id
int64
673k
4.14M
tag
stringlengths
1
39.7k
cite
stringlengths
1
8.39k
fullcite
stringlengths
1
50.9k
summary
stringlengths
1
47k
spoken
stringlengths
1
13.9k
fulltext
stringlengths
1
138k
textLength
float64
0
138k
markup
stringlengths
10
139k
pocket
stringlengths
1
863
hat
stringlengths
1
5.45k
block
stringlengths
1
16.5k
bucketId
int64
37
1.65M
duplicateCount
int64
1
3.81k
fileId
int64
14k
129k
filePath
stringlengths
60
188
roundId
int64
565k
915k
side
stringclasses
2 values
tournament
stringlengths
1
62
round
stringclasses
34 values
opponent
stringlengths
1
57
judge
stringlengths
1
87
report
stringlengths
1
612k
opensourcePath
stringlengths
48
176
caselistUpdatedAt
float64
teamId
int64
48.4k
77.9k
teamName
stringlengths
3
5
teamDisplayName
stringlengths
8
31
notes
float64
debater1First
stringclasses
164 values
debater1Last
stringclasses
183 values
debater2First
stringclasses
151 values
debater2Last
stringclasses
186 values
schoolId
int64
18.7k
26.1k
schoolName
stringclasses
306 values
schoolDisplayName
stringclasses
306 values
state
float64
chapterId
float64
caselistId
int64
1k
1.04k
caselistName
stringclasses
10 values
caselistDisplayName
stringclasses
10 values
year
int64
2.01k
2.02k
event
stringclasses
2 values
level
stringclasses
2 values
teamSize
int64
1
2
741,505
Prohibition leads to the use of harder drugs – non-uniques their cartel shift and public health arguments
BOETTKE et. al – 2013. Ph.D. Fellow and Ph.D. student at George Mason University, Oregon Law Review, “Keep off the Grass: The Economics of Prohibition and U.S. Drug Policy,” 2013, Accessed via LexisNexis on 7/29/2014) \
PETER J. BOETTKE et. al – 2013. (Professor of Economics and Philosophy, George Mason University; Ph.D., Economics, George Mason University; CHRISTOPHER J. COYNE, Professor of Economics, George Mason University; Ph.D., Economics, George Mason University; and ABIGAIL R. HALL, Mercatus Ph.D. Fellow and Ph.D. student at George Mason University, Oregon Law Review, “Keep off the Grass: The Economics of Prohibition and U.S. Drug Policy,” 2013, Accessed via LexisNexis on 7/29/2014) \
The first unintended consequence of prohibition is that individuals are more likely to consume poisonous substances and overdose with the increase in drug prices. As the price of a given drug rises, it creates additional profit opportunities for those willing to enter the drug trade. Since the drug market is illegal, and therefore, conducted underground, quality control is reduced compared to "above ground" markets. Drug users have few means available to determine which drugs are "pure" and have no recourse should they purchase a substance of inferior quality. Further, the underground market allows for less information sharing about products and vendors because transactions take place secretly to avoid authorities Consequently, more poor-quality drug products enter the market, which leads to a greater potential for poisoning and overdose. The illegality of drug use generates unintended "potency effects," On the supply side, prohibition results in drug dealers carrying and selling more potent drugs. under prohibition, suppliers prefer to transport cocaine, as compared to marijuana, because cocaine is more potent and therefore more valuable per unit. On the demand side, drug prices are driven up by prohibition, which causes drug users to seek "more bang for their buck." That is, since the overall cost of obtaining drugs is higher, more potent drugs are relatively cheaper than "weak" drugs. Because drug users must act illegally to obtain drugs, they seek to maximize the satisfaction or "high" from each dollar spent. drug users may switch from substances like marijuana to "harder" drugs like cocaine and heroin. Finally, drug users may employ more intense methods of drug use, such as injection. prohibition leads to a greater use of more potent substances, which increases the likelihood of overdose and drug-related death. these effects may be seen in the rate of unintended overdose deaths in the United States. In 1971, Nixon declared drugs to be a public menace Between 1990 and 2007 alone, overdose rates increased five-fold. n55 The most common sources of overdose deaths are higher potency drugs – mainly cocaine, heroin, and opioid painkillers. n56
The first unintended consequence of prohibition is that individuals are more likely to consume poisonous substances and overdose with the increase in drug prices. prohibition results in drug dealers carrying and selling more potent drugs suppliers prefer to transport cocaine because cocaine is more potent and therefore more valuable per unit drug prices are driven up by prohibition, which causes drug users to seek "more bang for their buck. since the overall cost of obtaining drugs is higher, more potent drugs are relatively cheaper than "weak" drugs. drug users may switch to "harder" drugs like cocaine and heroin. Between 1990 and 2007 alone, overdose rates increased five-fold The most common sources of overdose deaths are higher potency drugs – mainly cocaine, heroin, and opioid painkillers
The first unintended consequence of prohibition is that individuals are more likely to consume poisonous substances and overdose with the increase in drug prices. As the price of a given drug rises, it creates additional profit opportunities for those willing to enter the drug trade. Since the drug market is illegal, and therefore, conducted underground, quality control is reduced compared to "above ground" markets. Drug users have few means available to determine which drugs are "pure" and have no recourse should they purchase a substance of inferior quality. Further, the underground market allows for less information sharing about products and vendors because transactions take place secretly to avoid authorities. Consequently, more poor-quality drug products enter the market, which leads to a greater potential for poisoning and overdose.¶ The greater prevalence of poor-quality drugs is not the sole mechanism through which overdoses increase. The illegality of drug use generates unintended "potency effects," which affect both the supply and demand sides of the drug market. On the supply side, prohibition results in drug dealers carrying and selling more potent drugs. Because drug laws increase the risk of selling low potency drugs, suppliers tend to substitute toward higher potency drugs. For example, under prohibition, suppliers prefer to transport cocaine, as compared to marijuana, because cocaine is more potent and therefore more valuable per unit.¶ On the demand side, drug prices are driven up by prohibition, which causes drug users to seek "more bang for their buck." That is, since the overall cost of obtaining drugs is higher, more potent drugs are relatively cheaper than "weak" drugs. Because drug users must act illegally to obtain drugs, they seek to maximize the satisfaction or "high" from each dollar spent. This dynamic manifests itself in [*1079] several ways. Drug users may switch from lower potency to higher potency within a given drug (for example, from marijuana with lower levels of THC to marijuana with higher levels of THC). Alternatively, drug users may switch from substances like marijuana to "harder" drugs like cocaine and heroin. Finally, drug users may employ more intense methods of drug use, such as injection.¶ Taking both sides of the market together, prohibition leads to a greater use of more potent substances, which increases the likelihood of overdose and drug-related death. Indeed, these effects may be seen in the rate of unintended overdose deaths in the United States. In 1971, two years before the creation of the DEA and the year President Nixon declared drugs to be a public menace, just over one death per 100,000 deaths was due to an overdose. n53 By the year 2007, over 27,500 people died as a result of a drug overdose, which translates to almost ten per 100,000 deaths. n54 Between 1990 and 2007 alone, overdose rates increased five-fold. n55 The most common sources of overdose deaths are higher potency drugs – mainly cocaine, heroin, and opioid painkillers. n56
3,047
<h4><strong>Prohibition leads to the use of harder drugs – non-uniques their cartel shift and public health arguments </h4><p></strong>PETER J. <strong>BOETTKE et. al – 2013.</strong> (Professor of Economics and Philosophy, George Mason University; Ph.D., Economics, George Mason University; CHRISTOPHER J. COYNE, Professor of Economics, George Mason University; Ph.D., Economics, George Mason University; and ABIGAIL R. HALL, Mercatus<u><strong> Ph.D. Fellow and Ph.D. student at George Mason University, Oregon Law Review, “Keep off the Grass: The Economics of Prohibition and U.S. Drug Policy,” 2013, Accessed via LexisNexis on 7/29/2014) \</p><p><mark>The first unintended consequence of prohibition is that individuals are more likely to consume poisonous substances and overdose with the increase in drug prices.</mark> As the price of a given drug rises, it creates additional profit opportunities for those willing to enter the drug trade.</u></strong> <u><strong>Since the drug market is illegal, and therefore, conducted underground, quality control is reduced compared to "above ground" markets. Drug users have few means available to determine which drugs are "pure" and have no recourse should they purchase a substance of inferior quality. Further, the underground market allows for less information sharing about products and vendors because transactions take place secretly to avoid authorities</u></strong>. <u><strong>Consequently, more poor-quality drug products enter the market, which leads to a greater potential for poisoning and overdose.</u></strong>¶ The greater prevalence of poor-quality drugs is not the sole mechanism through which overdoses increase. <u><strong>The illegality of drug use generates unintended "potency effects,"</u></strong> which affect both the supply and demand sides of the drug market. <u><strong>On the supply side, <mark>prohibition results in drug dealers carrying and selling more potent drugs</mark>.</u></strong> Because drug laws increase the risk of selling low potency drugs, suppliers tend to substitute toward higher potency drugs. For example, <u><strong>under prohibition, <mark>suppliers prefer to transport cocaine</mark>, as compared to marijuana, <mark>because cocaine is more potent and therefore more valuable per unit</mark>.</u></strong>¶<u><strong> On the demand side, <mark>drug prices are driven up by prohibition, which causes drug users to seek "more bang for their buck.</mark>" That is, <mark>since the overall cost of obtaining drugs is higher, more potent drugs are relatively cheaper than "weak" drugs.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>Because drug users must act illegally to obtain drugs, they seek to maximize the satisfaction or "high" from each dollar spent.</u></strong> This dynamic manifests itself in [*1079] several ways. Drug users may switch from lower potency to higher potency within a given drug (for example, from marijuana with lower levels of THC to marijuana with higher levels of THC). Alternatively, <u><strong><mark>drug users may switch</mark> from substances like marijuana <mark>to "harder" drugs like cocaine and heroin.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>Finally, drug users may employ more intense methods of drug use, such as injection.</u></strong>¶ Taking both sides of the market together, <u><strong>prohibition leads to a greater use of more potent substances, which increases the likelihood of overdose and drug-related death.</u></strong> Indeed, <u><strong>these effects may be seen in the rate of unintended overdose deaths in the United States. In 1971,</u></strong> two years before the creation of the DEA and the year President <u><strong>Nixon declared drugs to be a public menace</u></strong>, just over one death per 100,000 deaths was due to an overdose. n53 By the year 2007, over 27,500 people died as a result of a drug overdose, which translates to almost ten per 100,000 deaths. n54 <u><strong><mark>Between 1990 and 2007 alone, overdose rates increased five-fold</mark>. n55 <mark>The most common sources of overdose deaths are higher potency drugs – mainly cocaine, heroin, and opioid painkillers</mark>. n56</p></u></strong>
null
null
Drug Cartels
430,240
6
17,021
./documents/ndtceda14/Butler/ToSc/Butler-Tock-Schmidt-Aff-JCCC-Round3.docx
564,790
A
JCCC
3
SMU
Stout
null
ndtceda14/Butler/ToSc/Butler-Tock-Schmidt-Aff-JCCC-Round3.docx
null
48,401
ToSc
Butler ToSc
null
Ph.....
To.....
Al.....
Sc.....
18,753
Butler
Butler
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,506
‘The pharmacopronographic regime is parasitic on the sexual Affect of living bodies. Orgasmic force or the potential for excitation, erection, ejaculation, and frustration is the new raw material for control. At stake is the total control of subjectivity and life itself through molecular management.
Preciado 13
Preciado 13 [Paul (formerly Beatriz), Prof of Political History of the Body, Gender Theory, and History of Performance at Paris VIII, Testo Junkie, trans. Bruce Benderson, p.41-6]
To understand how and why sexuality and the body became the objects of a minute governmental and industrial management, we must first elaborate a new concept in the pharmacopornographic domain that is equivalent to the force of work in the domain of classical economics. I call or “orgasmic force,” the (real or virtual) strength of a body’s (total) excitation.33 This strength is of indeterminate capacity; it has no gender; it is neither male nor female, neither human nor animal, neither animated nor inanimate. Its orientation emphasizes neither the feminine nor the masculine and creates no boundary between heterosexuality and homosexuality or between object and subject It favors no organ over any other, so that the penis possesses no more orgasmic force than the vagina, the eye, or the toe. Orgasmic force is the sum of the potential for excitation inherent in every material molecule. the twenty-first-century body is a technoliving system, the result of an irreversible implosion of modern binaries (female/male, animal/ human, nature/culture). Every technobody, including a dead technobody, can unleash orgasmic force, thus becoming a carrier of the power of production of sexual capital. necropolitics function as pharmacoporno politics, as planetary managements of [orgasmic force]. Sex, the so-called sexual organs, pleasure and impotence, joy and horror are moved to the center of technopolitical management as soon as the possibility of drawing profit from orgasmic force comes into play. we theorists of pharmacopornographic capitalism are interested in sexual work as a process of subjectivization, in the possibility of making the subject an inexhaustible supply of planetary ejaculation that can be transformed into abstraction and digital data—into capital.
To understand how sexuality and the body became the objects of governmental and industrial management, we must first elaborate a new concept in the domain of economics. “orgasmic force,” the (real or virtual) strength of a body’s (total) excitation has no gender; it is neither male nor female, neither human nor animal Its orientation creates no boundary between heterosexuality and homosexuality Orgasmic force is the sum of the potential for excitation inherent in every material molecule. the twenty-first-century body is the result of an irreversible implosion of modern binaries (female/male, animal/ human, nature/culture). Every technobody can unleash orgasmic force, becoming a carrier of the power of production of sexual capital. necropolitics function as planetary managements of [orgasmic force]. the sexual organs are moved to the center of technopolitical management as soon as drawing profit from orgasmic force comes into play. as a process of making the subject an inexhaustible supply of planetary ejaculation that can be transformed into capital.
To understand how and why sexuality and the body, the excitable body, at the end of the nineteenth century raided the heart of political action and became the objects of a minute governmental and industrial management, we must first elaborate a new philosophical concept in the pharmacopornographic domain that is equivalent to the force of work in the domain of classical economics. I call potentia gaudendi, or “orgasmic force,” the (real or virtual) strength of a body’s (total) excitation.33 This strength is of indeterminate capacity; it has no gender; it is neither male nor female, neither human nor animal, neither animated nor inanimate. Its orientation emphasizes neither the feminine nor the masculine and creates no boundary between heterosexuality and homosexuality or between object and subject; neither does it know the difference between being excited, being exciting, or being-excited-with. It favors no organ over any other, so that the penis possesses no more orgasmic force than the vagina, the eye, or the toe. Orgasmic force is the sum of the potential for excitation inherent in every material molecule. Orgasmic force is not seeking any immediate resolution, and it aspires only to its own extension in space and time, toward everything and everyone, in every place and at every moment. It is a force of transformation for the world in pleasure—“in pleasure with.” Potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force] unites all material, somatic, and psychic forces and seeks all biochemical resources and all the structures of the mind. In pharmacopornographic capitalism, the force of work reveals its actual substratum: orgasmic force, or potentia gaudendi. Current capitalism tries to put to work the potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force] in whatever form in which it exists, whether this be in its pharmacological form (a consumable molecule and material agency that will operate within the body of the person who is digesting it), as a pornographic representation (a semiotechnical sign that can be converted into numeric data or transferred into digital, televisual, or telephonic media), or as a sexual service (a live pharmacopornographic entity whose orgasmic force and emotional volume are put in service to a consumer during a specified time, according to a more or less formal contract of sale of sexual services). Potentia gaudendi [Orgasmic force] is characterized not only by its impermanence and great malleability, but also and above all by the impossibility of possessing and retaining it. Potentia gaudendi [Orgasmic force], as the fundamental energetics of pharmacopornism, does not allow itself to be reified or transformed into private property. I can neither possess nor retain another’s potentia gaudendi, but neither can one possess or retain what seems to be one’s own. Potentia gaudendi [Orgasmic force] exists exclusively as an event, a relation, a practice, or an evolutionary process. Orgasmic force is both the most abstract and the most material of all workforces. It is inextricably carnal and digital, viscous yet representational by numerical values, a phantasmatic or molecular wonder that can be transformed into capital. The living pansexual body is the bioport of the orgasmic force. Thus, it cannot be reduced to a prediscursive organism; its limits do not coincide with the skin capsule that surrounds it. This life cannot be understood as a biological given; it does not exist outside the interlacing of production and culture that belongs to technoscience. This body is a technoliving, multiconnected entity incorporating technology.34 Neither an organism nor a machine, but “the fluid, dispersed, networking techno-organic-textualmythic system.”35 This new condition of the body blurs the traditional modern distinction between art, performance, media, design, and architecture. The new pharmacological and surgical techniques set in motion tectonic construction processes that combine figurative representations derived from cinema and from architecture (editing, 3-D modeling, 3-D printing, etc.), according to which the organs, the vessels, the fluids (techno-blood, techno-sperm, etc.), and the molecules are converted into the prime material from which our pharmacopornographic corporality is manufactured. Technobodies are either not-yet-alive or already-dead: we are half fetuses, half zombies. Thus, every politics of resistance is a monster politics. Marshall McLuhan, Buckminster Fuller, and Norbert Wiener had an intuition about it in the 1950s: the technologies of communication function like an extension of the body. Today, the situation seems a lot more complex—the individual body functions like an extension of global technologies of communication. “Embodiment is significant prosthesis.”36 To borrow the terms of the American feminist Donna J. Haraway, the twenty-first-century body is a technoliving system, the result of an irreversible implosion of modern binaries (female/male, animal/ human, nature/culture). Even the term life has become archaic for identifying the actors in this new technology. For Foucault’s notion of “biopower,” Donna J. Haraway has substituted “techno-biopower.” It’s no longer a question of power over life, of the power to manage and maximize life, as Foucault wanted, but of power and control exerted over a technoliving and connected whole.37 In the circuit in which excitation is technoproduced, there are neither living bodies nor dead bodies, but present or missing, actual or virtual connectors. Images, viruses, computer programs, techno-organic fluids, Net surfers, electronic voices that answer phone sex lines, drugs and living dead animals in the laboratory on which they are tested, frozen embryos, mother cells, active alkaloid molecules . . . display no value in the current global economy as being “alive” or “dead,” but only to the extent that they can or can’t be integrated into a bioelectronics of global excitation. Haraway reminds us that “cyborg figures—such as the end-of-the-millennium seed, chip gene, database, bomb, fetus, race, brain, and ecosystem—are the offspring of implosions of subjects and objects and of the natural and artificial.”38 Every technobody, including a dead technobody, can unleash orgasmic force, thus becoming a carrier of the power of production of sexual capital. The force that lets itself be converted into capital lies neither in bios nor in soma, in the way that they have been conceived from Aristotle to Darwin, but in techno-eros, the technoliving enchanted body and its potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force]. And from this it follows that biopolitics (the politics of the control and production of life) as well as necropolitics (the politics of the control and production of death) function as pharmacoporno politics, as planetary managements of potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force]. Sex, the so-called sexual organs, pleasure and impotence, joy and horror are moved to the center of technopolitical management as soon as the possibility of drawing profit from orgasmic force comes into play. If the theorists of post-Fordism were interested in immaterial work, in cognitive work, in “non-objectifiable work,”39 in “affective work,”40 we theorists of pharmacopornographic capitalism are interested in sexual work as a process of subjectivization, in the possibility of making the subject an inexhaustible supply of planetary ejaculation that can be transformed into abstraction and digital data—into capital.
7,463
<h4>‘The pharmacopronographic regime is parasitic on the sexual Affect of living bodies. Orgasmic force or the potential for excitation, erection, ejaculation, and frustration is the new raw material for control. At stake is the total control of subjectivity and life itself through molecular management. </h4><p><strong>Preciado 13 </strong>[Paul (formerly Beatriz), Prof of Political History of the Body, Gender Theory, and History of Performance at Paris VIII, Testo Junkie, trans. Bruce Benderson, p.41-6]</p><p><u><strong><mark>To understand how </mark>and why<mark> sexuality and the body</u></strong></mark>, the excitable body, at the end of the nineteenth century raided the heart of political action and <u><strong><mark>became the objects of </mark>a minute <mark>governmental and industrial management, we must first elaborate a new</u></strong></mark> philosophical <u><strong><mark>concept</mark> in the pharmacopornographic domain that is equivalent to the force of work <mark>in the domain of</mark> classical <mark>economics.</mark> I call</u></strong> potentia gaudendi, <u><strong>or <mark>“orgasmic force,” the (real or virtual) strength of a body’s (total) excitation</mark>.33 This strength is of indeterminate capacity; it <mark>has no gender; it is neither male nor female, neither human nor animal</mark>, neither animated nor inanimate. <mark>Its orientation </mark>emphasizes neither the feminine nor the masculine and <mark>creates no boundary between heterosexuality and homosexuality</mark> or between object and subject</u></strong>; neither does it know the difference between being excited, being exciting, or being-excited-with. <u><strong>It favors no organ over any other, so that the penis possesses no more orgasmic force than the vagina, the eye, or the toe. <mark>Orgasmic force is the sum of the potential for excitation inherent in every material molecule.</mark> </u></strong>Orgasmic force is not seeking any immediate resolution, and it aspires only to its own extension in space and time, toward everything and everyone, in every place and at every moment. It is a force of transformation for the world in pleasure—“in pleasure with.” Potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force] unites all material, somatic, and psychic forces and seeks all biochemical resources and all the structures of the mind. In pharmacopornographic capitalism, the force of work reveals its actual substratum: orgasmic force, or potentia gaudendi. Current capitalism tries to put to work the potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force] in whatever form in which it exists, whether this be in its pharmacological form (a consumable molecule and material agency that will operate within the body of the person who is digesting it), as a pornographic representation (a semiotechnical sign that can be converted into numeric data or transferred into digital, televisual, or telephonic media), or as a sexual service (a live pharmacopornographic entity whose orgasmic force and emotional volume are put in service to a consumer during a specified time, according to a more or less formal contract of sale of sexual services). Potentia gaudendi [Orgasmic force] is characterized not only by its impermanence and great malleability, but also and above all by the impossibility of possessing and retaining it. Potentia gaudendi [Orgasmic force], as the fundamental energetics of pharmacopornism, does not allow itself to be reified or transformed into private property. I can neither possess nor retain another’s potentia gaudendi, but neither can one possess or retain what seems to be one’s own. Potentia gaudendi [Orgasmic force] exists exclusively as an event, a relation, a practice, or an evolutionary process. Orgasmic force is both the most abstract and the most material of all workforces. It is inextricably carnal and digital, viscous yet representational by numerical values, a phantasmatic or molecular wonder that can be transformed into capital. The living pansexual body is the bioport of the orgasmic force. Thus, it cannot be reduced to a prediscursive organism; its limits do not coincide with the skin capsule that surrounds it. This life cannot be understood as a biological given; it does not exist outside the interlacing of production and culture that belongs to technoscience. This body is a technoliving, multiconnected entity incorporating technology.34 Neither an organism nor a machine, but “the fluid, dispersed, networking techno-organic-textualmythic system.”35 This new condition of the body blurs the traditional modern distinction between art, performance, media, design, and architecture. The new pharmacological and surgical techniques set in motion tectonic construction processes that combine figurative representations derived from cinema and from architecture (editing, 3-D modeling, 3-D printing, etc.), according to which the organs, the vessels, the fluids (techno-blood, techno-sperm, etc.), and the molecules are converted into the prime material from which our pharmacopornographic corporality is manufactured. Technobodies are either not-yet-alive or already-dead: we are half fetuses, half zombies. Thus, every politics of resistance is a monster politics. Marshall McLuhan, Buckminster Fuller, and Norbert Wiener had an intuition about it in the 1950s: the technologies of communication function like an extension of the body. Today, the situation seems a lot more complex—the individual body functions like an extension of global technologies of communication. “Embodiment is significant prosthesis.”36 To borrow the terms of the American feminist Donna J. Haraway, <u><strong><mark>the twenty-first-century body is </mark>a technoliving system, <mark>the result of an irreversible implosion of modern binaries (female/male, animal/ human, nature/culture).</mark> </u></strong>Even the term life has become archaic for identifying the actors in this new technology. For Foucault’s notion of “biopower,” Donna J. Haraway has substituted “techno-biopower.” It’s no longer a question of power over life, of the power to manage and maximize life, as Foucault wanted, but of power and control exerted over a technoliving and connected whole.37 In the circuit in which excitation is technoproduced, there are neither living bodies nor dead bodies, but present or missing, actual or virtual connectors. Images, viruses, computer programs, techno-organic fluids, Net surfers, electronic voices that answer phone sex lines, drugs and living dead animals in the laboratory on which they are tested, frozen embryos, mother cells, active alkaloid molecules . . . display no value in the current global economy as being “alive” or “dead,” but only to the extent that they can or can’t be integrated into a bioelectronics of global excitation. Haraway reminds us that “cyborg figures—such as the end-of-the-millennium seed, chip gene, database, bomb, fetus, race, brain, and ecosystem—are the offspring of implosions of subjects and objects and of the natural and artificial.”38 <u><strong><mark>Every technobody</mark>, including a dead technobody, <mark>can unleash orgasmic force, </mark>thus <mark>becoming a carrier of the power of production of sexual capital.</mark> </u></strong>The force that lets itself be converted into capital lies neither in bios nor in soma, in the way that they have been conceived from Aristotle to Darwin, but in techno-eros, the technoliving enchanted body and its potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force]. And from this it follows that biopolitics (the politics of the control and production of life) as well as<u><strong> <mark>necropolitics</u></strong></mark> (the politics of the control and production of death) <u><strong><mark>function as</mark> pharmacoporno politics, as <mark>planetary managements of</u></strong></mark> potentia gaudendi <u><strong><mark>[orgasmic force]. </mark>Sex,<mark> the </mark>so-called <mark>sexual organs</mark>, pleasure and impotence, joy and horror <mark>are moved to the center of technopolitical management as soon as </mark>the possibility of <mark>drawing profit from orgasmic force comes into play.</mark> </u></strong>If the theorists of post-Fordism were interested in immaterial work, in cognitive work, in “non-objectifiable work,”39 in “affective work,”40 <u><strong>we theorists of pharmacopornographic capitalism are interested in sexual work <mark>as a process of</mark> subjectivization, in the possibility of <mark>making the subject an inexhaustible supply of planetary ejaculation that can be transformed</mark> into abstraction and digital data—<mark>into capital.</u></strong></mark> </p>
null
null
1AC
392,178
30
17,027
./documents/ndtceda14/Concordia/SnSh/Concordia-Snelling-Shields-Aff-NDT-Round5.docx
565,183
A
NDT
5
KCKCC GJ
Evans, Denney, Weitz
null
ndtceda14/Concordia/SnSh/Concordia-Snelling-Shields-Aff-NDT-Round5.docx
null
48,434
SnSh
Concordia SnSh
null
Ty.....
Sn.....
No.....
Sh.....
18,762
Concordia
Concordia
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,507
The pornification of the economy is the paradigm for all types of work – addiction stimulated by cycles of sexual excitation and frustration. All bodies become part of the pharmacopornographic circuit, as penetrable or penetrating, as a secretion facilitator or a secretor, or both
Preciado 13
Preciado 13 [Paul (formerly Beatriz), Prof of Political History of the Body, Gender Theory, and History of Performance at Paris VIII, Testo Junkie, trans. Bruce Benderson, p.265-77]
In its capacity as a cinematic industry, the goal of pornography is planetary multimedia masturbation. The pornographic image is characterized by its capacity to stimulate—independently of the spectator’s will—the biochemical and muscular mechanisms that regulate the production of pleasure. Pornography is sexuality transformed into spectacle, virtual, digital information. It is sexuality transformed into public representation, where public refers directly or indirectly to becoming “marketable.” Given the conditions of post-Fordist capitalism, a public representation implies an ability for exchange on the global market in a digital form that can be transformed into capital. A representation acquires pornographic status when it transforms into “public” that which is supposed to remain private. The word pornographic refers to an economic-political characterization of representation. The globalization of the pharmacoporno economy generates a butterfly effect in the global management of the cycles of excitation-frustration-excitation Pornography has the same characteristics as any other spectacle of the culture industry: performance, virtuosity, dramatization, spectacularization, technical reproducibility, digital transformation, and audiovisual distribution. The only difference for the moment rests in its underground status. The relationship of the pornographic industry to the industry of culture and the spectacle is equivalent to the relationship of traffic in illegal drugs to the pharmaceutical industry. It represents two of the covert engines of capitalism of the twenty-first century. it is a marginal and hidden aspect of the contemporary cultural industry, but it is also a paradigm for all other types of post-Fordist production. Within übermaterial capitalism, all forms of production offer benefits to the extent to which they approach the model of pharmacopornographic production. the sex industry reveals the truth about all other aspects of the communications and entertainment industry. Literature, film, television, the Internet, comics, video games, and so on want pornography, wish to produce pleasure and pornographic surplus value without having to suffer the marginalization that comes with pornographic representations, in the same way that contemporary producers of the legal pharmaceutical industry want to produce pleasure and sexual (addiction) and toxicological surplus value without suffering the marginalization and criminalization that come with doing business in illegal drugs. Pornography it reveals that sexuality is always performance, the public practice of a regulated repetition, a staging as well as an involuntary mechanism of connection to the global circuit of excitation-frustration-excitation. Today’s entertainment industry, with its division of representation into categories, such as “G” or “NC- 17” denies the performative value of pornography by reducing it to “hardcore sex,” as if—from a theatrical point of view—there were an ontological difference between a kiss, a brawl, and anal penetration. The current hegemony of the non-pornographic cultural industry stems from this moral axiom that labels organs considered sexual as extra-cinematic objects whose value as “truth” cannot be absorbed by representation and transformed into performance. But behind this hegemony hides the cultural industry’s wish to affect the techno-organic centers of the production of subjectivity with the same efficiency as pornography. The cultural industry is porn envy. Pornography isn’t simply a cultural industry like others; it’s [it is] the paradigm for all cultural industries. Pornography and its closed circuit of excitation-capital-frustration-excitation-capital provide in a particularly clear way a key to understanding any other type of post-Fordist cultural production. the province of sex is not the individual body or the private domain or any domestic space not the individual body, or the space called private, or domestic space escape political regulation. Sex, excitation, the demand for erection and ejaculation are at the center of pharmacopornographic political production and economy. the material process of work depends on a collection of sexual tractions, psychosomatic instincts, hormonal escalations, the establishment of synaptic connections, and the emission of chemical excretions. Sex is work. the object of work is not to satisfy, but to excite: setting in motion the somatic mechanism that regulates the excitation-frustration-excitation cycle. We are working at the porn factory: a technosomatic industry fueled by sperm, blood, urine, adrenalin, testosterone, insulin, silicone, psychostimulants, and estrogens, but also the digitized signs that can be transmitted at high speed, whether number, text, sound, or image. We call the pornification of labor the capture of sex and sexuality by economy, the process by which sex becomes work. The power of drugs, pornographic audiovisual material, sexual services—for the production of capital rests in their ability to function as prostheses of subjectivity. What’s being designed here is the logic of a general pharmacopornographic economy at the heart of which circulate organs, pills, financial codes, communication links, images, texts, jerk-off sessions, liters of silicone, chemical compounds, dollars, and so on. The theorists of this new conception of labor as excitation will no longer be classical economists (Ricardo, Marx, Keynes) but sex workers the crystal lines snaking from fashion runways to television sound stages or to the corridors of the stock exchange, the hundreds of thousands of doses of estrogen and progesterone prescribed for the past forty years as a contraceptive for cis-females of reproductive age, biotech laboratory animals and the ones that are slaughtered by the agrifood industry, the pharaonic volume of antidepressants swallowed by menopausal cis-females, the trafficking of illegal sex workers across European borders, Armstrong’s doping, the liters of sperm poured out each year during the making of porn films, the silent spread of the human immunodeficiency virus, the millions of senior citizens’ stomachs lined with omeprazole, the deaths of teenagers who took part in clinical trials of growth hormone, the syringe that produced the sheep Dolly by insemination, the synthetic guilelessness of weight-lifters’ muscles—these teach us more about current models of capitalist production than do all the classical economic treatises with their obsolete notions of work as mercantile production.
the goal of pornography is planetary multimedia masturbation. The pornographic image is characterized by its capacity to stimulate—independently of the spectator’s will—the biochemical and muscular mechanisms that regulate the production of pleasure. The word pornographic refers to an economic-political characterization of representation. The globalization of the pharmacoporno economy generates a butterfly effect in the global management of the cycles of excitation-frustration-excitation Pornography has the same characteristics as any other spectacle of the culture industry The only difference for the moment rests in its underground status it is a marginal and hidden aspect of the contemporary cultural industry, but it is also a paradigm for all other types of post-Fordist production. Within übermaterial capitalism, all forms of production offer benefits to the extent to which they approach the model of pharmacopornographic production. the sex industry reveals the truth about all other aspects of the communications and entertainment industry. sexuality is always performance, the public practice of a regulated repetition, a staging as well as an involuntary mechanism of connection to the global circuit of excitation-frustration-excitation The current hegemony of the non-pornographic cultural industry stems from this moral axiom that labels organs considered sexual as extra-cinematic objects whose value as “truth” cannot be absorbed by representation and transformed into performance. But behind this hegemony hides the cultural industry’s wish to affect the techno-organic centers of the production of subjectivity with the same efficiency as pornography. The cultural industry is porn envy. Pornography is] the paradigm for all cultural industries Sex, excitation, the demand for erection and ejaculation are at the center of pharmacopornographic political production and economy. the object of work is not to satisfy, but to excite: setting in motion the somatic mechanism that regulates the excitation-frustration-excitation cycle. We are working at the porn factory We call the pornification of labor the capture of sex and sexuality by economy, the process by which sex becomes work. The power of sexual services—for the production of capital rests in their ability to function as prostheses of subjectivity. The theorists of this new conception of labor as excitation will no longer be classical economists (Ricardo, Marx, Keynes) but sex workers the crystal lines snaking from fashion runways to television sound stages teach us more about current models of capitalist production than do all the classical economic treatises with their obsolete notions of work as mercantile production.
1. Pornography is a masturbatory virtual device (literary, audiovisual, cybernetic . . . ). In its capacity as a cinematic industry, the goal of pornography is planetary multimedia masturbation. The pornographic image is characterized by its capacity to stimulate—independently of the spectator’s will—the biochemical and muscular mechanisms that regulate the production of pleasure. Emphasizing the pornographic image’s capacity to become activated in the body of the spectator, Linda Williams defined pornography as “embodied image,” an image that incorporates itself as body and captures the body at the “encounter with an eroticized technological apparatus.”1 2. Pornography is sexuality transformed into spectacle, virtual, digital information. It is sexuality transformed into public representation, where public refers directly or indirectly to becoming “marketable.” Given the conditions of post-Fordist capitalism, a public representation implies an ability for exchange on the global market in a digital form that can be transformed into capital. A representation acquires pornographic status when it transforms into “public” that which is supposed to remain private. Therefore, we will speak of pornography as a device for the publication of the private. Or, even better, a device that, representing part of public space, thereby defines it as private while loading it with an added masturbatory value. The word pornographic refers to an economic-political characterization of representation. 3. Pornography is tele-techno-masturbation. The globalization of the pharmacoporno economy by means of audiovisual digitization and its ultrafast transmission, using a host of technical media (television, computer, telephone, external data storage devices such as pods, pads, etc.), generates a butterfly effect in the global management of the cycles of excitation-frustration-excitation: a pussy opening in one place, a mouth sucking in another, producing hundreds of releasings of pleasure at the other end of the world as their virtual displacement emits a living flow of capital. 4. Pornography has the same characteristics as any other spectacle of the culture industry: performance, virtuosity, dramatization, spectacularization, technical reproducibility, digital transformation, and audiovisual distribution. The only difference for the moment rests in its underground status. The porn producer David Friedman remarked that contemporary pornographic exploitation, conceived as a performative practice and audiovisual consumption, is an extension of the popular circus, the freak shows at fairs, and the amusement parks of the pre-cinematic era.2 Pornography and prostitution could be regarded as fields of the industry of the spectacle, condemned to ostracism and illegality during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. The modification of the aberrant, perverse, or deviant (disabled, freak, homosexual, nymphomaniac, whore . . . ) body from the status of carnival attraction to that of the mentally ill or criminal typical of the disciplinary biopolitical regime will accentuate this process of exclusion from public and economic domains. 5. The relationship of the pornographic industry to the industry of culture and the spectacle is equivalent to the relationship of traffic in illegal drugs to the pharmaceutical industry. It represents two of the covert engines of capitalism of the twenty-first century. Pharmacopornographic production functions on ambivalence: it is a marginal and hidden aspect of the contemporary cultural industry, but it is also a paradigm for all other types of post-Fordist production. Within übermaterial capitalism, all forms of production offer benefits to the extent to which they approach the model of pharmacopornographic production. 6. As an underground sector, the sex industry reveals the truth about all other aspects of the communications and entertainment industry. Literature, film, television, the Internet, comics, video games, and so on want pornography, wish to produce pleasure and pornographic surplus value without having to suffer the marginalization that comes with pornographic representations, in the same way that contemporary producers of the legal pharmaceutical industry want to produce pleasure and sexual (addiction) and toxicological surplus value without suffering the marginalization and criminalization that come with doing business in illegal drugs. 7. In pornography, sex is performance, which is to say that it is composed of public representations and processes of repetition that are socially and politically regulated. Let’s look again at the relationship between the industry of culture and the industry of sex. Judith Butler defined gender, masculinity, and femininity in terms of performances, regulated processes of repetition, norms internalized in the form of bodily style, representation, and public dramatization.3 In a parallel vein, in the 1980s, Annie Sprinkle introduced a new performative shift in the understanding of identity by defining not only gender, but also sexuality, in terms of performance.4 For Sprinkle, the truth of sexuality that pornographic representation claims to capture is merely the effect of a system of representation, an array of corporal choreographies regulated by gender codes of representation that are comparable to those that prevail in dance, traditional cinematic action, and classical theater. It follows that, for Sprinkle, pornography has no empirical or documentary value outside of a given system of representation. 8. The distinctive feature of pornography as image has more to do with issues of scenography, dramatization, and light than with content; it’s enough for a body (whether natural or artificial, “living” or “dead,” human or animal) to be very well lit,5 and as desirable as it is inaccessible, possessing a masturbatory value directly proportional to its ability to act as an abstract and dazzling fantasy. 9. The popular view of pornography as degree zero of representation is based on a sexotranscendental sovereign necro-political principle that we could call “spermatic Platonism,” and for which ejaculation (and death) is the only real thing. Foucault pointed out that sovereign (masculine, theological, monarchic) power was characterized by not the power of giving life but the power of giving death. From that standpoint, snuff is the ontocinematic model of this type of pornographic production: filming the real, the ejaculation, death in real time, and even better, making ontocinematic death and ejaculation coincide. The peculiarity of the dominant form of pornography is its tendency to produce the visual illusion of irruption within the purely real. Pornographic excitation is structured according to the boomerang: pleasure-in-the-desubjectification-of-the-other/pleasure-in-the-desubjectification-of-the-self: watching a subject that can’t control the force of its sexual production (potentia gaudendi) and seeing it at the very moment it renounces that force, to the benefit of an all-powerful spectator (oneself, the person who is watching) who, in turn, and through the representation, sees him- or herself desubjectified, reduced to a masturbatory response. The one watching is pleasured by his or her own process of desubjectification. If we consider the fact that the goal of all pornographic visual material is to make represented ejaculation coincide with the spectator’s ejaculation (understood in the abstract as a cis-male, the universal visual ejaculator), we should be able to conclude that the pleasure of the pornographic eye resides in a cruel contradiction. On one hand, the spectator receives the impression—by means of the desubjectification of the porn actors—that he’s the one who possesses the potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force] of the actors; on the other hand, the body of the spectator is being reduced to an involuntary receiver of ejaculatory stimuli, thereby putting him in a position deprived of any power to make sexual decisions. The distinctive feature of pornographic subjectivity is the visual swallowing of its own sperm, the fact of simultaneously being both a universal erect cock and a universal receiving anus; and this is something that points us toward a pornosophic precept: pornete ipsum. 10. Pornography tells the performative truth about sexuality. It is not the degree zero of representation. Rather, it reveals that sexuality is always performance, the public practice of a regulated repetition, a staging as well as an involuntary mechanism of connection to the global circuit of excitation-frustration-excitation. Today’s entertainment industry, with its division of representation into categories, such as “G” (general audience—all ages admitted) or “NC- 17” (no children under seventeen admitted) denies the performative value of pornography by reducing it to “hardcore sex,” as if—from a theatrical point of view—there were an ontological difference between a kiss, a brawl, and anal penetration. The current hegemony of the non-pornographic cultural industry stems from this moral axiom that labels organs considered sexual (in particular, the cock, pussy, and anus) as extra-cinematic objects (literally ob-scene, or “outside the scene”) whose value as “truth” cannot be absorbed by representation and transformed into performance. But behind this hegemony hides the cultural industry’s wish to affect the techno-organic centers of the production of subjectivity (centers for the production of pleasure, affect, a feeling of omnipotence and comfort) with the same efficiency as pornography. The cultural industry is porn envy. Pornography isn’t simply a cultural industry like others; it’s [it is] the paradigm for all cultural industries.6 Pornography— which sexualizes production and converts the body into information—and its closed circuit of excitation-capital-frustration-excitation-capital provide in a particularly clear way a key to understanding any other type of post-Fordist cultural production. I have no need to remind you—not you, who are reading this book—that the province of sex (and I mean your sex) is not the individual body (your body) or the private domain (your private domain) or any domestic space (your domestic space). That not the individual body, or the space called private, or domestic space escape political regulation. Sex, excitation, the demand for erection and ejaculation are at the center of pharmacopornographic political production and economy. Accordingly, the situation can be defined in the following terms: labor sexus est. In the cyberextended pharmacopornographic city, the material process of work depends on a collection of sexual tractions, psychosomatic instincts, hormonal escalations, the establishment of synaptic connections, and the emission of chemical excretions. Sex is work. Nevertheless, the object of work is not to satisfy, but to excite: setting in motion the somatic mechanism that regulates the excitation-frustration-excitation cycle. We are working at the porn factory: a technosomatic industry fueled by sperm, blood, urine, adrenalin, testosterone, insulin, silicone, psychostimulants, and estrogens, but also the digitized signs that can be transmitted at high speed, whether number, text, sound, or image. We call the pornification of labor the capture of sex and sexuality by economy, the process by which sex becomes work. Thus, in order to understand the praxis of post-Fordist labor, it is necessary to study in detail three domains that, until now, were considered peripheral or marginal to capitalist cycles of production and consumption: 1. The production, trafficking, and consumption of (legal or illegal) drugs. By drug, in this case, I mean what Derrida calls pharmakon: not only every chemical substance of natural or synthetic origin that typically affects the functions of the central nervous system of the living organism, but also, in a larger sense, all biologically active legal or illegal substances that are able to modify the metabolism of the cells on which they work. Texts and visual signs are also pharmakon.7 2. The production, circulation, and consumption of audiovisual pornographic materials. By pornography, I mean, in this case, any sexually active audiovisual technique capable of modifying the sensibility and production of desire, of activating cycles of excitation-frustration and the production of psychosomatic pleasure, in fine, of capturing the body’s system of affect production. 3. Sexual labor. The transformation of a body’s potentia gaudendi into a commodity by a contract (more or less formal) of service. The power of these three platforms—drugs, pornographic audiovisual material, sexual services—for the production of capital rests in their ability to function as prostheses of subjectivity. What’s being designed here is the logic of a general pharmacopornographic economy at the heart of which circulate organs, pills, financial codes, communication links, images, texts, jerk-off sessions, liters of silicone, chemical compounds, dollars, and so on. The theorists of this new conception of labor as excitation will no longer be classical economists (Ricardo, Marx, Keynes) but the pornographers (Candida Royale, Narcis Bosch, Nacho Vidal, HPG, etc.), porn actors and actresses (Annie Sprinkle, Nina Roberts, Coralie Trinh Thi, etc.), sex workers (Michelle Tea, Norma Jane Almodovar, Claire Carthonnet, etc.), and members of drug trafficking networks, from the producers of coke and the state mafias to the impoverished workers on opium plantations, as well as herbalists adept at ancestral traditions of witchcraft, pharmaceutical laboratories, petty traffickers, and junkies. Negri with Rocco Siffredi; Judith Butler with Jenna Jameson. Freud and his hits of coke, the life and death of Escobar, Sartre’s amphetamine consumption, the androgen-antidepressant cocktail now operational for the American soldiers in Iraq, Russian athletes’ cancers after taking high doses of concentrated testosterone in the form of Oral-Turinabol pills, the rise and fall of Linda Lovelace from Deep Throat, the crystal lines snaking from fashion runways to television sound stages or to the corridors of the stock exchange, the hundreds of thousands of doses of estrogen and progesterone prescribed for the past forty years as a contraceptive for cis-females of reproductive age, biotech laboratory animals and the ones that are slaughtered by the agrifood industry, the pharaonic volume of antidepressants swallowed by menopausal cis-females, the trafficking of illegal sex workers across European borders, Armstrong’s doping, the liters of sperm poured out each year during the making of porn films, the silent spread of the human immunodeficiency virus, the millions of senior citizens’ stomachs lined with omeprazole, the deaths of teenagers who took part in clinical trials of growth hormone, the syringe that produced the sheep Dolly by insemination, the synthetic guilelessness of weight-lifters’ muscles—these teach us more about current models of capitalist production than do all the industrial directories of the International Monetary Fund and their trivial indexes of growth or decline in unemployment. The international guide of pharmacological production of Viagra and its underground counterfeiting market will tell us more about the production of excitation-frustration-excitation values in post-Fordist society than will all the classical economic treatises with their obsolete notions of work as mercantile production.
15,564
<h4>The pornification of the economy is the paradigm for all types of work – addiction stimulated by cycles of sexual excitation and frustration. All bodies become part of the pharmacopornographic circuit, as penetrable or penetrating, as a secretion facilitator or a secretor, or both</h4><p><strong>Preciado 13 </strong>[Paul (formerly Beatriz), Prof of Political History of the Body, Gender Theory, and History of Performance at Paris VIII, Testo Junkie, trans. Bruce Benderson, p.265-77]</p><p>1. Pornography is a masturbatory virtual device (literary, audiovisual, cybernetic . . . ). <u><strong>In its capacity as a cinematic industry, <mark>the goal of pornography is planetary multimedia masturbation. The pornographic image is characterized by its capacity to stimulate—independently of the spectator’s will—the biochemical and muscular mechanisms that regulate the production of pleasure.</u></strong></mark> Emphasizing the pornographic image’s capacity to become activated in the body of the spectator, Linda Williams defined pornography as “embodied image,” an image that incorporates itself as body and captures the body at the “encounter with an eroticized technological apparatus.”1 2. <u><strong>Pornography is sexuality transformed into spectacle, virtual, digital information. It is sexuality transformed into public representation, where public refers directly or indirectly to becoming “marketable.” Given the conditions of post-Fordist capitalism, a public representation implies an ability for exchange on the global market in a digital form that can be transformed into capital. A representation acquires pornographic status when it transforms into “public” that which is supposed to remain private.</u></strong> Therefore, we will speak of pornography as a device for the publication of the private. Or, even better, a device that, representing part of public space, thereby defines it as private while loading it with an added masturbatory value. <u><strong><mark>The word pornographic refers to an economic-political characterization of representation.</u></strong></mark> 3. Pornography is tele-techno-masturbation. <u><strong><mark>The globalization of the pharmacoporno economy</u></strong></mark> by means of audiovisual digitization and its ultrafast transmission, using a host of technical media (television, computer, telephone, external data storage devices such as pods, pads, etc.), <u><strong><mark>generates a butterfly effect in the global management of the cycles of excitation-frustration-excitation</u></strong></mark>: a pussy opening in one place, a mouth sucking in another, producing hundreds of releasings of pleasure at the other end of the world as their virtual displacement emits a living flow of capital. 4. <u><strong><mark>Pornography has the same characteristics as any other spectacle of the culture industry</mark>: performance, virtuosity, dramatization, spectacularization, technical reproducibility, digital transformation, and audiovisual distribution. <mark>The only difference for the moment rests in its underground status</mark>.</u></strong> The porn producer David Friedman remarked that contemporary pornographic exploitation, conceived as a performative practice and audiovisual consumption, is an extension of the popular circus, the freak shows at fairs, and the amusement parks of the pre-cinematic era.2 Pornography and prostitution could be regarded as fields of the industry of the spectacle, condemned to ostracism and illegality during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. The modification of the aberrant, perverse, or deviant (disabled, freak, homosexual, nymphomaniac, whore . . . ) body from the status of carnival attraction to that of the mentally ill or criminal typical of the disciplinary biopolitical regime will accentuate this process of exclusion from public and economic domains. 5. <u><strong>The relationship of the pornographic industry to the industry of culture and the spectacle is equivalent to the relationship of traffic in illegal drugs to the pharmaceutical industry. It represents two of the covert engines of capitalism of the twenty-first century.</u></strong> Pharmacopornographic production functions on ambivalence: <u><strong><mark>it is a marginal and hidden aspect of the contemporary cultural industry, but it is also a paradigm for all other types of post-Fordist production. Within übermaterial capitalism, all forms of production offer benefits to the extent to which they approach the model of pharmacopornographic production.</u></strong></mark> 6. As an underground sector, <u><strong><mark>the sex industry reveals the truth about all other aspects of the communications and entertainment industry. </mark>Literature, film, television, the Internet, comics, video games, and so on want pornography, wish to produce pleasure and pornographic surplus value without having to suffer the marginalization that comes with pornographic representations, in the same way that contemporary producers of the legal pharmaceutical industry want to produce pleasure and sexual (addiction) and toxicological surplus value without suffering the marginalization and criminalization that come with doing business in illegal drugs.</u></strong> 7. In pornography, sex is performance, which is to say that it is composed of public representations and processes of repetition that are socially and politically regulated. Let’s look again at the relationship between the industry of culture and the industry of sex. Judith Butler defined gender, masculinity, and femininity in terms of performances, regulated processes of repetition, norms internalized in the form of bodily style, representation, and public dramatization.3 In a parallel vein, in the 1980s, Annie Sprinkle introduced a new performative shift in the understanding of identity by defining not only gender, but also sexuality, in terms of performance.4 For Sprinkle, the truth of sexuality that pornographic representation claims to capture is merely the effect of a system of representation, an array of corporal choreographies regulated by gender codes of representation that are comparable to those that prevail in dance, traditional cinematic action, and classical theater. It follows that, for Sprinkle, pornography has no empirical or documentary value outside of a given system of representation. 8. The distinctive feature of pornography as image has more to do with issues of scenography, dramatization, and light than with content; it’s enough for a body (whether natural or artificial, “living” or “dead,” human or animal) to be very well lit,5 and as desirable as it is inaccessible, possessing a masturbatory value directly proportional to its ability to act as an abstract and dazzling fantasy. 9. The popular view of pornography as degree zero of representation is based on a sexotranscendental sovereign necro-political principle that we could call “spermatic Platonism,” and for which ejaculation (and death) is the only real thing. Foucault pointed out that sovereign (masculine, theological, monarchic) power was characterized by not the power of giving life but the power of giving death. From that standpoint, snuff is the ontocinematic model of this type of pornographic production: filming the real, the ejaculation, death in real time, and even better, making ontocinematic death and ejaculation coincide. The peculiarity of the dominant form of pornography is its tendency to produce the visual illusion of irruption within the purely real. Pornographic excitation is structured according to the boomerang: pleasure-in-the-desubjectification-of-the-other/pleasure-in-the-desubjectification-of-the-self: watching a subject that can’t control the force of its sexual production (potentia gaudendi) and seeing it at the very moment it renounces that force, to the benefit of an all-powerful spectator (oneself, the person who is watching) who, in turn, and through the representation, sees him- or herself desubjectified, reduced to a masturbatory response. The one watching is pleasured by his or her own process of desubjectification. If we consider the fact that the goal of all pornographic visual material is to make represented ejaculation coincide with the spectator’s ejaculation (understood in the abstract as a cis-male, the universal visual ejaculator), we should be able to conclude that the pleasure of the pornographic eye resides in a cruel contradiction. On one hand, the spectator receives the impression—by means of the desubjectification of the porn actors—that he’s the one who possesses the potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force] of the actors; on the other hand, the body of the spectator is being reduced to an involuntary receiver of ejaculatory stimuli, thereby putting him in a position deprived of any power to make sexual decisions. The distinctive feature of pornographic subjectivity is the visual swallowing of its own sperm, the fact of simultaneously being both a universal erect cock and a universal receiving anus; and this is something that points us toward a pornosophic precept: pornete ipsum. 10. <u><strong>Pornography</u></strong> tells the performative truth about sexuality. It is not the degree zero of representation. Rather,<u><strong> it reveals that <mark>sexuality is always performance, the public practice of a regulated repetition, a staging as well as an involuntary mechanism of connection to the global circuit of excitation-frustration-excitation</mark>. Today’s entertainment industry, with its division of representation into categories, such as “G”</u></strong> (general audience—all ages admitted) <u><strong>or “NC- 17”</u></strong> (no children under seventeen admitted) <u><strong>denies the performative value of pornography by reducing it to “hardcore sex,” as if—from a theatrical point of view—there were an ontological difference between a kiss, a brawl, and anal penetration. <mark>The current hegemony of the non-pornographic cultural industry stems from this moral axiom that labels organs considered sexual</u></strong></mark> (in particular, the cock, pussy, and anus) <u><strong><mark>as extra-cinematic objects</mark> </u></strong>(literally ob-scene, or “outside the scene”) <u><strong><mark>whose value as “truth” cannot be absorbed by representation and transformed into performance. But behind this hegemony hides the cultural industry’s wish to affect the techno-organic centers of the production of subjectivity</u></strong></mark> (centers for the production of pleasure, affect, a feeling of omnipotence and comfort) <u><strong><mark>with the same efficiency as pornography. The cultural industry is porn envy. Pornography</mark> isn’t simply a cultural industry like others; it’s [it <mark>is] the paradigm for all cultural industries</mark>.</u></strong>6 <u><strong>Pornography</u></strong>— which sexualizes production and converts the body into information—<u><strong>and its closed circuit of excitation-capital-frustration-excitation-capital provide in a particularly clear way a key to understanding any other type of post-Fordist cultural production.</u></strong> I have no need to remind you—not you, who are reading this book—that <u><strong>the province of sex</u></strong> (and I mean your sex) <u><strong>is not the individual body</u></strong> (your body) <u><strong>or the private domain</u></strong> (your private domain) <u><strong>or any domestic space</u></strong> (your domestic space). That <u><strong>not the individual body, or the space called private, or domestic space escape political regulation. <mark>Sex, excitation, the demand for erection and ejaculation are at the center of pharmacopornographic political production and economy.</u></strong></mark> Accordingly, the situation can be defined in the following terms: labor sexus est. In the cyberextended pharmacopornographic city, <u><strong>the material process of work depends on a collection of sexual tractions, psychosomatic instincts, hormonal escalations, the establishment of synaptic connections, and the emission of chemical excretions. Sex is work.</u></strong> Nevertheless, <u><strong><mark>the object of work is not to satisfy, but to excite: setting in motion the somatic mechanism that regulates the excitation-frustration-excitation cycle. We are working at the porn factory</mark>: a technosomatic industry fueled by sperm, blood, urine, adrenalin, testosterone, insulin, silicone, psychostimulants, and estrogens, but also the digitized signs that can be transmitted at high speed, whether number, text, sound, or image. <mark>We call the pornification of labor the capture of sex and sexuality by economy, the process by which sex becomes work.</u></strong></mark> Thus, in order to understand the praxis of post-Fordist labor, it is necessary to study in detail three domains that, until now, were considered peripheral or marginal to capitalist cycles of production and consumption: 1. The production, trafficking, and consumption of (legal or illegal) drugs. By drug, in this case, I mean what Derrida calls pharmakon: not only every chemical substance of natural or synthetic origin that typically affects the functions of the central nervous system of the living organism, but also, in a larger sense, all biologically active legal or illegal substances that are able to modify the metabolism of the cells on which they work. Texts and visual signs are also pharmakon.7 2. The production, circulation, and consumption of audiovisual pornographic materials. By pornography, I mean, in this case, any sexually active audiovisual technique capable of modifying the sensibility and production of desire, of activating cycles of excitation-frustration and the production of psychosomatic pleasure, in fine, of capturing the body’s system of affect production. 3. Sexual labor. The transformation of a body’s potentia gaudendi into a commodity by a contract (more or less formal) of service. <u><strong><mark>The power of</u></strong></mark> these three platforms—<u><strong>drugs, pornographic audiovisual material, <mark>sexual services—for the production of capital rests in their ability to function as prostheses of subjectivity.</mark> What’s being designed here is the logic of a general pharmacopornographic economy at the heart of which circulate organs, pills, financial codes, communication links, images, texts, jerk-off sessions, liters of silicone, chemical compounds, dollars, and so on. <mark>The theorists of this new conception of labor as excitation will no longer be classical economists (Ricardo, Marx, Keynes) but</mark> </u></strong>the pornographers (Candida Royale, Narcis Bosch, Nacho Vidal, HPG, etc.), porn actors and actresses (Annie Sprinkle, Nina Roberts, Coralie Trinh Thi, etc.), <u><strong><mark>sex workers</u></strong></mark> (Michelle Tea, Norma Jane Almodovar, Claire Carthonnet, etc.), and members of drug trafficking networks, from the producers of coke and the state mafias to the impoverished workers on opium plantations, as well as herbalists adept at ancestral traditions of witchcraft, pharmaceutical laboratories, petty traffickers, and junkies. Negri with Rocco Siffredi; Judith Butler with Jenna Jameson. Freud and his hits of coke, the life and death of Escobar, Sartre’s amphetamine consumption, the androgen-antidepressant cocktail now operational for the American soldiers in Iraq, Russian athletes’ cancers after taking high doses of concentrated testosterone in the form of Oral-Turinabol pills, the rise and fall of Linda Lovelace from Deep Throat, <u><strong><mark>the crystal lines snaking from fashion runways to television sound stages </mark>or to the corridors of the stock exchange, the hundreds of thousands of doses of estrogen and progesterone prescribed for the past forty years as a contraceptive for cis-females of reproductive age, biotech laboratory animals and the ones that are slaughtered by the agrifood industry, the pharaonic volume of antidepressants swallowed by menopausal cis-females, the trafficking of illegal sex workers across European borders, Armstrong’s doping, the liters of sperm poured out each year during the making of porn films, the silent spread of the human immunodeficiency virus, the millions of senior citizens’ stomachs lined with omeprazole, the deaths of teenagers who took part in clinical trials of growth hormone, the syringe that produced the sheep Dolly by insemination, the synthetic guilelessness of weight-lifters’ muscles—these <mark>teach us more about current models of capitalist production than do all the</mark> </u></strong>industrial directories of the International Monetary Fund and their trivial indexes of growth or decline in unemployment. The international guide of pharmacological production of Viagra and its underground counterfeiting market will tell us more about the production of excitation-frustration-excitation values in post-Fordist society than will all the <u><strong><mark>classical economic treatises with their obsolete notions of work as mercantile production.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
1AC
430,241
1
17,027
./documents/ndtceda14/Concordia/SnSh/Concordia-Snelling-Shields-Aff-NDT-Round5.docx
565,183
A
NDT
5
KCKCC GJ
Evans, Denney, Weitz
null
ndtceda14/Concordia/SnSh/Concordia-Snelling-Shields-Aff-NDT-Round5.docx
null
48,434
SnSh
Concordia SnSh
null
Ty.....
Sn.....
No.....
Sh.....
18,762
Concordia
Concordia
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,508
The control of orgasmic power is the basis of extreme violence against those marked as other. All bodies are capable of sucking or being sucked, but lines of gender, race, ability, and humanity position some as global anuses and others as universal penetrators. They become the carnal resource that fuels the engines of post-industrial democracy.
Preciado 13
Preciado 13 [Paul (formerly Beatriz), Prof of Political History of the Body, Gender Theory, and History of Performance at Paris VIII, Testo Junkie, trans. Bruce Benderson, p.46-50]
the market isn’t an outside power coming to expropriate, repress, or control the sexual instincts of the individual. Orgasmic force in its role as the workforce finds itself progressively regulated by a strict techno-biopolitical control. The sexual body is the product of a sexual division of flesh according to which each organ is defined by its function. A sexuality always implies a precise governing of the mouth, hand, anus, vagina. Until recently, the relationship between buying/selling and dependence that united the capitalist to the worker also governed the relationship between the genders, which was conceived as a relationship between the ejaculator and the facilitator of ejaculation. Femininity is the quality of the orgasmic force when it can be converted into merchandise, into an object of economic exchange, into work. a male body can occupy (and in fact already does occupy) a position of female gender in the market of sex work and see its orgasmic power reduced to a capacity for work. The control of orgasmic power not only defines the difference between genders, the female/male dichotomy, it also governs, in a more general way, the techno-biopolitical difference between heterosexuality and homosexuality. The technical restriction of masturbation and the invention of homosexuality as a pathology are of a pair with the composition of a disciplinary regime at the heart of which the collective orgasmic force is put to work as a function of the heterosexual reproduction of the species. Heterosexuality must be understood as a politically assisted procreation technology. But after the 1940s, the moleculized sexual body was introduced into the machinery of capital and forced to mutate its forms of production. Biopolitical conditions change drastically when it becomes possible to derive benefits from masturbation through the mechanism of pornography and the employment of techniques for the control of sexual reproduction by means of contraceptives and artificial insemination. every human or animal, real or virtual, female or male body possesses this masturbatory potentiality, the power to produce molecular joy, and therefore also possesses productive power without being consumed and depleted in the process. Until now, we’ve been aware of the direct relationship between the pornification of the body and the level of oppression. Throughout history, the most pornified bodies have been those of non-human animals, women and children, the racialized bodies of the slave, and the homosexual body. But there is no ontological relationship between anatomy and [orgasmic force] The new hegemonic subject is a body (often codified as male, white, and heterosexual) supplemented pharmacopornographically and a consumer of pauperized sexual services (often in bodies codified as female, childlike, or racialized) Power is located not only in the (“female,” “childlike,” or “nonwhite”) body as a space traditionally imagined as prediscursive and natural, but also in the collection of representations that render it sexual and desirable. the distinctive feature of a body stripped of all legal or political status is that its use is intended as a source of production of potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force]. The distinctive feature of a body reduced to naked technolife, in both democratic societies and fascist regimes, is precisely the power to be the object of maximum pharmacopornographic exploitation. All these bodies are already functioning, in an inexhaustible manner, as carnal and digital sources of ejaculatory capital. For the Aristotelian distinction between zōē and bios we must today substitute the distinction between raw and biotech Biotechnological reality deprived of all civic context (the body of the migrant, the deported, the colonized, the porn actress/ actor, the sex worker, the laboratory animal, etc.) becomes that of the corpus pornographicus whose life lacking any right to citizenship, authorship, and right to work, is composed by and subject to self-surveillance and global mediatization. No need to resort to the dystopian model of the concentration or extermination camp in order to discover naked techno-life, because it’s [is] at the center of postindustrial democracies, forming part of a global, integrated multimedia laboratory-brothel, where the control of the flow of affect begins under the pop form of excitation-frustration.
Orgasmic force finds itself progressively regulated by techno-biopolitical control. The control of orgasmic power defines the difference between genders, the female/male dichotomy, it governs the techno-biopolitical difference between heterosexuality and homosexuality. Biopolitical conditions change drastically when it becomes possible to derive benefits from masturbation through the mechanism of pornography and the employment of techniques for the control of sexual reproduction by means of contraceptives and artificial insemination every human or animal, possesses masturbatory potentiality the power to produce molecular joy the most pornified bodies have been non-human animals, women the racialized bodies of the slave, and the homosexual body The new hegemonic subject is a body (often codified as male, white, and heterosexual) and a consumer of pauperized sexual services (often in bodies codified as female, childlike, or racialized): Power is located not only in the (“female,” or “nonwhite”) body as a space traditionally imagined as prediscursive but also in the collection of representations that render it sexual the feature of a body stripped of all legal or political status is its use is intended as a source of production of [orgasmic force]. The distinctive feature of a body reduced to naked technolife, in both democratic societies and fascist regimes, is precisely the power to be the object of maximum pharmacopornographic exploitation All these bodies are already functioning, in an inexhaustible manner, as carnal and digital sources of ejaculatory capital. Biotechnological reality deprived of all civic context (the body of the migrant, the deported, the colonized, the porn actress/ actor, the sex worker, the laboratory animal, etc.) becomes that of the corpus whose life lacking citizenship, authorship, and right to work, is composed by and subject to self-surveillance and global mediatization. naked techno-life [is] at the center of postindustrial democracies, forming part of a global, integrated multimedia laboratory-brothel, where the control of the flow of affect begins under excitation-frustration.
This theory of “orgasmic force” should not be read through a Hegelian paranoid or Rousseauist utopian/dystopian prism; the market isn’t an outside power coming to expropriate, repress, or control the sexual instincts of the individual. On the other hand, we are being confronted by the most depraved of political situations: the body isn’t aware of its potentia gaudendi as long as it does not put it to work. Orgasmic force in its role as the workforce finds itself progressively regulated by a strict techno-biopolitical control. The sexual body is the product of a sexual division of flesh according to which each organ is defined by its function. A sexuality always implies a precise governing of the mouth, hand, anus, vagina. Until recently, the relationship between buying/selling and dependence that united the capitalist to the worker also governed the relationship between the genders, which was conceived as a relationship between the ejaculator and the facilitator of ejaculation. Femininity, far from being nature, is the quality of the orgasmic force when it can be converted into merchandise, into an object of economic exchange, into work. Obviously, a male body can occupy (and in fact already does occupy) a position of female gender in the market of sex work and, as a result, see its orgasmic power reduced to a capacity for work. The control of orgasmic power (puissance) not only defines the difference between genders, the female/male dichotomy, it also governs, in a more general way, the techno-biopolitical difference between heterosexuality and homosexuality. The technical restriction of masturbation and the invention of homosexuality as a pathology are of a pair with the composition of a disciplinary regime at the heart of which the collective orgasmic force is put to work as a function of the heterosexual reproduction of the species. Heterosexuality must be understood as a politically assisted procreation technology. But after the 1940s, the moleculized sexual body was introduced into the machinery of capital and forced to mutate its forms of production. Biopolitical conditions change drastically when it becomes possible to derive benefits from masturbation through the mechanism of pornography and the employment of techniques for the control of sexual reproduction by means of contraceptives and artificial insemination. If we agree with Marx that “workforce is not actual work carried out but the simple potential or ability for work,” then it must be said that every human or animal, real or virtual, female or male body possesses this masturbatory potentiality, a potentia gaudendi, the power to produce molecular joy, and therefore also possesses productive power without being consumed and depleted in the process. Until now, we’ve been aware of the direct relationship between the pornification of the body and the level of oppression. Throughout history, the most pornified bodies have been those of non-human animals, women and children, the racialized bodies of the slave, the bodies of young workers and the homosexual body. But there is no ontological relationship between anatomy and potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force]. The credit goes to the French writer Michel Houellebecq for having understood how to build a dystopian fable about this new capacity of global capitalism, which has manufactured the megaslut and the megaletch. The new hegemonic subject is a body (often codified as male, white, and heterosexual) supplemented pharmacopornographically (by Viagra, coke, pornography) and a consumer of pauperized sexual services (often in bodies codified as female, childlike, or racialized): “When he can, a westerner works; he often finds his work frustrating or boring, but he pretends to find it interesting: this much is obvious. At the age of fifty, weary of teaching, of math, of everything, I decided to see the world. I had just been divorced for the third time; as far as sex was concerned, I wasn’t expecting much. My first trip was to Thailand, and immediately after that I left for Madagascar. I haven’t fucked a white woman since. I’ve never even felt the desire to do so. Believe me,” he added, placing a firm hand on Lionel’s forearm, “you won’t find a white woman with a soft, submissive, supple, muscular pussy anymore. That’s all gone now.”41 Power is located not only in the (“female,” “childlike,” or “nonwhite”) body as a space traditionally imagined as prediscursive and natural, but also in the collection of representations that render it sexual and desirable. In every case it remains a body that is always pharmacopornographic, a technoliving system that is the effect of a widespread cultural mechanism of representation and production. The goal of contemporary critical theory would be to unravel our condition as pharmacopornographic workers/ consumers. If the current theory of the feminization of labor omits the cum shot, conceals videographic ejaculation behind the screen of cooperative communication, it’s because, unlike Houellebecq, the philosophers of biopolitics prefer not to reveal their position as customers of the global pharmacopornomarket. In the first volume of Homo Sacer, Giorgio Agamben reclaims Walter Benjamin’s concept of the “naked life” in order to define the biopolitical status of the subject after Auschwitz, a subject whose paradigm would be the concentration camp prisoner or the illegal immigrant held in a temporary detention center, reduced to existing only physically and stripped of all legal status or citizenship. To such a notion of the “naked life,” we could add that of the pharmacopornographic life, or naked technolife; the distinctive feature of a body stripped of all legal or political status is that its use is intended as a source of production of potentia gaudendi [orgasmic force]. The distinctive feature of a body reduced to naked technolife, in both democratic societies and fascist regimes, is precisely the power to be the object of maximum pharmacopornographic exploitation. Identical codes of pornographic representation function in the images of the prisoners of Abu Ghraib,42 the eroticized images of Thai adolescents, advertisements for L’Oréal and McDonald’s, and the pages of Hot magazine. All these bodies are already functioning, in an inexhaustible manner, as carnal and digital sources of ejaculatory capital. For the Aristotelian distinction between zōē and bios, between animal life deprived of any intentionality and “exalted” life, that is, life gifted with meaning and self-determination that is a substrate of biopolitical government, we must today substitute the distinction between raw and biotech (biotechnoculturally produced); and the latter term refers to the condition of life in the pharmacopornographic era. Biotechnological reality deprived of all civic context (the body of the migrant, the deported, the colonized, the porn actress/ actor, the sex worker, the laboratory animal, etc.) becomes that of the corpus (and no longer that of homo) pornographicus whose life (a technical condition rather than a purely biological one), lacking any right to citizenship, authorship, and right to work, is composed by and subject to self-surveillance and global mediatization. No need to resort to the dystopian model of the concentration or extermination camp—which are easy to denounce as mechanisms of control— in order to discover naked techno-life, because it’s [is] at the center of postindustrial democracies, forming part of a global, integrated multimedia laboratory-brothel, where the control of the flow of affect begins under the pop form of excitation-frustration. CLIP
7,643
<h4>The control of orgasmic power is the basis of extreme violence against those marked as other. All bodies are capable of sucking or being sucked, but lines of gender, race, ability, and humanity position some as global anuses and others as universal penetrators. They become the carnal resource that fuels the engines of post-industrial democracy.</h4><p><strong>Preciado 13 </strong>[Paul (formerly Beatriz), Prof of Political History of the Body, Gender Theory, and History of Performance at Paris VIII, Testo Junkie, trans. Bruce Benderson, p.46-50]</p><p>This theory of “orgasmic force” should not be read through a Hegelian paranoid or Rousseauist utopian/dystopian prism; <u><strong>the market isn’t an outside power coming to expropriate, repress, or control the sexual instincts of the individual.</u></strong> On the other hand, we are being confronted by the most depraved of political situations: the body isn’t aware of its potentia gaudendi as long as it does not put it to work. <u><strong><mark>Orgasmic force</mark> in its role as the workforce <mark>finds itself progressively regulated by </mark>a strict <mark>techno-biopolitical control.</mark> The sexual body is the product of a sexual division of flesh according to which each organ is defined by its function. A sexuality always implies a precise governing of the mouth, hand, anus, vagina. Until recently, the relationship between buying/selling and dependence that united the capitalist to the worker also governed the relationship between the genders, which was conceived as a relationship between the ejaculator and the facilitator of ejaculation. Femininity</u></strong>, far from being nature, <u><strong>is the quality of the orgasmic force when it can be converted into merchandise, into an object of economic exchange, into work.</u></strong> Obviously, <u><strong>a male body can occupy (and in fact already does occupy) a position of female gender in the market of sex work and</u></strong>, as a result, <u><strong>see its orgasmic power reduced to a capacity for work. <mark>The control of orgasmic power</u></strong></mark> (puissance) <u><strong>not only <mark>defines the difference between genders, the female/male dichotomy, it </mark>also <mark>governs</mark>, in a more general way, <mark>the techno-biopolitical difference between heterosexuality and homosexuality.</mark> The technical restriction of masturbation and the invention of homosexuality as a pathology are of a pair with the composition of a disciplinary regime at the heart of which the collective orgasmic force is put to work as a function of the heterosexual reproduction of the species. Heterosexuality must be understood as a politically assisted procreation technology. But after the 1940s, the moleculized sexual body was introduced into the machinery of capital and forced to mutate its forms of production. <mark>Biopolitical conditions change drastically when it becomes possible to derive benefits from masturbation through the mechanism of pornography and the employment of techniques for the control of sexual reproduction by means of contraceptives and artificial insemination</mark>. </u></strong>If we agree with Marx that “workforce is not actual work carried out but the simple potential or ability for work,” then it must be said that <u><strong><mark>every human or animal, </mark>real or virtual, female or male body <mark>possesses </mark>this <mark>masturbatory potentiality</mark>,</u></strong> a potentia gaudendi, <u><strong><mark>the power to produce molecular joy</mark>, and therefore also possesses productive power without being consumed and depleted in the process. Until now, we’ve been aware of the direct relationship between the pornification of the body and the level of oppression. Throughout history, <mark>the most pornified bodies have been </mark>those of <mark>non-human animals, women </mark>and children, <mark>the racialized bodies of the slave, </u></strong></mark>the bodies of young workers<u><strong> <mark>and the homosexual body</mark>. But there is no ontological relationship between anatomy and </u></strong>potentia gaudendi<u><strong> [orgasmic force]</u></strong>. The credit goes to the French writer Michel Houellebecq for having understood how to build a dystopian fable about this new capacity of global capitalism, which has manufactured the megaslut and the megaletch. <u><strong><mark>The new hegemonic subject is a body (often codified as male, white, and heterosexual)</mark> supplemented pharmacopornographically</u></strong> (by Viagra, coke, pornography) <u><strong><mark>and a consumer of pauperized sexual services (often in bodies codified as female, childlike, or racialized)</u></strong>:</mark> “When he can, a westerner works; he often finds his work frustrating or boring, but he pretends to find it interesting: this much is obvious. At the age of fifty, weary of teaching, of math, of everything, I decided to see the world. I had just been divorced for the third time; as far as sex was concerned, I wasn’t expecting much. My first trip was to Thailand, and immediately after that I left for Madagascar. I haven’t fucked a white woman since. I’ve never even felt the desire to do so. Believe me,” he added, placing a firm hand on Lionel’s forearm, “you won’t find a white woman with a soft, submissive, supple, muscular pussy anymore. That’s all gone now.”41 <u><strong><mark>Power is located not only in the (“female,” </mark>“childlike,” <mark>or “nonwhite”) body as a space traditionally imagined as prediscursive</mark> and natural, <mark>but also in the collection of representations that render it sexual</mark> and desirable.</u></strong> In every case it remains a body that is always pharmacopornographic, a technoliving system that is the effect of a widespread cultural mechanism of representation and production. The goal of contemporary critical theory would be to unravel our condition as pharmacopornographic workers/ consumers. If the current theory of the feminization of labor omits the cum shot, conceals videographic ejaculation behind the screen of cooperative communication, it’s because, unlike Houellebecq, the philosophers of biopolitics prefer not to reveal their position as customers of the global pharmacopornomarket. In the first volume of Homo Sacer, Giorgio Agamben reclaims Walter Benjamin’s concept of the “naked life” in order to define the biopolitical status of the subject after Auschwitz, a subject whose paradigm would be the concentration camp prisoner or the illegal immigrant held in a temporary detention center, reduced to existing only physically and stripped of all legal status or citizenship. To such a notion of the “naked life,” we could add that of the pharmacopornographic life, or naked technolife; <u><strong><mark>the </mark>distinctive <mark>feature of a body stripped of all legal or political status is </mark>that <mark>its use is intended as a source of production of</mark> potentia gaudendi <mark>[orgasmic force]. The distinctive feature of a body reduced to naked technolife, in both democratic societies and fascist regimes, is precisely the power to be the object of maximum pharmacopornographic exploitation</mark>.</u></strong> Identical codes of pornographic representation function in the images of the prisoners of Abu Ghraib,42 the eroticized images of Thai adolescents, advertisements for L’Oréal and McDonald’s, and the pages of Hot magazine. <u><strong><mark>All these bodies are already functioning, in an inexhaustible manner, as carnal and digital sources of ejaculatory capital.</mark> For the Aristotelian distinction between zōē and bios</u></strong>, between animal life deprived of any intentionality and “exalted” life, that is, life gifted with meaning and self-determination that is a substrate of biopolitical government, <u><strong>we must today substitute the distinction between raw and biotech</u></strong> (biotechnoculturally produced); and the latter term refers to the condition of life in the pharmacopornographic era. <u><strong><mark>Biotechnological reality deprived of all civic context (the body of the migrant, the deported, the colonized, the porn actress/ actor, the sex worker, the laboratory animal, etc.) becomes that of the corpus</u></strong></mark> (and no longer that of homo) <u><strong>pornographicus <mark>whose life</u></strong></mark> (a technical condition rather than a purely biological one), <u><strong><mark>lacking </mark>any right to <mark>citizenship, authorship, and right to work, is composed by and subject to self-surveillance and global mediatization.</mark> No need to resort to the dystopian model of the concentration or extermination camp</u></strong>—which are easy to denounce as mechanisms of control— <u><strong>in order to discover <mark>naked techno-life</mark>, because it’s <mark>[is] at the center of postindustrial democracies, forming part of a global, integrated multimedia laboratory-brothel, where the control of the flow of affect begins under </mark>the pop form of <mark>excitation-frustration.</p><p></u></strong></mark>CLIP </p>
null
null
1AC
392,178
30
17,027
./documents/ndtceda14/Concordia/SnSh/Concordia-Snelling-Shields-Aff-NDT-Round5.docx
565,183
A
NDT
5
KCKCC GJ
Evans, Denney, Weitz
null
ndtceda14/Concordia/SnSh/Concordia-Snelling-Shields-Aff-NDT-Round5.docx
null
48,434
SnSh
Concordia SnSh
null
Ty.....
Sn.....
No.....
Sh.....
18,762
Concordia
Concordia
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,509
‘Paul Preciado, a testosterone junkie trans terrorist, calls on us to recognize the sexual monster that resides within ourselves. This is not a call to assimilate sex work and sexual deviance within the structures of normality or the law. Rather, it is a call to disidentify – to de-recognize ourselves as subjects of those systems of social and legal representation that criminalize it. We affirm the “legalization” of prostitution that comes with the de-recognition of its criminalization. This disidentification does not ignore our positionality and embodiment. We are aware of the fact our bodies have marked us for many advantages and shape our ways of being in the world. De-recognition is way of de-naturalizing these bodies—not to claim that we are brothel workers or that we share the experiences of black or trans prostitutes—but to recognize that our bodies are also monstrous techno-political constructions.
Preciado 13 [
Preciado 13 [Paul (formerly Beatriz), Prof of Political History of the Body, Gender Theory, and History of Performance at Paris VIII, Testo Junkie, trans. Bruce Benderson, p.394-8]
The cis-males and cis-females as well as transsexuals, who have access to surgical, endocrinological, or legal techniques of the production of identity, are not simple economic classes in the Marxist sense but genuine “pharmacopornographic factories”—existing simultaneously as raw materials, producers of biocodes of gender, and pharmacopornographic consumers. Porn actors; whores; the transgender; genderqueers; and producers, traffickers, and consumers of illegal drugs inhabit different cultures, but all are used as living pharmacoporn laboratories. All of them sell, buy, or get access to their biocodes as pharmacopornographic property. The sudden emergence of new gender statuses is creating a novel type of conflict between owners and managers of the patents of the microtechnologies of subjectification and the producers and traffickers of these techno-biocodes. The pharmacopornographic entrepreneurs, who are among the contemporary leaders of global capitalism, are trying to restrict and privatize the biocodes of gender and convert them into rare and naturalized objects by means of legal and market techniques. The pharmacopornographic gendercopyleft movement has a technoliving platform the body Not the naked body, or the body as unchanging nature, but the technoliving body as a biopolitical archive and cultural prosthesis. Your memory, your desire, your sensibility, your skin, your cock, your dildo, your blood, your sperm, your vulva, your ova . . . are the tools of a potential gendercopyleft revolution. sex workers are master hackers of gender, genuine traffickers of semiotico-technological flux, producers and tinkers of copyleft biocodes. Gender copyleft strategies must be minor but decisive: the survival of life on the planet is at stake. there will be no single name that can be transformed into a brand. It will be our responsibility to shift the code to open the political practice to multiple possibilities. This book is a protocol for self-tests carried out with testosterone in gel form, exercises of controlled poisoning on my own body. I am infecting myself with a chemical signifier culturally branded as masculine. Vaccinating yourself with testosterone can be a technique of resistance for bodies that have been assigned the status of cis-females. , the administration of testosterone has ceased to be a simple political test and has molted into a discipline, an asceticism, a way of restoring my spirit by means of the down growing on my arms, an addiction, a form of gratification, an escape, a prison, a paradise. Hormones are chemical prostheses. Political drugs. the substance not only modifies the filter through which we decode and recodify the world; it also radically modifies the body and, as a result, the mode under which we are decoded by others. Six months of testosterone, and any cis-female at all, not a should-have-been-boy or a lesbian, but any girl, any neighborhood kid, a Jennifer Lopez or a Rihanna, can become a member of the male species who cannot be told apart from any other member of the hegemonic class. I refuse the medico-political dose, its regime, its regularity, its direction. there is no norm, merely a diversity of viable monstrosities. My gender does not belong to my family or to the state or to the pharmaceutical industry. My gender does not belong to feminism or to the lesbian community or to queer theory. Gender must be torn from the macro-discourse and diluted with a good dose of micropolitical hedonist psychedelics. political subjectivity emerges precisely when the subject does not recognize itself in its representation. It is fundamental not to recognize oneself. De-recognition, disidentification is a condition for the emergence of the political as the possibility of transforming reality. the techniques of political representation always entail programs of the somatic production of subjectivity. I’m not opting for any direct action against representation, but for a micropolitics of disidentification, a kind of experimentation that doesn’t have faith in representation as an exteriority that will bring truth or happiness. In order to accomplish the work of therapy for the multitudes that I have begun with these doses of testosterone and with writing, I now need only to convince you, all of you, that you are like me, and not the opposite. I am not going to claim that I’m like you, your equal, or ask you to allow me to participate in your laws or to admit me as a part of your social normality. My ambition is to convince you that you are like me. Tempted by the same chemical abuse. You have it in you: you think that you’re cis-females, but you take the Pill; or you think you’re cis-males, but you take Viagra; you’re normal, and you take Prozac or Paxil in the hope that something will free you from your problems of decreased vitality, and you’ve shot cortisone and cocaine, taken alcohol and Ritalin and codeine . . . You, you as well, you are the monster that testosterone is awakening in me.
The cis-males and cis-females as well as transsexuals, who have access to surgical, endocrinological, or legal techniques of the production of identity, are not simple economic classes but genuine “pharmacopornographic factories”—existing simultaneously as raw materials, producers and consumers. Porn actors; whores; the transgender; genderqueers all are used as living pharmacoporn laboratories. All of them sell, buy, or get access to their biocodes as pharmacopornographic property. leaders of global capitalism, are trying to restrict and privatize the biocodes of gender and convert them into rare and naturalized objects Your memory, your desire, your sensibility, your skin, your cock, your dildo, your blood, your sperm, your vulva, your ova . . . are the tools of a potential gendercopyleft revolution. sex workers are master hackers of gender producers and tinkers of copyleft biocodes. there will be no single name that can be transformed into a brand. It will be our responsibility to shift the code to open the political practice to multiple possibilities there is no norm, merely a diversity of viable monstrosities My gender does not belong to my family or to the state or to the pharmaceutical industry. My gender does not belong to feminism or to the lesbian community or to queer theory. Gender must be torn from the macro-discourse political subjectivity emerges precisely when the subject does not recognize itself in its representation. It is fundamental not to recognize oneself. De-recognition, disidentification is a condition for the emergence of the political as the possibility of transforming reality. the techniques of political representation always entail programs of the somatic production of subjectivity. I’m opting for a politics of disidentification, a kind of experimentation that doesn’t have faith in representation In order to accomplish the work of therapy for the multitudes that I have begun with these doses of testosterone and with writing, I now need only to convince you, all of you, that you are like me, and not the opposite. I am not going to claim that I’m like you, your equal, or ask you to allow me to participate in your laws or to admit me as a part of your social normality. My ambition is to convince you that you are like me. Tempted by the same chemical abuse. You have it in you: you think that you’re cis-females, but you take the Pill; or you think you’re cis-males, but you take Viagra; you’re normal, and you take Prozac or Paxil in the hope that something will free you from your problems of decreased vitality, and you’ve shot cortisone and cocaine, taken alcohol and Ritalin and codeine . . . You, you as well, you are the monster that testosterone is awakening in me.
The cis-males and cis-females (indiscriminately heterosexual or homosexual), as well as transsexuals, who have access to surgical, endocrinological, or legal techniques of the production of identity, are not simple economic classes in the Marxist sense of the term, but genuine “pharmacopornographic factories”—existing simultaneously as raw materials, producers (but rarely proprietors) of biocodes of gender, and pharmacopornographic consumers. Porn actors; whores; the transgender; genderqueers; and producers, traffickers, and consumers of illegal drugs inhabit different cultures, but all are used as living pharmacoporn laboratories. All of them sell, buy, or get access to their biocodes as pharmacopornographic property. The sudden emergence of new gender statuses is creating a novel type of conflict between owners and managers of the patents of the microtechnologies of subjectification (sex hormones, psychotropic molecules, audiovisual codes, etc.) and the producers and traffickers of these techno-biocodes. The pharmacopornographic entrepreneurs, who are among the contemporary leaders of global capitalism, are trying to restrict and privatize the biocodes of gender and convert them into rare and naturalized objects by means of legal and market techniques. Computer hackers use the web and copyleft programs as tools of free and horizontal distribution of information and claim that they should be in reach of everyone. The pharmacopornographic gendercopyleft movement has a technoliving platform that is a lot easier to gain access to than the Internet: the body, the somathèque. Not the naked body, or the body as unchanging nature, but the technoliving body as a biopolitical archive and cultural prosthesis. Your memory, your desire, your sensibility, your skin, your cock, your dildo, your blood, your sperm, your vulva, your ova . . . are the tools of a potential gendercopyleft revolution. The various producers of sexual biocodes are very different from one another. Some get off on economic and social privileges, such as the models through whose bodies the dominant codes of male and female beauty are produced. Others, such as porn actors or sex workers, suffer from the lack of regulations for the open market of their biocodes. But all of them depend on the pharmacopornographic industry and its local alliances with the police forces of the nation-states. One day, they will all become hackers. Agnes, mother of all the techno-lambs: Del LaGrace Volcano, Kate Bornstein, Jacob Hale, Dean Spade, Mauro Cabral, Susan Stryker, Sandy Stone, King Erik, Moises Martínez— all are master hackers of gender, genuine traffickers of semiotico-technological flux, producers and tinkers of copyleft biocodes. Gender copyleft strategies must be minor but decisive: the survival of life on the planet is at stake. For this movement, there will be no single name that can be transformed into a brand. It will be our responsibility to shift the code to open the political practice to multiple possibilities. We could call this movement, which has already begun, Postporn, Free Fuckware, BodyPunk, OpenGender, FuckYourFather, PentratedState, TotalDrugs, PornTerror, AnalInflation, UnitedUniversalTechnoPriapism . . . This book, a legacy of Agnes’s self-experimentation politics, is a protocol for self-tests carried out with testosterone in gel form, exercises of controlled poisoning on my own body. I am infecting myself with a chemical signifier culturally branded as masculine. Vaccinating yourself with testosterone can be a technique of resistance for bodies that have been assigned the status of cis-females. To acquire a certain political immunity of gender, to get roaring drunk on masculinity, to know that it is possible to look like the hegemonic gender. Little by little, the administration of testosterone has ceased to be a simple political test and has molted into a discipline, an asceticism, a way of restoring my spirit by means of the down growing on my arms, an addiction, a form of gratification, an escape, a prison, a paradise. Hormones are chemical prostheses. Political drugs. In this case, the substance not only modifies the filter through which we decode and recodify the world; it also radically modifies the body and, as a result, the mode under which we are decoded by others. Six months of testosterone, and any cis-female at all, not a should-have-been-boy or a lesbian, but any girl, any neighborhood kid, a Jennifer Lopez or a Rihanna, can become a member of the male species who cannot be told apart from any other member of the hegemonic class. I refuse the medico-political dose, its regime, its regularity, its direction. I demand a virtuosity of gender; to each one, its dose; for each context, its exact requirement. Here, there is no norm, merely a diversity of viable monstrosities. I take testosterone like Walter Benjamin took hashish, Freud cocaine, or Michaux mescaline. And that is not an autobiographical excuse but a radicalization (in the chemical sense of the term) of my theoretical writing. My gender does not belong to my family or to the state or to the pharmaceutical industry. My gender does not belong to feminism or to the lesbian community or to queer theory. Gender must be torn from the macro-discourse and diluted with a good dose of micropolitical hedonist psychedelics. I don’t recognize myself. Not when I’m on T, or when I’m not on T. I’m neither more nor less myself. Contrary to the Lacanian theory of the mirror state, according to which the child’s subjectivity is formed when it recognizes itself for the first time in its specular image, political subjectivity emerges precisely when the subject does not recognize itself in its representation. It is fundamental not to recognize oneself. De-recognition, disidentification is a condition for the emergence of the political as the possibility of transforming reality. The question posed by Deleuze and Guattari in 1972 in Anti-Oedipus remains stuck in our throat: “Why do the masses desire fascism?” It’s not a question here of opposing a politics of representation to a politics of experimentation, but of becoming aware of the fact that the techniques of political representation always entail programs of the somatic production of subjectivity. I’m not opting for any direct action against representation, but for a micropolitics of disidentification, a kind of experimentation that doesn’t have faith in representation as an exteriority that will bring truth or happiness. In order to accomplish the work of therapy for the multitudes that I have begun with these doses of testosterone and with writing, I now need only to convince you, all of you, that you are like me, and not the opposite. I am not going to claim that I’m like you, your equal, or ask you to allow me to participate in your laws or to admit me as a part of your social normality. My ambition is to convince you that you are like me. Tempted by the same chemical abuse. You have it in you: you think that you’re cis-females, but you take the Pill; or you think you’re cis-males, but you take Viagra; you’re normal, and you take Prozac or Paxil in the hope that something will free you from your problems of decreased vitality, and you’ve shot cortisone and cocaine, taken alcohol and Ritalin and codeine . . . You, you as well, you are the monster that testosterone is awakening in me.
