id
int64
673k
4.14M
tag
stringlengths
1
39.7k
cite
stringlengths
1
8.39k
fullcite
stringlengths
1
50.9k
summary
stringlengths
1
47k
spoken
stringlengths
1
13.9k
fulltext
stringlengths
1
138k
textLength
float64
0
138k
markup
stringlengths
10
139k
pocket
stringlengths
1
863
hat
stringlengths
1
5.45k
block
stringlengths
1
16.5k
bucketId
int64
37
1.65M
duplicateCount
int64
1
3.81k
fileId
int64
14k
129k
filePath
stringlengths
60
188
roundId
int64
565k
915k
side
stringclasses
2 values
tournament
stringlengths
1
62
round
stringclasses
34 values
opponent
stringlengths
1
57
judge
stringlengths
1
87
report
stringlengths
1
612k
opensourcePath
stringlengths
48
176
caselistUpdatedAt
float64
teamId
int64
48.4k
77.9k
teamName
stringlengths
3
5
teamDisplayName
stringlengths
8
31
notes
float64
debater1First
stringclasses
164 values
debater1Last
stringclasses
183 values
debater2First
stringclasses
151 values
debater2Last
stringclasses
186 values
schoolId
int64
18.7k
26.1k
schoolName
stringclasses
306 values
schoolDisplayName
stringclasses
306 values
state
float64
chapterId
float64
caselistId
int64
1k
1.04k
caselistName
stringclasses
10 values
caselistDisplayName
stringclasses
10 values
year
int64
2.01k
2.02k
event
stringclasses
2 values
level
stringclasses
2 values
teamSize
int64
1
2
742,305
Structural violence is the largest proximate cause of war- creates priming that psychologically structures escalation
Scheper-Hughes and Bourgois ‘4
Scheper-Hughes and Bourgois ‘4
Absolutely central to our approach is a blurring of categories and distinctions between wartime and peacetime violence. Close attention to the “little” violences produced in the structures, habituses, and mentalites of everyday life shifts our attention to pathologies of class, race, and gender inequalities. The violence continuum also refers to the ease with which humans are capable of reducing the socially vulnerable into expendable nonpersons and assuming the license - even the duty - to kill, maim, or soul-murder. it is absolutely necessary to make just such existential leaps in purposefully linking violent acts in normal times to those of abnormal times. there is), an even greater risk lies in failing to sensitize ourselves, in misrecognizing protogenocidal practices and sentiments daily enacted as normative behavior by “ordinary” good-enough citizens. Peacetime crimes constitute the “small wars and invisible genocides” These are “invisible” genocides not because they are secreted away or hidden from view, but quite the opposite. , the things that are hardest to perceive are those which are right before our eyes and therefore taken for granted. Peacetime crimes suggests the possibility that war crimes are merely ordinary, everyday crimes of public consent applied systematically and dramatically in the extreme context of war The public consensus is based primarily on a new mobilization of an old fear of the mob, the mugger, the rapist, the Black man, the undeserving poor. How many public executions of mentally deficient prisoners in the United States are needed to make life feel more secure for the affluent? it is essential that we recognize the existence of a genocidal capacity among otherwise good-enough humans and that we need to exercise a defensive hypervigilance to the less dramatic, permitted, and even rewarded everyday acts of violence that render participation in genocidal acts and policies possible Under the violence continuum we include, therefore, all expressions of radical social exclusion, dehumanization, depersonal- ization, pseudospeciation, and reification which normalize atrocious behavior and violence toward others. A constant self-mobilization for alarm, a state of constant hyperarousal is, perhaps, a reasonable response to Benjamin’s view of late modern history as a chronic “state of emergency” Making that decisive move to recognize the continuum of violence allows us to see the capacity and the willingness - if not enthusiasm - of ordinary people, the practical technicians of the social consensus, to enforce genocidal-like crimes against categories of rubbish people. There is no primary impulse out of which mass violence and genocide are born, it is ingrained in the common sense of everyday social life. The mad, the differently abled, the mentally vulnerable have often fallen into this category of the unworthy living, as have the very old and infirm, the sick-poor, and, of course, the despised racial, religious, sexual, and ethnic groups of the moment. . Collective denial and misrecognition are prerequisites for mass violence and genocide. Everyday violence encompasses the implicit, legitimate, and routinized forms of violence inherent in particular social, economic, and political formations. that mass violence is part of a continuum, and that it is socially incremental and often experienced by perpetrators, collaborators, bystanders - and even by victims themselves - as expected, routine, even justified They harbor the “priming” that push social consensus toward devaluing certain forms of human life
