.¶ The reduction of a person to an immune system corresponds to the deceptive reduction of creation to a global system, Lovelock's Gaia. And in this perspective, responsibility ends up being understood as the self-steering of an immune system. As much as I would like to rescue for future use the word "responsible" -- a word that, as a philosophical concept, only appeared around 1920 -- to characterize my actions and omissions, I cannot do it. And this is true, not primarily because through this slogan for self-regulation of one's own "quality of life" sense is extinguished, management transfigured as beneficial, and politics reduced to feedback, but because God is thus blasphemed.¶ I ask you to pay careful attention to my form of expression. I am a Christian, but when I speak here about blaspheming God, I want to be understood as an historian, not as a theologian.¶ I have outlined my thinking. Longing for that which health and responsibility might have been in the recently arrived modernity I leave to romantics and drop-outs. I consider it a perversion to use the names of high-sounding illusions which cannot fit in the world of computer and media for the internalization and embodiment of systems and information theory.¶ Only if one understands the history of health and life in their historical interconnection is there a basis for the passion with which I call for the renunciation of "life." I completely agree with T. S. Eliot:¶ Where is the Life we have lost in living? Where is the wisdom we have lost in knowledge? Where is the knowledge we have lost in information? The cycles of Heaven in twenty centuries Bring us farther from God and nearer to the Drust.¶ The concept of a life which can be reduced to a survival phase of the immune system is not only a caricature, not only an idol, but a blasphemy. And seen in this light, desire for responsibility for the quality of this life is not only stupid or impertinent, it is a sin.¶ The Illusion of Responsibility¶ I can imagine no complex of controls capable of saving us from the flood of poisons, radiations, goods and services which sicken humans and animals more than ever before. What sickens us today is something altogether new. What determines the epoch since Kristallnacht is the growing matter-offact acceptance of a bottomless evil which Hitler and Stalin did not reach, but which today is the theme for elevated discussions on the atom, the gene, poison, health, and growth.¶ These are evils and crimes which render us speechless. Unlike death, pestilence, and devils, these evils are without meaning. They belong to a non-human order. They force us into impotence, helplessness, and powerlessness. We can suffer such evil, we can be broken by it, but we cannot make sense of it, cannot direct it.¶ There is no way out of this world. I live in a manufactured reality ever further removed from creation. And I know today what that signifies, what horror threatens each of us.¶ A few decades ago, I did not yet know it. At that time, it seemed possible that I could share responsibility for the remaking of this manufactured world. Today, I finally know what powerlessness is. I know that "responsibility" is an illusion.¶ In such a world, "being healthy" is reduced to a combination of the enjoyment of techniques, protection of the environment, and adaptation to the consequences of techniques, all three of which are, inevitably, privileges.¶ In order to live today, I must decisively renounce health and responsibility. Renounce, I say, not ignore or become resigned. I do not use the word to denote indifference. What I mean is that I must accept powerlessness, mourn that which is gone and renounce the irrecoverable. Renunciation can free one from the powerlessness which robs me of my awareness of my sense. But renunciation is not a familiar concept today. We no longer have a word for courageous, disciplined, self-critical renunciation accomplished in community -- but that is what I am talking about. I will call it askesis.¶ I would have preferred another word, for askesis today brings to mind Flaubert and Saint Antony in the desert -- turning away from wine, women and fragrance. But the renunciation of which I speak has very little to do with this.¶ The epoch in which we live is abstract and disembodied. The certainties on which it rests are largely sense-less. And their worldwide acceptance gives them a semblance of independence from history and culture. What I want to call epistemological askesis opens the path toward renouncing those axiomatic certainties on which the contemporary world view rests. I speak of convivial and critically practiced discipline. The so-called values of health and responsibility belong to these certainties. Examined in depth, one sees them as deeply sickening, disorienting phenomena. That is why I regard a call to take responsibility for my health as senseless, misleading, indecent, and, in a very particular way, blasphemous.¶ Hygienic Autonomy: A Manifesto¶ Many persons are confused today about something called "health." Experts prate knowingly about "health care systems." Some persons believe that without access to sophisticated and expensive treatments, people will be sick. Everyone worries about increasing costs. One even hears talk of a "health care crisis." I would like to say something about these matters.¶ First, I believe it necessary to assert the truth of the human condition: I suffer pain; I am afflicted with certain impairments; I will certainly die. Some undergo greater pain, some more debilitating disorders, but we all equally face death.¶ Looking around me, I see that we -- as people in other times and places -- have a great capacity to care for one another, especially in the moments of birthing, accidents and dying. Unless unbalanced by historical novelties, our households, in close cooperation with their surrounding communities, have been wonderfully hospitable, that is, generally adequate to care for the real needs of living, celebrating and dying.¶ In opposition to this experience, some of us today have come to believe that we desperately need packages, commodities, all under the label of "health," all designed and delivered by a system of professionalized services. Some try to convince us that an infant is born, not only helpless -- needing the loving care of household -- but also sick, requiring specialized treatment by self-certified experts. Others believe that adults routinely require various drugs and interventions in order to become old, while the dying need medical treatment.¶ Many have forgotten -- or are no longer able to enjoy -- those common-sense ways of living that contribute to one's well-being and ability to recover from illness. Many have allowed themselves to become dependent on a self-aggrandizing technological myth, against which they nevertheless complain, because of the impersonal ways in which it impoverishes many while enriching a few.¶ Sadly, I recognize that many of us are infected with a strange illusion: a person has a "right" to something called health care. Thus, one states a claim to receive the latest assortment of technological therapies, based on some professional's diagnosis, to enable one to survive longer in a situation which often ugly, injuries,or depressing or just boring.¶ I believe it is time to state clearly that specific situations and circumstances are "sickening," rather than that people themselves are sick. The symptoms which modern medicine attempts to treat often have little to do with the condition of our bodies; they are, rather, signals pointing to the disorders and presumptions of modern ways of working, playing and living.¶ Nevertheless. many of us are mesmerized by the glitter of high-tech "solutions, " we pathetically believe in"fix-it" drugs, we mistakenly think all pain is an evil to be suppressed, we seek to postpone death at almost any cost. I appeal to the actual experience of people, to the sensibleness of the ordinary person, in direct opposition to professional diagnosis and judgement. I appeal to people's memories, in opposition to the illusions of progress. Let us look at the conditions of our households and communities, not at the quality of "health care" delivery; health is not a deliverable commodity and care does not come out of a system.¶ I demand certain liberties for those who would celebrate living rather than preserve "life": the liberty to declare myself sick; the liberty to refuse any and all medical treatment at any time; the liberty to take any drug or treatment of my own choosing; the liberty to be treated by the person of my choice, that is, by anyone in the community who feels called to the practice of healing, whether that person be an acupuncturist, a homeopathic physician, a neurosurgeon, an astrologer, a witch doctor or someone else;¶ the liberty to die without diagnosis.¶ I do not believe that countries need a national "health" policy, something given to their citizens.¶ Rather, the latter need the courageous virtue to face certain truths:¶ we will never eliminate pain;¶ we will not cure all disorders;¶ we will certainly die.¶ Therefore, as sensible creatures, we must face the fact that the pursuit of health may be a sickening disorder. There are no scientific, technological solutions. There is the daily task of accepting the fragility and contingency of the human situation. There are reasonable limits which must be placed on conventional "health" care. We urgently need to define anew what duties belong to us as persons, what pertains to our communities, what we relinquish to the state.¶ Yes, we suffer pain, we become ill, we die. But we also hope, laugh, celebrate; we know the joy of caring for one another; often we are healed and we recover by many means. We do not have to pursue the path of the flattening out of human experience.¶ I invite all to shift their gaze, their thoughts, from worrying about health care to cultivating the art of living. And, today, with equal importance, to the art of suffering, the art of dying.
10,926
<h4><strong>Only this total rejection of the vital imperative can deconstruct the axiomatic truths which provide the foundations for medicalization, opening the possibility for practice founded upon an ethic of care</h4><p>Illich 94</p><p></strong>Ivan, Ph.D from the University of Salzburg, “BRAVE NEW BIOCRACY: HEALTH CARE FROM WOMB TO TOMB,” New Perspectives Quarterly, Winter 1994, Vol. 11, Issue 1, http://brandon.multics.org/library/Ivan%20Illich/against_life.html SJE</p><p>In recent times, as I discussed earlier, the representation of the substantive concept, "life," has prominently emerged. <u><strong>The physician was required to take responsibility for life</u></strong>. Around 1979, the quality of life was suddenly before us. <u><strong><mark>Biomedicine discovered its competence over "life."</mark>¶</u></strong> Studying the history of well-being, the history of health<u><strong>, it is obvious that with the arrival of life and its quality</u></strong> -- which was also called health -- <u><strong>the thread which linked that which is called health today with health in the past was broken.<mark> Health has become a scale on which one measures an immune system's fitness for living.¶</u></strong> <u><strong>The reduction of a person to an immune system corresponds to the deceptive reduction of creation to a global system</u></strong></mark>, Lovelock's Gaia. And in this perspective, <u><strong>responsibility ends up being understood as the self-steering of an immune system.</u></strong> As much as I would like to rescue for future use the word "responsible" -- a word that, as a philosophical concept, only appeared around 1920 -- to characterize my actions and omissions, I cannot do it. And this is true, not primarily because through this slogan for self-regulation of one's own "quality of life" sense is extinguished, management transfigured as beneficial, and politics reduced to feedback, but because God is thus blasphemed.¶ I ask you to pay careful attention to my form of expression. I am a Christian, but when I speak here about blaspheming God, I want to be understood as an historian, not as a theologian.¶ I have outlined my thinking. Longing for that which health and responsibility might have been in the recently arrived modernity I leave to romantics and drop-outs. I consider it a perversion to use the names of high-sounding illusions which cannot fit in the world of computer and media for the internalization and embodiment of systems and information theory.¶ Only if one understands the history of health and life in their historical interconnection is there a basis for the passion with which I call for the renunciation of "life." I completely agree with T. S. Eliot:¶ <u><strong><mark>Where is the Life we have lost in living? Where is the wisdom we have lost in knowledge? Where is the knowledge we have lost in information?</mark> </u></strong>The cycles of Heaven in twenty centuries Bring us farther from God and nearer to the Drust.¶ <u><strong><mark>The concept of a life which can be reduced to a survival phase of the immune system is</mark> </u></strong>not only <u><strong><mark>a caricature</u></strong></mark>, not only <u><strong><mark>an idol</u></strong></mark>, but a blasphemy. And seen in this light, desire for responsibility for the quality of this life is not only stupid or impertinent, it is a sin.¶ The Illusion of Responsibility¶ <u><strong>I can imagine no complex of controls capable of saving us from the flood of poisons, radiations, goods and services which sicken humans and animals more than ever before</u></strong>. What sickens us today is something altogether new. What determines the epoch since Kristallnacht is the growing matter-offact acceptance of a bottomless evil which Hitler and Stalin did not reach, but which today is the theme for elevated discussions on the atom, the gene, poison, health, and growth.¶ These are evils and crimes which render us speechless. Unlike death, pestilence, and devils, these evils are without meaning. They belong to a non-human order. They force us into impotence, helplessness, and powerlessness. We can suffer such evil, we can be broken by it, but we cannot make sense of it, cannot direct it.¶ There is no way out of this world. <u><strong>I live in a manufactured reality ever further removed from creation.</u></strong> And I know today what that signifies, what horror threatens each of us.¶ A few decades ago, I did not yet know it. At that time, it seemed possible that I could share responsibility for the remaking of this manufactured world. Today, I finally know what powerlessness is. I know that <u><strong><mark>"responsibility" is an illusion</mark>.¶</u></strong> <u><strong>In such a world, <mark>"being healthy" is reduced to a combination of the enjoyment of techniques, protection of the environment, and adaptation to the consequences of techniques, all three of which are, inevitably, privileges.¶</u></strong> <u><strong>In order to live today, I must decisively renounce health and responsibility</u></strong>.</mark> Renounce, I say, not ignore or become resigned. I do not use the word to denote indifference. What I mean is that <u><strong><mark>I must accept powerlessness, mourn that which is gone and renounce the irrecoverable. Renunciation can free one from the powerlessness which robs me of my awareness of my sense</u></strong></mark>. But renunciation is not a familiar concept today. We no longer have a word for courageous, disciplined, self-critical renunciation accomplished in community -- but that is what I am talking about. I will call it askesis.¶ I would have preferred another word, for askesis today brings to mind Flaubert and Saint Antony in the desert -- turning away from wine, women and fragrance. But the renunciation of which I speak has very little to do with this.¶ <u><strong><mark>The epoch in which we live is</mark> abstract and <mark>disembodied. The certainties on which it rests are</mark> largely <mark>sense-less</mark>. And their worldwide acceptance gives them a semblance of independence from history and culture.</u></strong> What I want to call <u><strong><mark>epistemological askesis opens the path toward renouncing those axiomatic certainties on which the contemporary world view rests.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>I speak of </u></strong>convivial and <u><strong>critically practiced discipline. The so-called values of health and responsibility belong to these certainties. Examined in depth, one sees them as deeply sickening, disorienting phenomena.</u></strong> That is why I regard a call to take responsibility for my health as senseless, misleading, indecent, and, in a very particular way, blasphemous.¶ Hygienic Autonomy: A Manifesto¶ Many persons are confused today about something called "health." Experts prate knowingly about "health care systems." Some persons believe that without access to sophisticated and expensive treatments, people will be sick. Everyone worries about increasing costs. One even hears talk of a "health care crisis." I would like to say something about these matters.¶ First<u><strong>, <mark>I believe it necessary to assert the truth of the human condition: I suffer </mark>pain; <mark>I am afflicted with </mark>certain <mark>impairments; I will</mark> certainly <mark>die</mark>.</u></strong> Some undergo greater pain, some more debilitating disorders, but <u><strong><mark>we all equally face death</mark>.¶</u></strong> Looking around me, I see that we -- as people in other times and places -- have a great capacity to care for one another, especially in the moments of birthing, accidents and dying. Unless unbalanced by historical novelties, our households, in close cooperation with their surrounding communities, have been wonderfully hospitable, that is, generally adequate to care for the real needs of living, celebrating and dying.¶ In opposition to this experience<u><strong>, some of us today have come to believe that we desperately need packages, commodities, all under the label of "health,"</u></strong> all <u><strong>designed and delivered by a system of professionalized services. </u></strong>Some try to convince us that an infant is born, not only helpless -- needing the loving care of household -- but also sick, requiring specialized treatment by self-certified experts. Others believe that adults routinely require various drugs and interventions in order to become old, while the dying need medical treatment.¶ <u><strong>Many have forgotten</u></strong> -- or are no longer able to enjoy -- those <u><strong>common-sense ways of living that contribute to one's well-being and ability to recover from illness. <mark>Many have allowed themselves to become dependent on a self-aggrandizing technological myth</u></strong></mark>, against which they nevertheless complain, because of <u><strong><mark>the impersonal ways in which it impoverishes many while enriching a few.</mark>¶</u></strong> Sadly, I recognize that many of us are infected with a strange illusion: a person has a "right" to something called health care. Thus, one states a claim to receive the latest assortment of technological therapies, based on some professional's diagnosis, to enable one to survive longer in a situation which often ugly, injuries,or depressing or just boring.¶ I believe it is time to state clearly that <u><strong>specific situations and circumstances are "sickening," rather than that people themselves are sick. <mark>The symptoms which modern medicine attempts to treat often have little to do with the condition of our bodies; they are</mark>, rather, <mark>signals pointing to the disorders and presumptions of modern ways of working, playing and living.</mark>¶</u></strong> Nevertheless. <u><strong>many</u></strong> of us <u><strong>are mesmerized by the glitter of high-tech "solutions, "</u></strong> we pathetically believe in"fix-it" drugs, we mistakenly think all pain is an evil to be suppressed, <u><strong><mark>we seek to postpone death at</mark> almost <mark>any cost</mark>.</u></strong> I appeal to the actual experience of people, to the sensibleness of the ordinary person, in direct opposition to professional diagnosis and judgement. I appeal to people's memories, in opposition to the illusions of progress. Let us look at the conditions of our households and communities, not at the quality of "health care" delivery; health is not a deliverable commodity and care does not come out of a system.¶ <u><strong><mark>I demand</mark> </u></strong>certain liberties for those who would <u><strong><mark>celebrate living rather than preserve "life"</u></strong></mark>: the liberty to declare myself sick; the liberty to refuse any and all medical treatment at any time; the liberty to take any drug or treatment of my own choosing; the liberty to be treated by the person of my choice, that is, by anyone in the community who feels called to the practice of healing, whether that person be an acupuncturist, a homeopathic physician, a neurosurgeon, an astrologer, a witch doctor or someone else;¶ <u><strong><mark>the liberty to die without diagnosis</mark>.¶ </u></strong>I do not believe that countries need a national "health" policy, something given to their citizens.¶ Rather, the latter need the courageous virtue to face certain truths:¶ <u><strong>we will never eliminate pain;¶ we will not cure all disorders;¶ we will certainly die.¶ </u></strong>Therefore, as sensible creatures, we must face the fact that <u><strong><mark>the pursuit of health may be a sickening disorder.</u></strong> <u><strong>There are no scientific, technological solutions. There is the daily task of accepting the fragility and contingency of the human situation. There are</u></strong></mark> reasonable <u><strong><mark>limits</mark> <mark>which must be placed on</mark> conventional <mark>"health" care.</u></strong></mark> We urgently need to define anew what duties belong to us as persons, what pertains to our communities, what we relinquish to the state.¶ Yes, <u><strong><mark>we suffer pain, we become ill, we die. But we also hope, laugh, celebrate; we know the joy of caring for one another; often we are healed and we recover by many means</u></strong>.</mark> We do not have to pursue the path of the flattening out of human experience.¶ I invite all to shift their gaze, their thoughts, from worrying about health care to cultivating the art of living. And, today, with equal importance, to the art of suffering, the art of dying.</p>
null
1AC
null
430,074
1
16,996
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
564,699
A
NDT
6
Kentucky GV
Hirn, Fisher, DeLo
1AC Illich 1NC T Cap K Block Cap K New Affs Bad 2NR Cap K New Affs Bad
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round6.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,981
China A2/AD card
Pan ‘13
Pan ‘13 (Chengxin Pan, Senior Lecturer in International Relations, Deakin University, Australia Knowledge, desire and power in global politics Publisher: Edward Elgar Pub (January 30, 2013) Page 26-27)
An obvious anomaly for the capability based ‘China threat’ paradigm is that if military capabilities are the sole criterion for threat assessment, the US would be more of a threat to China than the other way round. many American military officials’ own admission, China’s military power remains modest when compared to the US But under China threat’ paradigm, this ‘anomaly’ is ignored by a focus on China’s A2/AD threats the China threat argument looks hollow in a military sense, it is able to renew its credibility in an economic context
An obvious anomaly for the capability-based ‘China threat’ paradigm is that if military capabilities are the sole criterion for threat assessment, the US would be more of a threat to China than the other way round American military officials’ own admission military power remains modest when compared to the US But under threat’ paradigm this ‘anomaly’ ignored by a focus on China’s A2/AD threats the China threat looks hollow in a military sense
A paradigm qua paradigm needs to be able to account for anomalies. An obvious anomaly for the capability-based ‘China threat’ paradigm is that if military capabilities are the sole criterion for threat assessment, the US would be more of a threat to China than the other way round. By many American military officials’ own admission, China’s military power remains modest when compared to the US. But under the ‘China threat’ paradigm, this ‘anomaly’ is either ignored, or easily circumvented by a focus on China’s so- called ‘asymmetric warfare capabilities’, such as its so-called anti-access, area-denial (A2/AD) and cyber-espionage threats.27 Even if the China threat argument looks hollow in a military sense, it is able to renew its credibility in an economic context. For a start, China’s economic rise seems to pose a threat in that it could have potentially disastrous resource, environmental and ecological consequences. As early as 1994, American environmentalist Lester Brown, in his famous article ‘Who Will Feed China?’, predicted that China’s surging demand for food would dramatically increase the price of food worldwide.28 Other observers note that as it industrialises, China will require a dramatically larger share of world resources, and place a huge strain on global energy supplies. It will then contribute significantly to pollution and global warming, and lead to the intensification of regional conflict over resources and energy, especially in places like Africa and Latin America.29 To many, the so-called ‘China price’ strategy of using cheap labour and products is at the core of the economic challenge posed by China. The China price, dubbed ‘the three scariest words’ in some quarters of the US indus- try,30 is said to have, among other things, aggressively undercut competitors, caused massive job losses as well as increased US trade deficit and foreign debt. In February 2004, a bipartisan group of US senators argued that China’s undervalued currency renminbi (RMB) has contributed to the loss of 2.6 million US manufacturing jobs.31 Pennsylvania’s Democratic senator, Arlen Specter, complained to ‘Fox News Sunday’ that ‘We have a real problem with the Chinese…. They are very shrewd, and customarily they outmaneu- ver us. They take our jobs. They take our money, and then they lend it back to us and own a big part of America’.32
2,370
<h4><u><strong>China A2/AD card</h4><p>Pan ‘13</p><p></u></strong>(Chengxin Pan, Senior Lecturer in International Relations, Deakin University, Australia Knowledge, desire and power in global politics Publisher: Edward Elgar Pub (January 30, 2013) Page 26-27)</p><p>A paradigm qua paradigm needs to be able to account for anomalies. <u><mark>An obvious anomaly for the capability</u>-<u>based ‘China threat’ paradigm is that if military capabilities are the sole criterion for threat assessment, the US would be more of a threat to China than the other way round</mark>.</u> By <u>many <mark>American military officials’ own admission</mark>, China’s <mark>military power remains modest when compared to the US</u></mark>. <u><mark>But</mark> <mark>under</u></mark> the ‘<u>China <mark>threat’ paradigm</mark>, <mark>this ‘anomaly’</mark> is</u> either <u><mark>ignored</u></mark>, or easily circumvented <u><mark>by</mark> <mark>a</mark> <mark>focus</u> <u>on China’s</u></mark> so- called ‘asymmetric warfare capabilities’, such as its so-called anti-access, area-denial (<u><mark>A2/AD</u></mark>) and cyber-espionage <u><mark>threats</u></mark>.27 Even if <u><mark>the China threat</mark> argument <mark>looks hollow in a</mark> <mark>military sense</mark>, it is able to renew its credibility in an economic context</u>. For a start, China’s economic rise seems to pose a threat in that it could have potentially disastrous resource, environmental and ecological consequences. As early as 1994, American environmentalist Lester Brown, in his famous article ‘Who Will Feed China?’, predicted that China’s surging demand for food would dramatically increase the price of food worldwide.28 Other observers note that as it industrialises, China will require a dramatically larger share of world resources, and place a huge strain on global energy supplies. It will then contribute significantly to pollution and global warming, and lead to the intensification of regional conflict over resources and energy, especially in places like Africa and Latin America.29 To many, the so-called ‘China price’ strategy of using cheap labour and products is at the core of the economic challenge posed by China. The China price, dubbed ‘the three scariest words’ in some quarters of the US indus- try,30 is said to have, among other things, aggressively undercut competitors, caused massive job losses as well as increased US trade deficit and foreign debt. In February 2004, a bipartisan group of US senators argued that China’s undervalued currency renminbi (RMB) has contributed to the loss of 2.6 million US manufacturing jobs.31 Pennsylvania’s Democratic senator, Arlen Specter, complained to ‘Fox News Sunday’ that ‘We have a real problem with the Chinese…. They are very shrewd, and customarily they outmaneu- ver us. They take our jobs. They take our money, and then they lend it back to us and own a big part of America’.32</p>
1NR
FBI
China
430,075
1
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,982
And it leads to prostitution free zones
ALLIL No Date
ALLIL No Date
ETB] cities have employed zoning to exclude prostitutes by establishing "prostitution-free zones people who have been identified as known prostitutes are legally banned from whole sections of the city. The "cleansing" of New York City's Times Square in the 1990s is another example of such exclusionary strategies.