7,396
<h4>‘Paul Preciado, a testosterone junkie trans terrorist, calls on us to recognize the sexual monster that resides within ourselves. This is not a call to assimilate sex work and sexual deviance within the structures of normality or the law. Rather, it is a call to disidentify – to de-recognize ourselves as subjects of those systems of social and legal representation that criminalize it. We affirm the “legalization” of prostitution that comes with the de-recognition of its criminalization. This disidentification does not ignore our positionality and embodiment. We are aware of the fact our bodies have marked us for many advantages and shape our ways of being in the world. De-recognition is way of de-naturalizing these bodies—not to claim that we are brothel workers or that we share the experiences of black or trans prostitutes—but to recognize that our bodies are also monstrous techno-political constructions. </h4><p><strong>Preciado 13 [</strong>Paul (formerly Beatriz), Prof of Political History of the Body, Gender Theory, and History of Performance at Paris VIII, Testo Junkie, trans. Bruce Benderson, p.394-8]</p><p><u><strong><mark>The cis-males and cis-females</u></strong></mark> (indiscriminately heterosexual or homosexual), <u><strong><mark>as well as transsexuals, who have access to surgical, endocrinological, or legal techniques of the production of identity, are not simple economic classes</mark> in the Marxist sense</u></strong> of the term, <u><strong><mark>but genuine “pharmacopornographic factories”—existing simultaneously as raw materials, producers</u></strong></mark> (but rarely proprietors) <u><strong>of biocodes of gender, <mark>and</mark> pharmacopornographic <mark>consumers. Porn actors; whores; the transgender; genderqueers</mark>; and producers, traffickers, and consumers of illegal drugs inhabit different cultures, but <mark>all are used as living pharmacoporn laboratories. All of them sell, buy, or get access to their biocodes as pharmacopornographic property.</mark> The sudden emergence of new gender statuses is creating a novel type of conflict between owners and managers of the patents of the microtechnologies of subjectification</u></strong> (sex hormones, psychotropic molecules, audiovisual codes, etc.) <u><strong>and the producers and traffickers of these techno-biocodes. The pharmacopornographic entrepreneurs, who are among the contemporary <mark>leaders of global capitalism, are trying to restrict and privatize the biocodes of gender and convert them into rare and naturalized objects</mark> by means of legal and market techniques.</u></strong> Computer hackers use the web and copyleft programs as tools of free and horizontal distribution of information and claim that they should be in reach of everyone. <u><strong>The pharmacopornographic gendercopyleft movement has a technoliving platform</u></strong> that is a lot easier to gain access to than the Internet: <u><strong>the body</u></strong>, the somathèque. <u><strong>Not the naked body, or the body as unchanging nature, but the technoliving body as a biopolitical archive and cultural prosthesis. <mark>Your memory, your desire, your sensibility, your skin, your cock, your dildo, your blood, your sperm, your vulva, your ova . . . are the tools of a potential gendercopyleft revolution.</u></strong></mark> The various producers of sexual biocodes are very different from one another. Some get off on economic and social privileges, such as the models through whose bodies the dominant codes of male and female beauty are produced. Others, such as porn actors or <u><strong><mark>sex workers</u></strong></mark>, suffer from the lack of regulations for the open market of their biocodes. But all of them depend on the pharmacopornographic industry and its local alliances with the police forces of the nation-states. One day, they will all become hackers. Agnes, mother of all the techno-lambs: Del LaGrace Volcano, Kate Bornstein, Jacob Hale, Dean Spade, Mauro Cabral, Susan Stryker, Sandy Stone, King Erik, Moises Martínez— all <u><strong><mark>are master hackers of gender</mark>, genuine traffickers of semiotico-technological flux, <mark>producers and tinkers of copyleft biocodes. </mark>Gender copyleft strategies must be minor but decisive: the survival of life on the planet is at stake.</u></strong> For this movement, <u><strong><mark>there will be no single name that can be transformed into a brand. It will be our responsibility to shift the code to open the political practice to multiple possibilities</mark>.</u></strong> We could call this movement, which has already begun, Postporn, Free Fuckware, BodyPunk, OpenGender, FuckYourFather, PentratedState, TotalDrugs, PornTerror, AnalInflation, UnitedUniversalTechnoPriapism . . . <u><strong>This book</u></strong>, a legacy of Agnes’s self-experimentation politics, <u><strong>is a protocol for self-tests carried out with testosterone in gel form, exercises of controlled poisoning on my own body. I am infecting myself with a chemical signifier culturally branded as masculine. Vaccinating yourself with testosterone can be a technique of resistance for bodies that have been assigned the status of cis-females. </u></strong>To acquire a certain political immunity of gender, to get roaring drunk on masculinity, to know that it is possible to look like the hegemonic gender. Little by little<u><strong>, the administration of testosterone has ceased to be a simple political test and has molted into a discipline, an asceticism, a way of restoring my spirit by means of the down growing on my arms, an addiction, a form of gratification, an escape, a prison, a paradise. Hormones are chemical prostheses. Political drugs.</u></strong> In this case, <u><strong>the substance not only modifies the filter through which we decode and recodify the world; it also radically modifies the body and, as a result, the mode under which we are decoded by others. Six months of testosterone, and any cis-female at all, not a should-have-been-boy or a lesbian, but any girl, any neighborhood kid, a Jennifer Lopez or a Rihanna, can become a member of the male species who cannot be told apart from any other member of the hegemonic class. I refuse the medico-political dose, its regime, its regularity, its direction.</u></strong> I demand a virtuosity of gender; to each one, its dose; for each context, its exact requirement. Here, <u><strong><mark>there is no norm, merely a diversity of viable monstrosities</mark>.</u></strong> I take testosterone like Walter Benjamin took hashish, Freud cocaine, or Michaux mescaline. And that is not an autobiographical excuse but a radicalization (in the chemical sense of the term) of my theoretical writing. <u><strong><mark>My gender does not belong to my family or to the state or to the pharmaceutical industry. My gender does not belong to feminism or to the lesbian community or to queer theory. Gender must be torn from the macro-discourse</mark> and diluted with a good dose of micropolitical hedonist psychedelics.</u></strong> I don’t recognize myself. Not when I’m on T, or when I’m not on T. I’m neither more nor less myself. Contrary to the Lacanian theory of the mirror state, according to which the child’s subjectivity is formed when it recognizes itself for the first time in its specular image, <u><strong><mark>political subjectivity emerges precisely when the subject does not recognize itself in its representation.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>It is fundamental not to recognize oneself.</mark> <mark>De-recognition, disidentification is a condition for the emergence of the political as the possibility of transforming reality.</u></strong></mark> The question posed by Deleuze and Guattari in 1972 in Anti-Oedipus remains stuck in our throat: “Why do the masses desire fascism?” It’s not a question here of opposing a politics of representation to a politics of experimentation, but of becoming aware of the fact that <u><strong><mark>the techniques of political representation always entail programs of the somatic production of subjectivity. I’m</mark> not <mark>opting for</mark> any direct action against representation, but for <mark>a</mark> micro<mark>politics of disidentification, a kind of experimentation that doesn’t have faith in representation</mark> as an exteriority that will bring truth or happiness. <mark>In order to accomplish the work of therapy for the multitudes that I have begun with these doses of testosterone and with writing, I now need only to convince you, all of you, that you are like me, and not the opposite. I am not going to claim that I’m like you, your equal, or ask you to allow me to participate in your laws or to admit me as a part of your social normality. My ambition is to convince you that you are like me. Tempted by the same chemical abuse. You have it in you: you think that you’re cis-females, but you take the Pill; or you think you’re cis-males, but you take Viagra; you’re normal, and you take Prozac or Paxil in the hope that something will free you from your problems of decreased vitality, and you’ve shot cortisone and cocaine, taken alcohol and Ritalin and codeine . . . You, you as well, you are the monster that testosterone is awakening in me.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
1AC
430,243
45
17,027
./documents/ndtceda14/Concordia/SnSh/Concordia-Snelling-Shields-Aff-NDT-Round5.docx
565,183
A
NDT
5
KCKCC GJ
Evans, Denney, Weitz
null
ndtceda14/Concordia/SnSh/Concordia-Snelling-Shields-Aff-NDT-Round5.docx
null
48,434
SnSh
Concordia SnSh
null
Ty.....
Sn.....
No.....
Sh.....
18,762
Concordia
Concordia
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,510
Disidentification is a reclamation of our bodies as the sites for the production of sexual affect – experimentation outside of normative modes of representation is the only way to resist self-extinction
Preciado 13
Preciado 13 [Paul (formerly Beatriz), Prof of Political History of the Body, Gender Theory, and History of Performance at Paris VIII, Testo Junkie, trans. Bruce Benderson, p.348-53]
The first principle of a trans-feminism movement capable of facing porno-punk modernity: the fact that your body, the body of the multitude and the pharmacopornographic networks that constitute them are political laboratories, both effects of the process of subjection and control and potential spaces for political agency and critical resistance to normalization. I am pleading here for an array of politics of physical experimentation and semiotechnology that will be regulated by the “principle of the auto-guinea pig.” Before all the existing fragile archives about feminism and black, queer, and trans culture have been reduced to a state of radioactive shades, it is indispensible to transform such minority knowledge into collective experimentation, into physical practice, into ways of life and forms of cohabitation. We are no longer pleading for an understanding of life and history as effects of different discursive regimes. We are pleading to use discursive productions as stakeholders in a wider process of the technical materialization of life that is occurring on the planet. A materialization that each day resembles more and more a total technical destruction of all animal, vegetable, and cultural forms of life and that will end, undoubtedly, in the annihilation of the planet and the self-extinction of most of its species. it will become a matter of finding ways to record a planetary suicide. “If you intend to be a doctor, you must try to become a laboratory animal.”14 In order to transform conventional frameworks of the “cultural intelligibility” of human bodies, it is necessary to evolve toward practices of voluntary autointoxication. it seems urgent today, from the perspective of a trans-feminist project, to use our living bodies as biopolitical platforms to test the pharmacopornopolitical effects of synthetic sex hormones in order to create and demarcate new frameworks of cultural intelligibility for gender and sexual subjects. In an era in which pharmaceutical laboratories and corporations and state medico-legal institutions are controlling and regulating the use of gender and sex biocodes as well as chemical prostheses, it seems anachronistic to speak of practices of political representation without going through performative and biotechnological experiments on sexual subjectivity and gender. We must reclaim the right to participate in the construction of biopolitical fictions. We have the right to demand collective and “common” ownership of the biocodes of gender, sex, and race. We must wrest them from private hands, from technocrats and from the pharmacoporn complex. Such a process of resistance and redistribution could be called technosomatic communism. As a mode of the production of “common” knowledge and political transformation, the auto–guinea pig principle would be critical in the construction of the practices and discourses of trans-feminism and the coming liberation movements of gender, sexual, racial, and somatic-political minorities. it will consist of a positioned, responsible corporal political practice, so that anyone wishing to be a political subject will begin by being the lab rat in her or his own laboratory.
your body, the body of the multitude and the pharmacopornographic networks that constitute them are political laboratories Before all the existing fragile archives about feminism and black, queer, and trans culture have been reduced to a state of radioactive shades, it is indispensible to transform such knowledge into collective experimentation, into physical practice, into ways of life and forms of cohabitation We are pleading to use discursive productions as stakeholders in a wider process of the technical materialization of life that is occurring on the planet. A materialization that each day resembles more and more a total technical destruction of all animal, vegetable, and cultural forms of life and that will end in the annihilation of the planet and the self-extinction of most of its species it will become a matter of finding ways to record a planetary suicide it seems urgent today, from the perspective of a trans-feminist project, to use our living bodies as platforms to test to create and demarcate new frameworks of cultural intelligibility for gender and sexual subjects it seems anachronistic to speak of practices of political representation without going through performative and biotechnological experiments on sexual subjectivity We have the right to demand collective and “common” ownership of the biocodes of gender, sex, and race. We must wrest them from private hands, from technocrats and from the pharmacoporn complex a process of resistance and redistribution could be called technosomatic communism. As a mode of the production of “common” knowledge and political transformation, the auto–guinea pig principle would be critical in the construction of the practices and discourses of trans-feminism and the coming liberation movements of gender, sexual, racial, and somatic-political minorities anyone wishing to be a political subject will begin by being the lab rat in her or his own laboratory
The first principle of a trans-feminism movement capable of facing porno-punk modernity: the fact that your body, the body of the multitude and the pharmacopornographic networks that constitute them are political laboratories, both effects of the process of subjection and control and potential spaces for political agency and critical resistance to normalization. I am pleading here for an array of politics of physical experimentation and semiotechnology that (in the face of the principle of political representation, which dominates our social life and is at the core of political mass movements, which can be as totalitarian as they are democratic) will be regulated by the principle that—in accordance with Peter Sloterdijk’s intuitions—I will call the “principle of the auto-guinea pig.”12 In China, in 213 BC, all books were burned by order of the emperor. In the fifth century, after a series of wars had ransacked and decimated the library at Alexandria, it was accused of harboring pagan teachings contrary to the Christian faith and was destroyed by the decree of Emperor Theodosius. The greatest center of research, translation, and reading disappeared. Between 1330 and 1730, thousands of human bodies were burned during the Inquisition, thousands of books were destroyed, and hundreds of works related to the expertise and production of subjectivity were relegated to oblivion or to the underground. In 1813, American soldiers took York (now Toronto) and burned the parliament and legislative library. A year later, the Library of Congress was razed. In 1933, one of the first actions of the Nazi government was the destruction of the Institut für Sexualwissenschaft (Institute for Sexual Research) in Berlin. Created in 1919 by Magnus Hirschfeld, this center had for years played a role in the research and dissemination of progressive ideas and practices concerning sex and sexuality. Twenty thousand books from the Hirschfeld Institute were burned on May 10, 1933, on Opernplatz on a gigantic pyre whose flashing flames were imprinted on the camera film of Hitler’s reporters. On the night of March 9, 1943, an air raid on a library in Aachen destroyed five hundred thousand books. In 1993, Croatian militia destroyed dozens of libraries (among them, those in Stolac). In 2003, American bombs and Saddam loyalists sacked and destroyed the National Library of Baghdad13 . . . The theorico-political innovations produced during the past forty years by feminism, the black liberation movement, and queer and transgender theory do seem to be lasting acquisitions. However, in the context of global war, this collection of scholarship could be destroyed also, as fast as a microchip melting under intense heat. Before all the existing fragile archives about feminism and black, queer, and trans culture have been reduced to a state of radioactive shades, it is indispensible to transform such minority knowledge into collective experimentation, into physical practice, into ways of life and forms of cohabitation. We are no longer pleading, like our predecessors in the 1970s and 1980s, for an understanding of life and history as effects of different discursive regimes. We are pleading to use discursive productions as stakeholders in a wider process of the technical materialization of life that is occurring on the planet. A materialization that each day resembles more and more a total technical destruction of all animal, vegetable, and cultural forms of life and that will end, undoubtedly, in the annihilation of the planet and the self-extinction of most of its species. Alas, it will become a matter of finding ways to record a planetary suicide. Until the end of the eighteenth century, self-experimentation was still a part of the research protocols of pharmacology. Animal experimentation was not yet called into question, but an ethical precept dictated that the researcher take on the risk of unknown effects on his or her own body before enacting any test on the body of another human. Relying on the rhetoric of objectivity, the subject of scientific learning would progressively attempt to generate knowledge outside him- or herself, to exempt his or her body from the agonies of self-experimentation. In 1790, the physician Samuel Hahnemann self-administered strong daily doses of quinine in order to observe its effects in fighting malaria. His body reacted by developing symptoms that resembled the remittent fever characteristic of malaria. The experiment would serve as the basis for the invention of the homeopathic movement, which, based on the law of similars, maintains that it is possible to treat illness using minute doses of a substance that, in much larger amounts, would provoke the same symptoms of that illness in a healthy body, in the manner of a therapeutic mirror. Peter Sloterdijk, inspired by Hahnemann, will call the process of controlled and intentional poisoning “voluntary auto-intoxication” and will sum it up as follows: “If you intend to be a doctor, you must try to become a laboratory animal.”14 In order to transform conventional frameworks of the “cultural intelligibility”15 of human bodies, it is necessary to evolve toward practices of voluntary autointoxication. From Novalis to Ritter, the romanticism from which Sloterdijk draws his inspiration for a counterproject to modernity will make autoexperimentation the central technique of the self in a dystopian society. Nevertheless, romantic autoexperimentation carries the risk of individualism and depolitization. On the other hand, two of the discourses around which the critique of modern European subjectivity will develop—those of Sigmund Freud and Walter Benjamin—will begin under the form of the invention of new techniques of the self and repertories of practices of voluntary intoxication. But the dominant discourse of disciplinary modernity will brush them aside; the process of institutionalization that both psychoanalysis and the Frankfurt School will experience will go hand in hand with the pathologizing of intoxication and the clinical industrialization of experimentation. “It would be a good thing if a doctor were able to test many more drugs on himself,” declared the young doctor Mikhail Bulgakov in 1914, in “Morphine,” a text in which the protagonist describes the effects of morphine on his own body.16 Likewise, it seems urgent today, from the perspective of a trans-feminist project, to use our living bodies as biopolitical platforms to test the pharmacopornopolitical effects of synthetic sex hormones in order to create and demarcate new frameworks of cultural intelligibility for gender and sexual subjects. In an era in which pharmaceutical laboratories and corporations and state medico-legal institutions are controlling and regulating the use of gender and sex biocodes (the active molecules of progesterone, estrogen, and testosterone) as well as chemical prostheses, it seems anachronistic to speak of practices of political representation without going through performative and biotechnological experiments on sexual subjectivity and gender. We must reclaim the right to participate in the construction of biopolitical fictions. We have the right to demand collective and “common” ownership of the biocodes of gender, sex, and race. We must wrest them from private hands, from technocrats and from the pharmacoporn complex. Such a process of resistance and redistribution could be called technosomatic communism. As a mode of the production of “common” knowledge and political transformation, the auto–guinea pig principle would be critical in the construction of the practices and discourses of trans-feminism and the coming liberation movements of gender, sexual, racial, and somatic-political minorities. To echo Donna J. Haraway’s expression, it will consist of a positioned, responsible corporal political practice, so that anyone wishing to be a political subject will begin by being the lab rat in her or his own laboratory.
7,990
<h4>Disidentification is a reclamation of our bodies as the sites for the production of sexual affect – experimentation outside of normative modes of representation is the only way to resist self-extinction</h4><p><strong>Preciado 13 </strong>[Paul (formerly Beatriz), Prof of Political History of the Body, Gender Theory, and History of Performance at Paris VIII, Testo Junkie, trans. Bruce Benderson, p.348-53]</p><p><u><strong>The first principle of a trans-feminism movement capable of facing porno-punk modernity: the fact that <mark>your body, the body of the multitude and the pharmacopornographic networks that constitute them are political laboratories</mark>, both effects of the process of subjection and control and potential spaces for political agency and critical resistance to normalization. I am pleading here for an array of politics of physical experimentation and semiotechnology that</u></strong> (in the face of the principle of political representation, which dominates our social life and is at the core of political mass movements, which can be as totalitarian as they are democratic) <u><strong>will be regulated by the</u></strong> principle that—in accordance with Peter Sloterdijk’s intuitions—I will call the <u><strong>“principle of the auto-guinea pig.”</u></strong>12 In China, in 213 BC, all books were burned by order of the emperor. In the fifth century, after a series of wars had ransacked and decimated the library at Alexandria, it was accused of harboring pagan teachings contrary to the Christian faith and was destroyed by the decree of Emperor Theodosius. The greatest center of research, translation, and reading disappeared. Between 1330 and 1730, thousands of human bodies were burned during the Inquisition, thousands of books were destroyed, and hundreds of works related to the expertise and production of subjectivity were relegated to oblivion or to the underground. In 1813, American soldiers took York (now Toronto) and burned the parliament and legislative library. A year later, the Library of Congress was razed. In 1933, one of the first actions of the Nazi government was the destruction of the Institut für Sexualwissenschaft (Institute for Sexual Research) in Berlin. Created in 1919 by Magnus Hirschfeld, this center had for years played a role in the research and dissemination of progressive ideas and practices concerning sex and sexuality. Twenty thousand books from the Hirschfeld Institute were burned on May 10, 1933, on Opernplatz on a gigantic pyre whose flashing flames were imprinted on the camera film of Hitler’s reporters. On the night of March 9, 1943, an air raid on a library in Aachen destroyed five hundred thousand books. In 1993, Croatian militia destroyed dozens of libraries (among them, those in Stolac). In 2003, American bombs and Saddam loyalists sacked and destroyed the National Library of Baghdad13 . . . The theorico-political innovations produced during the past forty years by feminism, the black liberation movement, and queer and transgender theory do seem to be lasting acquisitions. However, in the context of global war, this collection of scholarship could be destroyed also, as fast as a microchip melting under intense heat. <u><strong><mark>Before all the existing fragile archives about feminism and black, queer, and trans culture have been reduced to a state of radioactive shades, it is indispensible to transform such</mark> minority <mark>knowledge into collective experimentation, into physical practice, into ways of life and forms of cohabitation</mark>. We are no longer pleading</u></strong>, like our predecessors in the 1970s and 1980s, <u><strong>for an understanding of life and history as effects of different discursive regimes. <mark>We are pleading to use discursive productions as stakeholders in a wider process of the technical materialization of life that is occurring on the planet. A materialization that each day resembles more and more a total technical destruction of all animal, vegetable, and cultural forms of life and that will end</mark>, undoubtedly, <mark>in the annihilation of the planet and the self-extinction of most of its species</mark>.</u></strong> Alas, <u><strong><mark>it will become a matter of finding ways to record a planetary suicide</mark>.</u></strong> Until the end of the eighteenth century, self-experimentation was still a part of the research protocols of pharmacology. Animal experimentation was not yet called into question, but an ethical precept dictated that the researcher take on the risk of unknown effects on his or her own body before enacting any test on the body of another human. Relying on the rhetoric of objectivity, the subject of scientific learning would progressively attempt to generate knowledge outside him- or herself, to exempt his or her body from the agonies of self-experimentation. In 1790, the physician Samuel Hahnemann self-administered strong daily doses of quinine in order to observe its effects in fighting malaria. His body reacted by developing symptoms that resembled the remittent fever characteristic of malaria. The experiment would serve as the basis for the invention of the homeopathic movement, which, based on the law of similars, maintains that it is possible to treat illness using minute doses of a substance that, in much larger amounts, would provoke the same symptoms of that illness in a healthy body, in the manner of a therapeutic mirror. Peter Sloterdijk, inspired by Hahnemann, will call the process of controlled and intentional poisoning “voluntary auto-intoxication” and will sum it up as follows: <u><strong>“If you intend to be a doctor, you must try to become a laboratory animal.”14 In order to transform conventional frameworks of the “cultural intelligibility”</u></strong>15 <u><strong>of human bodies, it is necessary to evolve toward practices of voluntary autointoxication.</u></strong> From Novalis to Ritter, the romanticism from which Sloterdijk draws his inspiration for a counterproject to modernity will make autoexperimentation the central technique of the self in a dystopian society. Nevertheless, romantic autoexperimentation carries the risk of individualism and depolitization. On the other hand, two of the discourses around which the critique of modern European subjectivity will develop—those of Sigmund Freud and Walter Benjamin—will begin under the form of the invention of new techniques of the self and repertories of practices of voluntary intoxication. But the dominant discourse of disciplinary modernity will brush them aside; the process of institutionalization that both psychoanalysis and the Frankfurt School will experience will go hand in hand with the pathologizing of intoxication and the clinical industrialization of experimentation. “It would be a good thing if a doctor were able to test many more drugs on himself,” declared the young doctor Mikhail Bulgakov in 1914, in “Morphine,” a text in which the protagonist describes the effects of morphine on his own body.16 Likewise, <u><strong><mark>it seems urgent today, from the perspective of a trans-feminist project, to use our living bodies as</mark> biopolitical <mark>platforms to test</mark> the pharmacopornopolitical effects of synthetic sex hormones in order <mark>to create and demarcate new frameworks of cultural intelligibility for gender and sexual subjects</mark>. In an era in which pharmaceutical laboratories and corporations and state medico-legal institutions are controlling and regulating the use of gender and sex biocodes</u></strong> (the active molecules of progesterone, estrogen, and testosterone) <u><strong>as well as chemical prostheses, <mark>it seems anachronistic to speak of practices of political representation without going through performative and biotechnological experiments on sexual subjectivity </mark>and gender. We must reclaim the right to participate in the construction of biopolitical fictions. <mark>We have the right to demand collective and “common” ownership of the biocodes of gender, sex, and race. We must wrest them from private hands, from technocrats and from the pharmacoporn complex</mark>. Such <mark>a process of resistance and redistribution could be called technosomatic communism. As a mode of the production of “common” knowledge and political transformation, the auto–guinea pig principle would be critical in the construction of the practices and discourses of trans-feminism and the coming liberation movements of gender, sexual, racial, and somatic-political minorities</mark>.</u></strong> To echo Donna J. Haraway’s expression, <u><strong>it will consist of a positioned, responsible corporal political practice, so that <mark>anyone wishing to be a political subject will begin by being the lab rat in her or his own laboratory</mark>.</p></u></strong>
null
null
1AC
314,400
24
17,027
./documents/ndtceda14/Concordia/SnSh/Concordia-Snelling-Shields-Aff-NDT-Round5.docx
565,183
A
NDT
5
KCKCC GJ
Evans, Denney, Weitz
null
ndtceda14/Concordia/SnSh/Concordia-Snelling-Shields-Aff-NDT-Round5.docx
null
48,434
SnSh
Concordia SnSh
null
Ty.....
Sn.....
No.....
Sh.....
18,762
Concordia
Concordia
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,511
Nopper 03 (6)The White Anti-Racist Is an Oxymoron: An Open Letter to “White Anti-Racists” By Tamara K.)
white anti-racism, is predicated on an economy of gratitude. …
Additionally, white activism, especially white anti-racism, is predicated on an economy of gratitude. We are supposed to be grateful that a white person is willing to work with non-white people. … Period. Finally, start thinking of what it would mean, in terms of actual structured social arrangements, for whiteness and white identity--even the white antiracist kind (because there really is no redeemable or reformed white identity)--to be destroyed.
Spillers 78 I would make a distinction in this case between "body" and "flesh" and impose that distinction as the central one between captive and liberated subject-positions… Scott 10 , Extravagant Abjection: Blackness Power and Sexuality in the African American Literary Imagination) In Morrison’s “breakfast” tale this corporeality is rendered “passive.” The black man is kneeling; he is a repository for the white man’s seed; he is a mouth, at best he is merely teeth … But it is a figure suggesting that even in the abject there is something with which to work.
I would make a distinction in this case between "body" and "flesh" and impose that distinction as the central one between captive and liberated subject-positions The black man is he is a repository for the white man’s seed; he is a mouth, at best
Spillers 78 (hortense, “mamas baby, papas maybe”) But I would make a distinction in this case between "body" and "flesh" and impose that distinction as the central one between captive and liberated subject-positions…We might concede, at the very least, that sticks and bricks might break our bones, but words will most certainly kill US. Their claim to disidentify is inaccessible and violent to the black body Scott 10 (Darieck, Extravagant Abjection: Blackness Power and Sexuality in the African American Literary Imagination) In Morrison’s “breakfast” tale this corporeality is rendered “passive.” The black man is kneeling; he is a repository for the white man’s seed; he is a mouth, at best (“best” judged in terms of “action” and “power”) he is merely teeth, an orifice dentata.…The image is not justified by these excessive or ancillary meanings; it does not receive the author’s or the reader’s forgiveness. But it is a figure suggesting that even in the abject there is something with which to work. 1NR Perm Answer Although the radicality of queer futurity may be a method to subvert civil society, it subsists on and reifies the denial of black subjectivity. This is an independent disadvantage. Agathangelou 2013 (Anna M. “Neoliberal Geopolitical Order and Value: Queerness as a Speculative Economy and Anti-Blackness as Terror” in International Feminist Journal of Politics vol. 15 no. 4 p. 469-470) The call to protect the queer from Africans by ‘the West’ in Clinton’s speech and the queer from the savage Muslim in the Human Rights Report, then, is a violence that orders the world, constituting competing formations of value in these projects, while sublimating the empire’s ineluctable terrorization of blackness by analogizing (a major strategy of the redistribution of global and sexual power) the suffering of slaves with that of queers, the colonized subjects and queers, the US and Africa. … Mbembe comments: ‘It is in relation to Africa that the notion of absolute "otherness" has been taken farthest’ (Mbembe2001: 2). Africa not only ‘stands out as the supreme receptacle of the West’s obsession with, and circular discourse about, the facts of “absence”, “lack” and“non-being” of identity and difference’ (Mbembe 2001: 4); it has also been consigned:
2,276
<h4><u><strong>Nopper 03</u> (6)The White Anti-Racist Is an Oxymoron: An Open Letter to “White Anti-Racists” By Tamara K.)</h4><p></strong>Additionally, white activism, especially <u><strong>white anti-racism, is predicated on an economy of gratitude.</u></strong> We are supposed to be grateful that a white person is willing to work with non-white people. <u><strong>…</u></strong> Period. Finally, start thinking of what it would mean, in terms of actual structured social arrangements, for whiteness and white identity--even the white antiracist kind (because there really is no redeemable or reformed white identity)--to be destroyed.</p><p><u><strong>Spillers 78</u></strong> (hortense, “mamas baby, papas maybe”)</p><p>But <u><strong><mark>I would make a distinction in this case between "body" and "flesh" and impose that distinction as the central one between captive and liberated subject-positions</mark>…</u>We might concede, at the very least, that sticks and bricks might break our bones, but words will most certainly kill US.</p><p>Their claim to disidentify is inaccessible and violent to the black body</p><p><u>Scott 10</u></strong> (Darieck<u><strong>, Extravagant Abjection: Blackness Power and Sexuality in the African American Literary Imagination)</p><p>In Morrison’s “breakfast” tale this corporeality is rendered “passive.” <mark>The black man is</mark> kneeling; <mark>he is a repository for the white man’s seed; he is a mouth, at best</u></strong></mark> (“best” judged in terms of “action” and “power”) <u><strong>he is merely teeth</u></strong>, an orifice dentata.<u><strong>…</u></strong>The image is not justified by these excessive or ancillary meanings; it does not receive the author’s or the reader’s forgiveness. <u><strong>But it is a figure suggesting that even in the abject there is something with which to work. </p><p></u>1NR Perm Answer</p><p>Although the radicality of queer futurity may be a method to subvert civil society, it subsists on and reifies the denial of black subjectivity. This is an independent disadvantage.</p><p>Agathangelou 2013 </strong>(Anna M. “Neoliberal Geopolitical Order and Value: Queerness as a Speculative Economy and Anti-Blackness as Terror” in International Feminist Journal of Politics vol. 15 no. 4 p. 469-470)</p><p>The call to protect the queer from Africans by ‘the West’ in Clinton’s speech and the queer from the savage Muslim in the Human Rights Report, then, is a violence that orders the world, constituting competing formations of value in these projects, while sublimating the empire’s ineluctable terrorization of blackness by analogizing (a major strategy of the redistribution of global and sexual power) the suffering of slaves with that of queers, the colonized subjects and queers, the US and Africa. …</p><p>Mbembe comments: ‘It is in relation to Africa that the notion of absolute "otherness" has been taken farthest’ (Mbembe2001: 2). Africa not only ‘stands out as the supreme receptacle of the West’s obsession with, and circular discourse about, the facts of “absence”, “lack” and“non-being” of identity and difference’ (Mbembe 2001: 4); it has also been consigned:</p>
null
null
null
430,244
1
17,050
./documents/ndtceda14/CUNY/AyMc/CUNY-Ayaz-McIntyre-Neg-Ndt-Round4.docx
564,841
N
Ndt
4
Baylor Boor-Barron
Cheek, Denney, Poapst
1AC was an argument about queering and flipping the codes of criminality that are imposed on queer bodies
ndtceda14/CUNY/AyMc/CUNY-Ayaz-McIntyre-Neg-Ndt-Round4.docx
null
48,407
AyMc
CUNY AyMc
null
Ab.....
Ay.....
Al.....
Mc.....
18,756
CUNY
CUNY
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,512
The United States Federal Government should amend the National Organ Transplant Act to permit regulated sale of human organs. A government agency should be established to purchase organs from those living in the United States, with payment in vouchers with a cash value set at an adjusted market-clearing price. Organs should be placed in the Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><strong>The United States Federal Government should amend the National Organ Transplant Act to permit regulated sale of human organs. A government agency should be established to purchase organs from those living in the United States, with payment in vouchers with a cash value set at an adjusted market-clearing price. Organs should be placed in the Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network.</h4></strong>
null
null
null
430,242
1
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,513
The ban on organ sales has created a large and growing shortage
Williams 14
Williams 14 Kristy L. Williams, University of Houston Law Center, Health Law & Policy Institute; University of Texas Medical Branch, Institute of Medical Humanities.; Marisa Finley, Baylor Scott & White Health Center for Health Care Policy; J. James Rohack, Baylor Scott & White Health March 31, 2014 American Journal of Law and Medicine, Forthcoming Just Say No to NOTA: Why the Prohibition of Compensation for Human Transplant Organs in NOTA Should Be Repealed and a Regulated Market for Cadaver
Organ transplantation saves thousands of lives every year. However, many individuals die waiting for transplants due to an insufficiency of organs Currently, more than 122,000 individuals are waitlisted for organs in the U S Due to financial and other barriers to becoming waitlisted, the actual number requiring organs is likely higher This gap between available organs and the need for organs continues to widen The supply of organs is limited as only a small number of individuals die in circumstances medically eligible for organ donation, The current organ donation system in the United States relies on the altruism of donors. The (NOTA) prohibits the receipt of any form of valuable consideration in exchange for organs to be used for transplantation other methods have been employed in attempts to increase donations Despite the implementation of these strategies, a severe organ shortage remains
many die waiting for transplants due to an insufficiency of organs more than 122,000 are waitlisted Due to other barriers actual number of requiring organs is likely higher.3 This gap continues to widen. NOTA) prohibits valuable consideration in exchange for organs for transplantation other methods have been employed in attempts to increase donations.9 Despite these , a severe organ shortage remains
Organs Instituted http://ssrn.com/abstract=2418514 Organ transplantation saves thousands of lives every year. However, many individuals die waiting for transplants due to an insufficiency of organs.1 Currently, more than 122,000 individuals are waitlisted for organs in the United States.2 Due to financial and other barriers to becoming waitlisted, the actual number of Americans requiring organs is likely higher.3 This gap between available organs and the need for organs continues to widen.4 The supply of organs is limited as only a small number of individuals die in circumstances medically eligible for organ donation, and less than sixty-eight percent of eligible individuals donate.5 As a result of those long waitlists and limited supply there is a substantial need to increase organ donations. This paper will focus on increasing consent rates for cadaveric organ donation in the Unites States by repealing current law prohibiting cadaveric donors and their estates from being financially compensated.6 The current organ donation system in the United States relies on the altruism of donors. The National Organ Transplantation Act (NOTA) prohibits the receipt of any form of valuable consideration in exchange for organs to be used for transplantation.7 State statutes also prohibit the sale of certain organs and tissue for transplantation; however, state laws vary widely as to what body parts are covered.8 As paying for organs is prohibited, other methods have been employed in attempts to increase donations.9 Despite the implementation of these strategies, a severe organ shortage remains.
1,611
<h4>The ban on organ sales has created a large and growing shortage</h4><p><strong>Williams 14</strong> Kristy L. Williams, University of Houston Law Center, Health Law & Policy Institute; University of Texas Medical Branch, Institute of Medical Humanities.; Marisa Finley, Baylor Scott & White Health Center for Health Care Policy; J. James Rohack, Baylor Scott & White Health March 31, 2014 American Journal of Law and Medicine, Forthcoming Just Say No to NOTA: Why the Prohibition of Compensation for Human Transplant Organs in NOTA Should Be Repealed and a Regulated Market for Cadaver </p><p>Organs Instituted http://ssrn.com/abstract=2418514</p><p><u>Organ transplantation saves thousands of lives every year. However, <mark>many</mark> individuals <mark>die waiting for transplants due to an insufficiency of organs</u></mark>.1 <u>Currently, <mark>more than</mark> <mark>122,000 </mark>individuals <mark>are waitlisted</mark> for organs in the U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates.2 <u><mark>Due to</mark> financial and <mark>other barriers</mark> to becoming waitlisted, the <mark>actual number </u>of</mark> Americans <u><mark>requiring organs is</mark> <mark>likely higher</u>.3</mark> <u><mark>This gap</mark> between available organs and the need for organs <mark>continues to widen</u>.</mark>4 <u>The supply of organs is limited as only a small number of individuals die in circumstances medically eligible for organ donation, </u>and less than sixty-eight percent of eligible individuals donate.5 As a result of those long waitlists and limited supply there is a substantial need to increase organ donations. This paper will focus on increasing consent rates for cadaveric organ donation in the Unites States by repealing current law prohibiting cadaveric donors and their estates from being financially compensated.6 <u>The current organ donation system in the United States relies on the altruism of donors. The</u> National Organ Transplantation Act <u>(<mark>NOTA) prohibits</mark> the receipt of any form of <mark>valuable consideration in exchange for organs</mark> to be used <mark>for transplantation</u></mark>.7 State statutes also prohibit the sale of certain organs and tissue for transplantation; however, state laws vary widely as to what body parts are covered.8 As paying for organs is prohibited, <u><mark>other methods have been</mark> <mark>employed in attempts to increase donations</u>.9 <u>Despite</mark> the implementation of <mark>these</mark> strategies<mark>, a severe organ shortage remains</u></mark>.</p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Shortage
430,245
16
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,514
voluntary donations fail – individually and in combination
Beard 8
Beard 8 T.RANDOLPH BEARD, JOHN D. JACKSON , AND DAVID L. KASERMAN, profs of economics, Auburn University Winter 2008 Regulation The Failure of US 'Organ Procurement Policy
the transplant industry has examined and adopted a series of policy options ostensibly designed to improve the system’s performance. All of these, however, continue to maintain the basic zero-price property of the altruistic system. As a result, the likelihood that any of them, even in combination, will resolve the organ shortage is remote At least seven such actions have been implemented INCREASED EDUCATIONAL EXPENDITURES ORGAN DONOR CARDS incorporating organ donor cards on states’ driver licenses. REQUIRED REQUEST Some federal legislation requiring all hospitals to request organ donation REQUIRED REFERRAL additional legislation to refer potential organ donors COLLABORATION the Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative,” ■ KIDNEY EXCHANGES REIMBURSEMENT OF DONOR COSTS Finally, i legislation authorizing reimbursement of any direct costs incurred by onors We must conclude that none of the policies should be expected to resolve the transplant organ shortage. . Rather, every time another one of these marginalist policies is devised, it delays the only real reform that is capable of fully resolving the organ shortage
transplant industry adopted policy options designed to improve the system’s performance. All of these, maintain the altruistic system. As a result, the likelihood that any of them, even in combination, will resolve the organ shortage is remo seven actions have been implemented INCREASED EDUCATIONAL EXPENDITURES ORGAN DONOR CARDS REQUIRED REQUEST REQUIRED REFERRAL OLLABORATION Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative KIDNEY EXCHANGES REIMBURSEMENT OF DONOR COSTS none of the policies resolve the transplant shortage it delays the only real reform that is capable of fully resolving the organ shortage.
http://object.cato.org/sites/cato.org/files/serials/files/regulation/2007/12/v30n4-3.pdf Aware of the increasingly dire consequences of continued reliance on the existing approach to cadaveric organ procurement and alarmed at the figures shown above, the transplant industry has examined and adopted a series of policy options ostensibly designed to improve the system’s performance. All of these, however, continue to maintain the basic zero-price property of the altruistic system. As a result, the likelihood that any of them, even in combination, will resolve the organ shortage is remote. At least seven such actions have been implemented over the last two decades or so: ■ INCREASED EDUCATIONAL EXPENDITURES In the absence of financial incentives, moral suasion becomes the principal avenue through which additional supply may be motivated. Consequently, the organ procurement organizations (opos) created under the 1984 Act have launched substantial promotional campaigns. The campaigns have been designed to both educate the general public about the desperate need for donated organs and educate physicians and critical care hospital staff regarding the identification of potential deceased donors. Over the years, a substantial sum has been spent on these types of educational activities. Recent empirical evidence, however, suggests that further spending on these programs is unlikely to increase supply by a significant amount. ■ ORGAN DONOR CARDS A related activity has been the process of incorporating organ donor cards on states’ driver licenses. The cards can be easily completed and witnessed at the time the licenses are issued or renewed. They serve as a pre-mortem statement of the bearer’s wish to have his or her organs removed for transplantation purposes at the time of death. Their principal use, in practice, is to facilitate the opos’ efforts to convince surviving family members to consent to such removal by revealing the decedant’s wishes. The 1968 Uniform Anatomical Gift Act gave all states the authority to issue donor cards and incorporate them in drivers’ licenses. Moreover, a few states have recently begun to rely entirely on donor cards to infer consent without requiring the surviving family’s permission when such cards are present. Survey evidence indicates that less than 40 percent of U.S. citizens have signed their donor cards. ■ REQUIRED REQUEST Some survey evidence published in the late 1980s and early 1990s found that in a number of cases families of potential deceased donors were not being asked to donate the organs. As a result, donation was apparently failing to occur in some of those instances simply because the request was not being presented. In response to this evidence, federal legislation was passed in 1987 requiring all hospitals receiving any federal funding (which, of course, is virtually all hospitals) to request organ donation in all deaths that occur under circumstances that would allow the deceased’s organs to be used in transplantation. It appears that this legal obligation is now being met in most, if not all, cases. Yet, the organ shortage has persisted and the waiting list has continued to grow. ■ REQUIRED REFERRAL While required-request legislation can compel hospitals to approach the families of recently deceased potential organ donors with an appeal for donation, it cannot ensure that the request will be made in a sincere, compassionate manner likely to elicit an agreement. Following implementation of the required-request law, there were a number of anecdotes in which the compulsory organ donation requests were presented in an insincere or even offensive manner that was clearly intended to elicit a negative response. The letter of the law was being met but not the spirit. As a result, additional legislation was passed that requires hospitals to refer potential organ donors to the regional opo so that trained procurement personnel can approach the surviving family with the donation request. This policy response has resulted in no perceptible progress in resolving the shortage. ■ COLLABORATION A fairly recent response to the organ shortage has been the so-called “Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative,” which was championed by then-secretary of health and human services Tommy Thompson. The program was initiated shortly after Thompson took office in 2001 and is currently continuing. The program’s basic motivation is provided by the observation of a considerable degree of variation in performance across the existing opos. Specifically, the number of deceased organ donors per thousand hospital deaths has been found to vary by a factor of almost five across the organizations. The presumption, then, is that the relatively successful opos employ superior procurement techniques and/or knowledge that, if shared with the relatively unsuccessful organizations, would significantly improve their performance. Thus, diffusion of “best practice” techniques is seen as a promising method through which cadaveric donation rates may be greatly improved. A thorough and objective evaluation of the Thompson initiative has not, to our knowledge, been conducted. Figure 1, in conjunction with a recent econometric study of observed variations in opo efficiency, suggests that such an evaluation would yield both good news and bad news. The good news is that the program appears to have had a positive (and potentially significant) impact on the number of donations. In particular, it appears that, after 2002, the growth rate of the waiting list has slowed somewhat. Whether this effect will permanently lower the growth rate of the waiting list or simply cause a temporary intercept shift remains to be seen. The bad news, however, is unequivocal— the initiative is not going to resolve the organ shortage. Even if, contrary to reasonable expectations, all opo relative inefficiencies were miraculously eliminated (i.e., if al organizations’ performance were brought up to the most efficient unit), the increase in donor collection rates would still be insufficient to eliminate the shortage. ■ KIDNEY EXCHANGES Another approach that has received some attention recently involves the exchange of kidneys between families who have willing but incompatible living donors. Suppose, for example, a person in one family needs a kidney transplant and a sibling has offered to donate the needed organ. Further suppose that the two siblings are not compatible — perhaps their blood types differ. If this family can locate a second, similarly situated family, then it may be possible that the donor in the first family will match the recipient in the second, and vice versa. A relatively small number of such exchanges have recently occurred and a unos-based computerized system of matching such interfamily donors has been proposed to facilitate a larger number of these living donor transactions. Two observations regarding kidney exchanges are worth noting. First, such exchanges obviously constitute a crude type of market in living donor kidneys that is based upon barter rather than currency. Like all such barter markets, this exchange will be considerably less efficient than currency-based trade. Puzzlingly, some of the staunchest critics of using financial incentives for cadaveric donors have openly supported expanded use of living donor exchanges. Apparently, it is not market exchange per se that offends them but, rather, the use of money to facilitate efficient market exchange. This combination of positions merely highlights the critics’ lack of knowledge regarding the operation of market processes. It is quite apparent that living donor kidney exchanges are not going to resolve the organ shortage. Opportunities for such barter-based exchanges are simply too limited. ■ REIMBURSEMENT OF DONOR COSTS Finally, in another effort to encourage an increase in the number of living (primarily kidney) donors, several states have passed legislation authorizing reimbursement of any direct (explicit) costs incurred by such donors (e.g., travel expenses, lost wages, and so on). Economically, this policy action raises the price paid to living kidney donors from a negative amount to zero. As such, it should be expected to increase the quantity of organs supplied from this source. Because the explicit, out-of-pocket expenses associated with live kidney donation are unlikely to be large relative to the longer-term implicit costs of potential health risks, however, such reimbursement should not be expected to bring forth a flood of new donors. Moreover, recent empirical evidence suggests that an increase in the number of living donors may have a negative impact on the number of deceased donors because of some degree of supply-side substitutability. Again, this policy is not a solution to the organ shortage. We must conclude that none of the above-listed policies should be expected to resolve the transplant organ shortage. We say this not because we oppose any of these policies; indeed, each appears sensible in its own right and some have unquestionably succeeded in raising the number of organ donors by some (perhaps nontrivial) amount. Rather, our concern is that every time another one of these marginalist policies is devised, it delays the only real reform that is capable of fully resolving the organ shortage.
9,339
<h4>voluntary donations fail – individually and in combination </h4><p><strong>Beard 8</strong> T.RANDOLPH BEARD, JOHN D. JACKSON , AND DAVID L. KASERMAN, profs of economics, Auburn University Winter 2008 Regulation The Failure of US 'Organ Procurement Policy</p><p>http://object.cato.org/sites/cato.org/files/serials/files/regulation/2007/12/v30n4-3.pdf</p><p> Aware of the increasingly dire consequences of continued reliance on the existing approach to cadaveric organ procurement and alarmed at the figures shown above, <u>the <mark>transplant industry</mark> has examined and <mark>adopted</mark> a series of <mark>policy options</mark> ostensibly <mark>designed to improve the system’s performance. All of these,</mark> however, continue to <mark>maintain the</mark> basic zero-price property of the <mark>altruistic system. As a result, the likelihood that any of them, even in combination, will resolve the organ shortage is remo</mark>te</u>. <u>At least <mark>seven</mark> such <mark>actions have been</mark> <mark>implemented</u></mark> over the last two decades or so: ■ <u><mark>INCREASED EDUCATIONAL EXPENDITURES</u></mark> In the absence of financial incentives, moral suasion becomes the principal avenue through which additional supply may be motivated. Consequently, the organ procurement organizations (opos) created under the 1984 Act have launched substantial promotional campaigns. The campaigns have been designed to both educate the general public about the desperate need for donated organs and educate physicians and critical care hospital staff regarding the identification of potential deceased donors. Over the years, a substantial sum has been spent on these types of educational activities. Recent empirical evidence, however, suggests that further spending on these programs is unlikely to increase supply by a significant amount. ■ <u><mark>ORGAN DONOR CARDS</u></mark> A related activity has been the process of <u>incorporating organ donor cards on states’ driver licenses.</u> The cards can be easily completed and witnessed at the time the licenses are issued or renewed. They serve as a pre-mortem statement of the bearer’s wish to have his or her organs removed for transplantation purposes at the time of death. Their principal use, in practice, is to facilitate the opos’ efforts to convince surviving family members to consent to such removal by revealing the decedant’s wishes. The 1968 Uniform Anatomical Gift Act gave all states the authority to issue donor cards and incorporate them in drivers’ licenses. Moreover, a few states have recently begun to rely entirely on donor cards to infer consent without requiring the surviving family’s permission when such cards are present. Survey evidence indicates that less than 40 percent of U.S. citizens have signed their donor cards.<u> </u>■ <u><mark>REQUIRED REQUEST</mark> Some</u> survey evidence published in the late 1980s and early 1990s found that in a number of cases families of potential deceased donors were not being asked to donate the organs. As a result, donation was apparently failing to occur in some of those instances simply because the request was not being presented. In response to this evidence, <u>federal legislation</u> was passed in 1987 <u>requiring all hospitals</u> receiving any federal funding (which, of course, is virtually all hospitals) <u>to request organ donation</u> in all deaths that occur under circumstances that would allow the deceased’s organs to be used in transplantation. It appears that this legal obligation is now being met in most, if not all, cases. Yet, the organ shortage has persisted and the waiting list has continued to grow. ■ <u><mark>REQUIRED REFERRAL</u></mark> While required-request legislation can compel hospitals to approach the families of recently deceased potential organ donors with an appeal for donation, it cannot ensure that the request will be made in a sincere, compassionate manner likely to elicit an agreement. Following implementation of the required-request law, there were a number of anecdotes in which the compulsory organ donation requests were presented in an insincere or even offensive manner that was clearly intended to elicit a negative response. The letter of the law was being met but not the spirit. As a result, <u>additional legislation</u> was passed that requires hospitals<u> to refer potential organ donors </u>to the regional opo so that trained procurement personnel can approach the surviving family with the donation request. This policy response has resulted in no perceptible progress in resolving the shortage. ■ <u>C<mark>OLLABORATION</mark> </u>A fairly recent response to the organ shortage has been <u>the </u>so-called “<u><mark>Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative</mark>,” </u>which was championed by then-secretary of health and human services Tommy Thompson. The program was initiated shortly after Thompson took office in 2001 and is currently continuing. The program’s basic motivation is provided by the observation of a considerable degree of variation in performance across the existing opos. Specifically, the number of deceased organ donors per thousand hospital deaths has been found to vary by a factor of almost five across the organizations. The presumption, then, is that the relatively successful opos employ superior procurement techniques and/or knowledge that, if shared with the relatively unsuccessful organizations, would significantly improve their performance. Thus, diffusion of “best practice” techniques is seen as a promising method through which cadaveric donation rates may be greatly improved. A thorough and objective evaluation of the Thompson initiative has not, to our knowledge, been conducted. Figure 1, in conjunction with a recent econometric study of observed variations in opo efficiency, suggests that such an evaluation would yield both good news and bad news. The good news is that the program appears to have had a positive (and potentially significant) impact on the number of donations. In particular, it appears that, after 2002, the growth rate of the waiting list has slowed somewhat. Whether this effect will permanently lower the growth rate of the waiting list or simply cause a temporary intercept shift remains to be seen. The bad news, however, is unequivocal— the initiative is not going to resolve the organ shortage. Even if, contrary to reasonable expectations, all opo relative inefficiencies were miraculously eliminated (i.e., if al organizations’ performance were brought up to the most efficient unit), the increase in donor collection rates would still be insufficient to eliminate the shortage. <u>■ <mark>KIDNEY</mark> <mark>EXCHANGES</u></mark> Another approach that has received some attention recently involves the exchange of kidneys between families who have willing but incompatible living donors. Suppose, for example, a person in one family needs a kidney transplant and a sibling has offered to donate the needed organ. Further suppose that the two siblings are not compatible — perhaps their blood types differ. If this family can locate a second, similarly situated family, then it may be possible that the donor in the first family will match the recipient in the second, and vice versa. A relatively small number of such exchanges have recently occurred and a unos-based computerized system of matching such interfamily donors has been proposed to facilitate a larger number of these living donor transactions. Two observations regarding kidney exchanges are worth noting. First, such exchanges obviously constitute a crude type of market in living donor kidneys that is based upon barter rather than currency. Like all such barter markets, this exchange will be considerably less efficient than currency-based trade. Puzzlingly, some of the staunchest critics of using financial incentives for cadaveric donors have openly supported expanded use of living donor exchanges. Apparently, it is not market exchange per se that offends them but, rather, the use of money to facilitate efficient market exchange. This combination of positions merely highlights the critics’ lack of knowledge regarding the operation of market processes. It is quite apparent that living donor kidney exchanges are not going to resolve the organ shortage. Opportunities for such barter-based exchanges are simply too limited. ■ <u><mark>REIMBURSEMENT OF DONOR COSTS</u></mark> <u>Finally, i</u>n another effort to encourage an increase in the number of living (primarily kidney) donors, several states have passed <u>legislation authorizing reimbursement of any direct </u>(explicit) <u>costs incurred by</u> such d<u>onors </u>(e.g., travel expenses, lost wages, and so on). Economically, this policy action raises the price paid to living kidney donors from a negative amount to zero. As such, it should be expected to increase the quantity of organs supplied from this source. Because the explicit, out-of-pocket expenses associated with live kidney donation are unlikely to be large relative to the longer-term implicit costs of potential health risks, however, such reimbursement should not be expected to bring forth a flood of new donors. Moreover, recent empirical evidence suggests that an increase in the number of living donors may have a negative impact on the number of deceased donors because of some degree of supply-side substitutability. Again, this policy is not a solution to the organ shortage. <u>We must conclude that <mark>none of the</u></mark> above-listed <u><mark>policies</mark> should be expected to <mark>resolve the transplant</mark> organ <mark>shortage</mark>.</u> We say this not because we oppose any of these policies; indeed, each appears sensible in its own right and some have unquestionably succeeded in raising the number of organ donors by some (perhaps nontrivial) amount<u>. Rather,</u> our concern is that <u>every time another one of these marginalist policies is devised, <mark>it delays the only real reform that is capable of fully resolving the organ shortage</u>.</p></mark>
null
null
Contention 1 – Shortage
430,246
21
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,515
The shortage means many die
Beard 8
Beard 8 T.RANDOLPH BEARD, JOHN D. JACKSON , AND DAVID L. KASERMAN, profs of economics, Auburn University Winter 2008 Regulation The Failure of US 'Organ Procurement Policy
our failure to adapt our organ procurement policy suggests that more than 80,000 lives have now been sacrificed on the altar of our so-called “altruistic” system. In addition, the unnecessary pain and suffering of those who have been forced to wait while undergoing dialysis, unemployment, and declining health must also be reckoned along with the growing despair of family members who must witness all of this. Nonetheless, the pain, suffering, and death imposed on the innocents thus far pales in comparison to what lies ahead if more fundamental change is not forthcoming we are able to produce forecasts of the expected size of future waiting lists We run the forecasts out 10 years a cumulative total of 196,310 patients are conservatively expected to die by 2015 as a consequence of the ongoing shortage.
failure to adapt organ procurement suggests more than 80,000 lives have been sacrificed of our so-called “altruistic” system the pain and suffering of those forced to wait unemployment, and declining health must be reckoned Nonetheless, the death imposed pales in comparison to what lies ahead if change is not forthcoming we are able to produce forecasts of the expected size of future waiting lists 196,310 patients are conservatively expected to die by 2015 as a consequence of the ongoing shortage.
http://object.cato.org/sites/cato.org/files/serials/files/regulation/2007/12/v30n4-3.pdf WAITING LISTS YET TO COME The consequences of our failure to adapt our cadaveric organ procurement policy to the changed technological realities of the transplant industry have been unconscionable. Figure 2, above, suggests that more than 80,000 lives have now been sacrificed on the altar of our so-called “altruistic” system. In addition, the unnecessary pain and suffering of those who have been forced to wait while undergoing dialysis, unemployment, and declining health must also be reckoned along with the growing despair of family members who must witness all of this. Nonetheless, the pain, suffering, and death imposed on the innocents thus far pales in comparison to what lies ahead if more fundamental change is not forthcoming. In order to illustrate the severe consequences of a continuation of the altruistic system, we use the data presented in Figures 1 and 2 above to generate forecasts of future waiting lists and deaths. The forecasts represent our best guess of what the future holds if fundamental change continues to be postponed. The results should serve as a wake-up call for those who argue that we should continue tinkering with the existing procurement system while further postponing the implementation of financial incentives. The costs of such a “wait and see” approach are rapidly becoming intolerable. CHANGING VARIABLE To produce reasonable forecasts of future waiting lists and deaths, we must first confront an apparent anomaly in the reported data that could cast doubt on the accuracy of some of the more recent figures. Specifically, the reported number of deaths of patients on the waiting list (plus those too sick to receive a transplant) follows a consistently upward trend that is very close to a constant proportion of the size of the waiting list over most of the sample period. Beginning in 2002, however, the number of deaths levels off and even starts to decline, despite continued growth of the waiting list. It is not clear why there is an abrupt change in the observed trend in this variable. Our investigation of this issue yielded several plausible explanations but no definitive answer. For example, it may be the case that recent advances in medical care, such as the left ventricular assist device, have extended some patients’ lives and, thereby, reduced the number of deaths on the list. Alternatively, it may be the case that because of rising criticism of the current system, unos has taken steps to remove some of the relatively higher-risk patients from the list before they die. For example, the meld/peld program, which was introduced in February 2002, removed a number of liver patients (who have a comparatively high death rate) from the waiting list. Additionally, the increasing use of so-called “extended criteria” donor organs may have a similar effect, getting the most critically ill patients off the list prior to their deaths. Clearly, the implications of these alternative explanations for reliance on the data are not the same. For example, if patients are, in fact, simply living longer and the data accurately reflect that reality, then our analysis should incorporate the observations. But if the more recent figures are, instead, a manifestation of strategic actions taken by the reporting agency, then they should be excluded. Because we have been unable to identify a single, convincing explanation for the observed phenomenon, we elected to perform our analysis both ways — including and excluding the post-2002 observations on the number of deaths. ESTIMATES Given the two alternative sample periods, the methodology we employ to generate our forecasts is as follows: First, because the number of deaths appears to be causally driven by the number of patients on the waiting list, we begin by estimating a simple linear regression model of the former as a function of the latter. The results of that estimation are reported in Table 1 for the two sample periods described above. Next, we estimate a second linear model with the number of patients on the waiting list regressed against time, again using the two alternative sample periods. Those results are reported in Table 2. From the results, we are able to produce forecasts of the expected size of future waiting lists for each of our sample periods. We run the forecasts out 10 years from the end of our longer sample period, to 2015. Given the forecasted waiting list values, we are then able to use the regression results in Table 1 to generate our forecasts of the number of deaths over the same period. The two alternative sets of forecasts are shown graphically in Figures 3 and 4. Depending upon the sample period chosen, the results show the waiting list reaching 145,691 to 152,400 patients by 2015. Of the patients listed at that time, between 10,547 and 13,642 are expected to die that year. Even more tragically, over the entire period of both actual and predicted values, a cumulative total of 196,310 patients are conservatively expected to die by 2015 as a consequence of the ongoing shortage. Figure 5 illustrates the results. In that figure, we incorporate several historical reference points in order to put the numbers in perspective. No one directly involved in the transplant industry is likely to be surprised by our results. Thirty years of experience consistently point to a continuation of the current, long-standing trends. There is nothing on the horizon that should lead anyone to expect a sudden reversal. But our purpose is not to surprise the parties who are already knowledgeable about this increasingly severe problem. Rather, our intent is to awaken the sleeping policymakers whose continuing inaction will inevitably lead to these results. They can no longer continue to postpone meaningful reform of the U.S. organ transplant system in the futile hope that, somehow, things will improve. They will not.
5,967
<h4>The shortage means many die</h4><p><strong>Beard 8</strong> T.RANDOLPH BEARD, JOHN D. JACKSON , AND DAVID L. KASERMAN, profs of economics, Auburn University Winter 2008 Regulation The Failure of US 'Organ Procurement Policy</p><p>http://object.cato.org/sites/cato.org/files/serials/files/regulation/2007/12/v30n4-3.pdf</p><p>WAITING LISTS YET TO COME The consequences of <u>our <mark>failure to adapt</mark> our</u> cadaveric <u><mark>organ</mark> <mark>procurement</mark> policy</u> to the changed technological realities of the transplant industry have been unconscionable. Figure 2, above, <u><mark>suggests</mark> that <mark>more than 80,000 lives have</mark> now <mark>been sacrificed</mark> on the altar <mark>of our so-called “altruistic” system</mark>. In addition, <mark>the</mark> unnecessary <mark>pain and</mark> <mark>suffering of those</mark> who have been <mark>forced to wait</mark> while undergoing dialysis, <mark>unemployment, and declining health must</mark> also <mark>be reckoned</mark> along with the growing despair of family members who must witness all of this. <mark>Nonetheless, the</mark> pain, suffering, and <mark>death imposed</mark> on the innocents thus far <mark>pales in comparison to what lies ahead if</mark> more fundamental <mark>change is not forthcoming</u></mark>. In order to illustrate the severe consequences of a continuation of the altruistic system, we use the data presented in Figures 1 and 2 above to generate forecasts of future waiting lists and deaths. The forecasts represent our best guess of what the future holds if fundamental change continues to be postponed. The results should serve as a wake-up call for those who argue that we should continue tinkering with the existing procurement system while further postponing the implementation of financial incentives. The costs of such a “wait and see” approach are rapidly becoming intolerable. CHANGING VARIABLE To produce reasonable forecasts of future waiting lists and deaths, we must first confront an apparent anomaly in the reported data that could cast doubt on the accuracy of some of the more recent figures. Specifically, the reported number of deaths of patients on the waiting list (plus those too sick to receive a transplant) follows a consistently upward trend that is very close to a constant proportion of the size of the waiting list over most of the sample period. Beginning in 2002, however, the number of deaths levels off and even starts to decline, despite continued growth of the waiting list. It is not clear why there is an abrupt change in the observed trend in this variable. Our investigation of this issue yielded several plausible explanations but no definitive answer. For example, it may be the case that recent advances in medical care, such as the left ventricular assist device, have extended some patients’ lives and, thereby, reduced the number of deaths on the list. Alternatively, it may be the case that because of rising criticism of the current system, unos has taken steps to remove some of the relatively higher-risk patients from the list before they die. For example, the meld/peld program, which was introduced in February 2002, removed a number of liver patients (who have a comparatively high death rate) from the waiting list. Additionally, the increasing use of so-called “extended criteria” donor organs may have a similar effect, getting the most critically ill patients off the list prior to their deaths. Clearly, the implications of these alternative explanations for reliance on the data are not the same. For example, if patients are, in fact, simply living longer and the data accurately reflect that reality, then our analysis should incorporate the observations. But if the more recent figures are, instead, a manifestation of strategic actions taken by the reporting agency, then they should be excluded. Because we have been unable to identify a single, convincing explanation for the observed phenomenon, we elected to perform our analysis both ways — including and excluding the post-2002 observations on the number of deaths. ESTIMATES Given the two alternative sample periods, the methodology we employ to generate our forecasts is as follows: First, because the number of deaths appears to be causally driven by the number of patients on the waiting list, we begin by estimating a simple linear regression model of the former as a function of the latter. The results of that estimation are reported in Table 1 for the two sample periods described above. Next, we estimate a second linear model with the number of patients on the waiting list regressed against time, again using the two alternative sample periods. Those results are reported in Table 2. From the results, <u><mark>we are able to produce forecasts of the expected size of future waiting lists</u></mark> for each of our sample periods. <u>We run the forecasts out 10 years</u> from the end of our longer sample period, to 2015. Given the forecasted waiting list values, we are then able to use the regression results in Table 1 to generate our forecasts of the number of deaths over the same period. The two alternative sets of forecasts are shown graphically in Figures 3 and 4. Depending upon the sample period chosen, the results show the waiting list reaching 145,691 to 152,400 patients by 2015. Of the patients listed at that time, between 10,547 and 13,642 are expected to die that year. Even more tragically, over the entire period of both actual and predicted values, <u>a cumulative total of <mark>196,310 patients are conservatively expected to die by 2015</mark> <mark>as a consequence of the ongoing shortage.</u></mark> Figure 5 illustrates the results. In that figure, we incorporate several historical reference points in order to put the numbers in perspective. No one directly involved in the transplant industry is likely to be surprised by our results. Thirty years of experience consistently point to a continuation of the current, long-standing trends. There is nothing on the horizon that should lead anyone to expect a sudden reversal. But our purpose is not to surprise the parties who are already knowledgeable about this increasingly severe problem. Rather, our intent is to awaken the sleeping policymakers whose continuing inaction will inevitably lead to these results. They can no longer continue to postpone meaningful reform of the U.S. organ transplant system in the futile hope that, somehow, things will improve. They will not.</p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Shortage
430,247
16
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,516
cadavers cant solve
Fry-Revere 14
Fry-Revere 14 Sigrid Fry-Revere. Director of bioethics studies, CATO Institute 2014
The Kidney Sellers: A Journey of Discovery in Iran p 6 Today the number of kidneys provided from cadavers could never be enough, even if every organ from every potential qualified donor could be harvested. This is true because not every death results in useable organs. Organs can be diseased or injured, or the body can be dead too long before it reaches the hospital. no matter how the process for retrieving organs from the dead improves, there will never be enough kidneys to meet the ever-growing demand.
number of kidneys provided from cadavers could never be enough, even if every organ from every potential qualified donor could be harvested. This is true because not every death results in useable organs. Organs can be diseased or injured, or the body can be dead too long before it reaches the hospital there will never be enough kidneys to meet the ever-growing demand
The Kidney Sellers: A Journey of Discovery in Iran p 6 At the time, what Congress did seemed reasonable, but over the following three decades, no matter how efficient the U.S. cadaver organ procurement sys- tem became, it could not satisfy the demand. Medical innovations keep people alive longer, and the ever-growing diabetes and hypertension epidemics contin- ually increased the number of people who could benefit from a kidney transplant. Today the number of kidneys provided from cadavers could never be enough, even if every organ from every potential qualified donor could be harvested. This is true because not every death results in useable organs. Organs can be diseased or injured, or the body can be dead too long before it reaches the hospital. Patients who die in the hospital after a car accident or similar trauma are the best potential organ donors because the appropriate medical equip- ment is at hand to switch gears from saving the patient to preserving organs for transplantation. Nevertheless, given what we know now, no matter how the process for retrieving organs from the dead improves, there will never be enough kidneys to meet the ever-growing demand.
1,179
<h4>cadavers cant solve </h4><p><strong>Fry-Revere 14</strong> Sigrid Fry-Revere. Director of bioethics studies, CATO Institute 2014 </p><p><u>The Kidney Sellers: A Journey of Discovery in Iran p 6</p><p></u>At the time, what Congress did seemed reasonable, but over the following three decades, no matter how efficient the U.S. cadaver organ procurement sys- tem became, it could not satisfy the demand. Medical innovations keep people alive longer, and the ever-growing diabetes and hypertension epidemics contin- ually increased the number of people who could benefit from a kidney transplant. <u>Today the <mark>number of kidneys provided from cadavers could never be enough, even if every organ from every potential qualified donor could be harvested. This is true because not every death results in useable organs. Organs can be diseased or injured, or the body can be dead too long before it reaches the hospital</mark>.</u> Patients who die in the hospital after a car accident or similar trauma are the best potential organ donors because the appropriate medical equip- ment is at hand to switch gears from saving the patient to preserving organs<u> </u>for transplantation. Nevertheless, given what we know now,<u> no matter how the process for retrieving organs from the dead improves, <mark>there will never be enough kidneys to meet the ever-growing demand</mark>.</p></u>
null
null
Contention 1 – Shortage
430,248
7
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,517
artificial organs are infeasible and decades away
Adhikari 14
Adhikari 14 Richard Adhikari has written about high-tech for leading industry publications since the 1990s
http://www.technewsworld.com/story/80198.html According to Jordan Miller at Rice "Parts of the body which require human cells to perform biomechanical functions, such as the liver or kidney, are still several decades away from reaching human patients," . "We are still in the feasibility stage -- not sure how to keep cells alive at high cell density and adequate size needed to match human organs." A 3D structure will require nearly 1 billion functioning cells to approximate the function of a liver or kidney, and "there are dozens of cell types in these organs," . "We are typically only looking at one or two cell types being put into a 3D printed structure."
According t Jordan Miller, at Rice Parts of the body which require human cells to perform biomechanical functions, such as the liver or kidney, are still several decades away We are still in the feasibility stage -- not sure how to keep cells alive at high cell density and adequate size needed to match human organs there are dozens of cell types in these organs We are typically only looking at one or two cell types being put into a 3D printed structure
03/26/14 Bioprinting, Part 1: The Promise and the Pitfalls http://www.technewsworld.com/story/80198.html [According to Jordan Miller, assistant professor of bioengineering at Rice University]. "Parts of the body which require human cells to perform biomechanical functions, such as the liver or kidney, are still several decades away from reaching human patients," Miller said. "We are still in the feasibility stage -- not sure how to keep cells alive at high cell density and adequate size needed to match human organs." A 3D structure will require nearly 1 billion functioning cells to approximate the function of a liver or kidney, and "there are dozens of cell types in these organs," Miller pointed out. "We are typically only looking at one or two cell types being put into a 3D printed structure." NOTE SOURCE WITH QUALS EDITED INTO BEGINNING OF CARD
861
<h4>artificial organs are infeasible and decades away</h4><p><strong>Adhikari 14</strong> Richard Adhikari has written about high-tech for leading industry publications since the 1990s </p><p>03/26/14 Bioprinting, Part 1: The Promise and the Pitfalls <u>http://www.technewsworld.com/story/80198.html</p><p></u>[<u><mark>According t</mark>o <mark>Jordan Miller</u>,</mark> assistant professor of bioengineering <u><mark>at Rice</u></mark> University]. <u>"<mark>Parts of the body which require human cells to perform biomechanical functions, such as the liver or kidney, are still several decades away </mark>from reaching human patients," </u>Miller said<u>. "<mark>We are still in the feasibility stage -- not sure how to keep cells alive at high cell density and adequate size needed to match human organs</mark>." A 3D structure will require nearly 1 billion functioning cells to approximate the function of a liver or kidney, and "<mark>there are dozens of cell types in these organs</mark>," </u>Miller pointed out<u>. "<mark>We are typically only looking at one or two cell types being put into a 3D printed structure</mark>."</p><p></u>NOTE SOURCE WITH QUALS EDITED INTO BEGINNING OF CARD</p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Shortage
430,249
7
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,518
Artificial are too expensive
Gopar 14
Gopar 14 Jennifer Julisa Gopar ans Dr. Rance LeFebvre 28 July 2014 COSMOS Cluster 7: Biomedical Sciences The Moral and Ethical Debate Regarding Artificial Organ Growth http://cosmos.ucdavis.edu/archives/2014/Cluster7/Gopar_Jennifer_EthicsofGrowingOrgans.pdf
The Scientist elaborated on this possible problem, stating Platt thinks that organ engineering is too costly to meet the needs of everyone waiting for a transplant. ‘You’d have to turn over the entire GDP of a country to accomplish that,’ he says. So it is still unclear whether the cost of these artificial organs will allow them to be within the reach of patients in need of an organ transplant.
organ engineering is too costly to meet the needs of everyone waiting for a transplant. ‘You’d have to turn over the entire GDP of a country to accomplish that,’ it is unclear whether the cost of these artificial organs will allow them to be within the reach of patients in need of an organ transplant.
With these possible outcomes taken consideration, it is now becoming clear that money will play an important role in artificial organ growth. If we begin producing artificial organs, will these be available to everyone? Or will these be only available to the wealthy? The whole purpose of artificial organ growth is to give hope to those waiting for an organ transplant. How would this fulfill that purpose if only the wealthy will be able to afford it? The Scientist elaborated on this possible problem, stating, “[Jeffrey] Platt thinks that organ engineering is too costly to meet the needs of everyone waiting for a transplant. ‘You’d have to turn over the entire GDP of a country to accomplish that,’ he says. On the other hand, ‘I could get a pig for a couple of hundred dollars.’ But [Paolo] Macchiarini argues that organ engineering is in its infancy, and every advance improves efficiency and lowers cost. ‘What we did in 2008 in 6 months, we can now do in a few weeks,’ he says. ‘We do care about getting this to every patient.’ [Joseph] Vacanti adds that mass-producing artificial scaffolds will make organ engineering even more cost-effective. ‘When you scale them up, the bulk materials and manufacturing tech are extremely cheap,’ he says. ‘I think it’s going to be cheaper than growing lots of pigs.’” So it is still unclear whether the cost of these artificial organs will allow them to be within the reach of patients in need of an organ transplant.
1,467
<h4>Artificial are too expensive</h4><p><strong>Gopar 14</strong> Jennifer Julisa Gopar ans Dr. Rance LeFebvre 28 July 2014 COSMOS Cluster 7: Biomedical Sciences The Moral and Ethical Debate Regarding Artificial Organ Growth</p><p><u>http://cosmos.ucdavis.edu/archives/2014/Cluster7/Gopar_Jennifer_EthicsofGrowingOrgans.pdf</p><p></u>With these possible outcomes taken consideration, it is now becoming clear that money will play an important role in artificial organ growth. If we begin producing artificial organs, will these be available to everyone? Or will these be only available to the wealthy? The whole purpose of artificial organ growth is to give hope to those waiting for an organ transplant. How would this fulfill that purpose if only the wealthy will be able to afford it? <u>The Scientist elaborated on this possible problem, stating</u>, “[Jeffrey] <u>Platt thinks that <mark>organ engineering is too</u> <u>costly to meet the needs of everyone waiting for a transplant. ‘You’d have to turn over <strong>the entire GDP of a country</strong> to accomplish that,’</mark> he says.</u> On the other hand, ‘I could get a pig for a couple of hundred dollars.’ But [Paolo] Macchiarini argues that organ engineering is in its infancy, and every advance improves efficiency and lowers cost. ‘What we did in 2008 in 6 months, we can now do in a few weeks,’ he says. ‘We do care about getting this to every patient.’ [Joseph] Vacanti adds that mass-producing artificial scaffolds will make organ engineering even more cost-effective. ‘When you scale them up, the bulk materials and manufacturing tech are extremely cheap,’ he says. ‘I think it’s going to be cheaper than growing lots of pigs.’” <u>So <mark>it is</mark> still <mark>unclear whether the cost of these artificial <strong>organs will allow them to be within the reach of patients in need of an organ transplant.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
Contention 1 – Shortage
430,251
5
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,519
sales solve – default to studies
Kaserman, 7
Kaserman, 7 Dr. David Kaserman is currently Torchmark Professor of Economics at Auburn University.
Proposals to resolve the organ shortage through the use of financial incentives have surfaced repeatedly over the years Importantly, every economist that has written on this subject has reached the same conclusion - i.e., that the shortage is caused by the zero price policy and that the straightforward cure, therefore, is the elimination of that policy.
over the years every economist that has written on this subject has reached the same conclusion - i.e., that the shortage is caused by the zero price policy and that the straightforward cure, therefore, is the elimination of that polic
Issues in Law & Medicine Summer, 2007 23 Issues L. & Med. 45 ARTICLE: Fifty Years of Organ Transplants: The Successes and The Failures lexis Financial Incentives Proposals to resolve the organ shortage through the use of financial incentives (or, similarly, through the formation of cadaveric organ procurement markets) have surfaced repeatedly over the years. n56 Importantly, every economist that has written on this subject has reached the same conclusion - i.e., that the shortage is caused by the zero price policy and that the straightforward cure, therefore, is the elimination of that policy. Other, non-economist commentators have reached that same conclusion as well.
688
<h4>sales solve – default to studies</h4><p><strong>Kaserman, 7</strong> Dr. David Kaserman is currently Torchmark Professor of Economics at Auburn University. </p><p>Issues in Law & Medicine Summer, 2007 23 Issues L. & Med. 45 ARTICLE: Fifty Years of Organ Transplants: The Successes and The Failures lexis</p><p>Financial Incentives <u>Proposals to resolve the organ shortage through the use of financial incentives</u> (or, similarly, through the formation of cadaveric organ procurement markets) <u>have surfaced repeatedly <mark>over the years</u></mark>. n56 <u>Importantly, <mark>every economist that has written on this subject has reached the same conclusion - i.e., that the shortage is caused by the zero price policy and that the straightforward cure, therefore, is the elimination of that polic</mark>y. </u>Other, non-economist commentators have reached that same conclusion as well.</p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Shortage
430,250
3
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,520
no crowd out – only real neg study is wrong
Economist 11
Economist 11 The Economist Feb 16th 2011 Blood, not money http://www.economist.com/blogs/blighty/2011/02/volunteering_and_profiteering
In a classic 1970 study called "The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy" Titmuss compared the voluntary British system with the American one in which payments were then widely made. Titmuss reckoned such a market was inefficient and wasteful, that it created shortages and surpluses, he was wrong, and such arguments have since been widely discredited
In a classic 1970 study called "The Gift Titmuss compared the voluntary British system with the American one in which payments were then widely made. Titmuss reckoned such a market was inefficient and wasteful, that it created shortages and surpluses, he was wrong, and such arguments have since been widely discredited
Blood donors are also unpaid, in Britain and elsewhere. A debate over whether or not they should be compensated for their efforts has raged for at least four decades. In a classic 1970 study called "The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy" Richard Titmuss compared the voluntary British system favourably with the American one in which payments were then widely made. Titmuss reckoned such a market was inefficient and wasteful, that it created shortages and surpluses, and led eventually to a contaminated product. Although he was wrong, and such arguments have since been widely discredited, Americans mostly no longer receive payment for giving blood. Too many people in poor health lied about their medical histories in order to make a few bucks, endangering those who were to receive the blood. As the World Health Organisation notes, people who give blood voluntarily and for altruistic reasons have a lower prevalence of HIV, hepatitis viruses and other blood-borne infections than do those who seek monetary reward. Presumably that is because being rich is a great protection against disease.
1,117
<h4>no crowd out – only real neg study is wrong</h4><p><strong>Economist 11</strong> The Economist Feb 16th 2011 Blood, not money</p><p>http://www.economist.com/blogs/blighty/2011/02/volunteering_and_profiteering</p><p>Blood donors are also unpaid, in Britain and elsewhere. A debate over whether or not they should be compensated for their efforts has raged for at least four decades. <u><mark>In a classic 1970 study called "The Gift</mark> Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy"</u> Richard <u><mark>Titmuss compared the voluntary British</u> <u>system</u></mark> favourably <u><mark>with the American one in which payments were then widely made. Titmuss reckoned such a market was inefficient and wasteful, that it created shortages and surpluses,</u></mark> and led eventually to a contaminated product. Although <u><mark>he was wrong, and such arguments have since been widely discredited</u></mark>, Americans mostly no longer receive payment for giving blood. Too many people in poor health lied about their medical histories in order to make a few bucks, endangering those who were to receive the blood. As the World Health Organisation notes, people who give blood voluntarily and for altruistic reasons have a lower prevalence of HIV, hepatitis viruses and other blood-borne infections than do those who seek monetary reward. Presumably that is because being rich is a great protection against disease.</p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Shortage
430,253
7
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,521
no crowd out - friends and family will still donate
Gill 2
Gill 2 Michael Gill, Ph.D., Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, College of Charleston AND Robert Sade, M.D.,Professor in the Department of Surgery and Director of the Institute of Human Values in Health Care, Medical University of South Carolina. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12.1 (2002) 17-45
In the early 1970s, Titmuss and Singer argued that the existence of financial incentives for blood products would decrease the amount of blood products overall, and some people might believe that the same argument can be extended to financial incentives for kidneys, first the available evidence does not support the conclusion that payment for blood products has reduced blood supply in the U S secondly, because live kidney donations are usually between family members, there is a significant difference between blood and kidneys that makes it illegitimate to transfer Titmuss and Singer's conclusions to the kidney debate.
first o the available evidence does not support the conclusion that payment for blood products has reduced blood supply in the U St secondly, because live kidney donations are usually between family members, there is a significant difference between blood and kidneys that makes it illegitimate to transfer Titmuss and Singer's conclusions to the kidney debate.
Paying for Kidneys: The Case against Prohibition http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/kennedy_institute_ of_ethics_journal/v012/12.1gill.html 3. In the early 1970s, Titmuss (1971) and Singer (1973) argued that the existence of financial incentives for blood products would decrease the amount of blood products overall, and some people might believe that the same argument can be extended to financial incentives for kidneys, leading to the conclusion that payment for kidneys will decrease the overall number of kidneys available for transplant. Singer and Titmuss's criticisms of payment for blood products are consequentialist—they argue that such payment is wrong because it would reduce the amount of blood for people who needed it. We believe, first of all, that their consequentialist arguments against payment for blood products have turned out to be inconclusive at best—that the available evidence does not support the conclusion that payment for blood products has reduced blood supply in the United States. And we believe, secondly, that because live kidney donations are usually between family members, there is a significant difference between blood and kidneys that makes it illegitimate to transfer Titmuss and Singer's conclusions to the kidney debate. We do, however, remain open to the possibility that future evidence may vitiate our belief that payment for kidneys will increase supplies. For discussion of Titmuss and Singer in relation to kidney sales, see Campbell (1992, pp. 41-42); Cherry (2000, pp. 340-41); and Harvey (1999, p. 119).
1,554
<h4>no crowd out - friends and family will still donate</h4><p><strong>Gill 2</strong> Michael Gill, Ph.D., Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, College of Charleston AND Robert Sade, M.D.,Professor in the Department of Surgery and Director of the Institute of Human Values in Health Care, Medical University of South Carolina. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12.1 (2002) 17-45</p><p>Paying for Kidneys: The Case against Prohibition http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/kennedy_institute_ of_ethics_journal/v012/12.1gill.html</p><p>3. <u>In the early 1970s, Titmuss</u> (1971) <u>and Singer</u> (1973) <u>argued that the existence of financial incentives for blood products would decrease the amount of blood products overall, and some people might believe that the same argument can be extended to financial incentives for kidneys,</u> leading to the conclusion that payment for kidneys will decrease the overall number of kidneys available for transplant. Singer and Titmuss's criticisms of payment for blood products are consequentialist—they argue that such payment is wrong because it would reduce the amount of blood for people who needed it. We believe, <u><mark>first </u>o</mark>f all, that their consequentialist arguments against payment for blood products have turned out to be inconclusive at best—that <u><mark>the available evidence does not support the conclusion that payment for blood products has reduced blood supply in the U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u>t</mark>ates. And we believe, <u><mark>secondly,</mark> </u>that<u> <mark>because live kidney donations are usually between family members, there is a significant difference between blood and kidneys that makes it illegitimate to transfer Titmuss and Singer's conclusions to the kidney debate.</u></mark> We do, however, remain open to the possibility that future evidence may vitiate our belief that payment for kidneys will increase supplies. For discussion of Titmuss and Singer in relation to kidney sales, see Campbell (1992, pp. 41-42); Cherry (2000, pp. 340-41); and Harvey (1999, p. 119). </p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Shortage
430,252
7
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,522
even with crowd out - Sales would solve the shortage. Study by Becker and Elias 14
null
Gary S. Becker, Nobel Prize-winning professor of economics at the University of Chicago and a senior fellow at the Hoover Institution; and Julio J. Elias, economics professor at the Universidad del CEMA in Argentina. Updated Jan. 18, 2014 Wall Street Journal Cash for Kidneys: The Case for a Market for Organs
http://online.wsj.com/news/articles/SB10001424052702304149404579322560004817176?mod=WSJ_hpp_MIDDLENexttoWhatsNewsFifth Finding a way to increase the supply of organs would reduce wait times and deaths, and it would greatly ease the suffering that many sick individuals now endure while they hope for a transplant. The most effective change would be to provide compensation to people who give their organs—that is, we recommend establishing a market for organs. Paying donors for their organs would finally eliminate the supply-demand gap sufficient payment to kidney donors would increase the supply of kidneys by a large percentage, without greatly increasing the total cost of a kidney transplant. We have estimated how much individuals would need to be paid for kidneys to be willing to sell them for transplants. Our conclusion is that a very large number of both live and cadaveric kidney donations would be available by paying about $15,000 for each kidney. Iran permits the sale of kidneys by living donors. waiting times to get kidneys have been largely eliminated Since the number of kidneys available at a reasonable price would be far more than needed to close the gap between the demand and supply of kidneys, there would no longer be any significant waiting time to get a kidney transplant. The number of people on dialysis would decline dramatically, and deaths due to long waits for a transplant would essentially disappear. the claim that payments would be ineffective in eliminating the shortage of organs isn't consistent with what we know about the supply of other parts of the body for medical use. Paying for organs would save the cost of dialysis for people waiting for kidney transplants and other costs to individuals waiting for other organs. More important, it would prevent thousands of deaths and improve the quality of life among those who now must wait years before getting the organs they need.