central to our approach is a blurring of wartime and peacetime violence Close attention to the “little” violences produced in structures of everyday life shifts our attention to pathologies of class, race, and gender inequalities humans are capable of reducing the socially vulnerable into expendable nonpersons it is absolutely necessary to make existential leaps in purposefully linking violent acts in normal times to those of abnormal times. an even greater risk lies in in misrecognizing protogenocidal practices daily enacted by “ordinary” citizens These are “invisible” genocides because they are right before our eyes and war crimes are ordinary, everyday crimes of public consent applied systematically in the extreme context of war it is essential that we exercise a defensive hypervigilance to the everyday acts of violence that render participation in genocidal acts and policies possible Making that decisive move to recognize the continuum of violence allows us to see the capacity of ordinary people, to enforce genocidal like crimes There is no primary impulse out of which mass violence and genocide are born, it is ingrained in the common sense of everyday social life Collective denial and misrecognition are prerequisites for mass violence mass violence is socially incremental and often experienced as expected, routine They harbor the priming that push social consensus toward devaluing certain forms of human life
(Prof of Anthropology @ Cal-Berkely; Prof of Anthropology @ UPenn) (Nancy and Philippe, Introduction: Making Sense of Violence, in Violence in War and Peace, pg. 19-22) **Answers no root cause- because there is no root cause we must be attentative to structural inequality of all kinds because it primes people for broader violence- our impact is about the scale of violence and the disproportionate relationship between that scale and warfare, not that one form of social exclusion comes first This large and at first sight “messy” Part VII is central to this anthology’s thesis. It encompasses everything from the routinized, bureaucratized, and utterly banal violence of children dying of hunger and maternal despair in Northeast Brazil (Scheper-Hughes, Chapter 33) to elderly African Americans dying of heat stroke in Mayor Daly’s version of US apartheid in Chicago’s South Side (Klinenberg, Chapter 38) to the racialized class hatred expressed by British Victorians in their olfactory disgust of the “smelly” working classes (Orwell, Chapter 36). In these readings violence is located in the symbolic and social structures that overdetermine and allow the criminalized drug addictions, interpersonal bloodshed, and racially patterned incarcerations that characterize the US “inner city” to be normalized (Bourgois, Chapter 37 and Wacquant, Chapter 39). Violence also takes the form of class, racial, political self-hatred and adolescent self-destruction (Quesada, Chapter 35), as well as of useless (i.e. preventable), rawly embodied physical suffering, and death (Farmer, Chapter 34). Absolutely central to our approach is a blurring of categories and distinctions between wartime and peacetime violence. Close attention to the “little” violences produced in the structures, habituses, and mentalites of everyday life shifts our attention to pathologies of class, race, and gender inequalities. More important, it interrupts the voyeuristic tendencies of “violence studies” that risk publicly humiliating the powerless who are often forced into complicity with social and individual pathologies of power because suffering is often a solvent of human integrity and dignity. Thus, in this anthology we are positing a violence continuum comprised of a multitude of “small wars and invisible genocides” (see also Scheper- Hughes 1996; 1997; 2000b) conducted in the normative social spaces of public schools, clinics, emergency rooms, hospital wards, nursing homes, courtrooms, public registry offices, prisons, detention centers, and public morgues. The violence continuum also refers to the ease with which humans are capable of reducing the socially vulnerable into expendable nonpersons and assuming the license - even the duty - to kill, maim, or soul-murder. We realize that in referring to a violence and a genocide continuum we are flying in the face of a tradition of genocide studies that argues for the absolute uniqueness of the Jewish Holocaust and for vigilance with respect to restricted purist use of the term genocide itself (see Kuper 1985; Chaulk 1999; Fein 1990; Chorbajian 1999). But we hold an opposing and alternative view that, to the contrary, it is absolutely necessary to make just such existential leaps in purposefully linking violent acts in normal times to those of abnormal times. Hence the title of our volume: Violence in War and in Peace. If (as we concede) there is a moral risk in overextending the concept of “genocide” into spaces and corners of everyday life where we might not ordinarily think to find it (and there is), an even greater risk lies in failing to sensitize ourselves, in misrecognizing protogenocidal practices and sentiments daily enacted as normative behavior by “ordinary” good-enough