cities have employed zoning to exclude prostitutes by establishing "prostitution-free zones people who have been identified as prostitutes are legally banned from whole sections of the city. The "cleansing" of Times Square is another example
[American Law and Legal Information Library, http://law.jrank.org/pages/1880/Prostitution-Regimes-prohibition-criminalization-regulation.html#ixzz3JKp8jdwf ETB] In the 1990s, other cities (notably Portland, Oregon) have employed zoning in a different fashion. Rather than quarantining sexual commerce by zoning it into a specific urban area like Boston's Combat Zone, now zoning is used to exclude prostitutes by establishing "prostitution-free zones." Drawing upon new urban strategies such as business improvement districts and area-specific gang-abatement injunctions, people who have been identified as known prostitutes are legally banned from whole sections of the city. The "cleansing" of New York City's Times Square in the 1990s is another example of such exclusionary strategies.
789
<h4><u><strong>And it leads to prostitution free zones</h4><p>ALLIL No Date</p><p></u></strong>[American Law and Legal Information Library, http://law.jrank.org/pages/1880/Prostitution-Regimes-prohibition-criminalization-regulation.html#ixzz3JKp8jdwf<u> ETB]</p><p></u>In the 1990s, other <u><mark>cities</u> </mark>(notably Portland, Oregon) <u><mark>have employed zoning</u> </mark>in a different fashion. Rather than quarantining sexual commerce by zoning it into a specific urban area like Boston's Combat Zone, now zoning is used <u><mark>to exclude prostitutes by establishing "prostitution-free zones</u></mark>." Drawing upon new urban strategies such as business improvement districts and area-specific gang-abatement injunctions, <u><mark>people who have been identified as</mark> known <mark>prostitutes are legally banned from whole sections of the city. The "cleansing" of</mark> New York City's <mark>Times Square</mark> in the 1990s <mark>is another example</mark> of such exclusionary strategies.</p></u>
1NC
null
Off
429,932
2
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,983
We control uniqueness: the instrumental responses to PAS are terrible – the aff increases neg ground because you can negate the stylistic parts of the aff – that’s the best middle ground between predictability and critical thinking
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><u><strong>We control uniqueness: the instrumental responses to PAS are terrible – the aff increases neg ground because you can negate the stylistic parts of the aff – that’s the best middle ground between predictability and critical thinking</h4></u></strong>
T
null
null
430,073
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,984
Double bind – either war won’t escalate or miscalc makes it inevitable
Branigan 12
Branigan 12
No one seriously envisages a major conflict in the South China Sea because it's not in anyone's interests. They depend on those sea lanes for their economies. "The real risk is that an accidental clash occurs and escalates it is just a matter of time before one of these standoffs gets really ugly and people get killed."
No one envisages a major conflict in the South China Sea because it's not in anyone's interests. They depend on those sea lanes for their economies The real risk is that an accidental clash occurs
(Tania, writer for the Guardian, "Chinese frigate runs aground in disputed part of South China Sea," 2012, http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2012/jul/13/chinese-frigate-runs-aground-sea) Ian Storey of the Institute of South-east Asian Studies in Singapore said that while the grounding was in itself unlikely to escalate tensions, it indicated the growing militarisation of the waters. "Resolution of the dispute is even further out of reach," he added. "No one seriously envisages a major conflict in the South China Sea because it's not in anyone's interests. They depend on those sea lanes for the continued functioning of their economies.¶ "The real risk is that an accidental clash occurs and escalates. In my mind, it is just a matter of time before one of these standoffs gets really ugly and people get killed."¶ Tensions have been building in the area since 2007, with increasing keenness to claim the energy resources, and growing pressure from nationalists in several of the countries. Vietnam has seen unusual street protests over the dispute in the past few weeks.
1,075
<h4>Double bind – either war won’t escalate or miscalc makes it inevitable</h4><p><u><strong>Branigan 12</u></strong> </p><p>(Tania, writer for the Guardian, "Chinese frigate runs aground in disputed part of South China Sea," 2012, http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2012/jul/13/chinese-frigate-runs-aground-sea)</p><p>Ian Storey of the Institute of South-east Asian Studies in Singapore said that while the grounding was in itself unlikely to escalate tensions, it indicated the growing militarisation of the waters. "Resolution of the dispute is even further out of reach," he added. "<u><strong><mark>No one</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>seriously <mark>envisages a major conflict in the South China Sea because it's not in anyone's interests. They depend on those sea lanes for</u></strong></mark> the continued functioning of <u><strong><mark>their economies</mark>.</u></strong>¶ <u><strong>"<mark>The real risk is that an accidental clash occurs</mark> and escalates</u></strong>. In my mind, <u><strong>it is just a matter of time before one of these standoffs gets really ugly and people get killed."</u></strong>¶ Tensions have been building in the area since 2007, with increasing keenness to claim the energy resources, and growing pressure from nationalists in several of the countries. Vietnam has seen unusual street protests over the dispute in the past few weeks.</p>
1NR
FBI
China
430,076
3
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,985
CP: The United States should publicly reverse its requirements that grantees of PEPFAR funding sign or abide by antiprostitution pledges, should cease prioritizing abstinence and fidelity as an approach to HIV, should cease all efforts to pressure UNAIDS to follow PEPFAR’s lead in emphasizing the reduction of sex work, should ends its sanction of any tier 3 or 4 country as per the Trafficking in person’s report, and should publicly communicate the message that brothel raids and more stringent anti-prostitution laws do not please the United states government
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>CP: The United States should publicly reverse its requirements that grantees of PEPFAR funding sign or abide by antiprostitution pledges, should cease prioritizing abstinence and fidelity as an approach to HIV, should cease all efforts to pressure UNAIDS to follow PEPFAR’s lead in emphasizing the reduction of sex work, should ends its sanction of any tier 3 or 4 country as per the Trafficking in person’s report, and should publicly communicate the message that brothel raids and more stringent anti-prostitution laws do not please the United states government</h4>
1NC
null
Off
430,077
1
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,986
No South China Sea war -- China rise is peaceful
Reuters 13
Reuters 13 (July 31st, http://www.reuters.com/article/2013/07/31/us-china-seas-idUSBRE96U0T120130731, “China's Xi says seeks peace in sea disputes but must be alert”, AB)
Chinese President told Politburo the country wanted to resolve its maritime territorial disputes peacefully and through talks China would adhere to the path of peaceful development China will "use peaceful means and negotiations to settle disputes and strive to safeguard peace and stability China will prepare to cope with complexities the country will adhere to a policy of "shelving disputes and carrying out joint development"
Chinese wanted to resolve maritime territorial disputes peacefully China would adhere to peaceful development China will use peaceful means and negotiations to settle disputes to safeguard peace the country will shelv disputes
(Reuters) - Chinese President Xi Jinping told his Politburo on Wednesday the country wanted to resolve its maritime territorial disputes peacefully and through talks, but would not compromise on sovereignty and had to step up its defensive capabilities. Territorial claims by Japan and China over the uninhabited islets and resource-rich waters in the East China Sea, as well as China's claims over the South China Sea, rank as some of Asia's biggest security risks. At a meeting with members of the ruling Communist Party's inner elite, Xi said China would adhere to the path of peaceful development, but "in no way will the country abandon its legitimate rights and interests, nor will it give up its core national interests", state media reported. China will "use peaceful means and negotiations to settle disputes and strive to safeguard peace and stability", Xi was quoted as saying, without naming any countries. His comments were the most high-level remarks on the subject in weeks. "China will prepare to cope with complexities, enhance its capacity in safeguarding maritime rights and interests, and resolutely safeguard its maritime rights and interests," Xi said, according to the official Xinhua news agency report. Becoming a maritime power is an "important task" for China as "the oceans and seas have an increasingly important strategic status concerning global competition in the spheres of politics, economic development, military, and scientific and technology", Xi said. Still, the country will adhere to a policy of "shelving disputes and carrying out joint development" for areas over which China claims sovereignty, while also promoting mutually beneficial and friendly cooperation, Xi added, repeating a line offered previously by Chinese officials.
1,772
<h4>No South China Sea war -- China rise is peaceful</h4><p><u><strong><mark>Reuters 13</u></strong></mark> (July 31st, http://www.reuters.com/article/2013/07/31/us-china-seas-idUSBRE96U0T120130731, “China's Xi says seeks peace in sea disputes but must be alert”, AB)</p><p>(Reuters) - <u><mark>Chinese </mark>President</u> Xi Jinping <u>told</u> his <u>Politburo</u> on Wednesday <u>the country <mark>wanted to resolve</mark> its <mark>maritime territorial disputes peacefully</mark> and through talks</u>, but would not compromise on sovereignty and had to step up its defensive capabilities. Territorial claims by Japan and China over the uninhabited islets and resource-rich waters in the East China Sea, as well as China's claims over the South China Sea, rank as some of Asia's biggest security risks. At a meeting with members of the ruling Communist Party's inner elite, Xi said <u><mark>China</mark> <mark>would</mark> <mark>adhere to</mark> the path of <mark>peaceful development</u></mark>, but "in no way will the country abandon its legitimate rights and interests, nor will it give up its core national interests", state media reported. <u><mark>China will</mark> "<mark>use peaceful means and negotiations to settle disputes</mark> and strive <mark>to</mark> <mark>safeguard peace</mark> and stability</u>", Xi was quoted as saying, without naming any countries. His comments were the most high-level remarks on the subject in weeks. "<u>China will prepare to cope with complexities</u>, enhance its capacity in safeguarding maritime rights and interests, and resolutely safeguard its maritime rights and interests," Xi said, according to the official Xinhua news agency report. Becoming a maritime power is an "important task" for China as "the oceans and seas have an increasingly important strategic status concerning global competition in the spheres of politics, economic development, military, and scientific and technology", Xi said. Still, <u><mark>the country will</mark> adhere to a policy of "<mark>shelv</mark>ing <mark>disputes</mark> and carrying out joint development"</u> for areas over which China claims sovereignty, while also promoting mutually beneficial and friendly cooperation, Xi added, repeating a line offered previously by Chinese officials.</p>
1NR
FBI
China
430,078
1
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,987
Skill Enforcement DA – their claims about skills and agency enforce a model of education which frames subjects as units of rationality to be bettered through civilizing practices – that dooms millions to suffer
Mourad 01
Mourad 01
739–759) The tacit, unchallenged belief is that through education, the human being must be made into something better than it was or would be absent a formal education. There are all kinds of versions of this subject and of what it should become qualified professional, good citizen, “leader,” independent actor, critical thinker, change agent, knowledgeable person. In all cases, the subject before education is viewed to be, like the subject before civilization, something in need of being made competent—and safe—in the mind of the educator It must be resolved, or contained in some way; and this is done immediately by rendering the student a rule follower – a follower of the social order, both in and out of the classroom. Or the student must be rendered a challenger of the social order, in favor of an order that overcomes oppression—to become a competent comrade. The individual must be taught how to be an individual in accordance with this balance. Being an individual means being “free”—it means being “self-determined,” it means competing, and it means obeying the law the remedy tends to be to provide the person with an opportunity to become competent This situation reflects that the logic of formal education and the state, is not predicated upon a recognition that the human being is susceptible to suffering or that the state’s reason for being should be to care for people. We talk about equipping children and adults to “solve problems.” Yet, problems do not fall from the sky; they do not exist as such until a human being gives them a name In contrast, the concept of contention suggests that the practical role of reason should be used to understand the human being as subject to suffering and to act accordingly as moral agents. That is very different from an educational philosophy, policy, and practice that views reason as an instrument by which to overcome obstacles and to conform to the social order it is commonly expressed that we live in a “complex world must “learn how to learn,” in order to “succeed in a world of rapid change.” One must be an “active learner” or else Why? The individual must be acted upon and rendered into an entity that engages reality in the ways that are deemed just by many educators, lawmakers, and others with a stake in the perpetuation of the given social order. This philosophy of improvement is not necessarily consistent with enhancement of living. It often has the opposite effect The modern idea that anyone can be rational leads quickly to the idea that everyone is responsible for being wholly rational, as that word is understood according to the social order. The perpetuation of the given social order in education as elsewhere is about gaining advantage and retaining power It is about cultural politics and about marginalization of various groups and about class and about socializing children to believe in capitalism as if it is a natural law. these major problems are symptoms of something more basic It is about the intense pressures on people to think and act in ways that serve broader interests that are not at all concerned with their well-being in a variety of contexts including psychological, social, economic, political, and cultural It is no answer to ground pedagogy in the notion of “building community.” The idea that something must be built implies that something must be made better in order for it to be tolerated. community” carries with it the prerequisite that one be made competent to be a member this ethos of betterment through competency will inevitably fail to fulfill the dreams of reformers and revolutionaries. It does not consider the human being as an entity to care for but rather as something to be equipped with skills and knowledge in order to improve itself. This failure is not only because there are millions of children and adults that live in poverty in the wealthiest countries in human history. It is because the state of mind that can tolerate such suffering is the same state that advances and maintains the ethos of civility as betterment, rather than civility as caring for people because they are subject to suffering. The alternative is intended to address an unacceptable state of contemporary Western civilization, namely, its repetitive and even escalating incidence of disregard for suffering and harm in many forms, despite intellectual, social, medical, legal, educational, scientific, and technological “progress.” We have had two hundred years of modern educational principles, and two hundred years of profound suffering along with them The problem of the individual calls for a new formulation and for a proper response one that cares for the individual rather than makes it competent. The “modern project” of betterment through competency and opportunity must be challenged and replaced by an emotionally intelligent ethos that expressly and fundamentally acknowledges suffering and limitation in philosophy, policy, and practice.