Finding a way to increase the supply of organs would reduce wait times and deaths The most effective change would be to provide compensation we recommend a market for organs. Paying donors for their organs would finally eliminate the supply-demand gap sufficient payment would increase the supply by a large percentage, without increasing the total cost very large number of both live and cadaveric kidney donations would be available by paying about $15,000 for each kidney Iran permits the sale by living donors waiting times have been eliminated Since the number uld be far more than needed to close the gap between the demand and supply o there would no longer be any significant waiting time deaths due to long waits for a transplant would disappear the claim that payments would be ineffective in eliminating the shortag isn't consistent with supply of other parts of the body for medical use.
http://online.wsj.com/news/articles/SB10001424052702304149404579322560004817176?mod=WSJ_hpp_MIDDLENexttoWhatsNewsFifth Finding a way to increase the supply of organs would reduce wait times and deaths, and it would greatly ease the suffering that many sick individuals now endure while they hope for a transplant. The most effective change, we believe, would be to provide compensation to people who give their organs—that is, we recommend establishing a market for organs. Organ transplants are one of the extraordinary developments of modern science. They began in 1954 with a kidney transplant performed at Brigham & Women's hospital in Boston. But the practice only took off in the 1970s with the development of immunosuppressive drugs that could prevent the rejection of transplanted organs. Since then, the number of kidney and other organ transplants has grown rapidly, but not nearly as rapidly as the growth in the number of people with defective organs who need transplants. The result has been longer and longer delays to receive organs. Many of those waiting for kidneys are on dialysis, and life expectancy while on dialysis isn't long. For example, people age 45 to 49 live, on average, eight additional years if they remain on dialysis, but they live an additional 23 years if they get a kidney transplant. That is why in 2012, almost 4,500 persons died while waiting for kidney transplants. Although some of those waiting would have died anyway, the great majority died because they were unable to replace their defective kidneys quickly enough. Enlarge Image The toll on those waiting for kidneys and on their families is enormous, from both greatly reduced life expectancy and the many hardships of being on dialysis. Most of those on dialysis cannot work, and the annual cost of dialysis averages about $80,000. The total cost over the average 4.5-year waiting period before receiving a kidney transplant is $350,000, which is much larger than the $150,000 cost of the transplant itself. Individuals can live a normal life with only one kidney, so about 34% of all kidneys used in transplants come from live donors. The majority of transplant kidneys come from parents, children, siblings and other relatives of those who need transplants. The rest come from individuals who want to help those in need of transplants. In recent years, kidney exchanges—in which pairs of living would-be donors and recipients who prove incompatible look for another pair or pairs of donors and recipients who would be compatible for transplants, cutting their wait time—have become more widespread. Although these exchanges have grown rapidly in the U.S. since 2005, they still account for only 9% of live donations and just 3% of all kidney donations, including after-death donations. The relatively minor role of exchanges in total donations isn't an accident, because exchanges are really a form of barter, and barter is always an inefficient way to arrange transactions. Exhortations and other efforts to encourage more organ donations have failed to significantly close the large gap between supply and demand. For example, some countries use an implied consent approach, in which organs from cadavers are assumed to be available for transplant unless, before death, individuals indicate that they don't want their organs to be used. (The U.S. continues to use informed consent, requiring people to make an active declaration of their wish to donate.) In our own highly preliminary study of a few countries—Argentina, Austria, Brazil, Chile and Denmark—that have made the shift to implied consent from informed consent or vice versa, we found that the switch didn't lead to consistent changes in the number of transplant surgeries. Other studies have found more positive effects from switching to implied consent, but none of the effects would be large enough to eliminate the sizable shortfall in the supply of organs in the U.S. That shortfall isn't just an American problem. It exists in most other countries as well, even when they use different methods to procure organs and have different cultures and traditions. Paying donors for their organs would finally eliminate the supply-demand gap. In particular, sufficient payment to kidney donors would increase the supply of kidneys by a large percentage, without greatly increasing the total cost of a kidney transplant. We have estimated how much individuals would need to be paid for kidneys to be willing to sell them for transplants. These estimates take account of the slight risk to donors from transplant surgery, the number of weeks of work lost during the surgery and recovery periods, and the small risk of reduction in the quality of life. Our conclusion is that a very large number of both live and cadaveric kidney donations would be available by paying about $15,000 for each kidney. That estimate isn't exact, and the true cost could be as high as $25,000 or as low as $5,000—but even the high estimate wouldn't increase the total cost of kidney transplants by a large percentage. Few countries have ever allowed the open purchase and sale of organs, but Iran permits the sale of kidneys by living donors. Scattered and incomplete evidence from Iran indicates that the price of kidneys there is about $4,000 and that waiting times to get kidneys have been largely eliminated. Since Iran's per capita income is one-quarter of that of the U.S., this evidence supports our $15,000 estimate. Other countries are also starting to think along these lines: Singapore and Australia have recently introduced limited payments to live donors that compensate mainly for time lost from work. Since the number of kidneys available at a reasonable price would be far more than needed to close the gap between the demand and supply of kidneys, there would no longer be any significant waiting time to get a kidney transplant. The number of people on dialysis would decline dramatically, and deaths due to long waits for a transplant would essentially disappear. Today, finding a compatible kidney isn't easy. There are four basic blood types, and tissue matching is complex and involves the combination of six proteins. Blood and tissue type determine the chance that a kidney will help a recipient in the long run. But the sale of organs would result in a large supply of most kidney types, and with large numbers of kidneys available, transplant surgeries could be arranged to suit the health of recipients (and donors) because surgeons would be confident that compatible kidneys would be available. The system that we're proposing would include payment to individuals who agree that their organs can be used after they die. This is important because transplants for heart and lungs and most liver transplants only use organs from the deceased. Under a new system, individuals would sell their organs "forward" (that is, for future use), with payment going to their heirs after their organs are harvested. Relatives sometimes refuse to have organs used even when a deceased family member has explicitly requested it, and they would be more inclined to honor such wishes if they received substantial compensation for their assent. The idea of paying organ donors has met with strong opposition from some (but not all) transplant surgeons and other doctors, as well as various academics, political leaders and others. Critics have claimed that paying for organs would be ineffective, that payment would be immoral because it involves the sale of body parts and that the main donors would be the desperate poor, who could come to regret their decision. In short, critics believe that monetary payments for organs would be repugnant. But the claim that payments would be ineffective in eliminating the shortage of organs isn't consistent with what we know about the supply of other parts of the body for medical use. For example, the U.S. allows market-determined payments to surrogate mothers—and surrogacy takes time, involves great discomfort and is somewhat risky. Yet in the U.S., the average payment to a surrogate mother is only about $20,000. Another illuminating example is the all-volunteer U.S. military. Critics once asserted that it wouldn't be possible to get enough capable volunteers by offering them only reasonable pay, especially in wartime. But the all-volunteer force has worked well in the U.S., even during wars, and the cost of these recruits hasn't been excessive. Whether paying donors is immoral because it involves the sale of organs is a much more subjective matter, but we question this assertion, given the very serious problems with the present system. Any claim about the supposed immorality of organ sales should be weighed against the morality of preventing thousands of deaths each year and improving the quality of life of those waiting for organs. How can paying for organs to increase their supply be more immoral than the injustice of the present system? Under the type of system we propose, safeguards could be created against impulsive behavior or exploitation. For example, to reduce the likelihood of rash donations, a period of three months or longer could be required before someone would be allowed to donate their kidneys or other organs. This would give donors a chance to re-evaluate their decisions, and they could change their minds at any time before the surgery. They could also receive guidance from counselors on the wisdom of these decisions. Though the poor would be more likely to sell their kidneys and other organs, they also suffer more than others from the current scarcity. Today, the rich often don't wait as long as others for organs since some of them go to countries such as India, where they can arrange for transplants in the underground medical sector, and others (such as the late Steve Jobs ) manage to jump the queue by having residence in several states or other means. The sale of organs would make them more available to the poor, and Medicaid could help pay for the added cost of transplant surgery. The altruistic giving of organs might decline with an open market, since the incentive to give organs to a relative, friend or anyone else would be weaker when organs are readily available to buy. On the other hand, the altruistic giving of money to those in need of organs could increase to help them pay for the cost of organ transplants. Paying for organs would lead to more transplants—and thereby, perhaps, to a large increase in the overall medical costs of transplantation. But it would save the cost of dialysis for people waiting for kidney transplants and other costs to individuals waiting for other organs. More important, it would prevent thousands of deaths and improve the quality of life among those who now must wait years before getting the organs they need.
10,811
<h4>even with crowd out - Sales would solve the shortage<strong>. Study by Becker and Elias 14 </h4><p></strong> Gary S. Becker, Nobel Prize-winning professor of economics at the University of Chicago and a senior fellow at the Hoover Institution; and Julio J. Elias, economics professor at the Universidad del CEMA in Argentina. Updated Jan. 18, 2014 Wall Street Journal Cash for Kidneys: The Case for a Market for Organs</p><p><u>http://online.wsj.com/news/articles/SB10001424052702304149404579322560004817176?mod=WSJ_hpp_MIDDLENexttoWhatsNewsFifth</p><p><mark>Finding a way to increase the supply of organs would reduce wait times and deaths</mark>, and it would greatly ease the suffering that many sick individuals now endure while they hope for a transplant. <mark>The most effective change</u></mark>, we believe, <u><mark>would be to provide</mark> <mark>compensation</mark> to people who give their organs—that is, <mark>we recommend</mark> establishing <mark>a market for organs.</mark> </u>Organ transplants are one of the extraordinary developments of modern science. They began in 1954 with a kidney transplant performed at Brigham & Women's hospital in Boston. But the practice only took off in the 1970s with the development of immunosuppressive drugs that could prevent the rejection of transplanted organs. Since then, the number of kidney and other organ transplants has grown rapidly, but not nearly as rapidly as the growth in the number of people with defective organs who need transplants. The result has been longer and longer delays to receive organs. Many of those waiting for kidneys are on dialysis, and life expectancy while on dialysis isn't long. For example, people age 45 to 49 live, on average, eight additional years if they remain on dialysis, but they live an additional 23 years if they get a kidney transplant. That is why in 2012, almost 4,500 persons died while waiting for kidney transplants. Although some of those waiting would have died anyway, the great majority died because they were unable to replace their defective kidneys quickly enough. Enlarge Image The toll on those waiting for kidneys and on their families is enormous, from both greatly reduced life expectancy and the many hardships of being on dialysis. Most of those on dialysis cannot work, and the annual cost of dialysis averages about $80,000. The total cost over the average 4.5-year waiting period before receiving a kidney transplant is $350,000, which is much larger than the $150,000 cost of the transplant itself. Individuals can live a normal life with only one kidney, so about 34% of all kidneys used in transplants come from live donors. The majority of transplant kidneys come from parents, children, siblings and other relatives of those who need transplants. The rest come from individuals who want to help those in need of transplants. In recent years, kidney exchanges—in which pairs of living would-be donors and recipients who prove incompatible look for another pair or pairs of donors and recipients who would be compatible for transplants, cutting their wait time—have become more widespread. Although these exchanges have grown rapidly in the U.S. since 2005, they still account for only 9% of live donations and just 3% of all kidney donations, including after-death donations. The relatively minor role of exchanges in total donations isn't an accident, because exchanges are really a form of barter, and barter is always an inefficient way to arrange transactions. Exhortations and other efforts to encourage more organ donations have failed to significantly close the large gap between supply and demand. For example, some countries use an implied consent approach, in which organs from cadavers are assumed to be available for transplant unless, before death, individuals indicate that they don't want their organs to be used. (The U.S. continues to use informed consent, requiring people to make an active declaration of their wish to donate.) In our own highly preliminary study of a few countries—Argentina, Austria, Brazil, Chile and Denmark—that have made the shift to implied consent from informed consent or vice versa, we found that the switch didn't lead to consistent changes in the number of transplant surgeries. Other studies have found more positive effects from switching to implied consent, but none of the effects would be large enough to eliminate the sizable shortfall in the supply of organs in the U.S. That shortfall isn't just an American problem. It exists in most other countries as well, even when they use different methods to procure organs and have different cultures and traditions. <u><mark>Paying donors for their organs would finally eliminate the supply-demand gap</u></mark>. In particular, <u><mark>sufficient</mark> <mark>payment</mark> to kidney donors <mark>would increase the supply</mark> of kidneys <mark>by a large percentage,</mark> <mark>without</mark> greatly <mark>increasing the total cost</mark> of a kidney transplant. We have estimated how much individuals would need to be paid for kidneys to be willing to sell them for transplants. </u>These estimates take account of the slight risk to donors from transplant surgery, the number of weeks of work lost during the surgery and recovery periods, and the small risk of reduction in the quality of life. <u>Our conclusion is that a <mark>very large number of both live and cadaveric kidney donations would be available by paying about $15,000 for each kidney</mark>.</u> That estimate isn't exact, and the true cost could be as high as $25,000 or as low as $5,000—but even the high estimate wouldn't increase the total cost of kidney transplants by a large percentage. Few countries have ever allowed the open purchase and sale of organs, but <u><mark>Iran permits the sale</mark> of kidneys <mark>by living donors</mark>.</u> Scattered and incomplete evidence from Iran indicates that the price of kidneys there is about $4,000 and that <u><mark>waiting times</mark> to get kidneys <mark>have</mark> <mark>been</mark> largely <mark>eliminated</u></mark>. Since Iran's per capita income is one-quarter of that of the U.S., this evidence supports our $15,000 estimate. Other countries are also starting to think along these lines: Singapore and Australia have recently introduced limited payments to live donors that compensate mainly for time lost from work. <u><mark>Since the number</mark> of kidneys available at a reasonable price wo<mark>uld be far more than needed to close the gap between the demand and supply o</mark>f kidneys, <mark>there would no longer be any significant waiting time </mark>to get a kidney transplant. The number of people on dialysis would decline dramatically, and <mark>deaths due to long waits for a transplant</mark> <mark>would</mark> essentially <mark>disappear</mark>. </u>Today, finding a compatible kidney isn't easy. There are four basic blood types, and tissue matching is complex and involves the combination of six proteins. Blood and tissue type determine the chance that a kidney will help a recipient in the long run. But the sale of organs would result in a large supply of most kidney types, and with large numbers of kidneys available, transplant surgeries could be arranged to suit the health of recipients (and donors) because surgeons would be confident that compatible kidneys would be available. The system that we're proposing would include payment to individuals who agree that their organs can be used after they die. This is important because transplants for heart and lungs and most liver transplants only use organs from the deceased. Under a new system, individuals would sell their organs "forward" (that is, for future use), with payment going to their heirs after their organs are harvested. Relatives sometimes refuse to have organs used even when a deceased family member has explicitly requested it, and they would be more inclined to honor such wishes if they received substantial compensation for their assent. The idea of paying organ donors has met with strong opposition from some (but not all) transplant surgeons and other doctors, as well as various academics, political leaders and others. Critics have claimed that paying for organs would be ineffective, that payment would be immoral because it involves the sale of body parts and that the main donors would be the desperate poor, who could come to regret their decision. In short, critics believe that monetary payments for organs would be repugnant. But <u><mark>the claim that payments would be ineffective in eliminating the shortag</mark>e of organs <mark>isn't consistent with</mark> what we know about the <mark>supply of other parts of the body for medical use.</u></mark> For example, the U.S. allows market-determined payments to surrogate mothers—and surrogacy takes time, involves great discomfort and is somewhat risky. Yet in the U.S., the average payment to a surrogate mother is only about $20,000. Another illuminating example is the all-volunteer U.S. military. Critics once asserted that it wouldn't be possible to get enough capable volunteers by offering them only reasonable pay, especially in wartime. But the all-volunteer force has worked well in the U.S., even during wars, and the cost of these recruits hasn't been excessive. Whether paying donors is immoral because it involves the sale of organs is a much more subjective matter, but we question this assertion, given the very serious problems with the present system. Any claim about the supposed immorality of organ sales should be weighed against the morality of preventing thousands of deaths each year and improving the quality of life of those waiting for organs. How can paying for organs to increase their supply be more immoral than the injustice of the present system? Under the type of system we propose, safeguards could be created against impulsive behavior or exploitation. For example, to reduce the likelihood of rash donations, a period of three months or longer could be required before someone would be allowed to donate their kidneys or other organs. This would give donors a chance to re-evaluate their decisions, and they could change their minds at any time before the surgery. They could also receive guidance from counselors on the wisdom of these decisions. Though the poor would be more likely to sell their kidneys and other organs, they also suffer more than others from the current scarcity. Today, the rich often don't wait as long as others for organs since some of them go to countries such as India, where they can arrange for transplants in the underground medical sector, and others (such as the late Steve Jobs ) manage to jump the queue by having residence in several states or other means. The sale of organs would make them more available to the poor, and Medicaid could help pay for the added cost of transplant surgery. The altruistic giving of organs might decline with an open market, since the incentive to give organs to a relative, friend or anyone else would be weaker when organs are readily available to buy. On the other hand, the altruistic giving of money to those in need of organs could increase to help them pay for the cost of organ transplants. <u>Paying for organs </u>would lead to more transplants—and thereby, perhaps, to a large increase in the overall medical costs of transplantation. But it <u>would save the cost of dialysis for people waiting for kidney transplants and other costs to individuals waiting for other organs. More important, it would prevent thousands of deaths and improve the quality of life among those who now must wait years before getting the organs they need.</p></u>
null
null
Contention 1 – Shortage
430,254
24
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,523
Market-clearing price specifically solves the shortage
Watkins 5
Watkins 5 Christy M. Watkins, University of Tulsa Journal of International and Comparative Law Spring, 2005 5 JICL 1 ARTICLE: A Deadly Dilemma: The Failure of Nations' Organ Procurement Systems and Potential Reform Alternatives n1 lexis
the organ supplier (potential donor or his or her surviving relatives) would be offered a market-determined price, which would fluctuate depending on supply and demand. Price flexibility would eliminate surpluses or shortages automatically.
the organ supplier (potential donor or his or her surviving relatives) would be offered a market-determined price, which would fluctuate depending on supply and demand Price flexibility would eliminate shortages automatically. n
2. The Market Process A minimum of five groups would be seriously affected by an organ market: (1) current and potential transplant candidates; (2) actual and potential organ donors and their families; (3) hospitals, physicians, and other transplant caregivers; (4) The United Network for Organ Sharing, the Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network, and other organ procurement [*27] organizations; and (5) taxpayers and those who finance patient care. n214 First, the organ supplier (potential donor or his or her surviving relatives) would be offered a market-determined price, which would fluctuate depending on supply and demand. n215 Price flexibility would eliminate surpluses or shortages automatically. n216 Organ procurement firms would then remove the organs at death and sell them to transplant centers that have put in an organ order. n217 In turn, the centers would include the price paid to the firm in the operation bill, with the resale price being the price paid to the donor plus the firm's collection and distribution cost. n218 From here, the center could allocate the organs in "precisely the same fashion they are allocated today" under the guidelines of the UNOS. n219 The firms acquiring the organs for sale would presumably operate competitively on a for-profit basis, resulting in powerful market incentives to create and use the best strategies in finding potential donors and encouraging them to donate. n220 Procurement agencies currently operate on a nonprofit basis, and while they may work diligently, it is doubtful they could match the performance of the competitive for-profit firms. n221
1,638
<h4>Market-clearing price specifically solves the shortage</h4><p><strong>Watkins 5</strong> Christy M. Watkins, University of Tulsa Journal of International and Comparative Law Spring, 2005 5 JICL 1 ARTICLE: A Deadly Dilemma: The Failure of Nations' Organ Procurement Systems and Potential Reform Alternatives n1 lexis</p><p>2. The Market Process</p><p>A minimum of five groups would be seriously affected by an organ market: (1) current and potential transplant candidates; (2) actual and potential organ donors and their families; (3) hospitals, physicians, and other transplant caregivers; (4) The United Network for Organ Sharing, the Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network, and other organ procurement [*27] organizations; and (5) taxpayers and those who finance patient care. n214 First, <u><mark>the organ supplier (potential donor or his or her surviving relatives) would be offered a market-determined price, which would fluctuate depending on supply and demand</mark>. </u> n215 <u><mark>Price flexibility would eliminate</mark> surpluses or <mark>shortages automatically. </u> n</mark>216 Organ procurement firms would then remove the organs at death and sell them to transplant centers that have put in an organ order. n217 In turn, the centers would include the price paid to the firm in the operation bill, with the resale price being the price paid to the donor plus the firm's collection and distribution cost. n218 From here, the center could allocate the organs in "precisely the same fashion they are allocated today" under the guidelines of the UNOS. n219 The firms acquiring the organs for sale would presumably operate competitively on a for-profit basis, resulting in powerful market incentives to create and use the best strategies in finding potential donors and encouraging them to donate. n220 Procurement agencies currently operate on a nonprofit basis, and while they may work diligently, it is doubtful they could match the performance of the competitive for-profit firms. n221</p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Shortage
430,257
4
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,524
The US ban on sales has created an international illegal market
Hughes 9
Hughes 9 J. Andrew Hughes, J.D. candidate, Vanderbilt University Law School, May 2009.
U.S. organ procurement policy has consequences beyond a domestic organ shortage. A thriving global market in human organs has resulted from U.S. policy banning organ sales The illegality of the organ trade is insufficient to discourage many of those faced with the possibility of dying on an organ waiting list, and "transplant tourism" has become its own industry. U.S. doctors perform illegal transplants, too, often under hospitals' "don't ask, don't tell" policy regarding transplants involving foreigners who claim to be related The lack of a regulated organ marketplace in the U.S. has resulted in exploitation of the poor throughout the world. In short, U.S. policy and its ban on organ sales have produced some of the same immoral and unethical consequences the ban was designed to avoid
A thriving global market in human organs has resulted from U.S. banning organ sales. illegality of the trade is insufficient to discourage many faced with the possibility of dying on an waiting list transplant tourism" has become its own industry S. doctors perform illegal transplants, too, under don't ask, don't tell" policy The lack of regulated organ marketplace in the U.S resulted in exploitation of the poor throughout the world .S. policy have produced immoral and unethical consequences
Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law January, 2009 42 Vand. J. Transnat'l L. 351 Note: You Get What You Pay For?: Rethinking U.S. Organ Procurement Policy in Light of Foreign Models U.S. organ procurement policy has consequences beyond a domestic organ shortage. A thriving global black market in human organs has resulted from U.S. policy banning organ sales. n78 While nearly all developed nations have banned the sale and purchase of human organs, many countries do not strictly enforce these laws. n79 The illegality of the organ trade is insufficient to discourage many of those faced with the possibility of dying on an organ waiting list, and "transplant tourism" has become its own industry. n80 In Bombay in 2001, nearly US$ 10 million were exchanged for kidney transplants. n81 Patients use kidney brokers to locate sellers, who circumvent a ban on kidney sales by signing an affidavit swearing that they are not being paid. n82 Before the U.S. invaded Iraq in 2003, that country was known as "one of [the] world's best black marketplaces for human organs." n83 The lack of effective prosecution of these transactions extends beyond Asia and the Middle East to Europe, as recent cases in Estonia and Germany suggest. n84 U.S. doctors perform illegal transplants, too, often under hospitals' "don't ask, don't tell" policy regarding transplants involving foreigners who claim to be related. n85 U.S. hospitals set their own rules for who can be a live organ donor, and organ brokers can locate hospitals that do not question a purported familial relationship between "donors" and "donees." n86 The lack of a regulated organ marketplace in the U.S. has resulted in exploitation of the poor throughout the world. n87 Organ sellers often face debt, unemployment, and serious health problems; as such, they are easy targets for abuse. n88 Prisoners and the homeless are among those exploited. n89 Sellers of organs on the black market are often paid less than what they were initially promised, while their financial situations and health often grow worse after the transplants. n90 Data from the Indian black market trade in kidneys [*363] support the concern about sellers' lack of adequate information about the risks involved. In one study, 86% of the sellers there reported that their health had "deteriorated substantially" after their organ sales, and "four out of five sellers would not recommend that others follow their lead in selling organs." n91 In short, U.S. policy and its ban on organ sales have produced some of the same immoral and unethical consequences the ban was designed to avoid. n92
2,620
<h4>The US ban on sales has created an international illegal market</h4><p><strong>Hughes 9</strong> J. Andrew Hughes, J.D. candidate, Vanderbilt University Law School, May 2009.</p><p>Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law January, 2009 42 Vand. J. Transnat'l L. 351</p><p>Note: You Get What You Pay For?: Rethinking U.S. Organ Procurement Policy in Light of Foreign Models</p><p><u>U.S. organ procurement policy has consequences beyond a domestic organ shortage. <mark>A</mark> <mark>thriving global</u></mark> black <u><mark>market in human organs has resulted from U.S.</mark> policy <mark>banning organ sales</u>.</mark> n78 While nearly all developed nations have banned the sale and purchase of human organs, many countries do not strictly enforce these laws. n79 <u>The <mark>illegality of the</mark> organ <mark>trade is insufficient to</mark> <mark>discourage many </mark>of those <mark>faced with the possibility of dying on an</mark> organ <mark>waiting list</mark>, and "<mark>transplant tourism" has become its own industry</mark>.</u> n80 In Bombay in 2001, nearly US$ 10 million were exchanged for kidney transplants. n81 Patients use kidney brokers to locate sellers, who circumvent a ban on kidney sales by signing an affidavit swearing that they are not being paid. n82 Before the U.S. invaded Iraq in 2003, that country was known as "one of [the] world's best black marketplaces for human organs." n83 The lack of effective prosecution of these transactions extends beyond Asia and the Middle East to Europe, as recent cases in Estonia and Germany suggest. n84 <u>U.<mark>S. doctors perform illegal transplants, too,</mark> often <mark>under</mark> hospitals' "<mark>don't ask, don't tell" policy</mark> regarding transplants involving foreigners who claim to be related</u>. n85 U.S. hospitals set their own rules for who can be a live organ donor, and organ brokers can locate hospitals that do not question a purported familial relationship between "donors" and "donees." n86 <u><mark>The lack of</mark> a <mark>regulated organ marketplace in the U.S</mark>. has <mark>resulted in</mark> <mark>exploitation of the poor throughout the world</mark>.</u> n87 Organ sellers often face debt, unemployment, and serious health problems; as such, they are easy targets for abuse. n88 Prisoners and the homeless are among those exploited. n89 Sellers of organs on the black market are often paid less than what they were initially promised, while their financial situations and health often grow worse after the transplants. n90 Data from the Indian black market trade in kidneys [*363] support the concern about sellers' lack of adequate information about the risks involved. In one study, 86% of the sellers there reported that their health had "deteriorated substantially" after their organ sales, and "four out of five sellers would not recommend that others follow their lead in selling organs." n91 <u>In short, U<mark>.S. policy</mark> and its ban on organ sales <mark>have produced</mark> some of the same <mark>immoral and unethical consequences</mark> the ban was designed to avoid</u>. n92</p>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
430,256
14
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,525
Economically desperate people are coerced into selling their organs in the hope of bettering their situation. As a result of the actions of unscrupulous organ brokers and inadequate medical care, they are actually made worse off.
Jaycox 12
Jaycox 12 Michael P. Jaycox, teaching fellow and Ph.D. candidate in theological ethics at Boston College, Developing World Bioethics Volume 12 Number 3 2012 pp 135–147 COERCION, AUTONOMY, AND THE PREFERENTIAL OPTION FOR THE POOR IN THE ETHICS OF ORGAN TRANSPLANTATION
Pakistani surgeon and bioethicist Farhat Moazam offers the results of a recent study He found that almost all of these organ vendors were in significant debt to wealthy landlords at the time they sold their kidneys; Although the vendors were promised by third-party brokers an average price of 160,000 rupees per kidney, the amount actually received by the vendors was an average of 103,000 rupees. As a result, a majority of them were ‘either still in debt or had accumulated new debts’ a majority of the vendors experienced long-term physical and psychological malady as a result of their nephrectomies, and a majority also expressed regret or shame for their decision because they were not freed from their debts and/or felt they had committed a morally wrong act. Moazam summarizes his findings with the conclusion that the sale of kidneys functions to reinforce the poverty of those who sell them:
Moazam found almost all organ vendors were in significant debt at the time they sold their kidneys Although vendors were promised by brokers 160,000 rupees the amount received was 103,000 rupees a majority were either still in debt or had accumulated new debts’ vendors experienced long-term physical and psychological malady majority expressed regret because they were not freed from their debts sale of kidneys functions to reinforce the poverty of those who sell them:
http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1471-8847.2012.00327.x/pdf Pakistani surgeon and bioethicist Farhat Moazam offers the results of a recent study in which he interviewed thirty-two farm laborers in Pakistan, each of whom had sold a kidney within the past three years. 14 He found that almost all of these organ vendors were in significant debt to wealthy landlords at the time they sold their kidneys; the average debt of each was 130,000 rupees at the time of sale. Although the vendors were promised by third-party brokers an average price of 160,000 rupees per kidney, the amount actually received by the vendors was an average of 103,000 rupees. As a result, a majority (17) of them were ‘either still in debt or had accumulated new debts’ at the time of their interviews. 15 Moreover, a majority of the vendors experienced long-term physical and psychological malady as a result of their nephrectomies, and a majority also expressed regret or shame for their decision because they were not freed from their debts and/or felt they had committed a morally wrong act. When asked why they had made the decision, ‘the most common [Urdu] words they used were majboori (a word that arises from the root jabr, which means a state that is beyond one’s control) and ghurbat (extreme poverty).’16,Moazam summarizes his findings with the conclusion that the sale of kidneys functions to reinforce the poverty of those who sell them: In the words of the vendors, they sell a kidney...in order to fulfill what they see as obligations toward immediate and extended families in which they are inextricably embedded, and within systems of social and economic inequalities which they can neither control nor escape. They sell kidneys in hopes of paying off loans taken to cover their families’ medical expenses or to meet the responsibilities for arranging marriages and burying their dead. These are recurring expenses, and for most the debts rapidly accumulate again, even if they have been partially or completely paid back with the money from selling a kidney. 17 4 F. Moazam, R.M. Zaman & A.M. Jafarey. Conversations with Kidney Vendors in Pakistan: An Ethnographic Study.Hastings Cent Rep 2009; 39: 29–44. Due to recent legislation (18 March 2010), the sale of human organs is now illegal in Pakistan, although the social effects of this new legislation remain to be studied; see T.M. Pope. Legal Briefing: Organ Donation and Allocation. J Clin Ethics 2010; 21: 243–263: 254.
2,479
<h4>Economically desperate people are coerced into selling their organs in the hope of bettering their situation. As a result of the actions of unscrupulous organ brokers and inadequate medical care, they are actually made worse off.</h4><p><strong>Jaycox 12</strong> Michael P. Jaycox, teaching fellow and Ph.D. candidate in theological ethics at Boston College,</p><p>Developing World Bioethics Volume 12 Number 3 2012 pp 135–147 COERCION, AUTONOMY, AND THE PREFERENTIAL OPTION FOR THE POOR IN THE ETHICS OF ORGAN TRANSPLANTATION</p><p>http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1471-8847.2012.00327.x/pdf</p><p><u>Pakistani surgeon and bioethicist Farhat <mark>Moazam</mark> offers the results of a recent study </u>in which he interviewed thirty-two farm laborers in Pakistan, each of whom had sold a kidney within the past three years. 14 <u>He <mark>found</mark> that <mark>almost all </mark>of these <mark>organ vendors were in significant debt</mark> to wealthy landlords <mark>at the time they sold their kidneys</mark>;</u> the average debt of each was 130,000 rupees at the time of sale. <u><mark>Although</mark> the <mark>vendors were promised by</mark> third-party <mark>brokers </mark>an average price of <mark>160,000 rupees</mark> per kidney, <mark>the amount</mark> actually <mark>received</mark> by the vendors <mark>was</mark> an average of <mark>103,000 rupees</mark>. As a result, <mark>a majority</mark> </u>(17) <u>of them <mark>were</mark> ‘<mark>either still in debt or had accumulated new debts’</mark> </u>at the time of their interviews. 15 Moreover, <u>a majority of the <mark>vendors experienced long-term physical and psychological malady</mark> as a result of their nephrectomies, and a <mark>majority</mark> also <mark>expressed regret</mark> or shame for their decision <mark>because they were not freed from their debts</mark> and/or felt they had committed a morally wrong act.</u> When asked why they had made the decision, ‘the most common [Urdu] words they used were majboori (a word that arises from the root jabr, which means a state that is beyond one’s control) and<u> </u>ghurbat (extreme poverty).’16,<u><strong>Moazam summarizes his findings with the conclusion that the <mark>sale of kidneys functions to reinforce the poverty of those who sell them:</strong></mark> </u>In the words of the vendors, they sell a kidney...in order to fulfill what they see as obligations toward immediate and extended families in which they are inextricably embedded, and within systems of social and economic inequalities which they can neither control nor escape. They sell kidneys in hopes of paying off loans taken to cover their families’ medical expenses or to meet the responsibilities for arranging marriages and burying their dead. These are recurring expenses, and for most the debts rapidly accumulate again, even if they have been partially or completely paid back with the money from selling a kidney. 17 4 F. Moazam, R.M. Zaman & A.M. Jafarey. Conversations with Kidney Vendors in Pakistan: An Ethnographic Study.Hastings Cent Rep 2009; 39: 29–44. Due to recent legislation (18 March 2010), the sale of human organs is now illegal in Pakistan, although the social effects of this new legislation remain to be studied; see T.M. Pope. Legal Briefing: Organ Donation and Allocation. J Clin Ethics 2010; 21: 243–263: 254.</p>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
430,255
14
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,526
For many, the coercion is more violent
Bowden 13
Bowden 13 Jackie Bowden, 2013 J.D. graduate from St. Thomas University School of Law. Intercultural Human Rights Law Review 2013 8 Intercultural Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 451 ARTICLE: FEELING EMPTY? ORGAN TRAFFICKING & TRADE: THE BLACK MARKET FOR HUMAN ORGANS lexis
Organ trafficking has been depriving innocent people of their fundamental right to life for decades Imagine living in a poor country As you walk peacefully you are grabbed and thrown into the back of an unmarked truck. a surgeon slices through your flesh to remove your kidney no anesthesia is administered and no medication is given to prevent infection Your body is then dumped on a side street, and you are extremely lucky if you live , there are reported accounts suggesting that abduction of organs is a harsh reality of organ trafficking. Furthermore, there is evidence of governmental involvement, which contributes to and exacerbates the problem.
Organ trafficking depriving innocent people of their fundamental right to life you are grabbed and thrown into the back of an unmarked truck a surgeon slices through your flesh to remove your kidney no anesthesia is administered and no medication is given Your body is then dumped you are extremely lucky if you live. on of organs is a harsh reality of organ trafficking
[*452] Introduction [*452] Introduction Organ trafficking has been depriving innocent people of their fundamental right to life for decades. n1 Imagine living in a poor country, where you wake up in the morning and set out to find work and food for the day. As you walk peacefully to your home at the end of the day, you are grabbed and thrown into the back of an unmarked truck. n2 You wake up, screaming from excruciating pain, as a surgeon slices through your flesh to remove your kidney. Due to the costs associated with such a procedure, no anesthesia is administered and no medication is given to prevent infection. n3 In the event that the surgery does not go as planned, no forms of emergency assistance are available. Your body is then dumped on a side street, and you are extremely lucky if you live. Should you report the incident to government officials? What if the government is actually involved in this inhumane activity? n4 [*453] There are conflicting views on whether people are actually kidnapped for their organs. n5 In fact, many believe these stories are just myths. n6 However, there are reported accounts suggesting that abduction of organs is a harsh reality of organ trafficking. n7 Reports indicate organ trafficking is so prevalent that there is a surplus of organs available for transplantation. n8 Furthermore, there is evidence of governmental involvement, which contributes to and exacerbates the problem. n9 Fortunately, most countries have enacted laws to prevent and prohibit organ trafficking from occurring. n10
1,550
<h4>For many, the coercion is more violent</h4><p><strong>Bowden 13</strong> Jackie Bowden, 2013 J.D. graduate from St. Thomas University School of Law. Intercultural Human Rights Law Review 2013 8 Intercultural Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 451 ARTICLE: FEELING EMPTY? ORGAN TRAFFICKING & TRADE: THE BLACK MARKET FOR HUMAN ORGANS lexis</p><p> [*452] Introduction</p><p>[*452] Introduction <u><mark>Organ trafficking</mark> has been <mark>depriving innocent people of their</mark> <mark>fundamental right to life</mark> for decades</u>. n1 <u>Imagine living in a poor country</u>, where you wake up in the morning and set out to find work and food for the day. <u>As you walk peacefully</u> to your home at the end of the day, <u><mark>you are grabbed and thrown into the back of an unmarked truck</mark>. </u>n2 You wake up, screaming from excruciating pain, as <u><mark>a surgeon slices through your flesh to remove your kidney</u></mark>. Due to the costs associated with such a procedure, <u><mark>no anesthesia is administered and no medication</mark> <mark>is given</mark> to prevent infection</u>. n3 In the event that the surgery does not go as planned, no forms of emergency assistance are available. <u><mark>Your body is then dumped</mark> on a side street, and <mark>you are extremely lucky if you live</u>.</mark> Should you report the incident to government officials? What if the government is actually involved in this inhumane activity? n4 [*453] There are conflicting views on whether people are actually kidnapped for their organs. n5 In fact, many believe these stories are just myths. n6 However<u>, there are reported accounts suggesting that abducti<mark>on of organs is a harsh reality of organ trafficking</mark>.</u> n7 Reports indicate organ trafficking is so prevalent that there is a surplus of organs available for transplantation. n8 <u>Furthermore, there is evidence of governmental involvement, which contributes to and exacerbates the problem. </u>n9 Fortunately, most countries have enacted laws to prevent and prohibit organ trafficking from occurring. n10</p><p> </p>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
430,258
14
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,527
And that market is widespread and expanding—desperation and profit ensures expansion and exploitation
Samadi 2012
Samadi 2012 – Vice Chairman of the Department of Urology and Chief of Robotics and Minimally Invasive Surgery at the Mount Sinai School of Medicine (David, May 30, 2012, “Consequences of the rise in illegal organ trafficking,” Fox News, http://www.foxnews.com/health/2012/05/30/consequences-rise-in-illegal-organ-trafficking/,)
the WHO released a report demonstrating a rise in the number of human organs being sold on the black market in 2010 over 10,000 organs were sold, translating to more than one organ sold every hour. Unfortunately the need for organs greatly outweighs the current supply An illegal market has capitalized on these individuals’ desperation the prospects of large profits are creating unfortunate incentives with patients willing to pay up to $200,000 for a kidney There are many ethical and health concerns surrounding the trafficking of human organs In the majority of situations, those selling their organs represent members of vulnerable populations In countries like Pakistan, China or India a person can sell a kidney for $5,000 while those handling the transaction make a substantial profit Prior reports demonstrated that the recipients of illegal organs tend to fair worse than those who have received one legally those obtaining organs abroad are at a higher risk of contracting transmissible diseases, such as hepatitis B or HIV the patient and organ survival rates abroad are significantly lower statistics might underestimate the risk as the data is vulnerable to survivor bias those who do not survive the procedure and return home are often not included in studies given the duplicitous nature of illegal organ trade, there are many scams the number of individuals needing organs continues to grow while the number of donors remains stable
WHO) released a report demonstrating a rise in the number of human organs being sold on the black market , in 2010 over 10,000 organs were sold, translating to more than one organ sold every hour. An illegal market has capitalized on these individuals’ desperation the prospects of large profits are creating unfortunate incentives, hose selling their organs represent members of vulnerable populations. ipients of illegal organs tend to fair worse than those who have received one legally. the patient and organ survival rates abroad are significantly lower
Earlier this week, the World Health Organization (WHO) released a report demonstrating a rise in the number of human organs being sold on the black market. According to the paper, in 2010 over 10,000 organs were sold, translating to more than one organ sold every hour. Organ transplantation is a necessary treatment for many individuals whose organs have failed and has been in practice in the United States since the 1950s. In the U.S. organ donations are regulated by an independent non-for-profit organization, United Network for Organ Sharing (UNOS). Organs are given to those whose need is the greatest, regardless of wealth or position. Unfortunately, the need for organs greatly outweighs the current supply. As of March 2012 over 113,115 patients are currently waiting for an organ to become available. An illegal market has capitalized on these individuals’ desperation, and the prospects of large profits are creating unfortunate incentives, with patients willing to pay up to $200,000 for a kidney. According to the WHO report, 76 percent of organs sold were kidneys, reflecting the growing demand secondary to complications of high blood pressure and diabetes. There are many ethical and health concerns surrounding the trafficking of human organs. In the majority of situations, those selling their organs represent members of vulnerable populations. In countries like Pakistan, China or India, a person can sell a kidney for $5,000, while those handling the transaction make a substantial profit. Prior reports have also demonstrated that the recipients of illegal organs tend to fair worse than those who have received one legally. A recent meta-analysis involving 39 original publications revealed that those obtaining organs abroad are at a higher risk of contracting transmissible diseases, such as hepatitis B or HIV. Furthermore the patient and organ survival rates abroad are significantly lower. These statistics might even underestimate the risk as the data is vulnerable to survivor bias; those who do not survive the procedure and return home are often not included in studies. Additionally, given the duplicitous nature of illegal organ trade, there are many scams. In 2010, a former psychiatrist was sentenced to more than 15 years in prison for offering false promises of organ transplants in the Philippines, while taking over $400,000 dollars from patients. Over five patients actually travelled to the Philippines only to find out that there was no organ awaiting them. One of these patients died in the Philippines. Regretfully, the number of individuals needing organs continues to grow while the number of donors remains stable
2,662
<h4>And that market is <u>widespread and expanding</u>—desperation and profit ensures expansion and exploitation</h4><p><strong>Samadi 2012</strong> – Vice Chairman of the Department of Urology and Chief of Robotics and Minimally Invasive Surgery at the Mount Sinai School of Medicine (David, May 30, 2012, “Consequences of the rise in illegal organ trafficking,” Fox News, http://www.foxnews.com/health/2012/05/30/consequences-rise-in-illegal-organ-trafficking/,)</p><p>Earlier this week, <u>the</u> World Health Organization (<u><mark>WHO</u>) <u>released a report demonstrating a rise in the number of human organs being sold on the black market</u></mark>. According to the paper<mark>, <u>in 2010 over 10,000 organs were sold, translating to more than one organ sold every hour.</mark> </u>Organ transplantation is a necessary treatment for many individuals whose organs have failed and has been in practice in the United States since the 1950s. In the U.S. organ donations are regulated by an independent non-for-profit organization, United Network for Organ Sharing (UNOS). Organs are given to those whose need is the greatest, regardless of wealth or position. <u>Unfortunately</u>, <u>the need for organs greatly outweighs the current supply</u>. As of March 2012 over 113,115 patients are currently waiting for an organ to become available. <u><mark>An illegal market has capitalized on these individuals’ desperation</u></mark>, and <u><mark>the prospects of large profits are creating unfortunate incentives</u>,</mark> <u>with</u> <u>patients willing to pay up to $200,000 for a kidney</u>. According to the WHO report, 76 percent of organs sold were kidneys, reflecting the growing demand secondary to complications of high blood pressure and diabetes. <u>There are many ethical and health concerns surrounding the trafficking of human organs</u>. <u>In the majority of situations, t<mark>hose selling their organs represent members of vulnerable populations</u>.</mark> <u>In countries like Pakistan, China or India</u>, <u>a person can sell a kidney for $5,000</u>, <u>while those handling the transaction make a substantial profit</u>. <u>Prior reports</u> have also <u>demonstrated that the rec<mark>ipients of illegal organs tend to fair worse than those who have received one legally</u>.</mark> A recent meta-analysis involving 39 original publications revealed that <u>those obtaining organs abroad are at a higher risk of contracting transmissible diseases, such as hepatitis B or HIV</u>. Furthermore <u><mark>the patient and organ survival rates abroad are significantly lower</u></mark>. These <u>statistics</u> <u>might</u> even <u>underestimate the risk as the data is vulnerable to survivor bias</u>; <u>those who do not survive the procedure and return home are often not included in studies</u>. Additionally, <u>given the duplicitous nature of illegal organ trade, there are many scams</u>. In 2010, a former psychiatrist was sentenced to more than 15 years in prison for offering false promises of organ transplants in the Philippines, while taking over $400,000 dollars from patients. Over five patients actually travelled to the Philippines only to find out that there was no organ awaiting them. One of these patients died in the Philippines. Regretfully, <u>the number of individuals needing organs continues to grow while the number of donors remains stable</u><strong> </p></strong>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
267,351
8
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,528
The illicit market exploits in a way like slavery
Delmonico 3
Delmonico 3 Francis L. Delmonico, Director of the Renal Transplantation Unit at Massachusetts
the exploitation of organ sellers veers dangerously close to human slavery The pressures put by organ brokers upon the desperation of the world’s dislocated, refugee, and poorest populations to provide the scarce commodities reveals the limits of argu- ments based solely on individual autonomy. the pressure of organ brokers upon the poor makes their decision to sell an organ anything but a free and autonomous choice. The most disturbing issue of organ sales is the formation of an economic underclass of organ donors throughout the world to serve the wealthy. they are indifferent to the social and individual pathologies that markets in kidneys and other body parts produce, such as the documented evidence of postsurgery medical complications, chronic pain, psychological problems, unemployment, decreased earning power, social ostracism, and social stigma faced by kidney sellers in many parts of the world
exploitation of organ sellers veers dangerously close to human slavery pressures put by organ brokers provide the scarce commodities reveals the limits of argu- ments based solely on individual autonomy. makes their decision to sell an organ anything but a free and autonomous choice formation of an economic underclass of organ donors throughout the world to serve the wealthy they are indifferent to the social and individual pathologies that markets in kidneys and other body parts produce medical complications, chronic pain, psychological problems, unemployment, decreased earning power, social ostracism, and social stigma faced by kidney sellers
General Hospital, the medical director at the New England Organ Bank, and Professor of Surgery at Harvard Medical School; and Nancy Scheper-Hughes.Director of Organs Watch and Professor of Medical Anthropology at the University of California at Berkeley Zygon, vol. 38, no. 3 (September 2003) WHY WE SHOULD NOT PAY FOR HUMAN ORGANS Ebsco Although class distinctions are an almost naturalized part of social life in all complex societies, in this particular instance the exploitation of organ sellers veers dangerously close to human slavery, as argued by Giovanni Berlinguer (Berlinguer and Garrafa 1996). The pressures put by organ brokers upon the desperation of the world’s dislocated, refugee, and poorest populations to provide the scarce commodities reveals the limits of argu- ments based solely on individual autonomy. Yes, even the poorest people of the world “make choices,” but they do not make these freely or under social or economic conditions of their own making. Further, the pressure of organ brokers upon the poor makes their decision to sell an organ anything but a free and autonomous choice. These secular arguments reach a conclusion similar to one derived from Christian morality—that the sale of human organs is unethical. The most disturbing issue of organ sales to both Christian and secular ethicists is the formation of an economic underclass of organ donors throughout the world to serve the wealthy. This is not to suggest that proponents of organ sales are in favor of exploiting the poor but, rather, that they are indifferent to the social and individual pathologies that markets in kidneys and other body parts produce, such as the documented evidence of postsurgery medical complications, chronic pain, psychological problems, unemployment, decreased earning power, social ostracism, and social stigma faced by kidney sellers in many parts of the world (see Zargooshi 2002; Jimenez and Scheper-Hughes 2002a; Ram 2002).
1,963
<h4><strong>The illicit market exploits in a way like slavery</h4><p>Delmonico 3 </strong>Francis L. Delmonico, Director of the Renal Transplantation Unit at Massachusetts</p><p>General Hospital, the medical director at the New England Organ Bank, and Professor of</p><p>Surgery at Harvard Medical School; and Nancy Scheper-Hughes.Director of Organs Watch and Professor of Medical Anthropology at the University of California at Berkeley Zygon, vol. 38, no. 3 (September 2003)</p><p>WHY WE SHOULD NOT PAY FOR HUMAN ORGANS Ebsco </p><p>Although class distinctions are an almost naturalized part of social life in all complex societies, in this particular instance <u>the <mark>exploitation of organ sellers veers dangerously close to human slavery</u></mark>, as argued by Giovanni Berlinguer (Berlinguer and Garrafa 1996). <u>The <mark>pressures put by organ brokers</mark> upon the desperation of the world’s dislocated, refugee, and poorest populations to <mark>provide the scarce commodities reveals the limits of argu- ments based solely on individual autonomy.</mark> </u>Yes, even the poorest people of the world “make choices,” but they do not make these freely or under social or economic conditions of their own making. Further, <u>the pressure of organ brokers upon the poor <mark>makes their decision to sell an organ anything but a free and autonomous choice</mark>. </u>These secular arguments reach a conclusion similar to one derived from Christian morality—that the sale of human organs is unethical. <u>The most disturbing issue of organ sales </u>to both Christian and secular ethicists <u>is the <mark>formation of an economic underclass of organ donors throughout the world to serve the wealthy</mark>.</u> This is not to suggest that proponents of organ sales are in favor of exploiting the poor but, rather, that <u><mark>they are indifferent to the social and individual pathologies that markets in kidneys and other body parts produce</mark>, such as the documented evidence of postsurgery <mark>medical complications, chronic pain, psychological problems, unemployment, decreased earning power, social ostracism, and social stigma faced by kidney sellers</mark> in many parts of the world</u> (see Zargooshi 2002; Jimenez and Scheper-Hughes 2002a; Ram 2002). </p>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
430,260
15
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,529
The illicit organ market is colonial in nature
Delmonico 3
Delmonico 3 Francis L. Delmonico, Director of the Renal Transplantation Unit at Massachusetts
The pattern of organ distribu- tion follows established routes of capital: from South to North, from Third to First World, from poor to rich, from black and brown to white, and from female to male recipients.
The pattern of organ distribu- tion follows established routes of capital: from South to North, from Third to First World, from poor to rich, from black and brown to white, and from female to male recipients
General Hospital, the medical director at the New England Organ Bank, and Professor of Surgery at Harvard Medical School; and Nancy Scheper-Hughes.Director of Organs Watch and Professor of Medical Anthropology at the University of California at Berkeley Zygon, vol. 38, no. 3 (September 2003) WHY WE SHOULD NOT PAY FOR HUMAN ORGANS Ebsco For several years, one of us (Nancy Scheper-Hughes [2003]) has been actively involved in multi-sited, ethnographic field research in nine countries on the global traffic in human organs. The pattern of organ distribu- tion follows established routes of capital: from South to North, from Third to First World, from poor to rich, from black and brown to white, and from female to male recipients. Residents of Japan, the Gulf States in the Middle East (Kuwait, Saudi Arabia, and Oman), Israel, Western Europe, and North America now travel in individually tailored or in organized group packages to medical centers in India, China, the Philippines, South America, Turkey, and Eastern Europe to purchase kidneys that are not available locally or legally. They are aided in their quest by a new class of organ brokers, some of whom operate on the Internet.
1,200
<h4><strong>The illicit organ market is colonial in nature</h4><p>Delmonico 3 </strong>Francis L. Delmonico, Director of the Renal Transplantation Unit at Massachusetts</p><p>General Hospital, the medical director at the New England Organ Bank, and Professor of</p><p>Surgery at Harvard Medical School; and Nancy Scheper-Hughes.Director of Organs Watch and Professor of Medical Anthropology at the University of California at Berkeley Zygon, vol. 38, no. 3 (September 2003)</p><p>WHY WE SHOULD NOT PAY FOR HUMAN ORGANS Ebsco </p><p>For several years, one of us (Nancy Scheper-Hughes [2003]) has been actively involved in multi-sited, ethnographic field research in nine countries on the global traffic in human organs. <u><mark>The pattern of organ distribu- tion follows established routes of capital: from South to North, from Third to First World, from poor to rich, from black and brown to white, and from female to male recipients</mark>. </u>Residents of Japan, the Gulf States in the Middle East (Kuwait, Saudi Arabia, and Oman), Israel, Western Europe, and North America now travel in individually tailored or in organized group packages to medical centers in India, China, the Philippines, South America, Turkey, and Eastern Europe to purchase kidneys that are not available locally or legally. They are aided in their quest by a new class of organ brokers, some of whom operate on the Internet.</p>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
430,259
4
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,530
The illicit market is apartheid medicine
SCHEPER-HUGHES 3
SCHEPER-HUGHES 3 Nancy Scheper-Hughes, Professor of Medical Anthropology at the University of California, Berkeley, where she directs the doctoral program in Critical Studies in Medicine, Science, and the Body. JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS, VOL . 2, NO. 2 (JUNE2003), 197–226 Rotten trade: millennial capitalism, human values and global justice in organs trafficking http://web.b.ebscohost.com/ehost/ pdfviewer/pdfviewer?sid =97cebe61-9315-4e5e-b8db-f7372c8a971e%40sessionmgr115&vid=1&hid=117
We have found almost everywhere a new form of globalized ‘apartheid medicine’ that privileges one class of patients, organ recipients, over another class of invisible and unrecognized ‘non-patients’, about whom almost nothing is known
We have found almost everywhere a new form of globalized ‘apartheid medicine’ that privileges one class of patients, organ recipients, over another class of invisible and unrecognized ‘non-patients’, about whom almost nothing is known
This paper continues my discussion (Scheper-Hughes 2000b, 2001a, 2001b, 2002) of the darker side of transplant practice. In all, three crucial points about the organs trade have emerged. The first is about invented scarcities and artificial needs within a new context of highly fetishized ‘fresh’ organs. The scarcity of cadaver organs has evolved into an active trade in ‘surplus’ organs from living ‘ suppliers’ as well as in new forms of ‘biopiracy’. The second point concerns the transplant rhetoric of altruism masking real demands for human sacrifice. The third point concerns surplus empathy and the relative visibility of two distinct populations – excluded and invisible organ givers and included and highly visible organ receivers. We have found almost everywhere a new form of globalized ‘apartheid medicine’ that privileges one class of patients, organ recipients, over another class of invisible and unrecognized ‘non-patients’, about whom almost nothing is known – an excellent place for a critical medical anthropologist (Scheper-Hughes 1990) to begin.
1,067
<h4>The illicit market is apartheid medicine</h4><p><strong>SCHEPER-HUGHES 3</strong> Nancy Scheper-Hughes, Professor of Medical Anthropology at the University of California, Berkeley, where she directs the doctoral program in Critical Studies in Medicine, Science, and the Body. JOURNAL OF HUMAN RIGHTS, VOL . 2, NO. 2 (JUNE2003), 197–226 Rotten trade: millennial capitalism, human values and global justice in organs trafficking http://web.b.ebscohost.com/ehost/ pdfviewer/pdfviewer?sid =97cebe61-9315-4e5e-b8db-f7372c8a971e%40sessionmgr115&vid=1&hid=117</p><p>This paper continues my discussion (Scheper-Hughes 2000b, 2001a, 2001b, 2002) of the darker side of transplant practice. In all, three crucial points about the organs trade have emerged. The first is about invented scarcities and artificial needs within a new context of highly fetishized ‘fresh’ organs. The scarcity of cadaver organs has evolved into an active trade in ‘surplus’ organs from living ‘ suppliers’ as well as in new forms of ‘biopiracy’. The second point concerns the transplant rhetoric of altruism masking real demands for human sacrifice. The third point concerns surplus empathy and the relative visibility of two distinct populations – excluded and invisible organ givers and included and highly visible organ receivers. <u><mark>We have found almost everywhere a new form of globalized ‘apartheid medicine’ that privileges one class of patients, organ recipients, over another class of invisible and unrecognized ‘non-patients’, about whom almost nothing is known</u></mark> – an excellent place for a critical medical anthropologist (Scheper-Hughes 1990) to begin.</p>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
171,178
30
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,531
Plan solves 2 internal links--
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Plan solves 2 internal links--</h4>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
430,261
1
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,532
First, It dries up the demand for illegal organs
Upchurch 12
Upchurch 12 Ryan Upchurch, Seton Hall Law 1-1-12 Seton Hall Law eRepository "The Man who Removes a Mountain Begins by Carrying Away Small Stones: Flynn v. Holder and a Re-Examination of The National Organ Transplantation Act of 1984" (2012). http://erepository.law.shu.edu/student_scholarship/18
By increasing the supply of available organs in the U S through compensation, citizens would have less reason to travel elsewhere to pay for an organ If demand dried up transplant tourism in these countries would take a major hit presumably American citizens make up a substantial percentage of the tourist patients seeking a new organ they cannot attain domestically. As one report stated, “Most of those organs ended up transplanted into American citizens If those American citizens with the means to purchase were not forced abroad to find an organ, it is very possible that stories like this would become much less commonplace.
By increasing the supply of organs in the U S through compensation, citizens would have less reason to travel elsewhere to pay for an organ If demand dried up transplant tourism would take a major hit merican citizens make up a substantial percentage of the tourist patients Most organs ended up transplanted into American citizens If those American citizens were not forced abroad to find an organ, this would become much less commonplace.
By increasing the supply of available organs in the United States through compensation, American citizens would have less reason to travel elsewhere to pay for an organ. For example, Aadil Hospital in Lahore, Pakistan advertises two transplant packages catered towards foreign patients: $14,000 for the first transplant and $16,000 for the second if the first organ fails.118 If demand dried up from foreign citizens, transplant tourism in these countries would take a major hit because brokers would fetch lower sums for organs they procure. Statistical information is difficult to come by for obvious reasons, but presumably American citizens make up a substantial percentage of the tourist patients seeking a new organ they cannot attain domestically. As one report about impoverished Bangladeshi villagers taken advantage of for their organs succinctly stated, “Most of those organs ended up transplanted into American citizens.”119 The black market for organs in other countries is not fueled by local patients. Rather, it is driven upwards and out of control by those American as well as European citizens who cannot acquire what they need domestically.120 One estimate is that the black market accounts for as high as twenty percent of all kidney transplants worldwide.121 Nadley Hakim, transplant surgeon for St. Mary’s Hospital in London, offered an interesting take on this problem of the black market when he said, “this trade is going on anyway, why not have a controlled trade where if someone wants to donate a kidney for a particular price, that would be acceptable? If it is done safely, the donor will not suffer.”122 Within the past month, an indigent Chinese teenager sold his kidney so that he could purchase an iPad and iPhone.123 The unnamed teenager now suffers from renal deficiency.124 Sadly, the boy received roughly ten percent of what the buyer paid, with the rest going to the surgeon and others involved in coordinating the operation.125 If those American citizens with the means to purchase were not forced abroad to find an organ, it is very possible that stories like this would become much less commonplace.
2,141
<h4>First, It dries up the<u> demand</u> for illegal organs </h4><p><strong>Upchurch 12</strong> Ryan Upchurch, Seton Hall Law 1-1-12 Seton Hall Law eRepository "The Man who Removes<u> a Mountain Begins by Carrying Away Small Stones: Flynn v. Holder and a Re-Examination of The National Organ Transplantation Act of 1984" (2012). http://erepository.law.shu.edu/student_scholarship/18</p><p><mark>By increasing the supply of</mark> available <mark>organs in the U</u></mark>nited<u> <mark>S</u></mark>tates<u> <mark>through compensation,</mark> </u>American<u> <mark>citizens would have less reason to travel elsewhere to pay for an organ</u></mark>. For example, Aadil Hospital in Lahore, Pakistan advertises two transplant packages catered towards foreign patients: $14,000 for the first transplant and $16,000 for the second if the first organ fails.118 <u><mark>If demand dried up</u></mark> from foreign citizens, <u><mark>transplant tourism</mark> in these countries <mark>would take a major hit</u></mark> because brokers would fetch lower sums for organs they procure. Statistical information is difficult to come by for obvious reasons, but <u>presumably A<mark>merican citizens make up a substantial percentage of the tourist patients</mark> seeking a new organ they cannot attain domestically. As one report </u>about impoverished Bangladeshi villagers taken advantage of for their organs<u> </u>succinctly <u>stated, “<mark>Most </mark>of those <mark>organs ended up transplanted into American citizens</u></mark>.”119 The<u> </u>black market for organs in other countries is not fueled by local patients. Rather, it is driven<u> </u>upwards and out of control by those American as well as European citizens who cannot acquire<u> </u>what they need domestically.120 One estimate is that the black market accounts for as high as twenty percent of all kidney transplants worldwide.121 Nadley Hakim, transplant surgeon for St. Mary’s Hospital in London, offered an interesting take on this problem of the black market when he said, “this trade is going on anyway, why not have a controlled trade where if someone wants to donate a kidney for a particular price, that would be acceptable? If it is done safely, the donor will not suffer.”122 Within the past month, an indigent Chinese teenager sold his kidney so that he could purchase an iPad and iPhone.123 The unnamed teenager now suffers from renal deficiency.124 Sadly, the boy received roughly ten percent of what the buyer paid, with the rest going to the surgeon and others involved in coordinating the operation.125 <u><mark>If those American citizens </mark>with the means to purchase <mark>were not forced abroad to find an organ,</mark> it is very possible that stories like <mark>this would become much less commonplace.</p></u></mark>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
430,262
14
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,533
Second, Legalizing organ sales in the US spills over globally
Calandrillo 4
Calandrillo 4 Steve P. Calandrillo, Associate Professor, Univ. of Washington School of Law. J.D., Harvard Law School. B.A. in Economics, Univ. of California at Berkeley. George Mason Law Review Fall, 2004 13 Geo. Mason L. Rev. 69 ARTICLE: Cash for Kidneys? Utilizing Incentives to End America's Organ Shortage lexis
if we cannot prevent the black markets in human organs that continue to thrive worldwide today, a thoughtful and responsible regulatory solution in America might be the best response a well-regulated legalized market in the U.S. However, it is reasonable to suspect that an American market would significantly reduce the demand for black market organs, especially given the ability of a regulated market to better ensure the quality of its product. Furthermore, a legalized market in the U.S. (with appropriate safeguards to prevent abuse of sellers) may lead to similar structures abroad.
if we cannot prevent the black markets in human organs America might be the best response a well-regulated legalized market in the U.S. would significantly reduce the demand for black market organs, especially given the ability of a regulated market to better ensure the quality of its product a legalized market U.S. may lead to similar structures abroad
Moreover, if we cannot prevent the black markets in human organs that continue to thrive worldwide today, a thoughtful and responsible regulatory solution in America might be the best response. Many scholars have chronicled the reality that today's black markets lead to a host of abuses, provide for no follow-up health care, and generally exploit the poor to the wealthy's advantage. n180 Stephen Spurr details the potential for misrepresentation and fraud against both buyers and sellers today, as prices spiral out of control for organs that are of dubious quality. n181 Gloria Banks decries the exploitation of society's most vulnerable individuals in the organ sale trade, and urges legal and ethical safeguards for their protection. n182 Susan Hankin Denise adds that a properly regulated organ market may therefore be a better solution to the problem of scarcity than the outright ban we witness today. n183 FOOTNOTE ATTACHED n183 See Denise, supra note 72, at 1035-36 (arguing that regulated markets are superior to the existing ban on organ sales in the U.S.). Of course, even a well-regulated legalized market in the U.S. may not completely eliminate black markets worldwide if patients can still find organs more cheaply abroad. However, it is reasonable to suspect that an American market would significantly reduce the demand for black market organs, especially given the ability of a regulated market to better ensure the quality of its product. Furthermore, a legalized market in the U.S. (with appropriate safeguards to prevent abuse of sellers) may lead to similar structures abroad. On the other hand, one might argue that competing markets might lead to a "race to the bottom" in terms of regulatory standards, as each country tries to gain more market share.
1,779
<h4>Second, Legalizing organ sales in the US spills over globally </h4><p><strong>Calandrillo 4</strong> Steve P. Calandrillo, Associate Professor, Univ. of Washington School of Law. J.D., Harvard Law School. B.A. in Economics, Univ. of California at Berkeley. George Mason Law Review Fall, 2004 13 Geo. Mason L. Rev. 69 ARTICLE: Cash for Kidneys? Utilizing Incentives to End America's Organ Shortage lexis</p><p> Moreover, <u><mark>if we cannot prevent the black markets in human organs</mark> that continue to thrive worldwide today, a thoughtful and responsible regulatory solution in <mark>America might be the best response</u></mark>. Many scholars have chronicled the reality that today's black markets lead to a host of abuses, provide for no follow-up health care, and generally exploit the poor to the wealthy's advantage. n180 Stephen Spurr details the potential for misrepresentation and fraud against both buyers and sellers today, as prices spiral out of control for organs that are of dubious quality. n181 Gloria Banks decries the exploitation of society's most vulnerable individuals in the organ sale trade, and urges legal and ethical safeguards for their protection. n182 Susan Hankin Denise adds that a properly regulated organ market may therefore be a better solution to the problem of scarcity than the outright ban we witness today. n183 FOOTNOTE ATTACHED n183 See Denise, supra note 72, at 1035-36 (arguing that regulated markets are superior to the existing ban on organ sales in the U.S.). Of course, even <u><mark>a well-regulated legalized market in the U.S.</mark> </u>may not completely eliminate black markets worldwide<u> </u>if patients can still find organs more cheaply abroad. <u>However, it is reasonable to suspect that an American market <mark>would <strong>significantly reduce the demand for black market organs</strong>, especially given the ability of a regulated market to better ensure <strong>the quality of its product</strong></mark>. Furthermore, <mark>a legalized market</mark> in the <mark>U.S.</mark> (with appropriate safeguards to prevent abuse of sellers) <strong><mark>may lead to similar structures abroad</strong></mark>.</u> On the other hand, one might argue that competing markets might lead to a "race to the bottom" in terms of regulatory standards, as each country tries to gain more market share. </p>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
430,264
17
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,534
Illegal market abuses are not an indication of what legal sales would be like – just the opposite
Kaserman, 7
Kaserman, 7 Dr. David Kaserman is currently Torchmark Professor of Economics at Auburn University.
In a truly ironic twist of logic, some opponents of the use of financial incentives have cited abuses and high prices associated with such black market activities as har-bingers of the sorts of outcomes likely to accompany legalized organ markets This line of "reasoning" is equivalent to arguing that legalization of liquor sales would lead to the sorts of mafia-related activities that arose during prohibi-tion. This argument stands accepted economic theory on its head. The truth is that the types of behavior and price levels that frequently accompany black market sales tend to disappear when trade is legalized Eliminating the shortage of cadaveric organs through legalization of financial incentives would greatly reduce, if not eliminate, the demand for living donor kidneys obtained through black markets
some opponents of the use of financial incentives ited buses to accompany legalized organ markets This line of "reasoning" is equivalent to arguing that legalization of liquor sales would lead to the sorts of mafia-related activities that arose during prohibi-tion This argument stands accepted economic theory on its head. The truth is that the types of behavior and price levels that frequently accompany black market sales tend to disappear when trade is legalized.
Issues in Law & Medicine Summer, 2007 23 Issues L. & Med. 45 ARTICLE: Fifty Years of Organ Transplants: The Successes and The Failures lexis In a truly ironic twist of logic, some opponents of the use of financial incentives for cadaveric organ donors have cited various human rights abuses and extraordinarily high prices associated with such black market activities as har-bingers of the sorts of outcomes likely to accompany legalized organ markets. n32 This line of "reasoning" is equivalent to arguing that legalization of liquor sales would lead to the sorts of mafia-related activities that arose during prohibi-tion. This argument stands accepted economic theory on its head. The truth is that the types of behavior and price levels that frequently accompany black market sales tend to disappear when trade is legalized. Legalized trade allows the market price to fall as legitimate businesses enter the market and increase supply. Moreover, costs decrease as the risks of both prosecution and violent actions by rival producers are eliminated. The outcome is lower prices, an increase in the volume of trade, and a cessation of criminal activities. Thus, the types of conduct associated with illegal suppliers involved in black market trade and the prices at which such trade takes place do not accurately reflect the behavior and prices likely to result from legalized sales. In fact, it has long been recognized that the most effective remedy for undesirable black market activity is to eliminate restrictions on trade. Stated succinctly, the cure for black market abuses is legalized trade. That conclusion holds a fortiori, in the case at hand. Eliminating the shortage of cadaveric organs through legalization of financial incentives would greatly reduce, if not eliminate, the demand for living donor kidneys obtained through black markets. Therefore, if one is opposed to current black market activities, then one should favor financial incentives for cadaveric organ donors.
2,002
<h4>Illegal market abuses are not an indication of what legal sales would be like – just the opposite</h4><p><strong>Kaserman, 7</strong> Dr. David Kaserman is currently Torchmark Professor of Economics at Auburn University. </p><p>Issues in Law & Medicine Summer, 2007 23 Issues L. & Med. 45 ARTICLE: Fifty Years of Organ Transplants: The Successes and The Failures lexis</p><p><u>In a truly ironic twist of logic, <mark>some opponents of the use of financial incentives</u></mark> for cadaveric organ donors <u>have c<mark>ited</mark> </u>various human rights <u>a<mark>buses</mark> and </u>extraordinarily <u>high prices associated with such black market activities as har-bingers of the sorts of outcomes likely <mark>to accompany legalized organ markets</u></mark>. n32 <u><mark>This line of "reasoning" is equivalent to arguing that legalization of liquor sales would lead to the sorts of mafia-related activities that arose during prohibi-tion</mark>. <mark>This argument stands accepted economic theory on its head. The truth is that the types of behavior and price levels that frequently accompany black market sales tend to disappear when trade is legalized</u>.</mark> Legalized trade allows the market price to fall as legitimate businesses enter the market and increase supply. Moreover, costs decrease as the risks of both prosecution and violent actions by rival producers are eliminated. The outcome is lower prices, an increase in the volume of trade, and a cessation of criminal activities. Thus, the types of conduct associated with illegal suppliers involved in black market trade and the prices at which such trade takes place do not accurately reflect the behavior and prices likely to result from legalized sales. In fact, it has long been recognized that the most effective remedy for undesirable black market activity is to eliminate restrictions on trade. Stated succinctly, the cure for black market abuses is legalized trade. That conclusion holds a fortiori, in the case at hand. <u>Eliminating the shortage of cadaveric organs through legalization of financial incentives would greatly reduce, if not eliminate, the demand for living donor kidneys obtained through black markets</u><strong>. Therefore, if one is opposed to current black market activities, then one should favor financial incentives for cadaveric organ donors. </p></strong>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
430,263
5
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,535
Specifically, debate over organ sales is necessary given shortages
Smith 11
Smith 11 Lewis Smith 05 January 2011 The Independent Sale of human organs should be legalised, say surgeons http://www.independent.co.uk/life-style/health-and-families/health-news/sale-of-human-organs-should-be-legalised-say-surgeons-2176110.html
Professor John Harris, an ethicist at the University of Manchester, believes a debate of an organ market long overdue. Professor Bell, former vice-president of the Royal College of Surgeons wants a public debate because there is such a shortage of organs for transplantation: "It is time to debate it again Opponents agree there should be a public debate about the merits and flaws of a market in organs. "The British Transplantation Society opposes this view, however it is prepared to debate this issue as the theoretical and empirical literature evolves," said a spokesman. Keith Rigg, the transplant surgeon and BTS president, said: "I'm happy to debate it. There are pros and cons
an ethicist at the University of Manchester, believes a debate of an organ market long overdue former vice-president of the Royal College of Surgeons wants a public debate because there is such a shortage of organs for transplantation: "It is time to debate it again Opponents agree there should be a public debate about the merits and flaws of a market in organs
Professor John Harris, an ethicist at the University of Manchester, believes a debate and the introduction of an organ market are long overdue. "Morality demands it," he said. "It's time to consider it because this country, to its eternal shame, has allowed a completely unnecessary shortage for 30 years. Thousands of people die each year [internationally] for want of organs. That's the measure of the urgency of the problem. "Being paid doesn't nullify altruism – doctors aren't less caring because they are paid. With the current system, everyone gets paid except for the donor." Professor Harris has developed proposals for an ethical market in organs in which donors would be paid as part of a regulated system. Such a system, he said, would have to be controlled within a strictly defined community, probably the UK but possibly extended to the EU, so every organ could be accounted for. No imports would be allowed. The NHS would be the sole supplier and would distribute organs as it does other treatments – ability to pay would not be a factor. Consent would be required for every donation and would have to be rigorously carried out to ensure no donor was subjected to untoward pressure. Professor Sir Peter Bell, former vice-president of the Royal College of Surgeons but now retired from practice, wants a public debate because there is such a shortage of organs for transplantation: "It is time to debate it again.[…] There is a great shortage of organs." There remains stiff opposition to liberalising the market, not least from the British Transplantation Society (BTS). Opponents agree there should be a public debate about the merits and flaws of a market in organs. "The British Transplantation Society opposes this view, however it is prepared to debate this issue as the theoretical and empirical literature evolves," said a spokesman. Keith Rigg, the transplant surgeon and BTS president, said: "I'm happy to debate it. There are pros and cons. I think the trouble is it would require a huge change in public opinion and legislation. One argument against a regulated market is if you are paying some people, what would be the impact on the existing deceased donor programme and living donor programme?"
2,224
<h4><strong>Specifically, debate over organ sales is necessary given shortages</h4><p>Smith 11</strong> Lewis Smith 05 January 2011 The Independent Sale of human organs should be legalised, say surgeons http://www.independent.co.uk/life-style/health-and-families/health-news/sale-of-human-organs-should-be-legalised-say-surgeons-2176110.html</p><p><u>Professor John Harris, <mark>an ethicist at the University of Manchester, believes a debate</mark> </u>and the introduction <u><mark>of an organ market</mark> </u>are <u><mark>long overdue</mark>.</u> "Morality demands it," he said. "It's time to consider it because this country, to its eternal shame, has allowed a completely unnecessary shortage for 30 years. Thousands of people die each year [internationally] for want of organs. That's the measure of the urgency of the problem. "Being paid doesn't nullify altruism – doctors aren't less caring because they are paid. With the current system, everyone gets paid except for the donor." Professor Harris has developed proposals for an ethical market in organs in which donors would be paid as part of a regulated system. Such a system, he said, would have to be controlled within a strictly defined community, probably the UK but possibly extended to the EU, so every organ could be accounted for. No imports would be allowed. The NHS would be the sole supplier and would distribute organs as it does other treatments – ability to pay would not be a factor. Consent would be required for every donation and would have to be rigorously carried out to ensure no donor was subjected to untoward pressure. <u>Professor</u> Sir Peter <u>Bell, <mark>former vice-president of the Royal College of Surgeons</u></mark> but now retired from practice, <u><mark>wants a public debate because there is such a shortage of organs for transplantation: "It is time to debate it again</u></mark>.[…] There is a great shortage of organs." There remains stiff opposition to liberalising the market, not least from the British Transplantation Society (BTS). <u><mark>Opponents agree there should be a public debate about the merits and flaws of a market in organs</mark>. "The British Transplantation Society opposes this view, however it is prepared to debate this issue as the theoretical and empirical literature evolves," said a spokesman. Keith Rigg, the transplant surgeon and BTS president, said: "I'm happy to debate it. There are pros and cons</u>. I think the trouble is it would require a huge change in public opinion and legislation. One argument against a regulated market is if you are paying some people, what would be the impact on the existing deceased donor programme and living donor programme?"</p>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
430,265
4
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,536
Debate on effective implementation is a moral responsibility
Taub et al 3
Taub et al 3 Sara Taub, Andrew H. Maixner, Karine Morin, Robert M. Sade, For The Council On Ethical And Judicial Affairs, American Medical Association. "Cadaveric Organ Donation: Encouraging The Study Of Motivation." Transplantation Forum. Vol. 76, 748–751, No. 4, August 27, 2003. https://www.musc.edu/humanvalues/pdf/Cadaveric-organ-donation.pdf
If policymakers, ethicists, or legislators prohibit the implementation of programs that could be shown to increase the number of available organs and reduce the number of deaths, then they must bear some moral responsibility for the patients who die from lack of an organ transplant. Therefore, a better informed debate is necessary, one that can occur only after the effectiveness of various incentive models has been measured.
null
A thorough discussion of this matter also must include an examination of the costs of foregoing such studies. Currently, about 16 patients die each day waiting for an available organ (15). If policymakers, ethicists, or legislators prohibit the implementation of programs that could be shown to increase the number of available organs and reduce the number of deaths, then they must bear some moral responsibility for the patients who die from lack of an organ transplant. Therefore, a better informed debate is necessary, one that can occur only after the effectiveness of various incentive models has been measured.
617
<h4>Debate on effective implementation is a moral responsibility</h4><p><strong>Taub et al 3</strong> Sara Taub, Andrew H. Maixner, Karine Morin, Robert M. Sade, For The Council On Ethical And Judicial Affairs, American Medical Association. "Cadaveric Organ Donation: Encouraging The Study Of Motivation." Transplantation Forum. Vol. 76, 748–751, No. 4, August 27, 2003. <u>https://www.musc.edu/humanvalues/pdf/Cadaveric-organ-donation.pdf</p><p></u>A thorough discussion of this matter also must include an examination of the costs of foregoing such studies. Currently, about 16 patients die each day waiting for an available organ (15). <u>If policymakers, ethicists, or legislators prohibit the implementation of programs that could be shown to increase the number of available organs and reduce the number of deaths, then they must bear some moral responsibility for the patients who die from lack of an organ transplant. Therefore, a better informed debate is necessary, one that can occur only after the effectiveness of various incentive models has been measured.</p></u>
null
null
Contention 2 Worldwide transplants will be better
430,266
7
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,537
The plan is an example of the broader principle of using prices as a mechanism to allocate resources. Market mechanism are an effective means; non-market economies have no other means of allocating resources than bureaucratic choice and this usually fails
Gongol 9
Gongol 9—owner Gongol.com[Brian, “Is Socialism Good for the Environment?” ,http://www.gongol.com/research/economics/socialismandtheenvironment/]RMT
Socialism assumes someone or some group has the ability to predict and plan for the needs of the many. This kind of omniscience is plainly impossible. there will inevitably be some difference between what the planner expects supply and demand for Stuff to be and what actually emerges. when too little Stuff is produced to meet demand, people needlessly suffer. this planning function is routinely achieved with great efficiency by the feedback systems of a market economy, in which freely-moving prices effectively tell everyone in the market whether too much or too little of anything is being produced
Socialism ability to predict needs of the many omniscience is plainly impossible. inevitably be some difference between expects supply and demand when too little Stuff is produced to meet demand, people needlessly suffe the feedback systems of a market economy effectively tell everyone in the market whether too much or too little of anything is being produced
Socialism assumes that someone or some group of people has the ability to predict and plan for the needs of the many. This kind of omniscience is plainly impossible. Pretend, for instance, that everything that people might need or want can be lumped together in a single category, called "Stuff." In any given planning period, the planner must determine how much Stuff people will want and how much Stuff must be produced. But there will inevitably be some difference between what the planner expects supply and demand for Stuff to be and what actually emerges. Even if the planner is occasionally correct, every deviation from the actual demand for Stuff causes waste -- when too little Stuff is produced to meet demand, people needlessly suffer. When too much Stuff is produced to meet demand, all that extra Stuff represents waste. Even a really, really good planner will be unable to accurately predict the vast fluctuations in day-to-day demand for Stuff, leading to huge amounts of either waste or suffering. Yet this planning function is routinely achieved with great efficiency by the feedback systems of a market economy, in which freely-moving prices effectively tell everyone in the market whether too much or too little of anything is being produced.
1,262
<h4><strong>The plan is an example of the broader principle of using prices as a mechanism to allocate resources. Market mechanism are an effective means; non-market economies have no other means of allocating resources than bureaucratic choice and this usually fails</h4><p>Gongol 9</strong>—owner Gongol.com[Brian, “Is Socialism Good for the Environment?” ,http://www.gongol.com/research/economics/socialismandtheenvironment/]RMT </p><p><u><mark>Socialism</mark> assumes </u>that<u> someone or some group </u>of people <u>has the <mark>ability to predict</mark> and plan for the <mark>needs of the many</mark>. This kind of <mark>omniscience is plainly impossible.</u></mark> Pretend, for instance, that everything that people might need or want can be lumped together in a single category, called "Stuff." In any given planning period, the planner must determine how much Stuff people will want and how much Stuff must be produced. But <u>there will <mark>inevitably be some difference between </mark>what the planner <mark>expects supply and demand</mark> for Stuff to be and what actually emerges. </u>Even if the planner is occasionally correct, every deviation from the actual demand for Stuff causes waste -- <u><mark>when too little Stuff is produced to meet demand, people needlessly suffe</mark>r.</u> When too much Stuff is produced to meet demand, all that extra Stuff represents waste. Even a really, really good planner will be unable to accurately predict the vast fluctuations in day-to-day demand for Stuff, leading to huge amounts of either waste or suffering. Yet <u>this planning function is routinely achieved with great efficiency by <mark>the feedback systems of a market economy</mark>, in which freely-moving prices <mark>effectively tell everyone in the market whether too much or too little of anything is being produced</u><strong></mark>. </p></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
229,027
7
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,538
Without prices to allocate resources, planners make the decisions on resource allocation, and they are too often subject to cronies and corruptions
Tanner 93
Mack Tanner Oct 93 The Common Good and the Free Rider, Freeman
http://www.thefreemanonline.org/columns/the-common-good-and-the-free-rider/ The central planners never serve the common good; they always serve the good of those who are clever enough to work the system to their own advantage. The winners are always the politicians, the bureaucrats, and those who learn to manipulate the system by spending money in the right places.
central planners serve the good of those who are clever enough to work the system The winners are always the politicians who learn to manipulate the system
http://www.thefreemanonline.org/columns/the-common-good-and-the-free-rider/ With the politicians and bureaucrats controlling growing amounts of money that have been forcibly collected in taxes, every citizen does everything possible to reduce the taxes he pays and to increase the benefits derived from the treasury. It’s a lot easier in America these days to join the free riders and pile onto the entitlements bandwagon than it is to engage in productive activity and then see forty percent or more of one’s income taken in taxes and given to other people. The central planners never serve the common good; they always serve the good of those who are clever enough to work the system to their own advantage. The winners are always the politicians, the bureaucrats, and those who learn to manipulate the system by spending money in the right places.
850
<h4><strong>Without prices to allocate resources, planners make the decisions on resource allocation, and they are too often subject to cronies and corruptions</h4><p></strong>Mack <strong>Tanner<u> </u></strong> Oct <strong>93<u> </u></strong> The Common Good and the Free Rider, Freeman</p><p><u>http://www.thefreemanonline.org/columns/the-common-good-and-the-free-rider/</p><p></u>With the politicians and bureaucrats controlling growing amounts of money that have been forcibly collected in taxes, every citizen does everything possible to reduce the taxes he pays and to increase the benefits derived from the treasury. It’s a lot easier in America these days to join the free riders and pile onto the entitlements bandwagon than it is to engage in productive activity and then see forty percent or more of one’s income taken in taxes and given to other people. <u>The <mark>central planners</mark> never serve the common good; they always<mark> serve the good of those who are clever enough to work the system</mark> to their own advantage. <mark>The winners are always the politicians</mark>, the bureaucrats, and those <mark>who learn to manipulate the system<strong></mark> by spending money in the right places. </p></u></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
430,269
1
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,539
By "regulation" we mean all government intervention in the market place. This would include not only regulation of business with regard to things like workplace safety and environmental quality, it also involves interventions like transfer payments, including public assistance and social security.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><strong>By "regulation" we mean all government intervention in the market place. This would include not only regulation of business with regard to things like workplace safety and environmental quality, it also involves interventions like transfer payments, including public assistance and social security.</h4></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
430,267
1
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,540
This should make it obvious that criticisms of pure capitalism are totally irrelevant.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><strong>This should make it obvious that criticisms of pure capitalism are totally irrelevant.</h4></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
430,268
1
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,541
Central purchasing is an example of regulated cap
Block et al 99
Block et al 99 Walter Block, Professor and Chair of the Department of Economics & Finance at the University of Central Arkansas; Roy Whitehead, Associate Professor of Business Law; Clint Johnson, Professor of Economics & Finance; Mana Davidson, Alan White & Stacey Chandler were students in Block's course, Modern Political Economy. Quinnipiac Health Law 1999 / 2000 3 Quinnipiac Health L.J. 87
, "the federal government might be designated as the only authority with the power to buy organs for transplants and would allocate them to hospitals with patients that need transplants." A market controlled by the government is certainly not compatible with free enterprise. Becker's idea more resembles marketing boards for agricultural products - where all farmers are compelled to sell only to state authorities - than a true free market.
null
SPECIAL SECTION: Human Organ Transplantation: Economic & Legal Issues lexis Gary Becker, the 1992 Nobel Laureate in economics, argued against price controls for body parts: "When demand exceeds supply for ordinary goods, the price is raised to suppliers in order to induce them to increase the quantities pro-vided. Using similar incentives would induce more people to allow their organs to be used for transplants after they die." n102 Certainly, this is consonant with the message of the present article. However, Becker nearly retracts his statement by stating, "the federal government might be designated as the only authority with the power to buy organs for transplants and would allocate them to hospitals with patients that need transplants." n103 This prospect [*108] is highly problematic. A market controlled by the government is certainly not compatible with free enterprise. It would be lunacy to advocate that the federal government play any such role with regard to "ordinary goods." Why should it do so in the market for body organs? Has not the lesson of the fall of the Berlin Wall and the debacle of the Russian economy taught us the lesson that central control of the economy is not only highly inefficient, but a violation of economic freedom as well? Becker concedes that freely fluctuating prices can bring supply into line with demand. n104 Why this mechanism could not work in the present situation is not specified by him. n105 Becker's idea may be preferable to the present system, but it more resembles marketing boards for agricultural products - where all farmers are compelled to sell only to state authorities - than a true free market. n106
1,683
<h4><strong>Central purchasing is an example of regulated cap</h4><p>Block et al 99</strong> Walter Block, Professor and Chair of the Department of Economics & Finance at the University of Central Arkansas; Roy Whitehead, Associate Professor of Business Law; Clint Johnson, Professor of Economics & Finance; Mana Davidson, Alan White & Stacey Chandler were students in Block's course, Modern Political Economy. Quinnipiac Health Law 1999 / 2000 3 Quinnipiac Health L.J. 87</p><p>SPECIAL SECTION: Human Organ Transplantation: Economic & Legal Issues lexis</p><p>Gary Becker, the 1992 Nobel Laureate in economics, argued against price controls for body parts: "When demand exceeds supply for ordinary goods, the price is raised to suppliers in order to induce them to increase the quantities pro-vided. Using similar incentives would induce more people to allow their organs to be used for transplants after they die." n102 Certainly, this is consonant with the message of the present article. However, Becker nearly retracts his statement by stating<u>, "the federal government might be designated as the only authority with the power to buy organs for transplants and would allocate them to hospitals with patients that need transplants."</u> n103 This prospect [*108] is highly problematic. <u>A market controlled by the government is certainly not compatible with free enterprise.</u> It would be lunacy to advocate that the federal government play any such role with regard to "ordinary goods." Why should it do so in the market for body organs? Has not the lesson of the fall of the Berlin Wall and the debacle of the Russian economy taught us the lesson that central control of the economy is not only highly inefficient, but a violation of economic freedom as well? Becker concedes that freely fluctuating prices can bring supply into line with demand. n104 Why this mechanism could not work in the present situation is not specified by him. n105 <u>Becker's idea</u> may be preferable to the present system, but it <u>more resembles marketing boards for agricultural products - where all farmers are compelled to sell only to state authorities - than a true free market. </u><strong>n106</p></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
430,270
1
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,542
regulated cap avoids all problems of pure capitalism
Newman 12
Newman 12 Rick Newman, author of Rebounders: How Winners Pivot From Setback To Success. December 6, 2012
America hasn't had pure capitalism in well over a century In the 1800s, the federal government largely stayed out of the economy, with nothing like the regulatory apparatus we have now. Public pressure led to a long series of reforms that morphed into the regulated free-market economy we have today ). We still have a capitalist system centered on private ownership and prices set by the free market, but it's layered with rules meant to prevent abuses.
America hasn't had pure capitalism in well over a century 1800s, nothing like the regulatory apparatus we have now We still have a capitalist system centered on private ownership and prices set by the free market, but it's layered with rules meant to prevent abuses
USNEWS.com HEADLINE: Why the Tension Between Socialism and Capitalism Will Intensify lexis This year's presidential election included many bastardized references to both economic systems, which have been broadly mischaracterized for a long time. Many defenders of capitalism argue that the nation's economic system was more pure a decade ago (or two, or three), but America hasn't had pure capitalism in well over a century. And when it did have a raw form of capitalism, the consequences were often disastrous for significant chunks of the population, which is why public support grew for the kind of [ENJOY: Political Cartoons on the Republican Party] In the 1800s, the federal government largely stayed out of the economy, with nothing like the regulatory apparatus we have now. That's one reason people like Andrew Carnegie, John Jacob Astor, John D. Rockefeller, Cornelius Vanderbilt, and J.P. Morgan built vast fortunes -- often from monopolies or cartels--that still exist in various forms today. But unregulated capitalism also generated speculative bubbles, financial panics and destitution much more frequently than those things have occurred over the last 70 years. Public pressure led to a long series of reforms that morphed into the regulated free-market economy we have today. In the early 1900s, Teddy Roosevelt started to break up some of the all-powerful monopolies that enriched a few while overcharging the masses. Congress created the Federal Reserve and the income tax in 1913. A slew of regulatory agencies grew out of the Great Depression. During the 20th century, presidents of both parties signed legislation creating new agencies to oversee food, medicine, the environment and Wall Street (ahem). We still have a capitalist system centered on private ownership and prices set by the free market, but it's layered with rules meant to prevent abuses.
1,878
<h4><strong>regulated cap avoids all problems of pure capitalism</h4><p>Newman 12</strong> Rick Newman, author of Rebounders: How Winners Pivot From Setback To Success. December 6, 2012</p><p>USNEWS.com HEADLINE: Why the Tension Between Socialism and Capitalism Will Intensify lexis</p><p>This year's presidential election included many bastardized references to both economic systems, which have been broadly mischaracterized for a long time. Many defenders of capitalism argue that the nation's economic system was more pure a decade ago (or two, or three), but <u><mark>America hasn't had pure capitalism in well over a century</u></mark>. And when it did have a raw form of capitalism, the consequences were often disastrous for significant chunks of the population, which is why public support grew for the kind of [ENJOY: Political Cartoons on the Republican Party]</p><p><u>In the <mark>1800s, </mark>the federal government largely stayed out of the economy, with <mark>nothing like the regulatory apparatus we have now</mark>.</u> That's one reason people like Andrew Carnegie, John Jacob Astor, John D. Rockefeller, Cornelius Vanderbilt, and J.P. Morgan built vast fortunes -- often from monopolies or cartels--that still exist in various forms today. But unregulated capitalism also generated speculative bubbles, financial panics and destitution much more frequently than those things have occurred over the last 70 years.</p><p><u>Public pressure led to a long series of reforms that morphed into the regulated free-market economy we have today</u>. In the early 1900s, Teddy Roosevelt started to break up some of the all-powerful monopolies that enriched a few while overcharging the masses. Congress created the Federal Reserve and the income tax in 1913. A slew of regulatory agencies grew out of the Great Depression. During the 20th century, presidents of both parties signed legislation creating new agencies to oversee food, medicine, the environment and Wall Street (ahem<u><strong>). <mark>We still have a capitalist system centered on private ownership and prices set by the free market, but it's layered with rules meant to prevent abuses</mark>.</p></u></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
194,434
9
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,543
Regulated capitalism gets the benefits of market mechanisms while avoiding the indictments through government intervention.
Foster 9
Foster 9 Nathan Foster SEPTEMBER 14, 2009 Regulated Capitalism vs. Socialism http://open.salon.com/blog/nathan_foster/2009/09/14/regulated_capitalism_vs_socialism
Regulated capitalism allows for the private ownership of capital, but regulates its use. any law or regulation reflects a degree of public control, and therefore, in a sense, regulated capitalism is really some degree of public control of capital I'm speaking of laws which protect the safety of the public, not direct control of capital, Strict regulation should be enough to prevent abuses of capital.
Regulated capitalism allows for the private ownership of capital, but regulates its use. regulated capitalism is really some degree of public control of capital protect the safety of the public not direct control of capital, Strict regulation should be enough to prevent abuses of capital
On the other hand, there is at least a hair-thin distinction between socialism and regulated capitalism. Regulated capitalism, as I envision it, allows for the private ownership of capital, but regulates its use. I'll allow for progressive taxation—the rich can be taxed more than the poor, which is justified based on the idea that the rich really don't have anything important to do with 30% of their money anyway. I'll also allow for trust-busting, as this is a form of regulation. The only possible argument that regulated capitalism is in fact socialism rests on the assumption that any law or regulation reflects a degree of public control, and therefore, in a sense, regulated capitalism is really some degree of public control of capital. But I think this argument falls apart because I'm speaking of laws which protect the safety of the public, not direct control of capital, and every nation on earth, no matter what system of government or socio-economic system you choose to identify it with, has laws to protect the safety of the public. You therefore can't use such laws to discriminate between different socio-economic systems or systems of government. That said, I prefer regulated capitalism to socialism for a couple of reasons. 1) Having money and influence is just sweet. I know this sounds silly, but the idea should not be discarded. I think there is real public benefit to having a class of people who have more money than they know what to do with. It shows just how good life gets, and motivates the public to improve their position. It is also, obviously, beneficial to those people who have the money. They get to enjoy life, and I think that's good for everybody. 2) Strict regulation should be enough to prevent abuses of capital. You don't have to resort to public ownership to prevent these abuses.
1,829
<h4><strong>Regulated capitalism gets the benefits of market mechanisms while avoiding the indictments through government intervention.</h4><p>Foster 9</strong> Nathan Foster SEPTEMBER 14, 2009 Regulated Capitalism vs. Socialism</p><p>http://open.salon.com/blog/nathan_foster/2009/09/14/regulated_capitalism_vs_socialism</p><p>On the other hand, there is at least a hair-thin distinction between socialism and regulated capitalism. <u><mark>Regulated capitalism</u></mark>, as I envision it,<u> <mark>allows for the private ownership of capital, but regulates its use.</u></mark> I'll allow for progressive taxation—the rich can be taxed more than the poor, which is justified based on the idea that the rich really don't have anything important to do with 30% of their money anyway. I'll also allow for trust-busting, as this is a form of regulation.</p><p>The only possible argument that regulated capitalism is in fact socialism rests on the assumption that <u>any law or regulation reflects a degree of public control, and therefore, in a sense, <mark>regulated capitalism is really some degree of public control of capital</u></mark>. But I think this argument falls apart because<u> I'm speaking of laws which <mark>protect the safety of the public</mark>, <mark>not direct control of capital,</u></mark> and every nation on earth, no matter what system of government or socio-economic system you choose to identify it with, has laws to protect the safety of the public. You therefore can't use such laws to discriminate between different socio-economic systems or systems of government.</p><p>That said, I prefer regulated capitalism to socialism for a couple of reasons.</p><p>1) Having money and influence is just sweet. I know this sounds silly, but the idea should not be discarded. I think there is real public benefit to having a class of people who have more money than they know what to do with. It shows just how good life gets, and motivates the public to improve their position. It is also, obviously, beneficial to those people who have the money. They get to enjoy life, and I think that's good for everybody.</p><p>2) <u><mark>Strict regulation should be enough to prevent abuses of capital</mark>. </u><strong>You don't have to resort to public ownership to prevent these abuses.</p></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
228,999
4
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,544
The benefits of regulated capitalism are clear. For example, it empirically reduces absolute poverty
Klein 12
Klein 12 Joe Klein Dec. 03, 2012 Time Magazine Campaign 2012: The Report Card
socialism has been an utter failure, and regulated capitalism has been the greatest eradicator of poverty in the history of the world. most people are comfortable with a regulated free-enterprise system in which the government helps provide education and health care for everyone and financial support for those who need it most,
regulated capitalism has been the greatest eradicator of poverty in the history of the world helps provide education and health care for everyone and financial support for those who need it most
http://www.time.com/time/magazine/article/0,9171,2129804,00.html I checked the dictionary. And socialism languishes there, just as it always has: "a system or condition of society in which the means of production are owned and controlled by the state." Is that what 49% of young people favor? I don't think so. If it is, count me on Bennett's team. That sort of socialism has been an utter failure, and regulated capitalism has been the greatest eradicator of poverty in the history of the world. But I suspect--and this would be wonderfully ironic, if true--that all those blacks and young people got their definition of socialism from Rush Limbaugh and the other wing-nut foghorns: socialism is when the government helps people out. What we've decided in this election is that most people are comfortable with a regulated free-enterprise system in which the government helps provide education and health care for everyone and financial support for those who need it most, especially the elderly. What we'll continue to debate is how extensive those regulations and supports should be. But there is no question--except in the minds of the deluded--that any of our truly basic freedoms, especially the freedom to make money, are threatened in any significant way. In the real world, there is less drama to all this than meets the eye. Lessons have been learned. I remain optimistic that the professional politicians who lead the Republican Party will find a way to close a budget deal long before we reach a cliff, since they know they'll be blamed by a voting majority of Americans for any impasse.
1,599
<h4><strong>The benefits of regulated capitalism are clear. For example, it empirically reduces absolute poverty</h4><p>Klein 12</strong> Joe Klein Dec. 03, 2012 Time Magazine Campaign 2012: The Report Card</p><p>http://www.time.com/time/magazine/article/0,9171,2129804,00.html</p><p>I checked the dictionary. And socialism languishes there, just as it always has: "a system or condition of society in which the means of production are owned and controlled by the state." Is that what 49% of young people favor? I don't think so. If it is, count me on Bennett's team. That sort of <u>socialism has been an utter failure, and <mark>regulated capitalism has been the greatest eradicator of poverty in the history of the world</mark>. </u>But I suspect--and this would be wonderfully ironic, if true--that all those blacks and young people got their definition of socialism from Rush Limbaugh and the other wing-nut foghorns: socialism is when the government helps people out.</p><p>What we've decided in this election is that <u>most people are comfortable with a regulated free-enterprise system in which the government <mark>helps provide education and health care for everyone and financial</mark> <mark>support for those who need it most</mark>, </u><strong>especially the elderly. What we'll continue to debate is how extensive those regulations and supports should be. But there is no question--except in the minds of the deluded--that any of our truly basic freedoms, especially the freedom to make money, are threatened in any significant way. In the real world, there is less drama to all this than meets the eye. Lessons have been learned. I remain optimistic that the professional politicians who lead the Republican Party will find a way to close a budget deal long before we reach a cliff, since they know they'll be blamed by a voting majority of Americans for any impasse.</p></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
194,438
4
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,545
Plan’s regulated market is the best way to solve—it’s the only method to eliminate exploitation—the alternative IS the black market
Satel and Hakim, 08
Satel and Hakim, 08 – MD, Resident Scholar, American Enterprise Institute, AND MD, Transplant Surgeon, Former President, International College of Surgeons (Sally AND Nadey, June 20, 2008, “What's Wrong with Selling Kidneys?,” American Enterprise Institute, http://www.aei.org/article/health/whats-wrong-with-selling-kidneys/,)
much of the world transplant establishment WHO advocate remedies that do not go far enough They insist on obliterating organ trafficking but ignore the time-tested fact that trying to stamp out underground markets either drives corruption further underground or causes it to flourish elsewhere trafficking will only recede when the crying need for organs disappears. The remedy to this corrupt and unregulated system of exchange is its mirror image: a regulated and transparent regime devoted to donor protection We suggest a system in which compensation is provided by a third party government, a charity or insurance and overseen by the government Because bidding and private buying will not be permitted, available organs will be distributed to the next in line--not just to the wealthy. we suggest that lump-sum cash payments not be offered By providing in-kind rewards the program would not be attractive to people who might otherwise rush to donate on the promise of a large sum of instant cash The only way to stop illicit markets is to create legal ones there is no better justification for testing legal modes of exchange than the very depredations of the underground market
WHO remedies do not go far enough trying to stamp out underground markets either drives corruption further underground or causes it to flourish elsewhere trafficking will only recede when the crying need for organs disappears The remedy to this unregulated system is a regulated and transparent regime devoted to donor protection. We suggest a system in which compensation is provided by a nd overseen by the government. Because bidding will not be permitted, organs will be distributed to the next in line--not just to the wealthy we suggest providing in-kind rewards -the program would not be attractive to people who might otherwise rush to donate on the promise of a large sum of instant cash. The only way to stop illicit markets is to create legal ones
Unfortunately, much of the world transplant establishment--including the WHO, the international Transplantation Society and the World Medical Association--advocate remedies that do not go far enough. They insist on obliterating organ trafficking but ignore the time-tested fact that trying to stamp out underground markets either drives corruption further underground or causes it to flourish elsewhere. The truth is that trafficking will only recede when the crying need for organs disappears. Opponents also allege that a legal system of exchange will inevitably replicate the sins of the black market. This is utterly backward. The remedy to this corrupt and unregulated system of exchange is its mirror image: a regulated and transparent regime devoted to donor protection. We suggest a system in which compensation is provided by a third party (government, a charity or insurance) and overseen by the government. Because bidding and private buying will not be permitted, available organs will be distributed to the next in line--not just to the wealthy. Finally, we suggest that lump-sum cash payments not be offered. By providing in-kind rewards--such as a down payment on a house, a contribution to a retirement fund or lifetime health insurance--the program would not be attractive to people who might otherwise rush to donate on the promise of a large sum of instant cash. The only way to stop illicit markets is to create legal ones. Indeed, there is no better justification for testing legal modes of exchange than the very depredations of the underground market.
1,574
<h4><strong>Plan’s regulated market is the best way to solve—it’s the <u>only </u>method to eliminate <u>exploitation</u>—the alternative IS the black market</h4><p>Satel and Hakim, 08</strong> – MD, Resident Scholar, American Enterprise Institute, AND MD, Transplant Surgeon, Former President, International College of Surgeons (Sally AND Nadey, June 20, 2008, “What's Wrong with Selling Kidneys?,” American Enterprise Institute, http://www.aei.org/article/health/whats-wrong-with-selling-kidneys/,)</p><p>Unfortunately, <u>much of the world transplant establishment</u>--including the <u><mark>WHO</u></mark>, the international Transplantation Society and the World Medical Association--<u>advocate <mark>remedies</mark> that <mark>do not go far enough</u></mark>. <u>They insist on obliterating organ trafficking but ignore the time-tested fact that <mark>trying to stamp out underground markets either drives corruption further underground or causes it to flourish elsewhere</u></mark>. The truth is that <u><mark>trafficking will only recede when the crying need for organs disappears</mark>. </u>Opponents also allege that a legal system of exchange will inevitably replicate the sins of the black market. This is utterly backward. <u><mark>The remedy to this</mark> corrupt and <mark>unregulated system</mark> of exchange <mark>is</mark> its mirror image: <mark>a regulated and transparent regime devoted to donor protection</u>. <u>We suggest a system in which compensation is provided by a </mark>third party</u> (<u>government, a charity or insurance</u>) <u>a<mark>nd overseen by the government</u>. <u>Because bidding</mark> and private buying <mark>will not be permitted,</mark> available <mark>organs will be distributed to the next in line--not just to the wealthy</mark>. </u>Finally, <u><mark>we suggest</mark> that lump-sum cash payments not be offered</u>. <u>By <mark>providing in-kind rewards</u></mark>--such as a down payment on a house, a contribution to a retirement fund or lifetime health insurance-<mark>-<u>the program would not be attractive to people who might otherwise rush to donate on the promise of a large sum of instant cash</u>. <u>The only way to stop illicit markets is to create legal ones</u></mark>. Indeed, <u>there is no better justification for testing legal modes of exchange than the very depredations of the underground market</u><strong>.</p></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
430,271
2
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,546
This success will continue
Hindery, 8
Hindery, 8 Leo Hindery, Jr. chairs the Smart Globalization Initiative at the New America Foundation, and is managing partner of a New York-based media industry private equity fund. Previously, he was CEO of AT&T Broadband and its predecessor, Tele-Communications, Inc. He is the author of "It Takes a CEO: It's Time to Lead With Integrity" October 31, 2008 02:02 PM Senator McCain, Regulated Capitalism is Not Socialism http://www.huffingtonpost.com/leo-hindery-jr/senator-mccain-regulated_b_139736.html
regulated capitalism we know with certainty promotes and fosters economic growth from the bottom up. Growth which will give us back full employment, a pathway to ending poverty, and progress toward solving the problems associated with our current health care, education, trade, taxation and ecology practices. The very best thing for America is and has always been a vibrant middle class that grows from the bottom up.
regulated capitalism fosters economic growth which will give us back full employment, a pathway to ending poverty, and progress toward solving the problems associated with our current health care, education, trade, taxation and ecology practices
Senator Obama's economic policies, however you want to describe them, would be the very best thing right now for American businesses, American workers and the American economy. His particular economic prescription would give us back vibrant, thoughtfully regulated capitalism of the sort that we know with certainty promotes and fosters economic growth from the bottom up. Growth which will give us back full employment, a pathway to ending poverty, and progress toward solving the problems associated with our current health care, education, trade, taxation and ecology practices. The very best thing for America -- workers and businesses alike -- is and has always been a vibrant middle class that grows from the bottom up. And Senator Obama reminds us of this in almost every speech. From vigorously enforcing our domestic labor laws to enabling all workers to have an unrestricted ability to join a union, a President Obama would provide all workers, but especially lower-wage workers, with the opportunities and the tools and the policies they need to realize again the American Dreams that, lately, have been torn from their futures.
1,139
<h4><strong>This success will continue</h4><p>Hindery, 8</strong> Leo Hindery, Jr. chairs the Smart Globalization Initiative at the New America Foundation, and is managing partner of a New York-based media industry private equity fund. Previously, he was CEO of AT&T Broadband and its predecessor, Tele-Communications, Inc. He is the author of "It Takes a CEO: It's Time to Lead With Integrity" October 31, 2008 02:02 PM Senator McCain, Regulated Capitalism is Not Socialism <u>http://www.huffingtonpost.com/leo-hindery-jr/senator-mccain-regulated_b_139736.html</p><p></u>Senator Obama's economic policies, however you want to describe them, would be the very best thing right now for American businesses, American workers and the American economy. His particular economic prescription would give us back vibrant, thoughtfully <u><mark>regulated capitalism</u></mark> of the sort that <u>we know with certainty promotes and <mark>fosters economic growth</mark> from the bottom up. Growth <mark>which will give us back full employment, a pathway to ending poverty, and progress toward solving the problems associated with our current health care, education, trade, taxation and ecology practices</mark>.</p><p>The very best thing for America</u> -- workers and businesses alike -- <u>is and has always been a vibrant middle class that grows from the bottom up.</u> And Senator Obama reminds us of this in almost every speech.</p><p>From vigorously enforcing our domestic labor laws to enabling all workers to have an unrestricted ability to join a union, a President Obama would provide all workers, but especially lower-wage workers, with the opportunities and the tools and the policies they need to realize again the American Dreams that, lately, have been torn from their futures.</p>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
228,998
2
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,547
Millions of life years are saved
Whiteman 15
Whiteman 15 Honor Whiteman, Medical News Today Saturday 31 January 2015 Organ transplants in the US 'have saved almost 2.3 million years of life' http://www.medicalnewstoday.com/articles/288673.php
A doctor holding a human organ for transplant Almost 2.3 million life-years have been saved by organ transplants between 1987 and 2012, according to the study. of the Baylor College of Medicine In the US, around 79 people each day receive an organ transplant. Every 10 seconds, a person is added to the waiting list to receive one. Organ transplantation is normally the only effective treatment for end-stage organ failure, meaning people's lives literally depend on the procedure. Statistics up to the beginning of December 2012 reveal that of patients who received a heart transplant, almost 70% were alive 5 years later. For patients who received a kidney transplant from a living donor, 92% were alive 5 years after the procedure. With figures like these, it is no wonder Dr. Rana and colleagues hail organ transplantation as the "marvel of modern medicine." "Although most of the findings in this analysis are not novel, this analysis concisely reports on the collective experience of solid-organ transplant in the United States, making it, to our knowledge, the largest study in the field of transplantation yet conducted. focusing exclusively on the survival benefit does not capture the vast improvements in quality of life and the drastically lowered morbidity rates after a transplant."
null
Little more than 50 years ago, the world's first successful kidney transplant took place. Now, more than 16,000 kidney transplants take place each year in the US alone, indicative of just how far organ transplantation has come. Now, researchers have analyzed 25 years of transplant data to determine how many years of life have been saved by the procedure. A doctor holding a human organ for transplant Almost 2.3 million life-years have been saved by organ transplants between 1987 and 2012, according to the study. The research team, including Dr. Abbas Rana of the Baylor College of Medicine in Houston, TX, publishes their findings in JAMA Surgery. In the US, around 79 people each day receive an organ transplant. Every 10 seconds, a person is added to the waiting list to receive one. Organ transplantation is normally the only effective treatment for end-stage organ failure, meaning people's lives literally depend on the procedure. Statistics up to the beginning of December 2012 reveal that of patients who received a heart transplant, almost 70% were alive 5 years later. For patients who received a kidney transplant from a living donor, 92% were alive 5 years after the procedure. With figures like these, it is no wonder Dr. Rana and colleagues hail organ transplantation as the "marvel of modern medicine." For their study, however, the team wanted to delve deeper into the survival benefits of organ transplantation in the US. They set out to determine how many years of life the procedure has saved between 1987 and 2012. The number of life-years saved is a 'stellar accomplishment' In 1987, the United Network for Organ Sharing (UNOS) began keeping records of all solid organ transplants that take place in the US, as well as records of patients who were waiting for a transplant. Using the UNOS database, Dr. Rana and colleagues reviewed the records of 1,112,835 patients with end-stage organ failure. Of these, 533,329 received a transplant and 579,506 were on the waiting list but did not have the procedure. The researchers calculated the number of life-years saved by organ transplantation between September 1st, 1987 and December 31st, 2012 by comparing the survival outcomes of patients who underwent the procedure with those who did not. The results of the analysis revealed that over the 25-year period, organ transplantation saved 2,270,859 years of life in the US. Each organ transplant was estimated to have saved around 4.3 years of life. The researchers also estimated the years of life saved by each type of organ transplantation, which were: Kidney transplant - 1.3 million years of life saved Liver transplant - 465,296 years of life saved Heart transplant - 269,715 years of life saved Pancreas-kidney transplant - 79,198 years of life saved Lung transplant - 64,575 years of life saved Pancreas transplant - 14,903 years of life saved Intestine transplant - 4,402 years of life saved. The researchers hail the almost 2.3 million life-years saved by organ transplantation in the US as a "stellar accomplishment." They add: "Although most of the findings in this analysis are not novel, this analysis concisely reports on the collective experience of solid-organ transplant in the United States, making it, to our knowledge, the largest study in the field of transplantation yet conducted. These results refute any lingering perception of transplantation as a niche field with limited practical benefit. Furthermore, focusing exclusively on the survival benefit does not capture the vast improvements in quality of life and the drastically lowered morbidity rates after a transplant."
3,619
<h4>Millions of life years are saved</h4><p><strong>Whiteman 15</strong> Honor Whiteman, Medical News Today Saturday 31 January 2015 Organ transplants in the US 'have saved almost 2.3 million years of life' http://www.medicalnewstoday.com/articles/288673.php</p><p>Little more than 50 years ago, the world's first successful kidney transplant took place. Now, more than 16,000 kidney transplants take place each year in the US alone, indicative of just how far organ transplantation has come. Now, researchers have analyzed 25 years of transplant data to determine how many years of life have been saved by the procedure.</p><p><u>A doctor holding a human organ for transplant</p><p>Almost 2.3 million life-years have been saved by organ transplants between 1987 and 2012, according to the study.</p><p></u>The research team, including Dr. Abbas Rana <u>of the Baylor College of Medicine</u> in Houston, TX, publishes their findings in JAMA Surgery.</p><p><u>In the US, around 79 people each day receive an organ transplant. Every 10 seconds, a person is added to the waiting list to receive one. Organ transplantation is normally the only effective treatment for end-stage organ failure, meaning people's lives literally depend on the procedure.</p><p>Statistics up to the beginning of December 2012 reveal that of patients who received a heart transplant, almost 70% were alive 5 years later. For patients who received a kidney transplant from a living donor, 92% were alive 5 years after the procedure. With figures like these, it is no wonder Dr. Rana and colleagues hail organ transplantation as the "marvel of modern medicine."</p><p></u>For their study, however, the team wanted to delve deeper into the survival benefits of organ transplantation in the US. They set out to determine how many years of life the procedure has saved between 1987 and 2012.</p><p>The number of life-years saved is a 'stellar accomplishment'</p><p>In 1987, the United Network for Organ Sharing (UNOS) began keeping records of all solid organ transplants that take place in the US, as well as records of patients who were waiting for a transplant.</p><p>Using the UNOS database, Dr. Rana and colleagues reviewed the records of 1,112,835 patients with end-stage organ failure. Of these, 533,329 received a transplant and 579,506 were on the waiting list but did not have the procedure.</p><p>The researchers calculated the number of life-years saved by organ transplantation between September 1st, 1987 and December 31st, 2012 by comparing the survival outcomes of patients who underwent the procedure with those who did not.</p><p>The results of the analysis revealed that over the 25-year period, organ transplantation saved 2,270,859 years of life in the US. Each organ transplant was estimated to have saved around 4.3 years of life.</p><p>The researchers also estimated the years of life saved by each type of organ transplantation, which were:</p><p> Kidney transplant - 1.3 million years of life saved</p><p> Liver transplant - 465,296 years of life saved</p><p> Heart transplant - 269,715 years of life saved</p><p> Pancreas-kidney transplant - 79,198 years of life saved</p><p> Lung transplant - 64,575 years of life saved</p><p> Pancreas transplant - 14,903 years of life saved</p><p> Intestine transplant - 4,402 years of life saved.</p><p>The researchers hail the almost 2.3 million life-years saved by organ transplantation in the US as a "stellar accomplishment." They add:</p><p><u> "Although most of the findings in this analysis are not novel, this analysis concisely reports on the collective experience of solid-organ transplant in the United States, making it, to our knowledge, the largest study in the field of transplantation yet conducted.</p><p></u> These results refute any lingering perception of transplantation as a niche field with limited practical benefit. Furthermore, <u>focusing exclusively on the survival benefit does not capture the vast improvements in quality of life and the drastically lowered morbidity rates after a transplant."</p></u>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
430,272
1
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,548
Cost benefit analysis is important for coalition building & sustaining support for organs. Conceptual and framework arguments can be overcome through calls for policy – political involvement inevitable
CECCOLI & GLEAN 13
CECCOLI & GLEAN 13 a Department of International Studies, Rhodes College, b. International Services, Midwestern State University [Stephen J. Ceccolia & Roland A. Glean, Explaining individual level support for organ procurement policy, The Social Science Journal, Volume 50, Issue 4, December 2013, Pages 426–437]
Conceptualizing organ procurement as a public health issue and a transaction cost problem is useful because it directs analytical attention to both structural and individual considerations in considering how societies should allocate scarce goods Horn's structure hypothesis” argues that enacting coalitions seek to make legislation and the resulting institutional frameworks as durable as possible so they will endure Other transaction costs may be structural and beyond the realm of the individual. others lament the controversy over what constitutes death – that is, the ‘certainty’ of death increasing the supply of donor organs also requires overcoming a number of individual transaction costs Through federal legislation, transaction costs associated with deceased donors have decreased Conversely transaction costs for live donation remain high individual-level factors are equally critical when considering different approaches to organ procurement An anarchic perspective suggests the absence of any state role. this remains closest to the libertarian position Such a system currently remains politically infeasible politics can be an important tool in the design of an effective organ procurement system. political institutions in the form of both legal rules and norms play a critical role in procuring of human organs Federal or state intervention reflects the government's mandate to promote and protect public health
Conceptualizing organ procurement as a public health issue and a transaction problem is useful because it directs analytical attention to both structural and individual considerations. in considering how societies should allocate scarce goods enacting coalitions seek to make egislation and the resulting institutional frameworks as durable as possible individual-level factors are equally critical when considering different approaches to organ procurement. An anarchic perspective suggests the absence of any state role. Such a system currently remains politically infeasible politics can be an important tool in the design of an effective organ procurement system political institutions in the form of both legal rules and norms play a critical role in procuring of organs
3. A model for explaining individual attitudes toward organ procurement Conceptualizing the organ procurement system as a public health issue and a transaction cost problem is useful because it directs analytical attention to both structural and individual considerations. For instance, in considering how societies should allocate scarce goods, Murray Horn's (1995) “structure hypothesis” argues that enacting coalitions seek to make the design of legislation and the resulting institutional frameworks as durable as possible so they will endure long after the dissolution of the enacting coalition. This approach also suggests that exogenous factors can “determine the relative importance of the different types of transaction problems and the availability of different types of institutional instruments” (Horn, 1995, p. 30). Other transaction costs – financial or non-financial – may be structural in nature and extend beyond the realm of the individual. For instance, Healy emphasizes “the cultural contexts and organizational mechanisms that provide people with reasons and opportunities to give” (2006, p. 2). Given that the current system is based on voluntarism, the shortage of organs for transplant may emerge largely because health care professionals simply fail to ask families to donate (Siminoff, Arnold, Caplan, Virnig, & Seltzer, 1995). Others contend that the problem lies in the denial of consent by the donor's next of kin (Sade, 1999 and Wendler and Dickert, 2001). Still others lament the controversy over what constitutes death – that is, the ‘certainty’ of death (Lock, 2002, Ott, 1995 and Youngner et al., 1999). The costly nature of organ donation is evidenced by the fact that just 40% of suitable individuals donate their organs following death (Conrad, Brigham, Eakin, Sheehy, & Hunsicker, 2000). Finally, the nationwide scarcity of donor organs may be a function of an ineffective or inefficient procurement system (Healy, 2006). In addition to the societal costs and structural factors described above, increasing the supply of donor organs also requires overcoming a number of individual transaction costs. Since becoming directly involved in the process by donating an organ imposes a certain set of costs on the individual, many individuals may be reluctant to become donors themselves and/or choose not to donate the organs of their next of kin at the time of their death. Here, too, it is instructive to distinguish between living and deceased donor transplants. Through the combination of UAGA and federal legislation, transaction costs associated with deceased donors have decreased as almost every state now gives its residents an opportunity to register as a donor when applying for a driver's license. Upon death, the Organ Procurement Organizations seek out the next of kin of potential donors to seek donations. Increasingly, states are requiring OPOs to harvest organs from people who have previously signed up to be donors even when next of kin object. Conversely, the transaction costs for live donation – often measured in terms of financial costs, informational costs, and health risks, among others – remain high (Beard et al., 2013). Thus, in addition to societal or structural considerations, individual-level factors are equally critical when considering different approaches to organ procurement. In the context of human organs as a scarce national resource, the public choice approach acknowledges at least four alternative ways in which public goods can be allocated: anarchy, altruism, markets and politics (McLean, 1987). These four approaches provide the basis of a framework for explaining individual-level considerations. 3.1. Anarchy An anarchic perspective in the case of organ procurement suggests the absence of any state role. This framework is most appropriate for characterizing the period, for example, prior to the 1950s, when there was simply no medical alternative for patients suffering from organ failure. However, as advances in modern medicine have created alternatives to extend life, this position for governing the organ procurement system remains closest to the libertarian position in which individuals would likely prefer a procurement system based purely on individual discretion and the absence of state controls. Such a system, however, currently remains politically infeasible. 3.2. Altruism In The Gift Relationship, British social researcher Richard Titumss (1970) provides the classic arguments for altruism in blood donation. Titmuss concludes that altruism, and not markets, provides a better system for maintaining the blood supply, higher quality blood donations, and more social cohesion. Taking a careful and highly nuanced look at Titmuss’ arguments from a sociological perspective, Healy acknowledges “‘Donation’ suggests a system where gifts are unconditionally given and gratefully received. But research on markets and actual systems of gift exchange shows a more complex reality than the stylized versions often found in public debates about commodification and altruism” ( Healy, 2006, p. 21). While voluntarism and altruism have provided the intellectual basis for the organ procurement policy regime in the United States for the past several decades, Healy (2006, p. 3) concedes that “the sale of human body parts is a standard trope in broader debates about commodification.” The following two approaches – markets and politics – provide a specific context for shaping individual-level sentiment and provide the basis for shaping individual-level hypotheses. 3.3. Markets Given the discussion of incentivized considerations above and using the logic of markets, we argue that whether and to what extent persons are supportive of regulating the sale of human organs for transplants are conditioned by several market-specific factors, including one's level of income, employment status, and educational attainment. The general consideration is that those who are better positioned to succeed in incentive-based interactions are more likely to be supportive of replacing the current approach embedded in altruism and voluntarism with one based on an incentivized mechanism. Those able to compete more successfully in the marketplace are better able to take advantage of incentivized opportunities that arise and better able to withstand and/or rebound from market downturns. Moreover, we posit that those with higher incomes are more supportive of the legalization of the sale of human organs for transplant as the wealthier are naturally in a stronger position to participate in an incentivized organ procurement system.4 Data limitations, however prevent us from using income as an explanatory variable in our model. Therefore, applying the same explanatory rationale for the inclusion of income, we argue that one's employment status is also positively related to support for the use of monetary or non-monetary incentives in organ procurement. That is, the employed are in a much better position to thrive in the marketplace than those who are unemployed. Thus, we expect to see a positive relationship between employment status and support for market forces in organ procurement. Like income and employment status, education is a form of human capital that provides inherent advantages in incentivized situations. As is the case with wealth, educational attainment, when conceptualized as a material consideration, should translate into advantages in an incentivized situation, as those with higher educational attainment have greater access to information and should be more nimble in navigating the vagaries of the market. Therefore, we posit that those with higher levels of educational attainment are more likely to be supportive of regulating the sale of human organs for transplants. 3.4. Politics Fourth, as demonstrated by Festle's (2010) characterization of the “politicization” of the history of organ procurement policy, politics can be an important tool in the design of an effective organ procurement system. Given the infeasibility of anarchy, the current experience with altruism and the inherent ethical concerns over the use of markets, political institutions in the form of both legal rules and norms play a critical role in procuring of human organs. Federal or state intervention reflects the government's mandate to promote and protect public health.
8,377
<h4>Cost benefit analysis is important for coalition building & sustaining support for organs. Conceptual and framework arguments can be overcome through calls for policy – political involvement inevitable</h4><p><strong>CECCOLI & GLEAN 13 </strong>a Department of International Studies, Rhodes College, b. International Services, Midwestern State University [Stephen J. Ceccolia & Roland A. Glean, Explaining individual level support for organ procurement policy, The Social Science Journal, Volume 50, Issue 4, December 2013, Pages 426–437]</p><p>3. A model for explaining individual attitudes toward organ procurement</p><p><u><mark>Conceptualizing</u></mark> the <u><mark>organ procurement</u></mark> system <u><strong><mark>as a public health issue</u></strong> <u>and a transaction</mark> cost <mark>problem</u> <u>is useful because it directs analytical attention</u> <u>to both structural and individual considerations</u>.</mark> For instance, <u><mark>in considering how societies should allocate scarce goods</u></mark>, Murray <u>Horn's</u> (1995) “<u>structure hypothesis” argues that <strong><mark>enacting coalitions</u></strong> <u>seek to make</u></mark> the design of <u>l<mark>egislation and the resulting institutional frameworks as durable as possible</u></mark> <u>so they will endure</u> long after the dissolution of the enacting coalition. This approach also suggests that exogenous factors can “determine the relative importance of the different types of transaction problems and the availability of different types of institutional instruments” (Horn, 1995, p. 30). <u>Other transaction costs</u> – financial or non-financial – <u>may be structural</u> in nature <u>and</u> extend <u>beyond the realm of the individual.</u> For instance, Healy emphasizes “the cultural contexts and organizational mechanisms that provide people with reasons and opportunities to give” (2006, p. 2). Given that the current system is based on voluntarism, the shortage of organs for transplant may emerge largely because health care professionals simply fail to ask families to donate (Siminoff, Arnold, Caplan, Virnig, & Seltzer, 1995). Others contend that the problem lies in the denial of consent by the donor's next of kin (Sade, 1999 and Wendler and Dickert, 2001). Still <u>others lament the controversy over what constitutes death – that is, the ‘certainty’ of death</u> (Lock, 2002, Ott, 1995 and Youngner et al., 1999). The costly nature of organ donation is evidenced by the fact that just 40% of suitable individuals donate their organs following death (Conrad, Brigham, Eakin, Sheehy, & Hunsicker, 2000). Finally, the nationwide scarcity of donor organs may be a function of an ineffective or inefficient procurement system (Healy, 2006).</p><p>In addition to the societal costs and structural factors described above, <u>increasing the supply of donor organs also requires overcoming a number of individual transaction costs</u>. Since becoming directly involved in the process by donating an organ imposes a certain set of costs on the individual, many individuals may be reluctant to become donors themselves and/or choose not to donate the organs of their next of kin at the time of their death. Here, too, it is instructive to distinguish between living and deceased donor transplants. <u>Through</u> the combination of UAGA and <u>federal legislation, transaction costs associated with deceased donors have decreased</u> as almost every state now gives its residents an opportunity to register as a donor when applying for a driver's license. Upon death, the Organ Procurement Organizations seek out the next of kin of potential donors to seek donations. Increasingly, states are requiring OPOs to harvest organs from people who have previously signed up to be donors even when next of kin object. <u>Conversely</u>, the <u>transaction costs for live donation</u> – often measured in terms of financial costs, informational costs, and health risks, among others – <u>remain high</u> (Beard et al., 2013). Thus, in addition to societal or structural considerations, <u><mark>individual-level factors are equally critical when considering different approaches to organ procurement</u>.</p><p></mark>In the context of human organs as a scarce national resource, the public choice approach acknowledges at least four alternative ways in which public goods can be allocated: anarchy, altruism, markets and politics (McLean, 1987). These four approaches provide the basis of a framework for explaining individual-level considerations.</p><p>3.1. Anarchy</p><p><u><mark>An anarchic perspective</u></mark> in the case of organ procurement <u><mark>suggests the absence of any state role.</u></mark> This framework is most appropriate for characterizing the period, for example, prior to the 1950s, when there was simply no medical alternative for patients suffering from organ failure. However, as advances in modern medicine have created alternatives to extend life, <u>this</u> position for governing the organ procurement system <u>remains closest to the libertarian position</u> in which individuals would likely prefer a procurement system based purely on individual discretion and the absence of state controls. <u><mark>Such a system</u></mark>, however, <u><strong><mark>currently remains politically infeasible</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>3.2. Altruism</p><p>In The Gift Relationship, British social researcher Richard Titumss (1970) provides the classic arguments for altruism in blood donation. Titmuss concludes that altruism, and not markets, provides a better system for maintaining the blood supply, higher quality blood donations, and more social cohesion. Taking a careful and highly nuanced look at Titmuss’ arguments from a sociological perspective, Healy acknowledges “‘Donation’ suggests a system where gifts are unconditionally given and gratefully received. But research on markets and actual systems of gift exchange shows a more complex reality than the stylized versions often found in public debates about commodification and altruism” ( Healy, 2006, p. 21). While voluntarism and altruism have provided the intellectual basis for the organ procurement policy regime in the United States for the past several decades, Healy (2006, p. 3) concedes that “the sale of human body parts is a standard trope in broader debates about commodification.” The following two approaches – markets and politics – provide a specific context for shaping individual-level sentiment and provide the basis for shaping individual-level hypotheses.</p><p>3.3. Markets</p><p>Given the discussion of incentivized considerations above and using the logic of markets, we argue that whether and to what extent persons are supportive of regulating the sale of human organs for transplants are conditioned by several market-specific factors, including one's level of income, employment status, and educational attainment. The general consideration is that those who are better positioned to succeed in incentive-based interactions are more likely to be supportive of replacing the current approach embedded in altruism and voluntarism with one based on an incentivized mechanism. Those able to compete more successfully in the marketplace are better able to take advantage of incentivized opportunities that arise and better able to withstand and/or rebound from market downturns. Moreover, we posit that those with higher incomes are more supportive of the legalization of the sale of human organs for transplant as the wealthier are naturally in a stronger position to participate in an incentivized organ procurement system.4 Data limitations, however prevent us from using income as an explanatory variable in our model. Therefore, applying the same explanatory rationale for the inclusion of income, we argue that one's employment status is also positively related to support for the use of monetary or non-monetary incentives in organ procurement. That is, the employed are in a much better position to thrive in the marketplace than those who are unemployed. Thus, we expect to see a positive relationship between employment status and support for market forces in organ procurement.</p><p>Like income and employment status, education is a form of human capital that provides inherent advantages in incentivized situations. As is the case with wealth, educational attainment, when conceptualized as a material consideration, should translate into advantages in an incentivized situation, as those with higher educational attainment have greater access to information and should be more nimble in navigating the vagaries of the market. Therefore, we posit that those with higher levels of educational attainment are more likely to be supportive of regulating the sale of human organs for transplants.</p><p>3.4. Politics</p><p>Fourth, as demonstrated by Festle's (2010) characterization of the “politicization” of the history of organ procurement policy, <u><mark>politics can be an important tool in the design of an effective organ procurement system</mark>. </u>Given the infeasibility of anarchy, the current experience with altruism and the inherent ethical concerns over the use of markets, <u><mark>political institutions in the form of both legal rules and norms play a critical role in procuring of </mark>human <mark>organs</u></mark>. <u>Federal or state intervention reflects the government's mandate to promote and protect public health</u>.</p>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
430,273
7
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,549
Single issue focus spills over and is distinct from the ideologies that determine its use – just because we’ve isolated one problem doesn’t mean we legitimize the broader system
Hunt 90
Alan Hunt 90, Professor of Law and Sociology, Carleton University, Ottawa, Canada, “Rights and Social Movements: Counter-Hegemon Strategies,” Journal of Law and Society Vol. 17 No. 3
There is a failure to distinguish between the very different types of social movements that have been studied the distinction can be drawn between 'single issue' movements and those whose goals would constitute a wider set of social changes than their immediate objectives some movements which are apparently single issue have extensive ramifications But movements directed towards local (or regional) hegemony can only be adequately judged in their capacity to transform a wide range of social practices and discourses the environmental movement and the civil rights movement also serve as my example of movements of 'local hegemony' in that while focused on a set of specific demands, their realization would both necessitate and occasion wider structural changes. their 'success' is not a matter of securing some immediate interest. a key feature of any such assessment revolves around their capacity to put in place a new or transformed discourse of rights which goes to the heart of the way in which the substantive issues are conceived, expressed, argued about, and struggled over. the immediate 'success' or 'failure' of specific litigation has to be approached in a different way which requires that we take account of the possibility that litigation 'failure' may, paradoxically, provide the conditions of 'success' The implications of this line of thought are that the whole question of the success or failure of litigation and its connection with transformative strategies is far more complex than our existing attempts to measure 'success' and 'failure' admit. A more far-reaching criticism is that 'law', is itself part of the problem. This This strand of the anti-rights critique is, , a form of 'Leftism' whose inescapable error lies in the fact that it imagines a terrain of struggle in which a social movement can, step outside the terrain on which the struggle is constituted that it is precisely in the engagement with the actually existing terrain, , that the possibility of their transformation and transcendence becomes possible.
'single issue' movements whose goals would constitute wider social changes have extensive ramifications movements directed towards local hegemony can transform a wide range of social practices and discourses the environmental and the civil rights movement serve as example of movements of 'local hegemony' that while focused on a set of specific demands, their realization would necessitate and occasion wider structural changes their capacity to put in place transformed discourse of rights goes to the heart of the way substantive issues are struggled over A criticism that, 'law' is itself the problem This critique s, inescapable error lies in that it imagines a social movement can step outside the terrain on which the struggle is constituted it is precisely in the engagement with the existing terrain that the possibility of transformation and transcendence becomes possible
Beyond questions concerning the criteria of 'success' there is another and perhaps more fundamental problem with the existing studies of the use of litigation by social movements. There is a failure to distinguish between the very different types of social movements that have been studied.26 What is missing is a concern with what I propose to call the 'hegemonic capacity' of social movements. In a first approximation the distinction can be drawn between 'single issue' movements and those whose goals would constitute a wider set of social changes than their immediate objectives. But this approximation requires further refinement because some movements which are apparently single issue have extensive ramifications. The abortion rights movement, whilst superficially focusing on a single issue, has ramifications extending beyond the immediate question of women's right to control their fertility. The abortion rights movement is a prime example of the concept of 'local hegemony'. Such a movement is not directed to the kind of global hegemony that Gramsci had in mind with his focus on the role of the revolutionary party. But movements directed towards local (or regional) hegemony can only be adequately judged in their capacity to transform a wide range of social practices and discourses. For present purposes I suggest that, in addition, the environmental movement and the civil rights movement also serve as my example of movements of 'local hegemony' in that while focused on a set of specific demands, their realization would both necessitate and occasion wider structural changes. The most immediate implication is that their 'success' is not a matter of securing some immediate interest. It follows that to evaluate the role of litigation for such movements necessitates that focus be directed to the articulation between the elements that make up the strategic project of the movement. My suggestion is that a key feature of any such assessment revolves around their capacity to put in place a new or transformed discourse of rights which goes to the heart of the way in which the substantive issues are conceived, expressed, argued about, and struggled over. My more controversial suggestion is that the immediate 'success' or 'failure' of specific litigation has to be approached in a different way which requires that we take account of the possibility that litigation 'failure' may, paradoxically, provide the conditions of 'success' that compel a movement forward. In current struggles over wife abuse, all those cases in which judges impose derisory sanctions are contexts which drive the movement forward because they provide instances of a dying discourse in which women 'deserve' chastisement by their husbands. Such judicial pronouncements become more self-evidently anachronistic and in this inverted form speak of a new and emergent discourse of rights and autonomy. The implications of this line of thought are that the whole question of the success or failure of litigation and its connection with transformative strategies is far more complex than our existing attempts to measure 'success' and 'failure' admit. A more far-reaching criticism of litigation is that, rather than helping, 'law', conceived variously as litigation or legal reform politics, is itself part of the problem. This line of argument is at the root of Kristin Bumiller's study of the civil rights movement.27 This strand of the anti-rights critique is, I want to suggest, even if unintended, a form of 'Leftism' whose inescapable error lies in the fact that it imagines a terrain of struggle in which a social movement can, by an act of will, step outside the terrain on which the struggle is constituted, Here a hegemonic strategy must insist that it is precisely in the engagement with the actually existing terrain, in particular, with its discursive forms, that the possibility of their transformation and transcendence becomes possible. To refuse this terrain is, in general, Leftist because is marks a refusal to engage with the conditions within which social change is grounded.
4,092
<h4>Single issue focus spills over and is distinct from the ideologies that determine its use – just because we’ve isolated one problem doesn’t mean we legitimize the broader system</h4><p>Alan <strong>Hunt 90</strong>, Professor of Law and Sociology, Carleton University, Ottawa, Canada, “Rights and Social Movements: Counter-Hegemon Strategies,” Journal of Law and Society Vol. 17 No. 3</p><p>Beyond questions concerning the criteria of 'success' there is another and perhaps more fundamental problem with the existing studies of the use of litigation by social movements. <u>There is a failure to distinguish between the very different types of social movements that have been studied</u>.26 What is missing is a concern with what I propose to call the 'hegemonic capacity' of social movements. In a first approximation <u>the distinction can be drawn between <strong><mark>'single issue' movements</strong> </mark>and those <mark>whose <strong>goals</mark> <mark>would constitute</mark> a <mark>wider</mark> set of <mark>social changes</strong></mark> than their immediate objectives</u>. But this approximation requires further refinement because <u>some movements which are apparently single issue <mark>have <strong>extensive ramifications</u></strong></mark>. The abortion rights movement, whilst superficially focusing on a single issue, has ramifications extending beyond the immediate question of women's right to control their fertility. The abortion rights movement is a prime example of the concept of 'local hegemony'. Such a movement is not directed to the kind of global hegemony that Gramsci had in mind with his focus on the role of the revolutionary party. <u>But <mark>movements directed towards local</mark> (or regional) <mark>hegemony can</mark> only be adequately judged in their capacity to <strong><mark>transform a wide range of social practices and discourses</u></strong></mark>. For present purposes I suggest that, in addition, <u><mark>the environmental</mark> movement <mark>and the civil rights movement</mark> also <mark>serve as</mark> my <mark>example of movements of 'local hegemony'</mark> in <mark>that <strong>while focused on a set of specific</mark> <mark>demands, their realization would</mark> both <mark>necessitate and occasion wider structural changes</mark>.</u></strong> The most immediate implication is that <u>their 'success' is not a matter of securing some immediate interest.</u> It follows that to evaluate the role of litigation for such movements necessitates that focus be directed to the articulation between the elements that make up the strategic project of the movement. My suggestion is that <u>a key feature of any such assessment revolves around <mark>their capacity to <strong>put in place</mark> a new or <mark>transformed discourse of rights</strong></mark> which <strong><mark>goes to the heart</strong> of the way</mark> in which the <mark>substantive issues</mark> <mark>are</mark> conceived, expressed, argued about, and <mark>struggled over</mark>.</u> My more controversial suggestion is that <u>the immediate <strong>'success' or 'failure' of specific litigation has to be approached in a different way</strong> which requires that we take account of the possibility that litigation 'failure' may, paradoxically, provide the conditions of 'success'</u> that compel a movement forward. In current struggles over wife abuse, all those cases in which judges impose derisory sanctions are contexts which drive the movement forward because they provide instances of a dying discourse in which women 'deserve' chastisement by their husbands. Such judicial pronouncements become more self-evidently anachronistic and in this inverted form speak of a new and emergent discourse of rights and autonomy. <u>The implications of this line of thought are that the whole question of the success or failure of litigation and its connection with transformative strategies is far more complex than our existing attempts to measure 'success' and 'failure' admit. <mark>A</mark> more far-reaching <mark>criticism</u></mark> of litigation <u>is <mark>that</u>,</mark> rather than helping, <u><mark>'law'</mark>,</u> conceived variously as litigation or legal reform politics, <u><mark>is itself</mark> part of <mark>the problem</mark>. This</u> line of argument is at the root of Kristin Bumiller's study of the civil rights movement.27 <u><mark>This</mark> strand of the anti-rights <mark>critique</mark> i<mark>s,</u></mark> I want to suggest, even if unintended<u>, a form of 'Leftism' whose <strong><mark>inescapable error</strong> lies in</mark> the fact <mark>that it imagines</mark> a terrain of struggle in which <mark>a social movement can</mark>, </u>by an act of will, <u><strong><mark>step outside the terrain on which the struggle is constituted</u></strong></mark>, Here a hegemonic strategy must insist <u>that <mark>it is <strong>precisely in the engagement with the </mark>actually <mark>existing terrain</strong></mark>,</u> in particular, with its discursive forms<u><strong>, <mark>that the possibility of</mark> their <mark>transformation and transcendence becomes possible</mark>. </u></strong>To refuse this terrain is, in general, Leftist because is marks a refusal to engage with the conditions within which social change is grounded.</p>
null
null
Contention 3 is method
146,043
31
17,052
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
565,315
A
Binghamton
2
JMU CH
Poapst
organs A1 - shortage A2 - illicit market
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAh/Dartmouth-Avendano-Ahmad-Aff-Binghamton-Round2.docx
null
48,461
AvAh
Dartmouth AvAh
null
Im.....
Av.....
Pi.....
Ah.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,550
Ghetto
null
Why should I confine myself
null
null
To the image they would fix me in? For pity’s sake, I’d suffocate segregated as exotic I’m no idol made of ebony Breathing phony incense In museums of the primitive I’m no sideshow cannibal Rolling ivory eyeballs To make the kiddies shiver If I shout a shout That burns my throat, it’s when my belly feels my brothers’ hunger; and if sometimes I howl with pain it’s when my toe is stuck beneath somebody’s boot. The nightingale sings many notes, my monotone laments are done. I’m no perspiring actor, arms lifted to the sky, sobbing out his pain before the camera’s eye. I’m frozen in no pose of militance or of damnation either. I’m a living creature, beast of prey every poised to leap to seize life which mocks at death; to pounce on joy which needs passport; to spring at love when it happens by my door. By Guy Tirolien
824
<h4><u>Ghetto</h4><p></u>Why should I confine myself</p><p>To the image</p><p>they would fix me in?</p><p>For pity’s sake,</p><p>I’d suffocate</p><p>segregated as exotic</p><p>I’m no idol made of ebony</p><p>Breathing phony incense</p><p>In museums of the primitive</p><p>I’m no sideshow cannibal</p><p>Rolling ivory eyeballs</p><p>To make the kiddies shiver</p><p>If I shout a shout</p><p>That burns my throat,</p><p>it’s when my belly</p><p>feels my brothers’ hunger;</p><p>and if sometimes</p><p>I howl with pain</p><p>it’s when my toe</p><p>is stuck beneath somebody’s boot.</p><p>The nightingale sings many notes,</p><p>my monotone laments are done.</p><p>I’m no perspiring actor,</p><p>arms lifted to the sky,</p><p>sobbing out his pain</p><p>before the camera’s eye.</p><p>I’m frozen in no pose of militance</p><p>or of damnation either.</p><p>I’m a living creature,</p><p>beast of prey</p><p>every poised to leap</p><p>to seize life</p><p>which mocks at death;</p><p>to pounce on joy</p><p>which needs passport;</p><p>to spring at love</p><p>when it happens by my door.</p><p>By Guy Tirolien</p>
null
null
null
430,274
2
17,053
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,309
A
Navy
1
James Madison Perez-Buchholz
Webster Dunn
Aff is social life in social death marijuana discussion is the link to the topic there's a poem at the top some written story then like 3 cards woopdidoo The third card is this sexton card which is literally like "why is it plans should come first we need to be able to articulate and deal with our suffering" I dont remember what the neg said probably fw
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,551
Legality and Marijuana
But cops be like…“I see you…walking down the street, standing on the corner lookin suspicious, you got a lot a of clothes on, why you got a lot of clothes on, it’s only 60 degrees, you got a hoodie on, you not following the rules, no loitering, cut it out…you a criminal…take that hood off...pull ya paints up…higher…higher…say yes sir”…
But cops be like…“I see you…walking down the street, standing on the corner lookin suspicious, you got a lot a of clothes on, why you got a lot of clothes on, it’s only 60 degrees, you got a hoodie on, you not following the rules, no loitering, cut it out…you a criminal…take that hood off...pull ya paints up…higher…higher…say yes sir”… This white cop…this white cop sees you shaking the hands of other folk…“A black person shaking a black person’s hand? There aint no solidarity around these parts…that’s…that’s suspicious, there aint no love in these streets…but there ain’t no love for you”…we aint got no love so we never move together…
null
null
no one ever taught us to love ourselves so we can’t even move alone…where you gone go, you don’t know where you been…how you gone live if you don’t know what life is…how you gone die if you exist as death… But shaking that hand…the cops say its weed…caught between the palms of death and death but life in death…that dime…that nick…are you hated for the weed? Are you hated for breaking the law?...did you break it or did the law break you…causality of duality, this pragmatism is dancing with death…if you didn’t shake that hand would the cop have looked any different…would prison not be in your periphery…would guns not magically appear in ya hands, holes in ya body, 22 caliber like dartboards switched with you like…but I can’t change that…you can’t change that… Are you a pessimist or are you a realist?…the product of natal alienation, general dishonor…dishonor…dishonor…who did you dishonor…why are you the victim of violence…why? There is no why…gratuitous violence… you exist as suffering but they affirm it…whiteness affirms it…it doesn’t want you to speak…don’t talk back to the cops… definitely not in this space…the debate space…this jail cell, policin people of color “you’re not predictable enough, what are your limits”…it seems we…we must always accommodate you, but when are you going to accommodate us…I should make your life easier…but when does mine get easy…why is everyone else prepared to have this discussion…except you…but you won’t win against what broke you…don’t break the rules…the cops might hurt you…debaters might hurt you…you have nothing to offer the world…that’s what bookings said…that’s what the community says…but you know better…you learned better… the world don’t love you, so don’t love the world…but love yourself affirm it in words…there’s death…there’s life…there’s life in death…they know you dead…but you know you’re alive…social life in social death…your good you young’n, look deep inside, your good young’n your good…love yourself…don’t love your suffering but love yourself…don’t love your death but find your life…find it in the music between the beats, find it in the bed between the sheets, find it in the smiles, find it in your friends, find it in your family, find it in your cannabis, find it in between the lines of your artistic words…find it in your life… life in death… affirm your life as a negation of the world, f it when the world defines you, define yourself,
2,427
<h4><strong>Legality and Marijuana</h4><p>But cops be like…“I see you…walking down the street, standing on the corner lookin suspicious, you got a lot a of clothes on, why you got a lot of clothes on, it’s only 60 degrees, you got a hoodie on, you not following the rules, no loitering, cut it out…you a criminal…take that hood off...pull ya paints up…higher…higher…say yes sir”…</p><p>This white cop…this white cop sees you shaking the hands of other folk…“A black person shaking a black person’s hand? There aint no solidarity around these parts…that’s…that’s suspicious, there aint no love in these streets…but there ain’t no love for you”…we aint got no love so we never move together…</p><p>no one ever taught us to love ourselves so we can’t even move alone…where you gone go, you don’t know where you been…how you gone live if you don’t know what life is…how you gone die if you exist as death…</p><p>But shaking that hand…the cops say its weed…caught between the palms of death and death but life in death…that dime…that nick…are you hated for the weed? Are you hated for breaking the law?...did you break it or did the law break you…causality of duality, this pragmatism is dancing with death…if you didn’t shake that hand would the cop have looked any different…would prison not be in your periphery…would guns not magically appear in ya hands, holes in ya body, 22 caliber like dartboards switched with you like…but I can’t change that…you can’t change that…</p><p>Are you a pessimist or are you a realist?…the product of natal alienation, general dishonor…dishonor…dishonor…who did you dishonor…why are you the victim of violence…why? There is no why…gratuitous violence…</p><p>you exist as suffering but they affirm it…whiteness affirms it…it doesn’t want you to speak…don’t talk back to the cops… definitely not in this space…the debate space…this jail cell, policin people of color “you’re not predictable enough, what are your limits”…it seems we…we must always accommodate you, but when are you going to accommodate us…I should make your life easier…but when does mine get easy…why is everyone else prepared to have this discussion…except you…but you won’t win against what broke you…don’t break the rules…the cops might hurt you…debaters might hurt you…you have nothing to offer the world…that’s what bookings said…that’s what the community says…but you know better…you learned better…</p><p>the world don’t love you, so don’t love the world…but love yourself affirm it in words…there’s death…there’s life…there’s life in death…they know you dead…but you know you’re alive…social life in social death…your good you young’n, look deep inside, your good young’n your good…love yourself…don’t love your suffering but love yourself…don’t love your death but find your life…find it in the music between the beats, find it in the bed between the sheets, find it in the smiles, find it in your friends, find it in your family, find it in your cannabis, find it in between the lines of your artistic words…find it in your life… life in death…</p><p>affirm your life as a negation of the world, f it when the world defines you, define yourself,</p></strong>
null
null
null
430,275
2
17,053
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,309
A
Navy
1
James Madison Perez-Buchholz
Webster Dunn
Aff is social life in social death marijuana discussion is the link to the topic there's a poem at the top some written story then like 3 cards woopdidoo The third card is this sexton card which is literally like "why is it plans should come first we need to be able to articulate and deal with our suffering" I dont remember what the neg said probably fw
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,552
Black death has black life which exists outside of your world
Sexton 10
Sexton 10 (Jared Sexton, Director, African American Studies School of Humanities , Associate Professor, African American StudiesSchool of Humanities, Associate Professor, Film & Media Studies School of Humanities at University of California Irvine, “The Social Life of Social Death: On Afro-Pessimism and Black Optimism” )
speak of black social life and black social death, black social life against black social death, black social life as black social death, black social life in black social death—all of this is to find oneself in the midst of an argument that is also a profound agreement, an agreement that takes shape in (between) meconnaissance and (dis)belief. Black optimism is not the negation of the negation that is afro-pessimism, just as black social life does not negate black social death by inhabiting it and vitalizing it. Nothing in afro-pessimism suggests that there is no black (social) life, only that black life is not social life in the universe formed by the codes of state and civil society, of citizen and subject, of nation and culture, of people and place, of history and heritage, of all the things that colonial society has in common with the colonized, of all that capital has in common with labor—the modern world system. Black life is not lived in the world that the world lives in, but it is lived underground, in outer space. This is agreed , one of the most polemical dimensions of afro-pessimism as a project: namely black life is not social, or rather that black life is lived in social death. Double emphasis, on lived and on death. That’s the whole point of the enterprise at some level. It is all about the implications of this agreed- upon point where arguments (should) begin, but they cannot (yet) proceed.
null
To speak of black social life and black social death, black social life against black social death, black social life as black social death, black social life in black social death—all of this is to find oneself in the midst of an argument that is also a profound agreement, an agreement that takes shape in (between) meconnaissance and (dis)belief. Black optimism is not the negation of the negation that is afro-pessimism, just as black social life does not negate black social death by inhabiting it and vitalizing it. A living death is as much a death as it is a living. Nothing in afro-pessimism suggests that there is no black (social) life, only that black life is not social life in the universe formed by the codes of state and civil society, of citizen and subject, of nation and culture, of people and place, of history and heritage, of all the things that colonial society has in common with the colonized, of all that capital has in common with labor—the modern world system. Black life is not lived in the world that the world lives in, but it is lived underground, in outer space. This is agreed. That is to say, what Moten asserts against afropessimism is a point already affirmed by afro-pessimism, is, in fact, one of the most polemical dimensions of afro-pessimism as a project: namely black life is not social, or rather that black life is lived in social death. Double emphasis, on lived and on death. That’s the whole point of the enterprise at some level. It is all about the implications of this agreed- upon point where arguments (should) begin, but they cannot (yet) proceed.
1,601
<h4><strong>Black death has black life which exists outside of your world </h4><p>Sexton 10 </strong>(Jared Sexton, Director, African American Studies School of Humanities , Associate Professor, African American StudiesSchool of Humanities, Associate Professor, Film & Media Studies School of Humanities at University of California Irvine, “The Social Life of Social Death: On Afro-Pessimism and Black Optimism” <u>)</p><p></u>To<u> speak of black social life and black social death, black social life against black social death, black social life as black social death, black social life in black social death—all of this is to find oneself in the midst of an argument that is also a profound agreement, an agreement that takes shape in (between) meconnaissance and (dis)belief. Black optimism is not the negation of the negation that is afro-pessimism, just as black social life does not negate black social death by inhabiting it and vitalizing it.</u> A living death is as much a death as it is a living. <u>Nothing in afro-pessimism suggests that there is no black (social) life, only that black life is not social life in the universe formed by the codes of state and civil society, of citizen and subject, of nation and culture, of people and place, of history and heritage, of all the things that colonial society has in common with the colonized, of all that capital has in common with labor—the modern world system. Black life is not lived in the world that the world lives in, but it is lived underground, in outer space. This is agreed</u>. That is to say, what Moten asserts against afropessimism is a point already affirmed by afro-pessimism, is, in fact<u>, one of the most polemical dimensions of afro-pessimism as a project: namely black life is not social, or rather that black life is lived in social death. Double emphasis, on lived and on death. That’s the whole point of the enterprise at some level. It is all about the implications of this agreed- upon point where arguments (should) begin, but they cannot (yet) proceed. </p></u>
null
null
null
40,272
236
17,053
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,309
A
Navy
1
James Madison Perez-Buchholz
Webster Dunn
Aff is social life in social death marijuana discussion is the link to the topic there's a poem at the top some written story then like 3 cards woopdidoo The third card is this sexton card which is literally like "why is it plans should come first we need to be able to articulate and deal with our suffering" I dont remember what the neg said probably fw
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,553
What’s going to keep blackness alive…Our poetry is fire to the mind, burning away at civil society while warming new conceptions of blackness, F yo faith in the system, white artists, black artists, it’s time to burst free Major ’69 Clarence Major, The New Black Poetry (1969) He has lectured and read his work in dozens of U. S. universities as well as in England, France, Liberia, West Germany, Ghana, and Italy. Clarence Major is also currently a professor of twentieth century American literature at the University of California at Davis.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>What’s going to keep blackness alive…Our poetry is fire to the mind, burning away at civil society while warming new conceptions of blackness, F yo faith in the system, white artists, black artists, it’s time to burst free</h4><p>Major ’69 Clarence Major, The New Black Poetry (1969) He has lectured and read his work in dozens of U. S. universities as well as in England, France, Liberia, West Germany, Ghana, and Italy. Clarence Major is also currently a professor of twentieth century American literature at the University of California at Davis.</p>
null
null
null
430,276
1
17,053
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,309
A
Navy
1
James Madison Perez-Buchholz
Webster Dunn
Aff is social life in social death marijuana discussion is the link to the topic there's a poem at the top some written story then like 3 cards woopdidoo The third card is this sexton card which is literally like "why is it plans should come first we need to be able to articulate and deal with our suffering" I dont remember what the neg said probably fw
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,554
Apocalyptic representations of climate change are an ineffective rhetorical strategy that produces a self-fulfilling prophecy
Hulme 6
Hulme (Professor of Environmental Sciences at the University of East Anglia, and Director of the Tyndall Centre for Climate Change Research) 6
(Mike, Chaotic world of climate truth, 4 November, http://newsvote.bbc.co.uk/mpapps/pagetools/print/news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/science/nature/6115644.stm) The language of fear and terror operates as an ever-weakening vehicle for effective communication or inducement for behavioural change Empirical work in relation to climate change communication and public perception shows that it operates here too. Framing climate change as an issue which evokes fear and personal stress becomes a self-fulfilling prophecy The IPCC scenarios of future climate change are significant enough without invoking catastrophe and chaos the discourse of catastrophe is in danger of tipping society onto a negative, depressive and reactionary trajectory.
The language of fear and terror operates as a weakening vehicle for effective communication or inducement for behavioural change Empirical work climate change communication and public perception shows that Framing climate change as an issue which evokes fear becomes a self-fulfilling prophecy The IPCC scenarios are significant enough without invoking catastrophe and chaos the discourse of catastrophe is in danger of tipping society onto a negative, depressive and reactionary trajectory.
(Mike, Chaotic world of climate truth, 4 November, http://newsvote.bbc.co.uk/mpapps/pagetools/print/news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/science/nature/6115644.stm) The language of catastrophe is not the language of science. It will not be visible in next year's global assessment from the world authority of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). To state that climate change will be "catastrophic" hides a cascade of value-laden assumptions which do not emerge from empirical or theoretical science. Is any amount of climate change catastrophic? Catastrophic for whom, for where, and by when? What index is being used to measure the catastrophe? The language of fear and terror operates as an ever-weakening vehicle for effective communication or inducement for behavioural change. This has been seen in other areas of public health risk. Empirical work in relation to climate change communication and public perception shows that it operates here too. Framing climate change as an issue which evokes fear and personal stress becomes a self-fulfilling prophecy. By "sexing it up" we exacerbate, through psychological amplifiers, the very risks we are trying to ward off. The careless (or conspiratorial?) translation of concern about Saddam Hussein's putative military threat into the case for WMD has had major geopolitical repercussions. We need to make sure the agents and agencies in our society which would seek to amplify climate change risks do not lead us down a similar counter-productive pathway. The IPCC scenarios of future climate change - warming somewhere between 1.4 and 5.8 Celsius by 2100 - are significant enough without invoking catastrophe and chaos as unguided weapons with which forlornly to threaten society into behavioural change. I believe climate change is real, must be faced and action taken. But the discourse of catastrophe is in danger of tipping society onto a negative, depressive and reactionary trajectory.
1,943
<h4><strong>Apocalyptic representations of climate change are an ineffective rhetorical strategy that produces a self-fulfilling prophecy </h4><p><mark>Hulme</mark> </strong>(Professor of Environmental Sciences at the University of East Anglia, and Director of the Tyndall Centre for Climate Change Research) <strong><mark>6</p><p><u></mark>(Mike, Chaotic world of climate truth, 4 November, http://newsvote.bbc.co.uk/mpapps/pagetools/print/news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/science/nature/6115644.stm)</p><p></u></strong>The language of catastrophe is not the language of science. It will not be visible in next year's global assessment from the world authority of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). To state that climate change will be "catastrophic" hides a cascade of value-laden assumptions which do not emerge from empirical or theoretical science. Is any amount of climate change catastrophic? Catastrophic for whom, for where, and by when? What index is being used to measure the catastrophe? <u><mark>The language of fear and terror operates as a</mark>n ever-<mark>weakening vehicle for effective communication or inducement for behavioural change</u></mark>. This has been seen in other areas of public health risk. <u><mark>Empirical work</mark> in relation to <mark>climate change</mark> <mark>communication and public perception shows that</mark> it operates here too.</u> <u><mark>Framing climate change as</mark> <mark>an issue which evokes fear </mark>and personal stress <strong><mark>becomes a self-fulfilling prophecy</u></strong></mark>. By "sexing it up" we exacerbate, through psychological amplifiers, the very risks we are trying to ward off. The careless (or conspiratorial?) translation of concern about Saddam Hussein's putative military threat into the case for WMD has had major geopolitical repercussions. We need to make sure the agents and agencies in our society which would seek to amplify climate change risks do not lead us down a similar counter-productive pathway. <u><mark>The IPCC scenarios</mark> of future climate change</u> - warming somewhere between 1.4 and 5.8 Celsius by 2100 - <u><mark>are significant</mark> <mark>enough without invoking catastrophe and chaos</mark> </u>as unguided weapons with which forlornly to threaten society into behavioural change. I believe climate change is real, must be faced and action taken. But <u><strong><mark>the</mark> <mark>discourse of catastrophe is in danger of tipping society onto a negative, depressive and reactionary trajectory.</mark>  </p></u></strong>
null
null
AIK 1NC
227,328
5
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,555
Apocalyptic reps of climate change trades off with focus on ongoing environmental structural violence
Crist 7
Crist (Prof in Department of Science and Technology in Society @ Virginia Tech) 7
apocalyptic thinking directs attention toward some future cataclysm, while dimming awareness of the present and real suffering of nonhumans disempowered people . Life’s ongoing devastation are the predicaments that we are called to face—not the preemption of some imagined crash in some imagined future.
apocalyptic thinking directs attention toward some future cataclysm dimming awareness of the present and real suffering of nonhumans disempowered people Life’s ongoing devastation are the predicaments that we are called to face—not the preemption of some imagined crash
(Eileen, Beyond the Climate Crisis: A Critique of Climate Change Discourse, Telos 4 (Winter 2007): 29–55) Besides coddling humanity’s proclivity for self-centered concern, apocalyptic thinking directs attention toward some future Hollywood- style cataclysm, while dimming awareness of the present and real suffering of nonhumans, disempowered and impoverished people, and consumers beleaguered by clutter and malaise. Life’s ongoing devastation, and humanity’s pathological imbalance with wild nature and schisms within itself, are the predicaments that we are called to face—not the preemption of some imagined crash in some imagined future.
648
<h4><strong>Apocalyptic reps of climate change trades off with focus on ongoing environmental structural violence</h4><p><mark>Crist</mark> </strong>(Prof in Department of Science and Technology in Society @ Virginia Tech)<strong> <mark>7</p><p></strong></mark>(Eileen, Beyond the Climate Crisis: A Critique of Climate Change Discourse, Telos 4 (Winter 2007): 29–55) </p><p>Besides coddling humanity’s proclivity for self-centered concern, <u> <mark>apocalyptic thinking directs attention</mark> <mark>toward some future</u></mark> Hollywood- style <u><mark>cataclysm</mark>, while <mark>dimming awareness of the present and real</mark> <mark>suffering of nonhumans</u></mark>, <u><mark>disempowered</u></mark> and impoverished <u><mark>people</u></mark>, and consumers beleaguered by clutter and malaise<u>. <mark>Life’s ongoing devastation</u></mark>, and humanity’s pathological imbalance with wild nature and schisms within itself, <u><mark>are the predicaments that we are called to face—not the preemption of some imagined crash<strong></mark> in some imagined future. </p></u></strong>
null
null
AIK 1NC
273,401
13
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,556
This North/South inequality creates multiple structural trends towards extinction
Szentes ‘8
Szentes ‘8 Tamás Szentes, a Professor Emeritus at the Corvinus University of Budapest. “Globalisation and prospects of the world society” 4/22/08 http://www.eadi.org/fileadmin/Documents/Events/exco/Glob.___prospects_-_jav..pdf
arms race and militarisation have not ended but escalated and continued many “invisible wars” are suffered by the poor , manifested in poverty, , exploitation and oppression, , ”, Behind “invisible wars” we find striking international and intrasociety inequities and distorted development patterns , which tend to generate social as well as international tensions paving the way for unrest and “visible” wars peace cannot be safeguarded in one part of the world when some others suffer visible or invisible wars no ecological balance can be ensured, unless the deep international development gap and intra-society inequalities are substantially reduced The narrow-minded, election-oriented, selfish behaviour motivated by thirst for power and wealth, paves the way for the final, last catastrophe Nevertheless, . Under the circumstances provided by rapidly progressing science and technological revolutions, human society cannot survive unless such profound intra-society and international inequalities prevailing today are soon eliminated. The real choice for the world society is between continuation of visible and “invisible wars” and transformation of the world order
arms race and militarisation have not ended but escalated and continued invisible wars” are suffered by the poor in exploitation and oppression we find striking distorted development patterns which generate social as well as international tensions paving the way for unrest and “visible” wars peace cannot be safeguarded when others suffer o ecological balance can be ensured, unless the deep development gap and inequalities are substantially reduced. he narrow-minded, selfish behaviour motivated by power and wealth paves the way for the final, last catastrophe.
It’ s a common place that human society can survive and develop only in a lasting real peace. Without peace countries cannot develop. Although since 1945 there has been no world war, but --numerous local wars took place, --terrorism has spread all over the world, undermining security even in the most developed and powerful countries, --arms race and militarisation have not ended with the collapse of the Soviet bloc, but escalated and continued, extending also to weapons of mass destruction and misusing enormous resources badly needed for development, --many “invisible wars” are suffered by the poor and oppressed people, manifested in mass misery, poverty, unemployment, homelessness, starvation and malnutrition, epidemics and poor health conditions, exploitation and oppression, racial and other discrimination, physical terror, organised injustice, disguised forms of violence, the denial or regular infringement of the democratic rights of citizens, women, youth, ethnic or religious minorities, etc., and last but not least, in the degradation of human environment, which means that --the “war against Nature”, i.e. the disturbance of ecological balance, wasteful management of natural resources, and large-scale pollution of our environment, is still going on, causing also losses and fatal dangers for human life. Behind global terrorism and “invisible wars” we find striking international and intrasociety inequities and distorted development patterns , which tend to generate social as well as international tensions, thus paving the way for unrest and “visible” wars. It is a commonplace now that peace is not merely the absence of war. The prerequisites of a lasting peace between and within societies involve not only - though, of course, necessarily - demilitarisation, but also a systematic and gradual elimination of the roots of violence, of the causes of “invisible wars”, of the structural and institutional bases of large-scale international and intra-society inequalities, exploitation and oppression. Peace requires a process of social and national emancipation, a progressive, democratic transformation of societies and the world bringing about equal rights and opportunities for all people, sovereign participation and mutually advantageous co-operation among nations. It further requires a pluralistic democracy on global level with an appropriate system of proportional representation of the world society, articulation of diverse interests and their peaceful reconciliation, by non-violent conflict management, and thus also a global governance with a really global institutional system. Under the contemporary conditions of accelerating globalisation and deepening global interdependencies in our world, peace is indivisible in both time and space. It cannot exist if reduced to a period only after or before war, and cannot be safeguarded in one part of the world when some others suffer visible or invisible wars. Thus, peace requires, indeed, a new, demilitarised and democratic world order, which can provide equal opportunities for sustainable development. “Sustainability of development” (both on national and world level) is often interpreted as an issue of environmental protection only and reduced to the need for preserving the ecological balance and delivering the next generations not a destroyed Nature with overexhausted resources and polluted environment. However, no ecological balance can be ensured, unless the deep international development gap and intra-society inequalities are substantially reduced. Owing to global interdependencies there may exist hardly any “zero-sum-games”, in which one can gain at the expense of others, but, instead, the “negative-sum-games” tend to predominate, in which everybody must suffer, later or sooner, directly or indirectly, losses. Therefore, the actual question is not about “sustainability of development” but rather about the “sustainability of human life”, i.e. survival of mankind – because of ecological imbalance and globalised terrorism. When Professor Louk de la Rive Box was the president of EADI, one day we had an exchange of views on the state and future of development studies. We agreed that development studies are not any more restricted to the case of underdeveloped countries, as the developed ones (as well as the former “socialist” countries) are also facing development problems, such as those of structural and institutional (and even system-) transformation, requirements of changes in development patterns, and concerns about natural environment. While all these are true, today I would dare say that besides (or even instead of) “development studies” we must speak about and make “survival studies”. While the monetary, financial, and debt crises are cyclical, we live in an almost permanent crisis of the world society, which is multidimensional in nature, involving not only economic but also socio-psychological, behavioural, cultural and political aspects. The narrow-minded, election-oriented, selfish behaviour motivated by thirst for power and wealth, which still characterise the political leadership almost all over the world, paves the way for the final, last catastrophe. One cannot doubt, of course, that great many positive historical changes have also taken place in the world in the last century. Such as decolonisation, transformation of socio-economic systems, democratisation of political life in some former fascist or authoritarian states, institutionalisation of welfare policies in several countries, rise of international organisations and new forums for negotiations, conflict management and cooperation, institutionalisation of international assistance programmes by multilateral agencies, codification of human rights, and rights of sovereignty and democracy also on international level, collapse of the militarised Soviet bloc and system-change3 in the countries concerned, the end of cold war, etc., to mention only a few. Nevertheless, the crisis of the world society has extended and deepened, approaching to a point of bifurcation that necessarily puts an end to the present tendencies, either by the final catastrophe or a common solution. Under the circumstances provided by rapidly progressing science and technological revolutions, human society cannot survive unless such profound intra-society and international inequalities prevailing today are soon eliminated. Like a single spacecraft, the Earth can no longer afford to have a 'crew' divided into two parts: the rich, privileged, wellfed, well-educated, on the one hand, and the poor, deprived, starving, sick and uneducated, on the other. Dangerous 'zero-sum-games' (which mostly prove to be “negative-sum-games”) can hardly be played any more by visible or invisible wars in the world society. Because of global interdependencies, the apparent winner becomes also a loser. The real choice for the world society is between negative- and positive-sum-games: i.e. between, on the one hand, continuation of visible and “invisible wars”, as long as this is possible at all, and, on the other, transformation of the world order by demilitarisation and democratization. No ideological or terminological camouflage can conceal this real dilemma any more, which is to be faced not in the distant future, by the next generations, but in the coming years, because of global terrorism soon having nuclear and other mass destructive weapons, and also due to irreversible changes in natural environment.
7,499
<h4><strong>This North/South inequality creates multiple structural trends towards extinction</h4><p><mark>Szentes ‘8</p><p></strong></mark>Tamás Szentes, a Professor Emeritus at the Corvinus University of Budapest. “Globalisation and prospects of the world society” 4/22/08 http://www.eadi.org/fileadmin/Documents/Events/exco/Glob.___prospects_-_jav..pdf</p><p>It’ s a common place that human society can survive and develop only in a lasting real peace. Without peace countries cannot develop. Although since 1945 there has been no world war, but --numerous local wars took place, --terrorism has spread all over the world, undermining security even in the most developed and powerful countries, --<u><mark>arms race and militarisation have not ended</u></mark> with the collapse of the Soviet bloc, <u><mark>but escalated and</mark> <mark>continued</u></mark>, extending also to weapons of mass destruction and misusing enormous resources badly needed for development, --<u>many “<mark>invisible wars” are suffered by the poor</mark> </u>and oppressed people<u>, manifested <mark>in</u></mark> mass misery, <u>poverty,</u> unemployment, homelessness, starvation<u> </u>and malnutrition, epidemics and poor health conditions<u>, <mark>exploitation and oppression</mark>, </u>racial and other discrimination, physical terror, organised injustice, disguised forms of violence, the denial or regular infringement of the democratic rights of citizens, women, youth, ethnic or religious minorities, etc.,<u> </u>and<u> </u>last but not least,<u> </u>in the degradation of human environment<u>, </u>which means that --the “war against Nature<u>”,</u> i.e. the disturbance of ecological balance, wasteful management of natural resources, and large-scale pollution of our environment, is still going on, causing also losses and fatal dangers for human life. <u>Behind</u> global terrorism and<u> “invisible wars” <mark>we find striking </mark>international and intrasociety inequities and <mark>distorted development patterns</mark> , <mark>which</mark> tend to <mark>generate social as well as</mark> <mark>international tensions</u></mark>, thus <u><mark>paving the way for unrest and “visible” wars</u></mark>. It is a commonplace now that peace is not merely the absence of war. The prerequisites of a lasting peace between and within societies involve not only - though, of course, necessarily - demilitarisation, but also a systematic and gradual elimination of the roots of violence, of the causes of “invisible wars”, of the structural and institutional bases of large-scale international and intra-society inequalities, exploitation and oppression. Peace requires a process of social and national emancipation, a progressive, democratic transformation of societies and the world bringing about equal rights and opportunities for all people, sovereign participation and mutually advantageous co-operation among nations. It further requires a pluralistic democracy on global level with an appropriate system of proportional representation of the world society, articulation of diverse interests and their peaceful reconciliation, by non-violent conflict management, and thus also a global governance with a really global institutional system. Under the contemporary conditions of accelerating globalisation and deepening global interdependencies in our world, <u><mark>peace</u></mark> is indivisible in both time and space. It cannot exist if reduced to a period only after or before war, and<u> <mark>cannot be safeguarded</mark> in one part of the world <mark>when</mark> some <mark>others suffer</mark> visible or invisible wars</u>. Thus, peace requires, indeed, a new, demilitarised and democratic world order, which can provide equal opportunities for sustainable development. “Sustainability of development” (both on national and world level) is often interpreted as an issue of environmental protection only and reduced to the need for preserving the ecological balance and delivering the next generations not a destroyed Nature with overexhausted resources and polluted environment. However,<u> n<mark>o ecological balance can be ensured, unless the deep</mark> international <mark>development gap and</mark> intra-society <mark>inequalities are substantially reduced</u>.</mark> Owing to global interdependencies there may exist hardly any “zero-sum-games”, in which one can gain at the expense of others, but, instead, the “negative-sum-games” tend to predominate, in which everybody must suffer, later or sooner, directly or indirectly, losses. Therefore, the actual question is not about “sustainability of development” but rather about the “sustainability of human life”, i.e. survival of mankind – because of ecological imbalance and globalised terrorism. When Professor Louk de la Rive Box was the president of EADI, one day we had an exchange of views on the state and future of development studies. We agreed that development studies are not any more restricted to the case of underdeveloped countries, as the developed ones (as well as the former “socialist” countries) are also facing development problems, such as those of structural and institutional (and even system-) transformation, requirements of changes in development patterns, and concerns about natural environment. While all these are true, today I would dare say that besides (or even instead of) “development studies” we must speak about and make “survival studies”. While the monetary, financial, and debt crises are cyclical, we live in an almost permanent crisis of the world society, which is multidimensional in nature, involving not only economic but also socio-psychological, behavioural, cultural and political aspects. <u>T<mark>he narrow-minded,</mark> election-oriented, <mark>selfish behaviour motivated by</mark> thirst for <mark>power and wealth</mark>,</u> which still characterise the political leadership almost all over the world, <u><mark>paves the way for <strong>the final, last catastrophe</u></strong>.</mark> One cannot doubt, of course, that great many positive historical changes have also taken place in the world in the last century. Such as decolonisation, transformation of socio-economic systems, democratisation of political life in some former fascist or authoritarian states, institutionalisation of welfare policies in several countries, rise of international organisations and new forums for negotiations, conflict management and cooperation, institutionalisation of international assistance programmes by multilateral agencies, codification of human rights, and rights of sovereignty and democracy also on international level, collapse of the militarised Soviet bloc and system-change3 in the countries concerned, the end of cold war, etc., to mention only a few. <u>Nevertheless, </u>the crisis of the world society has extended and deepened, approaching to a point of bifurcation that necessarily puts an end to the present tendencies, either by the final catastrophe or a common solution<u>. Under the circumstances provided by rapidly progressing science and technological revolutions, human society cannot survive unless such profound intra-society and international inequalities prevailing today are soon eliminated.</u> Like a single spacecraft, the Earth can no longer afford to have a 'crew' divided into two parts: the rich, privileged, wellfed, well-educated, on the one hand, and the poor, deprived, starving, sick and uneducated, on the other. Dangerous 'zero-sum-games' (which mostly prove to be “negative-sum-games”) can hardly be played any more by visible or invisible wars in the world society. Because of global interdependencies, the apparent winner becomes also a loser. <u>The real choice for the world society is between</u> negative- and positive-sum-games: i.e. between, on the one hand, <u>continuation of visible and “invisible wars”</u>, as long as this is possible at all, <u>and</u>, on the other, <u><strong>transformation of the world order</u></strong> by demilitarisation<strong> and democratization. No ideological or terminological camouflage can conceal this real dilemma any more, which is to be faced not in the distant future, by the next generations, but in the coming years, because of global terrorism soon having nuclear and other mass destructive weapons, and also due to irreversible changes in natural environment.</p></strong>
null
null
AIK 1NC
912
269
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,557
Our alternative is to reject the Aff’s representations of climate catastrophe
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><strong>Our alternative is to reject the Aff’s representations of climate catastrophe </h4></strong>
null
null
AIK 1NC
430,277
1
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,558
As communication scholars we have an obligation to determine effective rhetorical strategies for our policy proposals – apocalyptic reps of climate change must be rejected as an utter failure
Foust and Murphy 9
Foust and Murphy (Assistant Professor in the Department of Human Communication Studies at the University of Denver; doctoral student in the Department of Human Communication Studies at the University of Denver) 9 (Christina R. Foust & William O'Shannon Murphy, Revealing and Reframing Apocalyptic Tragedy in Global Warming Discourse, Environmental Communication: A Journal of Nature and Culture, pages 151-167,Volume 3, Issue 2, 2009)
an apocalyptic structure permeates the global warming narrative in the American elite and popular press communication scholars of all methodological commitments to join environmental advocates in their efforts to build a collective will A great part of this effort is reframing climate change discourse These efforts must extend to board rooms and classrooms By providing ways to structure communication that promote agency, rhetoricians might advance widespread public action on climate change.The apocalyptic frame is not an effective rhetorical strategy It has been developed over at least the last decade a time in which the US has refused all but the most paltry political action on greenhouse gas reductions apocalyptic discourse provokes resignation for humanity.
an apocalyptic structure permeates the global warming narrative in the elite and popular press communication scholars to join environmental advocates in their efforts to build a collective will A great part of this is reframing climate change discourse These efforts must extend to board rooms and classrooms By providing ways to structure communication that promote agency, rhetoricians might advance public action The apocalyptic frame is not an effective rhetorical strategy apocalyptic discourse provokes resignation
In conclusion, an apocalyptic structure permeates the global warming narrative in the American elite and popular press, with the potential to force the predicted tragedy into being, due to its limitations on human agency. We echo the call for communication scholars of all methodological commitments to join environmental advocates, climate scientists, and others, in their efforts to build a collective will to reduce greenhouse gas emissions (Moser & Dilling, 2007). A great part of this effort is in reframing the way the press constitutes climate change discourse (Boykoff, 2007b). These efforts also must extend beyond the media to include other arenas in which an active public is aroused, from kitchen tables and water coolers, to board rooms and classrooms. By providing the public, agenda-setting professionals (e.g., public relations practitioners and journalists), and community leaders with ways to structure communication that promote agency, rhetoricians might advance widespread public action on climate change.The apocalyptic frame, particularly in its tragic version, is not an effective rhetorical strategy for this situation. It has been developed over at least the last decade of press coverage, a time in which the US has refused all but the most paltry political action on greenhouse gas reductions. Tragic apocalyptic discourse encourages belief in prophesy at the expense of practicing persuasion, even as it provokes resignation in the face of a human-induced dilemma. Given the tragic apocalyptic frame's ineffectiveness at inspiring action-or, at least its persistent evacuation of agency-we must promote more action-oriented rhetorical strategies. Together, we may advance the climate change narrative from an apocalyptic tragedy to a more comic telos for humanity.
1,793
<h4><strong>As communication scholars we have an obligation to determine effective rhetorical strategies for our policy proposals – apocalyptic reps of climate change must be rejected as an utter failure</h4><p><mark>Foust and Murphy</strong></mark> (Assistant Professor in the Department of Human Communication Studies at the University of Denver; doctoral student in the Department of Human Communication Studies at the University of Denver) <strong><mark>9</p><p></strong></mark>(Christina R. Foust & William O'Shannon Murphy, Revealing and Reframing Apocalyptic Tragedy in Global Warming Discourse, Environmental Communication: A Journal of Nature and Culture, pages 151-167,Volume 3, Issue 2, 2009)</p><p>In conclusion, <u><mark>an apocalyptic structure permeates the global warming narrative in the</mark> American <mark>elite and popular press</u></mark>, with the potential to force the predicted tragedy into being, due to its limitations on human agency. We echo the call for <u><mark>communication scholars</mark> of all methodological commitments <mark>to</mark> <mark>join environmental advocates</u></mark>, climate scientists, and others, <u><mark>in their efforts to build a collective will</mark> </u>to reduce greenhouse gas emissions (Moser & Dilling, 2007). <u><mark>A great part of this</mark> effort <mark>is</mark> </u>in <u><mark>reframing</mark> </u>the way the press constitutes <u><mark>climate change discourse</u></mark> (Boykoff, 2007b). <u><mark>These efforts</mark> </u>also <u><mark>must extend</u></mark> beyond the media to include other arenas in which an active public is aroused, from kitchen tables and water coolers, <u><mark>to</mark> <mark>board rooms and classrooms</u></mark>. <u><mark>By providing</u></mark> the public, agenda-setting professionals (e.g., public relations practitioners and journalists), and community leaders with <u><mark>ways to structure communication that promote</mark> <mark>agency, rhetoricians might advance</mark> widespread <mark>public action</mark> on climate change.<mark>The apocalyptic</mark> <mark>frame</u></mark>, particularly in its tragic version, <u><mark>is not an effective rhetorical strategy</u></mark> for this situation. <u>It has been developed over at least the last decade</u> of press coverage, <u>a time in which the US has refused all but the most paltry political action on greenhouse gas reductions</u>. Tragic <u><mark>apocalyptic discourse</u></mark> encourages belief in prophesy at the expense of practicing persuasion, even as it <u><mark>provokes resignation</u></mark> in the face of a human-induced dilemma. Given the tragic apocalyptic frame's ineffectiveness at inspiring action-or, at least its persistent evacuation of agency-we must promote more action-oriented rhetorical strategies. Together, we may advance the climate change narrative from an apocalyptic tragedy to a more comic telos<u><strong> for humanity.</p></u></strong>
null
null
AIK 1NC
230,380
12
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,559
Emissions Need to be reduced by 50% to solve warming
Levin 13
Levin 13 Kelly Levin, Developed Nations Must Cut Emissions In Half By 2020, Says New Study, BY CLIMATE GUEST CONTRIBUTOR POSTED ON MARCH 7, 2013 AT 12:26 PM, http://thinkprogress.org/climate/2013/03/07/1685881/developed-nations-must-cut-emissions-in-half-by-2020-says-new-study/
we have to reduce emissions even more than scientists initially thought in order to avoid climate change’s developed countries must reduce their emissions by 50 percent
we have to reduce emissions even more than scientists initially thought in order to avoid climate change’s developed countries must reduce their emissions by 50 percent
Further research has continued to examine the global GHG emissions reductions necessary to avert dangerous climate change. And as countries implement existing policies and consider new ones, the scale of required emissions cuts is a fundamental question. In fact, it’s one of the most pressing questions facing the international climate change community. One new study shows that we have to reduce emissions even more than scientists initially thought in order to avoid climate change’s worst impacts. A paper published in Energy Policy on February 20 by Michel den Elzen and colleagues examines new information on likely future emissions trajectories in developing countries. This includes recent clarification of assumptions and conditions related to developing country pledges. In addition, countries have also come forward with further information on their emissions projections. As a result, the report finds that developed countries must reduce their emissions by 50 percent below 1990 levels by 2020 if we are to have a medium chance of limiting warming to 2°C, thus preventing some of climate change’s worst impacts.