The belief is that the human being must be made into something better than it was absent a formal education good citizen, critical thinker, change agent, knowledgeable person the subject before education is viewed to be before civilization something in need of being made competent We talk about equipping children and adults to “solve problems.” the practical role of reason should be used to understand being as subject to suffering and to act accordingly as moral agents this ethos of betterment through competency will inevitably fail It does not consider the human being as an entity to care for but rather as something to be equipped with skills and knowledge the state of mind that can tolerate suffering is the same state that advances and maintains the ethos of civility as betterment
(Roger Jr., Director of Institutional Research at Washtenaw College and teaches at the University of Michigan. His academic credentials include a Ph.D. in Higher Education, M.A. in Philosophy of Education, and J.D. in Law, all from the University of Michigan. He is the author of Postmodern Philosophical Critique and the Pursuit of Knowledge in Higher Education ~Westport: Greenwood, 1997! and several recent journal publications on epistemological, ethical, and legal issues pertaining to the nature and structure of institutionally organized education and its relation to the social good, “Education After Foucault: The Question of Civility” Teachers College Record Volume 103, Number 5, October 2001, pp. 739–759) EDUCATION FOR IMPROVEMENT, OR “KICKING THE DOG” Too many lost names too many rules to the game Better find a focus or you’re out of the picture.48 The idea that the fundamental issue of the just civil state is to find the right balance between preserving individual freedom and constraining individual threat has served as a tacit foundation within which belief and debate about educational philosophy, policy, and practice develop. This statement is not intended to suggest that there is some direct and specific historical connection that can be unequivocally demonstrated to exist between foundational political theory and mainstream educational theories and practices. However, I want to propose that there is a compatibility between them that has important consequences for a new critique of organized formal education. In the remainder of this paper, my aim is to argue that the tenor of the theories that I have summarized is endemic in the ordinary ways that we think about and engage in organized education. How is the idea of the basic human being that is posed as the fundamental social, political, and pedagogic problem for modern civilization, this human being that must be managed in order to keep it from harming itself and others, played out in educational presuppositions? The tacit, unchallenged belief is that through education, the human being must be made into something better than it was or would be absent a formal education. There are all kinds of versions of this subject and of what it should become: potential achiever, qualified professional, good citizen, “leader,” independent actor, critical thinker, change agent, knowledgeable person. In all cases, the subject before education is viewed to be, like the subject before civilization, something in need of being made competent—and safe—in the mind of the educator. From this vantage point, the pedagogic relationship between teacher and student, between competent adult and incompetent child ~or adult!, contains within it a possibility that it seeks to overcome, namely, a rejection of the socialization program of the former by the latter. There is an implicit conflict between individuals as soon as the student walks into the school or college classroom door from outside the civility that the teacher would have that student become. It must be resolved, or contained in some way; and this is done immediately by rendering the student a rule follower – a follower of the social order, both in and out of the classroom. Or the student must be rendered a challenger of the social order, in favor of an order that overcomes oppression—to become a competent comrade. The individual must be taught how to be an individual in accordance with this balance. Being an individual means being “free”—it means being “self-determined,” it means competing, and it means obeying the law. This is the case, even if the teaching is done with kindness and sensitivity. The responsibility for dealing with suffering and limitation lies almost solely with this individual, not the state. In fact, if suffering is viewed at all, it tends to be viewed as something that is good for the individual to endure or to fight in order to overcome it. Limitation is not acknowledged, unless the individual is deemed disadvantaged in some way, and the remedy tends to be to provide the person with an opportunity to become competent. Is it any wonder that parents of children with disabilities, aided by many educators, often must fight for educational and other services? This situation simply reflects that the basic logic of organized formal education and, more generally, the state, is not predicated upon a recognition that the human being is susceptible to suffering or that the state’s reason for being should be to care for people. If caring for its inhabitants were the basic purpose of the civil state, then there would be no need to fight for this recognition. Is it any wonder that the education of the ordinary child is mainly training for a far-off, abstract future that is destined to be better than life at present? Why must school be about overcoming anything? We talk about equipping children and adults to “solve problems.” Yet, problems do not fall from the sky; they do not exist as such until a human being gives them a name. In contrast, the concept of contention suggests that the practical role of reason should be used to understand the human being as subject to suffering and to act accordingly as moral agents. That is very different from an educational philosophy, policy, and practice that views reason as an instrument by which to overcome obstacles and to conform to the social order. It may be argued that modern education is about reason, about how to think and live reasonably and, therefore, how to live well and to care for oneself and for others. Yet it is commonly expressed that we live in a “complex world” and that children and adults must “learn how to learn,” in order to “succeed in a world of rapid change.” The question that needs to be asked is: Why should a person have to? In effect, education expects the human being to have an unlimited ability to think and act with reason sufficient to cope with increasingly complex situations that require individual intellect to adequately recognize, evaluate, and prioritize alternative courses of action, consider their consequences, and make good decisions. For the most part, the increasing complexity of civil society and the multiplicity of factors that intellect is expected to deal with in different situations are not questioned in education. Is this what education is rightly about? Education is as much about the use of intelligence to avoid suffering and feelings of limitation and about fending off feelings of fear as it is about learning. It is about acting upon other people and upon the civil order to deal with perceived threats. One must be an “active learner” or else. Why? The individual must be acted upon and rendered into an entity that engages reality in the ways that are deemed just by many educators, lawmakers, and others with a stake in the perpetuation of the given social order. Thus, the individual is exhorted to “do your best,” “make an effort,” “earn a grade,” “be motivated,” “work hard,” “overcome obstacles,” “achieve.” Why should education be about any of these things? Unfortunately, the culture of scholarship is thoroughly consistent with these precepts. When we question them, we challenge the ends that they serve but not the ideas themselves. We believe that education is rightly about improvement. This philosophy of improvement is not necessarily consistent with enhancement of living. It often has the opposite effect. How is this result justified? Certainly, it can feel good to accomplish something or to overcome obstacles. Does that mean that adversity should be a positive value of the civil state? The modern idea, beginning with Descartes and established through Lockean empiricism ~and made pedagogic by Rousseau’s Emile!, that anyone can be rational leads quickly to the idea that everyone is responsible for being wholly rational, as that word is understood according to the social order. The perpetuation of the given social order in education as elsewhere is about gaining advantage and retaining power. It is about cultural politics and about marginalization of various groups and about class and about socializing children to believe in capitalism as if it is a natural law. Yet under the analysis that I have made here, these major problems are symptoms of something more basic. The more basic problem that I have emphasized here is inextricable from the problem of the just civil state. It is about the intense pressures on people to think and act in ways that serve broader interests that are not at all concerned with their well-being in a variety of contexts including psychological, social, economic, political, and cultural. It is no answer to ground pedagogy in the notion of “building community.” The idea that something must be built implies that something must be made better in order for it to be tolerated. Moreover, “community” carries with it the prerequisite that one be made competent to be a member— again, the presumption that something must be done to the person to make it better in some way. I do not mean to say that educators have bad intent. I do mean that this ethos of betterment through competency will inevitably fail to fulfill the dreams of reformers and revolutionaries. It does not consider the human being as an entity to care for but rather as something to be equipped with skills and knowledge in order to improve itself. This failure is not only because there are millions of children and adults that live in poverty in the wealthiest countries in human history. It is because the state of mind that can tolerate such suffering is the same state that advances and maintains the ethos of civility as betterment, rather than civility as caring for people because they are subject to suffering. The alternative that I have only introduced in a very abbreviated way under the rubric that I called “contention” is intended to be pragmatic in the ways that Foucault and Richard Rorty are pragmatic in their respective approaches to the subject of the state.49 It is intended to address an unacceptable state of contemporary Western civilization, namely, its repetitive and even escalating incidence of disregard for suffering and harm in many forms, despite intellectual, social, medical, legal, educational, scientific, and technological “progress.” We have had two hundred years of modern educational principles, and two hundred years of profound suffering along with them. The problem of the individual calls for a new formulation and for a proper response—one that cares for the individual rather than makes it competent. The “modern project” of betterment through competency and opportunity must be challenged and replaced by an emotionally intelligent ethos that expressly and fundamentally acknowledges suffering and limitation in philosophy, policy, and practice.
10,916
<h4><u><strong>Skill Enforcement</strong> DA – their claims about skills and agency enforce a model of education which frames subjects as units of rationality to be bettered through civilizing practices – that dooms millions to suffer</h4><p><strong>Mourad 01 </p><p></u></strong>(Roger Jr., Director of Institutional Research at Washtenaw College and teaches at the University of Michigan. His academic credentials include a Ph.D. in Higher Education, M.A. in Philosophy of Education, and J.D. in Law, all from the University of Michigan. He is the author of Postmodern Philosophical Critique and the Pursuit of Knowledge in Higher Education ~Westport: Greenwood, 1997! and several recent journal publications on epistemological, ethical, and legal issues pertaining to the nature and structure of institutionally organized education and its relation to the social good, “Education After Foucault: The Question of Civility” Teachers College Record Volume 103, Number 5, October 2001, pp. <u>739–759)</p><p></u>EDUCATION FOR IMPROVEMENT, OR “KICKING THE DOG” Too many lost names too many rules to the game Better find a focus or you’re out of the picture.48 The idea that the fundamental issue of the just civil state is to find the right balance between preserving individual freedom and constraining individual threat has served as a tacit foundation within which belief and debate about educational philosophy, policy, and practice develop. This statement is not intended to suggest that there is some direct and specific historical connection that can be unequivocally demonstrated to exist between foundational political theory and mainstream educational theories and practices. However, I want to propose that there is a compatibility between them that has important consequences for a new critique of organized formal education. In the remainder of this paper, my aim is to argue that the tenor of the theories that I have summarized is endemic in the ordinary ways that we think about and engage in organized education. How is the idea of the basic human being that is posed as the fundamental social, political, and pedagogic problem for modern civilization, this human being that must be managed in order to keep it from harming itself and others, played out in educational presuppositions? <u><mark>The <strong></mark>tacit, unchallenged <mark>belief</strong> is that</mark> through education, <mark>the human being must be <strong>made into something better</strong> than it was</mark> or would be <mark>absent a <strong>formal education</strong></mark>.</u> <u>There are all kinds of versions of this subject and of what it should become</u>: potential achiever, <u><strong>qualified professional, <mark>good citizen, </mark>“leader,” independent actor, <mark>critical thinker, change agent, knowledgeable person</strong></mark>. In all cases, <mark>the subject before education is viewed to be</mark>, like the subject <strong><mark>before civilization</strong></mark>, <mark>something in need of being <strong>made competent</strong></mark>—and safe—in the mind of the educator</u>. From this vantage point, the pedagogic relationship between teacher and student, between competent adult and incompetent child ~or adult!, contains within it a possibility that it seeks to overcome, namely, a rejection of the socialization program of the former by the latter. There is an implicit conflict between individuals as soon as the student walks into the school or college classroom door from outside the civility that the teacher would have that student become. <u>It must be <strong>resolved</strong>, or contained in some way; and this is done immediately by rendering the student a <strong>rule follower</strong> – a follower of the social order, both in and out of the classroom. Or the student must be rendered a challenger of the social order, in favor of an order that overcomes oppression—to become a competent comrade.</u> <u>The individual must be taught how to be an individual in accordance with this balance. Being an individual means being “free”—it means being “self-determined,” <strong>it means competing, and it means obeying the law</u></strong>. This is the case, even if the teaching is done with kindness and sensitivity. The responsibility for dealing with suffering and limitation lies almost solely with this individual, not the state. In fact, if suffering is viewed at all, it tends to be viewed as something that is good for the individual to endure or to fight in order to overcome it. Limitation is not acknowledged, unless the individual is deemed disadvantaged in some way, and <u>the remedy tends to be to provide the person with an opportunity to become competent</u>. Is it any wonder that parents of children with disabilities, aided by many educators, often must fight for educational and other services? <u>This situation </u>simply <u>reflects</u> <u>that the </u>basic <u>logic of </u>organized <u>formal education and</u>, more generally, <u>the state, is not predicated upon a recognition that the human being is susceptible to suffering or that the state’s reason for being should be to care for people.</u> If caring for its inhabitants were the basic purpose of the civil state, then there would be no need to fight for this recognition. Is it any wonder that the education of the ordinary child is mainly training for a far-off, abstract future that is destined to be better than life at present? Why must school be about overcoming anything? <u><mark>We talk about <strong>equipping</strong> children and adults to <strong>“solve problems.”</mark> </strong>Yet, <strong>problems do not fall from the sky</strong>; they do not exist as such until a human being gives them a name</u>. <u>In contrast, the concept of contention suggests that <mark>the practical role of reason should be used to understand </mark>the human <mark>being as subject to suffering and to act accordingly as moral agents</mark>.</u> <u>That is</u> <u><strong>very different</strong> from an educational philosophy, policy, and practice that views reason as an instrument by which to overcome obstacles and to conform to the social order</u>. It may be argued that modern education is about reason, about how to think and live reasonably and, therefore, how to live well and to care for oneself and for others. Yet <u>it is commonly expressed that we live in a “complex world</u>” and that children and adults <u>must “learn how to learn,” in order to “succeed in a world of rapid change.”</u> The question that needs to be asked is: Why should a person have to? In effect, education expects the human being to have an unlimited ability to think and act with reason sufficient to cope with increasingly complex situations that require individual intellect to adequately recognize, evaluate, and prioritize alternative courses of action, consider their consequences, and make good decisions. For the most part, the increasing complexity of civil society and the multiplicity of factors that intellect is expected to deal with in different situations are not questioned in education. Is this what education is rightly about? Education is as much about the use of intelligence to avoid suffering and feelings of limitation and about fending off feelings of fear as it is about learning. It is about acting upon other people and upon the civil order to deal with perceived threats. <u><strong>One must be an “active learner” or else</u></strong>. <u>Why?</u> <u>The individual must be acted upon and rendered into an entity that engages reality in the ways that are deemed just by many educators, lawmakers, and others with a <strong>stake in the perpetuation of the given social order</strong>.</u> Thus, the individual is exhorted to “do your best,” “make an effort,” “earn a grade,” “be motivated,” “work hard,” “overcome obstacles,” “achieve.” Why should education be about any of these things? Unfortunately, the culture of scholarship is thoroughly consistent with these precepts. When we question them, we challenge the ends that they serve but not the ideas themselves. We believe that education is rightly about improvement. <u>This philosophy of improvement is not necessarily consistent with enhancement of living. It often has the opposite effect</u>. How is this result justified? Certainly, it can feel good to accomplish something or to overcome obstacles. Does that mean that adversity should be a positive value of the civil state? <u>The modern idea</u>, beginning with Descartes and established through Lockean empiricism ~and made pedagogic by Rousseau’s Emile!, <u>that anyone can be rational leads quickly to the idea that everyone is <strong>responsible for being wholly rational</strong>, as that word is understood according to the social order. The perpetuation of the given social order in education as elsewhere is about gaining advantage and retaining power</u>. <u>It is about cultural politics and about marginalization of various groups and about class and about socializing children to believe in capitalism as if it is a natural law.</u> Yet under the analysis that I have made here, <u>these major problems are symptoms of something more <strong>basic</u></strong>. The more basic problem that I have emphasized here is inextricable from the problem of the just civil state. <u>It is about the intense pressures on people to think and act in ways that serve broader interests that are <strong>not at all concerned with their well-being</strong> in a variety of contexts including psychological, social, economic, political, and cultural</u>. <u>It is no answer to ground pedagogy in the notion of “building community.” The idea that something must be built implies that something must be made better in order for it to be tolerated.</u> Moreover, “<u>community” carries with it the prerequisite that one be made competent to be a member</u>— again, the presumption that something must be done to the person to make it better in some way. I do not mean to say that educators have bad intent. I do mean that <u><mark>this ethos of betterment through competency will <strong>inevitably fail</strong> </mark>to fulfill the dreams of reformers and revolutionaries.</u> <u><mark>It does not consider the human being as an entity to care for but rather as something to be</mark> <strong><mark>equipped with skills and knowledge </strong></mark>in order to improve itself. This failure is not only because there are <strong>millions</strong> of children and adults that <strong>live in poverty in the wealthiest countries in human history</strong>. It is because <mark>the state of mind that can tolerate </mark>such <mark>suffering is the <strong>same state</strong> that advances and maintains the <strong>ethos of civility as betterment</strong></mark>, rather than civility as <strong>caring for people</strong> because they are subject to suffering.</u> <u>The alternative</u> that I have only introduced in a very abbreviated way under the rubric that I called “contention” is intended to be pragmatic in the ways that Foucault and Richard Rorty are pragmatic in their respective approaches to the subject of the state.49 It <u>is intended to address an <strong>unacceptable state of contemporary Western civilization</strong>, namely, its repetitive and even escalating incidence of disregard for suffering and harm in many forms, <strong>despite</strong> intellectual, social, medical, legal, educational, scientific, and technological <strong>“progress.”</strong> We have had two hundred years of modern educational principles, and two hundred years of profound suffering along with them</u>. <u>The problem of the individual calls for a new formulation and for a proper response</u>—<u>one that cares for the individual rather than makes it competent. <strong>The “modern project” of betterment through competency and opportunity must be challenged and replaced by an emotionally intelligent ethos that expressly and fundamentally acknowledges suffering and limitation in philosophy, policy, and practice</strong>.</p></u>
T
null
null
134,537
27
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,988
CP solves
Crago 14 (their author)
Crago 14 (their author)
(Anna-Louise. "“Bitches Killing the Nation”: Analyzing the Violent State-Sponsored Repression of Sex Workers in Zambia, 2004–2008." Signs 40.1 (2014). 374) In Zambia repression did not make sex workers disappear through displacement. they disappeared as people behind bodies that were increasingly made visible as sites of punishment and control— enactments of evicting sex work and HIV (as they became collapsed) from the national body. repression had transnational and national value for the Zambian government: , it aligned Zambia with the anti–sex work positions of US funders Zambia became a major recipient of funding through the United States’ PEPFAR The US government made clear its opposition to sex work through its requirement that grantees sign an antiprostitution pledge PEPFAR prioritized abstinence and fidelity as the approach to HIV prevention US officials attempted to pressure UNAIDS to follow PEPFAR’s lead in emphasizing reducing sex work rather than simply reducing HIV. Thus it is clear that Zambia’s efforts to reduce sex work in order to reduce HIV were in alignment with the position of its largest funder. Zambia’s dependency on US aid made it particularly vulnerable to pressure from another American foreign policy tool. Trafficking In Persons Report grades countries according to their performance in fighting trafficking. takes an antiprostitution approach that conflates sex work with trafficking and seeks a repressive approach to the sex trade. “Governments get the clear message that brothel raids and more stringent anti-prostitution laws please the U.S. government” increased repression of sex workers often follows a drop in a country’s grading after which the grade improves The repression of sex workers that took place through arrest and police violence, and officials’ statements blaming sex workers for HIV, were very public enactments of state action against the epidemic. This repression simultaneously positioned blame for the population’s sufferings squarely on sex workers’ shoulders and directed it away from the almost two decades of the president’s party’s intractable passivity in addressing the epidemic. It may well be that a similar period of repression would have occurred without the pressures from the US government simply because of domestic incentives for various actors however, both US and Zambian policy made repressing sex workers a strategy that produced political and economic value.