1,124
<h4><strong>Emissions Need to be reduced by 50% to solve warming</h4><p>Levin 13</strong> Kelly Levin, Developed Nations Must Cut Emissions In Half By 2020, Says New Study, BY CLIMATE GUEST CONTRIBUTOR POSTED ON MARCH 7, 2013 AT 12:26 PM, http://thinkprogress.org/climate/2013/03/07/1685881/developed-nations-must-cut-emissions-in-half-by-2020-says-new-study/</p><p>Further research has continued to examine the global GHG emissions reductions necessary to avert dangerous climate change. And as countries implement existing policies and consider new ones, the scale of required emissions cuts is a fundamental question. In fact, it’s one of the most pressing questions facing the international climate change community.</p><p>One new study shows that <u><mark>we have to reduce emissions even more than scientists initially thought in order to avoid climate change’s</u></mark> worst impacts. A paper published in Energy Policy on February 20 by Michel den Elzen and colleagues examines new information on likely future emissions trajectories in developing countries. This includes recent clarification of assumptions and conditions related to developing country pledges. In addition, countries have also come forward with further information on their emissions projections. As a result, the report finds that <u><mark>developed countries must reduce their</mark> <mark>emissions by 50 percent</u></mark> below 1990 levels by 2020 if we are to have a medium chance of limiting warming to 2°C, thus preventing some of climate change’s worst impacts.</p>
null
null
Hemp Industry
430,278
1
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,560
Carbon emissions in developing countries outpace cuts in the US – 127% increase
HuffPo 13
HuffPo 13 “Developing Countries' Carbon Emissions Will Vastly Outpace Developed Nations, U.S. EIA Says,” 07/25/2013 7:59 am EDT Updated: 09/24/2013 5:12 am EDT CARBON EMISSIONS, http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2013/07/25/carbon-emissions-developing-countries_n_3651513.html
Energy-related carbon dioxide emissions will be 127 percent higher carbon emissions will grow 46 percent by 2040 carbon dioxide emissions will outpace emissions from the developed countries
Energy-related carbon dioxide emissions will be 127 percent higher carbon emissions will grow 46 percent by 2040 carbon dioxide emissions will outpace emissions from the developed countries
WASHINGTON, July 25 (Reuters) - Energy-related carbon dioxide emissions from developing countries will be 127 percent higher than in the world's most developed economies by 2040, according to figures released Thursday by the U.S. Energy Information Administration (EIA). Under the policies currently in place worldwide, carbon emissions will grow 46 percent by 2040 from a 2010 baseline, the EIA projected in its biennial International Energy Outlook. Energy-related emissions will total around 45.5 billion tonnes in 2040, up from a reference level of 31.2 billion tonnes in 2010, said the agency, which is part of the U.S. Department of Energy. Developing countries' carbon dioxide emissions will outpace emissions from the developed countries of the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD) over the next three decades due to their generally stronger rate of economic growth and continued use of fossil fuels.
933
<h4><strong>Carbon emissions in developing countries outpace cuts in the US – 127% increase</h4><p>HuffPo 13</strong> “Developing Countries' Carbon Emissions Will Vastly Outpace Developed Nations, U.S. EIA Says,” 07/25/2013 7:59 am EDT Updated: 09/24/2013 5:12 am EDT CARBON EMISSIONS, http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2013/07/25/carbon-emissions-developing-countries_n_3651513.html</p><p>WASHINGTON, July 25 (Reuters) - <u><mark>Energy-related carbon dioxide emissions</u></mark> from developing countries <u><mark>will be 127 percent higher</u></mark> than in the world's most developed economies by 2040, according to figures released Thursday by the U.S. Energy Information Administration (EIA).</p><p>Under the policies currently in place worldwide, <u><mark>carbon emissions will grow 46 percent by 2040</u></mark> from a 2010 baseline, the EIA projected in its biennial International Energy Outlook.</p><p>Energy-related emissions will total around 45.5 billion tonnes in 2040, up from a reference level of 31.2 billion tonnes in 2010, said the agency, which is part of the U.S. Department of Energy.</p><p>Developing countries' <u><mark>carbon dioxide emissions will outpace emissions from the developed countries</u></mark> of the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD) over the next three decades due to their generally stronger rate of economic growth and continued use of fossil fuels.</p>
null
null
Hemp Industry
430,279
1
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,561
Organic farming is 80% less effective – not effective for food crops
Wilcox 12
Wilcox 12 Christie Wilcox, a Ph.D. student in cellular and molecular biology at the University of Hawaii, is the author of the Science Sushi blog at Scientific American, SEPTEMBER 10, 2012, http://www.nytimes.com/roomfordebate/2012/09/10/is-organic-food-worth-the-expense/the-ecological-case-against-organic-farming
organic farms use pesticides like rotenone and copper sulfate. While "natural" sounds better, it’s not synonymous with safe. natural ones aren’t in any way less dangerou organic farms are only about 80 percent as productive as conventional ones. Until organic farming can rival the production output of conventional farming, its ecological cost is devastating
organic farms use pesticides like rotenone and copper sulfate. While "natural" sounds better, it’s not synonymous with safe. natural ones aren’t in any way less dangerous. organic farms are only about 80 percent as productive as conventional ones Until organic farming can rival the production output of conventional farming, its ecological cost is devastating,
Most people say they buy organic food to avoid pesticides, but organic farms (especially those with products found in grocery stores) use natural pesticides like rotenone and copper sulfate. While "natural" sounds better, it’s not synonymous with safe. There are plenty of naturally occurring things that are bad for us -- after all, anthrax and botulinum toxin are 100 percent natural. Organic pesticides have been linked to a wide variety of diseases -- some at lower doses than synthetic ones. Fact is, all pesticides are designed to kill, and natural ones aren’t in any way less dangerous. But perhaps the crux of the organic argument is the idea that natural methods are better for the environment. The trouble is, organic farms are only about 80 percent as productive as conventional ones. Already, we have cleared more than a third of the Earth’s ice-free land for agriculture. To farm entirely organically, we’d need more. Decreased productivity isn’t just a space issue; it has real environmental consequences. While organic farming can be better for wildlife, a systematic review by Oxford University scientists found these benefits come at a high cost, as organic varieties actually produce more carbon emissions per unit of food, contributing to the devastating effects of climate change. Until organic farming can rival the production output of conventional farming, its ecological cost is devastating, and so far, science has been unable to support claims that organic foods are safer or healthier. Organic farming does have many potential upsides, but it isn’t a panacea. Instead, its methods need to be considered alongside conventional ones to create the best balance of productivity and sustainability.
1,720
<h4><strong>Organic farming is 80% less effective – not effective for food crops</h4><p>Wilcox 12</strong> Christie Wilcox, a Ph.D. student in cellular and molecular biology at the University of Hawaii, is the author of the Science Sushi blog at Scientific American, SEPTEMBER 10, 2012, http://www.nytimes.com/roomfordebate/2012/09/10/is-organic-food-worth-the-expense/the-ecological-case-against-organic-farming</p><p>Most people say they buy organic food to avoid pesticides, but <u><mark>organic farms</u></mark> (especially those with products found in grocery stores) <u><mark>use</u></mark> natural <u><mark>pesticides like rotenone and copper sulfate. While "natural" sounds better, it’s not synonymous with safe.</u></mark> There are plenty of naturally occurring things that are bad for us -- after all, anthrax and botulinum toxin are 100 percent natural. Organic pesticides have been linked to a wide variety of diseases -- some at lower doses than synthetic ones. Fact is, all pesticides are designed to kill, and <u><mark>natural ones aren’t in any way less dangerou</u>s.</p><p></mark>But perhaps the crux of the organic argument is the idea that natural methods are better for the environment. The trouble is, <u><mark>organic farms are only about 80 percent as productive as conventional ones</mark>.</u> Already, we have cleared more than a third of the Earth’s ice-free land for agriculture. To farm entirely organically, we’d need more. Decreased productivity isn’t just a space issue; it has real environmental consequences. While organic farming can be better for wildlife, a systematic review by Oxford University scientists found these benefits come at a high cost, as organic varieties actually produce more carbon emissions per unit of food, contributing to the devastating effects of climate change.</p><p><u><mark>Until organic farming can rival the production output of conventional farming, its ecological cost is devastating</u>,<strong></mark> and so far, science has been unable to support claims that organic foods are safer or healthier. Organic farming does have many potential upsides, but it isn’t a panacea. Instead, its methods need to be considered alongside conventional ones to create the best balance of productivity and sustainability.</p></strong>
null
null
Hemp Industry
430,280
2
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,562
No infrastructure, not feasible for paper, textiles or biofuels
Wishnia 2013
Wishnia 2013 (Steven is a writer for Salon. 2/16. “Can hemp save the economy?” http://www.salon.com/2013/02/16/politicians_are_pushing_to_bring_back_the_hemp_partner/)
hemp’s decades of illegality have left no infrastructure for growing, processing and selling it. all the seed stock is gone, except for feral ditchweed. “You’d have to breed again for varieties that work well here Kentucky was once a major hemp producer, and it also provided seeds for strains better suited to different latitudes, such as Wisconsin. There were also strains bred for fiber or for larger seeds that yielded more oil This lack of infrastructure has been a major barrier to producing hemp clothing and paper. Building a new decorticator mill for hemp paper would cost more than $100 million the whole textile industry is built on short-fiber cotton and synthetics,” says Steenstra. “There’s no infrastructure for processing hemp fiber into textiles biofuel is unlikely to be practical. At 50 gallons per acre, even if every acre of U.S. cropland were used for hemp, it would supply current U.S. demand for oil for less than three weeks.
hemp’s decades of illegality have left no infrastructure for selling it all the seed stock is gone infrastructure has been a major barrier to producing hemp the textile industry is built on short-fiber synthetics, There’s no infrastructure for processing hemp fiber even if every acre were used for hemp, it would supply current U.S. demand oil for less than three weeks.
One problem for the industry is that hemp’s decades of illegality have left almost no infrastructure for growing, processing and selling it. As no hemp has been grown legally in the U.S. since 1957, says Murphy, many parts of the industry would have to be re-established virtually from scratch. To begin with, all the seed stock is gone, except for feral ditchweed.¶ “You’d have to breed again for varieties that work well here,” he says. Kentucky was once a major hemp producer, and it also provided seeds for strains better suited to different latitudes, such as Wisconsin. There were also strains bred for fiber or for larger seeds that yielded more oil. Currently, Murphy says, Canada uses mostly Russian and European stock. Those seeds could also be cross-bred with local feral strains.¶ This lack of infrastructure has been a major barrier to producing hemp clothing and paper. Building a new decorticator mill for hemp paper would cost more than $100 million, says Murphy.¶ Several small companies are using hemp for specialized products such as archival-quality, filter, or cigarette papers, but its most likely general use will be when mixed with recycled paper, says Steenstra. “Blend in 10 to 15 percent hemp, and it’s great for making better-quality recycled paper,” he says. When paper gets recycled, he explains, its fibers get shorter, and the long fibers of hemp strengthen it.¶ There are similar issues with clothing. Though Calvin Klein, Ralph Lauren, Giorgio Armani, and several lesser-known manufacturers are using hemp in clothes, “the whole textile industry is built on short-fiber cotton and synthetics,” says Steenstra. “There’s no infrastructure for processing hemp fiber into textiles.”¶ Hemp oil for biofuel, another use dreamed of in the ‘90s, is unlikely to be practical. At 50 gallons per acre, even if every acre of U.S. cropland were used for hemp, it would supply current U.S. demand for oil for less than three weeks.
1,951
<h4><strong>No infrastructure, not feasible for paper, textiles or biofuels</h4><p>Wishnia 2013 </strong>(Steven is a writer for Salon. 2/16. “Can hemp<u> save the economy?” http://www.salon.com/2013/02/16/politicians_are_pushing_to_bring_back_the_hemp_partner/)</p><p></u>One problem for the industry is that <u><mark>hemp’s decades of illegality have left</u></mark> almost <u><strong><mark>no infrastructure for</strong></mark> growing, processing and <strong><mark>selling</strong> it</mark>.</u> As no hemp has been grown legally in the U.S. since 1957, says Murphy, many parts of the industry would have to be re-established virtually from scratch. To begin with, <u><mark>all the seed stock is gone</mark>, except for feral ditchweed.</u>¶<u> “You’d have to breed again for varieties that work well here</u>,” he says. <u>Kentucky was once a major hemp producer, and it also provided seeds for strains better suited to different latitudes, such as Wisconsin. There were also strains bred for fiber or for larger seeds that yielded more oil</u>. Currently, Murphy says, Canada uses mostly Russian and European stock. Those seeds could also be cross-bred with local feral strains.¶ <u>This lack of <mark>infrastructure has been a major barrier to producing hemp</mark> clothing and paper.</u> <u>Building a new decorticator mill for hemp paper would cost more than $100 million</u>, says Murphy.¶ Several small companies are using hemp for specialized products such as archival-quality, filter, or cigarette papers, but its most likely general use will be when mixed with recycled paper, says Steenstra. “Blend in 10 to 15 percent hemp, and it’s great for making better-quality recycled paper,” he says. When paper gets recycled, he explains, its fibers get shorter, and the long fibers of hemp strengthen it.¶ There are similar issues with clothing. Though Calvin Klein, Ralph Lauren, Giorgio Armani, and several lesser-known manufacturers are using hemp in clothes, “<u><mark>the</mark> whole <mark>textile industry is built on short-fiber</mark> cotton and <mark>synthetics,</mark>” says Steenstra. “<mark>There’s no infrastructure for processing hemp fiber</mark> into textiles</u>.”¶ Hemp oil for <u>biofuel</u>, another use dreamed of in the ‘90s, <u>is unlikely to be practical. At 50 gallons per acre, <mark>even if every acre</mark> of U.S. cropland <mark>were used for hemp, it would supply current U.S. demand</mark> for <strong><mark>oil for less than three weeks.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
Hemp Industry
429,938
9
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,563
No industry- can’t compete with other countries or materials
Ferner 2012
Ferner 2012 (Cites four marijuana policy experts: Dr. Jonathan P. Caulkins (Stever Professor of Operations Research and Public Policy at Carnegie Mellon University), Dr. Angela Hawken (Associate Professor of Public Policy at Pepperdine University), Dr. Beau Kilmer (Co-Director of the RAND Drug Policy Research Center), Dr. Mark Kleiman (Professor of Public Policy at UCLA), “'Marijuana Legalization: What Everyone Needs To Know' Authors Discuss Risks And Rewards Of Legal Weed”, 9/4/12, http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2012/09/04/marijuana-legalization-research_n_1850470.html)
Industrial hemp is a red herring. A number of European countries as well as China and Canada have legal industrial hemp production, yet the industry there remains stalled at small scale. It is not clear why farming hemp in Colorado would outcompete Canadian or European farmers (who are subsidized), and none of those countries competes effectively with China (which dominates global production). From a practical perspective, other materials are simply better than industrial hemp for most applications. Manila hemp (a different genus from cannabis) had already largely displaced cannabis hemp even before synthetic materials came on the scene hemp’s greatest asset is often its “hempness,” which can induce some people to pay a premium for a T-shirt made with hemp
European countries China and Canada have legal industrial hemp yet the industry there remains stalled at small scale. It is not clear why hemp in Colorado would outcompete Canadian or European farmers (who are subsidized none of those countries competes with China other materials are simply better Manila hemp (a different genus from cannabis already displaced hemp even before synthetic materials
Industrial hemp is mostly a red herring. A number of European countries as well as China and Canada have legal industrial hemp production, yet the industry there remains stalled at relatively small scale. It is not clear why farming hemp in Colorado would outcompete Canadian farmers or European farmers (who are subsidized), and none of those countries competes effectively with China (which dominates global production). From a practical perspective, other materials are simply better than industrial hemp for most applications. Manila hemp (a different genus from cannabis) had already largely displaced cannabis hemp even before synthetic materials came on the scene in the 20th century. Industrial hemp’s greatest asset is often its “hempness,” which can induce some people to pay a premium for a T-shirt made with hemp, akin to the way that some people once happily paid more for a shirt whose label said “Union Made” or “Made in the USA.”
945
<h4><strong>No industry- can’t compete with other countries or materials</h4><p>Ferner 2012</strong> (Cites four marijuana policy experts: Dr. Jonathan P. Caulkins (Stever Professor of Operations Research and Public Policy at Carnegie Mellon University), Dr. Angela Hawken (Associate Professor of Public Policy at Pepperdine University), Dr. Beau Kilmer (Co-Director of the RAND Drug Policy Research Center), Dr. Mark Kleiman (Professor of Public Policy at UCLA), “'Marijuana Legalization: What Everyone Needs To Know' Authors Discuss Risks And Rewards Of Legal Weed”, 9/4/12, http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2012/09/04/marijuana-legalization-research_n_1850470.html)</p><p><u>Industrial hemp is</u> mostly <u>a red herring. A number of <mark>European countries</mark> as well as <mark>China and Canada have legal industrial hemp</mark> production, <mark>yet the industry there <strong>remains stalled</strong> at</u></mark> relatively <u><mark>small scale. It is not clear why</mark> farming <mark>hemp in Colorado would outcompete Canadian</u></mark> farmers <u><mark>or European farmers (who are subsidized</mark>), and <mark>none of those countries competes</mark> effectively <mark>with <strong>China</strong></mark> (which dominates global production). From a practical perspective, <mark>other materials are <strong>simply better</strong></mark> than industrial hemp for most applications. <mark>Manila hemp (a different genus from cannabis</mark>) had <mark>already</mark> largely <mark>displaced</mark> cannabis <mark>hemp even before synthetic materials</mark> came on the scene</u> in the 20th century. Industrial <u>hemp’s greatest asset is often its “hempness,” which can induce some people to pay a premium for a T-shirt made with hemp</u><strong>, akin to the way that some people once happily paid more for a shirt whose label said “Union Made” or “Made in the USA.” </p></strong>
null
null
Hemp Industry
430,281
2
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,564
No domestic hemp industry- labor and transportation costs, tradeoffs with other profitable crops, and international competition
Johnson 2014
Johnson 2014 (Renee, Specialist in Agricultural Policy at the Congressional Research Service, Hemp as an Agricultural Commodity, CRS Report)
Two studies highlight challenges facing U.S. hemp producers USDA’s study projected that U.S. hemp markets “are, and will likely remain, small, thin markets” and cited “uncertainty about long-run demand for hemp products and the potential for oversupply the UW-M study concluded that hemp production “is not likely to generate profits and although hemp may be “slightly more profitable than traditional row crops” it is likely “less profitable than other specialty crops” due to the “current state of harvesting and processing technologies which are quite labor intensive, and result in high per unit costs U.S. hemp growers could be affected by competition from other world producers as well as production limitations in the United States including yield variability and lack of harvesting innovations and processing facilities as well as difficulty transporting bulk hemp. estimates of profitability from hemp production are highly speculative, and often do not include additional costs of growing hemp in a regulated market, such as the cost associated with “licensing, monitoring, and verification of commercial hemp A 2013 study by the University of Kentucky predicts that under current market conditions, it does not appear that anticipated hemp returns will be large enough to entice grain growers to shift out of grain production,” short run employment opportunities from a hemp industry appear limited because of continued uncertainty in the industry.28 Overall, the study concludes there are many remaining unknowns and further analysis and production research is needed. Given the absence since the 1950s of any commercial and unrestricted hemp production in the United States, it is not possible to predict the potential market and employment effects of relaxing current restrictions on U.S. hemp production. While expanded market opportunities might exist in some states or localities if current restrictions on production are lifted, it is not possible to predict the potential for future retail sales or employment gains in the United States, either nationally or within certain states or regions. Limited information is available from previous market analyses that have been conducted by researchers at USDA and land grant universities and state agencies.29
Two studies highlight challenges facing hemp USDA’s study projected that U.S. hemp markets “are, and will remain, small, and cited uncertainty about long-run demand hemp production “is not likely to generate profits although hemp may be “slightly more profitable it is likely “less profitable than other specialty crops” due to the “current state of harvesting and processing technologies, which are quite labor intensive, U.S. hemp growers could be affected by competition from other world producers as well as yield variability and lack of harvesting innovations and processing facilities as well as difficulty transporting bulk hemp estimates of profitability from hemp production are highly speculative, under current market conditions it does not appear that anticipated hemp returns will be large enough to entice grain growers to shift short run employment opportunities appear limited
Other studies focused on the total U.S. market differ from the various state reports and provide a less favorable aggregate view of the potential market for hemp growers in the United States. Two studies, conducted by researchers at USDA and University of Wisconsin-Madison (UW-M), highlight some of the continued challenges facing U.S. hemp producers. For example, USDA’s study projected that U.S. hemp markets “are, and will likely remain, small, thin markets” and also cited “uncertainty about long-run demand for hemp products and the potential for oversupply” among possible downsides of potential future hemp production. Similarly, the UW-M study concluded that hemp production “is not likely to generate sizeable profits” and although hemp may be “slightly more profitable than traditional row crops” it is likely “less profitable than other specialty crops” due to the “current state of harvesting and processing technologies, which are quite labor intensive, and result in relatively high per unit costs.”26 The study highlights that U.S. hemp growers could be affected by competition from other world producers as well as by certain production limitations in the United States, including yield variability and lack of harvesting innovations and processing facilities in the United States, as well as difficulty transporting bulk hemp. The study further claims that most estimates of profitability from hemp production are highly speculative, and often do not include additional costs of growing hemp in a regulated market, such as the cost associated with “licensing, monitoring, and verification of commercial hemp.”27 A 2013 study by researchers at the University of Kentucky highlights some of the issues and challenges for that state’s growers, processors, and industry. The study predicts that in Kentucky, despite “showing some positive returns, under current market conditions, it does not appear that anticipated hemp returns will be large enough to entice Kentucky grain growers to shift out of grain production,” under most circumstances; also, “short run employment opportunities evolving from a new Kentucky hemp industry appear limited (perhaps dozens of new jobs, not 100s),” because of continued uncertainty in the industry.28 Overall, the study concludes there are many remaining unknowns and further analysis and production research is needed. Given the absence since the 1950s of any commercial and unrestricted hemp production in the United States, it is not possible to predict the potential market and employment effects of relaxing current restrictions on U.S. hemp production. While expanded market opportunities might exist in some states or localities if current restrictions on production are lifted, it is not possible to predict the potential for future retail sales or employment gains in the United States, either nationally or within certain states or regions. Limited information is available from previous market analyses that have been conducted by researchers at USDA and land grant universities and state agencies.29
3,062
<h4><strong>No domestic hemp industry- labor and transportation costs, tradeoffs with other profitable crops, and international competition</h4><p>Johnson 2014</strong> (Renee, Specialist in Agricultural Policy at the Congressional Research Service, Hemp as an Agricultural Commodity, CRS Report)</p><p>Other studies focused on the total U.S. market differ from the various state reports and provide a less favorable aggregate view of the potential market for hemp growers in the United States. <u><mark>Two studies</u></mark>, conducted by researchers at USDA and University of Wisconsin-Madison (UW-M), <u><mark>highlight</u></mark> some of the continued <u><mark>challenges facing</mark> U.S. <mark>hemp</mark> producers</u>. For example, <u><mark>USDA’s study projected</mark> <mark>that</mark> <mark>U.S. hemp markets “are, and will</mark> likely <mark>remain, small,</mark> thin markets” <mark>and</u></mark> also <u><mark>cited</mark> “<mark>uncertainty about long-run demand</mark> for hemp products and the potential for oversupply</u>” among possible downsides of potential future hemp production. Similarly, <u>the UW-M study</u> <u>concluded that <mark>hemp production “is not likely to generate</u></mark> sizeable <u><mark>profits</u></mark>” <u>and <mark>although hemp may be “slightly more profitable</mark> than traditional row crops” <mark>it is likely “less profitable than other specialty crops” due to the “current state of harvesting and processing technologies</u>, <u>which are quite labor intensive,</mark> and result</u> <u>in</u> relatively <u>high per unit costs</u>.”26 The study highlights that <u><mark>U.S. hemp growers could be affected by competition from other world producers</mark> <mark>as well as</u></mark> by certain <u>production limitations in the United States</u>, <u>including <mark>yield variability and lack of harvesting innovations</mark> <mark>and</mark> <mark>processing facilities</u></mark> in the United States, <u><mark>as well as difficulty transporting bulk hemp</mark>.</u> The study further claims that most <u><mark>estimates of profitability from hemp production are highly speculative,</mark> and often do not include additional costs of growing hemp in a regulated market, such as the cost associated with “licensing, monitoring, and verification of commercial hemp</u>.”27 <u>A 2013 study by</u> researchers at <u>the University of Kentucky</u> highlights some of the issues and challenges for that state’s growers, processors, and industry. The study <u>predicts that</u> in Kentucky, despite “showing some positive returns, <u><mark>under current market conditions</mark>, <mark>it does not appear</mark> <mark>that anticipated hemp returns will be large enough to entice</u></mark> Kentucky <u><mark>grain growers to shift</mark> out of grain production,”</u> under most circumstances; also, “<u><mark>short run employment opportunities</u></mark> evolving <u>from a</u> new Kentucky <u>hemp industry <mark>appear limited</u></mark> (perhaps dozens of new jobs, not 100s),” <u>because of continued uncertainty <strong>in the industry.28 Overall, the study concludes there are many remaining unknowns and further analysis and production research is needed. Given the absence since the 1950s of any commercial and unrestricted hemp production in the United States, it is not possible to predict the potential market and employment effects of relaxing current restrictions on U.S. hemp production. While expanded market opportunities might exist in some states or localities if current restrictions on production are lifted, it is not possible to predict the potential for future retail sales or employment gains in the United States, either nationally or within certain states or regions. Limited information is available from previous market analyses that have been conducted by researchers at USDA and land grant universities and state agencies.29</p></u></strong>
null
null
Hemp Industry
430,164
19
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,565
No modeling – states lack infrastructural capacity
Levi 11
Levi 11 [Michael A. Levi David M. Rubenstein Senior Fellow for Energy and the Environment Why Don’t States Cooperate More on Energy and Climate? Posted on Tuesday, January 18, 2011 http://blogs.cfr.org/levi/2011/01/18/why-dont-states-cooperate-more-on-energy-and-climate/?utm_source=feedburner&utm_medium=feed&utm_campaign=Feed%3A+mlevi+%28Michael+Levi%27s+Blog%29&utm_content=Google+Reader]
states’ capacity to cooperate when it comes to energy and climate, it’s one of the bigger blind spots in how practitioners and scholars think about cooperation. Beijing doesn’t have many of the needed statistics Badgering them won’t change that; until they develop the capacity cooperation will fail. India won’t be able to force power plants to internalize pollution costs until it develops a serious environmental regulator. Brazil won’t get deforestation under control without stronger capacity to enforce laws China won’t improve its IPR protection until its innovation system becomes much more capable of developing tech Our view of international politics tends to focus much more on pure ambition than on these sorts of features that directly influence results.
India won’t be able to internalize pollution costs until it develops a serious environmental regulator. Brazil won’t get deforestation under control without stronger capacity to enforce laws China won’t improve IPR protection until its more capable of developing tech Our view of international politics tends to focus more on ambition than these features that directly influence results.
I spent Friday and Saturday at an excellent (largely academic) workshop on international institutions and global governance. In our discussions about why states do and don’t cooperate, I was struck by how absent states’ capacity to cooperate was from the discussion. In particular, when it comes to energy and climate, it’s one of the bigger blind spots in how both practitioners and scholars think about cooperation. Here’s a simple example of what I’m referring to: People argue that international oil markets would function more smoothly if states would publish basic data on their domestic markets (supply, demand, stocks, etc). They observe that China (among others) doesn’t do that. The immediate conclusion is that Beijing doesn’t want to. The only policy recourse, then, is to pressure or persuade China to change tack. But in more than one recent conversation, people have emphasized to me that Beijing doesn’t have many of the needed statistics itself (though it’s working on developing its capacity). Badgering them won’t change that; until they develop the capacity to collect the right statistics, cooperation will fail. The same thing is true much more broadly. India, for example, won’t be able to force power plants to internalize pollution costs until it develops a serious environmental regulator. Brazil won’t get deforestation properly under control without stronger capacity to enforce the laws that it puts on the books. One might even argue that China won’t improve its IPR protection until its innovation system becomes much more capable of developing technologies itself. Our view of international politics, though, tends to focus much more on pure ambition than on these sorts of features that directly influence results.
1,750
<h4><strong>No modeling – states lack infrastructural capacity</h4><p>Levi 11<u></strong><mark> [Michael A. Levi David M. Rubenstein Senior Fellow for Energy and the Environment Why Don’t States Cooperate More on Energy and Climate? Posted on Tuesday, January 18, 2011 http://blogs.cfr.org/levi/2011/01/18/why-dont-states-cooperate-more-on-energy-and-climate/?utm_source=feedburner&utm_medium=feed&utm_campaign=Feed%3A+mlevi+%28Michael+Levi%27s+Blog%29&utm_content=Google+Reader]</p><p></u></mark>I spent Friday and Saturday at an excellent (largely academic) workshop on international institutions and global governance. In our discussions about why states do and don’t cooperate, I was struck by how absent <u>states’ capacity to cooperate</u> was from the discussion. In particular, <u>when it comes to energy and climate, it’s one of the bigger blind spots in how</u> both <u>practitioners and scholars think about cooperation. </u> Here’s a simple example of what I’m referring to: People argue that international oil markets would function more smoothly if states would publish basic data on their domestic markets (supply, demand, stocks, etc). They observe that China (among others) doesn’t do that. The immediate conclusion is that Beijing doesn’t want to. The only policy recourse, then, is to pressure or persuade China to change tack. But in more than one recent conversation, people have emphasized to me that <u>Beijing doesn’t have many of the needed statistics</u> itself (though it’s working on developing its capacity). <u>Badgering them won’t change that; until they develop the capacity</u> to collect the right statistics, <u>cooperation will fail.</u> The same thing is true much more broadly. <u><mark>India</u></mark>, for example, <u><mark>won’t be able to </mark>force power plants to<mark> internalize pollution costs until it develops a serious environmental regulator. Brazil won’t get deforestation</u></mark> properly <u><mark>under control without stronger capacity to enforce</u></mark> the <u><mark>laws</u></mark> that it puts on the books. One might even argue that <u><mark>China won’t improve</mark> its <mark>IPR protection until its</mark> innovation system becomes much <mark>more capable of developing tech</u></mark>nologies itself. <u><mark>Our view of international politics</u></mark>, though, <u><mark>tends to focus </mark>much<mark> more on </mark>pure<mark> ambition than </mark>on<mark> these </mark>sorts of<mark> features that directly influence results.</p></u></mark>
null
null
1NC – Modeling
430,283
4
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,566
Case
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Case</h4>
null
null
1NC – Modeling
430,282
1
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,567
“Legalize” Must make an activity lawful--- doesnt allow  discretion to prohibit
null
Quinn 92 – Judge Quinn, Supreme Court of Colorado, 826 P.2d 1241; 1992 Colo. LEXIS 53; 16 BTR 133, 1-27, Lexis
null
null
Turning to Verlo's claim, we are satisfied that the Board's use of the term "legalize" in the title and in the ballot title and submission clause correctly and fairly expresses the true intent and meaning of the proposed constitutional amendment. The word "legalize" means "to make legal" or "to give legal validity or sanction to." Webster's Third New International Dictionary 1290 (1986); see also Black's Law Dictionary (6th ed. 1990) (legalize means "to make legal or lawful" or "to confirm or validate what was before void or unlawful"). In the context of the phrase "to legalize limited gaming in the cities of Manitou Springs and Fairplay," the word "legalize" expresses the sense that these cities will be required to legislate so as to make limited gaming legal within their respective municipalities. Contrary to Verlo's argument, we do not construe the word "legalize" as somehow suggesting that the cities of Manitou Springs and Fairplay [**11]  will retain the discretion either to legalize or to prohibit limited gaming as they see fit. The Board's decision to add a sentence to the summary stating that under the proposed constitutional amendment the cities of Manitou Springs and Fairplay would be "required to enact certain ordinances to implement limited gaming" merely expands upon what is conveyed in the title and in the ballot title and submission clause by the phrase "to legalize limited gaming in the cities of Manitou Springs and Fairplay." Nothing in the recordpersuades us that the Board's choice of language in the title and in the ballot title and submission clause is in any way misrepresentative of the true intent and meaning of the proposed constitutional amendment. We accordingly affirm the ruling of the Board.
1,747
<h4><strong>“Legalize” Must make an activity lawful--- doesnt allow  <u>discretion</u> to prohibit</h4><p></strong>Quinn 92 – Judge Quinn, Supreme Court of Colorado, 826 P.2d 1241; 1992 Colo. LEXIS 53; 16 BTR 133, 1-27, Lexis</p><p>Turning to Verlo's claim, we are satisfied that the Board's use of the term "legalize" in the title and in the ballot title and submission clause correctly and fairly expresses the true intent and meaning of the proposed constitutional amendment. The word "legalize" means "to make legal" or "to give legal validity or sanction to." Webster's Third New International Dictionary 1290 (1986); see also Black's Law Dictionary (6th ed. 1990) (legalize means "to make legal or lawful" or "to confirm or validate what was before void or unlawful"). In the context of the phrase "to legalize limited gaming in the cities of Manitou Springs and Fairplay," the word "legalize" expresses the sense that these cities will be required to legislate so as to make limited gaming legal within their respective municipalities. Contrary to Verlo's argument, we do not construe the word "legalize" as somehow suggesting that the cities of Manitou Springs and Fairplay [**11]  will retain the discretion either to legalize or to prohibit limited gaming as they see fit. The Board's decision to add a sentence to the summary stating that under the proposed constitutional amendment the cities of Manitou Springs and Fairplay would be "required to enact certain ordinances to implement limited gaming" merely expands upon what is conveyed in the title and in the ballot title and submission clause by the phrase "to legalize limited gaming in the cities of Manitou Springs and Fairplay." Nothing in the recordpersuades us that the Board's choice of language in the title and in the ballot title and submission clause is in any way misrepresentative of the true intent<strong> and meaning of the proposed constitutional amendment. We accordingly affirm the ruling of the Board.</p></strong>
null
null
null
430,284
78
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,568
IMPACTS OF WARMING ONLY SEEK TO MASK THE OPPRESSION AND EXPLOITION OF WHITE SUPREMACY AND INSTITUTIONALLY RACIST PRACTICES
null
The DEATH CULTURE posed by nuclear war has already ENDED the world for people of color, SURVIVAL AT ANY COST outweighs LIBERTY, PEACE and DIGNITY. People of color face NUCLEAR HOLOCAUST and GENOCIDE through their jobs, housing, schools, families and land. Someone MUST STAND UP and make the connection between NUCLEAR ARSENALS, RACISM, SEXISM and IMPERIALISM.
, p. 12; http://www.jstor.org/stable/4004305] Of course, for people of color the world over, starvation is already a common problem, when, for example, a nation’s crops are grown for export rather than to feed its own people. And the housing of people of color throughout the world’s urban areas is already blighted and inhumane: families live in shacks, shanty towns, or on the streets; even in the urban areas of North America, the poor may live without heat or running water. For people of color, the world as we knew it ended centuries ago. Our world, with its own languages, customs and ways, ended. And we are only now beginning to see with increasing clarity that our task is to reclaim that world, struggle for it, and rebuild it in our own image. The “death culture” we live in has convinced many to be more concerned with death than with life, more willing to demonstrate for “survival at any cost” than to struggle for liberty and peace with dignity. Nuclear disarmament becomes a safe issue when it is not linked to the daily and historic issues of racism, to the ways in which people of color continue to be murdered. Acts of war, nuclear holocausts, and genocide have already been declared on our jobs, our housing, our schools, our families, and our lands. We must fight as a people on all fronts, or we will continue to die as a people. We have fought in people’s wars and in countless daily encounters with landlords, welfare departments, and schools. These struggles are not abstractions, but the only means by which we have gained the ability to eat and to provide for the future of our people. We wonder who will lead the battle for nuclear disarmament Who will make the political links among racism, sexism, imperialism, cultural integrity, and nuclear arsenals and housing? Who will stand up?
Of course, for people of color the world over, starvation is already a common problem, when, for example, a nation’s crops are grown for export rather than to feed its own people. And the housing of people of color throughout the world’s urban areas is already blighted and inhumane: families live in shacks, shanty towns, or on the streets; even in the urban areas of North America, the poor may live without heat or running water. For people of color, the world as we knew it ended centuries ago. Our world, with its own languages, customs and ways, ended. And we are only now beginning to see with increasing clarity that our task is to reclaim that world, struggle for it, and rebuild it in our own image. The “death culture” we live in has convinced many to be more concerned with death than with life, more willing to demonstrate for “survival at any cost” than to struggle for liberty and peace with dignity. Nuclear disarmament becomes a safe issue when it is not linked to the daily and historic issues of racism, to the ways in which people of color continue to be murdered. Acts of war, nuclear holocausts, and genocide have already been declared on our jobs, our housing, our schools, our families, and our lands. Who will make the political links among racism, sexism, imperialism, cultural integrity, and nuclear arsenals and housing? Who will stand up?
OMOLADE ‘84 [Summer 1984, Barbara- City College Center for Worker Education in New York City a historian of black women for the past twenty years and an organizer in both the women’s and civil rights/black power movements; Women of Color and the Nuclear Holocaust; WOMEN’S STUDIES QUARTERLY, Vol. 12., No. 2, Teaching about Peace, War, and Women in the Military, p. 12; http://www.jstor.org/stable/4004305] In April, 1979, the U.S. Arms Control and Disarmament Agency released a report on the effects of nuclear war that concludes that, in a general nuclear war between the United States and the Soviet Union, 25 to 100 million people would be killed. This is approximately the same number of African people who died between 1492 and 1890 as a result of the African slave trade to the New World. The same federal report also comments on the destruction of urban housing that would cause massive shortages after a nuclear war, as well as on the crops that would be lost, causing massive food shortages. Of course, for people of color the world over, starvation is already a common problem, when, for example, a nation’s crops are grown for export rather than to feed its own people. And the housing of people of color throughout the world’s urban areas is already blighted and inhumane: families live in shacks, shanty towns, or on the streets; even in the urban areas of North America, the poor may live without heat or running water. For people of color, the world as we knew it ended centuries ago. Our world, with its own languages, customs and ways, ended. And we are only now beginning to see with increasing clarity that our task is to reclaim that world, struggle for it, and rebuild it in our own image. The “death culture” we live in has convinced many to be more concerned with death than with life, more willing to demonstrate for “survival at any cost” than to struggle for liberty and peace with dignity. Nuclear disarmament becomes a safe issue when it is not linked to the daily and historic issues of racism, to the ways in which people of color continue to be murdered. Acts of war, nuclear holocausts, and genocide have already been declared on our jobs, our housing, our schools, our families, and our lands. As women of color, we are warriors, not pacifists. We must fight as a people on all fronts, or we will continue to die as a people. We have fought in people’s wars in China, in Cuba, in Guinea-Bissau, and in such struggles as the civil rights movement, the women’s movement, and in countless daily encounters with landlords, welfare departments, and schools. These struggles are not abstractions, but the only means by which we have gained the ability to eat and to provide for the future of our people. We wonder who will lead the battle for nuclear disarmament with the vigor and clarity that women of color have learned from participating in other struggles. Who will make the political links among racism, sexism, imperialism, cultural integrity, and nuclear arsenals and housing? Who will stand up?
3,049
<h4>IMPACTS OF WARMING ONLY SEEK TO MASK THE OPPRESSION AND EXPLOITION OF WHITE SUPREMACY AND INSTITUTIONALLY RACIST PRACTICES</h4><p>The DEATH CULTURE posed by nuclear war has already ENDED the world for people of color, SURVIVAL AT ANY COST outweighs LIBERTY, PEACE and DIGNITY. People of color face NUCLEAR HOLOCAUST and GENOCIDE through their jobs, housing, schools, families and land. Someone MUST STAND UP and make the connection between NUCLEAR ARSENALS, RACISM, SEXISM and IMPERIALISM.</p><p><strong>OMOLADE ‘84</strong> [Summer 1984, Barbara- City College Center for Worker Education in New York City a historian of black women for the past twenty years and an organizer in both the women’s and civil rights/black power movements; Women of Color and the Nuclear Holocaust; WOMEN’S STUDIES QUARTERLY, Vol. 12., No. 2, Teaching about Peace, War, and Women in the Military<u><strong>, p. 12; http://www.jstor.org/stable/4004305]</p><p></u></strong>In April, 1979, the U.S. Arms Control and Disarmament Agency released a report on the effects of nuclear war that concludes that, in a general nuclear war between the United States and the Soviet Union, 25 to 100 million people would be killed. This is approximately the same number of African people who died between 1492 and 1890 as a result of the African slave trade to the New World. The same federal report also comments on the destruction of urban housing that would cause massive shortages after a nuclear war, as well as on the crops that would be lost, causing massive food shortages. <u><strong><mark>Of course, for people of color the world over, starvation is already a common problem, when, for example, a nation’s crops are grown for export rather than to feed its own people. And the housing of people of color throughout the world’s urban areas is already blighted and inhumane: families live in shacks, shanty towns, or on the streets; even in the urban areas of North America, the poor may live without heat or running water.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>For people of color, the world as we knew it ended centuries ago. Our world, with its own languages, customs and ways, ended. And we are only now beginning to see with increasing clarity that our task is to reclaim that world, struggle for it, and rebuild it in our own image.</mark> <mark>The “death culture” we live in has convinced many to be more concerned with death than with life, more willing to demonstrate for “survival at any cost” than to struggle for liberty and peace with dignity. Nuclear disarmament becomes a safe issue when it is not linked to the daily and historic issues of racism, to the ways in which people of color continue to be murdered. Acts of war, nuclear holocausts, and genocide have already been declared on our jobs, our housing, our schools, our families, and our lands.</mark> </u></strong>As women of color, we are warriors, not pacifists. <u><strong>We must fight as a people on all fronts, or we will continue to die as a people. We have fought in people’s wars</u></strong> in China, in Cuba, in Guinea-Bissau, and in such struggles as the civil rights movement, the women’s movement, <u><strong>and in countless daily encounters with landlords, welfare departments, and schools. These struggles are not abstractions, but the only means by which we have gained the ability to eat and to provide for the future of our people. We wonder who will lead the battle for nuclear disarmament</u></strong> with the vigor and clarity that women of color have learned from participating in other struggles. <u><strong><mark>Who will make the political links among racism, sexism, imperialism, cultural integrity, and nuclear arsenals and housing? Who will stand up?</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
1NC – Modeling
11,982
225
17,054
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
565,314
N
Navy
Octas
Georgia Boyce-Feinberg
Bender, Bobbitt, Hall
Marijuana aff with warming impacts and in round discourse important 2nc warming K - basically apocalyptic rhetoric about warming bad because then people don't want to do anything 1nri think it was just pessmism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Octas.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,569
CSA waivers don’t legalize – marijuana still presumptively prohibited nationwide
null
Grabarsky, 13 Todd, Law Clerk, United States Court, Northern District of California. J.D., Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law, 2012; B.A., University of Pennsylvania, “CONFLICTING FEDERAL AND STATE MEDICAL MARIJUANA POLICIES: ¶ A THREAT TO COOPERATIVE FEDERALISM,” Vitz
null
null
B. A Congressional Exemption for Medical Marijuana in Compliance with State Law Because it appears that the federal executive could not viably preserve the federalism balance, this Article turns to Congress. This Article proposes that Congress act to reconcile the state-federal conflict of laws regarding medical marijuana by creating an exemption from the CSA for medical marijuana usage and distribution in compliance with approved state laws and regulatory schemes. At the most, Congress could amend the CSA to expressly provide the exemption, or, at the very least, pass an act prohibiting the Executive from enforcing the CSA's medical marijuana proscription in states that permit it. Such an exemption would allow states to proceed with their medical marijuana programs while at the same time keeping the drug illegal at the federal level. The result would be that medical marijuana would be presumptively prohibited nationwide, except in states that takeaffirmative legislative and administrative steps (as some have already done) to legalize it. It is extremely important to note that this proposal does not call for a federal exemption to the CSA for medical marijuana. On one hand, in states like California that elect to legalize medical marijuana, the proposed exemption would allow those states' legislation and regulation to operate unimpeded by federal disruption. This will also allow these states to work with the federal authorities in focusing on the state-federal unity of interests in drug enforcement; for example California state agents will still be able and encouraged to work with their federal counterparts to curb the distribution and possession of drugs that remain illegal on both the federal and state level. On the other hand, in states that wish to keep medical marijuana prohibited, state authorities will continue to cooperate with the federal government to execute the CSA and its state law counterpart.
1,940
<h4><strong>CSA waivers don’t legalize – marijuana still presumptively prohibited nationwide</h4><p></strong>Grabarsky, 13 Todd, Law Clerk, United States Court, Northern District of California. J.D., Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law, 2012; B.A., University of Pennsylvania, “CONFLICTING FEDERAL AND STATE MEDICAL MARIJUANA POLICIES: ¶ A THREAT TO COOPERATIVE FEDERALISM,” Vitz</p><p>B. A Congressional Exemption for Medical Marijuana in Compliance with State Law Because it appears that the federal executive could not viably preserve the federalism balance, this Article turns to Congress. This Article proposes that Congress act to reconcile the state-federal conflict of laws regarding medical marijuana by creating an exemption from the CSA for medical marijuana usage and distribution in compliance with approved state laws and regulatory schemes. At the most, Congress could amend the CSA to expressly provide the exemption, or, at the very least, pass an act prohibiting the Executive from enforcing the CSA's medical marijuana proscription in states that permit it. Such an exemption would allow states to proceed with their medical marijuana programs while at the same time keeping the drug illegal at the federal level. The result would be that medical marijuana would be presumptively prohibited nationwide, except in states that takeaffirmative legislative and administrative steps (as some have already done) to legalize it. It is extremely important to note that this proposal does not call for a federal exemption to the CSA for medical marijuana. On one hand, in states like California that elect to legalize medical marijuana, the proposed exemption would allow those states' legislation and regulation to operate unimpeded by federal disruption. This will also allow these states to work with the federal authorities in focusing on the state-federal unity of interests in drug enforcement; for example California state agents will still be able and encouraged to work with their federal counterparts to curb the distribution and possession of drugs that remain illegal on both the federal and state level. On the other hand, in states that wish to keep medical marijuana prohibited, state authorities will continue to cooperate with the federal government to execute the CSA and its state law counterpart<strong>.</p></strong>
null
null
null
56,734
14
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,570
Probabalism and effects – plan facially removes zero prohibitions, every state could say no to the conditions, only two states have legalized so even if they said yes plan would only waive CSA for two states in the short term – crushes neg ground – destroys time sensitive disads, state specific legalization disads – unlimits – any policy could eventually result in legalization – including the status quo, or legalizing OTHER DRUGS
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><strong>Probabalism and effects – plan facially removes zero prohibitions, every state could say no to the conditions, only two states have legalized so even if they said yes plan would only waive CSA for two states in the short term – crushes neg ground – destroys time sensitive disads, state specific legalization disads – unlimits – any policy could eventually result in legalization – including the status quo, or legalizing OTHER DRUGS</h4><p> </p></strong>
null
null
null
430,285
1
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,571
Ground – fiating removal of prohibition on nearly all marijuana activities is the CORE locus of negative ground on the topic – uniquely key because theres no stable actor and legalization already allows tons of flexibility in regulatory regime
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><strong>Ground – fiating removal of prohibition on nearly all marijuana activities is the CORE locus of negative ground on the topic – uniquely key because theres no stable actor and legalization already allows tons of flexibility in regulatory regime</h4></strong>
null
null
null
430,286
1
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,572
The Understanding of American Hegemony as a Peace-Building Force is Ultimately Tied to a Grand Narrative, a Myth of Productive and Utilitarian Futures, Linked to the Very Concept of Nuclear Weapons—This Organization is Precisely the Cause of the World Ending Violence You Identify
)
Cyndy Hendershot, Prof of Film at Arkansas State, “From Trauma to Paranoia: Nuclear Weapons, Science Fiction and History,” Mosaic, Winter 1999 (Questia)
First detonated on 16 July 1945 in the New Mexico desert (see Fig. 1), the bomb and its implications were first experienced as trauma in the cities of Hiroshima and Nagasaki Bataille pinpoints a central ethical issue raised by the use of the bomb: "the death of sixty thousand is charged with meaning, in that it depended on their fellow men to kill them or to let them die. The atom bomb draws its meaning from its human origin: it is the possibility that the hands of man deliberately hang suspended over the future The realization that a human agency could in turn be responsible for the total death of humanity defies the imagination. One may, in fact, not be able to create effective psychological myths for the unimaginable prospect which has, only since nuclear weapons, become part of reality, both external and psychological And it is precisely this trauma--the awareness of the degree to which we (Americans, humans) are responsible for weapons of mass destruction and hold the fate of the world in our hands Central to this ahistoricism is the translation of the problem into something universal, mythological--or more appropriately, trauma becomes translated into paranoia The world of the paranoiac is a delusory one in which historical issues are played out as mythic battles between good and evil Cold War paranoia involved a re-defining of the historical as the mythological: ). In Franklin's view, the American myth of "the ultimate peacemaking weapons" that would lead to world peace under American hegemony directly shaped the nuclear policies of the United States
Bataille pinpoints a central ethical issue raised by the use of the bomb: "the death of sixty thousand is charged with meaning, in that it depended on their fellow men to kill them or to let them die. The realization that a human agency could in turn be responsible for the total death of humanity defies the imagination One may , not be able to create effective psychological myths for the unimaginable prospect which And it is precisely this trauma--the awareness of the degree to which we are responsible for weapons of mass destruction and hold the fate of the world in our hands Central to this ahistoricism is the translation of the problem into something universal, mythological The world of the paranoiac is a delusory one in which historical issues are played out as mythic battles between good and evil " Cold War paranoia involved a re-defining of the historical as the mythological: the American myth of "the ultimate peacemaking weapons" that would lead to world peace under American hegemony directly shaped the nuclear policies of the United States
First detonated on 16 July 1945 in the New Mexico desert (see Fig. 1), the bomb and its implications were first experienced as trauma in the cities of Hiroshima and Nagasaki. In addition to the naked human suffering experienced in those cities, what also needed addressing were the manifold philosophical questions arising from the United States's use of nuclear weapons. Commenting on John Hersey's account of the survivors of Hiroshima, French philosopher Georges Bataille pinpoints a central ethical issue raised by the use of the bomb: "the death of sixty thousand is charged with meaning, in that it depended on their fellow men to kill them or to let them die. The atom bomb draws its meaning from its human origin: it is the possibility that the hands of man deliberately hang suspended over the future" (226). Written in 1947, Bataille's estimate of the victims of the Hiroshima bomb has subsequently been upped to an immediate-death toll of 100,000 and the fatal-injury toll of 50,000 (Lifton & Mitchell xvii). The realization that a human agency could in turn be responsible for the total death of humanity defies the imagination. Discussing nuclear holocaust, psychoanalyst Leon Botstein argues that effective conceptualizing of nuclear war may be impossible: "Total death cannot truly even be imagined; no myth appeared even necessary for Freud. One may, in fact, not be able to create effective psychological myths for the unimaginable prospect which has, only since nuclear weapons, become part of reality, both external and psychological" (301). And it is precisely this trauma--the awareness of the degree to which we (Americans, humans) are responsible for weapons of mass destruction and hold the fate of the world in our hands--that causes our society to, so often, take nuclear weapons outside of history. Central to this ahistoricism is the translation of the problem into something universal, mythological--or more appropriately, trauma becomes translated into paranoia. The world of the paranoiac is a delusory one in which historical issues are played out as mythic battles between good and evil. In his history of the Cold War, for example, H.W. Brands describes the paranoiac's view of history as one in which the world is divided neatly into good and evil, which enables him/her to conclude that "Humanity's problems aren't the consequence of some abiding deficiency in all of us. Problems are the work of bad people" (38). Certainly, this was the attitude of Daniel Paul Schreber--a most famous paranoiac, who resorted to such psychic mechanisms in dealing with the history of his time, and whose published memoirs served as the basis for Freud's theory of paranoia. In dealing with fin-de-siecle German nationalism and its attendant anti-Semitism, Schreber's strategy was to place this phenomenon outside its specific cultural/historical moment, as when he stated that "the Germans were in modern times (possibly since the Reformation, perhaps since the migration of nations) God's chosen people whose language God preferred to use" (50). Similarly, listing some historical events--ranging from the destruction of Phillip II's Spanish Armada in 1588 to the severe winter of 1870-71--he claims to have been told through divine communication that these were determined by God. Translating elements from his own society into universal myths, he makes historically specific phenomena like the German Kulturkampf part of his paranoic cosmology, leading Eric L. Santer pointedly to title his study of Schreber's delusionary view of cultural events My Own Private Germany. As I see it, cases like Schreber provide classic examples on the individual level of how paranoia functions as a psychic-defense mechanism which takes the sting out of history by draining it of the element of human responsibility and placing it in eschatological/myth ological time and space. In America in the 1950s, cultural paranoia performed similar work. As Richard Hofstadter explained in his seminal 1966 essay "The Paranoid Style in American Politics," Cold War paranoia involved a re-defining of the historical as the mythological: "History is a conspiracy, set in motion by demonic forces of almost transcendent power, and what is felt to be needed to defeat it is not the usual methods of political give-and-take, but an all-out crusade" (29). Thus communism could be seen not as a historically specific political system but as an embodiment of mythological evil--pagan and satanic; the postwar Soviet Union becomes mythologically great and evil. Similarly, I.F. Stone astutely observed that during the 1950s American liberals and conservatives alike painted communists as "some supernatural breed of men, led by diabolic masterminds in that distant Kremlin, engaged in a satanic conspiracy to take over the world and enslave all mankind" (69). If the Cold War was a mythological battle against a pagan/sa tanic enemy, then we (the U.S.) as crusaders had been given the bomb by God. We were not responsible for its scientific creation and its implications. Indeed, Harry S. Truman expressed this very sentiment in his 1945 announcement after the destruction of Nagasaki: "We thank God it has come to us, instead of to our enemies; and we pray that He may guide us to use it in His ways and His purposes" (qtd. in Boyer 211). Thus the bomb is a weapon we have been given, and the trauma of using it is alleviated by paranoiac defense mechanisms. Another reason behind the mythologizing of nuclear technology in the 1940s and 1950s was that ignorance about the new scientific discovery caused people to search for a frame of reference that could make sense of the unrepresentable content of nuclear physics. In an interview in which he discusses the trauma suffered by the victims in Hiroshima, psychoanalyst Robert Jay Lifton observes: "In creating, in recreating experience, we need some prior imagery in order to do that work, in order to carry through that process. And there was precious little prior imagery that could enable people to take in the Hiroshima experience, the event of a weapon apparently destroying an entire city" (135). Lacking frames of reference, American society turned to myth to articulate the meanings of nuclear bombs. In the mythologizing of nuclear weapons in the 1940s and 1950s, few literary modes were better equipped or played a more key role than science fiction. As John W. Campbell, Jr., noted in a 1953 essay in which he attempted to "place" this genre, science fiction stands in opposition to history, operating as a mythology that charts "the hopes and dreams and fears (for some dreams are nightmares) of a technically based society" (12). In the same year, Gerald Heard argued that science fiction can guide humans in the Atomic Age in a manner similar to the cohesive social function performed by mythology in former times, that it can "shape our reactions to our destiny" by showing us "how to react, how to adapt, how to endure" (255). Focusing on science-fiction ifims, more recent critics have noted a similar dynamic. In Future Tense, for example, John Brosman argues that 1950s films resorted to "various euphemisms such as giant beasts" to depict the bomb (82), just as in Nuclear Fear Spencer Weart discusses the way tha t such films contributed to the creation of a space-age mythology. Other critics, however, have responded to this tendency in a less positive light. Philip Wylie, for example, complains that 1940s and 1950s science-fiction writers were irresponsible in creating "a new and sinister folklore" that obscured the scientific facts about the bomb (235). Richard Hodgens levels this type of criticism especially at science-fiction films, claiming that they associate technology with "The Black Arts" (261). For Frederic Jameson, science fiction attests to the inability of capitalist society to go beyond its own fixed mindset, that the "deepest vocation" of science fiction is "over and over again to demonstrate and dramatize our incapacity to imagine the future" (153). According to H. Bruce Franklin, moreover, not only did the various modes of science fiction bring an awareness of the Atomic Age to the attention of a popular audience, but they also created a mythology of nuclear weapons that was then adopted by American policymakers. Thus, in War Stars: The Superweapon and the American Imagination he argues: "For fifty years, from the first atomic explosion in Robert Cromies's 1895 novel The Crack of Doom until 1945, nuclear weapons existed nowhere but in science fiction, and in the imagination of those directly or indirectly influenced by this fiction, including scientists who converted these inventions from fantasy into facts of life" (131). In Franklin's view, the American myth of "the ultimate peacemaking weapons" that would lead to world peace under American hegemony directly shaped the nuclear policies of the United States (153)
8,927
<h4>The Understanding of American Hegemony as a Peace-Building Force is Ultimately Tied to a Grand Narrative, a Myth of Productive and Utilitarian Futures, Linked to the Very Concept of Nuclear Weapons—This Organization is Precisely the Cause of the World Ending Violence You Identify</h4><p>Cyndy Hendershot, Prof of Film at Arkansas State, “From Trauma to Paranoia: Nuclear Weapons, Science Fiction and History,” Mosaic, Winter 1999 (Questia<u><strong>)</p><p>First detonated on 16 July 1945 in the New Mexico desert (see Fig. 1), the bomb and its implications were first experienced as trauma in the cities of Hiroshima and Nagasaki</u></strong>. In addition to the naked human suffering experienced in those cities, what also needed addressing were the manifold philosophical questions arising from the United States's use of nuclear weapons. Commenting on John Hersey's account of the survivors of Hiroshima, French philosopher Georges <u><strong><mark>Bataille pinpoints a central ethical issue raised by the use of the bomb: "the death of sixty thousand is charged with meaning, in that it depended on their fellow men to kill them or to let them die.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>The atom bomb draws its meaning from its human origin: it is the possibility that the hands of man deliberately hang suspended over the future</u></strong>" (226). Written in 1947, Bataille's estimate of the victims of the Hiroshima bomb has subsequently been upped to an immediate-death toll of 100,000 and the fatal-injury toll of 50,000 (Lifton & Mitchell xvii). <u><strong><mark>The realization that a human agency could in turn be responsible for the total death of humanity defies the imagination</mark>.</u></strong> Discussing nuclear holocaust, psychoanalyst Leon Botstein argues that effective conceptualizing of nuclear war may be impossible: "Total death cannot truly even be imagined; no myth appeared even necessary for Freud. <u><strong><mark>One may</mark>, in fact<mark>, not be able to create effective psychological myths for the unimaginable prospect which</mark> has, only since nuclear weapons, become part of reality, both external and psychological</u></strong>" (301). <u><strong><mark>And it is precisely this trauma--the awareness of the degree to which we</mark> (Americans, humans) <mark>are responsible for weapons of mass destruction and hold the fate of the world in our hands</u></strong></mark>--that causes our society to, so often, take nuclear weapons outside of history.</p><p><u><strong><mark>Central to this ahistoricism is the translation of the problem into something universal, mythological</mark>--or more appropriately, trauma becomes translated into paranoia</u></strong>. <u><strong><mark>The world of the paranoiac is a delusory one in which historical issues are played out as mythic battles between good and evil</u></strong></mark>. In his history of the Cold War, for example, H.W. Brands describes the paranoiac's view of history as one in which the world is divided neatly into good and evil, which enables him/her to conclude that "Humanity's problems aren't the consequence of some abiding deficiency in all of us. Problems are the work of bad people" (38). Certainly, this was the attitude of Daniel Paul Schreber--a most famous paranoiac, who resorted to such psychic mechanisms in dealing with the history of his time, and whose published memoirs served as the basis for Freud's theory of paranoia.</p><p>In dealing with fin-de-siecle German nationalism and its attendant anti-Semitism, Schreber's strategy was to place this phenomenon outside its specific cultural/historical moment, as when he stated that "the Germans were in modern times (possibly since the Reformation, perhaps since the migration of nations) God's chosen people whose language God preferred to use" (50). Similarly, listing some historical events--ranging from the destruction of Phillip II's Spanish Armada in 1588 to the severe winter of 1870-71--he claims to have been told through divine communication that these were determined by God. Translating elements from his own society into universal myths, he makes historically specific phenomena like the German Kulturkampf part of his paranoic cosmology, leading Eric L. Santer pointedly to title his study of Schreber's delusionary view of cultural events My Own Private Germany. As I see it, cases like Schreber provide classic examples on the individual level of how paranoia functions as a psychic-defense mechanism which takes the sting out of history by draining it of the element of human responsibility and placing it in eschatological/myth ological time and space.</p><p>In America in the 1950s, cultural paranoia performed similar work. As Richard Hofstadter explained in his seminal 1966 essay "The Paranoid Style in American Politics,<mark>" <u><strong>Cold War paranoia involved a re-defining of the historical as the mythological:</u></strong></mark> "History is a conspiracy, set in motion by demonic forces of almost transcendent power, and what is felt to be needed to defeat it is not the usual methods of political give-and-take, but an all-out crusade" (29). Thus communism could be seen not as a historically specific political system but as an embodiment of mythological evil--pagan and satanic; the postwar Soviet Union becomes mythologically great and evil. Similarly, I.F. Stone astutely observed that during the 1950s American liberals and conservatives alike painted communists as "some supernatural breed of men, led by diabolic masterminds in that distant Kremlin, engaged in a satanic conspiracy to take over the world and enslave all mankind" (69). If the Cold War was a mythological battle against a pagan/sa tanic enemy, then we (the U.S.) as crusaders had been given the bomb by God. We were not responsible for its scientific creation and its implications. Indeed, Harry S. Truman expressed this very sentiment in his 1945 announcement after the destruction of Nagasaki: "We thank God it has come to us, instead of to our enemies; and we pray that He may guide us to use it in His ways and His purposes" (qtd. in Boyer 211). Thus the bomb is a weapon we have been given, and the trauma of using it is alleviated by paranoiac defense mechanisms.</p><p>Another reason behind the mythologizing of nuclear technology in the 1940s and 1950s was that ignorance about the new scientific discovery caused people to search for a frame of reference that could make sense of the unrepresentable content of nuclear physics. In an interview in which he discusses the trauma suffered by the victims in Hiroshima, psychoanalyst Robert Jay Lifton observes: "In creating, in recreating experience, we need some prior imagery in order to do that work, in order to carry through that process. And there was precious little prior imagery that could enable people to take in the Hiroshima experience, the event of a weapon apparently destroying an entire city" (135). Lacking frames of reference, American society turned to myth to articulate the meanings of nuclear bombs.</p><p>In the mythologizing of nuclear weapons in the 1940s and 1950s, few literary modes were better equipped or played a more key role than science fiction. As John W. Campbell, Jr., noted in a 1953 essay in which he attempted to "place" this genre, science fiction stands in opposition to history, operating as a mythology that charts "the hopes and dreams and fears (for some dreams are nightmares) of a technically based society" (12). In the same year, Gerald Heard argued that science fiction can guide humans in the Atomic Age in a manner similar to the cohesive social function performed by mythology in former times, that it can "shape our reactions to our destiny" by showing us "how to react, how to adapt, how to endure" (255). Focusing on science-fiction ifims, more recent critics have noted a similar dynamic. In Future Tense, for example, John Brosman argues that 1950s films resorted to "various euphemisms such as giant beasts" to depict the bomb (82), just as in Nuclear Fear Spencer Weart discusses the way tha t such films contributed to the creation of a space-age mythology.</p><p>Other critics, however, have responded to this tendency in a less positive light. Philip Wylie, for example, complains that 1940s and 1950s science-fiction writers were irresponsible in creating "a new and sinister folklore" that obscured the scientific facts about the bomb (235). Richard Hodgens levels this type of criticism especially at science-fiction films, claiming that they associate technology with "The Black Arts" (261). For Frederic Jameson, science fiction attests to the inability of capitalist society to go beyond its own fixed mindset, that the "deepest vocation" of science fiction is "over and over again to demonstrate and dramatize our incapacity to imagine the future" (153).</p><p>According to H. Bruce Franklin, moreover, not only did the various modes of science fiction bring an awareness of the Atomic Age to the attention of a popular audience, but they also created a mythology of nuclear weapons that was then adopted by American policymakers. Thus, in War Stars: The Superweapon and the American Imagination he argues: "For fifty years, from the first atomic explosion in Robert Cromies's 1895 novel The Crack of Doom until 1945, nuclear weapons existed nowhere but in science fiction, and in the imagination of those directly or indirectly influenced by this fiction, including scientists who converted these inventions from fantasy into facts of life" (131<u><strong>). In Franklin's view, <mark>the American myth of "the ultimate peacemaking weapons" that would lead to world peace under American hegemony directly shaped the nuclear policies of the United States</u></strong></mark> (153)</p>
null
Off
null
430,288
1
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,573
The Fear of Terror is an Attempt to Bring the Future To Bear in the Present—This Strategy is Precisely the Logic of the Pre-Emptive Strike and the War on Terror, Repressing the Erotic to Render Humanity’s Only Purpose the Preservation of Itself
Harney and Martin 07
Stefano Harney and Randy Martin, Director of Global Learning & Reader in Strategy at Queen Mary University of London School of Business and Management and Professor of art and Public policy and director of the graduate program in arts politics, Mode of Excess: Bataille, Criminality, and the War On Terror, Theory and Event, 2007 (Project Muse)
If the Cold War contested the future, its apparent heir, the war on terror battles over the present. This is more than the hyper-vigilance of a politics of fear. The terrorist is the quintessential figure of bad risk however effectively it may be deployed. We cannot await it. The only safety lies in bringing its moment into our midst, that is, by pre-emptive strike. Terror's temporality is anti-utopian, it implies the immanence of the future in the present. Terror wars are in this respect derivative wars They succeed in their initial displacements (of toppling regimes) but produce the very thing they claim to fight but that are in actuality their condition of further circulation, namely terror. Terror is an inassimilable excess that occasions intervention without end. thought would also have us refuse the enclosure of our own surplus capacity in so certain a lock down of interest-borne scarcity. There can be no denying oil's requirement to the present economic convention. But the necessity of oil politics as they are presented must be contested if the present mode of excess is to be seen as other than laying us all to waste as an inexorable drive to war to control supply in the face of imminent scarcity. The erotic which animated consumer desire has now been displaced by risk, which inhabits the intensities of circulation. Populations at risk may be treated instrumentally but they are also freed from instrumentality-they exist, not to accomplish further accumulation, but as human assemblages in their own right. The war on terror claims that population makes no difference and touts its capacity to intervene anywhere at anytime. Its excess belies another. The notion that intervention can be anywhere raises the prospect that it could be for anything. The recourse to war that cannot discern between foreign and domestic, that attacks terror, but also crime, drugs, culture, and the like, sketches in negative relief the magnitude of the difference that state and capital now resist.
The terrorist is the quintessential figure of bad risk We cannot await it. The only safety lies in bringing its moment into our midst, that is, by pre-emptive strike. Terror's temporality implies the immanence of the future in the pre Terror wars produce the very thing they claim to fight but that are in actuality their condition of further circulation, namely terror. Terror is an inassimilable excess that occasions intervention without end. The erotic which animated consumer desire has now been displaced by risk, which inhabits the intensities of circulation. Populations at risk may be treated instrumentally but they are also freed from instrumentality-they exist, not to accomplish further accumulation, but as human assemblages in their own right. The war on terror claims that population makes no difference and touts its capacity to intervene anywhere at anytime. Its excess belies another
If the Cold War contested the future, its apparent heir, the war on terror battles over the present. This is more than the hyper-vigilance of a politics of fear. The terrorist is the quintessential figure of bad risk however effectively it may be deployed. We cannot await it. The only safety lies in bringing its moment into our midst, that is, by pre-emptive strike. Terror's temporality is anti-utopian, it implies the immanence of the future in the present. The risk economy, the investment action upon a possible future difference in the present, shares the same sensibility. Foreign and domestic applications of risk management forge a nefarious connection in George W. Bush's 2002 National Security Document. In this proud proclamation of imperial doctrine, pre-emption is bequeathed to one nation and friends (whether old or newly acquired) affirm their allegiance by replicating U.S. anti-inflationary monetary policy. Low and behold this same language turns up in Iraq's strategy for national development. Inflation, when it is not an assault on labor (as low unemployment or high wages) anthropomorphizes the world of goods (supply being chased by demand and puffing itself up accordingly). Just as industrialization forced association upon self-sufficient labor, and consumerism wove a common web of dreams in the marketplace, financialization imposes a generalized condition of mutual indebtedness. Personal finance, like free wage labor, amounts to an enormous aggregation of the capacity to produce financial value while assuming the risks of failure to realize value. Like production and consumption, financialization is also a form of dispossession of one array of life-making circumstances that forces an elaboration of what people must subsequently do and be together. The future itself becomes a factor of production as each possible outcome is shifted into an actionable present. The derivative represents the moment when a small intervention, an arbitrager's momentary opportunity, seizes upon a highly dispersed volatility and leverages it to extensive effect. Unlike the entrepreneur, born of initiative, the arbitrager exists only through the action of others, deriving themselves as a cluster of volatilities. The derivative is the extensive energy within the body of finance. It is also incorporated into the grand strategy for engaging and negating unsupportable risk and excess. Terror wars are in this respect derivative wars. They "deter forward" using small deployments of risk capable special forces to leverage imperial intervention. They succeed in their initial displacements (of toppling regimes) but produce the very thing they claim to fight but that are in actuality their condition of further circulation, namely terror. Terror is an inassimilable excess that occasions intervention without end. Unlike earlier imperialisms that sought to extract, civilize and develop, this logic of occupation quickly becomes indifferent to its prize and impatient with itself. It would be tempting to see in the gap between a general interest in combating terror everywhere, and a particular occupation of two energy states an affirmation of Bataille's equilibration of devastation and profit. Afghanistan's geo-strategic potential for transshipment of oil and gas, Iraq's prized proven oil reserves, Halliburton's corrupt profiteering would seem to affirm the straightforward arithmetic captured by the slogan, "blood for oil." Control of energy consumption would prove the ultimate colonization of Bataille's accursed share. As compelling as the slogan has been to lay bare the motives of imperial excess, Bataille's thought would also have us refuse the enclosure of our own surplus capacity in so certain a lock down of interest-borne scarcity. There can be no denying oil's requirement to the present economic convention. But the necessity of oil politics as they are presented must be contested if the present mode of excess is to be seen as other than laying us all to waste as an inexorable drive to war to control supply in the face of imminent scarcity. While financial protocols have been installed as governing ideas, the occupation of Iraq looks like anything but a design for control. Instead, oil exports have held steady, and risk has been distributed throughout a population that has been cleaved from its national form and from its own productive capacities. Iraq's Public Distribution System, the last remnant of Baathist socialism is to be displaced by small cash handouts to fuel the now rampant speculative economy.ii But to render socialism scarce is to commit an error of measurement and concept. The extensive energy of consumption privileged the erotic as the alter to commodification, and maintained socialism as that portion of the world devoted to a social economy that capital could not absorb. The erotic which animated consumer desire has now been displaced by risk, which inhabits the intensities of circulation. Populations at risk may be treated instrumentally but they are also freed from instrumentality-they exist, not to accomplish further accumulation, but as human assemblages in their own right. The war on terror claims that population makes no difference and touts its capacity to intervene anywhere at anytime. Its excess belies another. The notion that intervention can be anywhere raises the prospect that it could be for anything. The empire of indifference passes intervention from necessity to the realm of discretion, acting upon difference becomes a luxury within reach. Added to this is the discretionary force of something like the derivatives market, a hitherto unfathomable wealth sundered from use that exists only to further itself. The recourse to war that cannot discern between foreign and domestic, that attacks terror, but also crime, drugs, culture, and the like, sketches in negative relief the magnitude of the difference that state and capital now resist. Never mind that they had a hand in proliferating it all. The abundance of difference in our midst, along with excess wealth advertised for all-purposes, presents the immanence of the social as a self-expanding luxury for all. The war on terror is not the only project legible in the transfer of Bataille's mode of excess into the present. Terror gives urgency to the proliferation of financial risk but it also deflects attention from that excess which the state has increasing trouble concealing--its own criminality. If capital morphs under the present mode of excess, so too does its strange bed-fellow, the state-form.
6,572
<h4>The Fear of Terror is an Attempt to Bring the Future To Bear in the Present—This Strategy is Precisely the Logic of the Pre-Emptive Strike and the War on Terror, Repressing the Erotic to Render Humanity’s Only Purpose the Preservation of Itself </h4><p>Stefano <u><strong>Harney and</u></strong> Randy <u><strong>Martin</u></strong>, Director of Global Learning & Reader in Strategy at Queen Mary University of London School of Business and Management and Professor of art and Public policy and director of the graduate program in arts politics, Mode of Excess: Bataille, Criminality, and the War On Terror, Theory and Event, 20<u><strong>07</u></strong> (Project Muse)</p><p><u><strong>If the Cold War contested the future, its apparent heir, the war on terror battles over the present. This is more than the hyper-vigilance of a politics of fear. <mark>The terrorist is the quintessential figure of bad risk</mark> however effectively it may be deployed. <mark>We cannot await it. The only safety lies in bringing its moment into our midst, that is, by pre-emptive strike. Terror's temporality</mark> is anti-utopian, it <mark>implies the immanence of the future in the pre</mark>sent.</u></strong> The risk economy, the investment action upon a possible future difference in the present, shares the same sensibility. Foreign and domestic applications of risk management forge a nefarious connection in George W. Bush's 2002 National Security Document. In this proud proclamation of imperial doctrine, pre-emption is bequeathed to one nation and friends (whether old or newly acquired) affirm their allegiance by replicating U.S. anti-inflationary monetary policy. Low and behold this same language turns up in Iraq's strategy for national development. Inflation, when it is not an assault on labor (as low unemployment or high wages) anthropomorphizes the world of goods (supply being chased by demand and puffing itself up accordingly).</p><p>    </p><p>Just as industrialization forced association upon self-sufficient labor, and consumerism wove a common web of dreams in the marketplace, financialization imposes a generalized condition of mutual indebtedness. Personal finance, like free wage labor, amounts to an enormous aggregation of the capacity to produce financial value while assuming the risks of failure to realize value. Like production and consumption, financialization is also a form of dispossession of one array of life-making circumstances that forces an elaboration of what people must subsequently do and be together. The future itself becomes a factor of production as each possible outcome is shifted into an actionable present. The derivative represents the moment when a small intervention, an arbitrager's momentary opportunity, seizes upon a highly dispersed volatility and leverages it to extensive effect. Unlike the entrepreneur, born of initiative, the arbitrager exists only through the action of others, deriving themselves as a cluster of volatilities. The derivative is the extensive energy within the body of finance. It is also incorporated into the grand strategy for engaging and negating unsupportable risk and excess. <u><strong><mark>Terror wars</mark> are in this respect derivative wars</u></strong>. They "deter forward" using small deployments of risk capable special forces to leverage imperial intervention. <u><strong>They succeed in their initial displacements (of toppling regimes) but <mark>produce the very thing they claim to fight but that are in actuality their condition of further circulation, namely terror. Terror is an inassimilable excess that occasions intervention without end.</u></strong></mark> Unlike earlier imperialisms that sought to extract, civilize and develop, this logic of occupation quickly becomes indifferent to its prize and impatient with itself.</p><p>    </p><p>It would be tempting to see in the gap between a general interest in combating terror everywhere, and a particular occupation of two energy states an affirmation of Bataille's equilibration of devastation and profit. Afghanistan's geo-strategic potential for transshipment of oil and gas, Iraq's prized proven oil reserves, Halliburton's corrupt profiteering would seem to affirm the straightforward arithmetic captured by the slogan, "blood for oil." Control of energy consumption would prove the ultimate colonization of Bataille's accursed share. As compelling as the slogan has been to lay bare the motives of imperial excess, Bataille's<u><strong> thought would also have us refuse the enclosure of our own surplus capacity in so certain a lock down of interest-borne scarcity. There can be no denying oil's requirement to the present economic convention. But the necessity of oil politics as they are presented must be contested if the present mode of excess is to be seen as other than laying us all to waste as an inexorable drive to war to control supply in the face of imminent scarcity.</p><p></u></strong>While financial protocols have been installed as governing ideas, the occupation of Iraq looks like anything but a design for control. Instead, oil exports have held steady, and risk has been distributed throughout a population that has been cleaved from its national form and from its own productive capacities. Iraq's Public Distribution System, the last remnant of Baathist socialism is to be displaced by small cash handouts to fuel the now rampant speculative economy.ii But to render socialism scarce is to commit an error of measurement and concept. The extensive energy of consumption privileged the erotic as the alter to commodification, and maintained socialism as that portion of the world devoted to a social economy that capital could not absorb. <u><strong><mark>The erotic which animated consumer desire has now been displaced by risk, which inhabits the intensities of circulation. Populations at risk may be treated instrumentally but they are also freed from instrumentality-they exist, not to accomplish further accumulation, but as human assemblages in their own right.</p><p>The war on terror claims that population makes no difference and touts its capacity to intervene anywhere at anytime. Its excess belies another</mark>. The notion that intervention can be anywhere raises the prospect that it could be for anything.</u></strong> The empire of indifference passes intervention from necessity to the realm of discretion, acting upon difference becomes a luxury within reach. Added to this is the discretionary force of something like the derivatives market, a hitherto unfathomable wealth sundered from use that exists only to further itself. <u><strong>The recourse to war that cannot discern between foreign and domestic, that attacks terror, but also crime, drugs, culture, and the like, sketches in negative relief the magnitude of the difference that state and capital now resist.</u></strong> Never mind that they had a hand in proliferating it all. The abundance of difference in our midst, along with excess wealth advertised for all-purposes, presents the immanence of the social as a self-expanding luxury for all. The war on terror is not the only project legible in the transfer of Bataille's mode of excess into the present. Terror gives urgency to the proliferation of financial risk but it also deflects attention from that excess which the state has increasing trouble concealing--its own criminality. If capital morphs under the present mode of excess, so too does its strange bed-fellow, the state-form.</p>
null
Off
null
430,289
1
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,574
This Refusal to Acknowledge Our Repression of Transgressive use of Excess is the Basis of Empirical Violence in the Arms Race and War. The Attempt To Conceive of Impacts in Relation to Survival Makes the World Circular, We Survive Merely In Order to Ensure Our Survival—We Instead Must Evaluate Survival as the Merely Incidental Consequence of Expenditure to Survive or Care About Survival in the First Place
Stoekl, 07
Alan Stoekl, professor of French and comparative literature at Penn State University, Bataille’s Peak: Energy, Religion and Postsustainability, 2007 (Pg 44 – 46)
The modern economy does not recognize excess Utility ends up impractical: only so much output can be reabsorbed into the ever-more-efficient productive process. excess will have to be burned off. This can happen either peacefully or violently through war in the end, the world itself will be fully developed, with no place for the excess to go. The bad alternative will result in a depopulated earth. War is an adjunct to economic expansion; it is a practical use of excessive forces. destructiveness is masked by the appearance of an ultimate utility: in this case the spread of the American economy The “end” of humankind is the destruction of this surplus. The meaning of the limit and its affirmation is inseparable from the senselessness of its transgression in expenditure Once we recognize that everything cannot be saved the ultimate end of our existence becomes the disposal of excess Survival and reproduction alone are not the ultimate ends of human existence. By characterizing survival as a means not an end expenditure becomes a real end This does not preclude a kind of ethical aftereffect of Bataille’s expenditure: survival for this reason can be read as the fundamentally unintentional consequence of expenditure rather than its purpose. Seeing a nuclear buildup as the wrong kind of expenditure can lead to a rethinking of the role of expenditure in the modern world and hence survival
only so much output can be reabsorbed into the productive process excess will have to be burned off. This can peacefully or through war in the end, the world itself will be fully developed, with no place for the excess to go. The bad alternative a depopulated earth War is a practical use of excessive forces , destructiveness is masked by the appearance of an ultimate utility Once we recognize that everything cannot be saved the ultimate end becomes the disposal of excess Survival and reproduction are not the ultimate ends of existence y characterizing survival as a means not an end expenditure becomes a real end survival can be read a unintentional consequence of expenditure rather than its purpose.
Bataille does, then, implicitly face the question of carrying capacity. Perhaps the ultimate example of this is nuclear war. The modern economy, according to Bataille, does not recognize the possibility of excess and therefore limits; the Protestant, and then the Marxist, ideal is to reinvest all excess back into the productive process, always augmenting output in this way. “Utility” in this model ends up being perfectly impractical: only so much output can be reabsorbed into the ever-more-efficient productive process. As in the case with Tibet, ultimately the excess will have to be burned off. This can happen either peacefully, through various postcapitalist mechanisms that Bataille recommends, such as the Marshall Plan, which will shift growth to other parts of the world, or violently and apocalyptically through the ultimate in war: nuclear holocaust. One can see that, in the end, the world itself will be en vase clos, fully developed, with no place for the excess to go. The bad alternative—nuclear holocaust—will result in the ultimate reduction in carrying capacity: a burned-out, depopulated earth. Humanity is, at the same time, through industry, which uses energy for the development of the forces of production, both a multiple opening of the possibilities of growth, and the infinite faculty for burnoff in pure loss (facilite infinie de consumation en pure perte]. (OC. 7: 170; AS, 181) Modern war is first of all a renunciation: one produces and amasses wealth in order to overcome a foe. War is an adjunct to economic expansion; it is a practical use of excessive forces. And this perhaps is the ultimate danger of the present-day (1949) buildup of nuclear arms: armament, seemingly a practical way of defending one’s own country or spreading one’s own values, in other words, of growing, ultimately leads to the risk of a “pure destruction” of excess—and even of carrying capacity In the case of warfare, destructiveness is masked, made unrecognizable, by the appearance of an ultimate utility: in this case the spread of the American economy and the American way of life around the globe. Paradoxically, there is a kind of self-consciousness concerning excess, in the “naïve” society—which recognizes expenditure for what it is (in the form of unproductive glory in primitive warfare)— and a thorough ignorance of it in the modem one, which would always attempt to put waste to work (“useful” armaments) even at the cost of wholesale destruction. Bataille, then, like Le Blanc, can be characterized as a thinker of society who situates his theory in the context of ecological limits. From Bataille’s perspective, however, there is always too much rather than too little, given the existence of ecological (“natural”) and social (“cultural”) limits. The “end” of humankind, its ultimate goal, is thus the destruction of this surplus. While Le Blanc stresses war and sacrifice as a means of obtaining or maintaining what is essential to bare human (personal, social) survival, Bataille emphasizes the maintenance of limits and survival as mere preconditions for engaging in the glorious destruction of excess. The meaning of the limit and its affirmation is inseparable from the senselessness of its transgression in expenditure (la dépense). By seeing warfare as a mere (group) survival mechanism, Le Blanc makes the same mistake as that made by the supporters of a nuclear buildup; he, like they, sees warfare as practical, serving a purpose, and not as the sheer burn-off it really is. If, however, our most fundamental gesture is the destruction of a surplus, the production of that surplus must be seen as subsidiary. Once we recognize that everything cannot be saved and reinvested, the ultimate end (and most crucial problem) of our existence becomes the disposal of excess wealth (concentrated, nonusable energy). All other activity leads to something else, is a means to some other end; the only end that leads nowhere is the act of destruction by which we may—or may not—assure our (personal) survival (there is nothing to guarantee that radical destruction—consumation—does not turn on its author). We work in order to spend. We strive to produce sacred (charged) things, not practical things. Survival and reproduction alone are not the ultimate ends of human existence. We could characterize Bataille for this reason as a thinker of ecology who nevertheless emphasizes the primacy of an ecstatic social act (destruct ion). By characterizing survival as a means not an end (the most fundamental idea in “general economy”), expenditure for Bataille becomes a limitless, insubordinate act—a real end (that which does not lead outside itself). I follow Bataille in this primacy of the delirium of expenditure over the simple exigency of personal or even social survival (Le Blanc). This does not preclude, however, a kind of ethical aftereffect of Bataille’s expenditure: survival for this reason can be read as the fundamentally unintentional consequence of expenditure rather than its purpose. Seeing a nuclear buildup as the wrong kind of expenditure—because it is seen as a means not an end—can lead, in Bataille’s view, to a rethinking of the role of expenditure in the modern world and hence, perhaps, the world’s (but not modernity’s) survival.
5,295
<h4>This Refusal to Acknowledge Our Repression of Transgressive use of Excess is the Basis of Empirical Violence in the Arms Race and War. The Attempt To Conceive of Impacts in Relation to Survival Makes the World Circular, We Survive Merely In Order to Ensure Our Survival—We Instead Must Evaluate Survival as the Merely Incidental Consequence of Expenditure to Survive or Care About Survival in the First Place</h4><p>Alan <u><strong>Stoekl,</u></strong> professor of French and comparative literature at Penn State University, Bataille’s Peak: Energy, Religion and Postsustainability, 20<u><strong>07</u></strong> (Pg 44 – 46)</p><p>Bataille does, then, implicitly face the question of carrying capacity. Perhaps the ultimate example of this is nuclear war. <u>The modern economy</u>, according to Bataille, <u>does not recognize</u> the possibility of <u>excess</u> and therefore limits; the Protestant, and then the Marxist, ideal is to reinvest all excess back into the productive process, always augmenting output in this way. “<u>Utility</u>” in this model <u>ends up</u> being perfectly <u>impractical: <mark>only so much output can be reabsorbed into the</mark> ever-more-efficient <mark>productive process</mark>.</u> As in the case with Tibet, ultimately the <u><mark>excess will have to be burned off. This can</mark> happen either <mark>peacefully</u></mark>, through various postcapitalist mechanisms that Bataille recommends, such as the Marshall Plan, which will shift growth to other parts of the world, <u><mark>or</mark> violently</u> and apocalyptically <u><mark>through</u></mark> the ultimate in <u><mark>war</u></mark>: nuclear holocaust. One can see that, <u><mark>in the end, the world itself will be</u></mark> en vase clos, <u><mark>fully</u> <u>developed, with no place for the excess to go. The bad alternative</u></mark>—nuclear holocaust—<u>will result in</u> the ultimate reduction in carrying capacity: <u><mark>a</u></mark> burned-out, <u><mark>depopulated earth</mark>.</u> Humanity is, at the same time, through industry, which uses energy for the development of the forces of production, both a multiple opening of the possibilities of growth, and the infinite faculty for burnoff in pure loss (facilite infinie de consumation en pure perte]. (OC. 7: 170; AS, 181) Modern war is first of all a renunciation: one produces and amasses wealth in order to overcome a foe. <u><mark>War is</mark> an adjunct to economic expansion; it is <mark>a practical use of excessive forces</mark>.</u> And this perhaps is the ultimate danger of the present-day (1949) buildup of nuclear arms: armament, seemingly a practical way of defending one’s own country or spreading one’s own values, in other words, of growing, ultimately leads to the risk of a “pure destruction” of excess—and even of carrying capacity In the case of warfare<mark>, <u>destructiveness is masked</u></mark>, made unrecognizable, <u><mark>by the appearance of an ultimate utility</mark>: in this case the spread of the American economy</u> and the American way of life around the globe. Paradoxically, there is a kind of self-consciousness concerning excess, in the “naïve” society—which recognizes expenditure for what it is (in the form of unproductive glory in primitive warfare)— and a thorough ignorance of it in the modem one, which would always attempt to put waste to work (“useful” armaments) even at the cost of wholesale destruction. Bataille, then, like Le Blanc, can be characterized as a thinker of society who situates his theory in the context of ecological limits. From Bataille’s perspective, however, there is always too much rather than too little, given the existence of ecological (“natural”) and social (“cultural”) limits. <u>The “end” of humankind</u>, its ultimate goal, <u>is</u> thus <u>the destruction of this surplus.</u> While Le Blanc stresses war and sacrifice as a means of obtaining or maintaining what is essential to bare human (personal, social) survival, Bataille emphasizes the maintenance of limits and survival as mere preconditions for engaging in the glorious destruction of excess. <u>The meaning of the limit and its affirmation is inseparable from the senselessness of its transgression in expenditure</u> (la dépense). By seeing warfare as a mere (group) survival mechanism, Le Blanc makes the same mistake as that made by the supporters of a nuclear buildup; he, like they, sees warfare as practical, serving a purpose, and not as the sheer burn-off it really is. If, however, our most fundamental gesture is the destruction of a surplus, the production of that surplus must be seen as subsidiary. <u><mark>Once we recognize that everything cannot be saved</u></mark> and reinvested, <u><mark>the ultimate end</u></mark> (and most crucial problem) <u>of our existence <mark>becomes the disposal of excess</u></mark> wealth (concentrated, nonusable energy). All other activity leads to something else, is a means to some other end; the only end that leads nowhere is the act of destruction by which we may—or may not—assure our (personal) survival (there is nothing to guarantee that radical destruction—consumation—does not turn on its author). We work in order to spend. We strive to produce sacred (charged) things, not practical things. <u><mark>Survival and reproduction</mark> alone <mark>are not the ultimate ends of</mark> human <mark>existence</mark>.</u> We could characterize Bataille for this reason as a thinker of ecology who nevertheless emphasizes the primacy of an ecstatic social act (destruct ion). <u>B<mark>y characterizing survival as a means not an end</u></mark> (the most fundamental idea in “general economy”), <u><mark>expenditure</u></mark> for Bataille <u><mark>becomes</u></mark> a limitless, insubordinate act—<u><mark>a real end</u></mark> (that which does not lead outside itself). I follow Bataille in this primacy of the delirium of expenditure over the simple exigency of personal or even social survival (Le Blanc). <u>This does not preclude</u>, however, <u>a kind of ethical aftereffect of Bataille’s expenditure: <mark>survival</mark> for this reason <mark>can be read a</mark>s the fundamentally <mark>unintentional consequence of expenditure rather than its purpose.</mark> Seeing a nuclear buildup as the wrong kind of expenditure</u>—because it is seen as a means not an end—<u>can lead</u>, in Bataille’s view, <u>to a rethinking of the role of expenditure in the modern world and hence</u>, perhaps, the world’s (but not modernity’s) <u>survival</u>.</p>
null
Off
null
179,985
8
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,575
Attempts to adapt to climate change within a utilitarian framework inevitability fail – we must break free from the logic utility to have any chance at all
Yusoff 09
Yusoff 09 (Kathryn Yusoff, Professor of Geography at the University of Exeter, “Excess, catastrophe, and climate change,” October, 2009, Environment and Planning D: Society and Space advance online publication, http://www.envplan.com/epd/fulltext/dforth/d7407.pdf)
The wager of knowledge opens two paths.'' One path, Bataille suggests, is to carry on with the provisional nature of data to strengthen knowledge into degrees of certainty and predictability. This is to cleave apart knowledge from nonknowledge or climate uncertainties and respond only to what we think we know is certain. This as evidenced by the computation of polar sea ice retreat, is to ignore the dimensions of knowledge that threaten the capacity of knowledge to have mastery over the planet. nonknowledge exceeds the capacity of GCMs' the cost is that we continue to regulate and respond to this knowledge in ways that narrowly account for the circuit of cosmic energy, such as the recirculation of carbon credits. To be opened to the abyss in Bataillean terms is to risk ourselves in light of this knowledge, to be radically open to the implications of it. To envision rapidly retreating ice streams is to be attentive to their efficacy in the world, the poetry and excess of their motion as experience that will have to be borne by others and is transformative in ways that contemporary experience in the Arctic attests to. With the loss of ice comes the loss of intimacy with ways of knowing in the Arctic. The magnitude of the climate change challenge is such a response of a higher order is needed' What is required is an excessive response that breaks with the vicious circuit of accounting in the Arctic, where sea ice loss and its future disappearance feed into the development of energy production opportunities and further the circulation of carbon credits. We need on the one hand to go beyond the narrow limits within which we ordinarily remain, and on the other hand somehow bring our going-beyond back within our limits'' This means that more than ways of accounting, limiting, and conserving, what GCM models give us is a form of nonknowledge, the futurity of climate change as a site of destruction that has many uncertainties that cannot be assimilated in the current narrow limits of modelling. when the theme everywhere is that we must change, we cannot do so without a radical new thinking that does not repeat the partial responses of the political order and the moving, urgent responses of the spiritual order. More than anything this excessive dimension of the informational models of climate change prediction offers us a vision of loss. This vital strategy moves us away from the utilitarian models of accounting for loss in billions of dollars and contracts for CO2 which are produced through and maintained by forms of digitalised globalism and perhaps into intimate experiments with another energy formösolar power(15)öthat is, for Bataille, the only limit of the biosphere.