Zambia became a major recipient of funding through the United States’ PEPFAR The US government made clear its opposition to sex work through its requirement that grantees sign an antiprostitution pledge PEPFAR prioritized abstinence and fidelity as the approach to HIV prevention US officials attempted to pressure to follow PEPFAR’s lead in emphasizing reducing sex work rather than simply reducing HIV Trafficking In Persons Report rades countries according to their performance in fighting trafficking takes an antiprostitution approach that conflates sex work with trafficking and seeks a repressive approach to the sex trade Governments get the clear message that brothel raids and more stringent anti-prostitution laws please the U.S. government It may well be that a similar period of repression would have occurred without the pressures from the US government simply because of domestic incentives for various actors
Trudeau Foundation, PhD in Anthropology (Anna-Louise. "“Bitches Killing the Nation”: Analyzing the Violent State-Sponsored Repression of Sex Workers in Zambia, 2004–2008." Signs 40.1 (2014). 374) Melissa W. Wright 2004 has stated that efforts to “disappear” ð370Þ sex workers from public space are attempts by states to generate political and economic value. In Zambia repression did not make sex workers disappear through displacement. Rather, they disappeared as people behind bodies that were increasingly made visible as sites of punishment and control— enactments of evicting sex work and HIV (as they became collapsed) from the national body. As such, repression had transnational and national value for the Zambian government: transnationally, it aligned Zambia with the anti–sex work positions of US funders on whom it became largely dependent in 2004; domestically, it reinforced the government’s moral authority. In 2003, Zambia became a major recipient of funding through the United States’ President’s Emergency Plan for Aids Relief ðPEPFARÞ, receiving $544 million between 2003 and 2007 ðPatterson 2006Þ. Though much of this money was channeled through nongovernmental organizations ðNGOsÞ, the Zambian National Aids Council and Central Board of Health also were grantees ðPEPFAR 2005Þ. The US government made clear its opposition to sex work through its requirement that grantees sign an antiprostitution pledge ðCenter for Health and Gender Equity 2008Þ. Furthermore, PEPFAR prioritized abstinence and fidelity as the approach to HIV prevention. At the 2004 International AIDS Conference, the US government held up Uganda as the model pupil for this approach ðDe Vries 2004Þ. In the process, PEPFAR reinvigorated aging Ugandan dictator Yoweni Kaguta Musevini’s lease on power. Despite PEPFAR’s framing of sex workers primarily as victims, Uganda’s much celebrated abstinence and fidelity policy was implemented in part through local councils that enforced the policy by instigating physical attacks against young women who went to bars ðcommonly sex-work venuesÞ or were considered to be sexually misbehaving ðDe Waal 2006Þ. The strength of the United States’ desire to reduce sex work globally through HIV policy was unbowed by such details. In 2006, flying in the face of proper UN protocol, US officials attempted to pressure UNAIDS to follow PEPFAR’s lead in emphasizing reducing sex work rather than simply reducing HIV. Thus it is clear that Zambia’s efforts to reduce sex work in order to reduce HIV were in alignment with the position of its largest funder. More importantly, however, Zambia’s dependency on US aid made it particularly vulnerable to pressure from another American foreign policy tool. The “Trafficking In Persons ðTIPÞ Report” was inaugurated as the cornerstone of George W. Bush’s transnational campaign against the “special evil” of trafficking ðSoderlund 2005, 77Þ. The report grades countries according to their performance in fighting trafficking. The report, true to the combined influence of carceral feminists and evangelical militarized humanitarians ðBernstein 2010Þ, takes an antiprostitution approach that conflates sex work with trafficking and seeks a repressive approach to the sex trade. Countries are sorted into four tiers—in descending order, Tier 1, Tier 2, Tier 2 Watch List, and Tier 3. Countries in Tier 3 face economic sanctions: the United States withholds aid and opposes the provision of assistance from the International Monetary Fund or World Bank ðexceptions are made for humanitarian, trade-related, and certain development-related aid; US Department of State 2008Þ. According to research on Asia conducted by the Center for Health and Gender Equity ð2008Þ, “Governments get the clear message that brothel raids and more stringent anti-prostitution laws please the U.S. government” ð5Þ. Research on the impact of the TIP report in Thailand, Cambodia, and Vietnam found that increased repression of sex workers often follows a drop in a country’s grading, after which the grade improves.15 Poor placement in the TIP report has led Cambodia, Korea, and Guatemala to introduce more repressive legislation against sex work ðKim 2007; Human Rights Watch 2010; AMARC ALC 2011Þ and to instigate large-scale campaigns of raids and other repressive tactics against sex workers. 16 In 2004, Zambia was placed on the Tier 2 Watch List. Following the United States’ reprimand that it was not doing enough to stop child pros went to bars ðcommonly sex-work venuesÞ or were considered to be sexually misbehaving ðDe Waal 2006Þ. The strength of the United States’ desire to reduce sex work globally through HIV policy was unbowed by such details. In 2006, flying in the face of proper UN protocol, US officials attempted to pressure UNAIDS to follow PEPFAR’s lead in emphasizing reducing sex work rather than simply reducing HIV. Thus it is clear that Zambia’s efforts to reduce sex work in order to reduce HIV were in alignment with the position of its largest funder. More importantly, however, Zambia’s dependency on US aid made it particularly vulnerable to pressure from another American foreign policy tool. The “Trafficking In Persons ðTIPÞ Report” was inaugurated as the cornerstone of George W. Bush’s transnational campaign against the “special evil” of trafficking ðSoderlund 2005, 77Þ. The report grades countries according to their performance in fighting trafficking. The report, true to the combined influence of carceral feminists and evangelical militarized humanitarians ðBernstein 2010Þ, takes an antiprostitution approach that conflates sex work with trafficking and seeks a repressive approach to the sex trade. Countries are sorted into four tiers—in descending order, Tier 1, Tier 2, Tier 2 Watch List, and Tier 3. Countries in Tier 3 face economic sanctions: the United States withholds aid and opposes the provision of assistance from the International Monetary Fund or World Bank ðexceptions are made for humanitarian, trade-related, and certain development-related aid; US Department of State 2008Þ. According to research on Asia conducted by the Center for Health and Gender Equity ð2008Þ, “Governments get the clear message that brothel raids and more stringent anti-prostitution laws please the U.S. government” ð5Þ. Research on the impact of the TIP report in Thailand, Cambodia, and Vietnam found that increased repression of sex workers often follows a drop in a country’s grading, after which the grade improves.15 Poor placement in the TIP report has led Cambodia, Korea, and Guatemala to introduce more repressive legislation against sex work ðKim 2007; Human Rights Watch 2010; AMARC ALC 2011Þ and to instigate large-scale campaigns of raids and other repressive tactics against sex workers. 16 In 2004, Zambia was placed on the Tier 2 Watch List. Following the United States’ reprimand that it was not doing enough to stop child pros a punitive approach to sex work and its National HIV/AIDS/STI/TB Policy, rather than creating an obstacle, was compatible with repression due to its endorsement of the need to stop women engaging in sex work through both a prohibitionist and abolitionist logic ðMinistry of Health 2005Þ. From the vantage point of 2004, scapegoating sex workers offered great value in reinforcing the government’s moral authority to rule. It overlapped with and helped justify the curfew legislation and in so doing accorded President Levy Mwanawasa far greater control over his population as a whole. It also allowed the president to deflect criticisms of his ability to lead by asserting himself as capable of protecting citizens from crime and HIV. This was all the more important since 2004 coincided with Mwanawasa’s declaration that HIV was a national crisis, the first time in Zambian history that a president had made such a statement. The repression of sex workers that took place through arrest and police violence, and officials’ statements blaming sex workers for HIV, were very public enactments of state action against the epidemic. This repression simultaneously positioned blame for the population’s sufferings squarely on sex workers’ shoulders and directed it away from the almost two decades of the president’s party’s intractable passivity in addressing the epidemic. It may well be that a similar period of repression would have occurred without the pressures from the US government simply because of domestic incentives for various actors. As it was, however, both US and Zambian policy made repressing sex workers a strategy that produced political and economic value.
8,602
<h4><u><strong>CP solves </h4><p>Crago 14 (their author)</p><p></u></strong> Trudeau Foundation, PhD in Anthropology</p><p><u>(Anna-Louise. "“Bitches Killing the Nation”: Analyzing the Violent State-Sponsored Repression of Sex Workers in Zambia, 2004–2008." Signs 40.1 (2014). 374)</p><p></u>Melissa W. Wright 2004 has stated that efforts to “disappear” ð370Þ sex workers from public space are attempts by states to generate political and economic value. <u>In Zambia repression did not make sex workers disappear through displacement.</u> Rather, <u>they disappeared as people behind bodies that were increasingly made visible as sites of punishment and control— enactments of evicting sex work and HIV (as they became collapsed) from the national body.</u> As such, <u>repression had transnational and national value for the Zambian government: </u>transnationally<u>, it aligned Zambia with the anti–sex work positions of US funders </u>on whom it became largely dependent in 2004; domestically, it reinforced the government’s moral authority. In 2003, <u><mark>Zambia became a major recipient of funding through the United States’</u></mark> President’s Emergency Plan for Aids Relief ð<u><mark>PEPFAR</u></mark>Þ, receiving $544 million between 2003 and 2007 ðPatterson 2006Þ. Though much of this money was channeled through nongovernmental organizations ðNGOsÞ, the Zambian National Aids Council and Central Board of Health also were grantees ðPEPFAR 2005Þ. <u><mark>The US government made clear its opposition to sex work through its</mark> <mark>requirement that grantees sign an antiprostitution pledge</u></mark> ðCenter for Health and Gender Equity 2008Þ. Furthermore, <u><mark>PEPFAR prioritized abstinence and fidelity as the approach to HIV prevention</u></mark>. At the 2004 International AIDS Conference, the US government held up Uganda as the model pupil for this approach ðDe Vries 2004Þ. In the process, PEPFAR reinvigorated aging Ugandan dictator Yoweni Kaguta Musevini’s lease on power. Despite PEPFAR’s framing of sex workers primarily as victims, Uganda’s much celebrated abstinence and fidelity policy was implemented in part through local councils that enforced the policy by instigating physical attacks against young women who went to bars ðcommonly sex-work venuesÞ or were considered to be sexually misbehaving ðDe Waal 2006Þ. The strength of the United States’ desire to reduce sex work globally through HIV policy was unbowed by such details. In 2006, flying in the face of proper UN protocol, <u><mark>US officials attempted to pressure</mark> UNAIDS <mark>to follow PEPFAR’s lead in emphasizing reducing sex work rather than simply reducing HIV</mark>.</u> <u>Thus it is clear that Zambia’s efforts to reduce sex work in order to reduce HIV were in alignment with the position of its largest funder. </u>More importantly, however, <u>Zambia’s dependency on US aid made it particularly vulnerable to pressure from another American foreign policy tool.</u> The “<u><mark>Trafficking In Persons</u></mark> ðTIPÞ <u><mark>Report</u></mark>” was inaugurated as the cornerstone of George W. Bush’s transnational campaign against the “special evil” of trafficking ðSoderlund 2005, 77Þ. The report <u>g<mark>rades countries according to their performance in fighting trafficking</mark>.</u> The report, true to the combined influence of carceral feminists and evangelical militarized humanitarians ðBernstein 2010Þ, <u><mark>takes an antiprostitution approach that conflates sex work with trafficking and seeks a repressive approach to the sex trade</mark>.</u> Countries are sorted into four tiers—in descending order, Tier 1, Tier 2, Tier 2 Watch List, and Tier 3. Countries in Tier 3 face economic sanctions: the United States withholds aid and opposes the provision of assistance from the International Monetary Fund or World Bank ðexceptions are made for humanitarian, trade-related, and certain development-related aid; US Department of State 2008Þ. According to research on Asia conducted by the Center for Health and Gender Equity ð2008Þ, <u>“<mark>Governments get the clear message that <strong>brothel raids</strong> and more <strong>stringent anti-prostitution laws please the U.S. government</strong></mark>”</u> ð5Þ. Research on the impact of the TIP report in Thailand, Cambodia, and Vietnam found that <u>increased repression of sex workers often follows a drop in a country’s grading</u>, <u>after which the grade improves</u>.15 Poor placement in the TIP report has led Cambodia, Korea, and Guatemala to introduce more repressive legislation against sex work ðKim 2007; Human Rights Watch 2010; AMARC ALC 2011Þ and to instigate large-scale campaigns of raids and other repressive tactics against sex workers. 16 In 2004, Zambia was placed on the Tier 2 Watch List. Following the United States’ reprimand that it was not doing enough to stop child pros went to bars ðcommonly sex-work venuesÞ or were considered to be sexually misbehaving ðDe Waal 2006Þ. The strength of the United States’ desire to reduce sex work globally through HIV policy was unbowed by such details. In 2006, flying in the face of proper UN protocol, US officials attempted to pressure UNAIDS to follow PEPFAR’s lead in emphasizing reducing sex work rather than simply reducing HIV. Thus it is clear that Zambia’s efforts to reduce sex work in order to reduce HIV were in alignment with the position of its largest funder. More importantly, however, Zambia’s dependency on US aid made it particularly vulnerable to pressure from another American foreign policy tool. The “Trafficking In Persons ðTIPÞ Report” was inaugurated as the cornerstone of George W. Bush’s transnational campaign against the “special evil” of trafficking ðSoderlund 2005, 77Þ. The report grades countries according to their performance in fighting trafficking. The report, true to the combined influence of carceral feminists and evangelical militarized humanitarians ðBernstein 2010Þ, takes an antiprostitution approach that conflates sex work with trafficking and seeks a repressive approach to the sex trade. Countries are sorted into four tiers—in descending order, Tier 1, Tier 2, Tier 2 Watch List, and Tier 3. Countries in Tier 3 face economic sanctions: the United States withholds aid and opposes the provision of assistance from the International Monetary Fund or World Bank ðexceptions are made for humanitarian, trade-related, and certain development-related aid; US Department of State 2008Þ. According to research on Asia conducted by the Center for Health and Gender Equity ð2008Þ, “Governments get the clear message that brothel raids and more stringent anti-prostitution laws please the U.S. government” ð5Þ. Research on the impact of the TIP report in Thailand, Cambodia, and Vietnam found that increased repression of sex workers often follows a drop in a country’s grading, after which the grade improves.15 Poor placement in the TIP report has led Cambodia, Korea, and Guatemala to introduce more repressive legislation against sex work ðKim 2007; Human Rights Watch 2010; AMARC ALC 2011Þ and to instigate large-scale campaigns of raids and other repressive tactics against sex workers. 16 In 2004, Zambia was placed on the Tier 2 Watch List. Following the United States’ reprimand that it was not doing enough to stop child pros a punitive approach to sex work and its National HIV/AIDS/STI/TB Policy, rather than creating an obstacle, was compatible with repression due to its endorsement of the need to stop women engaging in sex work through both a prohibitionist and abolitionist logic ðMinistry of Health 2005Þ. From the vantage point of 2004, scapegoating sex workers offered great value in reinforcing the government’s moral authority to rule. It overlapped with and helped justify the curfew legislation and in so doing accorded President Levy Mwanawasa far greater control over his population as a whole. It also allowed the president to deflect criticisms of his ability to lead by asserting himself as capable of protecting citizens from crime and HIV. This was all the more important since 2004 coincided with Mwanawasa’s declaration that HIV was a national crisis, the first time in Zambian history that a president had made such a statement. <u>The repression of sex workers that took place through arrest and police violence, and officials’ statements blaming sex workers for HIV, were very public enactments of state action against the epidemic. This repression simultaneously positioned blame for the population’s sufferings squarely on sex workers’ shoulders and directed it away from the almost two decades of the president’s party’s intractable passivity in addressing the epidemic.</u> <u><mark>It may well be that a similar period of repression would have occurred without the pressures from the US government simply because of domestic incentives for various actors</u></mark>. As it was, <u>however, both US and Zambian policy made repressing sex workers a strategy that produced political and economic value.</p></u>
1NC
null
Off
191,042
4
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,989
Consumption DA: The idea that subjects should be maximally reciprocal destroys the possibility for individual value
Robinson 12
Robinson 12
Baudrillard sees communication and sociality being corrupted into sign-values to be consumed. The loss of genuine, spontaneous, reciprocal human relations is covered up by the standardised production of signs of social warmth and participation. it simulates intimacy. These simulated signs are what now counts as abstract ‘interpersonal skills’. such false sociality is shot through with the flaws of the mode of production, including aggression and frustration. It turns into an entire value-system dressed-up as functionality. It has a constant repressive effect, pacifying social relations. The act of conforming to a model is presented as narcissistic self-assertion through small signified differences. People think they are creating themselves when in fact they are consuming themselves femininity and masculinity are models which govern, rather than express, women and men such models shape how people see each other People set up signs of happiness in the hope that happiness will alight on them. There is a ‘fun system’ of enforced enjoyment, which imposes a duty to happiness and denies any right not to be happy. Consumption is a institution and a system of values with functions of social integration and control. The anarchic consumer is a thing of the past. People are pressured to consume in standard ways this pressure destroys enjoyment from the inside. Consumption is haunted by its inner puritanism, rendering it compulsive and limitless. At the same time as socialising people, it atomises people into private consumption. They mark conformity with the code, not individuality. The system is based on abolishing real difference so as to usher in a process of differentiation Excessive social contact due to urbanism leads to psychological pauperisation. People gain an increased need for objects as signifiers of differentiation Consumption excludes the possibility of enjoyment. because consumption is always collective whereas enjoyment is personal. The disappearance of altruistic forms of integration leads to an expanded role for state repression. Atomisation leads to bureaucratic control, disguised as freedom. The ‘people’ are glorified as long as they do not try to exercise their putative sovereignty on a political or social stage, and instead stick to consuming. Competition leads to generalised fatigue Such fatigue is really a resistance, akin to a slowdown by workers or boredom in school. Such resistance becomes habitual and ‘grows into’ people’s It is a partial revolt necessary to prevent total breakdown, which is instantly available as a source of discontent in crisis situations. The real social effect of the pursuit of system-promoted goals is an exhausting rat-race. The system of unstable, precarious employment creates generalised insecurity and generalised competition for status. The constant treadmill of work leaves some on the scrapheap and others successful but exhausted. the ideology of consumption lulls people into believing that they are affluent, fulfilled, happy and liberated. Baudrillard writes of the production of a new kind of character-armoured subject: the sociometric individual. Sociability is mis-perceived as something personal, while being rendered simply functional. Instead of being autonomous, people display marks of ‘personalisation’. A person transformed is at home everywhere and nowhere – able to display superficial intimacy, but belonging nowhere. Rather than conformity, the system demands of such people that they be maximally sociable and maximally compatible with others across a wide range of situations. Such people are part of an enforced mobilisation, always available as calculable and accountable units for use in political and sociometric planning. They become psychologically dependent on gaining approval, and lose individual transcendental aspirations. This leads to a new social morality. Ideology and individual values are replaced relativity, receptivity, agreement and anxious communication, all of which render people programmable. Baudrillard’s critique extends to politics. The contradiction between ‘services’ and democratic ideology leads to an entire simulation of absent reciprocity. A superficial layer of minimal communication is used to paper over the hostility and social distance which are everywhere. This layer is ‘functional’ enough to personalise and pacify power, but is stripped of every affective and psychological aspect. People can demand signs of sociability and sincerity. But the signs only reproduce the mistrust. They have become empty signs in a closed system, which no longer convey real trust.
The loss of genuine relations is covered up by signs of participation. These simulated signs now count as skills It has a constant repressive effect, pacifying social relations. People think they are creating themselves when they are consuming themselves such models shape how people see each other There is a ‘fun system’ of enforced enjoyment, which imposes a duty to happiness and denies any right not to be happy. Consumption is social control. it atomises people into private consumption They mark conformity with the code, not individuality. Atomisation leads to bureaucratic control, disguised as freedom. people’ are glorified as long as they do not try to exercise their sovereignty and consum Competition leads to fatigue The treadmill of work lulls people into believing that they are liberated. A person transformed is at home everywhere and nowhere but belonging nowhere. individual values are replaced which render people programmable. The contradiction between democratic ideology leads to an simulation of absent reciprocity. A superficial layer of minimal communication is used to paper over the hostility and social distance everywhere
(Andrew, Political Theorist, Activist Based in the UK and research fellow affiliated to the Centre for the Study of Social and Global Justice (CSSGJ), University of Nottingham, April 14, 2012, “Jean Baudrillard: Critique of Alienation – Draft 1,” http://ceasefiremagazine.co.uk/in-theory-baudrillard-3/ Baudrillard also sees communication and sociality being corrupted into sign-values to be consumed. This occurs through the consumption of ‘services’ based on sociability. The loss of genuine, spontaneous, reciprocal human relations (which require a symbolic dimension) is covered up by the standardised production of signs of social warmth and participation. As with the smile of the salesman, receptionist or PR executive, or the “have a nice day” of McDonald’s, it simulates intimacy. These simulated signs are what now counts as abstract ‘interpersonal skills’. In practice, Baudrillard observes, such false sociality is shot through with the flaws of the mode of production, including aggression and frustration. It turns into an entire value-system dressed-up as functionality. It has a constant repressive effect, pacifying social relations. The act of conforming to a model is presented as narcissistic self-assertion through small signified differences. People think they are creating themselves when in fact they are consuming themselves, or their images. For example, femininity and masculinity are models which govern, rather than express, women and men. Baudrillard believes that such models shape how people see each other, regardless of whether people actually conform to them. Similarly, sites such as holiday resorts are constructed as planned communities and total environments realising a particular ideal of abstract happiness. These sites replace distinct elements with homogeneous ones. People set up signs of happiness in the hope that happiness will alight on them. There is a ‘fun system’ of enforced enjoyment, which imposes a duty (not a right) to happiness and denies any right not to be happy. Consumption is a morality, an institution and a system of values with functions of social integration and control. The anarchic consumer, free to consume or not, is a thing of the past. People are now pressured to consume in standard ways and even to seek out new experiences. Yet this pressure destroys enjoyment from the inside. Consumption is haunted by its inner puritanism, rendering it compulsive and limitless. It is both lived as an affirmative myth, and endured as a kind of social adaptation to a new collective regime. At the same time as socialising people, it atomises people into private consumption. Beauty products and the like often claim to be drawing out an inherent personality, or recovering one which has been lost. In fact they are products of the industrial mass-production of systematic differences. These differences are derived from a model and are only artificially diversified. They mark conformity with the code, not individuality. Baudrillard writes of ‘monopoly concentration of the production of differences’. The system is based on abolishing real difference (and for instance nature) so as to usher in a process of differentiation (and naturalisation, etc). Difference within the code is based on the smallest marginal difference, used as a sign of hierarchy. Excessive social contact due to urbanism leads to psychological pauperisation. People gain an increased need for objects as signifiers of differentiation. Consumption actually excludes the possibility of enjoyment. This is because consumption is always collective, at least indirectly, whereas enjoyment is personal. The disappearance of altruistic forms of integration leads to an expanded role for state repression. Atomisation leads to bureaucratic control, disguised as freedom. Credit is used to condition people into capitalistic forms of action. The ‘people’ or consumers are glorified as long as they do not try to exercise their putative sovereignty on a political or social stage, and instead stick to consuming. Consumer goods are experienced as miraculous, because their production is concealed. They seem as if they come from technology, progress or growth. In fact we have only the signs of affluence, coexisting with ever more impoverished social relations. Competition, generalised across social life as consumption as well as production is ranked, leads to generalised fatigue. Such fatigue is really a resistance, akin to a slowdown by workers or boredom in school. Such resistance, as the only resistance available, becomes habitual and ‘grows into’ people’s bodies. It is a partial revolt necessary to prevent total breakdown, which is also instantly available as a source of discontent in crisis situations. The real social effect of the pursuit of system-promoted goals is an exhausting rat-race. The system of unstable, precarious employment creates generalised insecurity and generalised competition for status. The constant treadmill of work, retraining and status-competition leaves some on the scrapheap and others successful but exhausted. But the ideology of consumption lulls people into believing that they are affluent, fulfilled, happy and liberated. Baudrillard writes of the production of a new kind of character-armoured subject: the sociometric individual. Sociability is mis-perceived as something personal, while in fact being rendered simply functional. Instead of being autonomous, people display marks of ‘personalisation’. A person thus transformed is at home everywhere and nowhere – able to display superficial intimacy, but belonging nowhere. Social action is subordinated to the pursuit of status. Rather than conformity, the system demands of such people that they be maximally sociable and maximally compatible with others across a wide range of situations. Such people are part of an enforced mobilisation, always available as calculable and accountable units for use in political and sociometric planning. They become psychologically dependent on gaining approval, and lose individual transcendental aspirations. This in turn leads to a new social morality. Ideology and individual values are replaced in this morality with relativity, receptivity, agreement and anxious communication, all of which render people programmable. Baudrillard’s critique also extends to politics. The contradiction between ‘services’ and democratic ideology leads to an entire simulation of absent reciprocity. A superficial layer of minimal communication is used to paper over the hostility and social distance which are everywhere. This layer is ‘functional’ enough to personalise and pacify power, but is stripped of every affective and psychological aspect. Instead it is constructed from the calculated model of an ideal relationship. People can no longer trust themselves or each other. It is for this reason that they demand signs of sociability and sincerity. But the signs only reproduce the mistrust. They have become empty signs in a closed system, which no longer convey real trust. The welfare state is criticised as a way to portray an exchange society as if it were a service society, giving back what it takes from workers. Equality and democracy conceal the real system of discrimination, based on whether or not one can decode consumer goods. Furthermore, the system conditions people to constantly want a little more than they have. The system produces the needs it satisfies (through advertising and demand management), produces only for its own needs, and hides behind the alibi of individual needs (inventing an idea of economic man to prop itself up). It rests on real needs being misrecognised. And it produces needs which it then refuses to satisfy, instead using them as inducements to conformity.
7,778
<h4><u>Consumption DA</u>: The idea that subjects should be maximally reciprocal destroys the possibility for individual value</h4><p><u><strong>Robinson 12</u></strong> </p><p>(Andrew, Political Theorist, Activist Based in the UK and research fellow affiliated to the Centre for the Study of Social and Global Justice (CSSGJ), University of Nottingham, April 14, 2012, “Jean Baudrillard: Critique of Alienation – Draft 1,” http://ceasefiremagazine.co.uk/in-theory-baudrillard-3/</p><p><u>Baudrillard</u> also <u>sees communication and sociality being corrupted into sign-values to be consumed. </u> This occurs through the consumption of ‘services’ based on sociability. <u><mark>The loss of genuine</mark>, spontaneous, reciprocal human <mark>relations</u></mark> (which require a symbolic dimension) <u><mark>is covered up by</mark> the standardised production of <mark>signs of <strong></mark>social warmth and <mark>participation.</u></strong></mark> As with the smile of the salesman, receptionist or PR executive, or the “have a nice day” of McDonald’s, <u>it simulates intimacy.</u> <u><strong><mark>These simulated signs</mark> are what <mark>now count</mark>s <mark>as</mark> abstract ‘interpersonal <mark>skills</mark>’.</u></strong> In practice, Baudrillard observes, <u>such false sociality is shot through with the flaws of the mode of production, including aggression and frustration.</u> <u>It turns into an entire value-system dressed-up as functionality. <strong><mark>It has a constant repressive effect, pacifying social relations.</u></strong></mark> <u>The act of conforming to a model is presented as narcissistic self-assertion through small signified differences.</u> <u><mark>People think they are creating themselves when </mark>in fact <mark>they are consuming themselves</u></mark>, or their images. For example, <u>femininity and masculinity are models which govern, rather than express, women and men</u>. Baudrillard believes that <u><strong><mark>such models shape how people see each other</u></strong></mark>, regardless of whether people actually conform to them. Similarly, sites such as holiday resorts are constructed as planned communities and total environments realising a particular ideal of abstract happiness. These sites replace distinct elements with homogeneous ones. <u>People set up signs of happiness in the hope that happiness will alight on them.</u> <u><strong><mark>There is a ‘fun system’ of enforced enjoyment, which imposes a duty</u></strong></mark> (not a right) <u><strong><mark>to happiness and denies any right not to be happy.</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>Consumption is</mark> a</u> morality, an <u>institution and a system of values with functions of <mark>social </mark>integration and <mark>control.</u></mark> <u>The anarchic consumer</u>, free to consume or not, <u>is a thing of the past.</u> <u>People are</u> now <u>pressured to consume in standard ways</u> and even to seek out new experiences. Yet <u><strong>this pressure destroys enjoyment from the inside.</u></strong> <u>Consumption is haunted by its inner puritanism, rendering it compulsive and limitless.</u> It is both lived as an affirmative myth, and endured as a kind of social adaptation to a new collective regime. <u>At the same time as socialising people, <mark>it atomises people into private consumption</mark>. </u>Beauty products and the like often claim to be drawing out an inherent personality, or recovering one which has been lost. In fact they are products of the industrial mass-production of systematic differences. These differences are derived from a model and are only artificially diversified. <u><strong><mark>They mark conformity with the code, not individuality.</u></strong></mark> Baudrillard writes of ‘monopoly concentration of the production of differences’. <u>The system is based on abolishing real difference</u> (and for instance nature) <u>so as to usher in a process of differentiation</u> (and naturalisation, etc). Difference within the code is based on the smallest marginal difference, used as a sign of hierarchy. <u>Excessive social contact due to urbanism leads to psychological pauperisation.</u> <u>People gain an increased need for objects as signifiers of differentiation</u>. <u><strong>Consumption</u></strong> actually <u><strong>excludes the possibility of enjoyment.</u></strong> This is <u>because consumption is always collective</u>, at least indirectly, <u>whereas enjoyment is personal. The disappearance of altruistic forms of integration leads to <strong>an expanded role for state repression.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>Atomisation leads to bureaucratic control, disguised as freedom.</u></strong></mark> Credit is used to condition people into capitalistic forms of action. <u>The ‘<mark>people’</u></mark> or consumers <u><mark>are glorified as long as they do not try to exercise their</mark> putative <mark>sovereignty</mark> on a political or social stage, <strong><mark>and </mark>instead stick to <mark>consum</mark>ing.</u></strong> Consumer goods are experienced as miraculous, because their production is concealed. They seem as if they come from technology, progress or growth. In fact we have only the signs of affluence, coexisting with ever more impoverished social relations. <u><mark>Competition</u></mark>, generalised across social life as consumption as well as production is ranked, <u><mark>leads to</mark> generalised <mark>fatigue</u></mark>. <u>Such fatigue is really a resistance, akin to a slowdown by workers or boredom in school.</u> <u>Such resistance</u>, as the only resistance available, <u>becomes habitual and ‘grows into’ people’s</u> bodies. <u>It is a partial revolt necessary to prevent total breakdown, which is </u>also <u>instantly available as a source of discontent in crisis situations. <strong>The real social effect of the pursuit of system-promoted goals is an exhausting rat-race.</u></strong> <u>The system of unstable, precarious employment creates generalised insecurity and generalised competition for status.</u> <u><strong><mark>The </mark>constant <mark>treadmill of work</u></strong></mark>, retraining and status-competition <u>leaves some on the scrapheap and others successful but exhausted.</u> But <u><strong>the ideology of consumption <mark>lulls people into believing that they are</mark> affluent, fulfilled, happy and <mark>liberated.</u></strong></mark> <u>Baudrillard writes of the production of a new kind of character-armoured subject: the sociometric individual.</u> <u>Sociability is mis-perceived as something personal, while</u> in fact <u>being rendered simply functional. Instead of being autonomous, people display marks of ‘personalisation’. <mark>A person</u></mark> thus <u><mark>transformed is at home everywhere and nowhere </mark>– able to display superficial intimacy, <strong><mark>but belonging nowhere.</u></strong></mark> Social action is subordinated to the pursuit of status. <u>Rather than conformity, the system demands of such people that they be maximally sociable and maximally compatible with others <strong>across a wide range of situations.</u></strong> <u>Such people are part of an enforced mobilisation, always available as calculable and accountable units for use in political and sociometric planning.</u> <u><strong>They become psychologically dependent on gaining approval, and lose individual transcendental aspirations.</u></strong> <u>This</u> in turn <u>leads to a new social morality.</u> <u>Ideology and <mark>individual values are replaced</mark> </u>in this morality with <u>relativity, receptivity, agreement and anxious communication, <strong>all of <mark>which render people programmable.</mark> Baudrillard’s critique</u></strong> also <u><strong>extends to politics.</u></strong> <u><mark>The contradiction between </mark>‘services’ and <mark>democratic ideology leads to an </mark>entire <mark>simulation of absent reciprocity. A superficial layer of minimal communication is used to paper over the hostility and social distance</mark> which are <mark>everywhere</mark>. This layer is ‘functional’ enough to personalise and pacify power, but is stripped of every affective and psychological aspect.</u> Instead it is constructed from the calculated model of an ideal relationship. <u>People</u> <u>can</u> no longer trust themselves or each other. It is for this reason that they <u>demand signs of sociability and sincerity. <strong>But the signs only reproduce the mistrust.</u></strong> <u>They have become empty signs in a closed system, which no longer convey real trust. </u>The welfare state is criticised as a way to portray an exchange society as if it were a service society, giving back what it takes from workers. Equality and democracy conceal the real system of discrimination, based on whether or not one can decode consumer goods. Furthermore, the system conditions people to constantly want a little more than they have. The system produces the needs it satisfies (through advertising and demand management), produces only for its own needs, and hides behind the alibi of individual needs (inventing an idea of economic man to prop itself up). It rests on real needs being misrecognised. And it produces needs which it then refuses to satisfy, instead using them as inducements to conformity.</p>
T
null
null
430,039
3
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,990
Heg decline will be peaceful - deductive and empirical evidence goes negative
Parent 11
Parent 11
Some argu that hegemonic transitions are conflict prone there are deductive and empirical reasons to doubt this argument. Fallen hegemons still have formidable capability, which threatens grave harm to any state that tries to cross them. they are no longer the top target for balancing coalitions, and recovering hegemons may be influential because they can play a pivotal role in alliance formation hegemonic powers possess more extensive overseas commitments; they should be able to more readily identify and eliminate extraneous burdens without exposing vulnerabilities We believe the empirical record supports these conclusions The last reversal at the pinnacle of power was the AngloAmerican transition, and was resolved without armed confrontation. Although China and the United States differ in regime type, similar factors may work to cushion the impending Sino-American transition. Both are large, relatively secure continental great powers, a fact that mitigates potential geopolitical competition
Some argu that hegemonic transitions are conflict prone there are deductive and empirical reasons to doubt this Fallen hegemons still have formidable capability, which threatens harm to any state that tries to cross them. they are no longer the top target and recovering hegemons can play a pivotal role in alliance formation. empirical record supports these conclusions the AngloAmerican transition was resolved without armed confrontation. similar factors may work to cushion the Sino-American transition.
Assistant for of pol sci, U Miami. PhD in pol sci, Columbia—and—Paul MacDonald—assistant prof of pol sci, Williams (Joseph, Graceful Decline?;The Surprising Success of Great Power Retrenchment, Intl. Security, Spring 1, p. 7) Some observers might dispute our conclusions, arguing that hegemonic transitions are more conflict prone than other moments of acute relative decline. We counter that there are deductive and empirical reasons to doubt this argument. Theoretically, hegemonic powers should actually find it easier to manage acute relative decline. Fallen hegemons still have formidable capability, which threatens grave harm to any state that tries to cross them. Further, they are no longer the top target for balancing coalitions, and recovering hegemons may be influential because they can play a pivotal role in alliance formation. In addition, hegemonic powers, almost by deªnition, possess more extensive overseas commitments; they should be able to more readily identify and eliminate extraneous burdens without exposing vulnerabilities or exciting domestic populations. We believe the empirical record supports these conclusions. In particular, periods of hegemonic transition do not appear more conºict prone than those of acute decline. The last reversal at the pinnacle of power was the AngloAmerican transition, which took place around 1872 and was resolved without armed confrontation. The tenor of that transition may have been inºuenced by a number of factors: both states were democratic maritime empires, the United States was slowly emerging from the Civil War, and Great Britain could likely coast on a large lead in domestic capital stock. Although China and the United States differ in regime type, similar factors may work to cushion the impending Sino-American transition. Both are large, relatively secure continental great powers, a fact that mitigates potential geopolitical competition. 93 China faces a variety of domestic political challenges, including strains among rival regions, which may complicate its ability to sustain its economic performance or engage in foreign policy adventurism.
2,129
<h4>Heg decline will be peaceful - deductive and empirical evidence goes negative</h4><p><u><strong>Parent 11</p><p></u></strong>Assistant for of pol sci, U Miami. PhD in pol sci, Columbia—and—Paul MacDonald—assistant prof of pol sci, Williams (Joseph, Graceful Decline?;The Surprising Success of Great Power Retrenchment, Intl. Security, Spring 1, p. 7)</p><p><u><mark>Some</u></mark> observers might dispute our conclusions, <u><mark>argu</u></mark>ing <u><mark>that hegemonic transitions are</u></mark> more <u><mark>conflict prone</u></mark> than other moments of acute relative decline. We counter that <u><mark>there are deductive and empirical reasons to doubt this</mark> argument.</u> Theoretically, hegemonic powers should actually find it easier to manage acute relative decline. <u><mark>Fallen hegemons still have formidable capability, which threatens</mark> grave <mark>harm to any state that tries to cross them.</u></mark> Further, <u><mark>they are no longer the top target</mark> for balancing coalitions, <mark>and recovering hegemons</mark> may be influential because they <mark>can play a pivotal role in alliance formation</u>.</mark> In addition, <u>hegemonic powers</u>, almost by deªnition, <u>possess more extensive overseas commitments; they should be able to more readily identify and eliminate extraneous burdens without exposing vulnerabilities</u> or exciting domestic populations. <u>We believe the <strong><mark>empirical record supports these conclusions</u></strong></mark>. In particular, periods of hegemonic transition do not appear more conºict prone than those of acute decline. <u>The last reversal at the pinnacle of power was <mark>the AngloAmerican transition</mark>,</u> which took place around 1872 <u>and <mark>was resolved without armed confrontation.</u></mark> The tenor of that transition may have been inºuenced by a number of factors: both states were democratic maritime empires, the United States was slowly emerging from the Civil War, and Great Britain could likely coast on a large lead in domestic capital stock. <u>Although China and the United States differ in regime type, <mark>similar factors may work to cushion the</mark> impending <mark>Sino-American transition.</mark> Both are large, relatively secure continental great powers, a fact that mitigates potential geopolitical competition</u>. 93 China faces a variety of domestic political challenges, including strains among rival regions, which may complicate its ability to sustain its economic performance or engage in foreign policy adventurism.</p>
1NR
Cartels
Heg
97,153
117
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,991
Clinic discrimination is an alt cause to trans HIV scenario
Brydum 13 (their author)
Brydum 13 (their author)
complicating efforts to combat HIV among transgender people is that population’s basic lack of access to medical care. The 2009 NIH study identified a number of reasons that transgender women aren’t seeking preventive health care, including limited access to low-cost care and safe, trans-inclusive medical environments, along with the incompetence of many doctors about basic transgender health care, which results in trans women feeling unsafe to disclose their HIV status. The combination of social stigma, institutional discrimination, economic hardship, and distrust of medical professionals creates a major barrier to connecting transgender women with HIV-related care
complicating efforts to combat HIV among transgender people is basic lack of access to medical care. 2009 NIH study identified a number of reasons limited access to low-cost care and trans-inclusive medical environments incompetence of doctors about transgender health care social stigma institutional discrimination economic hardship, and distrust of medical professionals creates a major barrier to connecting transgender women with HIV-related care
(SUNNIVIE BRYDUM, “Invisible Women: Why Transgender Women Are Hit So Hard By HIV,” APRIL 08 2013, http://www.hivplusmag.com/case-studies/2013/04/08/invisible-women-why-transgender-women-are-hit-so-hard-hiv Further complicating efforts to combat HIV among transgender people is that population’s basic lack of access to medical care. The 2009 NIH study examined one community-based health clinic in New York City and identified a number of reasons that transgender women aren’t seeking preventive health care, including limited access to low-cost care and safe, trans-inclusive medical environments, along with the incompetence of many doctors about basic transgender health care, which results in trans women feeling unsafe to disclose their HIV status. The combination of social stigma, institutional discrimination, economic hardship, and distrust of medical professionals creates a major barrier to connecting transgender women with HIV-related care. “Not much HIV-prevention messaging is aimed toward or accessible to trans people,” says Nova. Noting that most HIV-prevention programming is for gay and bisexual men, Nova argues that current prevention efforts don’t meet the needs of HIV-positive trans women.