One path is to carry on with the nature of data to strengthen knowledge into degrees of certainty This i to cleave apart knowledge from nonknowle and respond only to what we think we know is certain. This is to ignore the dimensions of knowledge that threaten the capacity of knowledge to have mastery over the planet nonknowledge exceeds the capacity of GCMs' the cost is that we continue to regulate and respond to this knowledge in ways that narrowly account for the circuit of cosmic energy To be opened to the abyss is to be radically open to the implications of it. To envision rapidly retreating ice streams is to be attentive to their efficacy in the world, the poetry and excess of their motion as experience that will have to be borne by others and is transformative in ways that contemporary experience in the Arctic attests to. What is required is an excessive response that breaks with the vicious circuit of accounting in the Arctic , the futurity of climate change as a site of destruction that has many uncertainties that cannot be assimilated in the current narrow limits of modelling. when the theme everywhere is that we must change, we cannot do so without a radical new thinking that does not repeat the partial responses of the political order and the moving, urgent responses of the spiritual order This vital strategy moves us away from the utilitarian models of accounting for loss in billions of dollars and perhaps into intimate experiments with another energy
``Knowledge is the agreement of the organism and the environment from which it emerges. Without knowledge, without the identity of the organism, and without this agreement, life could not be imagined. What therefore is the organism in the world, if not the unconsidered flight of a possible into the heart of the impossible that surrounds it? Developing this idea, knowledge strives to restore the impossible (the unforeseeable) to the possible (the foreseeable). Through knowledge, this hazardous flight is changed into a wise calculation: calculation is itself only possible by giving its possibility a fundamental value. The wager of knowledge opens two paths.'' Bataille (2001, pages 221 ^ 222) One path, Bataille suggests, is to carry on with the provisional nature of data to strengthen knowledge into degrees of certainty and predictability. This is, I have argued, to cleave apart knowledge from nonknowledge or climate uncertainties and respond only to what we think we know is certain. This route, as evidenced by the computation of polar sea ice retreat, is to ignore the dimensions of knowledge that threaten the capacity of knowledge to have mastery over the planet. There is a cost to this splitting of the ambiguities of knowledge into a restricted economy. At a practical level, the cost is that this nonknowledge exceeds the capacity of GCMs' limited registers and renders them useless. At a political level, the cost is that we continue to regulate and respond to this knowledge in ways that narrowly account for the circuit of cosmic energy, such as the recirculation of carbon credits. In this knowledge, ``nothing is tragic, terrifying or sacred...nothing in this region is poetic'' (Bataille, 2001, page 222, emphasis in original). The other side of the wager is to respond to how ``the movement of poetry departs from the known and leads to the unknown'' (Bataille, 1970b, page 20) and how ``poetic language once again opens me to the abyss'' (2001, page 222). To be opened to the abyss in Bataillean terms is to risk ourselves in light of this knowledge, to be radically open to the implications of it. To envision rapidly retreating ice streams is to be attentive to their efficacy in the world, the poetry and excess of their motion as experience that will have to be borne by others and is transformative in ways that contemporary experience in the Arctic attests to. With the loss of ice comes the loss of intimacy with ways of knowing in the Arctic. It is for circumpolar peoples a loss of traditional knowledge of their environment. For Aqqaluk Lynge, President of the Inuit Circumpolar Council, Greenland, ``The magnitude of the climate change challenge is such a response of a higher order is needed'' (2008, page 102). What is required is an excessive response that breaks with the vicious circuit of accounting in the Arctic, where sea ice loss and its future disappearance feed into the development of energy production opportunities and further the circulation of carbon credits. If we take Char's assertion that ``we are closer to the catastrophe than the alarm itself'' to mean that our relationship to the disaster is presently more intimate than our power to represent itöfifty-year climate lags, the lack of computing power that impedes complex GCMs, unknown teleconnections and feedbacks, insufficient res- ponse to our knowledgeöwe might think about how to recuperate some excess from the disaster itself to compose our ``well-being of misfortune'' (Bataille, 1994, page 132). Both Bataille and Blanchot sought to write into this experience to somehow bring back the disaster into a space of vital thought and ethical possibility. And, if we acknowl- edge that the disaster of climate change will not be a single event, but a multiple field of destructions that like the Burkean sublime can be found in the everyday of our wasting world, the call to bring back something of the energy burst of the disaster seems urgent.(14) Bataille says: ``We need on the one hand to go beyond the narrow limits within which we ordinarily remain, and on the other hand somehow bring our going-beyond back within our limits'' (1991, page 69). The way to `bring back' for Bataille is to acknowledge the ambiguities of knowledge that are often excluded and the intimacy of knowledge as a form of experience. This means that more than ways of accounting, limiting, and conserving, what GCM models give us is a form of nonknowledge, the futurity of climate change as a site of destruction that has many uncertainties that cannot be assimilated in the current narrow limits of modelling. This intimate space of the imagination is a vision of the world that breaks through the narrow limits of data to scream forth that we must be changed by this knowledge. This is the cost of knowledge, that, as Blanchot warns, means we cannot go ``Let us change, let us change, and remain the same'' (1997, page 102, emphasis in original). He suggests that, when the theme everywhere is that we must change, we cannot do so without a radical new thinking that does not repeat the partial responses of the political order and the moving, urgent responses of the spiritual order. More than anything this excessive dimension of the informational models of climate change prediction offers us a vision of loss. For Bataille and Char the consciousness of an expanded or general economy is the ``vital quality which urges struggle'' (Bataille, 1994, page 132). This vital quality is born of an exuberance that is not quantifiable and is matched only by the generosity of the sun. This vital strategy moves us away from the utilitarian models of accounting for loss in billions of dollars and contracts for CO2 which are produced through and maintained by forms of digitalised globalism and perhaps into intimate experiments with another energy formösolar power(15)öthat is, for Bataille, the only limit of the biosphere.
5,926
<h4>Attempts to adapt to climate change within a utilitarian framework inevitability fail – we must break free from the logic utility to have any chance at all </h4><p><strong>Yusoff 09</strong> (Kathryn Yusoff, Professor of Geography at the University of Exeter, “Excess, catastrophe, and climate change,” October, 2009, Environment and Planning D: Society and Space advance online publication, http://www.envplan.com/epd/fulltext/dforth/d7407.pdf)</p><p>``Knowledge is the agreement of the organism and the environment from which it emerges. Without knowledge, without the identity of the organism, and without this agreement, life could not be imagined. What therefore is the organism in the world, if not the unconsidered flight of a possible into the heart of the impossible that surrounds it? Developing this idea, knowledge strives to restore the impossible (the unforeseeable) to the possible (the foreseeable). Through knowledge, this hazardous flight is changed into a wise calculation: calculation is itself only possible by giving its possibility a fundamental value. <u>The wager of knowledge opens two paths.''</u> Bataille (2001, pages 221 ^ 222) <u><mark>One path</mark>, Bataille suggests, <mark>is to carry</mark> <mark>on with the</mark> provisional <mark>nature of data to strengthen knowledge into degrees of certainty</mark> and predictability. <mark>This i</mark>s</u>, I have argued, <u><mark>to cleave apart knowledge from nonknowle</mark>dge or climate uncertainties <mark>and respond only to what we think we know is certain. This</u></mark> route, <u>as evidenced by the computation of polar sea ice retreat, <mark>is to ignore the dimensions of knowledge that threaten the capacity of knowledge to have mastery over the planet</mark>. </u>There is a cost to this splitting of the ambiguities of knowledge into a restricted economy. At a practical level, the cost is that this <u><mark>nonknowledge exceeds the capacity of GCMs'</u></mark> limited registers and renders them useless. At a political level, <u><mark>the cost is that we continue to regulate and respond to this knowledge in ways that narrowly account for the circuit of cosmic energy</mark>, such as the recirculation of carbon credits.</u> In this knowledge, ``nothing is tragic, terrifying or sacred...nothing in this region is poetic'' (Bataille, 2001, page 222, emphasis in original). The other side of the wager is to respond to how ``the movement of poetry departs from the known and leads to the unknown'' (Bataille, 1970b, page 20) and how ``poetic language once again opens me to the abyss'' (2001, page 222). <u><mark>To be opened to the abyss</mark> in Bataillean terms <mark>is</mark> to risk ourselves in light of this knowledge, <mark>to be radically open to the implications of it. To envision rapidly retreating ice streams is to be attentive to their efficacy in the world, the poetry and excess of their motion as experience that will have to be borne by others and is transformative in ways that contemporary experience in the Arctic attests to.</mark> With the loss of ice comes the loss of intimacy with ways of knowing in the Arctic.</u> It is for circumpolar peoples a loss of traditional knowledge of their environment. For Aqqaluk Lynge, President of the Inuit Circumpolar Council, Greenland, ``<u>The magnitude of the climate change challenge is such a response of a higher order is needed'</u>' (2008, page 102). <u><mark>What is required is an excessive response that breaks with the vicious circuit of accounting in the Arctic</mark>, where sea ice loss and its future disappearance feed into the development of energy production opportunities and further the circulation of carbon credits.</u> If we take Char's assertion that ``we are closer to the catastrophe than the alarm itself'' to mean that our relationship to the disaster is presently more intimate than our power to represent itöfifty-year climate lags, the lack of computing power that impedes complex GCMs, unknown teleconnections and feedbacks, insufficient res- ponse to our knowledgeöwe might think about how to recuperate some excess from the disaster itself to compose our ``well-being of misfortune'' (Bataille, 1994, page 132). Both Bataille and Blanchot sought to write into this experience to somehow bring back the disaster into a space of vital thought and ethical possibility. And, if we acknowl- edge that the disaster of climate change will not be a single event, but a multiple field of destructions that like the Burkean sublime can be found in the everyday of our wasting world, the call to bring back something of the energy burst of the disaster seems urgent.(14) Bataille says: ``<u>We need on the one hand to go beyond the narrow limits within which we ordinarily remain, and on the other hand somehow bring our going-beyond back within our limits''</u> (1991, page 69). The way to `bring back' for Bataille is to acknowledge the ambiguities of knowledge that are often excluded and the intimacy of knowledge as a form of experience. <u>This means that more than ways of accounting, limiting, and conserving, what GCM models give us is a form of nonknowledge<mark>, the futurity of climate change as a site of destruction that has many uncertainties that cannot be assimilated in the current narrow limits of modelling.</u></mark> This intimate space of the imagination is a vision of the world that breaks through the narrow limits of data to scream forth that we must be changed by this knowledge. This is the cost of knowledge, that, as Blanchot warns, means we cannot go ``Let us change, let us change, and remain the same'' (1997, page 102, emphasis in original). He suggests that, <u><mark>when the theme everywhere is that we must change, we cannot do so without a radical new thinking that does not repeat the partial responses of the political order and the moving, urgent responses of the spiritual order</mark>.</u> <u>More than anything this excessive dimension of the informational models of climate change prediction offers us a vision of loss.</u> For Bataille and Char the consciousness of an expanded or general economy is the ``vital quality which urges struggle'' (Bataille, 1994, page 132). This vital quality is born of an exuberance that is not quantifiable and is matched only by the generosity of the sun. <u><mark>This vital strategy moves us away from the utilitarian models of accounting for loss in billions of dollars</mark> and contracts for CO2 which are produced through and maintained by forms of digitalised globalism <mark>and perhaps into intimate experiments with another energy</mark> formösolar power(15)öthat is, for Bataille, the only limit of the biosphere.</u> </p>
null
Off
null
430,290
1
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,576
Therefore, we propose the following alternative: the ballot should be an endorsement of the methodology of transgression. Only this prevents the catastrophic expenditure of energy and allows for true enjoyment of life.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Therefore, we propose the following alternative: the ballot should be an endorsement of the methodology of transgression. Only this prevents the catastrophic expenditure of energy and allows for true enjoyment of life.</h4>
null
Off
null
430,287
1
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,577
The opposition to transgression is precisely the model of the taboo–in refusing to acknowledge this moment of transgression we refuse to engage in the embrace of excess–We must use and affirm transgression as an example of our discontinuity as subjects–that is to say, we recognize that we cannot be linked together through any unified discourse or structure and as such we must be exposed to violence to have any experience of the world whatsoever
Igrek 04 )
Apple Zefelius Igrek, Vanderbilt University, Violence and Heterogeneity: A Response to Habermas’ “Between Eroticism and General Economics: Georges Bataille” Janus Head, 2004 (http://www.janushead.org/7-2/Igrek.pdf)
Discontinuity is Bataille’s term for a self-enclosed, self-protecting individual. It is a vital concept because if there were no discontinuous beings, ardently attached to the perpetuation of their singular existence, neither would there be violence or transgression. In a sense, then, the affirmation of a transgressive erotics, what Bataille also calls a return to continuity, is likewise an affirmation of the discontinuity without which eroticism and communication are unimaginable. the creation and conservation of interiority is inseparable from the movement of repulsion that was discussed in the previous section. Taboos are the socializing articulations of passionate loathing which cannot be disjoined from the individual’s attempt to ward off danger, violence, or anything reminiscent of life out of control. Taboos therefore reinforce a sense of interiority on the part of the subject who removes herself, as best as she can, from the scene of violence. In other words, the discontinuous being who lives in accordance with social regulation as determined by the banishment of violence no longer sees itself as participating in the excess of life destroying itself in dazzling, tumultuous upheavals life is never totally forgotten even by those who live according to the strictest rules. The crucial point here, however, is that discontinuity, translated as interiority in the realm of things, takes on the meaning of disguising its innermost truth qua violence. Each being is distinct from all others . . . . Between one being and another, there is a gulf, a discontinuity. This gulf exists, for instance, between you, listening to me, and me, speaking to you. We are attempting to communicate, but no communication between us can abolish our fundamental difference. the infinite abyss, when taken seriously, reminds us that individuated existence is absolutely incomprehensible, unsynthesizable. I say this because if it weren’t true then the discontinuous being could be subsumed by a system of thought which connected this being, in a manner befitting a logical organization of social reality, to all those other beings ostensibly divided by an infinite gulf Insofar as a particular subject can be assimilated to an all-encompassing logic of reality, it follows that the individual is self-identical, unchanging, and wholly complete.30 An unsynthesizable being can therefore be understood as devoted to its finite, particular ends only on the condition that its self-preservation is seen as a genuine effort. Such an effort assumes that the discontinuous self is vulnerable to all sorts of accidents, diseases, insecurities, predators, injuries, reprisals and the very loss of self which is so urgently defended. If the closure of discontinuity weren’t vulnerable to the dangers of the outside, as well as the inside, no effort would be required to secure its borders.
Discontinuity is the creation and conservation of interiority is inseparable from the movement of repulsion Taboos are articulations of passionate loathing which ward off violence the discontinuous being who lives in accordance with social regulation as determined by the banishment of violence no longer sees itself as participating in the excess of life life is never totally forgotten even by those who live according to the strictest rules. discontinuity takes on the meaning of disguising its innermost truth qua violence. if it weren’t true then the discontinuous being could be subsumed by a system of thought which connected this being, in a manner befitting a logical organization of social reality, to all those other beings ostensibly divided by an infinite gulf a particular subject can be assimilated to an all-encompassing logic of reality, it follows that the individual is self-identical, unchanging, and wholly complet Such an effort assumes that the discontinuous self is vulnerable to all sorts of accidents, diseases, insecurities
Discontinuity is Bataille’s term for a self-enclosed, self-protecting individual. It is a vital concept because if there were no discontinuous beings, ardently attached to the perpetuation of their singular existence, neither would there be violence or transgression. In a sense, then, the affirmation of a transgressive erotics, what Bataille also calls a return to continuity, is likewise an affirmation of the discontinuity without which eroticism and communication are unimaginable. To cast some light on these strange remarks it is paramount to first explain what is meant here by discontinuity. One way of ascertaining its meaning for Bataille is by looking at the interiority of individual existence, in particular the existence of a being who is aware of that existence objectively.27 First, it can be said that the creation and conservation of interiority is inseparable from the movement of repulsion that was discussed in the previous section. Taboos are the socializing articulations of passionate loathing which cannot be disjoined from the individual’s attempt to ward off danger, violence, or anything reminiscent of life out of control. Taboos therefore reinforce a sense of interiority on the part of the subject who removes herself, as best as she can, from the scene of violence. What is meant by this interiority is the subject’s perception that intimate life has been excluded from the movements and operations of a life subordinated to the authority of prohibition.28 In other words, the discontinuous being who lives in accordance with social regulation as determined by the banishment of violence no longer sees itself as participating in the excess of life destroying itself in dazzling, tumultuous upheavals. Banishment is unevenly realized, and the fact of the matter is that life is never totally forgotten even by those who live according to the strictest rules. The crucial point here, however, is that discontinuity, translated as interiority in the realm of things, takes on the meaning of disguising its innermost truth qua violence. Let’s take a look at how Bataille himself illustrates discontinuity: “Each being is distinct from all others . . . . Between one being and another, there is a gulf, a discontinuity. This gulf exists, for instance, between you, listening to me, and me, speaking to you. We are attempting to communicate, but no communication between us can abolish our fundamental difference. If you die, it is not my death. You and I are discontinuous beings.”29 What is the importance of gesturing toward an infinite gulf separating all individual beings? What does this fundamental difference tell us about self-protecting, self-interested creatures? It seems to me that the infinite abyss, when taken seriously, reminds us that individuated existence is absolutely incomprehensible, unsynthesizable. I say this because if it weren’t true then the discontinuous being could be subsumed by a system of thought which connected this being, in a manner befitting a logical organization of social reality, to all those other beings ostensibly divided by an infinite gulf. But in that case the gulf would be measurable and distinct beings would lose their absolute particularity to a system of thought which beholds in particularity the birth of sameness. Insofar as a particular subject can be assimilated to an all-encompassing logic of reality, it follows that the individual is self-identical, unchanging, and wholly complete.30 An unsynthesizable being can therefore be understood as devoted to its finite, particular ends only on the condition that its self-preservation is seen as a genuine effort. Such an effort assumes that the discontinuous self is vulnerable to all sorts of accidents, diseases, insecurities, predators, injuries, reprisals and the very loss of self which is so urgently defended. If the closure of discontinuity weren’t vulnerable to the dangers of the outside, as well as the inside, no effort would be required to secure its borders.
4,012
<h4>The opposition to transgression is precisely the model of the taboo–in refusing to acknowledge this moment of transgression we refuse to engage in the embrace of excess–We must use and affirm transgression as an example of our discontinuity as subjects–that is to say, we recognize that we cannot be linked together through any unified discourse or structure and as such we must be exposed to violence to have any experience of the world whatsoever</h4><p>Apple Zefelius <u><strong>Igrek</u></strong>, Vanderbilt University, Violence and Heterogeneity: A Response to Habermas’ “Between Eroticism and General Economics: Georges Bataille” Janus Head, 20<u><strong>04</u></strong> (http://www.janushead.org/7-2/Igrek.pdf<u><strong>)</p><p></strong><mark>Discontinuity is </mark>Bataille’s term for a self-enclosed, self-protecting individual. It is a vital concept because if there were no discontinuous beings, ardently attached to the perpetuation of their singular existence, neither would there be violence or transgression. In a sense, then, the affirmation of a transgressive erotics, what Bataille also calls a return to continuity, is likewise an affirmation of the discontinuity without which eroticism and communication are unimaginable. </u>To cast some light on these strange remarks it is paramount to first explain what is meant here by discontinuity. One way of ascertaining its meaning for Bataille is by looking at the interiority of individual existence, in particular the existence of a being who is aware of that existence objectively.27 First, it can be said that <u><mark>the creation and conservation of interiority is inseparable from the movement of repulsion </mark>that was discussed in the previous section. <mark>Taboos are </mark>the socializing<mark> articulations of passionate loathing which </mark>cannot be disjoined from the individual’s attempt to <mark>ward off</mark> danger, <mark>violence</mark>, or anything reminiscent of life out of control. Taboos therefore reinforce a sense of interiority on the part of the subject who removes herself, as best as she can, from the scene of violence.</u> What is meant by this interiority is the subject’s perception that intimate life has been excluded from the movements and operations of a life subordinated to the authority of prohibition.28 <u>In other words, <mark>the discontinuous being who lives in accordance with social regulation as determined by the banishment of violence no longer sees itself as participating in the excess of life</mark> destroying itself in dazzling, tumultuous upheavals</u>. Banishment is unevenly realized, and the fact of the matter is that <u><mark>life is never totally forgotten even by those who live according to the strictest rules.</mark> The crucial point here, however, is that <mark>discontinuity</mark>, translated as interiority in the realm of things, <mark>takes on the meaning of disguising its innermost truth qua violence.</mark> </u>Let’s take a look at how Bataille himself illustrates discontinuity: “<u>Each being is distinct from all others . . . . Between one being and another, there is a gulf, a discontinuity. This gulf exists, for instance, between you, listening to me, and me, speaking to you. We are attempting to communicate, but no communication between us can abolish our fundamental difference<strong>.</u></strong> If you die, it is not my death. You and I are discontinuous beings.”29 What is the importance of gesturing toward an infinite gulf separating all individual beings? What does this fundamental difference tell us about self-protecting, self-interested creatures? It seems to me that <u>the infinite abyss, when taken seriously, reminds us that individuated existence is absolutely incomprehensible, unsynthesizable. I say this because <mark>if it weren’t true then the discontinuous being could be subsumed by a system of thought which connected this being, in a manner befitting a logical organization of social reality, to all those other beings ostensibly divided by an infinite gulf</u></mark>. But in that case the gulf would be measurable and distinct beings would lose their absolute particularity to a system of thought which beholds in particularity the birth of sameness. <u>Insofar as <mark>a particular subject can be assimilated to an all-encompassing logic of reality, it follows that the individual is self-identical, unchanging, and wholly complet</mark>e.30 An unsynthesizable being can therefore be understood as devoted to its finite, particular ends only on the condition that its self-preservation is seen as a genuine effort. <mark>Such an effort assumes that the discontinuous self is vulnerable to all sorts of accidents, diseases, insecurities</mark>, predators, injuries, reprisals and the very loss of self which is so urgently defended. If the closure of discontinuity weren’t vulnerable to the dangers of the outside, as well as the inside, no effort would be required to secure its borders. </p></u>
null
Off
null
430,291
1
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,578
Reject their education model – it props up whiteness and excludes students who don’t ascribe to utilitarian frameworks
McLaren Et Al 01
McLaren Et Al 01 Peter McLaren, Distinguished Professor in Critical Studies @ Chapman University, Co-Director of the Paulo Freire Democratic Project; Zeus Leonardo, Ph.D in Education from UCLA, Faculty member at UCB; and Ricky Lee Allen, Associate Professor, Educational Thought and Sociocultural Studies UNM; 2001, “Epistemologies of Whiteness: Transgressing and Transforming Pedagogical Knowledge,” in “Multicultural Curriculum: New Directions for Social Theory, Practice, and Policy,” p. 116 - 121
Schools accumulate useful knowledge to the point where they cannot hold it. Students memorize, tabulate, and synthesize knowledge for future-oriented purposes. Eventually, unproductive student behavior erupts and then spreads as students resist and rebel against work as a guiding principle. The conventional explanation is"unproductivity” Resistant students are either alienated or lazy, and they willfully opt out of work. Bataillean pedagogy understands this to be a state of wasteful activity Bataille's pedagogy attempts to transgress the utility of current school knowledge. It is at this intersection between work and nonwork that we locate a revolution both of student work and waste. Injected in this dialectic is the indictment of whiteness as an ideology that alienates students from real knowledge as well as preventing them from rejoicing in the event of knowing, unfettered from utilitarian concerns. School knowledge has become not only a commodity but has taken on the quality of a thing that exists for other things. Bataille's perspective decries this utilitarian condition wherein students are subjected to schoolwork that apparently has no intrinsic worth but an exchange value in the markets of white capitalism. A radical education recognizes that liberated work then affords students the opportunity for leisure In schools, the moment of learning is subjugated to the utilitarian economic principle of saving the concrete knowledge gained, for an abstract, future purpose. This is the pathological consequence of autocapitalism, which becomes obsessed with "growth for growth's sake" Student curiosity and spontaneity are forsaken, and the excitement—the Aha!—of learning is deferred. What results is the alienation of student subjectivity for utilitarian goals. Homogeneous societies, or social formations determined by utility, are characterized by limits because their imagination is bound by a foreseeable end that turns any form of waste into what Bataille calls the "accursed share," or the cursed portion of society. White fascism is simultaneous policing of excess, where these may threaten the puritanical code of white govemmentality. . School classrooms function under this sign of general repression where quietude is valued over movement and vitality. As an apparatus of whiteness, schools become places of the saving of energy rather than the spending of it. Simple life forms excrete waste, factories spew smoke, and stars explode as supernova only to give birth to new star formations from leftover stellar material. Inasmuch as capitalism commodities any and all social spaces for profit, whiteness refuses to divest itself of excess but saves it for further growth, forestalling its inevitable and disastrous expression. Wars, riots, and civil unrest are today's social potlatch. Bataillean pedagogy recognizes the value in school experiences promoting knowledge that serves no master. But it also realizes that a master currently exists and must be deposed strategically. Pushing the contradictions of white capitalism to their extreme exposes the weak joints of the economy. Only then can we approach what Bataille calls "unknowing " or knowledge divorced from utilitarian ends, because it reconciles student interests in work as these evolve in their liberated form and not as they (re)produce certain outcomes. Bataille is involved in a performative contradiction that uses reasoned arguments to reject the metanarrative of rational knowledge Bataille's suggestions open up knowledge to all possibilities. Transforming student labor and transgressing utilitarian experience represents the double move out of alienated school knowledge. a priori Finis - - Gas Masks, Pogo, and the Ecological Indian: - Earth Day and the Visual Politics of American Environmentalism – A quarterly- project muse there was a struggle to define the meanings and scope of the environmental movement subaltern groups, including African Americans in urban areas and Latino farmworkers, developed a form of politics that situated "environmental concerns within the context of inequality Mainstream environmental organizations, in contrast, promoted a vision of universal risk and vulnerability, In upholding this conception of environmentalism, these groups tended to ignore environmental hazards—including lead poisoning in the inner cities and the effects of pesticides on farmworkers—that were clearly marked by the unequal distribution of risk. Indeed, mainstream groups often refused to consider such concerns as true environmental issues Popular imagery stressed that individual decisions and actions—especially those related to consumption and reproduction—led to the environmental crisis The scientist Barry Commoner, argued that decisions made by corporate and government leaders accounted for most of the nation's environmental problems. Commoner's analysis of the causes of the environmental crisis and his agenda for social change echoed the claims of some environmental activists, especially those involved with subaltern struggles. Nevertheless, these perspectives would be submerged by the proliferation of imagery that emphasized individual responsibility.5 Even though the media stressed the role of the individual, the period surrounding Earth Day did lead to major environmental reforms these policies established the main features of the environmental regulatory state and expressed confidence in the government's ability to solve social problems. Thus, we find a paradox embedded in the environmental politics of the period: the regulatory state expanded while, simultaneously, the visual media emphasized individual responsibility. To end pollution, Americans were told to look both to the federal government and to their own actions in daily life. This essay will explain how these seemingly opposing trends actually reinforced one another and how they bequeathed a problematic legacy to U.S. environmental politics: one that successfully lowered lead levels in the ambient environment but did not strive to protect inner-city children from the hazards of lead paint; one that banned DDT but did not confront the dangers other pesticides posed to farmworkers; one that appeared to enact race-neutral policies but that ultimately intensified environmental inequalities throughout the United States. These discussions occurred during the advent of the Iraq War and our efforts to stop it During those months it became very clear to us that the Left in the United States was at a crossroads, and much of what we had participated in under the banner of “activism” no longer provided an adequate response to our current conditions e found that an old friend—the Ejército Zapatista de Liberación Nacio- nal (Zapatista Army of National Liberation, EZLN)—was already taking enormous strides to move toward a politics adequate to our time, and that it was thus necessary to attempt an evaluation of Zapatismo that would in turn be adequate to the real ‘event’ of their appearance despite the fresh air that the Zapatista uprising had blown into the US political scene since 1994, we began to feel that even the inspiration of Zapatismo had been quickly con- tained through its insertion into a well-worn and untenable narrative: Zapatismo was another of many faceless and indifferent “third world” movements that demanded and deserved solidarity from leftists in the “global north.” From our position as an organization composed in large part by people of color in the United States, we viewed this focus on “solidarity” as the foreign policy equivalent of “white guilt,” quite distinct from any authentic impulse toward, or recognition of, the necessity for radical social change notion of “solidarity” that still pervades much of the Left in the U.S. has continually served an intensely conservative political agenda that dresses itself in the radical rhetoric of the latest rebellion in the “darker nations” while carefully maintaining political action at a distance from our own daily lives, thus producing a political subject ) that more closely resembles a spectator or voyeur than a participant or active agent, while simultaneously working to reduce the solidarity recipient to a mere object the process of solidarity ensures that subjects and political action never meet; in this way it serves to make change an a priori impossibility this practice of solidarity urges us to participate in its perverse logic by accepting the narrative that power tells us about itself: that those who could make change don’t need it and that those who need change can’t make it It has inspired in us the ability, and impressed upon us the necessity, of always viewing our- selves as dignified political subjects with desires, needs, and projects worthy of struggle. it even clearer that we must move be- yond appeals to this stunted form of solidarity, and they present us with a far more difficult challenge: that wherever in the world we may be located, we must become “companer@s” (neither followers nor leaders) in a truly global struggle to change the world. Imprisoned Intellectuals # Conference Brown University, April 13th 2002 Civil society is not a terrain intended for the Black subject. It is coded as waged and wages are White This structurally impossible position is a paradox, because the Black subject, the slave, is vital to political economy: s/he kick-starts capital at its genesis and rescues it from its over-accumulation crisis at its end. But Marxism has no account of this phenomenal birth and life-saving role played by the Black subject: . But Black subjectivity itself disarticulates the Gramscian dream as a ubiquitous emancipatory strategy, because Gramsci has no theory of the unwaged, no solidarity with the slave If we are to take Fanon at his word Decolonization, which sets out to change the order of the world, is, obviously, a program of complete disorder # (37) then we must accept the fact that no other body functions in the Imaginary, the Symbolic, or the Real so completely as a repository of complete disorder as the Black body. Blackness is the site of absolute dereliction at the level of the Real, for in its magnetizing of bullets the Black body functions as the map of gratuitous violence through which civil society is possible: namely, those other bodies for which violence is, or can be, contingent. Blackness in America generates no categories for the chromosome of History, no data for the categories of Immigration or Sovereignty; it is an experience without analog # a past, without a heritage. Blackness is the site of absolute dereliction at the level of t he Imaginary for #whoever says #rape # says Black, # (Fanon) , whoever says #prison # says Black, and whoever says #AIDS # says Black But whereas this realization is, and should be cause for alarm, it should not be cause for lament, or worse, disavowal # not at least, for a true revolutionary, or for a truly revolutionary movement If a social movement is to be neither social democratic, nor Marxist, in terms of the structure of its political desire then it should grasp the invitation to assume the positionality of subjects of social death that present themselves; and, if we are to be honest with ourselves we must admit that the “Negro “ has been inviting Whites, and as well as civil society #s junior partners, to the dance of social death for hundreds of years, but few have wanted to learn the steps. They have been, and remain today # even in the most anti-racist movements, invested elsewhere. This is not to say that all oppositional political desire today is pro-White, but it is to say that it is almost always “anti-Black” which is to say it will not dance with death. Black liberation, as a prospect, makes radicalism more dangerous to the U.S. Not because it raises the specter of some alternative polity (like socialism, or community control of existing resources) but because its condition of possibility as well as its gesture of resistance functions as a negative dialectic: a politics of refusal and a refus al to affirm , a program of complete disorder. One mus t embrace its disorder, its in coherence and allow oneself to be elaborated by it, if indeed one's politics are to be underwritten by a desire to take this country down. A civil war which reclaims Blackness not as a positive value, but as a politically enabling site, to quote Fanon, of “absolute dereliction“: a scandal which rends civil society asunder. Civil war, then, becomes that unthought, but never forgotten understudy of hegemony. A Black specter waiting in the wings, an endless antagonism that cannot be satisfied (via reform or reparation) but must nonetheless be pursued to the death. VIEW THE 1AC AS UNETHICAL
Schools accumulate useful knowledge to the point where they cannot hold it. Students synthesize knowledge for future-oriented purposes. Eventually, unproductive student behavior erupts and then spreads as students rebel Resistant students are either alienated or lazy, and they willfully opt out of work School knowledge has taken on the quality that exists for other things. Bataille's decries this condition wherein students are subjected to schoolwork that has no intrinsic worth but an exchange value in the markets of white capitalism Student curiosity and spontaneity are forsaken, and the excitement is deferred. What results is the alienation of student subjectivity social formations determined by utility, are characterized by limits because their imagination is bound by a foreseeable end that turns any form of waste into the "accursed share White fascism is simultaneous policing of excess School classrooms function under this sign of general repression where quietude is valued over movement and vitality As an apparatus of whiteness, schools become places of the saving of energy rather than the spending of it. Bataillean pedagogy recognizes the value in school experiences promoting knowledge that serves no master
Transforming labor, and consequently student work, requires a revolutionary disposition toward relations of production. In particular, it is imperative that educators link the transformation of the economy with a critique of whiteness. However, theories of whiteness must be linked to the idea that capitalism is not only the exploitation of knowledge for profits, but the simultaneous repression of expenditure, or what Georges Bataille (1997, 1991, 1988, 1985) describes as the human proclivity to expend energy and not to accumulate it. Transformation of labor produces social relations that flourish in conditions free of alienation and exploitation. A discourse on production must also consider alternative theoretical frameworks to explain students' inner experiences and the knowledge they gain from them. Transforming relations of production allows students, as concrete subjects, to experience schooling in new ways, but Bataille's theory of expenditure provides a general framework that explains how we come to know these inner experiences themselves, a theory that functions not within the logic of production, but within that of waste. As Bataille (1988) explains, On the surface of the globe, for living matter in general, energy is always in excess; the question is always posed in terms of extravagance. The choice is limited to how the wealth is to be squandered.... The general movement of exudation (of waste) of living matter implies him [sic], and he cannot stop it;... it destines him, in a privileged way, to that glorious operation, to useless consumption. The latter cannot accumulate limitlessly in the productive forces; eventually, like a river into the sea, it is bound to escape us and be lost to us. (23; emphasis in the original) Schools accumulate useful knowledge to the point where they cannot hold it. Students memorize, tabulate, and synthesize knowledge for future-oriented purposes. Eventually, unproductive student behavior erupts and then spreads as students resist and rebel against work as a guiding principle. The conventional explanation for disruptive student behavior is"unproductivity” Resistant students are either alienated or lazy, and they willfully opt out of work. Bataillean pedagogy understands this to be a state of wasteful activity that cannot be fully explained by a productivist logic. It represents the "blind spot** of the discourse on work. Bataille's pedagogy attempts to transgress the utility of current school knowledge. Educators isolate unproductive students from their peers to ensure that they "do their work" or detain them after school to give them extra work. Meanwhile, what escapes our understanding is the principle of expenditure, or how students squander schoolwork for no apparently useful or productive reason. The theory of expenditure does not deny the presence of work, let alone the importance of liberated labor. It acknowledges the production of life for purposes of subsistence, survival, and improvement of the species. Furthermore, the modified theory of expenditure we are presenting recognizes the importance of revolutionizing student work as part of an overall transformation of social life. In fact, Batailie (1997) clarifies, "Class struggle ... becomes the grandest form of social expenditure when it is taken up again and developed, this time on the part of the workers, and on such a scale that it threatens the very existence of the masters" (178). It is at this intersection between work and nonwork that we locate a revolution both of student work and waste. Injected in this dialectic is the indictment of whiteness as an ideology that alienates students from real knowledge as well as preventing them from rejoicing in the event of knowing, unfettered from utilitarian concerns. School knowledge has become not only a commodity in the Marxian sense, but has taken on the quality of a thing that exists for other things. And as things go, school knowledge is deemed useful for something outside of itself, to fulfill a destiny that has been predetermined, such as grades or higher education. Bataille's perspective decries this utilitarian condition wherein students are subjected to schoolwork that apparently has no intrinsic worth but an exchange value in the markets of white capitalism. A radical education understands that combating capitalism is the call for unalienated student work, but it also recognizes that liberated work then affords students the opportunity for leisure, or luxurious work. As Herbert Kliebard (1986) notes, the etymological root of school finds itself in the word leisure. This is to say that as much as capitalism exploits labor, it also reduces our capacity to celebrate nonwork life. This mode of celebration is not to be found in white societies but expresses itself in what Jean Baudrillard (1975) calls "primitive" societies. As Bataille (1997) describes it, one finds the "festival" or "potlatch" in social arrangements that function under the sign of the gift exchange. Euro-white societies, which function under the sign of classical economics, find the gift exchange rather foreign and irrational. In his endorsement of the gift principle imported by Marcel Mauss, Bataille (1997) writes, The "merchants" of Mexico practised the paradoxical system of exchange 1 have described as a regular sequence of gifts; these customs, not barter, in fact constituted the archaic organization of exchange. Potlatch, still practised by the Indians of the north-west coast of America, is its typical form. Ethnographers now employ this term to designate institutions functioning on a similar principle; they find traces of it in all societies. Among the Tlingit, the Haida, the Tsimshian, the Kwakiutl, pot-latch is of prime importance in social life— Potlatch is, like commerce, a means of circulating wealth, but it excludes bargaining. More often than not it is the solemn giving of considerable riches, offered by a chief to his rival for the purpose of humiliation, challenging and obligating him. The recipient has to erase the humiliation and take up the challenge; he must satisfy the obligation that was contracted by accepting. He can only reply, a short time later, by means of a new potlatch, more generous than the first: he must pay back with interest. (202) Expenditure is a form of social obligation between subjects who exchange "gifts" and then transcend their limits. A "countergift" raises the stakes. Seen this way, expenditure is inherently intersubjective and anti-individualistic. It binds, for example, teachers and students with one another as each benefits from the others challenge. The gift is an alternative form of exchange opposed to classical economic transactions. The gift is ruled by the principle of loss, not profit or accumulation. Accumulating gifts without offering countergifts violates the exchange and institutes power in favor of the giver over the receiver. To maintain the equilibrium, it is necessary to perpetuate the exchange, and more important, to raise the stakes with more extravagant gifts. Indeed, in some cases the gift object is produced, but it is produced only to be squandered. In schools, the moment of learning is subjugated to the utilitarian economic principle of saving the concrete knowledge gained, for an abstract, future purpose. This is the pathological consequence of autocapitalism, which becomes obsessed with "growth for growth's sake" (Ashley 1997), a process with no end in sight. Student curiosity and spontaneity are forsaken, and the excitement—the Aha!—of learning is deferred. What results is the alienation of student subjectivity for utilitarian goals. In short, the gift of knowledge is violated. Bataillean pedagogy reinstitutes the challenge involved in transgressing the current regimes of school knowledge surveilled by white governmentality through considering schooling as a gift to be returned. Furthermore, this inter-subjective process is guided by the principle of expenditure rather than accumu¬lation for utilitarian purposes. A critical perspective on epistemologies of whiteness considers the general terrorism of the Protestant ethic to negate nonwork life in schools. Within our framework, we suggest that Max Weber's immanent insight neglects the evolution of the spirit of whiteness along with the coevolution of capitalism and Protestantism. In its search to procure salvation through work and accumulation of things, the parallel evolution of Protestantism, whiteness, and capitalism sup-presses students' capacity to enjoy the fruits of their work. Students' immediate gratification from work is always either denied or deferred. Salvation through work becomes the only good, against which all other endeavors are measured (Richardson 1994). A student quickly learns that one's worth becomes coextensive with one's work. Human identity becomes the kind of work one takes up: / am an attorney! / am a doctor! Take note of the dejection a person feels when he loses his job. Over and beyond the feeling of improvidence, he feels worthless. Extending Weber's thesis, we argue that capitalism is also linked with the Protestant ethic, or the hyperutilitarianism found in white patriarchal capitalism. That is, Weber s findings neglect the construction of whiteness with respect to work and utilitarianism, or the making of a Protestant ethnic We suggest that any discourse that negates white capitalism as the exploitation of labor for profit must also critique the way it exploits all facets of learning as determined by utilitarian labor. Homogeneous societies, or social formations determined by utility, are characterized by limits because their imagination is bound by a foreseeable end that turns any form of waste into what Bataille calls the "accursed share," or the cursed portion of society. On the other hand, heterogeneous societies, or social formations determined by expenditure, know no bounds since they are driven by transgression of the sacred. The accursed share, those denigrated discursive and material spaces of people of color in white territories, is jettisoned by the mechanisms of white capitalism since it is seen as unproductive by white governmentalities. The high unemployment of people of color is considered a natural residue of competition and ameliorating homelessness an inefficient endeavor. In Donnie Brasco's words, "Forget about it." Learning-disabled students, gang members, physically handicapped children, and high school dropouts represent the cursed parts of schooling and are grouped under the sign "unproductive." Yet their heterogeneous existence points to their alternative way of being, an experience that can be explained through its contrast with utilitarian work. This does not suggest that these subjects do not want to work, or work hard for that matter. Often, as Paul Willis (1977), Peter McLaren (1999), and Jay MacLeod (1987) have shown, some of the most alienated students are the ones who valorize work. But it goes without saying that their perceived incompatibility with production is responsible for labeling them as part of the accursed share of white capitalism. Bataillean pedagogy speaks up for the oppressed segments of our schools, the heterogeneous other of the workaday world (Pefanis 1991). Much has been said about white fascism (see, e.g., McLaren 1995, 1997). For Georges Bataille (1997), fascism's renegade morality represents something of the order of the heterogeneous and warrants critical attention from the perspective of expenditure. In his studies of German and Italian fascism, Bataille writes, Opposed to democratic politicians, who represent in different countries the platitude inherent to homogeneous [i.e., productive) society, Mussolini and Hitler immediately stand out as something other. Whatever emotions their actual existence as political agents of evolution provokes, it is impossible to ignore the force that situates them above men, parties and even laws: a force that disrupts the regular course of things, the peaceful but fastidious homogeneity powerless to maintain itself (the fact that laws are broken is only the most obvious sign of the transcendent, heterogeneous nature of fascist action). (128) Bataille does not promote fascists and their human atrocities. This is unequivocal, and his unrelenting critique of fascism is well documented (Richardson 1994). What captures his interest is fascism's utmost heterogeneity and extreme authority, which exists for itself before it exists for any useful or productive reasons. To Bataille, the psychological structure of fascism exceeds any conventional ideas about morality involving good and bad. There seems to be no boundary to fascist atrocities. "Evil" just does not seem to suffice as a descriptor. What can we call Adolf Hitler's disgusting campaign of death? What signifier fits the image, the punishment for the crime? Fascism is driven to extreme social hypnosis as a way of concentrating the people's effective flows before it is linked with any productive ends. It is wasteful in all its manifestation, and fascism—etymologically tied to "uniting" or "concentrating" (Bataille 1997, 135)—becomes the hoarding of human energy for the fascist leader. In short, what was originally explorable in terms of expenditure becomes a convenient story about accumulation of power, of energy, and ultimately of homogeneous purpose. White fascism is not only the enforcement of white territorial control of the means of production. It is also the simultaneous policing of excess, of curbing expenditure and revelry (not to mention ribaldry) where these may threaten the puritanical code of white govemmentality. How many examples do we have of the carnivalesque activity, outlawry, and social brigandage of student behavior quelled by the repressive power of state or local police? Celebration is confused for lawlessness as the antiriot unit marches into the potlatch to subdue its energy. School classrooms function under this sign of general repression where quietude is valued over movement and vitality. Yet shift the scene to a crowded hallway or students on their way to their lockers and the noise deafens even the hard of hearing. White fascism is as much about the control of expenditure as it is the control of the means of production. As an apparatus of whiteness, schools become places of the saving of energy rather than the spending of it. It should be plain to see that white capitalism has encoded the colored body as a site of excess. To the white fascist, black students (especially males) have become the site of supersexuality and the Latina body a site of superreproduction. On the other hand, the white body has been constructed as the site of rationality and savings. The white body is almost nonsexualized. This erotic economy of "excess" is linked to a genocidal tendency in the history and geography of whiteness to the extent that white ideology has been involved in consistent crimes against the eroticized other. The oppression of the sexual other is evidence of a certain repression of the expenditure that whiteness represses in itself. That is, whiteness recognizes an excess beyond productivity but fails to squander it, fearing the ecstatic consequences of such a waste. It is a vicarious living of sorts that robs whiteness of any life of its own. It is a mitigated, surreptitious experience that partitions the erotic—that is, the irreducible experience—into fantasies rather than participating in its flows. It is a projection of what whiteness fears about itself and foils to understand: a certain excessive drive. This may sound like the eroticization of the racial ized subject represented in the white imaginary. For it seems a standard white discourse to portray the other as a site of excess. However, remaining consistent with Bataille's theory, expenditure is a general economy that inheres in all humans. It is not an economic drive particular to non-Western societies, but one that finds its expression in them, and its repression in whiteness. Simple life forms excrete waste, factories spew smoke, and stars explode as supernova only to give birth to new star formations from leftover stellar material. Inasmuch as capitalism commodities any and all social spaces for profit, whiteness refuses to divest itself of excess but saves it for further growth, forestalling its inevitable and disastrous expression. Wars, riots, and civil unrest are today's social potlatch. The theory of expenditure proposed here is a modified Bataillean pedagogy. It represents an alternative theory to production that nevertheless depends on the transformation of labor to realize its luxurious goals. A modified theory of expenditure recognizes the value in school experiences promoting knowledge that serves no master. But it also realizes that a master currently exists and must be deposed strategically. The double helix of whiteness and capitalism is the conspiratorial first cause. Pushing the contradictions of white capitalism to their extreme exposes the weak joints of the economy. Only then can we approach what Bataille calls "unknowing " or knowledge divorced from utilitarian ends, because it reconciles student interests in work as these evolve in their liberated form and not as they (re)produce certain outcomes. Bataillean pedagogy, as Jurgen Habermas (1987) suggests, appears like a form of fantastic anarchism because it lacks a ratio-nal basis for valuing one form of student work over another (since this is beyond linguistic representation). Moreover, Bataille is involved in a performative contradiction that uses reasoned arguments to reject the metanarrative of rational knowledge (Jay 1993). However, it is also possible to construct Bataille's suggestions not as anarchistic, but as an opening up of knowledge to all possibilities. Transforming student labor and transgressing utilitarian experience represents the double move out of alienated school knowledge. The 1ac looks to legalize marijuana as a demand of the human without recognizing the cause of the violence, slaves look for freedom within opioids and the assume the ethicality of the world through their advantages where they probably gunna build farms in the suburbs but justify pollution in the hood. The only ethical demand available to modern politics is that of the Slave and the Savage, the demand for the end of America itself. This cry, born out of the belly of slave ships and the churning vertigo of constitutive genocide, exposes the grammar of the Affirmative’s calls for larger institutional access as a fundamental fortification of White Settler and Slave Master civil society by its diversionary focus on the ethicality of the policies and practices of the United States as opposed to the a priori question its very existence. This means that any kind of enviornmental movement fails and reinscribes racial violence – also the positing of warming as a universal risk is self-defeating Finis Dunaway - assistant professor of history at Trent University in Peterborough, Ontario.- 2008- Gas Masks, Pogo, and the Ecological Indian: - Earth Day and the Visual Politics of American Environmentalism – A quarterly- project muse It would be too simple, though, to assign all the blame to the media for this particular framing of environmentalism. During this time, there was a struggle to define the meanings and scope of the environmental movement, a contest over such questions as what constituted an environmental issue and whether or not environmental causes would be linked to broader struggles for social justice. As the geographer Laura Pulido explains, subaltern groups, including African Americans in urban areas and Latino farmworkers, developed a form of politics that situated "environmental concerns within the context of inequality and attempts to alter dominant power arrangements." Mainstream environmental organizations, in contrast, promoted a vision of universal risk and vulnerability, what the sociologist Ulrich Beck would later describe as a "generalized consciousness of affliction." In upholding this conception of environmentalism, these groups tended to ignore environmental hazards—including lead poisoning in the inner cities and the effects of pesticides on farmworkers—that were clearly marked by the unequal distribution of risk. Indeed, mainstream groups often refused to consider such concerns as true environmental issues and concentrated instead on problems that supposedly threatened all Americans equally. By placing iconic images—gas masks, Pogo, and the Ecological Indian—in dialogue with these other environmental struggles, this essay will explore the complex relationship between the mass media and the multiple environmentalisms. Ultimately, both the media and mainstream organizations failed to understand the links between social inequality and the disproportionate experience of risk among racialized minorities.4 Likewise, while some Earth Day organizers sought to focus on power relations and corporate responsibility for environmental degradation, the media instead emphasized collective guilt: everyone was blamed for causing pollution. Popular imagery stressed that individual decisions and actions—especially those related to consumption and reproduction—led to the environmental crisis. According to these explanations, both a growing population and increasing affluence inevitably resulted in widespread pollution. If "Americans" (almost always described in these reports as a monolithic, undifferentiated group) would change their actions in daily life—if they would have fewer children and consume less—then they could overcome this crisis. This focus on personal responsibility obscured other explanations that considered the social origins of environmental degradation. The scientist Barry Commoner, in The Closing Circle and other publications, argued that decisions made by corporate and government leaders accounted for most of the nation's environmental problems. In particular, Commoner focused on the shift to "new productive technologies" and other "counterecological pattern[s] of growth" [End Page 69] after World War II. From the introduction of synthetic fibers and nonreturnable bottles to the proliferation of pesticides and the massive allocation of funds to the interstate highway system (and with it, the underwriting of the automobile industry rather than public transportation), Commoner detailed the effects of these changes implemented by powerful public and private institutions. "The earth is polluted," he concluded, "neither because man is some kind of especially dirty animal nor because there are too many of us. The fault lies with human society—with the ways in which society has elected to win, distribute, and use the wealth that has been extracted by human labor from the planet's resources. Once the social origins of the crisis become clear, we can begin to design appropriate social actions to resolve it." For Commoner, these solutions would entail a shift away from counterecological technologies, the cultivation of a more democratic form of science attuned to the environmental consequences of modern industry, and the recognition that the burden of environmental risk often fell on poor and minority communities. Commoner's analysis of the causes of the environmental crisis and his agenda for social change echoed the claims of some environmental activists, especially those involved with subaltern struggles. Nevertheless, these perspectives would be submerged by the proliferation of imagery that emphasized individual responsibility.5 Even though the media stressed the role of the individual, the period surrounding Earth Day did lead to major environmental reforms: from the founding of the Environmental Protection Agency to the passage of the Clean Air Act and other legislation, these policies established the main features of the environmental regulatory state and expressed confidence in the government's ability to solve social problems. Thus, we find a paradox embedded in the environmental politics of the period: the regulatory state expanded while, simultaneously, the visual media emphasized individual responsibility. To end pollution, Americans were told to look both to the federal government and to their own actions in daily life. This essay will explain how these seemingly opposing trends actually reinforced one another and how they bequeathed a problematic legacy to U.S. environmental politics: one that successfully lowered lead levels in the ambient environment but did not strive to protect inner-city children from the hazards of lead paint; one that banned DDT but did not confront the dangers other pesticides posed to farmworkers; one that appeared to enact race-neutral policies but that ultimately intensified environmental inequalities throughout the United States. The affirmative’s form of political change is nothing but a solidarity action used to reify the current structures of white supremacy that produces us as political subjects who are spectators, complacent with current structures unable to create change El Kilombo 2007 (El Kilombo Intergalactico, people of color collective made up of students, migrants, and other community members in Durham, North Carolina, “Beyond Resistance Everything: An Interview with Subcomandante Insurgente Marcos” DM) The following lines are the product of intense collective discussions that took place within what is today El Kilombo Intergaláctico during much of 2003 and 2004. These discussions occurred during the advent of the Iraq War and our efforts (though ultimately ineffective) to stop it. During those months it became very clear to us that the Left in the United States was at a crossroads, and much of what we had participated in under the banner of “activism” no longer provided an adequate response to our current conditions. In our efforts to forge a new path, we found that an old friend—the Ejército Zapatista de Liberación Nacio- nal (Zapatista Army of National Liberation, EZLN)—was already taking enormous strides to move toward a politics adequate to our time, and that it was thus necessary to attempt an evaluation of Zapatismo that would in turn be adequate to the real ‘event’ of their appearance. That is, despite the fresh air that the Zapatista uprising had blown into the US political scene since 1994, we began to feel that even the inspiration of Zapatismo had been quickly con- tained through its insertion into a well-worn and untenable narrative: Zapatismo was another of many faceless and indifferent “third world” movements that demanded and deserved solidarity from leftists in the “global north.” From our position as an organization composed in large part by people of color in the United States, we viewed this focus on “solidarity” as the foreign policy equivalent of “white guilt,” quite distinct from any authentic impulse toward, or recognition of, the necessity for radical social change. The notion of “solidarity” that still pervades much of the Left in the U.S. has continually served an intensely conservative political agenda that dresses itself in the radical rhetoric of the latest rebellion in the “darker nations” while carefully maintaining political action at a distance from our own daily lives, thus producing a political subject (the solidarity provider) that more closely resembles a spectator or voyeur (to the suffering of others) than a participant or active agent, while simultaneously working to reduce the solidarity recipient to a mere object (of our pity and mismatched socks). At both ends of this relationship, the process of solidarity ensures that subjects and political action never meet; in this way it serves to make change an a priori impossibility. In other words, this practice of solidarity urges us to participate in its perverse logic by accepting the narrative that power tells us about itself: that those who could make change don’t need it and that those who need change can’t make it. To the extent that human solidarity has a future, this logic and practice do not! For us, Zapatismo was (and continues to be) unique exactly because it has provided us with the elements to shatter this tired schema. It has inspired in us the ability, and impressed upon us the necessity, of always viewing our- selves as dignified political subjects with desires, needs, and projects worthy of struggle. With the publication of The Sixth Declaration of the Lacandón Jungle in June of 2005, the Zapatistas have made it even clearer that we must move be- yond appeals to this stunted form of solidarity, and they present us with a far more difficult challenge: that wherever in the world we may be located, we must become “companer@s” (neither followers nor leaders) in a truly global struggle to change the world. As a direct response to this call, this analysis is our attempt to read Zapatismo as providing us with the rough draft of a manual for contemporary political action that eventually must be written by us all. The black body is the site of social death par excellence, having become dead by a 700-year injunction barring its subjectivity. Social death is a condition of existence and not some avoidable impact—how we relate to this condition is all that is important. Wilderson- 2002 Frank Wilderson- The Prison Slave as Hegemony's (Silent) Scandal-Presented a t #Imprisoned Intellectuals # Conference Brown University, April 13th 2002 Civil society is not a terrain intended for the Black subject. It is coded as waged and wages are White. Civil society is the terrain where hegemony is produced, contested, mapped. And th e invitat ion to p articipate in hegemony's gestures of influence, leadership, and consent is not ext ended to t he unwaged. We live in the world , but ex ist out side of civil s ociety. This structurally impossible position is a paradox, because the Black subject, the slave, is vital to political economy: s/he kick-starts capital at its genesis and rescues it from its over-accumulation crisis at its end. But Marxism has no account of this phenomenal birth and life-saving role played by the Black subject: from Marx and Gr amsci we have con sistent s ilence. In taking Foucau lt to ta sk for a ssum ing a univ ersal s ubject in r evolt ag ainst d iscipline, in the same s pirit in which I have t aken Gr amsci to ta sk for as suming a u niversal sub ject, the subject of civil societ y in revolt a gainst capita l, Joy Jam es writes : The U.S. carceral network kills, however, and in its prisons, it kills more blacks than any other ethnic group. American prisons constitute an "outside" in U.S. political life. In fact, our society displays waves of concentric outside circles with increasing distances from bourgeois self-policing. The state routinely polices the14 unassim ilable in the hell of lockdow n, deprivat ion tanks , control units , and holes for political prisoners (Resisting State Violence 1996: 34 ) But this peculiar preoccupation is not Gramsci's bailiwick. His concern is with White folks; or with folks in a White (ned) enough subject position that they are confronted by, or threat ened by th e remova l of, a wag e -- be it monetary or social. But Black subjectivity itself disarticulates the Gramscian dream as a ubiquitous emancipatory strategy, because Gramsci, like most White activists, and radical American movements like the prison abolition movement, has no theory of the unwaged, no solidarity with the slave If we are to take Fanon at his word when he writes, #Decolonization, which sets out to change the order of the world, is, obviously, a program of complete disorder # (37) then we must accept the fact that no other body functions in the Imaginary, the Symbolic, or the Real so completely as a repository of complete disorder as the Black body. Blackness is the site of absolute dereliction at the level of the Real, for in its magnetizing of bullets the Black body functions as the map of gratuitous violence through which civil society is possible: namely, those other bodies for which violence is, or can be, contingent. Blackness is the site of absolute dereliction at the level of the Symbolic, for Blackness in America generates no categories for the chromosome of History, no data for the categories of Immigration or Sovereignty; it is an experience without analog # a past, without a heritage. Blackness is the site of absolute dereliction at the level of t he Imaginary for #whoever says #rape # says Black, # (Fanon) , whoever says #prison # says Black, and whoever says #AIDS # says Black (Sexton) # the #Negro is a phobogenic object # (Fanon). Indeed &a phobogenic object &a past without a heritage &the map of gratuitous violence &a program of complete disorder. But whereas this realization is, and should be cause for alarm, it should not be cause for lament, or worse, disavowal # not at least, for a true revolutionary, or for a truly revolutionary movement such as prison a bolition. 15 If a social movement is to be neither social democratic, nor Marxist, in terms of the structure of its political desire then it should grasp the invitation to assume the positionality of subjects of social death that present themselves; and, if we are to be honest with ourselves we must admit that the “Negro “ has been inviting Whites, and as well as civil society #s junior partners, to the dance of social death for hundreds of years, but few have wanted to learn the steps. They have been, and remain today # even in the most anti-racist movements, like the prison abolition movement # invested elsewhere. This is not to say that all oppositional political desire today is pro-White, but it is to say that it is almost always “anti-Black” which is to say it will not dance with death. Black liberation, as a prospect, makes radicalism more dangerous to the U.S. Not because it raises the specter of some alternative polity (like socialism, or community control of existing resources) but because its condition of possibility as well as its gesture of resistance functions as a negative dialectic: a politics of refusal and a refus al to affirm , a program of complete disorder. One mus t embrace its disorder, its in coherence and allow oneself to be elaborated by it, if indeed one's politics are to be underwritten by a desire to take this country down. If this is not the desire which underwrites one #s politics then through what strategy of legitimation is the word #prison # being linked t o the wo rd #abolition #? Wh at ar e this movem ent #s lines of po litical a ccount abilit y? There #s nothing foreign, frightening, or even unpracticed about the embrace of disorder and incoherence. The desire to be embraced, and elaborated, by disorder and incoherence is not anathema in and of itself: no one, for example, has ever been known to say #gee-whiz, if only my orgasms would end a little sooner, or maybe not come at all. # But few so-called radicals desire to be embraced, and elaborated, by the disorder and incoherence of Blackness # and the state of politica l movemen ts in A merica to day is ma rked by t his very N egroph obogen isis: #gee-whiz, if only Black rage could be more coherent, or maybe not come at all. # Perhaps there #s something more terrifying about the joy of Black, then there is about the joy of sex (unless one is talking sex wit h a Negr o). Perhaps coalitions today p refer to remain in- orgas mic in the fa ce of civilsociety # with hegemony as a handy prophylactic, just in case. But if, through this stasis, or paralysis , they tr y to do t he work of pr ison a bolit ion # that work will fail; because it is always work from a position of coherence (i.e. the worker) on behalf of a position of incoherence, the Black subject, or prison slave. In this way, social formations on the Left remain blind to the contradictions of coalitions bet ween worker s and s laves. T hey remain coalitions opera ting with in the logic of civil society; and function less as revolutionary promises and more as crowding out scenarios of Black antagonisms # they simply feed our frustration. Whereas the positionality of the worker # be s/he a factory worker demanding a monetary wage or an immigrant or White woman demanding a social wage # gestures toward the reconfiguration of civil society, the positionality of the Black subject # be s/he a prison-slave or a prison-slave-in-waiting # gestures toward the disconfiguration of civil society: from the coherence of civil society, t he Black subject beckons with the in coherence of civil war. A civil war which reclaims Blackness not as a positive value, but as a politically enabling site, to quote Fanon, of “absolute dereliction“: a scandal which rends civil society asunder. Civil war, then, becomes that unthought, but never forgotten understudy of hegemony. A Black specter waiting in the wings, an endless antagonism that cannot be satisfied (via reform or reparation) but must nonetheless be pursued to the death. VIEW THE 1AC AS UNETHICAL
37,146
<h4>Reject their education model – it props up whiteness and excludes students who don’t ascribe to utilitarian frameworks </h4><p><strong>McLaren Et Al 01</strong> Peter McLaren, Distinguished Professor in Critical Studies @ Chapman University, Co-Director of the Paulo Freire Democratic Project; Zeus Leonardo, Ph.D in Education from UCLA, Faculty member at UCB; and Ricky Lee Allen, Associate Professor, Educational Thought and Sociocultural Studies UNM; 2001, “Epistemologies of Whiteness: Transgressing and Transforming Pedagogical Knowledge,” in “Multicultural Curriculum: New Directions for Social Theory, Practice, and Policy,” p. 116 - 121</p><p>Transforming labor, and consequently student work, requires a revolutionary disposition toward relations of production. In particular, it is imperative that educators link the transformation of the economy with a critique of whiteness. However, theories of whiteness must be linked to the idea that capitalism is not only the exploitation of knowledge for profits, but the simultaneous repression of expenditure, or what Georges Bataille (1997, 1991, 1988, 1985) describes as the human proclivity to expend energy and not to accumulate it. Transformation of labor produces social relations that flourish in conditions free of alienation and exploitation. A discourse on production must also consider alternative theoretical frameworks to explain students' inner experiences and the knowledge they gain from them. Transforming relations of production allows students, as concrete subjects, to experience schooling in new ways, but Bataille's theory of expenditure provides a general framework that explains how we come to know these inner experiences themselves, a theory that functions not within the logic of production, but within that of waste. As Bataille (1988) explains,</p><p>On the surface of the globe, for living matter in general, energy is always in excess; the question is always posed in terms of extravagance. The choice is limited to how the wealth is to be squandered.... The general movement of exudation (of waste) of living matter implies him [sic], and he cannot stop it;... it destines him, in a privileged way, to that glorious operation, to useless consumption. The latter cannot accumulate limitlessly in the productive forces; eventually, like a river into the sea, it is bound to escape us and be lost to us. (23; emphasis in the original)</p><p><u><mark>Schools accumulate useful knowledge to the point where they cannot hold it. Students</mark> memorize, tabulate, and <mark>synthesize knowledge for future-oriented purposes. Eventually, unproductive student behavior erupts and then spreads as students</mark> resist and <mark>rebel</mark> against work as a guiding principle. The conventional explanation</u> for disruptive student behavior <u>is"unproductivity” <mark>Resistant students are either alienated or lazy, and they willfully opt out of work</mark>. Bataillean pedagogy understands this to be a state of wasteful activity</u> that cannot be fully explained by a productivist logic. It represents the "blind spot** of the discourse on work. <u>Bataille's pedagogy attempts to transgress the utility of current school knowledge.</u> Educators isolate unproductive students from their peers to ensure that they "do their work" or detain them after school to give them extra work. Meanwhile, what escapes our understanding is the principle of expenditure, or how students squander schoolwork for no apparently useful or productive reason.</p><p>The theory of expenditure does not deny the presence of work, let alone the importance of liberated labor. It acknowledges the production of life for purposes of subsistence, survival, and improvement of the species. Furthermore, the modified theory of expenditure we are presenting recognizes the importance of revolutionizing student work as part of an overall transformation of social life. In fact, Batailie (1997) clarifies, "Class struggle ... becomes the grandest form of social expenditure when it is taken up again and developed, this time on the part of the workers, and on such a scale that it threatens the very existence of the masters" (178).</p><p><u>It is at this intersection between work and nonwork that we locate a revolution both of student work and waste. Injected in this dialectic is the indictment of whiteness as an ideology that alienates students from real knowledge as well as preventing them from rejoicing in the event of knowing, unfettered from utilitarian concerns.</p><p><mark>School knowledge</mark> has become not only a commodity</u> in the Marxian sense, <u>but <mark>has taken on the quality</mark> of a thing <mark>that exists for other things.</u></mark> And as things go, school knowledge is deemed useful for something outside of itself, to fulfill a destiny that has been predetermined, such as grades or higher education. <u><mark>Bataille's</mark> perspective <mark>decries this</mark> utilitarian <mark>condition wherein students are subjected to schoolwork that</mark> apparently <mark>has no intrinsic worth but an exchange value in the markets of white capitalism</mark>.</p><p>A radical education</u> understands that combating capitalism is the call for unalienated student work, but it also <u>recognizes that liberated work then affords students the opportunity for leisure</u>, or luxurious work. As Herbert Kliebard (1986) notes, the etymological root of school finds itself in the word leisure. This is to say that as much as capitalism exploits labor, it also reduces our capacity to celebrate nonwork life. This mode of celebration is not to be found in white societies but expresses itself in what Jean Baudrillard (1975) calls "primitive" societies. As Bataille (1997) describes it, one finds the "festival" or "potlatch" in social arrangements that function under the sign of the gift exchange. Euro-white societies, which function under the sign of classical economics, find the gift exchange rather foreign and irrational. In his endorsement of the gift principle imported by Marcel Mauss, Bataille (1997) writes,</p><p>The "merchants" of Mexico practised the paradoxical system of exchange 1 have described as a regular sequence of gifts; these customs, not barter, in fact constituted the archaic organization of exchange. Potlatch, still practised by the Indians of the north-west coast of America, is its typical form. Ethnographers now employ this term to designate institutions functioning on a similar principle; they find traces of it in all societies. Among the Tlingit, the Haida, the Tsimshian, the Kwakiutl, pot-latch is of prime importance in social life—</p><p>Potlatch is, like commerce, a means of circulating wealth, but it excludes bargaining. More often than not it is the solemn giving of considerable riches, offered by a chief to his rival for the purpose of humiliation, challenging and obligating him. The recipient has to erase the humiliation and take up the challenge; he must satisfy the obligation that was contracted by accepting. He can only reply, a short time later, by means of a new potlatch, more generous than the first: he must pay back with interest. (202)</p><p>Expenditure is a form of social obligation between subjects who exchange "gifts" and then transcend their limits. A "countergift" raises the stakes. Seen this way, expenditure is inherently intersubjective and anti-individualistic. It binds, for example, teachers and students with one another as each benefits from the others challenge. The gift is an alternative form of exchange opposed to classical economic transactions. The gift is ruled by the principle of loss, not profit or accumulation. Accumulating gifts without offering countergifts violates the exchange and institutes power in favor of the giver over the receiver. To maintain the equilibrium, it is necessary to perpetuate the exchange, and more important, to raise the stakes with more extravagant gifts. Indeed, in some cases the gift object is produced, but it is produced only to be squandered.</p><p><u>In schools, the moment of learning is subjugated to the utilitarian economic principle of saving the concrete knowledge gained, for an abstract, future purpose. This is the pathological consequence of autocapitalism, which becomes obsessed with "growth for growth's sake"</u> (Ashley 1997), a process with no end in sight. <u><mark>Student curiosity and spontaneity are forsaken, and the excitement</mark>—the Aha!—of learning <mark>is deferred. What results is the alienation of student subjectivity</mark> for utilitarian goals. </u>In short, the gift of knowledge is violated.</p><p>Bataillean pedagogy reinstitutes the challenge involved in transgressing the current regimes of school knowledge surveilled by white governmentality through considering schooling as a gift to be returned. Furthermore, this inter-subjective process is guided by the principle of expenditure rather than accumu¬lation for utilitarian purposes.</p><p>A critical perspective on epistemologies of whiteness considers the general terrorism of the Protestant ethic to negate nonwork life in schools. Within our framework, we suggest that Max Weber's immanent insight neglects the evolution of the spirit of whiteness along with the coevolution of capitalism and Protestantism. In its search to procure salvation through work and accumulation of things, the parallel evolution of Protestantism, whiteness, and capitalism sup-presses students' capacity to enjoy the fruits of their work. Students' immediate gratification from work is always either denied or deferred. Salvation through work becomes the only good, against which all other endeavors are measured (Richardson 1994). A student quickly learns that one's worth becomes coextensive with one's work. Human identity becomes the kind of work one takes up: / am an attorney! / am a doctor! Take note of the dejection a person feels when he loses his job. Over and beyond the feeling of improvidence, he feels worthless. Extending Weber's thesis, we argue that capitalism is also linked with the Protestant ethic, or the hyperutilitarianism found in white patriarchal capitalism. That is, Weber s findings neglect the construction of whiteness with respect to work and utilitarianism, or the making of a Protestant ethnic We suggest that any discourse that negates white capitalism as the exploitation of labor for profit must also critique the way it exploits all facets of learning as determined by utilitarian labor.</p><p><u>Homogeneous societies, or <mark>social formations determined by utility, are characterized by limits because their imagination is bound by a foreseeable end that turns any form of waste into</mark> what Bataille calls <mark>the "accursed share</mark>," or the cursed portion of society.</u> On the other hand, heterogeneous societies, or social formations determined by expenditure, know no bounds since they are driven by transgression of the sacred. The accursed share, those denigrated discursive and material spaces of people of color in white territories, is jettisoned by the mechanisms of white capitalism since it is seen as unproductive by white governmentalities. The high unemployment of people of color is considered a natural residue of competition and ameliorating homelessness an inefficient endeavor. In Donnie Brasco's words, "Forget about it." Learning-disabled students, gang members, physically handicapped children, and high school dropouts represent the cursed parts of schooling and are grouped under the sign "unproductive." Yet their heterogeneous existence points to their alternative way of being, an experience that can be explained through its contrast with utilitarian work. This does not suggest that these subjects do not want to work, or work hard for that matter. Often, as Paul Willis (1977), Peter McLaren (1999), and Jay MacLeod (1987) have shown, some of the most alienated students are the ones who valorize work. But it goes without saying that their perceived incompatibility with production is responsible for labeling them as part of the accursed share of white capitalism. Bataillean pedagogy speaks up for the oppressed segments of our schools, the heterogeneous other of the workaday world (Pefanis 1991).</p><p>Much has been said about white fascism (see, e.g., McLaren 1995, 1997). For Georges Bataille (1997), fascism's renegade morality represents something of the order of the heterogeneous and warrants critical attention from the perspective of expenditure. In his studies of German and Italian fascism, Bataille writes,</p><p>Opposed to democratic politicians, who represent in different countries the platitude inherent to homogeneous [i.e., productive) society, Mussolini and Hitler immediately stand out as something other. Whatever emotions their actual existence as political agents of evolution provokes, it is impossible to ignore the force that situates them above men, parties and even laws: a force that disrupts the regular course of things, the peaceful but fastidious homogeneity powerless to maintain itself (the fact that laws are broken is only the most obvious sign of the transcendent, heterogeneous nature of fascist action). (128)</p><p>Bataille does not promote fascists and their human atrocities. This is unequivocal, and his unrelenting critique of fascism is well documented (Richardson 1994). What captures his interest is fascism's utmost heterogeneity and extreme authority, which exists for itself before it exists for any useful or productive reasons. To Bataille, the psychological structure of fascism exceeds any conventional ideas about morality involving good and bad. There seems to be no boundary to fascist atrocities. "Evil" just does not seem to suffice as a descriptor. What can we call Adolf Hitler's disgusting campaign of death? What signifier fits the image, the punishment for the crime? Fascism is driven to extreme social hypnosis as a way of concentrating the people's effective flows before it is linked with any productive ends. It is wasteful in all its manifestation, and fascism—etymologically tied to "uniting" or "concentrating" (Bataille 1997, 135)—becomes the hoarding of human energy for the fascist leader. In short, what was originally explorable in terms of expenditure becomes a convenient story about accumulation of power, of energy, and ultimately of homogeneous purpose.</p><p><u><mark>White fascism is</u></mark> not only the enforcement of white territorial control of the means of production. It is also the <u><mark>simultaneous policing of excess</mark>,</u> of curbing expenditure and revelry (not to mention ribaldry) <u>where these may threaten the puritanical code of white govemmentality.</u> How many examples do we have of the carnivalesque activity, outlawry, and social brigandage of student behavior quelled by the repressive power of state or local police? Celebration is confused for lawlessness as the antiriot unit marches into the potlatch to subdue its energy<u>. <mark>School classrooms function under this sign of general repression where quietude is valued over movement and vitality</mark>.</u> Yet shift the scene to a crowded hallway or students on their way to their lockers and the noise deafens even the hard of hearing. White fascism is as much about the control of expenditure as it is the control of the means of production. <u><mark>As an apparatus of whiteness, schools become places of the saving of energy rather than the spending of it.</u></mark> </p><p>It should be plain to see that white capitalism has encoded the colored body as a site of excess. To the white fascist, black students (especially males) have become the site of supersexuality and the Latina body a site of superreproduction. On the other hand, the white body has been constructed as the site of rationality and savings. The white body is almost nonsexualized. This erotic economy of "excess" is linked to a genocidal tendency in the history and geography of whiteness to the extent that white ideology has been involved in consistent crimes against the eroticized other. The oppression of the sexual other is evidence of a certain repression of the expenditure that whiteness represses in itself. That is, whiteness recognizes an excess beyond productivity but fails to squander it, fearing the ecstatic consequences of such a waste. </p><p>It is a vicarious living of sorts that robs whiteness of any life of its own. It is a mitigated, surreptitious experience that partitions the erotic—that is, the irreducible experience—into fantasies rather than participating in its flows. It is a projection of what whiteness fears about itself and foils to understand: a certain excessive drive. This may sound like the eroticization of the racial ized subject represented in the white imaginary. For it seems a standard white discourse to portray the other as a site of excess. However, remaining consistent with Bataille's theory, expenditure is a general economy that inheres in all humans. It is not an economic drive particular to non-Western societies, but one that finds its expression in them, and its repression in whiteness. </p><p><u>Simple life forms excrete waste, factories spew smoke, and stars explode as supernova only to give birth to new star formations from leftover stellar material. Inasmuch as capitalism commodities any and all social spaces for profit, whiteness refuses to divest itself of excess but saves it for further growth, forestalling its inevitable and disastrous expression. Wars, riots, and civil unrest are today's social potlatch. </p><p></u>The theory of expenditure proposed here is a modified <u><mark>Bataillean pedagogy</u></mark>. It represents an alternative theory to production that nevertheless depends on the transformation of labor to realize its luxurious goals. A modified theory of expenditure <u><mark>recognizes the value in school experiences promoting knowledge that serves no master</mark>. But it also realizes that a master currently exists and must be deposed strategically. </u>The double helix of whiteness and capitalism is the conspiratorial first cause. <u>Pushing the contradictions of white capitalism to their extreme exposes the weak joints of the economy. Only then can we approach what Bataille calls "unknowing " or knowledge divorced from utilitarian ends, because it reconciles student interests in work as these evolve in their liberated form and not as they (re)produce certain outcomes.</u> Bataillean pedagogy, as Jurgen Habermas (1987) suggests, appears like a form of fantastic anarchism because it lacks a ratio-nal basis for valuing one form of student work over another (since this is beyond linguistic representation). Moreover, <u>Bataille is involved in a performative contradiction that uses reasoned arguments to reject the metanarrative of rational knowledge</u> (Jay 1993). However, it is also possible to construct <u>Bataille's suggestions</u> not as anarchistic, but as an <u>open</u>ing <u>up</u> of <u><strong>knowledge to all possibilities. Transforming student labor and transgressing utilitarian experience represents the double move out of alienated school knowledge.</p><p></u>The 1ac looks to legalize marijuana as a demand of the human without recognizing the cause of the violence, slaves look for freedom within opioids and the assume the ethicality of the world through their advantages where they probably gunna build farms in the suburbs but justify pollution in the hood. The only ethical demand available to modern politics is that of the Slave and the Savage, the demand for the end of America itself. This cry, born out of the belly of slave ships and the churning vertigo of constitutive genocide, exposes the grammar of the Affirmative’s calls for larger institutional access as a fundamental fortification of White Settler and Slave Master civil society by its diversionary focus on the ethicality of the policies and practices of the United States as opposed to the <u>a priori</u> question its very existence.</p><p>This means that any kind of enviornmental movement fails and reinscribes racial violence – also the positing of warming as a universal risk is self-defeating</p><p><u>Finis </u>Dunaway <u>- </u></strong>assistant professor of history at Trent University in Peterborough, Ontario.- 20<strong>08<u></strong>- Gas Masks, Pogo, and the Ecological Indian: - Earth Day and the Visual Politics of American Environmentalism – A quarterly- project muse</p><p></u>It would be too simple, though, to assign all the blame to the media for this particular framing of environmentalism. During this time, <u>there was a struggle to define the meanings and scope of the environmental movement</u>, a contest over such questions as what constituted an environmental issue and whether or not environmental causes would be linked to broader struggles for social justice. As the geographer Laura Pulido explains,<u> subaltern groups, including African Americans in urban areas and Latino farmworkers, developed a form of politics that situated "environmental concerns within the context of inequality </u>and attempts to alter dominant power arrangements." <u>Mainstream environmental organizations, in contrast, promoted a vision of universal risk and vulnerability, </u>what the sociologist Ulrich Beck would later describe as a "generalized consciousness of affliction." <u>In upholding this conception of environmentalism, these groups tended to ignore environmental hazards—including lead poisoning in the inner cities and the effects of pesticides on farmworkers—that were clearly marked by the unequal distribution of risk. Indeed, mainstream groups often refused to consider such concerns as true environmental issues </u>and concentrated instead on problems that supposedly threatened all Americans equally. By placing iconic images—gas masks, Pogo, and the Ecological Indian—in dialogue with these other environmental struggles, this essay will explore the complex relationship between the mass media and the multiple environmentalisms. Ultimately, both the media and mainstream organizations failed to understand the links between social inequality and the disproportionate experience of risk among racialized minorities.4 Likewise, while some Earth Day organizers sought to focus on power relations and corporate responsibility for environmental degradation, the media instead emphasized collective guilt: everyone was blamed for causing pollution. <u>Popular imagery stressed that individual decisions and actions—especially those related to consumption and reproduction—led to the environmental crisis</u>. According to these explanations, both a growing population and increasing affluence inevitably resulted in widespread pollution. If "Americans" (almost always described in these reports as a monolithic, undifferentiated group) would change their actions in daily life—if they would have fewer children and consume less—then they could overcome this crisis. This focus on personal responsibility obscured other explanations that considered the social origins of environmental degradation. <u>The scientist Barry Commoner, </u>in The Closing Circle and other publications, <u>argued that decisions made by corporate and government leaders accounted for most of the nation's environmental problems.</u> In particular, Commoner focused on the shift to "new productive technologies" and other "counterecological pattern[s] of growth" [End Page 69] after World War II. From the introduction of synthetic fibers and nonreturnable bottles to the proliferation of pesticides and the massive allocation of funds to the interstate highway system (and with it, the underwriting of the automobile industry rather than public transportation), Commoner detailed the effects of these changes implemented by powerful public and private institutions. "The earth is polluted," he concluded, "neither because man is some kind of especially dirty animal nor because there are too many of us. The fault lies with human society—with the ways in which society has elected to win, distribute, and use the wealth that has been extracted by human labor from the planet's resources. Once the social origins of the crisis become clear, we can begin to design appropriate social actions to resolve it." For Commoner, these solutions would entail a shift away from counterecological technologies, the cultivation of a more democratic form of science attuned to the environmental consequences of modern industry, and the recognition that the burden of environmental risk often fell on poor and minority communities. <u>Commoner's analysis of the causes of the environmental crisis and his agenda for social change echoed the claims of some environmental activists, especially those involved with subaltern struggles. Nevertheless, these perspectives would be submerged by the proliferation of imagery that emphasized individual responsibility.5 Even though the media stressed the role of the individual, the period surrounding Earth Day did lead to major environmental reforms</u>: from the founding of the Environmental Protection Agency to the passage of the Clean Air Act and other legislation, <u>these policies established the main features of the environmental regulatory state and expressed confidence in the government's ability to solve social problems. Thus, we find a paradox embedded in the environmental politics of the period: the regulatory state expanded while, simultaneously, the visual media emphasized individual responsibility. To end pollution, Americans were told to look both to the federal government and to their own actions in daily life. This essay will explain how these seemingly opposing trends actually reinforced one another and how they bequeathed a problematic legacy to U.S. environmental politics: one that successfully lowered lead levels in the ambient environment but did not strive to protect inner-city children from the hazards of lead paint; one that banned DDT but did not confront the dangers other pesticides posed to farmworkers; one that appeared to enact race-neutral policies but that ultimately intensified environmental inequalities throughout the United S<strong>tates.</p><p></u>The affirmative’s form of political change is nothing but a solidarity action used to reify the current structures of white supremacy that produces us as political subjects who are spectators, complacent with current structures unable to create change</p><p>El Kilombo 2007</p><p></strong>(El Kilombo Intergalactico, people of color collective made up of students, migrants, and other community members in Durham, North Carolina, “Beyond Resistance Everything: An Interview with Subcomandante Insurgente Marcos” DM)</p><p>The following lines are the product of intense collective discussions that took place within what is today El Kilombo Intergaláctico during much of 2003 and 2004. <u>These discussions occurred during the advent of the Iraq War and our efforts </u>(though ultimately ineffective) <u>to stop it</u>. <u>During those months it became very clear to us that the Left in the United States was at a crossroads, and much of what we had participated in under the banner of “activism” no longer provided an adequate response to our current conditions</u>. In our efforts to forge a new path, w<u>e found that an old friend—the Ejército Zapatista de Liberación Nacio- nal (Zapatista Army of National Liberation, EZLN)—was already taking enormous strides to move toward a politics adequate to our time, and that it was thus necessary to attempt an evaluation of Zapatismo that would in turn be adequate to the real ‘event’ of their appearance</u>. That is, <u>despite the fresh air that the Zapatista uprising had blown into the US political scene since 1994, we began to feel that even the inspiration of Zapatismo had been quickly con- tained through its insertion into a well-worn and untenable narrative: Zapatismo was another of many faceless and indifferent “third world” movements that demanded and deserved solidarity from leftists in the “global north.” From our position as an organization composed in large part by people of color in the United States, we viewed this focus on “solidarity” as the foreign policy equivalent of “white guilt,” quite distinct from any authentic impulse toward, or recognition of, the necessity for radical social change</u>. The <u>notion of “solidarity” that still pervades much of the Left in the U.S. has continually served an intensely conservative political agenda that dresses itself in the radical rhetoric of the latest rebellion in the “darker nations” while carefully maintaining political action at a distance from our own daily lives, thus producing a political subject </u>(the solidarity provider<u>) that more closely resembles a spectator or voyeur </u>(to the suffering of others) <u>than a participant or active agent, while simultaneously working to reduce the solidarity recipient to a mere object </u>(of our pity and mismatched socks). At both ends of this relationship, <u>the process of solidarity ensures that subjects and political action never meet; in this way it serves to make change an a priori impossibility</u>. In other words, <u>this practice of solidarity urges us to participate in its perverse logic by accepting the narrative that power tells us about itself: that those who could make change don’t need it and that those who need change can’t make it</u>. To the extent that human solidarity has a future, this logic and practice do not! For us, Zapatismo was (and continues to be) unique exactly because it has provided us with the elements to shatter this tired schema. <u>It has inspired in us the ability, and impressed upon us the necessity, of always viewing our- selves as dignified political subjects with desires, needs, and projects worthy of struggle.</u> With the publication of The Sixth Declaration of the Lacandón Jungle in June of 2005, the Zapatistas have made<u> it even clearer that we must move be- yond appeals to this stunted form of solidarity, and they present us with a far more difficult challenge: that wherever in the world we may be located, we must become “companer@s” (neither followers nor leaders) in a truly global struggle to change the world.</u> As a direct response to this call, this analysis is our attempt to read Zapatismo<strong> as providing us with the rough draft of a manual for contemporary political action that eventually must be written by us all. </p><p>The black body is the site of social death par excellence, having become dead by a 700-year injunction barring its subjectivity. Social death is a condition of existence and not some avoidable impact—how we relate to this condition is all that is important. </p><p>Wilderson- 2002</p><p></strong>Frank Wilderson- The Prison Slave as Hegemony's (Silent) Scandal-Presented a t #<u>Imprisoned Intellectuals # Conference Brown University, April 13th 2002</p><p>Civil society is not a terrain intended for the Black subject. It is coded as waged and wages are White</u>. Civil society is the terrain where hegemony is produced, contested, mapped. And th e invitat ion to p articipate in hegemony's gestures of influence, leadership, and consent is not ext ended to t he unwaged. We live in the world , but ex ist out side of civil s ociety. <u>This structurally impossible position is a paradox, because the Black subject, the slave, is vital to political economy: s/he kick-starts capital at its genesis and rescues it from its over-accumulation crisis at its end. But Marxism has no account of this phenomenal birth and life-saving role played by the Black subject:<strong> </u></strong>from Marx<u><strong> </u></strong>and Gr amsci we have con sistent s ilence. In taking Foucau lt to ta sk for a ssum ing a univ ersal s ubject in r evolt ag ainst d iscipline, in the same s pirit in which I have t aken Gr amsci to ta sk for as suming a u niversal sub ject, the subject of civil societ y in revolt a gainst capita l, Joy Jam es writes : The U.S. carceral network kills, however, and in its prisons, it kills more blacks than any other ethnic group. American prisons constitute an "outside" in U.S. political life. In fact, our society displays waves of concentric outside circles with increasing distances from bourgeois self-policing. The state routinely polices the14 unassim ilable in the hell of lockdow n, deprivat ion tanks , control units , and holes for political prisoners (Resisting State Violence 1996: 34 ) But this peculiar preoccupation is not Gramsci's bailiwick. His concern is with White folks; or with folks in a White (ned) enough subject position that they are confronted by, or threat ened by th e remova l of, a wag e -- be it monetary or social<u>. But Black subjectivity itself disarticulates the Gramscian dream as a ubiquitous emancipatory strategy, because Gramsci</u>, like most White activists, and radical American movements like the prison abolition movement, <u>has no theory of the unwaged, no solidarity with the slave If we are to take Fanon at his word </u>when he writes, #<u>Decolonization<strong>, which sets out to change the order of the world</strong>, is, obviously, a program of complete disorder<strong> # (37) </strong>then we must accept the fact that no other body functions in the Imaginary, the Symbolic, or the Real so completely as a repository of complete disorder as the Black body. Blackness is the site of absolute dereliction at the level of the Real, for in its magnetizing of bullets the Black body functions as the map of gratuitous violence through which civil society is possible: namely, those other bodies for which violence is, or can be, contingent. </u>Blackness is the site of absolute dereliction at the level of the Symbolic, for <u>Blackness in America generates no categories for the chromosome of History, no data for the categories of Immigration or Sovereignty;<strong> it is an experience without analog # a past, without a heritage. </strong>Blackness is the site of absolute dereliction<strong> at the level of t he Imaginary for </strong>#whoever says #rape # says Black<strong>, # (Fanon) , </strong>whoever says #prison # says Black<strong>, and whoever says #AIDS # says Black </u></strong>(Sexton) # the #Negro is a phobogenic object # (Fanon). Indeed &a phobogenic object &a past without a heritage &the map of gratuitous violence &a program of complete disorder. <u><strong>But whereas </strong>this realization is<strong>, and should be </strong>cause for alarm, it should not be cause for lament,<strong> or worse, disavowal # not at least, </strong>for a true revolutionary<strong>, or for a truly revolutionary movement </u></strong>such as prison a bolition. 15 <u>If a social movement is to be neither social democratic, nor Marxist, in terms of the structure of its political desire then it should grasp the invitation to assume the positionality of subjects of social death<strong> that present themselves; and, if we are to be honest with ourselves we must admit that </strong>the “Negro “ has been inviting Whites, and as well as civil society #s junior partners, to the dance of social death for hundreds of years, but few have wanted to learn the steps. They have been<strong>, and remain today </strong># even in the most anti-racist movements,<strong> </u></strong>like the prison abolition movement # <u>invested elsewhere. This is not to say that all oppositional political desire today is pro-White, but it is to say that it is almost always “anti-Black” which is to say it will not dance with death. Black liberation,<strong> as a prospect</strong>, makes radicalism more dangerous <strong>to the U.S. Not because it raises the specter of some alternative polity (like socialism, or community control of existing resources) </strong>but because its condition of possibility as well as its gesture of resistance functions as a negative dialectic: a politics of refusal and a refus al to affirm , a program of complete disorder. One mus t embrace its disorder, its in coherence and allow oneself to be elaborated by it, if indeed one's politics are to be underwritten by a desire to take this country down.<strong> </u></strong>If this is not the desire which underwrites one #s politics then through what strategy of legitimation is the word #prison # being linked t o the wo rd #abolition #? Wh at ar e this movem ent #s lines of po litical a ccount abilit y? There #s nothing foreign, frightening, or even unpracticed about the embrace of disorder and incoherence. The desire to be embraced, and elaborated, by disorder and incoherence is not anathema in and of itself: no one, for example, has ever been known to say #gee-whiz, if only my orgasms would end a little sooner, or maybe not come at all. # But few so-called radicals desire to be embraced, and elaborated, by the disorder and incoherence of Blackness # and the state of politica l movemen ts in A merica to day is ma rked by t his very N egroph obogen isis: #gee-whiz, if only Black rage could be more coherent, or maybe not come at all. # Perhaps there #s something more terrifying about the joy of Black, then there is about the joy of sex (unless one is talking sex wit h a Negr o). Perhaps coalitions today p refer to remain in- orgas mic in the fa ce of civilsociety # with hegemony as a handy prophylactic, just in case. But if, through this stasis, or paralysis , they tr y to do t he work of pr ison a bolit ion # that work will fail; because it is always work from a position of coherence (i.e. the worker) on behalf of a position of incoherence, the Black subject, or prison slave. In this way, social formations on the Left remain blind to the contradictions of coalitions bet ween worker s and s laves. T hey remain coalitions opera ting with in the logic of civil society; and function less as revolutionary promises and more as crowding out scenarios of Black antagonisms # they simply feed our frustration. Whereas the positionality of the worker # be s/he a factory worker demanding a monetary wage or an immigrant or White woman demanding a social wage # gestures toward the reconfiguration of civil society, the positionality of the Black subject # be s/he a prison-slave or a prison-slave-in-waiting # gestures toward the disconfiguration of civil society: from the coherence of civil society, t he Black subject beckons with the in coherence of civil war. <u>A civil war which reclaims Blackness not as a positive value, but as a politically enabling site, to quote Fanon, of “absolute dereliction“: a scandal which rends civil society asunder. Civil war, then, becomes that unthought, but never forgotten understudy of hegemony. A Black specter waiting in the wings, an endless antagonism that cannot be satisfied (via reform or reparation) but must nonetheless be pursued to the death.</p><p>VIEW THE 1AC AS UNETHICAL</p></u>
null
Off
null
57,104
304
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,579
Federalism’s resilient
Bulman-Pozen 2014 (Jessica, “From Sovereignty and Process to Administration and Politics: The Afterlife of American Federalism,” 123 Yale L.J. 1920)
Bulman-Pozen 2014 (Jessica, “From Sovereignty and Process to Administration and Politics: The Afterlife of American Federalism,” 123 Yale L.J. 1920)
Federalism scholarship has largely resisted the easy narrative of federal aggrandizement at the expense of the states Acknowledging the federal government has assumed regulatory authority over ever more domains the literature has argued this signifies not federalism's demise but rather a change in the mechanisms that safeguard the place of states in our system. process federalisms have recast forces traditionally envisioned as threats to a robust federalism as its guardians: Congress and the President, Democratic and Republican parties and the administrative state have each been given a new role. these recastings they retain its core commitment to state autonomy and distinctive interests. Novel forms of state-federal integration are means of preserving state-federal separation the integration of state and federal actors safeguards the separation of state and federal action.