1,214
<h4>Clinic discrimination is an alt cause to trans<u><strong> HIV scenario</h4><p>Brydum 13 (their author)</p><p></u></strong>(SUNNIVIE BRYDUM, “Invisible Women: Why Transgender Women Are Hit So Hard By HIV,” APRIL 08 2013, http://www.hivplusmag.com/case-studies/2013/04/08/invisible-women-why-transgender-women-are-hit-so-hard-hiv</p><p>Further <u><mark>complicating efforts to combat HIV among transgender people is</mark> that population’s <strong><mark>basic lack of access to medical care.</strong></mark> The <mark>2009 NIH study</u></mark> examined one community-based health clinic in New York City and <u><mark>identified a number of reasons</mark> that transgender women aren’t seeking preventive health care, including <strong><mark>limited access to low-cost care</strong> and</mark> safe, <strong><mark>trans-inclusive medical environments</strong></mark>, along with the <strong><mark>incompetence of</mark> many <mark>doctors about</mark> basic <mark>transgender health care</strong></mark>, which results in trans women feeling unsafe to disclose their HIV status.</u> <u>The combination of <strong><mark>social stigma</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>institutional discrimination</strong></mark>, <strong><mark>economic hardship</strong>, and <strong>distrust of medical professionals</strong> creates a major barrier to connecting transgender women with HIV-related care</u></mark>. “Not much HIV-prevention messaging is aimed toward or accessible to trans people,” says Nova. Noting that most HIV-prevention programming is for gay and bisexual men, Nova argues that current prevention efforts don’t meet the needs of HIV-positive trans women.</p>
1NC
null
Case
430,079
1
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,992
Anasthesia DA: Their framework is a demand for anesthesia through the enforcement of gatekeeping of predictable knowledge – this turns debate into a depoliticized simulation and reaffirms sovereign exceptionalism.
Lafleur 07
Lafleur 07 Marc Lafleur, Dept of Anthropology, York University Culture, Trauma, and Conflict: Cultural Studies Perspectives on War, edited by Nico Carpentier 2007 222-224
It is only when a perceived or imagined sense of intimacy comes under scrutiny. “when states, populations, or persons sense that their definition of the real is under threat; when the normative relays between personal and collective ethics become frayed and exposed , a sense of anxiety will be pervasively felt about how to determine responsibility for the disruption of hegemonic comfort” The gateways of the body close, shielding itself from the excesses of the modern world perceived as a series of threats and hazards. Modern anesthesia removes the subject from a position of judgment and decision by immersion into an apparently limitless ether of the image and the commodity. Biopolitical sovereignty controls through reducing the subject to the present tense in which desire plays off against disaster, with consumption acting as the fleeting narcotic easing the fear that haunts sovereignty’s ersatz management that which is unknown, unstable, unpredictable, and beyond one’s control In transforming the unknown it into a source of fear rather than excitement or anticipation, biopolitics as mobile system of sovereignty based upon stasis and enclosed management reveals its genius, So it is through the production of anaesthetized bodies that sovereignty — through an untempered violence embedded within it pushes the state of exception into permanence and maintains it there. Anesthesia and the state of exception rely upon one another The technoaesthetics of these compensatory realities foster social relationships, communal action and interaction, and communication via sophisticated yet thoroughly de-politicized simulations that render the need or desire for human engagement null.
It is only when persons sense that their definition of the real is under threat anxiety will be felt about how to determine responsibility for the disruption of hegemonic comfort The gateways close, shielding from the excesses of the modern world perceived as a series of threats and hazards. sovereignty controls through reducing the subject to the present tense in which desire plays off against disaster consumption as the fleeting narcotic easing the fear that haunts sovereignty that which is unknown, unstable, unpredictable, and beyond one’s control In transforming the unknown into a source of fear biopolitics as mobile system of sovereignty based upon stasis and enclosed management reveals its genius through the production of anaesthetized bodies sovereignty pushes the state of exception into permanence and maintains it these realities foster communication via de-politicized simulations that render the need or desire for human engagement null.
It is only when a perceived or imagined sense of intimacy comes under scrutiny. “when states, populations, or persons sense that their definition of the real is under threat; when the normative relays between personal and collective ethics become frayed and exposed ; and when the traditional sites of pleasure and profit seem to get “taken away” by the political actions of subordinated groups, a sense of anxiety will be pervasively felt about how to determine responsibility for the disruption of hegemonic comfort” (Berlant 2000, 7). Ms. Sasamori did not just call into question the suitability of the “Blast from the Past” event, but cast its underlying project, the buttressing of American identity itself, into a state of unease and panic. Deftly, and with one stroke of denial and an emphatic re-embrace of fantasy the two women had explained away the trauma that had momentarily interrupted not just the smooth unfolding of their holiday but the very illusion of the good life to which they subscribed themselves with such effort. Again, as we saw with Little Boy, it is an intimacy which is cast not simply in the common experience of the spectacle of the catastrophe, but the catastrophe which is then deferred, parried and denied. The seeming paradox of this intimacy is that instead of opening up the body to the affective trace of trauma, a trace which according to Berlant (2000) is always sensual, it functions by reinforcing the shell of anesthesia that chokes off the senses from the world around it. Instead of jolting the senses, and jump-starting the body, however artificially, this intimacy tries to shore up the (mass) body by deadening its senses in ever greater attempts to elude the haunting knocks of the traumatic real, This is what Walter Benjamin was afraid of when he formulated his theories of shock and the aestheticization of the political (1968, 1978). In the modem world with its infinite possibilities of both physical and psychic trauma, the synaesthetic system —the human nervous system and the environment to which it responds becomes transformed, changing its machinery from the sensory to the protective. No longer is the apparatus of human perception open to world. The gateways of the body close, shielding itself from the excesses of the modern world perceived as a series of threats and hazards. The circuitry of the body’s senses reverse course in such a situation, attempting to “deaden” or mute themselves from the outside world. Modern anesthesia removes the subject from a position of judgment and decision by immersion into an apparently limitless ether of the image and the commodity. The aestheticization of the political results in the annesthetizing of the body. Biopolitical sovereignty controls through reducing the subject to the present tense in which desire plays off against disaster, with consumption acting as the fleeting narcotic easing the fear that haunts sovereignty’s ersatz management — that which is unknown, unstable, unpredictable, and beyond one’s control (Massumi 1993). In transforming the unknown it into a source of fear rather than excitement or anticipation, biopolitics as mobile system of sovereignty based upon stasis and enclosed management reveals its genius, for it is at this moment that power’s almost complete implantation or location within the body is demonstrated. So it is through the production of anaesthetized bodies that sovereignty — through an untempered violence embedded within it pushes the state of exception into permanence and maintains it there. Anesthesia and the state of exception rely upon one another, there cannot be one without the other. The technoaesthetics of these compensatory realities foster social relationships, communal action and interaction, and communication via sophisticated yet thoroughly de-politicized simulations that render the need or desire for human engagement null. Anesthesia is accomplished via a concurrent starvation and deluge of the senses. “The dialectical reversal, whereby aesthetics changes from a cognitive mode of being in touch with reality to a way of blocking out reality destroys the human organism’s power to respond politically even when self-preservation is at stake: so someone who is past experiencing is no longer capable of telling ...proven friend., from mortal enemy (Buck Morss 1992, 18).
4,353
<h4><u>Anasthesia DA: Their framework is a demand for anesthesia through the enforcement of gatekeeping of predictable knowledge – this turns debate into a depoliticized simulation and reaffirms sovereign exceptionalism.</h4><p><strong>Lafleur 07</p><p></u></strong>Marc Lafleur, Dept of Anthropology, York University Culture, Trauma, and Conflict: Cultural Studies Perspectives on War, edited by Nico Carpentier 2007 222-224</p><p><u><mark>It is only when</mark> a perceived or imagined sense of intimacy comes under scrutiny. “when states, populations, or <mark>persons sense that their definition of the real is under threat</mark>; when the normative relays between personal and collective ethics become frayed and exposed </u>; and when the traditional sites of pleasure and profit seem to get “taken away” by the political actions of subordinated groups<u>, a sense of <mark>anxiety will be</mark> pervasively <mark>felt about how to determine responsibility for the</mark> <mark>disruption of hegemonic comfort</mark>”</u> (Berlant 2000, 7). Ms. Sasamori did not just call into question the suitability of the “Blast from the Past” event, but cast its underlying project, the buttressing of American identity itself, into a state of unease and panic. Deftly, and with one stroke of denial and an emphatic re-embrace of fantasy the two women had explained away the trauma that had momentarily interrupted not just the smooth unfolding of their holiday but the very illusion of the good life to which they subscribed themselves with such effort. Again, as we saw with Little Boy, it is an intimacy which is cast not simply in the common experience of the spectacle of the catastrophe, but the catastrophe which is then deferred, parried and denied. The seeming paradox of this intimacy is that instead of opening up the body to the affective trace of trauma, a trace which according to Berlant (2000) is always sensual, it functions by reinforcing the shell of anesthesia that chokes off the senses from the world around it. Instead of jolting the senses, and jump-starting the body, however artificially, this intimacy tries to shore up the (mass) body by deadening its senses in ever greater attempts to elude the haunting knocks of the traumatic real, This is what Walter Benjamin was afraid of when he formulated his theories of shock and the aestheticization of the political (1968, 1978). In the modem world with its infinite possibilities of both physical and psychic trauma, the synaesthetic system —the human nervous system and the environment to which it responds becomes transformed, changing its machinery from the sensory to the protective. No longer is the apparatus of human perception open to world. <u><mark>The gateways</mark> of the body <mark>close, shielding</mark> itself <mark>from the excesses of the modern world perceived as a series of threats and hazards.<strong></mark> </u>The </strong>circuitry of the body’s senses reverse course in such a situation, attempting to “deaden” or mute themselves from the outside world. <u>Modern anesthesia removes the subject from a position of judgment and decision by immersion into an apparently limitless ether of the image and the commodity.</u><strong> The aestheticization of the political results in the annesthetizing of the body</strong>. <u>Biopolitical <mark>sovereignty controls through reducing the subject to the present tense in which desire plays off against disaster</mark>, with <mark>consumption</mark> acting <mark>as the fleeting narcotic easing <strong>the fear that haunts sovereignty</strong></mark>’s ersatz management</u><strong> — <u><mark>that which is unknown, unstable, unpredictable, and beyond one’s control</u></strong></mark> (Massumi 1993<strong>). <u></strong><mark>In <strong>transforming the unknown</strong></mark> it <strong><mark>into a source of fear</strong></mark> rather than excitement or anticipation, <mark>biopolitics as mobile system of sovereignty based upon stasis and enclosed management reveals its genius</mark>,</u> for it is at this moment that power’s almost complete implantation or location within the body is demonstrated. <u>So it is <mark>through the production of anaesthetized bodies</mark> that <mark>sovereignty</mark> — through an untempered violence embedded within it <mark>pushes the state of exception into permanence and maintains it</mark> there. Anesthesia and the state of exception rely upon one another</u>, there cannot be one without the other. <u>The technoaesthetics of <mark>these</mark> compensatory <mark>realities foster</mark> social relationships, communal action and interaction, and <mark>communication via</mark> sophisticated yet thoroughly<strong> <mark>de-politicized simulations that render the need or desire for human engagement null.</u></strong></mark> Anesthesia is accomplished via a concurrent starvation and deluge of the senses. “The dialectical reversal, whereby aesthetics changes from a cognitive mode of being in touch with reality to a way of blocking out reality destroys the human organism’s power to respond politically even when self-preservation is at stake: so someone who is past experiencing is no longer capable of telling ...proven friend., from mortal enemy (Buck Morss 1992, 18).</p>
T
null
null
430,081
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,993
Realism is not inevitable, it is a product of a particular historical context that assumes discursive hegemony because it has been represented as such
Bleiker, 2001
Bleiker, 2001 (Roland, Millennium: Journal of International Studies Vol. 30, No. 3, pp. 509-533)
The task of critically analysing world politics is to make fuller use of various faculties and to challenge the mimetic and exclusive conventions of Realist international politics We all have an intuitive longing for the hope that what we represent is what we see and think, and that what we see and think must really be real We know that Cold War spy films are not real, yet it is much more difficult to accept that a scientific analysis of Cold War intelligence contain equally subjective representational dimensions. we are wedded to conventions of language Representation is always an act of power. This power is at its peak if a form of representation is able to disguise its subjective origins and values. Realism has been unusually successful in this endeavour: it has turned one of many credible interpretations into a form of representation that is not only widely accepted as 'realistic'. but also appears and functions as essence
The task of critically analysing world politics is to challenge conventions of Realist politics t a scientific analysis of Cold War intelligence contain equally subjective dimensions we are wedded to conventions of language power is at peak a form of representation able to disguise its subjective values Realism has been successful in this : it has turned one of many credible interpretations into a form of representation that is not only widely accepted as 'realistic'. but also appears as essence
Nothing is harder than to notice the obvious that was not noticed before. The task of critically analysing world politics is to make fuller use of various faculties and to challenge the mimetic and exclusive conventions of Realist international politics, just as Magritte's painting of a pipe was aimed at undermining 'the mimetic conventions of realistic painting'. But few tasks are more daunting than that. We all have an intuitive longing for the hope that what we represent is what we see and think, and that what we see and think must really be real. The belief in resemblance and recognition is part of our desire to order the world. We know, of course, that Cold War spy films are not real, yet it is much more difficult to accept, for instance, that a scientific analysis of Cold War intelligence, based on quantitative archival research, can contain equally subjective representational dimensions. This is because we are wedded to conventions of language; conventions that tell us, to appropriate Michel Foucault's words, that the entire purpose of a scholarly analysis 'is to elicit recognition, to allow the object it represents to appear without hesitation and equivocation'.26 Representation is always an act of power. This power is at its peak if a form of representation is able to disguise its subjective origins and values. Realism has been unusually successful in this endeavour: it has turned one of many credible interpretations into a form of representation that is not only widely accepted as 'realistic'. but also appears and functions as essence. Realism has been able to take historically contingent and political motivated commentaries-say by E.H. Carr and Hans Morgenthau about how to deal with the spread of Nazi Germany, or by Kenneth Waltz about how to interpret the 'logic' of 'anarchy' during the Cold War-and then turn them into universal and a-historic explanations that allegedly capture the 'essence' of human nature and international politics.27 Expressed in other words, Realism has managed to suppress what Kant would have called the 'aesthetic Quality' of politics. that is, the elements which are 'purely subjective in the representation of an object, i.e., what constitutes its reference to the subject, not to the object' .
2,267
<h4>Realism is not inevitable, it is a product of a particular historical context that assumes discursive hegemony because it has been represented as such</h4><p><u><strong><mark>Bleiker</mark>, 200<mark>1</u></strong></mark> (Roland, Millennium: Journal of International Studies Vol. 30, No. 3, pp. 509-533)</p><p>Nothing is harder than to notice the obvious that was not noticed before. <u><mark>The task of critically analysing world politics is to</mark> make fuller use of various faculties and to <mark>challenge </mark>the mimetic and exclusive <mark>conventions of Realist </mark>international <mark>politics</u></mark>, just as Magritte's painting of a pipe was aimed at undermining 'the mimetic conventions of realistic painting'. But few tasks are more daunting than that. <u>We all have an intuitive longing for the hope that what we represent is what we see and think, and that what we see and think must really be real</u>. The belief in resemblance and recognition is part of our desire to order the world. <u>We know</u>, of course, <u>that Cold War spy films are not real, yet it is much more difficult to accept</u>, for instance, <u>tha<mark>t a scientific analysis of Cold War intelligence</u></mark>, based on quantitative archival research, can <u><mark>contain equally subjective </mark>representational <mark>dimensions</mark>.</u> This is because <u><mark>we are wedded to conventions of language</u></mark>; conventions that tell us, to appropriate Michel Foucault's words, that the entire purpose of a scholarly analysis 'is to elicit recognition, to allow the object it represents to appear without hesitation and equivocation'.26 <u>Representation is always an act of power. This <mark>power is</mark> <mark>at</mark> its <mark>peak</mark> if <mark>a form of representation</mark> is <mark>able to disguise its subjective</mark> origins and <mark>values</mark>. <mark>Realism has been </mark>unusually <mark>successful in this </mark>endeavour<mark>:</mark> <mark>it has turned one of many credible interpretations into a form of representation that is not only widely accepted as 'realistic'. but also appears </mark>and functions <mark>as essence</u></mark>. Realism has been able to take historically contingent and political motivated commentaries-say by E.H. Carr and Hans Morgenthau about how to deal with the spread of Nazi Germany, or by Kenneth Waltz about how to interpret the 'logic' of 'anarchy' during the Cold War-and then turn them into universal and a-historic explanations that allegedly capture the 'essence' of human nature and international politics.27 Expressed in other words, Realism has managed to suppress what Kant would have called the 'aesthetic Quality' of politics. that is, the elements which are 'purely subjective in the representation of an object, i.e., what constitutes its reference to the subject, not to the object' .</p>
1NR
Cartels
Realism
1,646,729
6
16,990
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
564,708
N
Kentucky
Doubles
George Mason KL
Rebecca Steiner, Kelly Young, and Brian Box
1ac was marijuana CSA 1nc was T not CSA GOP bad midterms Waivers CP Security K and case 2nc was Security and Midterms 1nr was Waivers and case 2nr was Security and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-Kentucky-Doubles.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,994
Reasonability
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Reasonability</h4>
T
null
null
430,080
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,995
Their turn to the state for protection legitimizes state violence and racist and patriarchal norms; and it removes social responsibility for sexual violence by rending women as vulnerable objects of masculine power
Heberle ‘96
Heberle ‘96
Turning to institutions offers increased legitimacy to the violence of the state and to racist and patriarchal norms vis-a-vis justice movement for women going to the state removes responsibility from society for combatting sexual violence. It individuates women as vulnerable objects of masculinist power and disallows public acknowledgement of the complex logic of sexual violence writ large At best it offers individual women a limited sense of safety and some (increasingly limited) resources In the long run, state-centered, bureaucratic, and legalistic strategies may do more to normalize violence as a constitutive aspect of political life than to prevent sexual violence as a constitutive aspect of social life pointing to the immediacy and "reality" of the problem as the grounds for policy shores up masculinist forms of social power and its ability to define the limits of women's live
Turning to institutions offers increased legitimacy to the violence of the state and to racist and patriarchal norms vis-a-vis justice movement for women going to the state removes responsibility from society for combatting sexual violence. It individuates women as vulnerable objects of masculinist power and disallows public acknowledgement of the complex logic of sexual violence writ large state-centered legalistic strategies may do more to normalize violence than to prevent sexual violence pointing to the reality" of the problem as the grounds for policy shores up masculinist forms of social power and its ability to define the limits of women's live
(Renee."Deconstructive strategies and the movement against sexual violence. " Hypatia  11.4 (1996): 63. GenderWatch (GW) Turning to these institutions offers increased legitimacy to the violence of the state in general and to racist and patriarchal norms vis-a-vis justice and freedom of movement for women in particular. Advocating strong policing strategies as a means of protection places feminist critiques of the racist/patriarchal state in the background in light of the "reality" of sexual violence.14 Further, going to the state can be extremely isolating and removes responsibility from society for combatting sexual violence. It literally individuates women as vulnerable objects of masculinist power (women have to argue their immanent vulnerability in order to prove they were raped and in need of services) and disallows public acknowledgement of the complex logic of sexual violence writ large.15 At best it offers individual women a limited sense of safety and some (increasingly limited) resources. In the long run, however, state-centered, bureaucratic, and legalistic strategies may do more to normalize violence as a constitutive aspect of political life than to prevent sexual violence as a constitutive aspect of social life. Scarry's theory of the inversions of pain and power which invest the reality of pain in the reality of power encourages us to take note of the fragility of the edifice of masculine power. It has been shown that sexual violence escalates to murderous proportions when batterers fear a woman's imminent withdrawal or separation. Women who are battered risk death when they become pregnant, attempt to leave, or file for divorce. In these situations, batterers experience a lack of control and try, through violence, to gain it back-to establish the certainty of "their woman's" commitment. Violence often manifests itself in blows to the woman's stomach to cause a miscarriage. Pregnancy appears as a form of separation and therefore a threat to male power (Jones 1994; Schneider 1992; Walker 1984, 1989). In response to this, the movement often advocates further protectionist strategies in alliance with a masculinist state. The question I raise is not whether those are necessary in the moment for individual women in danger, but whether the habit of continually pointing to the immediacy and "reality" of the problem as the grounds for creating global social and political policy further shores up masculinist forms of social power and its ability to define the limits of women's lives. Remembering the reasons for earlier feminist insistence upon autonomy from the state and inventing alternatives may point us in a direction of isolating sexual violence as a cultural phenomenon due to its inability to affect the terms on whichwomen live their lives (Schechter 1982).