Federalism has largely resisted the easy narrative of federal aggrandizement at the expense of the states. the literature has argued this signifies not federalism's demise but rather a change in the mechanisms that safeguard the place of states in our system. Congress and the President retain its core commitment to state autonomy Novel forms of integration are means of preserving state-federal separation
Federalism scholarship in the latter half of the twentieth century and the beginning of the twenty-first has largely resisted the easy narrative of federal aggrandizement at the expense of the states. Acknowledging that the federal government has assumed regulatory authority over ever more domains, the literature has argued that this signifies not federalism's demise but rather a change in the mechanisms that safeguard the place of states in our system. A variety of process federalisms have recast forces traditionally envisioned as threats to a robust federalism as its guardians: Congress and the President, the Democratic and Republican parties, and the administrative state have each, in turn, been given a new role. But even as these recastings shed dual federalism's insistence on judicial review and clearly delineated spheres of state and federal authority, they retain its core commitment to state autonomy and distinctive interests. Novel forms of state-federal integration are thus treated as means of preserving state-federal separation: the integration of state and federal actors safeguards the separation of state and federal action.
1,153
<h4>Federalism’s resilient</h4><p><strong>Bulman-Pozen 2014 <u>(Jessica, “From Sovereignty and Process to Administration and Politics: The Afterlife of American Federalism,” 123 Yale L.J. 1920)</p><p></strong><mark>Federalism</mark> scholarship</u> in the latter half of the twentieth century and the beginning of the twenty-first <u><mark>has largely <strong>resisted the easy narrative</strong> of federal</mark> <mark>aggrandizement at the expense of the states</u>.</mark> <u>Acknowledging </u>that <u>the federal government has assumed regulatory authority over ever more domains</u>, <u><mark>the literature has argued</u></mark> that <u><mark>this signifies not federalism's demise</u> <u><strong>but rather a change in the mechanisms that safeguard the</mark> <mark>place of states in our system.</u></strong></mark> A variety of <u>process federalisms have</u> <u>recast forces traditionally envisioned as threats to a robust federalism as its guardians<strong>: <mark>Congress and the President</mark>,</u></strong> the <u><strong>Democratic and Republican parties</u></strong>, <u><strong>and the administrative state</u></strong> <u>have each</u>, in turn, <u>been given a new role. </u>But even as <u>these recastings</u> shed dual federalism's insistence on judicial review and clearly delineated spheres of state and federal authority, <u>they <mark>retain its</mark> <strong><mark>core commitment to state autonomy</mark> and distinctive interests.</u></strong> <u><mark>Novel forms of</mark> state-federal <mark>integration are</mark> </u>thus treated as <u><strong><mark>means of</mark> <mark>preserving state-federal separation</u></strong></mark>: <u><strong>the integration of state and federal actors safeguards the separation of state and federal action.</p></u></strong>
null
Off
Federalism
30,484
43
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,580
Cooperative federalism’s resilient
Greve 2000 (Michael, John G. Searle Scholar, American Enterprise Institute; Ph.D. (Government) Cornell University, 1987, “Against Cooperative Federalism” Mississippi Law Journal, 70 Miss. L.J. 557, Lexis)
Greve 2000 (Michael, John G. Searle Scholar, American Enterprise Institute; Ph.D. (Government) Cornell University, 1987, “Against Cooperative Federalism” Mississippi Law Journal, 70 Miss. L.J. 557, Lexis)
Cooperative federalism is enormously resilient and self-stabilizing. The range of conflict within the system is defined by the participant-beneficiaries' fight over the terms of cooperation. State and local governments will complain about federal imposition; national interest groups and congressional patrons will complain about state shirking and non-compliance. Furor over unfunded mandates produces more money and less onerous federal conditions; interest group complaints leads to the re-categorization of federal programs Either way, the system returns to its bargaining equilibrium cooperative arrangements are virtually immune to political reform In Germany and in the United States, cooperative federalism came under challenge during periods of serious economic malaise and manifest civic alienation The record strongly suggests that cooperative federalism is impregnable even under those disadvantageous conditions.
Cooperative federalism is enormously resilient and self-stabilizing Furor over unfunded mandates produces more money and less onerous federal conditions; interest group complaints leads to the re-categorization of federal programs system returns to its bargaining equilibrium cooperative arrangements are virtually immune to political reform cooperative federalism came under challenge during periods of serious economic malaise and manifest civic alienation The record strongly suggests that cooperative federalism is impregnable even under those
Cooperative federalism is enormously resilient and, moreover, self-stabilizing. The range of conflict within the system is defined by the participant-beneficiaries' fight over the terms of cooperation. State and local governments will complain about unfunded mandates and federal imposition; national interest groups and their congressional patrons will complain about state shirking and non-compliance. Furor over unfunded mandates produces more money and less onerous federal conditions; interest group complaints over the states' failure to use federal block grants for their intended purposes leads to the re-categorization of federal programs. n150 Either way, the system returns to its bargaining equilibrium, typically at a higher level of aggregate spending.¶ Under ordinary political conditions, cooperative arrangements are virtually immune to political reform. In Germany and in the United States, cooperative federalism came under challenge during periods of serious economic malaise and manifest civic alienation, coupled with exogenous shocks (re-unification and European integration in Germany's case, and the ascent of a determined, ideological administration in the United States). The record strongly suggests that cooperative federalism is impregnable even under those disadvantageous conditions.
1,315
<h4>Cooperative federalism’s resilient</h4><p><strong>Greve 2000</strong> <u><strong>(Michael, John G. Searle Scholar, American Enterprise Institute; Ph.D. (Government) Cornell University, 1987, “Against Cooperative Federalism” Mississippi Law Journal, 70 Miss. L.J. 557, Lexis)</p><p></strong><mark>Cooperative federalism is <strong>enormously resilient</strong> and</u></mark>, moreover, <u><mark>self-stabilizing</mark>. The range of conflict within the system is defined by the participant-beneficiaries' fight over the terms of cooperation. State and local governments will complain</u> <u>about </u>unfunded mandates and <u>federal imposition; national interest groups and</u> their <u>congressional patrons will complain about state shirking and non-compliance. <mark>Furor over unfunded mandates produces more money and less onerous federal conditions; interest group complaints</u></mark> over the states' failure to use federal block grants for their intended purposes <u><mark>leads to the re-categorization of federal programs</u></mark>. n150 <u>Either way, the <mark>system returns to its bargaining equilibrium</u></mark>, typically at a higher level of aggregate spending.¶ Under ordinary political conditions, <u><mark>cooperative arrangements are <strong>virtually immune</strong> to political reform</u></mark>. <u>In Germany and in the United States, <mark>cooperative federalism came under challenge during periods of serious economic malaise and manifest civic alienation</u></mark>, coupled with exogenous shocks (re-unification and European integration in Germany's case, and the ascent of a determined, ideological administration in the United States). <u><mark>The record <strong>strongly suggests</strong> that cooperative federalism is <strong>impregnable</strong> even under those </mark>disadvantageous conditions.</p></u>
null
Off
Federalism
56,547
27
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,581
Marijuana doesn’t bring in much cartel money- their cards are based on total fabrications
Bond et al 2010
Bond et al 2010 (Brittany M., economist at the U.S. Department of Commerce; Jonathan Caulkins, H. Guyford Stever Professorship of Operations Research and Public Policy at Carnegie Mellon; Beau Kilmer and Peter Reuter, Reducing Drug Trafficking Revenues and Violence in Mexico, http://www.rand.org/content/dam/rand/pubs/occasional_papers/2010/RAND_OP325.pdf)
violence in Mexico plays a prominent role in debates about marijuana legalization in the United States. Often, big numbers of dubious origin are tossed around with little thought one analysis estimated that 60 percent of all Mexican DTO drug revenue comes from exporting marijuana the figures have been repeated in the popular press The figure appears to come from multiplying a $525-per-pound2 markup by an estimate from the Mexican government that 35 million pounds were produced in Mexico and then rounding up. no data support the claim that U.S. users consume 35 million pounds let alone that they consume this much marijuana from Mexico. This is three times the UNODC upper bound for total U.S. consumption
violence in Mexico plays a prominent role in debates about marijuana big numbers of dubious origin are tossed around one analysis estimated that 60 percent of DTO drug revenue comes from marijuana no data support the claim that U.S. users consume 35 million pounds let alone that they consume this much marijuana from Mexico This is three times the UNODC upper bound for total U.S. consumption
Not surprisingly, violence in Mexico plays a prominent role in debates about marijuana legalization in the United States. Often, big numbers of dubious origin are tossed around in drug policy discussions with little thought and, frankly, little consequence. Some U.S. government reports suggest that Mexican and Colombian DTOs combined earn $18 billion–$39 billion annually in wholesale drug proceeds (NDIC, 2008d), and one analysis even estimated that 60 percent of all Mexican DTO drug revenue comes from exporting marijuana (ONDCP, 2006). Legalization advocates seize on such figures to supplement their traditional arguments, and the figures have been repeated in the popular press, with even respectable news sources claiming that “the Mexican cartels could be selling $20 billion worth of marijuana in the U.S. market each year” (Fainaru and Booth, 2009). The $20 billion figure appears to come from multiplying a $525-per-pound2 markup by an estimate from the Mexican government that 35 million pounds were produced in Mexico and then rounding up. However, no data support the claim that U.S. users consume 35 million pounds (~16,000 metric tons [MT]) per year, let alone that they consume this much marijuana from Mexico. (This point is addressed in detail in Chapter Three.) This is three times the United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime’s (UNODC) (2009) upper bound for total U.S. consumption and nearly four times the amount estimated by the Drug Enforcement Administration (DEA) (DASC, 2002).
1,506
<h4>Marijuana doesn’t bring in much cartel money- their cards are based on total fabrications</h4><p><strong>Bond et al 2010</strong> (Brittany M., economist at the U.S. Department of Commerce; Jonathan Caulkins, H. Guyford Stever Professorship of Operations Research and Public Policy at Carnegie Mellon; Beau Kilmer and Peter Reuter, Reducing Drug Trafficking Revenues and Violence in Mexico, http://www.rand.org/content/dam/rand/pubs/occasional_papers/2010/RAND_OP325.pdf)</p><p>Not surprisingly, <u><mark>violence in Mexico plays a prominent role in debates about marijuana</mark> legalization in the United States. Often, <mark>big numbers of dubious origin are tossed around</u></mark> in drug policy discussions <u>with little thought</u> and, frankly, little consequence. Some U.S. government reports suggest that Mexican and Colombian DTOs combined earn $18 billion–$39 billion annually in wholesale drug proceeds (NDIC, 2008d), and <u><mark>one analysis</u></mark> even <u><mark>estimated that 60 percent of</mark> all Mexican <mark>DTO drug revenue comes from</mark> exporting <mark>marijuana</u></mark> (ONDCP, 2006). Legalization advocates seize on such figures to supplement their traditional arguments, and <u>the figures have been repeated in the popular press</u>, with even respectable news sources claiming that “the Mexican cartels could be selling $20 billion worth of marijuana in the U.S. market each year” (Fainaru and Booth, 2009). <u>The</u> $20 billion <u>figure appears to come from multiplying a $525-per-pound2 markup by an estimate from the Mexican government that 35 million pounds were produced in Mexico and then rounding up.</u> However, <u><strong><mark>no data support the claim</u></strong> <u>that U.S. users consume 35 million pounds</u></mark> (~16,000 metric tons [MT]) per year, <u><mark>let alone that they consume this much marijuana from Mexico</mark>.</u> (This point is addressed in detail in Chapter Three.) <u><strong><mark>This is three times</u></strong> <u><strong>the</u></strong></mark> United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime’s (<u><strong><mark>UNODC</u></strong></mark>) (2009) <u><strong><mark>upper bound for total U.S. consumption</u></strong></mark> and nearly four times the amount estimated by the Drug Enforcement Administration (DEA) (DASC, 2002).</p>
null
Off
Cartels
55,187
7
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,582
Can’t solve- shift and profits in legal economy and gray markets
Krache-Morris 2013
Krache-Morris 2013 (Evelyn, International Secretary Program Fellow at the Belfer Center for Science and International affairs at Harvard University, “Think Again: Mexican Drug Cartels”, http://www.foreignpolicy.com/articles/2013/12/03/think_again_mexican_drug_cartels)
Legalization has become an increasingly popular proposal But because DTOs are dealing in far more than just illegal drugs, the disappearance of one revenue stream would not eradicate the cartels or decisively erode their power. Even if the cartels were dependent on drug money, which they aren't, the idea that legalization is a binary switch that would cut off profits from the drug trade is fundamentally flawed In marijuana, "legalization" implies wide availability and fairly easy access, but it is highly unlikely that the U.S. government would remove restrictions on drugs like ecstasy or heroin, leaving the cartels' business in those narcotics intact even legitimate drugs can spur illicit trade if they are in high demand but the supply is tightly controlled restrictions gave rise to a thriving black market Licit drugs can also create highly profitable arbitrage opportunities for enterprising criminals if the laws that govern their distribution differ from state to state, as would likely be the case if marijuana or other drugs were widely legalized because of differing state tax rates, the opportunity for profit is substantial
DTOs are in far more than illegal drugs, one revenue stream would not erode their power. Even if the cartels were dependent it is unlikely the U.S. would remove restrictions on ecstasy or heroin, leaving business intact even legitimate drugs spur illicit trade if supply is controlled Licit drugs can also create arbitrage opportunities if the laws differ state to state, as would be the case opportunity for profit is substantial
Hardly. Legalization has become an increasingly popular, if still controversial, proposal among those who think that the costs of the war on drugs have overwhelmed the benefits, including some Central and South American leaders, like Guatemalan President Otto Pérez Molina. But because DTOs are dealing in far more than just illegal drugs, the disappearance of one revenue stream would not eradicate the cartels or decisively erode their power. Even if the cartels were dependent on drug money, which they aren't, the idea that legalization is a binary switch that would cut off profits from the drug trade is fundamentally flawed. In the context of drugs like marijuana, "legalization" implies wide availability and fairly easy access, but it is highly unlikely that the U.S. government would remove all, or even many, restrictions on drugs like ecstasy or heroin, leaving the cartels' business in those narcotics intact. What's more, even legitimate drugs can spur illicit trade if they are in high demand but the supply is tightly controlled. Drugs like oxycodone, a highly addictive painkiller, are legally manufactured and sold in the United States, but "oxy" is strictly regulated under Schedule II of the 1970 Controlled Substances Act. Those restrictions gave rise to a thriving black market in the drug, with prices reaching as high as $150 per pill. Licit drugs can also create highly profitable arbitrage opportunities for enterprising criminals if the laws that govern their distribution differ from state to state, as would likely be the case if marijuana or other drugs were widely legalized. Cigarettes are legal, yet interstate cigarette smuggling makes a great deal of money for organized crime; because of differing state tax rates, the opportunity for profit is substantial. Virginia, for example, which has among the lowest cigarette taxes in the nation, is grappling with increased criminal activity, because of trafficking to high-tax states like New York and New Jersey. (And Virginia's hardly the only one; other states, like Texas, have even seen armed hijackings of cigarette trucks.)
2,110
<h4>Can’t solve- shift and profits in legal economy and gray markets</h4><p><strong>Krache-Morris 2013</strong> (Evelyn, International Secretary Program Fellow at the Belfer Center for Science and International affairs at Harvard University, “Think Again: Mexican Drug Cartels”, http://www.foreignpolicy.com/articles/2013/12/03/think_again_mexican_drug_cartels)</p><p>Hardly. <u>Legalization has become an increasingly popular</u>, if still controversial, <u>proposal</u> among those who think that the costs of the war on drugs have overwhelmed the benefits, including some Central and South American leaders, like Guatemalan President Otto Pérez Molina. <u>But because <mark>DTOs are </mark>dealing <mark>in far more than </mark>just <mark>illegal drugs, </mark>the disappearance of <mark>one revenue stream would not </mark>eradicate the cartels or decisively <mark>erode their power.</u></mark> <u><mark>Even if the cartels were dependent </mark>on drug money, which they aren't, the idea that legalization is a binary switch that would cut off profits from the drug trade is fundamentally flawed</u>. <u>In</u> the context of drugs like <u>marijuana, "legalization" implies wide availability and fairly easy access, but <mark>it is</mark> highly <mark>unlikely </mark>that <mark>the U.S.</mark> government <mark>would remove</u></mark> all, or even many, <u><mark>restrictions on </mark>drugs like <mark>ecstasy or heroin, leaving </mark>the cartels' <mark>business </mark>in those narcotics <mark>intact</u></mark>. What's more, <u><mark>even legitimate drugs </mark>can <mark>spur illicit trade if </mark>they are in high demand but the <mark>supply is </mark>tightly <mark>controlled</u></mark>. Drugs like oxycodone, a highly addictive painkiller, are legally manufactured and sold in the United States, but "oxy" is strictly regulated under Schedule II of the 1970 Controlled Substances Act. Those <u>restrictions gave rise to a thriving black market</u> in the drug, with prices reaching as high as $150 per pill. <u><mark>Licit drugs can also create </mark>highly profitable <mark>arbitrage opportunities</mark> for enterprising criminals <mark>if the laws </mark>that govern their distribution <mark>differ </mark>from <mark>state to state, as would </mark>likely <mark>be the case </mark>if marijuana or other drugs were widely legalized</u>. Cigarettes are legal, yet interstate cigarette smuggling makes a great deal of money for organized crime; <u>because of differing state tax rates, the <mark>opportunity for profit is substantial</u></mark>. Virginia, for example, which has among the lowest cigarette taxes in the nation, is grappling with<strong> increased criminal activity, because of trafficking to high-tax states like New York and New Jersey. (And Virginia's hardly the only one; other states, like Texas, have even seen armed hijackings of cigarette trucks.)</p></strong>
null
Off
Cartels
45,890
62
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,583
Warming’s inevitable—newest computer modeling prove—their studies don’t assume ocean heat uptake
Science 2.0 11-25 http://www.science20.com/news_articles/even_if_emissions_are_halted_carbon_dioxide_could_warm_earth_centuries-125099
Science 2.0 11-25 News Staff citing Thomas Frölicher, postdoctoral researcher in Princeton's Program in Atmospheric and Oceanic Sciences and Jorge Sarmiento, the George J. Magee Professor of Geoscience and Geological Engineering, Princeton University; “Even If Emissions Are Halted, Carbon Dioxide Could Warm Earth For Centuries” Science 2.0; November 25, 2013; http://www.science20.com/news_articles/even_if_emissions_are_halted_carbon_dioxide_could_warm_earth_centuries-125099
Because carbon dioxide emissions persist for a long time, even a sudden halt today means the carbon dioxide already in Earth's atmosphere could continue to warm our planet for hundreds of years, according to a numerical model which suggests that it might take a lot less carbon than previously thought to reach the global temperature scientists deem unsafe.¶ The researchers simulated an Earth on which, all carbon dioxide emissions suddenly stopped. Scientists commonly use the scenario of emissions screeching to a stop to gauge the heat-trapping staying power of carbon dioxide Within a millennium of this simulated shutoff, the carbon itself faded steadily with 40 percent absorbed by Earth's oceans and landmasses within 20 years and 80 percent soaked up at the end of the 1,000 years.¶ By itself, such a decrease of atmospheric carbon dioxide should lead to cooling But the heat trapped by the carbon dioxide took a divergent track on their computer. ¶ In a numerical model, while carbon dioxide steadily dissipates, the absorption of heat the oceans decreases especially in the polar oceans such as off of Antarctica This effect has not been accounted for in existing research. ¶ The lingering warming effect the researchers found, however, suggests that the 2-degree point may be reached with much less carbon, previous research did not account for a gradual reduction in the oceans' ability to absorb heat from the atmosphere, particularly the polar oceans, Although carbon dioxide steadily dissipates, Frölicher and his co-authors were able to see that the oceans that remove heat from the atmosphere gradually take up less. Eventually, the residual heat offsets the cooling that occurred due to dwindling amounts of carbon dioxide Previous models have not really represented that very well," Frölicher said.¶ "Scientists have thought that the temperature stays constant or declines once emissions stop, but now we show that the possibility of a temperature increase can not be excluded," Frölicher said. "This is illustrative of how difficult it may be to reverse climate change — we stop the emissions, but still get an increase in the global mean temperature." I write out of a personal existential context. This context is a profound source of knowledge connected to my "raced" body I write from a place of lived embodied experience, a site of exposure. In philosophy, the only thing that we are taught to "expose" is a weak argument, a fallacy, or someone's "inferior" reasoning power. The embodied self is bracketed and deemed irrelevant to theory, superfluous and cumbersome in one's search for truth. It is best, or so we are told, to reason from nowhere. Hence, the white philosopher/author presumes to speak for all of "us" without the slightest mention of his or her "raced" identity. Self-consciously writing as a white male philosopher, Crispin Sartwell observes: Left to my own devices, I disappear as an author. That is the "whiteness" of my authorship. This whiteness of authorship is, for us, a form of authority; to speak (apparently) from nowhere, for everyone, is empowering, though one wields power here only by becoming lost to oneself. But such an authorship and authority is also pleasurable: it yields the pleasure of self-forgetting or [End Page 215] apparent transcendence of the mundane and the particular, and the pleasure of power expressed in the "comprehension" of a range of materials. To theorize the Black body one must "turn to the [Black] body as the radix for interpreting racial experience 1 It is important to note that this particular strategy also functions as a lens through which to theorize and critique whiteness; for the Black body's "racial" experience is fundamentally linked to the oppressive modalities of the "raced" white body there is no denying that my own "racial" experiences or the social performances of whiteness can become objects of critical reflection my objective is to describe and theorize situations where the Black body's subjectivity, its lived reality, is reduced to instantiations of the white imaginary, resulting in what I refer to as "the phenomenological return of the Black body. 2 These instantiations are embedded within and evolve out of the complex social and historical interstices of whites' efforts at self-construction through complex acts of erasure vis-à-vis Black people Mythification is the replacement of history with a surrogate ideology of [white] elevation or [Black] demotion along a scale of human value whiteness operates rhetorically and ideologically in public political discourse. First, the ideology of white privilege maintains its invisibility through rhetorical silence. Rhetorical silence protects the invisibility of whiteness because it both reflects and sustains the assumption that to be white is the "natural condition," the assumed norm. Rhetorical silence about whiteness preserves material white privilege because it masks its existence and makes the denial of white privilege plausible. Ideological systems are made up of both presences and absences
Because carbon dioxide emissions persist for a long time, even a sudden halt today means the carbon dioxide already in Earth's atmosphere could continue to warm our planet for hundreds of years, Scientists commonly use the scenario of emissions screeching to a stop to gauge the heat-trapping staying power of carbon dioxide. Within a millennium of this simulated shutoff, the carbon itself faded steadily with 40 percent absorbed by Earth's oceans and landmasses within 20 years and 80 percent soaked up at the end of the 1,000 years.¶ In a numerical model, while carbon dioxide steadily dissipates, the absorption of heat the oceans decreases This effect has not been accounted for in existing research ¶ The lingering warming effect the researchers found, however, suggests that the 2-degree point may be reached with much less carbon previous research did not account for a gradual reduction in the oceans' ability to absorb heat from the atmosphere, particularly the polar oceans, "This is illustrative of how difficult it may be to reverse climate change — we stop the emissions, but still get an increase in the global mean temperature." Yancy 05 I write out of a personal existential context. This context is a profound source of knowledge connected to my "raced" body The embodied self is bracketed and deemed irrelevant to theory, superfluous and cumbersome in one's search for truth. It is best, or so we are told, to reason from nowhere. Hence, the white philosopher/author presumes to speak for all of "us" without the slightest mention of his or her "raced" identity. Self-consciously writing as a white male philosopher, Left to my own devices, I disappear as an author. That is the "whiteness" of my authorship. This whiteness of authorship is, for us, a form of authority; to speak (apparently) from nowhere, for everyone, is empowering, though one wields power here only by becoming lost to oneself. But such an authorship and authority is also pleasurable: it yields the pleasure of self-forgetting or ] apparent transcendence of the mundane and the particular, and the pleasure of power expressed in the "comprehension" of a range of materials. To theorize the Black body one must "turn to the [Black] body as the radix for interpreting racial experience It is important to note that this particular strategy also functions as a lens through which to theorize and critique whiteness; for the Black body's "racial" experience is fundamentally linked to the oppressive modalities of the "raced" white body These instantiations are embedded within and evolve out of the complex social and historical interstices of whites' efforts at self-construction through complex acts of erasure vis-à-vis Black people whiteness operates rhetorically and ideologically the ideology of white privilege maintains its invisibility through rhetorical silence. it both reflects and sustains the assumption that to be white is the "natural condition," the assumed norm. it masks its existence and makes the denial of white privilege plausible Ideological systems are made up of both presences and absences
Global warming was set in motion around 1600 AD, it seems. ¶ Because carbon dioxide emissions persist for a long time, even a sudden halt today means the carbon dioxide already in Earth's atmosphere could continue to warm our planet for hundreds of years, according to a numerical model which suggests that it might take a lot less carbon than previously thought to reach the global temperature scientists deem unsafe.¶ The researchers simulated an Earth on which, after 1,800 billion tons of carbon entered the atmosphere, all carbon dioxide emissions suddenly stopped. Scientists commonly use the scenario of emissions screeching to a stop to gauge the heat-trapping staying power of carbon dioxide. Within a millennium of this simulated shutoff, the carbon itself faded steadily with 40 percent absorbed by Earth's oceans and landmasses within 20 years and 80 percent soaked up at the end of the 1,000 years.¶ By itself, such a decrease of atmospheric carbon dioxide should lead to cooling. But the heat trapped by the carbon dioxide took a divergent track on their computer. ¶ In a numerical model, while carbon dioxide steadily dissipates, the absorption of heat the oceans decreases, especially in the polar oceans such as off of Antarctica (above). This effect has not been accounted for in existing research. Photo courtesy of Eric Galbraith, McGill University.¶ After a century of cooling, their model of the planet warmed by 0.37 degrees Celsius (0.66 Fahrenheit) during the next 400 years as the ocean absorbed less and less heat. While the resulting temperature spike seems slight, a little heat goes a long way here. Earth has warmed by only 0.85 degrees Celsius (1.5 degrees Fahrenheit) since pre-industrial times. ¶ The Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change estimates that global temperatures 3.6 degrees Fahrenheit higher than pre-industrial levels would dangerously interfere with the climate system. To avoid that point would mean humans have to keep cumulative carbon dioxide emissions below 1,000 billion tons of carbon, about half of which has already been put into the atmosphere since the dawn of industry. ¶ The lingering warming effect the researchers found, however, suggests that the 2-degree point may be reached with much less carbon, said first author Thomas Frölicher, who conducted the work as a postdoctoral researcher in Princeton's Program in Atmospheric and Oceanic Sciences under co-author Jorge Sarmiento, the George J. Magee Professor of Geoscience and Geological Engineering.¶ "If our results are correct, the total carbon emissions required to stay below 2 degrees of warming would have to be three-quarters of previous estimates, only 750 billion tons instead of 1,000 billion tons of carbon," said Frölicher, now a researcher at the Swiss Federal Institute of Technology in Zurich. "Thus, limiting the warming to 2 degrees would require keeping future cumulative carbon emissions below 250 billion tons, only half of the already emitted amount of 500 billion tons."¶ The researchers' work contradicts a scientific consensus that the global temperature would remain constant or decline if emissions were suddenly cut to zero. But previous research did not account for a gradual reduction in the oceans' ability to absorb heat from the atmosphere, particularly the polar oceans, Frölicher said. Although carbon dioxide steadily dissipates, Frölicher and his co-authors were able to see that the oceans that remove heat from the atmosphere gradually take up less. Eventually, the residual heat offsets the cooling that occurred due to dwindling amounts of carbon dioxide.¶ Frölicher and his co-authors showed that the change in ocean heat uptake in the polar regions has a larger effect on global mean temperature than a change in low-latitude oceans, a mechanism known as "ocean-heat uptake efficacy." This mechanism was first explored in a 2010 paper by Frölicher's co-author, Michael Winton, a researcher at the National Oceanic and Atmospheric Administration's Geophysical Fluid Dynamics Laboratory (GFDL) on Princeton's Forrestal Campus.¶ "The regional uptake of heat plays a central role. Previous models have not really represented that very well," Frölicher said.¶ "Scientists have thought that the temperature stays constant or declines once emissions stop, but now we show that the possibility of a temperature increase can not be excluded," Frölicher said. "This is illustrative of how difficult it may be to reverse climate change — we stop the emissions, but still get an increase in the global mean temperature." THE 1AC DOESN’T EVEN GIVE LIP SERVICE TO DISCUSSIONS OF THEIR RACE AND SWITCHES 1AC’S , OR THEIR AUTHORS RACE AND SWITCHES THE 1AC S TO PERFORM FOR YOU TAYLOR, ALLOWING THEM TO DISAPPEAR AS AUTHORS WHICH LOCKS THE BLACK BODY IN A SYSTEM OF ERSAURE GIVING AUTHORITY TO THE WHITE AUTHORSHIP OF THE 1AC AND DEEMING BLACKNESS IRRELEVANT TO THESE SUPPOSEDLY “PRODUCTIVE” DISCUSSIONS THE “VEIW FROM NOWHERE” THAT MOST PHILOSPHICAL DISCOURSE FOSTERS CANNOT THEORIZE THE BLACK BODY OR HOPE TO SOLVE FOR THE HARMS OF WHITE SUPREMACY Yancy 05 Journal of Speculative Philosophy 19.4 (2005) 215-241 I write out of a personal existential context. This context is a profound source of knowledge connected to my "raced" body. Hence, I write from a place of lived embodied experience, a site of exposure. In philosophy, the only thing that we are taught to "expose" is a weak argument, a fallacy, or someone's "inferior" reasoning power. The embodied self is bracketed and deemed irrelevant to theory, superfluous and cumbersome in one's search for truth. It is best, or so we are told, to reason from nowhere. Hence, the white philosopher/author presumes to speak for all of "us" without the slightest mention of his or her "raced" identity. Self-consciously writing as a white male philosopher, Crispin Sartwell observes: Left to my own devices, I disappear as an author. That is the "whiteness" of my authorship. This whiteness of authorship is, for us, a form of authority; to speak (apparently) from nowhere, for everyone, is empowering, though one wields power here only by becoming lost to oneself. But such an authorship and authority is also pleasurable: it yields the pleasure of self-forgetting or [End Page 215] apparent transcendence of the mundane and the particular, and the pleasure of power expressed in the "comprehension" of a range of materials. (1998, 6) To theorize the Black body one must "turn to the [Black] body as the radix for interpreting racial experience" (Johnson [1993, 600]).1 It is important to note that this particular strategy also functions as a lens through which to theorize and critique whiteness; for the Black body's "racial" experience is fundamentally linked to the oppressive modalities of the "raced" white body. However, there is no denying that my own "racial" experiences or the social performances of whiteness can become objects of critical reflection. In this paper, my objective is to describe and theorize situations where the Black body's subjectivity, its lived reality, is reduced to instantiations of the white imaginary, resulting in what I refer to as "the phenomenological return of the Black body." HYPERLINK "http://ezproxy.bgc.bard.edu:2053/journals/journal_of_speculative_philosophy/v019/19.4yancy.html" \l "FOOT2" 2 These instantiations are embedded within and evolve out of the complex social and historical interstices of whites' efforts at self-construction through complex acts of erasure vis-à-vis Black people. These acts of self-construction, however, are myths/ideological constructions predicated upon maintaining white power. As James Snead has noted, "Mythification is the replacement of history with a surrogate ideology of [white] elevation or [Black] demotion along a scale of human value" (Snead 1994, 4). - Rhetorical silence protects the invisibility of whiteness and preserves material white privilege. Ideological systems are made up of both presences and absences. What is absent, unmarked, the UNSPOKEN, the UNSAYABLE becomes positively marked as the ASSUMED NORM. Dr. Crenshaw ‘97 Prof of Speech Comm @ Univ. Ala. Carrie-PhD. USC; former director of debate @ Univ. of Ala.; WESTERN JOURNAL OF COMMUNICATION; Resisting Whiteness’ Rhetorical Silence; 61(3), Summer; pp. 253-278. This analysis brings into focus several observations about how whiteness operates rhetorically and ideologically in public political discourse. First, the ideology of white privilege maintains its invisibility through rhetorical silence. Rhetorical silence protects the invisibility of whiteness because it both reflects and sustains the assumption that to be white is the "natural condition," the assumed norm. Rhetorical silence about whiteness preserves material white privilege because it masks its existence and makes the denial of white privilege plausible. Hall argues that language is the principle medium of ideologies because ideologies are sets or chains of meaning which are located in language. However, ideologies also "work" through rhetorical silences which conceal privilege. Ideological systems are made up of both presences and absences because positively marked terms 'signify' "in relation to what is absent, unmarked, the unspoken, the unsayable" (Hall, "Signification" 109). In this case, the ideology of white privilege "works" through rhetorical silence about whiteness.
9,417
<h4><strong>Warming’s inevitable—newest computer modeling prove—their studies don’t assume ocean heat uptake</h4><p>Science 2.0 11-25 </strong>News Staff citing Thomas Frölicher, postdoctoral researcher in Princeton's Program in Atmospheric and Oceanic Sciences and Jorge Sarmiento, the George J. Magee Professor of Geoscience and Geological Engineering, Princeton University; “Even If Emissions Are Halted, Carbon Dioxide Could Warm Earth For Centuries” Science 2.0; November 25, 2013; <u><strong>http://www.science20.com/news_articles/even_if_emissions_are_halted_carbon_dioxide_could_warm_earth_centuries-125099</p><p></u>Global warming was set in motion around 1600 AD, it seems. ¶ <u></strong><mark>Because carbon dioxide emissions persist for a long time, even a sudden halt today means the carbon dioxide already in Earth's atmosphere could continue to warm our planet for hundreds of years,</mark> according to a numerical model which suggests that it might take a lot less carbon than previously thought to reach the global temperature scientists deem unsafe.¶</u><strong> <u></strong>The researchers simulated an Earth on which,</u><strong> after 1,800 billion tons of carbon entered the atmosphere, <u></strong>all carbon dioxide emissions suddenly stopped. <mark>Scientists commonly use the scenario of emissions screeching to a stop to gauge the heat-trapping staying power of carbon dioxide</u><strong>. <u></strong>Within a millennium of this simulated shutoff, the carbon itself faded steadily with 40 percent absorbed by Earth's oceans and landmasses within 20 years and 80 percent soaked up at the end of the 1,000 years.¶</mark> By itself, such a decrease of atmospheric carbon dioxide should lead to cooling</u><strong>. <u></strong>But the heat trapped by the carbon dioxide took a divergent track on their computer. ¶ <strong><mark>In a numerical model, while carbon dioxide steadily dissipates, the absorption of heat the oceans decreases</u></mark>, <u></strong>especially in the polar oceans such as off of Antarctica</u><strong> (above). <u><mark>This effect has not been accounted for in existing research</mark>. </u>Photo courtesy of Eric Galbraith, McGill University.¶ After a century of cooling, their model of the planet warmed by 0.37 degrees Celsius (0.66 Fahrenheit) during the next 400 years as the ocean absorbed less and less heat. While the resulting temperature spike seems slight, a little heat goes a long way here. Earth has warmed by only 0.85 degrees Celsius (1.5 degrees Fahrenheit) since pre-industrial times. ¶ The Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change estimates that global temperatures 3.6 degrees Fahrenheit higher than pre-industrial levels would dangerously interfere with the climate system. To avoid that point would mean humans have to keep cumulative carbon dioxide emissions below 1,000 billion tons of carbon, about half of which has already been put into the atmosphere since the dawn of industry. <u><mark>¶ The lingering warming effect the researchers found, however, suggests that the 2-degree point may be reached with much less carbon</mark>,</u> said first author Thomas Frölicher, who conducted the work as a postdoctoral researcher in Princeton's Program in Atmospheric and Oceanic Sciences under co-author Jorge Sarmiento, the George J. Magee Professor of Geoscience and Geological Engineering.¶ "If our results are correct, the total carbon emissions required to stay below 2 degrees of warming would have to be three-quarters of previous estimates, only 750 billion tons instead of 1,000 billion tons of carbon," said Frölicher, now a researcher at the Swiss Federal Institute of Technology in Zurich. "Thus, limiting the warming to 2 degrees would require keeping future cumulative carbon emissions below 250 billion tons, only half of the already emitted amount of 500 billion tons."¶ The researchers' work contradicts a scientific consensus that the global temperature would remain constant or decline if emissions were suddenly cut to zero. But <u><mark>previous research did not account for a gradual reduction in the oceans' ability to absorb heat from the atmosphere, particularly the polar oceans,</u></mark> Frölicher said. <u></strong>Although carbon dioxide steadily dissipates, Frölicher and his co-authors were able to see that the oceans that remove heat from the atmosphere gradually take up less. Eventually, the residual heat offsets the cooling that occurred due to dwindling amounts of carbon dioxide</u><strong>.¶ Frölicher and his co-authors showed that the change in ocean heat uptake in the polar regions has a larger effect on global mean temperature than a change in low-latitude oceans, a mechanism known as "ocean-heat uptake efficacy." This mechanism was first explored in a 2010 paper by Frölicher's co-author, Michael Winton, a researcher at the National Oceanic and Atmospheric Administration's Geophysical Fluid Dynamics Laboratory (GFDL) on Princeton's Forrestal Campus.¶ "The regional uptake of heat plays a central role. <u></strong>Previous models have not really represented that very well," Frölicher said.¶ "Scientists have thought that the temperature stays constant or declines once emissions stop, but now we show that the possibility of a temperature increase can not be excluded," Frölicher said. <strong><mark>"This is illustrative of how difficult it may be to reverse climate change — we stop the emissions, but still get an increase in the global mean temperature."</p><p></u></strong></mark>THE 1AC DOESN’T EVEN GIVE LIP SERVICE TO DISCUSSIONS OF THEIR RACE AND SWITCHES 1AC’S , OR THEIR AUTHORS RACE AND SWITCHES THE 1AC S TO PERFORM FOR YOU TAYLOR, ALLOWING THEM TO DISAPPEAR AS AUTHORS WHICH LOCKS THE BLACK BODY IN A SYSTEM OF ERSAURE GIVING AUTHORITY TO THE WHITE AUTHORSHIP OF THE 1AC AND DEEMING BLACKNESS IRRELEVANT TO THESE SUPPOSEDLY “PRODUCTIVE” DISCUSSIONS</p><p>THE “VEIW FROM NOWHERE” THAT MOST PHILOSPHICAL DISCOURSE FOSTERS CANNOT THEORIZE THE BLACK BODY OR HOPE TO SOLVE FOR THE HARMS OF WHITE SUPREMACY</p><p><mark>Yancy 05</mark> Journal of Speculative Philosophy 19.4 (2005) 215-241</p><p><u><mark>I write out of a personal existential context. This context is a profound source of knowledge connected to my "raced" body</u></mark>. Hence, <u>I write from a place of lived embodied experience, a site of exposure.</u> <u>In philosophy, the only thing that we are taught to "expose" is a weak argument, a fallacy, or someone's "inferior" reasoning power. <mark>The embodied self is bracketed and deemed irrelevant to theory, superfluous and cumbersome in one's search for truth. It is best, or so we are told, to reason from nowhere. Hence, the white philosopher/author presumes to speak for all of "us" without the slightest mention of his or her "raced" identity. Self-consciously writing as a white male philosopher,</mark> Crispin Sartwell observes: </p><p><mark>Left to my own devices, I disappear as an author. That is the "whiteness" of my authorship. This whiteness of authorship is, for us, a form of authority; to speak (apparently) from nowhere, for everyone, is empowering, though one wields power here only by becoming lost to oneself. But such an authorship and authority is also pleasurable: it yields the pleasure of self-forgetting or</mark> <strong>[End Page 215<mark>]</strong> apparent transcendence of the mundane and the particular, and the pleasure of power expressed in the "comprehension" of a range of materials.</mark> </p><p></u>(1998, 6) </p><p><u><mark>To theorize the Black body one must "turn to the [Black] body as the radix for interpreting racial experience</u></mark>" (Johnson [1993, 600]).<u>1 <mark>It is important to note that this particular strategy also functions as a lens through which to theorize and critique whiteness; for the Black body's "racial" experience is fundamentally linked to the oppressive modalities of the "raced" white body</u></mark>. However, <u>there is no denying that my own "racial" experiences or the social performances of whiteness can become objects of critical reflection</u>. In this paper, <u>my objective is to describe and theorize situations where the Black body's subjectivity, its lived reality, is reduced to instantiations of the white imaginary, resulting in what I refer to as "the phenomenological return of the Black body.</u>" HYPERLINK "http://ezproxy.bgc.bard.edu:2053/journals/journal_of_speculative_philosophy/v019/19.4yancy.html" \l "FOOT2" <u>2</u> <u><mark>These instantiations are embedded within and evolve out of the complex social and historical interstices of whites' efforts at self-construction through complex acts of erasure vis-à-vis Black people</u></mark>. These acts of self-construction, however, are myths/ideological constructions predicated upon maintaining white power. As James Snead has noted, "<u>Mythification is the replacement of history with a surrogate ideology of [white] elevation or [Black] demotion along a scale of human value</u>" (Snead 1994, 4). </p><p><strong>-</p><p>Rhetorical silence protects the invisibility of whiteness and preserves material white privilege. Ideological systems are made up of both presences and absences. What is absent, unmarked, the UNSPOKEN, the UNSAYABLE becomes positively marked as the ASSUMED NORM.</p><p>Dr. Crenshaw ‘97</strong> Prof of Speech Comm @ Univ. Ala. Carrie-PhD. USC; former director of debate @ Univ. of Ala.; WESTERN JOURNAL OF COMMUNICATION; Resisting Whiteness’ Rhetorical Silence; 61(3), Summer; pp. 253-278.</p><p>This analysis brings into focus several observations about how <u><mark>whiteness operates rhetorically and ideologically</mark> in public political discourse. First, <mark>the ideology of white privilege maintains its invisibility through rhetorical silence.</mark> Rhetorical silence protects the invisibility of whiteness because <mark>it both reflects and sustains the assumption that to be white is the "natural condition," the assumed norm.</mark> Rhetorical silence about whiteness preserves material white privilege because <mark>it masks its existence and makes the denial of white privilege plausible</mark>.</u> Hall argues that language is the principle medium of ideologies because ideologies are sets or chains of meaning which are located in language. However, ideologies also "work" through rhetorical silences which conceal privilege. <u><mark>Ideological systems are made up of both presences and absences</u></mark> because positively marked terms 'signify' "in relation to what is absent, unmarked, the unspoken, the unsayable" (Hall, "Signification" 109). In this case, the ideology of white privilege "works" through rhetorical silence about whiteness.</p>
null
Off
Cartels
57,113
114
17,055
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,312
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Waldinger
Plan The United States should legalize marijuana by amending the Controlled Substances Act of 1970 to allow states meeting specified criteria to opt out of the federal Controlled Substances Act provisions relating to marihuana Federalism Cartels 2nr was like bataille with the transgression alt not suicide
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvAn/Dartmouth-Avendano-Anderson-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,460
AvAn
Dartmouth AvAn
null
Im.....
Av.....
Ty.....
An.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,584
The United States Federal Government should-
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The United States Federal Government should-</h4>
null
1NC
Off
430,292
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,585
Improve interagency coordination on anti-trafficking efforts in the Executive Branch.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Improve interagency coordination on anti-trafficking efforts in the Executive Branch.</h4>
null
1NC
Off
430,294
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,586
Develop a strategic plan based on addressing prevention, protection, and prosecution of human trafficking.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Develop a strategic plan based on addressing prevention, protection, and prosecution of human trafficking.</h4>
null
1NC
Off
430,293
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,587
Require the National Security Council to coordinate with multilateral institutions on anti-trafficking measures.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Require the National Security Council to coordinate with multilateral institutions on anti-trafficking measures.</h4>
null
1NC
Off
430,295
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,588
This is what THEIR evidence says is necessary AND the CP functions as alt causes to aff solvency
Action Group ‘8
Action Group ‘8 (Recommendations for¶ Fighting Human Trafficking in¶ the United States and Abroad¶ Transition Report for the Next Presidential Administration¶ Respectfully submitted by The Action Group To End Human Trafficking and Modern-Day Slavery¶ November 2008,https://www.freetheslaves.net/Document.Doc?id=96)
U S infrastructure for the creation and implementation of anti-trafficking laws and policy requires improvement The lack of coordination with statutorily mandated roles has resulted in a failure to establish, achieve and monitor coherent goals GAO and CRS reports and independent studies have repeatedly highlighted a lack of overall strategy and coordination Improved Interagency Coordination No single department or agency is capable of wielding the authority necessary to bring together the full range of anti-trafficking actors and activities across the Executive Branch Improved Strategic Planning The U.S. must continue to develop and elaborate a comprehensive strategic plan which reflects an integrated approach to addressing prevention, protection and prosecution Improved International Coordination The next President should exercise U.S. leadership to coordinate effective international responses to trafficking. must establish the fundamental balance between human rights and law enforcement responses to trafficking. The White House should charge the NSC to improve coordination with multilateral institutions to more effectively combat human trafficking. require the U.S. to ensure that its international cooperative efforts engage actors that individually and collectively help to achieve this objective Performance, Assessment and Data Collection If the U.S. is to mount a more effective anti-trafficking effort, intelligence and data on human trafficking must be better integrated with and among all federal agencies
The lack of coordination with statutorily mandated roles has resulted in a failure GAO and CRS reports and independent studies have repeatedly highlighted a lack of overall strategy and coordination a No single department or agency is capable of wielding the authority necessary to bring together the full range of anti-trafficking actors and activities The U.S. must continue to develop and elaborate a comprehensive strategic plan which reflects an integrated approach to addressing prevention, protection and prosecution The White House should charge the NSC to improve coordination with multilateral institutions to more effectively combat human trafficking the U.S. is to mount a more effective anti-trafficking effort, intelligence and data on human trafficking must be better integrated
The current United States government’s infrastructure for the creation and implementation of anti-trafficking laws and policy requires improvement. The lack of coordination among agencies with statutorily mandated roles and responsibilities has resulted in a failure to establish, achieve and monitor coherent goals, objectives and timetables. GAO and CRS reports and independent studies have repeatedly highlighted a lack of overall strategy and coordination and have uniformly urged the need for leadership to address these serious deficiencies. The next Administration must confront and resolve these issues to ensure that the three policy touchstones of prevention, protection and prosecution are adequately addressed. Improved Interagency Coordination No single department or agency is capable of wielding the authority necessary to bring together the full range of anti-trafficking actors and activities across the Executive Branch. Securing effective interagency coordination to combat human trafficking at home and overseas continues to be a central challenge for the U.S. government. • United States Government Interagency Oversight should reside in the White House. The President needs to take an active and informed leadership role to improve interagency collaboration and provide oversight and accountability because of the broad and complex interagency jurisdictional nature of this issue. The relevant agencies – despite coordinating task forces – do not work optimally absent direction and leadership from the White House. • The next President should communicate Administration strategy, policy directives and accountability to all executive branch agencies. A Presidential Directive should set forth strategic frameworks for Executive Branch actors. In order to improve coordination of U.S. efforts to combat human trafficking in the U.S. and abroad, the White House, through designated senior staff on the National Security Council and Domestic Policy Council working collaboratively, should facilitate and enforce coordinated strategies among agencies and departments that regard themselves as co-equal with one another. The White House would provide critical oversight and direction to ensure that the work of the Senior Policy Operating Group (SPOG) is incorporated into the President’s Interagency Task Force (PITF) coordination and that the agencies are carrying out the President’s policies and strategies. • The next President should direct that senior White House officials, both from the National Security Council (NSC) and the Domestic Policy Council (DPC), be vested with the responsibility for human trafficking and work collaboratively to facilitate implementation of effective, coordinated anti-trafficking strategies and initiatives among agencies and departments. Human trafficking should be incorporated into the respective portfolios of the NSC and DPC. This would ensure more effective coordination, especially in instances where existing interagency coordinating structures prove insufficient to implement coordinated domestic and international anti-trafficking efforts. An enhanced DPC/NSC role would ensure that the White House provides significant leadership on human trafficking. Improved Strategic Planning The U.S. must continue to develop and elaborate a comprehensive strategic plan which reflects an integrated approach to addressing prevention, protection and prosecution. Activities and initiatives in the U.S. and worldwide could be placed within this comprehensive plan. Key Recommendations Relating to the Prevention of Human Trafficking: • The next Administration should prioritize implementation of targeted and tailored prevention initiatives that address core contributing factors to trafficking in persons. These initiatives should place a particular emphasis on economic development strategies that help individuals to find and hold viable jobs in communities and countries of origin. • The next Administration should convene multi-party discussions between businesses, workers’ organizations (trade unions), non-governmental organizations and governments to develop anti-trafficking policies, programs and initiatives domestically and internationally. As part of this effort, the next President should work with the private sector and workers’ organizations to develop joint strategies to address trafficking in corporate supply chains, prevent all forms of worker exploitation, and promote adherence to core international labor standards (including freedom from forced and child labor, freedom from discrimination, and the freedom of association and right to organize and collectively bargain). • The next Administration should consider ways that the U.S. might learn from, and build on, the example of Brazil in combating trafficking in supply chains. Brazil’s National Plan for the Eradication of Slave Labor is widely recognized as a useful model for addressing forced labor in supply chains. It rests on a foundation of federal enforcement activity, extensive supply chain research, and corporate education and engagement. Entities found to be using forced labor are subject to civil sanction and oversight; companies pledge through the counterpart National Pact not to source from these entities. The ILO has played a key role in shaping this initiative, work that the U.S. has supported. Building on the Brazil model could include, among other initiatives, continued support for the ILO’s work, sensitizing U.S. companies to the issue and raising awareness about the program, encouraging U.S. corporate adoption and implementation of ILO training tools and materials, and U.S. corporate participation in Brazil’s National Pact as appropriate. • The next President should direct State/DRL and Labor/ILAB to work with and through the ILO, and its partners, to promote awareness of and adoption of ILO tools and programs to address forced labor in global supply chains among its tripartite partners (business, trade unions, and governments). The ILO has decades of experience on the issue, demonstrated expertise in technical cooperation, and the capacity to foster business engagement and monitor results. • The State Department’s Tier 2 Watch List should be the focus of an array of innovative initiatives to help move countries from failure to improved responsiveness and capacity in combating human trafficking. • The next Administration should improve the Oversight of Government Contractors and Procurement Regulations as they relate to human trafficking. Currently, antitrafficking provisions require contractors to notify employees of the zero tolerance policy and to specify what actions will be taken against employees violating the policy. However, self-regulation does not ensure the accountability necessary to prevent trafficking, and staff training is virtually non-existent. Key Recommendations for the Protection of Victims of Human Trafficking: • The next Administration must improve the identification and protection of victims of human trafficking, both in the United States and abroad. To help with identification and referral of human trafficking victims in the U.S., the next President should call upon Executive Branch entities to develop systematic and coordinated training programs for the range of local first responders associated with each agency’s anti-trafficking work. • All relevant Executive Branch departments/agencies, such as DOJ and HHS, should be directed to develop educational and training materials/programs for state and local law enforcement. These programs will improve cooperation between local, state, and federal government officials in finding and supporting potential victims of trafficking. • The next Administration should ensure, to the greatest extent possible by Executive Action, that the provision of services for victims of trafficking is de-linked from cooperation with law enforcement. Currently, a TVPA provision requires victims of trafficking to cooperate with law enforcement in order to be eligible for needed protection services. Victims should be entitled to protection services solely because they are victims of trafficking. • The next Administration should explore all legal mechanisms to allow trafficking victims to remain safely in the U.S. through the adjudication process. • The next President should call upon relevant departments and agencies to review issues with respect to the protection of “minor” victims of trafficking. Currently minors who are recognized by federal law as victims of trafficking are often unjustly charged and processed within the juvenile offenders system. • The next Administration must ensure that victims of trafficking receive comprehensive and appropriate services. Housing is among the most urgent and consistently needed services for survivors of human trafficking. The next President should direct that federal agencies with custody of trafficking victims place them in appropriate housing options where their special needs can be addressed. Increased funding for human trafficking shelters should not impact funding for domestic violence or other shelters. Moreover, the President should ensure that quality legal services are provided to trafficking survivors. The need for quality case management for all trafficking survivors in the U.S. is also essential and must be ensured. Finally, the next Administration should ensure that those trafficking victims who require long-term recovery support receive appropriate services. • The next President should call for reducing bureaucratic burdens on providers of services to victims of trafficking. The President should also institute an administration wide system to track the expenditures on victim services by federal grantees. • The next President should strengthen protection of domestic workers employed by diplomats. This can be accomplished by directing relevant Executive Branch departments and other entities to work with NGOs and others to develop and institute a system that includes check-ins and information sessions for the domestic workers to ensure they are aware of their rights and have access to appropriate resources. Key Recommendations for the Prosecution of Human Traffickers: The next Administration needs to seek full resources for federal investigation and prosecution efforts against traffickers and promote the importance of the role of state and local law enforcement in addressing trafficking in persons. The federal government should take steps to help establish this crime as a priority for state and local law enforcement. It should strengthen institutional processes and procedures to ensure seamless cooperation and collaboration among law enforcement at all levels of government in identifying, investigating and prosecuting human trafficking cases, while concurrently assisting and protecting the victims of human trafficking. • The next President should direct Executive Branch departments to support the strengthening of training for all levels of state and local law enforcement to increase capability to identify and investigate human trafficking cases. • The next President needs to ensure that DOJ’s Human Trafficking Protection Unit (HTPU) receives adequate funds to execute its expanded role and responsibilities. • The next President and his Administration should work with state and local law enforcement associations to mobilize state and local law enforcement attention on anti-trafficking measures. • The U.S. Government must request that foreign missions waive criminal and/or civil immunity for diplomats or family members of diplomats who abuse domestic workers. It should negotiate restitution for the victims and penalize foreign governments that fail to cooperate in cases of human trafficking and/or abuse of domestic workers. Improved International Coordination The next President should exercise U.S. leadership to coordinate effective international responses to trafficking. These responses must establish the fundamental balance between human rights and law enforcement responses to trafficking. The White House should charge the NSC, in concert with the Department of State to improve coordination with multilateral institutions to more effectively combat human trafficking. To advance both human rights interests and law enforcement will require the U.S. to ensure that its international cooperative efforts engage actors that individually and collectively help to achieve this objective. • The U.S. should urge the UN Secretary General to establish a coordinating office on human trafficking, accountable to the SG, to foster a more effective response and the integration of efforts by all relevant UN agencies. • The next Administration should encourage regional anti-trafficking accords with strong victim protection measures. The Council of Europe Convention is a good model for regional agreements. • The next Administration needs to ensure a more effective integration of antitrafficking efforts with international labor and migration policies. The Department of Labor, the State Department’s TIP office, and the DRL should engage with the ILO on strategies to address forced labor among transnational migrant workers, indigenous populations, and child labor. The next Administration should take an active approach in steering the existing IOM “Colombo Process” into a dialogue on labor migration that promotes human rights and protects migrant workers from trafficking. Moreover, anti-trafficking goals should be included in the context of general international labor negotiations or discussions, and in regional or international exchanges on migration policies. • The U.S. should exert its leadership to drive anti-trafficking initiatives and programs and improve coordination among bilateral, regional and multilateral donors, such as the G-8 agenda and the development banks. The next President should also work with other donor countries to incorporate anti-trafficking and slavery conditionality in future debt forgiveness for Heavily Indebted Poor Countries (HIPC). Performance, Assessment and Data Collection If the U.S. is to mount a more effective anti-trafficking effort, intelligence and data on human trafficking must be better integrated with and among all federal agencies. • A central entity, possibly the Center for Trafficking and Smuggling, must be vested with the resources and authority to provide leadership on the inter-agency development of a coherent approach to collecting and analyzing data that can be used to inform anti-trafficking responses. Raw data alone is not useful. A process and understanding needs to be organized within the federal government to collect and analyze the data needed to achieve a better understanding of the problem and craft effective responses. • The next President must ensure that the Center for Human Smuggling and Trafficking is significantly restructured with appropriate staff and direction to carry out its intended mission to address human trafficking. • The next Administration should support in-depth research that can be applied to improve practical anti-trafficking responses and produce more effective results. The Administration should also evaluate funded anti-trafficking programs for evidence of anti-trafficking impact. Responsibilities of Federal Agencies Several Federal Agencies are mandated under the law with responsibilities for combating human trafficking. These include the Department of Justice, Department of State, Department of Labor, Department of Defense and Department of Homeland Security. This report contains additional recommendations for these respective agencies. It also includes key examples of authorized priority programs within certain agencies that have yet to be fully funded. The body of this report identifies a number of specific steps that need to be taken by the new Administration to achieve these important strategic objectives and to improve the effectiveness of this country’s anti-trafficking initiatives in the United States and around the world.
16,050
<h4>This is what THEIR evidence says is necessary AND the CP functions as alt causes to aff solvency </h4><p><strong>Action Group ‘8</strong> (Recommendations for¶ Fighting Human Trafficking in¶ the United States and Abroad¶ Transition Report for the Next Presidential Administration¶ Respectfully submitted by The Action Group To End Human Trafficking and Modern-Day Slavery¶ November 2008,https://www.freetheslaves.net/Document.Doc?id=96)</p><p>The current <u>U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates government’s <u>infrastructure for the creation and implementation of anti-trafficking laws and policy requires improvement</u>. <u><mark>The lack of coordination</mark> </u>among agencies <u><mark>with statutorily mandated roles</u></mark> and responsibilities <u><mark>has resulted in a failure</mark> to establish, achieve and monitor coherent goals</u>, objectives and timetables. <u><mark>GAO and CRS reports and independent studies have repeatedly highlighted a lack of overall strategy and coordination</u> a</mark>nd have uniformly urged the need for leadership to address these serious deficiencies. The next Administration must confront and resolve these issues to ensure that the three policy touchstones of prevention, protection and prosecution are adequately addressed. <u>Improved Interagency Coordination</u> <u><mark>No single department or agency is capable of wielding the authority necessary to bring together the full range of anti-trafficking actors and activities </mark>across the Executive Branch</u>. Securing effective interagency coordination to combat human trafficking at home and overseas continues to be a central challenge for the U.S. government. • United States Government Interagency Oversight should reside in the White House. The President needs to take an active and informed leadership role to improve interagency collaboration and provide oversight and accountability because of the broad and complex interagency jurisdictional nature of this issue. The relevant agencies – despite coordinating task forces – do not work optimally absent direction and leadership from the White House. • The next President should communicate Administration strategy, policy directives and accountability to all executive branch agencies. A Presidential Directive should set forth strategic frameworks for Executive Branch actors. In order to improve coordination of U.S. efforts to combat human trafficking in the U.S. and abroad, the White House, through designated senior staff on the National Security Council and Domestic Policy Council working collaboratively, should facilitate and enforce coordinated strategies among agencies and departments that regard themselves as co-equal with one another. The White House would provide critical oversight and direction to ensure that the work of the Senior Policy Operating Group (SPOG) is incorporated into the President’s Interagency Task Force (PITF) coordination and that the agencies are carrying out the President’s policies and strategies. • The next President should direct that senior White House officials, both from the National Security Council (NSC) and the Domestic Policy Council (DPC), be vested with the responsibility for human trafficking and work collaboratively to facilitate implementation of effective, coordinated anti-trafficking strategies and initiatives among agencies and departments. Human trafficking should be incorporated into the respective portfolios of the NSC and DPC. This would ensure more effective coordination, especially in instances where existing interagency coordinating structures prove insufficient to implement coordinated domestic and international anti-trafficking efforts. An enhanced DPC/NSC role would ensure that the White House provides significant leadership on human trafficking. <u>Improved Strategic Planning <mark>The U.S. must continue to develop and elaborate a comprehensive strategic plan which reflects an integrated approach to addressing prevention, protection and prosecution</u></mark>. Activities and initiatives in the U.S. and worldwide could be placed within this comprehensive plan. Key Recommendations Relating to the Prevention of Human Trafficking: • The next Administration should prioritize implementation of targeted and tailored prevention initiatives that address core contributing factors to trafficking in persons. These initiatives should place a particular emphasis on economic development strategies that help individuals to find and hold viable jobs in communities and countries of origin. • The next Administration should convene multi-party discussions between businesses, workers’ organizations (trade unions), non-governmental organizations and governments to develop anti-trafficking policies, programs and initiatives domestically and internationally. As part of this effort, the next President should work with the private sector and workers’ organizations to develop joint strategies to address trafficking in corporate supply chains, prevent all forms of worker exploitation, and promote adherence to core international labor standards (including freedom from forced and child labor, freedom from discrimination, and the freedom of association and right to organize and collectively bargain). • The next Administration should consider ways that the U.S. might learn from, and build on, the example of Brazil in combating trafficking in supply chains. Brazil’s National Plan for the Eradication of Slave Labor is widely recognized as a useful model for addressing forced labor in supply chains. It rests on a foundation of federal enforcement activity, extensive supply chain research, and corporate education and engagement. Entities found to be using forced labor are subject to civil sanction and oversight; companies pledge through the counterpart National Pact not to source from these entities. The ILO has played a key role in shaping this initiative, work that the U.S. has supported. Building on the Brazil model could include, among other initiatives, continued support for the ILO’s work, sensitizing U.S. companies to the issue and raising awareness about the program, encouraging U.S. corporate adoption and implementation of ILO training tools and materials, and U.S. corporate participation in Brazil’s National Pact as appropriate. • The next President should direct State/DRL and Labor/ILAB to work with and through the ILO, and its partners, to promote awareness of and adoption of ILO tools and programs to address forced labor in global supply chains among its tripartite partners (business, trade unions, and governments). The ILO has decades of experience on the issue, demonstrated expertise in technical cooperation, and the capacity to foster business engagement and monitor results. • The State Department’s Tier 2 Watch List should be the focus of an array of innovative initiatives to help move countries from failure to improved responsiveness and capacity in combating human trafficking. • The next Administration should improve the Oversight of Government Contractors and Procurement Regulations as they relate to human trafficking. Currently, antitrafficking provisions require contractors to notify employees of the zero tolerance policy and to specify what actions will be taken against employees violating the policy. However, self-regulation does not ensure the accountability necessary to prevent trafficking, and staff training is virtually non-existent. Key Recommendations for the Protection of Victims of Human Trafficking: • The next Administration must improve the identification and protection of victims of human trafficking, both in the United States and abroad. To help with identification and referral of human trafficking victims in the U.S., the next President should call upon Executive Branch entities to develop systematic and coordinated training programs for the range of local first responders associated with each agency’s anti-trafficking work. • All relevant Executive Branch departments/agencies, such as DOJ and HHS, should be directed to develop educational and training materials/programs for state and local law enforcement. These programs will improve cooperation between local, state, and federal government officials in finding and supporting potential victims of trafficking. • The next Administration should ensure, to the greatest extent possible by Executive Action, that the provision of services for victims of trafficking is de-linked from cooperation with law enforcement. Currently, a TVPA provision requires victims of trafficking to cooperate with law enforcement in order to be eligible for needed protection services. Victims should be entitled to protection services solely because they are victims of trafficking. • The next Administration should explore all legal mechanisms to allow trafficking victims to remain safely in the U.S. through the adjudication process. • The next President should call upon relevant departments and agencies to review issues with respect to the protection of “minor” victims of trafficking. Currently minors who are recognized by federal law as victims of trafficking are often unjustly charged and processed within the juvenile offenders system. • The next Administration must ensure that victims of trafficking receive comprehensive and appropriate services. Housing is among the most urgent and consistently needed services for survivors of human trafficking. The next President should direct that federal agencies with custody of trafficking victims place them in appropriate housing options where their special needs can be addressed. Increased funding for human trafficking shelters should not impact funding for domestic violence or other shelters. Moreover, the President should ensure that quality legal services are provided to trafficking survivors. The need for quality case management for all trafficking survivors in the U.S. is also essential and must be ensured. Finally, the next Administration should ensure that those trafficking victims who require long-term recovery support receive appropriate services. • The next President should call for reducing bureaucratic burdens on providers of services to victims of trafficking. The President should also institute an administration wide system to track the expenditures on victim services by federal grantees. • The next President should strengthen protection of domestic workers employed by diplomats. This can be accomplished by directing relevant Executive Branch departments and other entities to work with NGOs and others to develop and institute a system that includes check-ins and information sessions for the domestic workers to ensure they are aware of their rights and have access to appropriate resources. Key Recommendations for the Prosecution of Human Traffickers: The next Administration needs to seek full resources for federal investigation and prosecution efforts against traffickers and promote the importance of the role of state and local law enforcement in addressing trafficking in persons. The federal government should take steps to help establish this crime as a priority for state and local law enforcement. It should strengthen institutional processes and procedures to ensure seamless cooperation and collaboration among law enforcement at all levels of government in identifying, investigating and prosecuting human trafficking cases, while concurrently assisting and protecting the victims of human trafficking. • The next President should direct Executive Branch departments to support the strengthening of training for all levels of state and local law enforcement to increase capability to identify and investigate human trafficking cases. • The next President needs to ensure that DOJ’s Human Trafficking Protection Unit (HTPU) receives adequate funds to execute its expanded role and responsibilities. • The next President and his Administration should work with state and local law enforcement associations to mobilize state and local law enforcement attention on anti-trafficking measures. • The U.S. Government must request that foreign missions waive criminal and/or civil immunity for diplomats or family members of diplomats who abuse domestic workers. It should negotiate restitution for the victims and penalize foreign governments that fail to cooperate in cases of human trafficking and/or abuse of domestic workers. <u>Improved International Coordination The next President should exercise U.S. leadership to coordinate effective international responses to trafficking.</u> These responses <u>must establish the fundamental balance between human rights and law enforcement responses to trafficking. <mark>The White House should charge the NSC</u></mark>, in concert with the Department of State <u><mark>to improve coordination with multilateral institutions to more effectively combat human trafficking</mark>. </u>To advance both human rights interests and law enforcement will <u>require the U.S. to ensure that its international cooperative efforts engage actors that individually and collectively help to achieve this objective</u>. • The U.S. should urge the UN Secretary General to establish a coordinating office on human trafficking, accountable to the SG, to foster a more effective response and the integration of efforts by all relevant UN agencies. • The next Administration should encourage regional anti-trafficking accords with strong victim protection measures. The Council of Europe Convention is a good model for regional agreements. • The next Administration needs to ensure a more effective integration of antitrafficking efforts with international labor and migration policies. The Department of Labor, the State Department’s TIP office, and the DRL should engage with the ILO on strategies to address forced labor among transnational migrant workers, indigenous populations, and child labor. The next Administration should take an active approach in steering the existing IOM “Colombo Process” into a dialogue on labor migration that promotes human rights and protects migrant workers from trafficking. Moreover, anti-trafficking goals should be included in the context of general international labor negotiations or discussions, and in regional or international exchanges on migration policies. • The U.S. should exert its leadership to drive anti-trafficking initiatives and programs and improve coordination among bilateral, regional and multilateral donors, such as the G-8 agenda and the development banks. The next President should also work with other donor countries to incorporate anti-trafficking and slavery conditionality in future debt forgiveness for Heavily Indebted Poor Countries (HIPC). <u>Performance, Assessment and Data Collection If <mark>the U.S. is to mount a more effective anti-trafficking effort, intelligence and data on human trafficking must be better integrated</mark> with and among all federal agencies</u>. • A central entity, possibly the Center for Trafficking and Smuggling, must be vested with the resources and authority to provide leadership on the inter-agency development of a coherent approach to collecting and analyzing data that can be used to inform anti-trafficking responses. Raw data alone is not useful. A process and understanding needs to be organized within the federal government to collect and analyze the data needed to achieve a better understanding of the problem and craft effective responses. • The next President must ensure that the Center for Human Smuggling and Trafficking is significantly restructured with appropriate staff and direction to carry out its intended mission to address human trafficking. • The next Administration should support in-depth research that can be applied to improve practical anti-trafficking responses and produce more effective results. The Administration should also evaluate funded anti-trafficking programs for evidence of anti-trafficking impact. Responsibilities of Federal Agencies Several Federal Agencies are mandated under the law with responsibilities for combating human trafficking. These include the Department of Justice, Department of State, Department of Labor, Department of Defense and Department of Homeland Security. This report contains additional recommendations for these respective agencies. It also includes key examples of authorized priority programs within certain agencies that have yet to be fully funded. The body of this report identifies a number of specific steps that need to be taken by the new Administration to achieve these important strategic objectives and to improve the effectiveness of this country’s anti-trafficking initiatives in the United States and around the world.</p>
null
1NC
Off
430,299
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,589
The United States should remove criminal prohibitions and penalties for nearly all prostitution and facilitators of prostitution in the United States.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The United States should remove criminal prohibitions and penalties for nearly all prostitution and facilitators of prostitution in the United States.</h4>
null
1NC
Off
430,296
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,590
Competes- the CP is just decriminalization. We legalize nothing. We don’t include the regulations placed on facilitated or organized prostitution.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Competes- the CP is just decriminalization. We legalize nothing. We don’t include the regulations placed on facilitated or organized prostitution.</h4>
null
1NC
Off
430,298
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,591
Legalization results in an OVERLY RESTRICTIVE regulatory regime – causes increased underground & legal prostitution – this two tier system causes health hazards, intolerable conditions, and industry control that hurts the individual prostitute.
Jordan 05
Jordan 05 (Jan, Institute of Criminology Victoria University of Wellington, “The Sex Industry in New Zealand: A Literature Review”)
The state of Victoria has long been referred to as a classic example of a legalised model Sex workers could work legally from their homes or from parlours and escort agencies as long as the business obtained a planning permit from the local counc However, since many councils were reluctant to sanction prostitution as a business, such permits were difficult to obtain. new prostitution laws were introduced in Victoria that increased the penalties associated with illegal prostitution, especially street work A regulatory framework was established requiring all ‘prostitution service providers’ to be licensed, with applicants having to pay high licence fees and undergo rigorous police scrutiny in addition to holding a valid council planning permit for their establishment In an attempt to prevent organised crime, as well as having to be licensed, brothel owners in Victoria are each restricted to the operation of one brothel venue. The licensing system comprises a range of permits and licences for brothels, operators, and workers, with Section 15 of the Act stating that simply being in, entering or leaving an unlicensed brothel without a lawful excuse is an offence Victoria’s system of legalised prostitution has resulted in a split, two-tiered sex industry evolving, with a tightly controlled legal sector operating alongside a large and often vulnerable illegal sector one group of workers hold positions in the state-approved brothels, often claiming that they work in virtual slave-like conditions for the privilege of being ‘state approved’. Those who cannot obtain employment in the licensed brothels work instead in the illicit underground sex industry where their insecure legal status renders them vulnerable to exploitation, harassment and organised crime Both the legal and illegal sectors are said to have expanded since the legislation’s introduction with the real growth occurring in the illegal sector which now outnumbers legitimate sex businesses The cost and legal scrutiny involved in the licensing process means that many (perhaps a majority) of prostitution businesses in Victoria remain illegal the legalisation process has been accompanied by a proliferation of different forms of sex businesses all seeking to meet clients’ demands for more explicit and alternative commercial sexual services Rather than resulting in sex workers in Victoria being empowered by law reform initiatives despite the legislation seeking to limit this, large-scale sex industrialists now control the legal industry Women working in legal brothels may be forced to hand over 50-60% of their takings to managers and operators ile women who want to work from home or smaller cottage-type settings are forced into industrial or docklands areas if they want to work legally Such environments bring increased risks of violence and isolation and work against health and safety concerns. The Queensland Prostitution Act 1999 seeks to regulate prostitution by a brothel licensing system and town planning controls tight regulatory framework has left most brothels operating illegally and put the lives of street workers at risk
a classic example of a legalised model Sex workers could work as long as the business obtained a permit However such permits were difficult to obtain. prostitution laws in Victoria increased the penalties associated with illegal prostitution, regulatory framework was established requiring all providers’ to be licensed, with applicants having to pay high fees and undergo rigorous scrutiny brothel owners are restricted to one venue simply being in, entering or leaving an unlicensed brothel without a lawful excuse is an offence legalised prostitution resulted in a split, two-tiered sex industry evolving, with a tightly controlled legal sector operating alongside a large and often vulnerable illegal sector workers often claim that they work in virtual slave-like conditions for the privilege of being ‘state approved’. Those who cannot obtain employment work in the illicit underground sex industry vulnerable to exploitation, harassment and crime the legal and illegal sectors have expanded with the real growth occurring in the illegal sector, which outnumbers legitimate businesses legalisation has been accompanied by a proliferation of different forms of sex businesses Rather than resulting in sex workers being empowered by law reform initiatives despite legislation large-scale sex industrialists now control the legal industry women are forced into industrial areas if they want to work legally. Such environments bring increased risks of violence and isolation and work against health and safety concerns.
Legalisation: Victoria, Queensland and Western Australia The state of Victoria has long been referred to as a classic example of a legalised model. The Prostitution Regulation Act 1986 introduced the possibility of legal work within the sex industry. Sex workers could work legally from their homes or from parlours and escort agencies as long as the business obtained a planning permit from the local council (Sullivan, 1999). However, since many councils were reluctant to sanction prostitution as a business, such permits were difficult to obtain. In 1994 new prostitution laws were introduced in Victoria that increased the penalties associated with illegal prostitution, especially street work. The Prostitution Control Act 1994 sought to actively involve the police in the regulation of the brothel industry. A regulatory framework was established requiring all ‘prostitution service providers’ to be licensed, with applicants having to pay high licence fees and undergo rigorous police scrutiny in addition to holding a valid council planning permit for their establishment (Arnot, 2002; Sullivan, 1999). The planning controls determined under the Planning and Environment Act 1997 include requirements that sex establishments must not be located near schools, churches or other areas where children congregate, ensure their exclusion from residential areas, and limit the size of brothels to a maximum of six rooms (Sullivan, 1999). In an attempt to prevent organised crime, as well as having to be licensed, brothel owners in Victoria are each restricted to the operation of one brothel venue. The licensing system comprises a range of permits and licences for brothels, operators, and workers, with Section 15 of the Act stating that simply being in, entering or leaving an unlicensed brothel without a lawful excuse is an offence (Smith, 1999). Concern has been expressed that Victoria’s system of legalised prostitution has resulted in a split, two-tiered sex industry evolving, with a tightly controlled legal sector operating alongside a large and often vulnerable illegal sector (Dobinson, 1992, cited in Sullivan, 1999). Thus one group of workers hold positions in the state-approved brothels, often claiming that they work in virtual slave-like conditions for the privilege of being ‘state approved’. Those who cannot obtain employment in the licensed brothels work instead in the illicit underground sex industry where their insecure legal status renders them vulnerable to exploitation, harassment and organised crime (Arnot, 2002). Both the legal and illegal sectors are said to have expanded since the legislation’s introduction, with the real growth occurring in the illegal sector, which now outnumbers legitimate sex businesses (Arnot, 2002; Sullivan, 1999). In December 1998 there were 82 licensed brothels in Victoria (79 of which were in Melbourne), as well as five ‘exempt’ brothels (solo or twoperson establishments that were exempt from the licensing requirements but still needed town planning permits (Sullivan, 1999)). The number of unlicensed premises was unknown but believed to be considerable. Hence Sullivan argues that: The cost and legal scrutiny involved in the licensing process means that many (perhaps a majority) of prostitution businesses in Victoria remain illegal. (Sullivan, 1999, 10). Concern has been expressed that the legalisation process has been accompanied by a proliferation of different forms of sex businesses all seeking to meet clients’ demands for more explicit and alternative commercial sexual services (Sullivan, 1999). Rather than resulting in sex workers in Victoria being empowered by law reform initiatives, it is argued that, despite the legislation seeking to limit this, large-scale sex industrialists now control the legal industry (ibid.). Women working in legal brothels may be forced to hand over 50-60% of their takings to managers and operators, while women who want to work from home or smaller cottage-type settings are forced into industrial or docklands areas if they want to work legally. Such environments bring increased risks of violence and isolation and work against health and safety concerns. The Queensland Prostitution Act 1999 seeks to regulate prostitution by a brothel licensing system and town planning controls. Recent criticisms have been made suggesting that the tight regulatory framework has left most brothels operating illegally and put the lives of street workers at risk. One of the only 12 licensed brothel owners commented: We’ve been pushed into industrial areas and hidden, we’re paying $20,000 a year for our licence before we can even open the doors, we’re fingerprinted and interrogated, we have trouble getting workers because we can’t advertise and they’re (the Government) in our faces all the time. (The Courier-Mail, 2003, quoted in Smith, 2003, 21).
4,867
<h4>Legalization results in an <u>OVERLY RESTRICTIVE</u> regulatory regime – causes increased underground & legal prostitution – this two tier system causes health hazards, intolerable conditions, and industry control that hurts the individual prostitute. </h4><p><strong>Jordan 05 </strong>(Jan, Institute of Criminology Victoria University of Wellington, “The Sex Industry in New Zealand: A Literature Review”)</p><p>Legalisation: Victoria, Queensland and Western Australia <u>The state of Victoria has long been referred to as <mark>a <strong>classic example of a legalised model</u></strong></mark>. The Prostitution Regulation Act 1986 introduced the possibility of legal work within the sex industry. <u><mark>Sex workers could work</mark> legally from their homes or from parlours and escort agencies <mark>as long as the business obtained a</mark> planning <mark>permit</mark> from the local counc</u>il (Sullivan, 1999). <u><mark>However</mark>, since many councils were reluctant to sanction prostitution as a business, <strong><mark>such permits were difficult to obtain.</mark> </u></strong>In 1994 <u>new <mark>prostitution laws</mark> were introduced <mark>in Victoria</mark> that <strong><mark>increased the penalties associated with illegal prostitution,</strong></mark> especially street work</u>. The Prostitution Control Act 1994 sought to actively involve the police in the regulation of the brothel industry. <u>A <mark>regulatory framework was established requiring all</mark> ‘prostitution service <mark>providers’ to be licensed, with applicants having to pay</mark> <mark>high</mark> licence <mark>fees and undergo rigorous</mark> police <mark>scrutiny</mark> in addition to holding a valid council planning permit for their establishment</u> (Arnot, 2002; Sullivan, 1999). The planning controls determined under the Planning and Environment Act 1997 include requirements that sex establishments must not be located near schools, churches or other areas where children congregate, ensure their exclusion from residential areas, and limit the size of brothels to a maximum of six rooms (Sullivan, 1999).<u> In an attempt to prevent organised crime, as well as having to be licensed, <mark>brothel owners</mark> in Victoria <mark>are</mark> each <mark>restricted to</mark> the operation of <mark>one </mark>brothel <mark>venue</mark>.</u> <u>The licensing system comprises a range of permits and licences for brothels, operators, and workers, with Section 15 of the Act stating that <mark>simply being in, entering or leaving an unlicensed brothel <strong>without a lawful excuse is an offence</u></strong></mark> (Smith, 1999). Concern has been expressed that <u>Victoria’s system of <mark>legalised prostitution</mark> has <strong><mark>resulted in a split, two-tiered sex industry evolving, with a tightly controlled legal sector operating alongside a large and often vulnerable illegal sector</u></strong></mark> (Dobinson, 1992, cited in Sullivan, 1999). Thus <u>one group of <mark>workers</mark> hold positions in the state-approved brothels,</u> <u><strong><mark>often claim</mark>ing <mark>that they work in virtual slave-like conditions</u></strong> <u><strong>for the privilege of being ‘state approved’</strong>.</u> <u>Those who cannot obtain employment</mark> in the licensed brothels</u> <u><mark>work</mark> instead <mark>in the <strong>illicit underground sex industry</mark> where their insecure legal status renders them <mark>vulnerable to exploitation, harassment and</mark> organised <mark>crime</u></strong></mark> (Arnot, 2002). <u>Both <mark>the <strong>legal and illegal sectors</strong></mark> are <strong>said to <mark>have expanded</strong></mark> since the legislation’s introduction</u>, <u><mark>with the real growth <strong>occurring in the illegal sector</u></strong>, <u>which</mark> now <strong><mark>outnumbers legitimate</mark> sex <mark>businesses</u></strong></mark> (Arnot, 2002; Sullivan, 1999). In December 1998 there were 82 licensed brothels in Victoria (79 of which were in Melbourne), as well as five ‘exempt’ brothels (solo or twoperson establishments that were exempt from the licensing requirements but still needed town planning permits (Sullivan, 1999)). The number of unlicensed premises was unknown but believed to be considerable. Hence Sullivan argues that: <u>The cost and legal scrutiny involved in the licensing process means that many (perhaps a majority) of prostitution businesses in Victoria remain illegal</u>. (Sullivan, 1999, 10). Concern has been expressed that<u> the <mark>legalisation</mark> process <mark>has been accompanied by a proliferation <strong>of different forms of sex businesses</strong></mark> all seeking to meet clients’ demands for more explicit and alternative commercial sexual services</u> (Sullivan, 1999). <u><strong><mark>Rather than resulting in sex workers</mark> in Victoria <mark>being empowered by law reform initiatives</u></strong></mark>, it is argued that, <u><mark>despite</mark> the <mark>legislation</mark> seeking to limit this, <strong><mark>large-scale sex industrialists now control the legal industry</mark> </u></strong>(ibid.). <u>Women working in legal brothels may be forced to hand over 50-60% of their takings to managers and operators</u>, wh<u>ile <mark>women</mark> who want to work from home or smaller cottage-type settings <mark>are <strong>forced into industrial</mark> or docklands <mark>areas if they want to work legally</u></strong>. <u>Such environments bring increased risks of violence and isolation and <strong>work against health and safety concerns</strong>.</mark> The Queensland Prostitution Act 1999 seeks to regulate prostitution by a brothel licensing system and town planning controls</u>. Recent criticisms have been made suggesting that the <u>tight regulatory framework has left most brothels operating illegally and put the lives of street workers at risk</u>. One of the only 12 licensed brothel owners commented: We’ve been pushed into industrial areas and hidden, we’re paying $20,000 a year for our licence before we can even open the doors, we’re fingerprinted and interrogated, we have trouble getting workers because we can’t advertise and they’re (the Government) in our faces all the time. (The Courier-Mail, 2003, quoted in Smith, 2003, 21).</p>
null
1NC
Off
430,300
9
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,592
That means the CP solves trafficking but the plan can’t
Huisman ’14
Huisman ’14 [Wim Huisman and Edward R. Kleemans, VU School of Criminology, Department of Criminal Law and Criminology, Faculty of Law, VU University, “The challenges of fighting sex trafficking in the legalized prostitution market of the Netherlands” 11 January 2014]
legalization leads to an increase in the numbers of trafficked women working in the regulated sector monitoring the regulated sector drains capacity from investigating the unregulated sector; and monitoring drains the capacity for investigating cases of human trafficking. there is insufficient police capacity left to play a major monitoring and investigative role with regard to punishable forms of operation outside the licensed sector. the licensed prostitution sector is not being fully monitored any increase in the police capacity to fight sex trafficking becomes dependent on the priority that local municipalities put on it.
monitoring the regulated sector drains capacity from investigating the unregulated sector; and drains the capacity for investigating cases of human trafficking. there is insufficient police capacity left to play a major role with regard to punishable forms of operation outside the licensed sector the licensed prostitution sector is not being fully monitored the police capacity to fight sex trafficking becomes dependent on local municipalities
In three ways, the legalization and regulation of the prostitution sector can influence the capacity of the police (in terms of manpower) to fight sex trafficking: first, when legalization leads to an increase in the numbers of trafficked women working in the regulated sector; second, when monitoring the regulated sector drains capacity from investigating the unregulated sector; and, third, when monitoring drains the capacity for investigating cases of human trafficking. Evaluation studies show that the police play a pivotal role in monitoring the licensed sector and in carrying out inspections [1]. The downside of these efforts is that there is insufficient police capacity left to play a major monitoring and investigative role with regard to punishable forms of operation outside the licensed sector. Thus, the assumption that the new policy would allow the police more capacity to fight human trafficking has not come to fruition. What is more, the feeling in the prostitution sector is that licensed businesses are inspected more often than non-licensed businesses, a situation which undermines the willingness of operators of licensed businesses to adhere to the rules and complicates the efforts to combat human trafficking [1]. Internal evaluations made by the police also show that the licensed prostitution sector is not being fully monitored and that it takes a lot of effort to monitor the unregulated parts of the business [26, 27]. The monitoring of the unregulated sector was described as ‘inefficient’ and ‘ineffective’ [26: 101]. Many police forces limit themselves to incidental and reactive inspections. The internal evaluations also show that the money spent on police efforts to support local authorities is not always reimbursed. In some regional police forces, local authorities financed extra police-officers. This can mean, however, that any increase in the police capacity to fight sex trafficking becomes dependent on the priority that local municipalities put on it. The National Rapporteur on Human Trafficking has frequently pointed at the importance of an inclusive policy which—besides monitoring the regulated side of the prostitution sector—also gives sufficient priority to fighting the unregulated, illegal side of prostitution. The reporter has repeatedly stressed the importance of having more capacity for criminal investigations of sex trafficking. The Dutch government has clearly stated that the police should increase their efforts to investigate and prosecute sex trafficking generally. Recent major criminal cases, however, have all targeted sex traffickers operating in the regulated sector [14].
2,650
<h4>That means the CP solves trafficking but the plan can’t</h4><p><strong>Huisman ’14 </strong>[Wim Huisman and Edward R. Kleemans, VU School of Criminology, Department of Criminal Law and Criminology, Faculty of Law, VU University, “The challenges of fighting sex trafficking in the legalized prostitution market of the Netherlands” 11 January 2014]</p><p>In three ways, the legalization and regulation of the prostitution sector can influence the capacity of the police (in terms of manpower) to fight sex trafficking: first, when <u>legalization leads to an increase in the numbers of trafficked women working in the regulated sector</u>; second, when <u><mark>monitoring the regulated sector drains capacity from investigating the unregulated sector;</mark> <mark>and</u></mark>, third, when <u>monitoring <mark>drains the capacity for investigating cases of human trafficking.</u></mark> Evaluation studies show that the police play a pivotal role in monitoring the licensed sector and in carrying out inspections [1]. The downside of these efforts is that <u><mark>there is insufficient police capacity left to play a major</mark> monitoring and investigative <mark>role with regard to punishable forms of operation outside the licensed sector</mark>.</u> Thus, the assumption that the new policy would allow the police more capacity to fight human trafficking has not come to fruition. What is more, the feeling in the prostitution sector is that licensed businesses are inspected more often than non-licensed businesses, a situation which undermines the willingness of operators of licensed businesses to adhere to the rules and complicates the efforts to combat human trafficking [1]. Internal evaluations made by the police also show that <u><mark>the licensed prostitution sector is not being fully monitored</u></mark> and that it takes a lot of effort to monitor the unregulated parts of the business [26, 27]. The monitoring of the unregulated sector was described as ‘inefficient’ and ‘ineffective’ [26: 101]. Many police forces limit themselves to incidental and reactive inspections. The internal evaluations also show that the money spent on police efforts to support local authorities is not always reimbursed. In some regional police forces, local authorities financed extra police-officers. This can mean, however, that <u>any increase in <mark>the</mark> <mark>police capacity to fight sex trafficking becomes dependent on</mark> the priority that <mark>local municipalities</mark> put on it.</u> The National Rapporteur on Human Trafficking has frequently pointed at the importance of an inclusive policy which—besides monitoring the regulated side of the prostitution sector—also gives sufficient priority to fighting the unregulated, illegal side of prostitution. The reporter has repeatedly stressed the importance of having more capacity for criminal investigations of sex trafficking. The Dutch government has clearly stated that the police should increase their efforts to investigate and prosecute sex trafficking generally. Recent major criminal cases, however, have all targeted sex traffickers operating in the regulated sector [14].</p>
null
1NC
Off
430,301
9
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,593
Turns stigmatization – the plan just shifts the burden onto those who cannot comply with regulations
Scoular 10,
Scoular 10, Jane, Professor of Law at University of Strathclyde, March 2010, “What's Law Got To Do With it? How and Why Law Matters in the Regulation of Sex Work,” Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 37, No. 1, Wiley Online, Accessed 9/10/14
contemporary forms of governance operate through these techniques of responsibilization. leading to increasing conditionality in citizenship and penality for those who cannot meet their terms regulation produces exclusions. legalized systems create a two-tiered industry, as the costs and norms of compliance are too onerous for most individuals and small brothel owners to bear. , it overwhelmingly favours profitable sex businesses which can now hardly be described as `other' to late-capitalist industries. the system of licensing encourages workers to self regulate to conform to certain modes of working in order to meet the conditions of registration. Inclusion is offered to those who `can perform the rituals of middle class society' with all of the typical exclusions based on age, status, race, health, and class This `ideal' typifies the rational subjects as law operates alongside practices while licensing can offer some increased improvement in the working conditions for a small section of workers, it operates to identify and exclude those who cannot meet the increasingly conditional nature of citizenship Thus in both systems, the moral engineering of advanced liberal governance has co-opted feminist concerns into techniques of governance and control. social exclusion is being used as leverage for increased control rather than for increased social justice. Empowerment simply operates to sanction forms of self-governance that support neo-liberal interests.
contemporary governance operate through techniques of responsibilization increasing conditionality in citizenship and penality for those who cannot meet terms regulation produces exclusions. legalized systems create a two-tiered industry, as the costs of compliance are too onerous for individuals and brothel owners it favours profitable sex businesses which as late-capitalist industries. licensing encourages workers to conform to modes of working Inclusion is offered to those who perform rituals of middle class society' with typical exclusions based on age, race, and class licensing operates to identify and exclude those who cannot meet the conditional nature of citizenship social exclusion is being used as leverage for control rather than justice. Empowerment operates to sanction forms of self-governance that support neo-liberal interests.
Despite being heralded as a `renewed welfare approach', which in any event is not necessarily benign, as my previous work with Maggie O'Neill94 points out, contemporary forms of governance operate through these techniques of responsibilization. Techniques of `exiting' women from prostitution must be viewed in the wider context of neo-liberalism in which welfare states, including the much renowned Swedish system, are retracting and being replaced by systems of private insurance, thus leading to increasing conditionality in citizenship and penality for those who cannot meet their terms/manage risks. In this context social exclusion is not tackled by structural change but via individual re-education, re-training, and entry into legitimate economies and relationships. By prioritizing `exiting' as a means of facilitating social inclusion rather than offering recognition, rights or redistribution to sex workers as a group, abolitionist systems promote forms of self-governance which require active citizens to self-regulate according to the norms of the family and the market. Those who act responsibly by adopting appropriate lifestyles via work and norms of sexuality are offered inclusion, those who do not or cannot and instead remain in sex work (which retains its criminal label) are further excluded, having failed to meet the increasingly normalized terms of citizenship in late-capitalist societies. The increased focus on male clients involves the promotion of similar individuating modes of governance. Despite the rhetoric of gender equality, the increased punitiveness towards (some) purchasers represents no more than the shifting of the `whore stigma' to a new deviant group. Responsibility becomes increasingly narrowed to client motives and individual sexual ethics, which are pathologized rather than explained in relation to their historical specificity and to the social and economic institutions that themselves structure the relations of gender domination.95 When action is taken through criminalization, or via the quasi-legal forums of john schools and name-and-shame campaigns, it typically operates on `a lower-tier of male heterosexual practices' or to `re-gender sexual stigma in certain middle class fractions',96 leaving the more mainstream corporate and private market untouched. The system of regulationism in the Netherlands encourages similar forms of self-governance and produces analogous exclusions. Research suggests that legalized systems create a two-tiered (if not more) industry, as the costs and norms of compliance are too onerous for most individuals and small brothel owners to bear. Thus, it overwhelmingly favours profitable sex businesses which, as Brents and Hausbeck note, can now hardly be described as `other' to late-capitalist industries.97 Alongside this, the system of licensing encourages workers to self regulate98 their behaviour in the interests of public health promotion, to conform to certain modes of working in order to meet the conditions of registration. Inclusion is offered to those who `can perform the rituals of middle class society'99 with all of the typical exclusions based on age, status, race, health, and class that this entails. This point is well illustrated in an advert which followed the decriminalization of brothels in New South Wales: . . . tall, blonde and stylish, she recently completed her tertiary marketing course and is looking for employment in the field . . . She provides her own condoms . . . and comes complete with a medical certificate.100 This `ideal' typifies the rational subjects encouraged by these processes, as law operates alongside practices, such as public health, to create and maintain what Scott calls a `responsible prostitution population'.101 The low take-up rate in the Netherlands indicates that very few can conform to this responsibilized model, meaning that while licensing can offer some increased improvement in the working conditions for a small section of workers, it also operates to identify and exclude those who cannot meet the increasingly conditional nature of citizenship, for example, migrants, the underage, and drug-users, all of whom are not incorporated within the framework of regulatory protection. Thus in both systems, the moral engineering of advanced liberal governance has co-opted feminist concerns into techniques of governance and control. Whether based on a recognition of sex workers' inherent agency or victimhood, social exclusion is being used as leverage for increased control rather than for increased social justice. Empowerment simply operates to sanction forms of self-governance that support neo-liberal interests. As Cruikshank notes, the recent proliferation of state-sponsored programmes of empowerment must be treated with critical caution, as even while they are utilizing the vocabulary of radical politics, their promise of emancipation may be merely rhetorical as they `endeavour to operationalise the self-governing capacity of the governed in the pursuit of governmental objectives'.102 Yet what both processes do well is to identify those who cannot perform, rendering them vulnerable to exclusion or banishment.
5,190
<h4>Turns stigmatization – the plan just shifts the burden onto those who cannot comply with regulations</h4><p><strong>Scoular 10, </strong>Jane, Professor of Law at University of Strathclyde, March 2010, “What's Law Got To Do With it? How and Why Law Matters in the Regulation of Sex Work,” Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 37, No. 1, Wiley Online, Accessed 9/10/14</p><p>Despite being heralded as a `renewed welfare approach', which in any event is not necessarily benign, as my previous work with Maggie O'Neill94 points out, <u><mark>contemporary</mark> forms of <mark>governance operate through</mark> these <mark>techniques of responsibilization</mark>. </u>Techniques of `exiting' women from prostitution must be viewed in the wider context of neo-liberalism in which welfare states, including the much renowned Swedish system, are retracting and being replaced by systems of private insurance, thus <u>leading to <mark>increasing conditionality in citizenship and penality for those who cannot meet</mark> their <mark>terms</u></mark>/manage risks. In this context social<u> </u>exclusion is not tackled by structural change but via individual re-education, re-training, and entry into legitimate economies and relationships. By prioritizing `exiting' as a means of facilitating social inclusion rather than offering recognition, rights or redistribution to sex workers as a group, abolitionist systems promote forms of self-governance which require active citizens to self-regulate according to the norms of the family and the market. Those who act responsibly by adopting appropriate lifestyles via work and norms of sexuality are offered inclusion, those who do not or cannot and instead remain in sex work (which retains its criminal label) are further excluded, having failed to meet the increasingly normalized terms of citizenship in late-capitalist societies. The increased focus on male clients involves the promotion of similar individuating modes of governance. Despite the rhetoric of gender equality, the increased punitiveness towards (some) purchasers represents no more than the shifting of the `whore stigma' to a new deviant group. Responsibility becomes increasingly narrowed to client motives and individual sexual ethics, which are pathologized rather than explained in relation to their historical specificity and to the social and economic institutions that themselves structure the relations of gender domination.95 When action is taken through criminalization, or via the quasi-legal forums of john schools and name-and-shame campaigns, it typically operates on `a lower-tier of male heterosexual practices' or to `re-gender sexual stigma in certain middle class fractions',96 leaving the more mainstream corporate and private market untouched. The system of <u><strong><mark>regulation</u></strong></mark>ism in the Netherlands encourages similar forms of self-governance and <u><strong><mark>produces</u></strong></mark> analogous <u><strong><mark>exclusions.</u></strong></mark> Research suggests that <u><mark>legalized systems create a two-tiered</u></mark> (if not more) <u><mark>industry, as the costs</mark> and norms <mark>of compliance are too onerous for</mark> most <mark>individuals and</mark> small <mark>brothel owners</mark> to bear.</u> Thus<u>, <mark>it</mark> overwhelmingly <mark>favours profitable sex businesses which</u></mark>, as Brents and Hausbeck note, <u>can now hardly be described <mark>as</mark> `other' to <mark>late-capitalist industries.</u></mark>97 Alongside this, <u>the system of <mark>licensing encourages workers</mark> to self regulate</u>98 their behaviour in the interests of public health promotion, <u><mark>to conform to</mark> certain <mark>modes of working</mark> in order to meet the conditions of registration. <mark>Inclusion is offered to those who</mark> `can <mark>perform</mark> the <mark>rituals of middle class society'</u></mark>99 <u><mark>with</mark> all of the <mark>typical exclusions based on <strong>age,</strong></mark> status, <strong><mark>race,</strong></mark> health, <mark>and <strong>class</u></strong></mark> that this entails. This point is well illustrated in an advert which followed the decriminalization of brothels in New South Wales: . . . tall, blonde and stylish, she recently completed her tertiary marketing course and is looking for employment in the field . . . She provides her own condoms . . . and comes complete with a medical certificate.100 <u>This `ideal' typifies the rational subjects</u> encouraged by these processes, <u>as law operates alongside practices</u>, such as public health, to create and maintain what Scott calls a `responsible prostitution population'.101 The low take-up rate in the Netherlands indicates that very few can conform to this responsibilized model, meaning that <u>while <mark>licensing</mark> can offer some increased improvement in the working conditions for a small section of workers, it</u> also <u><mark>operates to identify and exclude those who cannot meet the</mark> increasingly <mark>conditional nature of citizenship</u></mark>, for example, migrants, the underage, and drug-users, all of whom are not incorporated within the framework of regulatory protection. <u>Thus in both systems, the moral engineering of advanced liberal governance has co-opted feminist concerns into techniques of governance and control.</u> Whether based on a recognition of sex workers' inherent agency or victimhood, <u><mark>social exclusion is being used as leverage for</mark> increased <mark>control rather than</mark> for increased social <mark>justice. Empowerment</mark> simply <mark>operates to sanction</mark> <mark>forms of self-governance that support neo-liberal interests.</u></mark> As Cruikshank notes, the recent proliferation of state-sponsored programmes of empowerment must be treated with critical caution, as even while they are utilizing the vocabulary of radical politics, their promise of emancipation may be merely rhetorical as they `endeavour to operationalise the self-governing capacity of the governed in the pursuit of governmental objectives'.102 Yet what both processes do well is to identify those who cannot perform, rendering them vulnerable to exclusion or banishment. </p>
null
1NC
Off
429,913
13
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,594
Legal regimes for sex work require licensing and zoning. These mechanisms will be used to police racial and class Others.
Scoular 10,
Scoular 10, Jane, Professor of Law at University of Strathclyde, March 2010, “What's Law Got To Do With it? How and Why Law Matters in the Regulation of Sex Work,” Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 37, No. 1, Wiley Online, Accessed 9/10/14
Empirical evidence points to two parallel processes in which prostitution becomes a target for the state's wider efforts to responsibilize citizens, while simultaneously maintaining spaces for the operation of the capitalist economy. Processes of licensing and exiting operate to normalize particular forms of citizenship and sexual activity which enhance a broader structure of consumption, rendering deviant those who cannot through poverty, race, immigration status or health meet these increasingly restricted norms of citizenship, and marginalizing unproductive spaces. the normalization of commercial sex business reveal a shared set of underlying economic and cultural interests; the excision of class and racial Others from gentrifying inner cities, the facilitation of the post-industrial service sector, and the creation of clean urban spaces in which middle-class men can safely indulge in recreational commercial sexual consumption. This normative order is established via a continuum of regulatory mechanisms Law does play a vital role in authorizing other forms of knowledge, helping to shape content, and empowering a group of regulatory agents in exercising diffuse power an extended group of regulatory agents exercise normalizing power in `the bureaucratic workings of our over-governed existence'. These forums feature a hybridization of legal and non-legal authority. The state's role may be augmented by a wider range of control mechanisms and forms of professional intervention that may be even more pervasive Licensing decision making operates to reaffirm the dividing lines between legitimate and illegitimate forms of commercial sex. This ensures that the wider structures of governmentality fit with local conditions while appearing to comply with the liberal objection to state interference. the economic and racial segregation apparent in indoor settings appears distant and accidental as it is effected by powers exercised by diverse groups. the apparent increased `protection' promised by reforms results in the increased policing of many women's lives. the current preoccupation with particular subjects and spaces of sex work and the operationalizing of forms of governance to save, empower, responsibilize, and ethically reconstruct individuals all testament to law's increasing normalizing ambitions as it construct `the fabric of the modern subject'. both licensing and exiting operate to encourage subjects to perform as `self-governing, rational actors' required by the wider context of neo-liberalism and to identify those who cannot self-manage or who resist normalization in order that they be excluded.
Empirical evidence points to two parallel processes in which prostitution becomes a target for the state's efforts to responsibilize citizens, while maintaining the capitalist economy. licensing and exiting operate to normalize particular forms of citizenship enhance a broader structure of consumption, rendering deviant those who cannot through poverty, race, immigration status or health and marginalizing unproductive spaces. the normalization of commercial sex business reveal the excision of class and racial Others from inner cities, the facilitation of the post-industrial service sector, and creation of clean urban spaces in which middle-class men can safely indulge in sexual consumption. via a continuum of regulatory mechanisms regulatory agents exercise normalizing power The state may be augmented by wider control mechanisms and professional intervention Licensing operates to reaffirm the dividing lines between legitimate and illegitimate forms of sex. `protection' promised results in increased policing licensing and exiting encourage subjects to perform as `self-governing, rational actors' required by neo-liberalism and to identify those who resist normalization in order that they be excluded.
HOW LAW MATTERS 1. Norms By examining what law is doing in both cases, it becomes apparent that despite the difference in rhetoric, legal strategies for the governance of sex work share a number of similarities in terms of their regulatory ambitions. Empirical evidence points to two parallel processes in which prostitution becomes a target for the state's wider efforts to responsibilize citizens, while simultaneously maintaining spaces for the operation of the capitalist economy. Processes of licensing and exiting operate to normalize particular forms of citizenship and sexual activity which enhance a broader structure of consumption, rendering deviant those who cannot through poverty, race, immigration status or health meet these increasingly restricted norms of citizenship, and marginalizing unproductive spaces. As Bernstein notes: both the state policing of the street-level sex trade and the normalization of other forms of commercial sex business reveal a shared set of underlying economic and cultural interests; the excision of class and racial Others from gentrifying inner cities, the facilitation of the post-industrial service sector, and the creation of clean and shiny urban spaces in which middle-class men can safely indulge in recreational commercial sexual consumption.86 This normative order is established not through law as such but via a continuum of regulatory mechanisms of which it forms part. Law has no privilege in this system but it does play a vital role in authorizing other forms of knowledge, helping to shape content, and empowering a much wider group of regulatory agents in exercising more diffuse forms of power. 2. Authorizations Examining the extended forms of governance operating in this area may enlighten us more about what law is doing than the statute book. Thus, in the context of Sweden and the Netherlands, despite differences at a sovereign level in prostitution policy, law authorizes and operates though a number of quasi-legal forums (john schools, exiting programmes, rehabilitation schemes, and licensing boards) and techniques (anti-social behaviour orders, fines, rehabilitation orders, licenses) in which an extended group of regulatory agents exercise normalizing power: `all the little judges of conduct [who] exercise their petty powers of adjudication and enforcement'87 in what Valverde and Rose call `the bureaucratic workings of our over-governed existence'.88 These forums feature a hybridization of legal and non-legal authority. The state's role appears to recede but it may actually be augmented by a wider range of control mechanisms and forms of professional intervention that may be even more pervasive than the previous systems. Licensing decision making is devolved to a wider group, yet operates to reaffirm the dividing lines between legitimate and illegitimate forms of commercial sex. Indeed, it may be more useful than direct control as delegated authority refines law more minutely in response to shifting realities on the ground and employs a wider group of authorities in its realization. This ensures that the wider structures of governmentality fit with local conditions while appearing to comply with the liberal objection to state interference. Thus, in the case of the Netherlands, while street sex work has not been outlawed it has been made more and more difficult, as a number of municipalities in closing their tippelzones have dispensed with their previous assumed duties to provide safe places for street sex work. Similarly the economic and racial segregation apparent in indoor settings appears distant and accidental as it is effected by powers exercised by diverse groups. In Sweden decriminalization premised on exiting may actually signal a wider range of control mechanisms and forms of professional intervention which are even more pervasive than the previous system of fines. Thus, the apparent increased `protection' promised by reforms results in the increased policing of many women's lives.89 3. Subjectifications There is a question which is essential in the Modern Tribunal, but which would have had a strange ring to it 150 years [ago]: `Who are You?'90 Foucault's observation in The Dangerous Individual is that law in normalizing societies is increasingly concerned with lives rather than with acts. This is evident in the current preoccupation with particular subjects and spaces of sex work and the operationalizing of forms of governance to save, empower, responsibilize, and ethically reconstruct individuals – all testament to law's increasing normalizing ambitions as it acts alongside other discourses to construct `the fabric of the modern subject'.91 In doing so it operates not ideologically, as there is always resistance, nor through the simple imputation of legal consciousness,92 but through a process of subjectification, encouraging self-projects in ways that align with the diverse objectives of legislation.93 Thus, if we examine the continuities in the projects of self-governance promoted in each jurisdiction, we begin to see that the commonly accepted opposition between victim and agent may not be as marked when viewed through a governmental lens. Thus, through parallel forms of subjectification, both licensing and exiting operate to encourage subjects to perform as `self-governing, rational actors' required by the wider context of neo-liberalism and to identify those who cannot self-manage or who resist normalization in order that they be excluded.
5,500
<h4>Legal regimes for sex work require licensing and zoning. These mechanisms will be used to police racial and class Others. </h4><p><strong>Scoular 10, </strong>Jane, Professor of Law at University of Strathclyde, March 2010, “What's Law Got To Do With it? How and Why Law Matters in the Regulation of Sex Work,” Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 37, No. 1, Wiley Online, Accessed 9/10/14</p><p>HOW LAW MATTERS 1. Norms By examining what law is doing in both cases, it becomes apparent that despite the difference in rhetoric, legal strategies for the governance of sex work share a number of similarities in terms of their regulatory ambitions. <u><mark>Empirical evidence points to two parallel processes in which prostitution becomes a target for the state's</mark> wider <mark>efforts to responsibilize citizens, while</mark> simultaneously <mark>maintaining</mark> spaces for the operation of <mark>the capitalist economy.</mark> Processes of <mark>licensing and exiting operate to normalize particular forms of citizenship</mark> and sexual activity which <mark>enhance a broader structure of consumption, rendering deviant those who cannot through <strong>poverty, race, immigration status or health</strong></mark> meet these increasingly restricted norms of citizenship, <mark>and <strong>marginalizing unproductive spaces.</u></strong></mark> As Bernstein notes: both the state policing of the street-level sex trade and <u><mark>the normalization of</u></mark> other forms of <u><mark>commercial sex business reveal</mark> a shared set of underlying economic and cultural interests; <strong><mark>the excision of class and racial Others</strong> from</mark> gentrifying <mark>inner cities,</mark> <mark>the facilitation of the post-industrial service sector, and</mark> the <mark>creation of clean</u></mark> and shiny <u><mark>urban spaces in which middle-class men can safely indulge in</mark> recreational commercial <mark>sexual consumption.</u></mark>86 <u>This normative order is established</u> not through law as such but <u><strong><mark>via a continuum of regulatory mechanisms</u></strong></mark> of which it forms part. <u>Law</u> has no privilege in this system but it <u>does play a vital role in authorizing other forms of knowledge, helping to shape content, and empowering a</u> much wider <u>group of regulatory agents in exercising </u>more <u>diffuse</u> forms of<u> power</u>. 2. Authorizations Examining the extended forms of governance operating in this area may enlighten us more about what law is doing than the statute book. Thus, in the context of Sweden and the Netherlands, despite differences at a sovereign level in prostitution policy, law authorizes and operates though a number of quasi-legal forums (john schools, exiting programmes, rehabilitation schemes, and licensing boards) and techniques (anti-social behaviour orders, fines, rehabilitation orders, licenses) in which <u>an extended group of <mark>regulatory agents exercise normalizing power</u></mark>: `all the little judges of conduct [who] exercise their petty powers of adjudication and enforcement'87 <u>in</u> what Valverde and Rose call <u>`the bureaucratic workings of our over-governed existence'.</u>88 <u>These forums feature a hybridization of legal and non-legal authority. <mark>The state</mark>'s role</u> appears to recede but it <u><mark>may</u></mark> actually <u><mark>be augmented by</mark> a <mark>wider</mark> range of <mark>control mechanisms and</mark> forms of <mark>professional intervention</mark> that may be even more pervasive</u> than the previous systems. <u><mark>Licensing</mark> decision making</u> is devolved to a wider group, yet <u><mark>operates to reaffirm the dividing lines between legitimate and illegitimate forms of </mark>commercial <mark>sex.</mark> </u>Indeed, it may be more useful than direct control as delegated authority refines law more minutely in response to shifting realities on the ground and employs a wider group of authorities in its realization. <u>This ensures that the wider structures of governmentality fit with local conditions while appearing to comply with the liberal objection to state interference.</u> Thus, in the case of the Netherlands, while street sex work has not been outlawed it has been made more and more difficult, as a number of municipalities in closing their tippelzones have dispensed with their previous assumed duties to provide safe places for street sex work. Similarly <u>the economic and racial segregation apparent in indoor settings appears distant and accidental as it is effected by powers exercised by diverse groups.</u> In Sweden decriminalization premised on exiting may actually signal a wider range of control mechanisms and forms of professional intervention which are even more pervasive than the previous system of fines. Thus, <u>the apparent increased <mark>`protection' promised</mark> by reforms <mark>results in</mark> the <mark>increased policing</mark> of many women's lives.</u>89 3. Subjectifications There is a question which is essential in the Modern Tribunal, but which would have had a strange ring to it 150 years [ago]: `Who are You?'90 Foucault's observation in The Dangerous Individual is that law in normalizing societies is increasingly concerned with lives rather than with acts. This is evident in <u>the current preoccupation with particular subjects and spaces of sex work and the operationalizing of forms of governance to save, empower, responsibilize, and ethically reconstruct individuals</u> – <u>all testament to law's increasing normalizing ambitions as it</u> acts alongside other discourses to <u>construct `the fabric of the modern subject'.</u>91 In doing so it operates not ideologically, as there is always resistance, nor through the simple imputation of legal consciousness,92 but through a process of subjectification, encouraging self-projects in ways that align with the diverse objectives of legislation.93 Thus, if we examine the continuities in the projects of self-governance promoted in each jurisdiction, we begin to see that the commonly accepted opposition between victim and agent may not be as marked when viewed through a governmental lens. Thus, through parallel forms of subjectification, <u>both <mark>licensing and exiting</mark> operate to <mark>encourage subjects to perform as `self-governing, rational actors' required by</mark> the wider context of <mark>neo-liberalism and to identify those</mark> who cannot self-manage or <mark>who resist normalization in order that they be excluded.</u></mark> </p>
null
1NC
Off
1,240,914
14
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,595
A vote on Iran is coming but Obama has sufficient PC to sustain a veto- that’s key to negotiation success
Politico 3/17
Politico 3/17/2015 (White House blitzes Hill on Iran, http://www.politico.com/story/2015/03/white-house-blitzes-hill-on-iran-116170.html)
The White House is moving aggressively to limit Democratic defections on Capitol Hill that could undermine its negotiations with Iran dispatching Obama himself to lobby senators The push is to prevent a veto-proof majority from building by heading off any fresh Democratic support for the plan Obama has spoken directly with Democratic senators on the Foreign Relations Committee including Cardin Other senators who are weighing whether to join the legislative effort, such as Manchin have been briefed it amounted to a White House moving with dispatch to limit Democratic dissension in the face of a growing revolt from Congress Democratic leaders are letting the White House mount the lobbying push on its own. With virtually all 54 Republicans expected to back the bill, and 11 Senate Democratic Caucus members signaling their support, the White House has little margin for error in heading off a veto-proof majority In the letter to Corker McDonough reiterated Obama’s veto threats for the bipartisan legislation and urged Congress to hit the pause button until the final deal with Iran is reached. That could stretch into the summer moving on Corker’s bill while any stage of the negotiations is ongoing would not serve “the country’s interests Corker remained confident that his committee will vote on the Iran bill next week That timeline would give McConnell the ability to begin debate on Corker’s bill by mid-April the White House whipping operation is causing some Democratic senators to have second thoughts about whether to support Corker’s bill Cardin would not commit to voting for Corker’s bill Nelson wouldn’t say how he would vote I’m talking to the White House almost every day about this said Murphy their high level of activity this week is going to move the needle the White House lobbying effort seems to have persuaded other Democrats not to break ranks Shaheen opposes moving forward on the matter in committee
The White House is moving to limit Democratic defections that could undermine negotiations with Iran, dispatchin Obama himself to lobby senators The push is to prevent a veto-proof majority Democratic leaders are letting the White House mount the push on its own he White House has little margin for erro In the letter to Corker McDonough urged Congress to hit the pause button until the final deal with Iran is reached moving on Corker’s bill while any stage of the negotiations is ongoing would not serve “the country’s interests. Corker remained confident that his committee will vote on the Iran bill next week That would give McConnell the ability to begin debate by mid-April the White House whipping operation is causing some Democratic senators to have second thoughts about whether to support Corker’s bill Cardin would not commit Nelson wouldn’t say how he would vote their activity is going to move the needle Shaheen opposes moving forward
The White House is moving aggressively to limit Democratic defections on Capitol Hill that could undermine its negotiations with Iran, dispatching senior officials and President Barack Obama himself to lobby senators against taking action before a nuclear deal with the rogue regime is reached. Senior administration officials have asked Senate Democrats to notify the White House if they are considering signing onto a bill drafted by Sens. Bob Corker (R-Tenn.) and Robert Menendez (D-N.J.) that would give Congress the ability to accept or reject any nuclear deal. The push, several Senate sources said, is to prevent a veto-proof majority from building by heading off any fresh Democratic support for the plan and persuade supporters to keep their powder dry until the conclusion of multilateral negotiations with Iran. The lobbying effort has come from all quarters. Obama has spoken directly with Democratic senators on the Foreign Relations Committee, including Ben Cardin of Maryland. Other senators who are weighing whether to join the legislative effort, such as Joe Manchin of West Virginia, have been briefed by the likes of Samantha Power, the U.S. ambassador to the United Nations. Vice President Joe Biden, Secretary of State John Kerry and Treasury Secretary Jack Lew have reached out directly to senators, according to sources on Capitol Hill. And the White House chief of staff, Denis McDonough, warned lawmakers bluntly in a Saturday night letter not to interfere before a tentative deal is reached this month and the final terms are inked in late June. All told, senators said, it amounted to a White House moving with dispatch to limit Democratic dissension in the face of a growing revolt from Congress. “I would call it serious-minded,” said Maine Sen. Angus King, an independent who caucuses with Democrats and has discussed the Corker-Menendez bill with administration officials in recent days. He has co-sponsored the plan but has not said how he would vote if the measure heads to the floor imminently. “I think they are concerned.” With their caucus divided, Senate Democratic leaders are letting the White House mount the lobbying push on its own. Asked Tuesday whether he was encouraging his members to oppose the Corker-Menendez bill, Senate Minority Leader Harry Reid said flatly, “No.” With virtually all 54 Republicans expected to back the bill, and 11 Senate Democratic Caucus members signaling their support, the White House has little margin for error in heading off a veto-proof majority. White House officials declined to comment. But they pointed to the McDonough letter, which showcased the administration’s thinking on Hill action as negotiations intensify between six world powers and Iran aimed at alleviating sanctions on the Middle East nation in exchange for curbing its nuclear program. The White House says there have been more than 100 meetings, hearings, briefings and calls with lawmakers on the matter since January. In the letter to Corker on Saturday, McDonough reiterated Obama’s veto threats for the bipartisan legislation and urged Congress to hit the pause button until the final deal with Iran is reached. That could stretch into the summer after this month’s deadline to sign off on the outlines of a plan. McDonough said plainly that moving on Corker’s bill while any stage of the negotiations is ongoing would not serve “the country’s interests.” “Let us complete the negotiations before the Congress acts on legislation,” McDonough wrote. “If we successfully negotiate a framework by the end of this month, and a final deal by the end of June, we expect a robust debate in Congress.” Corker, chairman of the Foreign Relations Committee, is frustrated by the White House’s handling of the issue. He said Tuesday he remained “fairly” confident that his committee will vote on the Iran bill next week, coinciding with the March 24 deadline Democratic supporters of the bill have set before pushing forward. Detractors worry that a bad deal would only pave the way for Iran to build a nuclear bomb. “They’re using every tactic available to try to keep Congress from playing its rightful role on Iran,” Corker said of the White House. “We’ve delayed the vote to accommodate people’s desire to let the 24th come and go. But I think we’re at a place now where we need to go ahead and move it through committee.” That timeline would give Senate Majority Leader Mitch McConnell (R-Ky.) the ability to begin debate on Corker’s bill by perhaps mid-April, when the Senate reconvenes after Easter recess. But symbolic votes on Iran could take place on the floor next week when the Senate takes up its annual budget resolution. While Menendez is a co-sponsor of the bill, he has said Congress should hold off acting until after the March 24 deadline. Whether he would wait until June is another question. “As I said, we’re going to wait until the 24th, which was their deadline originally, and then we will come to a conclusion,” Menendez, the committee’s ranking member, said when asked about holding off until June. Asked if he would commit to voting for the plan in the Foreign Relations Committee next week, Menendez would say only that he’s “talking to the chairman about it.” But the White House whipping operation is causing some Democratic senators to have second thoughts about whether to support Corker’s bill in committee next week or in April, when Senate leaders hope to bring the bill to the Senate floor. “What I got from the president is he needs the latitude to be able to negotiate, which I support. And this could impact his ability to negotiate,” said Cardin, who would not commit to voting for Corker’s bill even after March 24. “I want to give the president every opportunity, but I do think we have certain responsibilities in Congress.” Sen. Bill Nelson (D-Fla.), who also co-sponsored the bill, said that it was “preferable” that Congress wait until after June to weigh in, but he wouldn’t say how he would vote before then. “I’d prefer that they wait,” he said. “I’m talking to the White House almost every day about this. I think their antenna is up,” said Sen. Chris Murphy (D-Conn.), a member of the Foreign Relations Committee. “My hope is their high level of activity this week is going to move the needle and persuade us to unite behind the president.” But others are less concerned with the timing of congressional action, demanding instead that they get the bill ready so Capitol Hill has a vehicle for expressing its support or opposition to an Iran deal. The bill would also prohibit the president from suspending congressional sanctions on Iran for 60 days while Congress reviews the deal. And it would require that Obama report on Iran’s compliance with the deal every three months. Democratic Sen. Tim Kaine of Virginia, another Foreign Relations Committee member, did not appear eager to heed the White House’s request to wait until June. “Last Thursday, I talked to a key administration official who said, ‘I hope you’re going to wait at least until the end of March.’ Then it sounded like it’s kind of till the end of the June,” Kaine said. “Look, Congress is going to weigh in. … I don’t think the timing issue is that critical.” King added: “I talked to [the White House]. I’m still listening. I thought the McDonough letter was well written and thoughtful, but right now I continue to believe having a congressional role is responsible.” Others are also ready to buck the administration. Sen. Richard Blumenthal, a liberal Democrat, said he was asking for changes to the Corker-Menendez bill before he “probably” will sign onto it. “Iran is at the table now because of sanctions that Congress has firmly pressed,” said Blumenthal, who has spoken to a “variety” of administration officials in recent weeks. “The principle of congressional review and the Senate’s role is an important principle that should be established from the outset.” Still, the White House lobbying effort seems to have persuaded other Democrats not to break ranks. Sen. Jeanne Shaheen of New Hampshire, who sits on the Foreign Relations Committee, said she opposes moving forward on the matter in committee next week. “The conversations that I had were about where they are in the negotiations, what currently the sticking points are, how they’re feeling about potential progress,” Shaheen said of her discussions with the administration. “I want to see if we get an agreement, what might be in that kind of agreement and then make a decision at that point.”
8,524
<h4>A vote on Iran is coming but Obama has sufficient PC to sustain a veto- that’s key to negotiation success</h4><p><strong>Politico 3/17</strong>/2015 (White House blitzes Hill on Iran, http://www.politico.com/story/2015/03/white-house-blitzes-hill-on-iran-116170.html)</p><p><u><mark>The White House is moving</mark> aggressively <mark>to limit Democratic defections</mark> on Capitol Hill <mark>that could undermine</mark> its <mark>negotiations with Iran</u>, <u><strong>dispatchin</mark>g</u></strong> senior officials and President Barack <u><strong><mark>Obama himself to lobby senators</u></strong></mark> against taking action before a nuclear deal with the rogue regime is reached. Senior administration officials have asked Senate Democrats to notify the White House if they are considering signing onto a bill drafted by Sens. Bob Corker (R-Tenn.) and Robert Menendez (D-N.J.) that would give Congress the ability to accept or reject any nuclear deal. <u><mark>The push</u></mark>, several Senate sources said, <u><mark>is to prevent a veto-proof majority</mark> from building by heading off any fresh Democratic support for the plan</u> and persuade supporters to keep their powder dry until the conclusion of multilateral negotiations with Iran. The lobbying effort has come from all quarters. <u>Obama has spoken directly with Democratic senators on the Foreign Relations Committee</u>, <u>including</u> Ben <u>Cardin</u> of Maryland. <u>Other senators who are weighing whether to join the legislative effort, such as</u> Joe <u>Manchin</u> of West Virginia, <u>have been briefed</u> by the likes of Samantha Power, the U.S. ambassador to the United Nations. Vice President Joe Biden, Secretary of State John Kerry and Treasury Secretary Jack Lew have reached out directly to senators, according to sources on Capitol Hill. And the White House chief of staff, Denis McDonough, warned lawmakers bluntly in a Saturday night letter not to interfere before a tentative deal is reached this month and the final terms are inked in late June. All told, senators said, <u>it amounted to a White House moving with dispatch to limit Democratic dissension in the face of a growing revolt from Congress</u>. “I would call it serious-minded,” said Maine Sen. Angus King, an independent who caucuses with Democrats and has discussed the Corker-Menendez bill with administration officials in recent days. He has co-sponsored the plan but has not said how he would vote if the measure heads to the floor imminently. “I think they are concerned.” With their caucus divided, Senate <u><mark>Democratic leaders are letting the White House mount the</mark> lobbying <mark>push on its own</mark>.</u> Asked Tuesday whether he was encouraging his members to oppose the Corker-Menendez bill, Senate Minority Leader Harry Reid said flatly, “No.” <u>With virtually all 54 Republicans expected to back the bill, and 11 Senate Democratic Caucus members signaling their support, <strong>t<mark>he White House has little margin for erro</mark>r in heading off a veto-proof majority</u></strong>. White House officials declined to comment. But they pointed to the McDonough letter, which showcased the administration’s thinking on Hill action as negotiations intensify between six world powers and Iran aimed at alleviating sanctions on the Middle East nation in exchange for curbing its nuclear program. The White House says there have been more than 100 meetings, hearings, briefings and calls with lawmakers on the matter since January. <u><mark>In the letter to Corker</u></mark> on Saturday, <u><mark>McDonough</mark> reiterated Obama’s veto threats for the bipartisan legislation and <mark>urged Congress to hit the pause button until the final deal with Iran is reached</mark>. That could stretch into the summer</u> after this month’s deadline to sign off on the outlines of a plan. McDonough said plainly that <u><mark>moving on Corker’s bill while any stage of the negotiations is ongoing would not serve “the country’s interests</u>.</mark>” “Let us complete the negotiations before the Congress acts on legislation,” McDonough wrote. “If we successfully negotiate a framework by the end of this month, and a final deal by the end of June, we expect a robust debate in Congress.” <u><mark>Corker</u></mark>, chairman of the Foreign Relations Committee, is frustrated by the White House’s handling of the issue. He said Tuesday he <u><mark>remained</u></mark> “fairly” <u><mark>confident that his committee will vote on the Iran bill next week</u></mark>, coinciding with the March 24 deadline Democratic supporters of the bill have set before pushing forward. Detractors worry that a bad deal would only pave the way for Iran to build a nuclear bomb. “They’re using every tactic available to try to keep Congress from playing its rightful role on Iran,” Corker said of the White House. “We’ve delayed the vote to accommodate people’s desire to let the 24th come and go. But I think we’re at a place now where we need to go ahead and move it through committee.” <u><mark>That</mark> timeline <mark>would give</u></mark> Senate Majority Leader Mitch <u><mark>McConnell</u></mark> (R-Ky.) <u><mark>the ability to begin debate</mark> on Corker’s bill <mark>by</u></mark> perhaps <u><mark>mid-April</u></mark>, when the Senate reconvenes after Easter recess. But symbolic votes on Iran could take place on the floor next week when the Senate takes up its annual budget resolution. While Menendez is a co-sponsor of the bill, he has said Congress should hold off acting until after the March 24 deadline. Whether he would wait until June is another question. “As I said, we’re going to wait until the 24th, which was their deadline originally, and then we will come to a conclusion,” Menendez, the committee’s ranking member, said when asked about holding off until June. Asked if he would commit to voting for the plan in the Foreign Relations Committee next week, Menendez would say only that he’s “talking to the chairman about it.” But <u><strong><mark>the White House whipping operation is causing some Democratic senators to have second thoughts about whether to support Corker’s bill</u></strong></mark> in committee next week or in April, when Senate leaders hope to bring the bill to the Senate floor. “What I got from the president is he needs the latitude to be able to negotiate, which I support. And this could impact his ability to negotiate,” said <u><mark>Cardin</u></mark>, who <u><mark>would</mark> <mark>not commit</mark> to voting for Corker’s bill</u> even after March 24. “I want to give the president every opportunity, but I do think we have certain responsibilities in Congress.” Sen. Bill <u><mark>Nelson</u></mark> (D-Fla.), who also co-sponsored the bill, said that it was “preferable” that Congress wait until after June to weigh in, but he <u><mark>wouldn’t say how he would vote</u></mark> before then. “I’d prefer that they wait,” he said. “<u>I’m talking to the White House almost every day about this</u>. I think their antenna is up,” <u>said</u> Sen. Chris <u>Murphy</u> (D-Conn.), a member of the Foreign Relations Committee. “My hope is <u><strong><mark>their</mark> high level of <mark>activity</mark> this week <mark>is going to move the needle</u></strong></mark> and persuade us to unite behind the president.” But others are less concerned with the timing of congressional action, demanding instead that they get the bill ready so Capitol Hill has a vehicle for expressing its support or opposition to an Iran deal. The bill would also prohibit the president from suspending congressional sanctions on Iran for 60 days while Congress reviews the deal. And it would require that Obama report on Iran’s compliance with the deal every three months. Democratic Sen. Tim Kaine of Virginia, another Foreign Relations Committee member, did not appear eager to heed the White House’s request to wait until June. “Last Thursday, I talked to a key administration official who said, ‘I hope you’re going to wait at least until the end of March.’ Then it sounded like it’s kind of till the end of the June,” Kaine said. “Look, Congress is going to weigh in. … I don’t think the timing issue is that critical.” King added: “I talked to [the White House]. I’m still listening. I thought the McDonough letter was well written and thoughtful, but right now I continue to believe having a congressional role is responsible.” Others are also ready to buck the administration. Sen. Richard Blumenthal, a liberal Democrat, said he was asking for changes to the Corker-Menendez bill before he “probably” will sign onto it. “Iran is at the table now because of sanctions that Congress has firmly pressed,” said Blumenthal, who has spoken to a “variety” of administration officials in recent weeks. “The principle of congressional review and the Senate’s role is an important principle that should be established from the outset.” Still, <u>the White House lobbying effort seems to have persuaded other Democrats not to break ranks</u>. Sen. Jeanne <u><mark>Shaheen</u></mark> of New Hampshire, who sits on the Foreign Relations Committee, said she <u><mark>opposes moving forward</mark> on the matter in committee</u> next week. “The conversations that I had were about where they are in the negotiations, what currently the sticking points are, how they’re feeling about potential progress,” Shaheen said of her discussions with the administration. “I want to see if we get an agreement, what might be in that kind of agreement and then make a decision at that point.”</p>
null
1NC
Off
430,302
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,596
Zero support for legalization
Weitzer 2012
Weitzer 2012 (Ronald John Weitzer is a sociologist specializing in criminology and a professor at George Washington University, known for his publications on police-minority relations and on the sex industry, Legalizing Prostitution, http://www.academia.edu/8455363/Conclusion_chapter_LEGALIZING_PROSTITUTION)
victimization or harm is viewed as much more prevalent in prostitution than in other areas despite the fact that sex workers favor decriminalization, they have been reluctant to mobilize for reform; the "right" to controlwhat one does sexually with one's body has not Per- suaded policymakers a lack of debate in political circles and in the media regarding alternatives to criminalization; limited public support weak or nonexis- tent alliances between sex workers' rights groups and other influential interest groups and potent opposition a robust and influential coalition of interest groups on the right and left commit- ted to keeping prostitution illegal
victimization is viewed as prevalent in prostitution sex workers have been reluctant to mobilize for reform the "right" to controlwhat one does with one's body has not Per- suaded policymakers a lack of debate in political circles regarding alternatives to criminalization and potent opposition: a robust and influential coalition of interest groups on the right and left commit- ted to keeping prostitution illegal
There are several reasons: (r) victimization or harm is viewed as much more prevalent in prostitution than in some of the other areas (marijuana use, gam- bling, gay rights); (z) a largely silent constituency: despite the fact that many sex workers and clients favor decriminalization, they have been reluctant to mobilize for reform;" (:) a shakier rights justification: the "right" to controlwhat one does sexually with one's body is frequently advanced but has not Per- suaded policymakers (in contrast to gay rights, abortion rights, free-speech rights underlying pornography); (+) a lack of debate in political circles and in the media regarding alternatives to criminalization; (;) limited public support for decriminalization in the United States compared to many other nationsand in contrast to Americans' overwhelming support for legal garnbling and medical marijuana and growing support for gay rights; (6) weak or nonexis- tent alliances between sex workers' rights groups and other influential interest groups, especially women's rights organizations; and (Z) potent opposition: a robust and influential coalition of interest groups on the right and left commit- ted to keeping prostitution illegal and criminalizing other types of sex work.
1,253
<h4>Zero support for legalization</h4><p><strong>Weitzer 2012</strong> (Ronald John Weitzer is a sociologist specializing in criminology and a professor at George Washington University, known for his publications on police-minority relations and on the sex industry, Legalizing Prostitution, http://www.academia.edu/8455363/Conclusion_chapter_LEGALIZING_PROSTITUTION)</p><p>There are several reasons: (r) <u><mark>victimization</mark> or harm <mark>is viewed as</mark> much more <mark>prevalent in prostitution</mark> than in </u>some of the <u>other areas</u> (marijuana use, gam- bling, gay rights); (z) a largely silent constituency: <u>despite the fact that</u> many <u><mark>sex workers</u></mark> and clients <u>favor decriminalization, they <mark>have been reluctant to mobilize for reform</mark>;</u>" (:) a shakier rights justification: <u><mark>the "right" to controlwhat one does</mark> sexually <mark>with one's body</u></mark> is frequently advanced but <u><mark>has not Per- suaded policymakers</u></mark> (in contrast to gay rights, abortion rights, free-speech rights underlying pornography); (+) <u><mark>a lack of debate in political circles</mark> and in the media <mark>regarding alternatives to criminalization</mark>;</u> (;) <u>limited public support</u> for decriminalization in the United States compared to many other nationsand in contrast to Americans' overwhelming support for legal garnbling and medical marijuana and growing support for gay rights; (6) <u>weak or nonexis- tent alliances between sex workers' rights groups and other influential interest groups</u>, especially women's rights organizations; <u><mark>and</u></mark> (Z) <u><strong><mark>potent opposition</u></strong>: <u>a robust and influential coalition of interest groups on the right and left <strong>commit- ted to keeping prostitution illegal</u></strong></mark> and criminalizing other types of sex work.</p>
null
1NC
Off
430,303
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,597
bill tanks Iran negotiations
Cohen 3/4
Cohen 3/4 (Rachel M, The American Prospect, 3/4/15, “how to sabotage iran negotiations in the name of avoiding war”, http://prospect.org/article/how-sabotage-iran-negotiations-name-avoiding-war)
Corker-Menendez bill Edward Levine, an advisory board member for the Center for Arms Control and Non-Proliferation, a nonprofit research organization dedicated to international peace and security, argues that the bill is more harmful than helpful: send a message to Tehran that the President may be unable to fulfill his commitments move the goalposts by adding support for terrorism to the list of reasons for reinstating sanctions? The Corker bill will endanger both the negotiations and the sanctions regime; it does not merit support Let’s just hope that the Iranians do not take this as a signal that the negotiators’ commitment to ease sanctions in exchange for good behavior is feeble. Because if the negotiations fail, the war that everyone is trying to avoid is that much more likely
Corker-Menendez bill Edward Levine, an advisory board member for the Center for Arms Control and Non-Proliferation, argues that the bill is harmful t send a message to Tehran that the President may be unable to fulfill his commitments move the goalposts by adding support for terrorism to the list of reasons for reinstating sanctions will endanger both the negotiations and the sanctions regime hope that the Iranians do not take this as a signal Because if the negotiations fail, the war that everyone is trying to avoid is that much more likely.
Passing the Corker-Menendez bill might be an easier sell in Congress than imposing additional sanctions, because it is easier to argue that Congress should have “a voice” in the negotiating process. However, Senate Majority Leader Mitch McConnell announced Tuesday night that he wants to fast-track the bill, which might complicate its ability to garner enough Democratic support in time. Menendez has threatened to vote against his own bill, “outraged” at McConnell’s political move. Edward Levine, an advisory board member for the Center for Arms Control and Non-Proliferation, a nonprofit research organization dedicated to international peace and security, argues that the bill is more harmful than helpful: Do [Senators] really want to send a message to Tehran that the President may be unable to fulfill his commitments? Do they really want to move the goalposts by adding support for terrorism to the list of reasons for reinstating sanctions? The Corker bill will endanger both the negotiations and the sanctions regime; it does not merit support. AIPAC is also trying to bolster Congress’s role in the negotiations by minimizing the fact that there has always been significant presidential authority built into U.S. sanctions legislation. The authority comes through various mechanisms, such as “waivers,” special rules, and legislative exemptions, which allow a president to decide, often unilaterally, whether and to what degree to lift or implement sanctions. He can make these choices if he believes doing so is in the national security interest of the United States. On Capitol Hill on Tuesday, AIPAC’s legions of supporters pressured Congress to impose more sanctions and to reduce the executive branch’s power to lift sanctions. Let’s just hope that the Iranians do not take this as a signal that the negotiators’ commitment to ease sanctions in exchange for good behavior is feeble. Because if the negotiations fail, the war that everyone is trying to avoid is that much more likely.
2,000
<h4>bill tanks Iran negotiations </h4><p><strong>Cohen 3/4</strong> (Rachel M, The American Prospect, 3/4/15, “how to sabotage iran negotiations in the name of avoiding war”, http://prospect.org/article/how-sabotage-iran-negotiations-name-avoiding-war)</p><p>Passing the <u><mark>Corker-Menendez bill</u></mark> might be an easier sell in Congress than imposing additional sanctions, because it is easier to argue that Congress should have “a voice” in the negotiating process. However, Senate Majority Leader Mitch McConnell announced Tuesday night that he wants to fast-track the bill, which might complicate its ability to garner enough Democratic support in time. Menendez has threatened to vote against his own bill, “outraged” at McConnell’s political move. <u><mark>Edward Levine, an advisory board member for the Center for Arms Control and Non-Proliferation,</mark> a nonprofit research organization dedicated to international peace and security, <mark>argues that the bill is</mark> more <mark>harmful t</mark>han helpful: </u>Do [Senators] really want to <u><mark>send a message to Tehran that the President may be unable to fulfill his commitments</u></mark>? Do they really want to <u><mark>move the goalposts by adding support for terrorism to the list of reasons for reinstating sanctions</mark>? The Corker bill <mark>will endanger both the negotiations and the sanctions regime</mark>; it does not merit support</u>. AIPAC is also trying to bolster Congress’s role in the negotiations by minimizing the fact that there has always been significant presidential authority built into U.S. sanctions legislation. The authority comes through various mechanisms, such as “waivers,” special rules, and legislative exemptions, which allow a president to decide, often unilaterally, whether and to what degree to lift or implement sanctions. He can make these choices if he believes doing so is in the national security interest of the United States. On Capitol Hill on Tuesday, AIPAC’s legions of supporters pressured Congress to impose more sanctions and to reduce the executive branch’s power to lift sanctions. <u>Let’s just <mark>hope that the Iranians do not take this as a signal</mark> that the negotiators’ commitment to ease sanctions in exchange for good behavior is feeble. <mark>Because if the negotiations fail, the war that everyone is trying to avoid is that much more likely</u>.</mark> </p>
null
1NC
Off
430,304
2
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,598
Extinction - Negotiations failure triggers military strikes and regional proliferation-causes escalatory wars and collapses the economy
Cordesman, , 2013
Cordesman, CSIS, 2013 (Anthony, “Negotiating with Iran: The Strategic Case for Pragmatism and Real Progress”, 9-23, http://csis.org/publication/negotiating-iran-strategic-case-pragmatism-and-real-progress)
Nevertheless, it makes no sense at all to reject Hassan Rouhani’s opening or condemn the Obama Administration’s response Iran’s grams have moved to the point where it is extremely doubtful that there will be another chance to begin a difficult process and an attempt at resolution is far better than any of the real world alternatives. As long as any negotiations that follow are realistic in terms of their content they offer what will be the last real hope of avoiding preventive strikes or a process of containment that would lock the region into an Iranian-Israeli nuclear arms race, a probable Saudi effort to acquire its own nuclear weapons, and a U.S. commitment to extended deterrence. Iran may well face a series of preventive strikes – triggered by Israel or planned by the United States – that will destroy far more than its nuclear facilities. A limited set of Israeli preventive strikes could either force the United States to follow up, or create a situation in which Iran rejects all arms control and UN inspection and carries out a massive new disperse nuclear program or a crash basis. It could also drive Iran to lash out into a new wave of confrontation with the United States and Iran’s neighbors. result would be years more of a regional arms race, military tension, and Iranian efforts to find ways to attack or pressure the Arab states, Israel, and United States. no one can predict limits to Iran’s reactions, ability to use third parties, and willingness to confront the United States and the region with new nuclear, missile, and asymmetric threats. If there are no preventive strikes – or preventive strikes fail to halt Iran – what is now a largely quiet one-sided nuclear arms race would become far more threatening At one level, this arms race would become one between Iran and any allies it could find and the United States and its Arab allies in or near the Gulf. A nuclear Iran could change the balance in terms of the credibility of U.S. and Arab willingness to engage against Iranian threats, intimidation, and use of its asymmetric forces It would inevitably make Gulf petroleum exports the scene of an ongoing arms race and constant tension, and risk a clash that might escalate in untended ways. Israel would scarcely be passive however, and Israel already has far more capable missiles than Iran Israel will pose more of an existentialist threat to an Iran as dependent on the survival of Tehran than Iran can pose to an Israel dependent on the survival of Tel Aviv. The problem with mutually assured destruction is that no state can ever win an existential strike contest. the resulting threat to world oil exports and the world economy is not likely to intimidate to any degree that will benefit Iran. It will push both the United States and Arab states into responding. Iran can only vastly increase the scale of the resulting destruction that the United States and its allies inflict if Iran ever actually escalates to the use of nuclear weapons. But the United States, the Arab allies, Israel, and other regional states will suffer as well – along with the global economy – if the end result is a major interruption in the flow of Gulf petroleum exports.
Iran moved to where it is doubtful there will be another chance and resolution is better than alternatives they offer the last hope of avoiding strikes or containment that would lock in nuclear arms race Israeli preventive strikes force the U S to follow up, or create a situation in which Iran rejects arms control carries out a massive nuclear program or a crash basis. It could drive Iran to lash out result would be a regional arms race, military tension If there are no strikes what is a one-sided nuclear race would become more threatening between Iran and allies in the Gulf It would make Gulf petroleum exports the scene of an ongoing arms race and tension, and risk a clash that might escalate The problem with m a d is no state can ever win an existential strike the resulting threat to the world economy is not likely to intimidate Iran Iran vastly increase the resulting destruction the U S Arab allies, Israel, and regional states will suffer as well – along with the global economy
Nevertheless, it makes no sense at all to reject Hassan Rouhani’s opening or condemn the Obama Administration’s response. Iran’s nuclear programs have moved to the point where it is extremely doubtful that there will be another chance to begin what may be a long and difficult process for all nations involved, and an attempt at resolution is far better than any of the real world alternatives. As long as any negotiations that follow are realistic in terms of their content, and do not endorse indefinite delay in a U.S. response while Iran’s nuclear programs move forward, they offer what will be the last real hope of avoiding preventive strikes or a process of containment that would lock the region into an Iranian-Israeli nuclear arms race, a probable Saudi effort to acquire its own nuclear weapons, and a U.S. commitment to extended deterrence. The Uncertain Outcome of Preventive Strikes The United States, Iran, and all the other nations involved need to be far more pragmatic about what will happen if time does run out and Iran does go nuclear. Iran may well face a series of preventive strikes – triggered by Israel or planned by the United States – that will destroy far more than its nuclear facilities. This may or may not actually halt the Iranian nuclear effort. A limited set of Israeli preventive strikes could either force the United States to follow up, or create a situation in which Iran rejects all arms control and UN inspection and carries out a massive new disperse nuclear program or a crash basis. It could also drive Iran to lash out into a new wave of confrontation with the United States and Iran’s neighbors. A U.S.-led set of preventive strikes would be more successful, but the United States could only be sure of suppressing a meaningful Iran nuclear effort if it quickly re-strikes any known target it fails to destroy the first time, carries out constant surveillance of Iran, and repeatedly and thoroughly strikes at the targets created by any new Iranian initiatives. The United States would need regional support to do this and probably prolonged regional agreement to U.S. basing. At a minimum, the result would be years more of a regional arms race, military tension, and Iranian efforts to find ways to attack or pressure the Arab states, Israel, and United States. As the current conflict in Syria makes all too clear, no one can predict how much support the United States will really get from any of its allies, its own U.S. Congress, and no one can predict the limits to Iran’s reactions, ability to use third parties, and willingness to confront the United States and the region with new nuclear, missile, and asymmetric threats. The United States would face an almost certain challenge in the UN from Russia and China, and there is no way any U.S. action against Iran could be separated from Iran’s efforts in Iraq, Syria, or Lebanon; Afghanistan, or any other issue where Iran could try to find some form of revenge. This is not an argument for not acting. The risk of a fully nuclear Iran is simply too great. It is a very strong argument for finding a good alternative if one can be negotiated on realistic terms. The Uncertain Outcome of Iran Nuclear Weapons and Containment: The Most Likely Outcome is a No Win Escalation Ladder Contest If there are no preventive strikes – or preventive strikes fail to halt Iran – what is now a largely quiet one-sided nuclear arms race would become far more threatening. At one level, this arms race would become one between Iran and any allies it could find and the United States and its Arab allies in or near the Gulf. A nuclear Iran could change the balance in terms of the credibility of U.S. and Arab willingness to engage against Iranian threats, intimidation, and use of its asymmetric forces. It would inevitably make Gulf petroleum exports the scene of an ongoing arms race and constant tension, and risk a clash that might escalate in untended ways. What is less apparent – and needs far more realistic attention in Iran and outside assessments of the Iranian nuclear threat – is the impact of Iran actually going nuclear. One or several crude nuclear devices do not create a nuclear force. Iran cannot produce enough capable nuclear forces for at least the next decade to pose more of an existential threat to Israel than Israel can pose to Iran. Israel would scarcely be passive, however, and Israel already has far more capable missiles than Iran. Israel also has thermonuclear weapons, rather than the early fission devices Iran will probably be limited to for at least the next half-decade. As a result Israel will pose more of an existentialist threat to an Iran as dependent on the survival of Tehran than Iran can pose to an Israel dependent on the survival of Tel Aviv. As the United States and former Soviet Union both learned during the Cold War, even Iranian parity or superiority would be meaningless. The problem with mutually assured destruction is that no state can ever win an existential strike contest. As for the rest of the Middle East, if Iran shows it is going nuclear to enhance its power and dominate the Gulf region – as may be Iran’s real motive – the resulting threat to world oil exports and the world economy is not likely to intimidate to any degree that will benefit Iran. It will push both the United States and Arab states into responding. The fact Iran succeeded in acquiring nuclear weapons might increase the level of deterrence of a direct invasion, but would not lead the United States, or surrounding Arab states to passively accept the result. The United States already is transferring more than ten times the value of Iran’s total arms imports to its Gulf allies. Its ties to Kuwait, Bahrain, Qatar, Saudi Arabia, the UAE, and Oman already give the United States and its Gulf allies the ability to devastatingly defeat Iran in any direct military confrontation. Iran can only vastly increase the scale of the resulting destruction that the United States and its allies inflict if Iran ever actually escalates to the use of nuclear weapons. But the United States, the Arab allies, Israel, and other regional states will suffer as well – along with the global economy – if the end result is a major interruption in the flow of Gulf petroleum exports.
6,292
<h4>Extinction - Negotiations failure triggers <u>military strikes and regional proliferation</u><strong>-causes escalatory wars and collapses the economy</h4><p>Cordesman, </strong>CSIS<strong>, 2013</p><p></strong>(Anthony, “Negotiating with Iran: The Strategic Case for Pragmatism and Real Progress”, 9-23, http://csis.org/publication/negotiating-iran-strategic-case-pragmatism-and-real-progress<u><strong>)</p><p></strong>Nevertheless, it makes no sense at all to reject Hassan Rouhani’s opening or condemn the Obama Administration’s response</u>. <u><mark>Iran</mark>’s</u> nuclear pro<u>grams have <mark>moved to </mark>the point <mark>where it is</mark> extremely <mark>doubtful</mark> that <mark>there will be another chance</mark> to begin </u>what may be <u>a</u> long and <u>difficult process</u> for all nations involved, <u><strong><mark>and </mark>an attempt at <mark>resolution is</mark> far <mark>better than</mark> any of the real world <mark>alternatives</mark>. </strong>As long as any negotiations that follow are realistic in terms of their content</u>, and do not endorse indefinite delay in a U.S. response while Iran’s nuclear programs move forward, <u><strong><mark>they offer</mark> what will be <mark>the last</mark> real <mark>hope of avoiding </mark>preventive <mark>strikes or</mark> a process of <mark>containment that would lock </mark>the region <mark>in</mark>to an Iranian-Israeli <mark>nuclear arms race</mark>, a probable Saudi effort to acquire its own nuclear weapons, and a U.S. commitment to extended deterrence. </u></strong>The Uncertain Outcome of Preventive Strikes The United States, Iran, and all the other nations involved need to be far more pragmatic about what will happen if time does run out and Iran does go nuclear. <u>Iran may well face a series of preventive strikes – triggered by Israel or planned by the United States – that will destroy far more than its nuclear facilities.</u> This may or may not actually halt the Iranian nuclear effort. <u>A limited set of <mark>Israeli preventive strikes </mark>could either <mark>force the U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>to follow up, or create a situation in which Iran rejects </mark>all <mark>arms control</mark> and UN inspection and <mark>carries out a massive</mark> new disperse <mark>nuclear program <strong>or a crash basis. It could</mark> also <mark>drive Iran to lash out </mark>into a new wave of confrontation with the United States and Iran’s neighbors. </u></strong>A U.S.-led set of preventive strikes would be more successful, but the United States could only be sure of suppressing a meaningful Iran nuclear effort if it quickly re-strikes any known target it fails to destroy the first time, carries out constant surveillance of Iran, and repeatedly and thoroughly strikes at the targets created by any new Iranian initiatives. The United States would need regional support to do this and probably prolonged regional agreement to U.S. basing. At a minimum, the <u><mark>result would be </mark>years more of <mark>a regional arms race, military tension</mark>, and Iranian efforts to find ways to attack or pressure the Arab states, Israel, and United States. </u>As the current conflict in Syria makes all too clear, <u>no one can predict</u> how much support the United States will really get from any of its allies, its own U.S. Congress, and no one can predict the <u>limits to Iran’s reactions, ability to use third parties, and willingness to confront the United States and the region with new nuclear, missile, and asymmetric threats. </u>The United States would face an almost certain challenge in the UN from Russia and China, and there is no way any U.S. action against Iran could be separated from Iran’s efforts in Iraq, Syria, or Lebanon; Afghanistan, or any other issue where Iran could try to find some form of revenge. This is not an argument for not acting. The risk of a fully nuclear Iran is simply too great. It is a very strong argument for finding a good alternative if one can be negotiated on realistic terms. The Uncertain Outcome of Iran Nuclear Weapons and Containment: The Most Likely Outcome is a No Win Escalation Ladder Contest <u><mark>If there are no </mark>preventive <mark>strikes</mark> – or preventive strikes fail to halt Iran – <mark>what is</mark> now <mark>a</mark> largely quiet <mark>one-sided nuclear </mark>arms <mark>race would <strong>become</mark> far <mark>more threatening</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>At one level, this arms race would become one <mark>between Iran and</mark> any <mark>allies</mark> it could find and the United States and its Arab allies <mark>in</mark> or near <mark>the Gulf</mark>. </strong>A nuclear Iran could change the balance in terms of the credibility of U.S. and Arab willingness to engage against Iranian threats, intimidation, and use of its asymmetric forces</u>. <u><strong><mark>It would</mark> inevitably <mark>make Gulf petroleum exports the scene of an ongoing arms race and </mark>constant <mark>tension, and risk a clash that might escalate</mark> in untended ways. </u></strong>What is less apparent – and needs far more realistic attention in Iran and outside assessments of the Iranian nuclear threat – is the impact of Iran actually going nuclear. One or several crude nuclear devices do not create a nuclear force. Iran cannot produce enough capable nuclear forces for at least the next decade to pose more of an existential threat to Israel than Israel can pose to Iran. <u>Israel would scarcely be passive</u>, <u>however, and Israel already has far more capable missiles than Iran</u>. Israel also has thermonuclear weapons, rather than the early fission devices Iran will probably be limited to for at least the next half-decade. As a result <u>Israel will pose more of an existentialist threat to an Iran as dependent on the survival of Tehran than Iran can pose to an Israel dependent on the survival of Tel Aviv. </u>As the United States and former Soviet Union both learned during the Cold War, even Iranian parity or superiority would be meaningless. <u><strong><mark>The problem with m</mark>utually <mark>a</mark>ssured<mark> d</mark>estruction<mark> is </mark>that <mark>no state can ever win an existential strike </mark>contest. </u></strong>As for the rest of the Middle East, if Iran shows it is going nuclear to enhance its power and dominate the Gulf region – as may be Iran’s real motive – <u><mark>the resulting threat to</mark> world oil exports and <mark>the world economy is not likely to intimidate</mark> to any degree that will benefit <mark>Iran</mark>. It will push both the United States and Arab states into responding. </u>The fact Iran succeeded in acquiring nuclear weapons might increase the level of deterrence of a direct invasion, but would not lead the United States, or surrounding Arab states to passively accept the result. The United States already is transferring more than ten times the value of Iran’s total arms imports to its Gulf allies. Its ties to Kuwait, Bahrain, Qatar, Saudi Arabia, the UAE, and Oman already give the United States and its Gulf allies the ability to devastatingly defeat Iran in any direct military confrontation. <u><strong><mark>Iran </mark>can only <mark>vastly increase the </mark>scale of the <mark>resulting destruction</mark> that the United States and its allies inflict if Iran ever actually escalates to the use of nuclear weapons.</u></strong> <u>But <mark>the</mark> <mark>U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates, the <mark>Arab allies, Israel, and </mark>other <mark>regional states will suffer as well – along with the global economy</mark> – if the end result is a major interruption in the flow of Gulf petroleum exports.</p></u>
null
1NC
Off
247,504
18
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,599
Legalization doesn’t remove the stigma or prevent violence against sex workers
Day 12
Day 12 — Kristina Day, Creighton University (“ADDRESSING THE SEX TRAFFICKING CRISIS: HOW PROSTITUTION LAWS CAN HELP”, Spring 2012, Creighton International and Comparative Law Journal, 2 Creighton Int’l & Comp. L.J. 149, Lexis-Nexis)
Despite criticisms, a number of jurisdictions have legalized prostitution While prostitution is legalized with the assumption that it will bring positive outcomes, this result has continually failed to materialize Legalization has been proven to be ineffective in removing the stigma of prostitution it has also failed to protect women from violence The German government concluded that legalizing the sex industry failed to make it safer for prostitutes, improve their working conditions, or create a means for prostitutes to leave the industry illegal forms of prostitution and trafficking explode under a system of legalization from a business perspective, it makes sense for pimps to traffic the victims where prostitution is legal When legal, there is little-to-no risk for pimps
While prostitution is legalized with the assumption that it will bring positive outcomes, this result has failed to materialize. Legalization has been proven to be ineffective in removing the stigma of prostitution; it failed to protect women from violence legalizing the sex industry failed to improve their working conditions, or create a means for prostitutes to leave th industry illegal forms of prostitution and trafficking explode under legalization
Despite such criticisms, a number of jurisdictions have legalized acts of prostitution, including the Netherlands, Victoria (in Australia), Nevada (in the United States), and Germany. n70 Most Australian states repealed the law that made commercial sex illegal and have since adopted a number of measures to try to control the sex industry. n71 For example, the prostitution law in Queensland, Australia has two legal forms of sex work: (1) a sole operator, where the sex worker works alone but is prohibited from making public solicitations for prostitution, and (2) sex work performed in a licensed brothel. n72 All other forms of sex work remain illegal in Queensland, which include "unlicensed brothels or parlours, street workers, two sex workers sharing one premises (even if the workers both work alone in split shifts), and out-calls provided by a licensed brothel." n73 While prostitution is typically legalized with the assumption that it will bring positive outcomes, this result has continually failed to materialize. n74 Legalization has been proven to be ineffective in removing the stigma of prostitution; it has also failed to protect women from violence. n75 The German government, which legalized prostitution, concluded that legalizing the sex industry failed to make [*158] it safer for prostitutes, improve their working conditions, or create a means for prostitutes to leave the sex industry. n76 Additionally, illegal forms of prostitution and trafficking explode under a system of legalization. n77 This should come as no surprise because, from a business perspective, it makes sense for pimps to traffic the victims where prostitution is legal. n78 When prostitution is legal, there is little-to-no risk for pimps, even if trafficking is illegal. n79
1,777
<h4>Legalization doesn’t remove the stigma or prevent violence against sex workers</h4><p><strong>Day 12</strong> — Kristina Day, Creighton University (“ADDRESSING THE SEX TRAFFICKING CRISIS: HOW PROSTITUTION LAWS CAN HELP”, Spring 2012, Creighton International and Comparative Law Journal, 2 Creighton Int’l & Comp. L.J. 149, Lexis-Nexis)</p><p><u>Despite</u> such <u>criticisms, a number of jurisdictions have legalized</u> acts of <u>prostitution</u>, including the Netherlands, Victoria (in Australia), Nevada (in the United States), and Germany. n70 Most Australian states repealed the law that made commercial sex illegal and have since adopted a number of measures to try to control the sex industry. n71 For example, the prostitution law in Queensland, Australia has two legal forms of sex work: (1) a sole operator, where the sex worker works alone but is prohibited from making public solicitations for prostitution, and (2) sex work performed in a licensed brothel. n72 All other forms of sex work remain illegal in Queensland, which include "unlicensed brothels or parlours, street workers, two sex workers sharing one premises (even if the workers both work alone in split shifts), and out-calls provided by a licensed brothel." n73</p><p><u><mark>While prostitution is</u></mark> typically <u><mark>legalized with the assumption that it will bring positive outcomes, this result</mark> <mark>has</mark> <strong>continually <mark>failed to materialize</u></strong>.</mark> n74 <u><mark>Legalization has been proven to be <strong>ineffective in removing the stigma</strong> of prostitution</u>;</mark> <u><mark>it</mark> has also <strong><mark>failed to protect women from violence</u></strong></mark>. n75 <u>The German government</u>, which legalized prostitution, <u>concluded that <mark>legalizing the sex industry failed to</mark> make</u> [*158] <u>it safer for prostitutes, <mark>improve their working conditions, or create a means for prostitutes to leave th</mark>e</u> sex <u><mark>industry</u></mark>. n76 Additionally, <u><mark>illegal forms of prostitution and trafficking <strong>explode</strong> under</mark> a system of <mark>legalization</u></mark>. n77 This should come as no surprise because, <u>from a business perspective, it makes sense for pimps to traffic the victims where prostitution is legal</u>. n78 <u>When</u> prostitution is <u>legal, there is little-to-no risk for pimps</u>, even if trafficking is illegal. <strong>n79</p></strong>
null
1NC
Stigma
430,305
2
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,600
Legalization doesn’t solve- doesn’t erase stigmas they face, womyn don’t want to be publicly marked as sex workers by registering, and doesn’t get rid of violence sex workers face
Farley 04
Farley 04
Advocates argue health of those in prostitution will be improved because otherwise women will not have access to health care. It is assumed that women will seek health care as soon as the stigma of arrest is removed from prostitution. If the stigma is removed, advocates argue, women will then file a complaint whenever they are abused, raped, or assaulted in prostitution. They assume that the complaint will be followed with a police response that treats women in prostitution with dignity and as ordinary citizens. Unfortunately, health care workers and police too often share the same contempt toward those in prostitution that others do he dilemma for the per son in prostitution is not that there is no legal redress for coercion, physical assault, and rape in the new law or in old laws. The dilemma is that in prostitution there is no avoiding sexual harass ment, sexual exploitation, rape, and acts that are the equivalent of torture concern was the loss of anonymity that exists in legal prostitution. Once officially registered as prostitutes, Dutch women feared that this designation would pursue them for the rest of their lives. Despite the fact that if officially registered as prostitutes they would accrue pension funds, the women still pre ferred anonymity They wanted to leave prosti tution as quickly as possible with no legal record of having been in prostitution despite attempts to unionize women in Germany’s $16.5 billion legal prostitution industry, the women not only avoided unions, they avoided registering with the government and they continued to engage in illegal prostitu tion in part because they felt that the remote areas where prostitu tion is zoned put them at increased, not decreased, risk of physical danger
Advocates argue health will be improved the stigma removed women will file a complaint whenever they are abused, in prostitution Unfortunately, health care workers and police often share the same contempt toward those in prostitution that others do The dilemma is in prostitution there is no avoiding sexual harass ment exploitation, rape, and torture concern was the loss of anonymity in legal prostitution. Once officially registered as prostitutes, Dutch women feared this would pursue them for the rest of their lives. Despite the fact they would accrue pension funds despite attempts to unionize women in Germany women not only avoided unions, they avoided registering and continued to engage in illegal prostitu tion
(Melissa, Violence Against Women, ““Bad for the Body, Bad for the Heart”: Prostitution Harms Women Even if Legalized or Decriminalized,” 2004, Sage Publications) /wyo-mm Advocates of decriminalization argue that the health of those in prostitution will be improved by decriminalization because otherwise women will not have access to health care. It is assumed that women will seek health care as soon as the stigma of arrest is removed from prostitution. If the stigma is removed, advocates argue, women will then file a complaint whenever they are abused, raped, or assaulted in prostitution. They assume that the complaint will be followed with a police response that treats women in prostitution with dignity and as ordinary citizens. Unfortunately, health care workers and police too often share the same contempt toward those in prostitution that others do. A former prostitute in NZ said to the Parliament: “This bill pro vides people like me. . . with some form of red ress [italics added], for the brutalisation that may happen.. .when you’re with a client and you have a knife pulled on you” (Georgina Beyer, speech, Wellington, NZ, June 26, 2003). The specific form of redress offered by the NZ decriminalization law was not described by the speaker, nor is it articulated in the law. The dilemma for the per son in prostitution is not that there is no legal redress for coercion, physical assault, and rape in the new law or in old laws. The dilemma is that in prostitution there is no avoiding sexual harass ment, sexual exploitation, rape, and acts that are the equivalent of torture. Decriminalization in NZ was promoted as a means of provid ing those in prostitution with legal redress against violent johns. However, prostituted women could already take legal action under existing laws but rarely did so. Explaining this situation, a NZ Prostitutes Collective member stated, “They don’t want to draw attention to themselves and what they’re doing” (Else, 2003, np.). Women in the Netherlands have expressed similar senti ments, even though prostitution has been legal there for many years. Their concern was the loss of anonymity that exists in legal prostitution. Once officially registered as prostitutes, Dutch women feared that this designation would pursue them for the rest of their lives. Despite the fact that if officially registered as prostitutes they would accrue pension funds, the women still pre ferred anonymity (Schippers, 2002). They wanted to leave prosti tution as quickly as possible with no legal record of having been in prostitution (Daley, 2001). Similarly, despite attempts to unionize women in Germany’s $16.5 billion legal prostitution industry, the women not only avoided unions, they avoided registering with the government and they continued to engage in illegal prostitu tion in part because they felt that the remote areas where prostitu tion is zoned put them at increased, not decreased, risk of physical danger (Taubitz, 2004).
2,981
<h4><strong>Legalization doesn’t solve- doesn’t erase stigmas they face, womyn don’t want to be publicly marked as sex workers by registering, and doesn’t get rid of violence sex workers face</h4><p>Farley 04</p><p></strong>(Melissa, Violence Against Women, ““Bad for the Body, Bad for the Heart”: Prostitution Harms Women Even if Legalized or Decriminalized,” 2004, Sage Publications) /wyo-mm</p><p><u><mark>Advocates</u></mark> of decriminalization <u><mark>argue</u></mark> that the <u><mark>health</mark> of those in prostitution <mark>will be improved</u></mark> by decriminalization <u>because otherwise women will not have access to health care. It is assumed that women will seek health care as soon as <mark>the stigma</mark> of arrest is <mark>removed</mark> from prostitution. If the stigma is removed, advocates argue, <mark>women will</mark> then <mark>file a complaint whenever they are abused,</mark> raped, or assaulted <mark>in prostitution</mark>. They assume that the complaint will be followed with a police response that treats women in prostitution with dignity and as ordinary citizens<strong>. <mark>Unfortunately, health care workers and police</mark> too <mark>often share the same contempt toward those in prostitution that others do</u></strong></mark>. A former prostitute in NZ said to the Parliament: “This bill pro vides people like me. . . with some form of red ress [italics added], for the brutalisation that may happen.. .when you’re with a client and you have a knife pulled on you” (Georgina Beyer, speech, Wellington, NZ, June 26, 2003). The specific form of redress offered by the NZ decriminalization law was not described by the speaker, nor is it articulated in the law. T<u>he dilemma for the per son in prostitution is not that there is no legal redress for coercion, physical assault, and rape in the new law or in old laws. <mark>The dilemma is</mark> that <mark>in prostitution there is no avoiding sexual harass ment</mark>, sexual <mark>exploitation, rape, and</mark> acts that are the equivalent of <mark>torture</u></mark>. Decriminalization in NZ was promoted as a means of provid ing those in prostitution with legal redress against violent johns. However, prostituted women could already take legal action under existing laws but rarely did so. Explaining this situation, a NZ Prostitutes Collective member stated, “They don’t want to draw attention to themselves and what they’re doing” (Else, 2003, np.). Women in the Netherlands have expressed similar senti ments, even though prostitution has been legal there for many years. Their <u><mark>concern was the loss of anonymity</mark> that exists <mark>in legal prostitution. Once officially registered as prostitutes, Dutch women feared</mark> that <mark>this</mark> designation <mark>would pursue them for the rest of their lives. Despite the fact</mark> that if officially registered as prostitutes <mark>they would accrue pension funds</mark>, the women still pre ferred anonymity</u> (Schippers, 2002). <u>They wanted to leave prosti tution as quickly as possible with no legal record of having been in prostitution</u> (Daley, 2001). Similarly, <u><mark>despite attempts to unionize women in Germany</mark>’s $16.5 billion legal prostitution industry, the <mark>women not only avoided unions, they avoided registering</mark> with the government <mark>and</mark> they <mark>continued to engage in illegal prostitu tion</mark> in part because they felt that the remote areas where prostitu tion is zoned put them at increased, not decreased, risk of physical danger</u> (Taubitz, 2004).</p>
null
1NC
Stigma
194,350
9
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,601
Even if essentializing the state of prostitutes is bad, the aff is worse:
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Even if essentializing the state of prostitutes is bad, the aff is worse:</h4>
null
1NC
Stigma
430,306
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,602
90% of prostituted persons not there by choice.
Farley ’14
Farley ’14 [Melissa Farley, Ph.D “Prostitution Research & Education” [PASS] The Pacific Alliance to Stop Slavery http://www.passhawaii.org/faq.html]
The reality is that over 90% of prostituted persons do not want to be involved in prostitution but feel that they are trapped by their pimps or their dire financial situation. Sex trafficked persons are not willing to prostitute themselves and have been either forced or manipulated into prostitution. In cases of both sex trafficking and prostitution, pimps and traffickers often have control over the prostituted person in terms of movement, eating habits, earned income, fashion, and social life. Essentially, the pimp controls the freedom of the prostituted person who is seen as nothing more than his commodity.
over 90% of prostituted persons do not want to be involved in prostitution but feel that they are trapped by their pimps or financial situation. trafficked persons are not willing to prostitute themselves and have been forced or manipulated pimps and traffickers often have control over the prostituted person in terms of movement, eating habits, earned income, fashion, and social life the pimp controls the freedom of the prostituted person who is seen as nothing more than his commodity
Sex trafficking and prostitution are extremely similar, except in rare cases where someone willingly chooses to pimp him or herself to clients for money. The reality is that over 90% of prostituted persons do not want to be involved in prostitution but feel that they are trapped by their pimps or their dire financial situation. Sex trafficked persons are not willing to prostitute themselves and have been either forced or manipulated into prostitution. It is also important to note that all prostituted minors are automatically defined by the U.S. Trafficking Victims Protection Act (TVPA) as victims of sex trafficking. In cases of both sex trafficking and prostitution, pimps and traffickers often have control over the prostituted person in terms of movement, eating habits, earned income, fashion, and social life. Essentially, the pimp controls the freedom of the prostituted person who is seen as nothing more than his commodity.
938
<h4>90% of prostituted persons not there by choice.</h4><p><strong>Farley ’14</strong> [Melissa Farley, Ph.D<u> “Prostitution Research & Education” [PASS] The Pacific Alliance to Stop Slavery http://www.passhawaii.org/faq.html]</p><p></u>Sex trafficking and prostitution are extremely similar, except in rare cases where someone willingly chooses to pimp him or herself to clients for money. <u>The reality is that <mark>over 90% of prostituted persons do not want to be involved in prostitution</mark> <mark>but feel that they are trapped by their pimps or</mark> their dire <mark>financial situation.</mark> Sex <mark>trafficked persons are not willing to prostitute themselves</mark> <mark>and have been</mark> either <mark>forced or manipulated</mark> into prostitution.</u> It is also important to note that all prostituted minors are automatically defined by the U.S. Trafficking Victims Protection Act (TVPA) as victims of sex trafficking. <u>In cases of both sex trafficking and prostitution, <mark>pimps and traffickers often have control over the prostituted person in terms of movement, eating habits, earned income, fashion, and social life</mark>. Essentially, <mark>the pimp controls the freedom of the prostituted person who is seen as nothing more than his commodity</mark>. </p></u>
null
1NC
Stigma
430,307
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,603
Prostituted women conditioned to stay in sex works – turns their agency claims.
MacKinnon ’11
MacKinnon ’11 [Catharine A. MacKinnon, Professor of Law at the University of Michigan, “Trafficking, Prostitution, and Inequality” Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review Vol. 46 2011]
in the sex trade, adults and children are not two separate groups of people. They are the same group of people at two points in time. Those children for whom nothing was done who managed not to die yet are most of today’s prostituted women. One consequence of childhood sexual abuse can be to feel valued and approved when being sexually violated in a context of feeling funda- mentally worthless.95 Meantime law, policy, and popular culture just wait for them to live long enough to be written off as consenting adults.
the sex trade, adults and children are not two separate groups of people. They are the same group of people at two points in time. One consequence of childhood sexual abuse can be to feel valued and approved when being sexually violated in a context of feeling funda- mentally worthless law, policy, and popular culture just wait for them to live long enough to be written off as consenting adults
Although no one can deny that most women enter the sex industry with previously violated childhoods, what is denied is that defending prostitution supports their continuous violation on the rationale that they are no longer little girls. What those seem to miss who care only about prostituted chil- dren (if they care about anything in this picture94) is that in the sex trade, adults and children are not two separate groups of people. They are the same group of people at two points in time. Too, this is why nothing effec- tive can be done for one without doing it for both. Those children for whom nothing was done who managed not to die yet are most of today’s prostituted women. One consequence of childhood sexual abuse can be to feel valued and approved when being sexually violated in a context of feeling funda- mentally worthless.95 Meantime law, policy, and popular culture just wait for them to live long enough to be written off as consenting adults. Under- stood as a practice of sexual exploitation, prostitution cannot be made safe. Those in it cannot realistically be protected. Once you face this, recognizing its harms selectively is unmasked as a strategic retreat that allows its intrin- sic harms to continue, lifting the sex industry’s ever-sagging public face as ever more violated women flee and find their voices.
1,341
<h4>Prostituted women conditioned to stay in sex works – turns their agency claims.</h4><p><strong>MacKinnon ’11</strong> [Catharine A. MacKinnon, Professor of Law at the University of Michigan, “Trafficking, Prostitution, and Inequality” Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review Vol. 46 2011]</p><p>Although no one can deny that most women enter the sex industry with previously violated childhoods, what is denied is that defending prostitution supports their continuous violation on the rationale that they are no longer little girls. What those seem to miss who care only about prostituted chil- dren (if they care about anything in this picture94) is that <u>in <mark>the sex trade, adults and children are not two separate groups of people. They are the same group of people at two points in time.</mark> </u>Too, this is why nothing effec- tive can be done for one without doing it for both. <u>Those children for whom nothing was done who managed not to die yet are most of today’s prostituted women. <mark>One consequence of childhood sexual abuse can be to feel valued and approved when being sexually violated in a context of feeling funda- mentally worthless</mark>.95 Meantime <mark>law, policy, and popular culture just wait for them to live long enough to be written off as consenting adults</mark>.</u> Under- stood as a practice of sexual exploitation, prostitution cannot be made safe. Those in it cannot realistically be protected. Once you face this, recognizing its harms selectively is unmasked as a strategic retreat that allows its intrin- sic harms to continue, lifting the sex industry’s ever-sagging public face as ever more violated women flee and find their voices.</p>
null
1NC
Stigma
430,308
1
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
741,604
Women don’t want legalization.
Raymond ‘3
Raymond ‘3 [Janice G. Raymond “Ten Reasons for Not Legalizing Prostitution And a Legal Response to the Demand for Prostitution” Journal of Trauma Practice, 2, 2003: pp. 315-332; and in Prostitution, Trafficking and Traumatic Stress. Melissa Farley (Ed.). Binghamton: Haworth Press, 2003]
Women in systems of prostitution do not want the sex industry legalized or decriminalized. In a 5-country study on sex trafficking, most of the trafficked and prostituted women interviewed strongly stated their opinion that prostitution should not be legalized and considered legitimate work, warning that legalization would create more risks and harm for women from already violent customers and pimp
Women in systems of prostitution do not want the sex industry legalized In a 5-country study of the trafficked and prostituted women interviewed ngly stated their opinion that prostitution should not be legalized warning that legalization would create more risks from already violent customers
10. Women in systems of prostitution do not want the sex industry legalized or decriminalized. In a 5-country study on sex trafficking, most of the trafficked and prostituted women interviewed in the Philippines, Venezuela and the United States (3) strongly stated their opinion that prostitution should not be legalized and considered legitimate work, warning that legalization would create more risks and harm for women from already violent customers and pimps (Raymond et al, 2002). One woman said, “No way. It’s not a profession. It is humiliating, and violence from the men’s side.” Not one woman we interviewed wanted her children, family or friends to have to earn money by entering the sex industry. Another woman stated: “Prostitution stripped me of my life, my health, everything” (Raymond et al., 2002).
814
<h4>Women don’t want legalization. </h4><p><strong>Raymond ‘3 </strong>[Janice G. Raymond “Ten Reasons for Not Legalizing Prostitution And a Legal Response to the Demand for Prostitution” Journal of Trauma Practice, 2, 2003: pp. 315-332; and in Prostitution, Trafficking and Traumatic Stress. Melissa Farley (Ed.). Binghamton: Haworth Press, 2003] </p><p>10. <u><mark>Women in systems of prostitution do not want the sex industry legalized</mark> or decriminalized.</u> <u><mark>In a 5-country study</mark> on sex trafficking, most <mark>of the trafficked and prostituted women interviewed</u></mark> in the Philippines, Venezuela and the United States (3) <u>stro<mark>ngly stated their opinion that prostitution should not be legalized</mark> and considered legitimate work, <mark>warning that legalization would create more risks</mark> and harm for women <mark>from</mark> <mark>already violent customers</mark> and pimp</u>s (Raymond et al, 2002). One woman said, “No way. It’s not a profession. It is humiliating, and violence from the men’s side.” Not one woman we interviewed wanted her children, family or friends to have to earn money by entering the sex industry. Another woman stated: “Prostitution stripped me of my life, my health, everything” (Raymond et al., 2002).</p>
null
1NC
Stigma
429,959
8
17,057
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
565,292
N
Cedanats
1
Washington Elizondo-Micovic
Stone
1AC - Prostitution 1NC - Trafficking Adv CP Decrim CP Politics Case 2NC - CPs Case 1NR - Politics 2NR - Adv CP Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/AvMa/Dartmouth-Avendano-Martin-Neg-Cedanats-Round1.docx
null
48,458
AvMa
Dartmouth AvMa
null
Im.....
Av.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2