2,819
<h4><u><strong>Their turn to the state for protection legitimizes state violence and racist and patriarchal norms; and it removes social responsibility for sexual violence by rending women as vulnerable objects of masculine power</h4><p>Heberle ‘96</p><p></u></strong>(Renee."Deconstructive strategies and the movement against sexual violence. " Hypatia  11.4 (1996): 63. GenderWatch (GW)</p><p><u><strong><mark>Turning to</u></strong> </mark>these <u><strong><mark>institutions offers increased legitimacy to the violence of the state</u></strong> </mark>in general <u><strong><mark>and to racist and patriarchal norms vis-a-vis justice</u></strong> </mark>and freedom of <u><strong><mark>movement for women</u></strong> </mark>in particular. Advocating strong policing strategies as a means of protection places feminist critiques of the racist/patriarchal state in the background in light of the "reality" of sexual violence.14 Further, <u><strong><mark>going to the state</u></strong></mark> can be extremely isolating and <u><strong><mark>removes responsibility from society for combatting sexual violence. It</u></strong></mark> literally <u><strong><mark>individuates women as vulnerable objects of masculinist power</u></strong> </mark>(women have to argue their immanent vulnerability in order to prove they were raped and in need of services) <u><mark>and disallows public acknowledgement of the complex logic of sexual violence writ large</u></mark>.15 <u>At best it offers individual women a limited sense of safety and some (increasingly limited) resources</u>. <u>In the long run, </u>however, <u><strong><mark>state-centered</strong></mark>, bureaucratic, and <strong><mark>legalistic strategies may do more to normalize violence</strong> </mark>as a constitutive aspect of political life <strong><mark>than to prevent sexual violence</strong> </mark>as a constitutive aspect of social life</u>. Scarry's theory of the inversions of pain and power which invest the reality of pain in the reality of power encourages us to take note of the fragility of the edifice of masculine power. It has been shown that sexual violence escalates to murderous proportions when batterers fear a woman's imminent withdrawal or separation. Women who are battered risk death when they become pregnant, attempt to leave, or file for divorce. In these situations, batterers experience a lack of control and try, through violence, to gain it back-to establish the certainty of "their woman's" commitment. Violence often manifests itself in blows to the woman's stomach to cause a miscarriage. Pregnancy appears as a form of separation and therefore a threat to male power (Jones 1994; Schneider 1992; Walker 1984, 1989). In response to this, the movement often advocates further protectionist strategies in alliance with a masculinist state. The question I raise is not whether those are necessary in the moment for individual women in danger, but whether the habit of continually <u><mark>pointing to the </mark>immediacy and "<mark>reality" of the problem</u> <u>as the grounds for</u> </mark>creating global social and political <u><mark>policy</u> </mark>further <u><strong><mark>shores up masculinist forms of social power and its ability to define the limits of women's live</u></strong></mark>s. Remembering the reasons for earlier feminist insistence upon autonomy from the state and inventing alternatives may point us in a direction of isolating sexual violence as a cultural phenomenon due to its inability to affect the terms on whichwomen live their lives (Schechter 1982). </p>
1NC
null
Case
429,939
6
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,996
Multiple solvency deficits
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Multiple solvency deficits</h4>
JPIC
null
null
430,082
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,997
Legalization stigmatizes prostitutes as bodies in need of regulation and control, which outweighs their internal links and turns solvency
Thompson 2k
Thompson 2k
Although a system of legalization appears to be a viable alternative to criminalization, legalization is very problematic on its own it represents the ultimate form of control over women's bodies and sexuality the government's tight control over prostitution, creates a situation where the government may be considered the pimp. the government controls with whom, when, and where the prostitute engages in prostitution through a rigid series of time, place, and manner restrictions Instead of providing women with a degree of control and personal autonomy over their lives, the system of legalization ensures that prostitutes have no input over their lives and livelihood. This lack of choice and control, leaves women fully dependent on the government for every aspect of their work. Once a prostitute is licensed to work in the legal brothel, she automatically gives up her freedom to choose who her customers are, when to work, and how much she will receive for her services. A brothel prostitute typically works fourteen hour shifts, everyday, for a three-week period. brothel prostitute may see at least ten to fifteen men a day Prostitutes have no control over the clients they see so they have no right to refuse or deny a customer service they must split their earnings with management and are expected to pay for expenses, such as room and board, condoms, maid services, and a portion of weekly venereal disease checkups prostitutes' movements outside of the brothel are strictly controlled Once licensed, the female prostitute may not live in the same area that she works, socialize outside the brothel, or vacation in the same area the legalization of prostitution through a system of licensing and registration stigmatizes prostitutes as a group of women in need of regulation and control Although prostitutes are no longer stigmatized as criminals, they are stigmatized as "bad girls." The system of legalization perpetuates the ideology of the whore/ madonna dichotomy by emphasizing that whores are the source of diseases and licensing is the only way to control their behavior. the madonna is the pure, good girl, who unlike the "other" woman, does not have to be controlled by strict regulations This forced stigmatization may cause some prostitutes to work illegally, for fear that registration and licensing may make their identity known Under this scheme of control, the prostitute is not granted the same rights of privacy afforded to the clients who enter the brothels a closer examination shows that legalization does not promote freedom or choice in prostitution, but rather eliminates all freedom associated with the choice of prostitution. the legalized system of control is more exploitative than the criminalized model of prostitution control Under legalization, women are not given any options. Either they work within the strict regulations that dictate their behavior and activities, or work outside of the law and risk potential violence and arrest brothel prostitutes enjoy less freedom than the average worker at a fast-food restaurant. the worker at a fast-food establishment may actually fare better than the brothel prostitute because that worker is not subjected to mandatory weekly and monthly health examinations, and is free to walk and travel where she pleases More importantly, if she loses her job or is unable to work, unemployment, disability insurance, and other social benefits are available for her protection. The system of legalization is - created, operated, and condoned by the government, in order to control women's sexuality. the legalized prostitute is the most exploited worker She is forced to work for the "master," with no questions asked. This legalized system of imprisonment is carefully structured so the prostitute does all the work and receives none of the benefits. The system of legalization forces us to question who truly benefits from the laws of legalization?
legalization represents the ultimate form of control over women's bodies and sexuality the government's tight control creates a situation where the government may be the pimp. the government controls with whom, when, and where the prostitute engages in prostitution through a rigid series of restrictions Instead of providing autonomy legalization ensures prostitutes have no input over their lives This lack of choice leaves women fully dependent on the government Once a prostitute is licensed she gives up her freedom to choose who her customers are, when to work, and how much she will receive for her services legalization stigmatizes prostitutes as a group of women in need of regulation and control legalization perpetuates the ideology of the whore/ madonna dichotomy by emphasizing that whores are the source of diseases and licensing is the only way to control their behavior. This may cause some prostitutes to work illegally, for fear that registration may make their identity known legalization eliminates all freedom associated with the choice of prostitution. the legalized system is more exploitative Either they work within strict regulations or work outside the law and risk violence and arrest brothel prostitutes enjoy less freedom than the average worker at a fast-food restaurant. legalization is created by the government, to control women's sexuality the legalized prostitute is the most exploited worker
[Susan, J.D. Candidate, Capital University Law School May 2000; 21 Women's Rights L. Rep. 217. ETB] Although a system of legalization appears to be a viable alternative to criminalization, legalization is very problematic on its own. Opponents to legalization argue that it represents the ultimate form of control over women's bodies and sexuality. n477 While the typical "pimp- [*243] prostitute" relationship is seemingly non-existent, the government's tight control over prostitution, creates a situation where the government may be considered the pimp. n478 Similar to the traditional pimp, the government controls with whom, when, and where the prostitute engages in prostitution through a rigid series of time, place, and manner restrictions. n479¶ Instead of providing women with a degree of control and personal autonomy over their lives, the system of legalization ensures that prostitutes have no input over their lives and livelihood. This lack of choice and control, leaves women fully dependent on the government for every aspect of their work. n480 Once a prostitute is licensed to work in the legal brothel, she automatically gives up her freedom to choose who her customers are, when to work, and how much she will receive for her services. n481 A brothel prostitute typically works fourteen hour shifts, everyday, for a three-week period. n482 During that time, a brothel prostitute may see at least ten to fifteen men a day. n483 Prostitutes have no control over the clients they see so they have no right to refuse or deny a customer service, unless the customer is aggressive and abusive. n484 Legal brothel prostitutes may generate a decent income from their work, however, they must split their earnings with management and are expected to pay for expenses, such as room and board, condoms, maid services, and a portion of weekly venereal disease checkups. n485 Additionally, prostitutes' movements outside of the brothel are strictly controlled. n486 Once licensed, the female prostitute may not live in the same area that she works, socialize outside the brothel, or vacation in the same area. n487 On the whole, prostitutes are forbidden to leave the brothels except to go to a doctor's appointment or the beauty salon. n488¶ The mandatory health checks have been influential in reducing the rate of STDs and AIDS in prostitution. n489 However, the mandatory health controls do little to protect the prostitute from infected clients who are either unaware they are infected or aware and continue to visit legal brothels. n490 Once the prostitute tests positive for a disease such as AIDS, she is forced to give up her only means of income, with no chance of receiving disability or unemployment insurance to compensate her for her loss. n491 Additionally, mandatory health care may present some problems regarding the right to refuse medical treatment when prostitutes are forced to undergo medical examinations. n492¶ Lastly, the legalization of prostitution through a system of licensing and registration stigmatizes prostitutes as a group of women in need of regulation and control. n493 Although prostitutes are no longer stigmatized as criminals, under a system of criminalization, they are stigmatized as "bad girls." n494 The system of legalization perpetuates the ideology of the whore/ madonna dichotomy by emphasizing that whores are the source of diseases and licensing is the only way to control their behavior. n495 Alternatively, the madonna is the pure, good girl, who unlike the "other" woman, does not have to be controlled by strict regulations. Arguably, there is a fine line between the whore/madonna which can easily be crossed by not only selling sex, but by giving it away improperly through adultery or promiscuity. n496 This forced stigmatization may cause some prostitutes to work illegally, for fear that registration and licensing may make their identity known. n497 Under this scheme of control, the prostitute is not granted the same rights of privacy afforded to the clients who enter the brothels. n498 Clients who seek the service of a brothel prostitute do not face registration or [*244] risk friends and family finding out about their activities without their knowledge. n499 Had clients been forced to register before visiting a brothel, one is left to wonder, how many, if any, would continue to frequent brothels under such strict conditions?¶ At first glance, the system of legalization appears to be the best model of control, for allowing women the freedom to practice prostitution if they choose. However, a closer examination shows that legalization does not promote freedom or choice in prostitution, but rather eliminates all freedom associated with the choice of prostitution. In some ways, the legalized system of control is more exploitative and criminal than the criminalized model of prostitution control. Under legalization, women are not given any options. Either they work within the strict regulations that dictate their behavior and activities, or work outside of the law and risk potential violence and arrest. Although brothel prostitutes may make a decent living, they enjoy less freedom than the average worker at a fast-food restaurant. n500 In some ways, the worker at a fast-food establishment may actually fare better than the brothel prostitute because that worker is not subjected to mandatory weekly and monthly health examinations, and is free to walk and travel where she pleases. n501 More importantly, if she loses her job or is unable to work, unemployment, disability insurance, and other social benefits are available for her protection. The system of legalization is a form of modern day slavery - created, operated, and condoned by the government, in order to control women's sexuality. n502 In essence, the legalized prostitute is the most exploited worker under a system of capitalism. She is forced to work for the "master," with no questions asked. This legalized system of imprisonment is carefully structured so the prostitute does all the work and receives none of the benefits. The system of legalization forces us to question who truly benefits from the laws of legalization?
6,185
<h4><u><strong>Legalization stigmatizes prostitutes as bodies in need of regulation and control, which outweighs their internal links and turns solvency</h4><p>Thompson 2k</p><p></u></strong>[Susan, J.D. Candidate, Capital University Law School May 2000; 21 Women's Rights L. Rep. 217. ETB]</p><p><u>Although a system of legalization appears to be a viable alternative to criminalization, <strong><mark>legalization</strong> </mark>is very problematic on its own</u>. Opponents to legalization argue that <u>it <strong><mark>represents</strong> <strong>the ultimate form of</strong> <strong>control over women's bodies and sexuality</u></strong></mark>. n477 While the typical "pimp- [*243] prostitute" relationship is seemingly non-existent, <u><strong><mark>the government's tight control</strong> </mark>over prostitution, <strong><mark>creates a situation where the government may be</strong> </mark>considered <strong><mark>the pimp.</u></strong> </mark>n478 Similar to the traditional pimp, <u><strong><mark>the government controls with whom, when, and where the prostitute engages in prostitution through a rigid series of</strong> </mark>time, place, and manner <strong><mark>restrictions</u></strong></mark>. n479¶ <u><strong><mark>Instead of providing </strong></mark>women with a degree of control and personal <strong><mark>autonomy </strong></mark>over their lives, the system of <strong><mark>legalization ensures </strong></mark>that <strong><mark>prostitutes have no input over their lives</strong></mark> and livelihood. <strong><mark>This lack of choice</strong></mark> and control, <strong><mark>leaves women fully dependent on the government</strong> </mark>for every aspect of their work.</u> n480 <u><mark>Once a prostitute is licensed </mark>to work in the legal brothel, <mark>she </mark>automatically <mark>gives up her freedom to choose who her customers are, when to work, and how much she will receive for her services</mark>.</u> n481 <u>A brothel prostitute typically works fourteen hour shifts, everyday, for a three-week period.</u> n482 During that time, a <u>brothel prostitute may see at least ten to fifteen men a day</u>. n483 <u>Prostitutes have no control over the clients they see so they have no right to refuse or deny a customer service</u>, unless the customer is aggressive and abusive. n484 Legal brothel prostitutes may generate a decent income from their work, however, <u>they must split their earnings with management and are expected to pay for expenses, such as room and board, condoms, maid services, and a portion of weekly venereal disease checkups</u>. n485 Additionally, <u>prostitutes' movements outside of the brothel are strictly controlled</u>. n486 <u>Once licensed, the female prostitute may not live in the same area that she works, socialize outside the brothel, or vacation in the same area</u>. n487 On the whole, prostitutes are forbidden to leave the brothels except to go to a doctor's appointment or the beauty salon. n488¶ The mandatory health checks have been influential in reducing the rate of STDs and AIDS in prostitution. n489 However, the mandatory health controls do little to protect the prostitute from infected clients who are either unaware they are infected or aware and continue to visit legal brothels. n490 Once the prostitute tests positive for a disease such as AIDS, she is forced to give up her only means of income, with no chance of receiving disability or unemployment insurance to compensate her for her loss. n491 Additionally, mandatory health care may present some problems regarding the right to refuse medical treatment when prostitutes are forced to undergo medical examinations. n492¶ Lastly, <u>the <mark>legalization </mark>of prostitution through a system of licensing and registration <mark>stigmatizes</mark> <mark>prostitutes as a group of women in need of regulation and control</u></mark>. n493 <u>Although prostitutes are no longer stigmatized as criminals,</u> under a system of criminalization, <u>they are stigmatized as "bad girls."</u> n494 <u>The system of <strong><mark>legalization perpetuates the ideology of the whore/ madonna dichotomy by emphasizing that whores are the source of diseases and licensing is the only way to control their behavior.</u></strong></mark> n495 Alternatively, <u>the madonna is the pure, good girl, who unlike the "other" woman, does not have to be controlled by strict regulations</u>. Arguably, there is a fine line between the whore/madonna which can easily be crossed by not only selling sex, but by giving it away improperly through adultery or promiscuity. n496 <u><strong><mark>This</strong> </mark>forced stigmatization <strong><mark>may cause some prostitutes to work illegally, for fear that registration</strong> </mark>and licensing <strong><mark>may make their identity known</u></strong></mark>. n497 <u>Under this scheme of control, the prostitute is not granted the same rights of privacy afforded to the clients who enter the brothels</u>. n498 Clients who seek the service of a brothel prostitute do not face registration or [*244] risk friends and family finding out about their activities without their knowledge. n499 Had clients been forced to register before visiting a brothel, one is left to wonder, how many, if any, would continue to frequent brothels under such strict conditions?¶ At first glance, the system of legalization appears to be the best model of control, for allowing women the freedom to practice prostitution if they choose. However, <u>a closer examination shows that <strong><mark>legalization </strong></mark>does not promote freedom or choice in prostitution, but rather <strong><mark>eliminates all freedom associated with the choice of prostitution.</u></strong></mark> In some ways, <u><strong><mark>the legalized system</strong> </mark>of control <strong><mark>is more</strong> <strong>exploitative</u></strong> </mark>and criminal <u>than the criminalized model of prostitution control</u>. <u>Under legalization, women are not given any options. <mark>Either they work within </mark>the <mark>strict regulations </mark>that dictate their behavior and activities, <mark>or work outside</mark> of <mark>the law and risk </mark>potential <mark>violence and arrest</u></mark>. Although <u><strong><mark>brothel prostitutes</u></strong> </mark>may make a decent living, they <u><strong><mark>enjoy less freedom than the average worker at a fast-food restaurant.</u></strong></mark> n500 In some ways, <u>the worker at a fast-food establishment may actually fare better than the brothel prostitute because that worker is not subjected to mandatory weekly and monthly health examinations, and is free to walk and travel where she pleases</u>. n501 <u>More importantly, if she loses her job or is unable to work, unemployment, disability insurance, and other social benefits are available for her protection. The system of <strong><mark>legalization is </u></strong></mark>a form of modern day slavery <u>- <strong><mark>created</strong></mark>, operated, and condoned <strong><mark>by the government,</strong> </mark>in order <strong><mark>to control women's</strong> <strong>sexuality</strong></mark>. </u>n502 In essence, <u><mark>the legalized prostitute is the most exploited worker</u> </mark>under a system of capitalism. <u>She is forced to work for the "master," with no questions asked. This legalized system of imprisonment is carefully structured so the prostitute does all the work and receives none of the benefits. The system of legalization forces us to question who truly benefits from the laws of legalization?</p></u>
1NC
null
Case
429,940
15
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,998
Removes the physician which doesn’t solve medicalization - injection of unruly death into the medical sphere is key to expose the limits of medicalization to physicians themselves
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Removes the physician which doesn’t solve medicalization - injection of unruly death into the medical sphere is key to expose the limits of medicalization to physicians themselves</h4>
JPIC
null
null
430,083
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
740,999
The links prove that the aff draws lines of legality – refuse that oscillation between inside and outside
Edkins and Pin-Fat 05.
Edkins and Pin-Fat 05. Jenny Edkins, professor of international politics at Prifysgol Aberystwyth University (in Wales) and Veronique Pin-Fat, senior lecturer in politics at Manchester Universit, “Through the Wire: Relations of Power and Relations of Violence,” Millennium - Journal of International Studies 2005 34: pg. 14
One potential form of challenge to sovereign power consists of a refusal to draw any lines between zoe- and bios, inside and outside sovereign power does not involve a power relation . It is more appropriately considered to have become a form of governance or technique of administration through relationships of violence that reduce political subjects to mere bare or naked life In asking for a refusal to draw lines as a possibility of challenge we are not asking for the elimination of power relations and consequently, we are not asking for the erasure of the possibility of a mode of political being that is empowered and empowering, is free and that speaks: quite the opposite it is only through a refusal to draw any lines at all between forms of life (and indeed, nothing less will do) that sovereign power as a form of violence can be contested and a properly political power relation reinstated We could call this challenging the logic of sovereign power through refusal we can evade sovereign power and reinstate a form of power relation by contesting sovereign power’s assumption of the right to draw lines, that is, by contesting the sovereign ban Any other challenge always inevitably remains within this relationship of violence we need not only to contest its right to draw lines in particular places, but also to resist the call to draw any lines of the sort sovereign power demands.¶ The grammar of sovereign power cannot be resisted by challenging or fighting over where the lines are drawn Whilst this is a strategy that can be deployed, it is not a challenge to sovereign power per se as it still tacitly or even explicitly accepts that lines must be drawn somewhere (and preferably more inclusively) such strategies contest the violence of sovereign power’s drawing of a particular line, they risk replicating such violence in demanding the line be drawn differently such forms of challenge fail to refuse sovereign power’s line-drawing ‘ethos’, an ethos which renders us all now homines sacri or bare life we now turn to look at how the assumption of bare life can produce forms of challenge. Agamben puts it in terms of a transformation:¶ This biopolitical body that is bare life must itself instead be transformed into the site for the constitution and installation of a form of life that is wholly exhausted in bare life and a bios that is only its own zoe If we give the name form-of-life to this being that is only its own bare existence and to this life that, being its own form, remains inseparable from it we will witness the emergence of a field of research beyond the terrain defined by the intersection of politics and philosophy, medico-biological sciences and jurisprudence
challenge to sovereign power consists of a refusal to draw any lines between inside and outside it is only through a refusal to draw any lines at all that sovereign power can be contested we can evade sovereign power by contesting sovereign power’s right to draw lines Any other challenge inevitably remains within this relationship of violence sovereign power cannot be resisted by challenging where the lines are drawn it still accepts that lines must be drawn somewhere such strategies risk replicating violence in demanding the line be drawn differently
One potential form of challenge to sovereign power consists of a refusal to draw any lines between zoe- and bios, inside and outside.59 As we have shown, sovereign power does not involve a power relation in Foucauldian terms. It is more appropriately considered to have become a form of governance or technique of administration through relationships of violence that reduce political subjects to mere bare or naked life. In asking for a refusal to draw lines as a possibility of challenge, then, we are not asking for the elimination of power relations and consequently, we are not asking for the erasure of the possibility of a mode of political being that is empowered and empowering, is free and that speaks: quite the opposite. Following Agamben, we are suggesting that it is only through a refusal to draw any lines at all between forms of life (and indeed, nothing less will do) that sovereign power as a form of violence can be contested and a properly political power relation (a life of power as potenza) reinstated. We could call this challenging the logic of sovereign power through refusal. Our argument is that we can evade sovereign power and reinstate a form of power relation by contesting sovereign power’s assumption of the right to draw lines, that is, by contesting the sovereign ban. Any other challenge always inevitably remains within this relationship of violence. To move outside it (and return to a power relation) we need not only to contest its right to draw lines in particular places, but also to resist the call to draw any lines of the sort sovereign power demands.¶ The grammar of sovereign power cannot be resisted by challenging or fighting over where the lines are drawn. Whilst, of course, this is a strategy that can be deployed, it is not a challenge to sovereign power per se as it still tacitly or even explicitly accepts that lines must be drawn somewhere (and preferably more inclusively). Although such strategies contest the violence of sovereign power’s drawing of a particular line, they risk replicating such violence in demanding the line be drawn differently. This is because such forms of challenge fail to refuse sovereign power’s line-drawing ‘ethos’, an ethos which, as Agamben points out, renders us all now homines sacri or bare life.¶ Taking Agamben’s conclusion on board, we now turn to look at how the assumption of bare life can produce forms of challenge. Agamben puts it in terms of a transformation:¶ This biopolitical body that is bare life must itself instead be transformed into the site for the constitution and installation of a form of life that is wholly exhausted in bare life and a bios that is only its own zoe-.... If we give the name form-of-life to this being that is only its own bare existence and to this life that, being its own form, remains inseparable from it we will witness the emergence of a field of research beyond the terrain defined by the intersection of politics and philosophy, medico-biological sciences and jurisprudence.60
3,019
<h4>The links prove that the aff draws lines of legality – refuse that oscillation between inside and outside</h4><p><u><strong>Edkins and Pin-Fat 05.</u></strong> Jenny Edkins, professor of international politics at Prifysgol Aberystwyth University (in Wales) and Veronique Pin-Fat, senior lecturer in politics at Manchester Universit, “Through the Wire: Relations of Power and Relations of Violence,” Millennium - Journal of International Studies 2005 34: pg. 14</p><p><u>One potential form of <mark>challenge to sovereign power consists of <strong>a refusal to draw any lines between </mark>zoe- and bios, <mark>inside and outside</u></mark>.</strong>59 As we have shown, <u><strong>sovereign power</strong> does not involve a power relation</u> in Foucauldian terms<u>. It is more appropriately considered to have become a form of governance or technique of administration through relationships of violence that reduce political subjects to mere bare or naked life</u>. <u>In asking for a refusal to draw lines as a possibility of challenge</u>, then, <u>we are not asking for the elimination of power relations and consequently, we are not asking for the erasure of the possibility of a mode of political being that is empowered and empowering, is free and that speaks: <strong>quite the opposite</u></strong>. Following Agamben, we are suggesting that <u><mark>it is only through <strong>a refusal to draw any lines at all </mark>between forms of life (and indeed, nothing less will do)</strong> <mark>that sovereign power</mark> as a form of violence <strong><mark>can be contested</strong></mark> and a properly political power relation</u> (a life of power as potenza) <u><strong>reinstated</u></strong>. <u>We could call this <strong>challenging the logic of sovereign power through refusal</u></strong>. Our argument is that <u><mark>we can evade sovereign power</mark> and reinstate a form of power relation <mark>by <strong>contesting sovereign power’s </mark>assumption of the <mark>right to draw lines</strong></mark>, that is, by contesting the sovereign ban</u>. <u><strong><mark>Any other challenge</mark> always <mark>inevitably remains within this relationship of violence</u></strong></mark>. To move outside it (and return to a power relation) <u>we need not only to contest its right to draw lines in particular places, but also to resist the call to draw any lines of the sort sovereign power demands.¶ <strong>The grammar of <mark>sovereign power cannot be resisted by challenging </mark>or fighting over <mark>where the lines are drawn</u></strong></mark>. <u>Whilst</u>, of course, <u>this is a strategy that can be deployed, it is not a challenge to sovereign power per se as <strong><mark>it still </mark>tacitly or even explicitly <mark>accepts that lines must be drawn somewhere</strong></mark> (and preferably more inclusively)</u>. Although <u><mark>such strategies</mark> contest the violence of sovereign power’s drawing of a particular line, <strong>they <mark>risk replicating </mark>such <mark>violence in demanding the line be drawn differently</u></mark>.</strong> This is because <u>such forms of challenge <strong>fail to refuse sovereign power’s line-drawing ‘ethos’, an ethos which</u></strong>, as Agamben points out, <u><strong>renders us all now homines sacri or bare life</u></strong>.¶ Taking Agamben’s conclusion on board, <u>we now turn to look at how the assumption of bare life can produce forms of challenge. Agamben puts it in terms of a transformation:¶ This biopolitical body that is bare life must itself instead be transformed into the site for the constitution and installation of a form of life that is wholly exhausted in bare life and a bios that is only its own zoe</u>-.... <u>If we give the name form-of-life to this being that is only its own bare existence and to this life that, being its own form, remains inseparable from it we will <strong>witness the emergence of a field of research beyond the terrain defined by the intersection of politics and philosophy, medico-biological sciences and jurisprudence</u></strong>.60</p>
2NC
Legalism K
A2: Perm
98,563
72
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,000
Because death is excluded from liberalism, it death into proximity of the medical sphere is key to rupture that mentality, that’s Golder and Murray
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Because death is excluded from liberalism, it death into proximity of the medical sphere is key to rupture that mentality, that’s Golder and Murray </h4>
JPIC
null
null
430,084
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,001
We must reject liberalism writ large if we are to avoid its ability to co-opt criticism and reduce it to a footnote.
Abbas 2010
Abbas 2010
Liberalism and Human Suffering: Materialist Reflections on Politics, Ethics, and Aesthetics, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pg. Pg. 38-39/ when touchy liberals desire better attention to the fact of human pain and suffering, they manage to talk about cruelty where, ironically, cruel actions are derivatives of cruel agents and the victim’s suffering is just fallout inability to dispel the primacy of the agent and the perpetrator in favor of the sufferer of pain, the current status of cruelty betrays a fetish of the active agent. It is no accident that the terms “good” and “evil” require a focus on cruelty and its infliction, leaving untouched the suffering of cruelty. Moral psychology ends up being the psychology of cruelty, which is a moral question, and hence of those who cause it. suffering is never a moral, let alone political or legal, question unless a moral agent with a conscience has caused it. All sufferers automatically become victims in the eyes of politics and law when “recognized.” Suffering is thus relevant as a political question only after it is a moral one, when it is embodied and located in a certain way, when it surpasses arbitrary thresholds. It is one thing to claim that liberalism cannot overcome its subject-centeredness even in its moments of empathy for the “victim.” It is another to understand the stubborn constitution of the agent at the helm of liberal justice and ask what makes it so incurable and headstrong and what the temperament of this stubbornness might be: pathetic, squishy, helplessly compassionate, humble, philanthropic, imperialist, venomous, neurotic Not figuring out this pathos is bound to reduce all interaction with liberal assertions to one or another act of editing or “correcting” them. all protests to liberalism tread a limited, predictable path and will be, at some point, incorporated within it. Liberalism’s singular gall and violence is accessed every time a resistance to it is accommodated by liberalism. Think not only of how often liberals affirm their clumsiness and mediocrity in speaking for the other’s suffering but also of how quickly its antagonists “make space” for the voice of others without challenging the (liberal, colonizing) structures that determine and distribute the suffering and speaking self, and the suffering and speaking other, to begin with. This protest leaves unquestioned what it means to speak for one’s own, or others’, suffering and whether there are other ways of speaking suffering that problematize these as the only options.
when touchy liberals desire better attention to suffering, they talk about cruelty where, ironically, cruel actions are derivatives of cruel agents the current status of cruelty betrays a fetish of the active agent. suffering is never a moral political or legal, question unless a moral agent caused it. All sufferers automatically become victims when “recognized.” It is one thing to claim that liberalism cannot overcome its subject-centeredness It is another to understand the stubborn constitution of the agent and ask what makes it so incurable bound to reduce all interaction to editing or “correcting” them. all protests to liberalism will be incorporated Liberalism’s violence is accessed every time a resistance is accommodated liberal colonizing structures determine and distribute the suffering
/Asma, Professor and Division Head in Social Studies, Political Science, Philosophy at the Liebowitz Center for International Studies at Bard College at Simon’s Rock, Liberalism and Human Suffering: Materialist Reflections on Politics, Ethics, and Aesthetics, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pg. Pg. 38-39/ The dizzying back and forth between professed Kantians and Humeans blurs the fact that, regardless of whether morality is anchored interior to the acting subject or determined by the effects of the actions of the subject as they play out in the outside world, the unit of analysis is quite the same. Thus, when touchy liberals desire better attention to the fact of human pain and suffering, they manage to talk about cruelty where, ironically, cruel actions are derivatives of cruel agents and the victim’s suffering is just fallout. Besides this shared inability to dispel the primacy of the agent and the perpetrator in favor of the sufferer of pain, the rift between Kant and Hume is deceptive in another way. In terms of historical evolution, the current status of cruelty betrays a fetish of the active agent. It is no accident that the terms “good” and “evil” require a focus on cruelty and its infliction, leaving untouched the suffering of cruelty. Moral psychology ends up being the psychology of cruelty, which is a moral question, and hence of those who cause it. In the same frame, suffering is never a moral, let alone political or legal, question unless a moral agent with a conscience has caused it. All sufferers automatically become victims in the eyes of politics and law when “recognized.” Suffering is thus relevant as a political question only after it is a moral one, when it is embodied and located in a certain way, when it surpasses arbitrary thresholds. It is one thing to claim that liberalism, whether empiricist or idealist, cannot overcome its subject-centeredness even in its moments of empathy for the “victim.” It is another to understand the stubborn constitution of the agent at the helm of liberal justice and ask what makes it so incurable and headstrong and what the temperament of this stubbornness might be: is it pathetic, squishy, helplessly compassionate, humble, philanthropic, imperialist, venomous, neurotic, all of the above, or none of these? Not figuring out this pathos is bound to reduce all interaction with liberal assertions to one or another act of editing or “correcting” them. Inadvertently, all protests to liberalism tread a limited, predictable path and will be, at some point, incorporated within it. Liberalism’s singular gall and violence is accessed every time a resistance to it is accommodated by liberalism. Think, for instance, not only of how often liberals affirm their clumsiness and mediocrity in speaking for the other’s suffering but also of how quickly its antagonists—purveyors of many a righteous anti-representational politics—“make space” for the voice of others without challenging the (liberal, colonizing) structures that determine and distribute the suffering and speaking self, and the suffering and speaking other, to begin with. This protest leaves unquestioned what it means to speak for one’s own, or others’, suffering and whether there are other ways of speaking suffering that problematize these as the only options.
3,313
<h4><u><strong>We must reject liberalism writ large if we are to avoid its ability to co-opt criticism and reduce it to a footnote.</h4><p>Abbas 2010</p><p></u></strong>/Asma, Professor and Division Head in Social Studies, Political Science, Philosophy at the Liebowitz Center for International Studies at Bard College at Simon’s Rock, <u>Liberalism and Human Suffering: Materialist Reflections on Politics, Ethics, and Aesthetics, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pg. Pg. 38-39/</p><p></u>The dizzying back and forth between professed Kantians and Humeans blurs the fact that, regardless of whether morality is anchored interior to the acting subject or determined by the effects of the actions of the subject as they play out in the outside world, the unit of analysis is quite the same. Thus, <u><mark>when touchy liberals desire better attention to</mark> the fact of human pain and <mark>suffering, they</mark> manage to <mark>talk about cruelty where, ironically, cruel actions are derivatives of cruel agents</mark> and the victim’s suffering is just fallout</u>. Besides this shared <u>inability to dispel the primacy of the agent and the perpetrator in favor of the sufferer of pain,</u> the rift between Kant and Hume is deceptive in another way. In terms of historical evolution, <u><mark>the current status of cruelty betrays a fetish of the active agent.</mark> It is no accident that the terms “good” and “evil” require a focus on cruelty and its infliction, leaving untouched the suffering of cruelty. Moral psychology ends up being the psychology of cruelty, which is a moral question, and hence of those who cause it.</u> In the same frame, <u><mark>suffering is never a moral</mark>, let alone <mark>political or legal, question unless a moral agent</mark> with a conscience has <mark>caused it. All sufferers automatically become victims</mark> in the eyes of politics and law <mark>when “recognized.”</mark> Suffering is thus relevant as a political question only after it is a moral one, when it is embodied and located in a certain way, when it surpasses arbitrary thresholds. <mark>It is one thing to claim that liberalism</u></mark>, whether empiricist or idealist, <u><mark>cannot overcome its subject-centeredness</mark> even in its moments of empathy for the “victim.” <mark>It is another to understand the stubborn constitution of the agent</mark> at the helm of liberal justice <mark>and ask what makes it so incurable</mark> and headstrong and what the temperament of this stubbornness might be:</u> is it <u>pathetic, squishy, helplessly compassionate, humble, philanthropic, imperialist, venomous, neurotic</u>, all of the above, or none of these? <u>Not figuring out this pathos is <mark>bound to reduce all interaction</mark> with liberal assertions <mark>to </mark>one or another act of <mark>editing or “correcting” them.</u></mark> Inadvertently, <u><mark>all protests to liberalism</mark> tread a limited, predictable path and <mark>will be</mark>, at some point, <mark>incorporated</mark> within it. <mark>Liberalism’s</mark> singular gall and <mark>violence is accessed every time a resistance </mark>to it <mark>is accommodated</mark> by liberalism. Think</u>, for instance, <u>not only of how often liberals affirm their clumsiness and mediocrity in speaking for the other’s suffering but also of how quickly its antagonists</u>—purveyors of many a righteous anti-representational politics—<u>“make space” for the voice of others without challenging the (<mark>liberal</mark>, <mark>colonizing</mark>) <mark>structures</mark> that <mark>determine and distribute the suffering</mark> and speaking self, and the suffering and speaking other, to begin with. This protest leaves unquestioned what it means to speak for one’s own, or others’, suffering and whether there are other ways of speaking suffering that problematize these as the only options.</p></u>
2NC
Legalism K
A2: Perm
157,661
15
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,002
Doesn’t solve the genealogy portion of the aff
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Doesn’t solve the genealogy portion of the aff</h4>
JPIC
null
null
430,085
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,003
Legalization devolves zoning laws
Bricker ‘6
Bricker ‘6
legalization leaves related regulation and zoning to municipal governments
legalization leaves related regulation and zoning to municipal governments
[Mindy, WeNews Correspondent, http://womensenews.org/story/athleticssports/060606/activists-blow-trafficking-whistle-world-cup#.VGoySPnF_Po ETB] Since the legalization of prostitution, which leaves related regulation and zoning to municipal governments, some German cities--including World Cup hosts--have designated red-light districts for the trade.
351
<h4><u><strong>Legalization devolves zoning laws</h4><p>Bricker ‘6</p><p></u></strong>[Mindy, WeNews Correspondent, http://womensenews.org/story/athleticssports/060606/activists-blow-trafficking-whistle-world-cup#.VGoySPnF_Po ETB]</p><p>Since the <u><mark>legalization</u> </mark>of prostitution, which <u><mark>leaves related regulation and zoning to municipal</u> <u>governments</u></mark>, some German cities--including World Cup hosts--have designated red-light districts for the trade.</p>
1NR
Zoning DA
Link
429,952
2
16,995
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
564,732
N
NDT
8
JMU LM
James Taylor, Joel Rollins, Jonah Feldman
1ac was prostitution 1nc was legal failure k t regulation municipalities da pepfar cp and case 2nc was legal failure k 1nr was pepfar cp municipalities da and case 2nr was legal failure k and case
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,004
It’s a tactic of sovereign power - regulating one’s choice to die through excluding certain ways of saying it – means autonomy can only exist on the sovereign’s terms
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><u><strong>It’s a tactic of sovereign power - regulating one’s choice to die through excluding certain ways of saying it – means autonomy can only exist on the sovereign’s terms</h4></u></strong>
JPIC
null
null
430,086
1
16,994
./documents/ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
564,700
A
NDT
7
NYU IZ
Mathis, Pasquinelli, Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Baylor/EvZo/Baylor-Evans-Zoda-Aff-NDT-Round7.docx
null
48,386
EvZo
Baylor EvZo
null
Sa.....
Ev.....
Gr.....
Zo.....
18,750
Baylor
Baylor
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2