citizens. Peacetime crimes, such as prison construction sold as economic development to impoverished communities in the mountains and deserts of California, or the evolution of the criminal industrial complex into the latest peculiar institution for managing race relations in the United States (Waquant, Chapter 39), constitute the “small wars and invisible genocides” to which we refer. This applies to African American and Latino youth mortality statistics in Oakland, California, Baltimore, Washington DC, and New York City. These are “invisible” genocides not because they are secreted away or hidden from view, but quite the opposite. As Wittgenstein observed, the things that are hardest to perceive are those which are right before our eyes and therefore taken for granted. In this regard, Bourdieu’s partial and unfinished theory of violence (see Chapters 32 and 42) as well as his concept of misrecognition is crucial to our task. By including the normative everyday forms of violence hidden in the minutiae of “normal” social practices - in the architecture of homes, in gender relations, in communal work, in the exchange of gifts, and so forth - Bourdieu forces us to reconsider the broader meanings and status of violence, especially the links between the violence of everyday life and explicit political terror and state repression, Similarly, Basaglia’s notion of “peacetime crimes” - crimini di pace - imagines a direct relationship between wartime and peacetime violence. Peacetime crimes suggests the possibility that war crimes are merely ordinary, everyday crimes of public consent applied systematically and dramatically in the extreme context of war. Consider the parallel uses of rape during peacetime and wartime, or the family resemblances between the legalized violence of US immigration and naturalization border raids on “illegal aliens” versus the US government- engineered genocide in 1938, known as the Cherokee “Trail of Tears.” Peacetime crimes suggests that everyday forms of state violence make a certain kind of domestic peace possible. Internal “stability” is purchased with the currency of peacetime crimes, many of which take the form of professionally applied “strangle-holds.” Everyday forms of state violence during peacetime make a certain kind of domestic “peace” possible. It is an easy-to-identify peacetime crime that is usually maintained as a public secret by the government and by a scared or apathetic populace. Most subtly, but no less politically or structurally, the phenomenal growth in the United States of a new military, postindustrial prison industrial complex has taken place in the absence of broad-based opposition, let alone collective acts of civil disobedience. The public consensus is based primarily on a new mobilization of an old fear of the mob, the mugger, the rapist, the Black man, the undeserving poor. How many public executions of mentally deficient prisoners in the United States are needed to make life feel more secure for the affluent? What can it possibly mean when incarceration becomes the “normative” socializing experience for ethnic minority youth in a society, i.e., over 33 percent of young African American men (Prison Watch 2002). In the end it is essential that we recognize the existence of a genocidal capacity among otherwise good-enough humans and that we need to exercise a defensive hypervigilance to the less dramatic, permitted, and even rewarded everyday acts of violence that render participation in genocidal acts and policies possible (under adverse political or economic conditions), perhaps more easily than we would like to recognize. Under the violence continuum we include, therefore, all expressions of radical social exclusion, dehumanization, depersonal- ization, pseudospeciation, and reification which normalize atrocious behavior and violence toward others. A constant self-mobilization for alarm, a state of constant hyperarousal is, perhaps, a reasonable response to Benjamin’s view of late modern history as a chronic “state of emergency” (Taussig, Chapter 31). We are trying to recover here the classic anagogic thinking that enabled Erving Goffman, Jules Henry, C. Wright Mills, and Franco Basaglia among other mid-twentieth-century radically critical thinkers, to perceive the symbolic and structural relations, i.e., between inmates and patients, between concentration camps, prisons, mental hospitals, nursing homes, and other “total institutions.” Making that decisive move to recognize the continuum of violence allows us to see the capacity and the willingness - if not enthusiasm - of ordinary people, the practical technicians of the social consensus, to enforce genocidal-like crimes against categories of rubbish people. There is no primary impulse out of which mass violence and genocide are born, it is ingrained in the common sense of everyday social life. The mad, the differently abled, the mentally vulnerable have often fallen into this category of the unworthy living, as have the very old and infirm, the sick-poor, and, of course, the despised racial, religious, sexual, and ethnic groups of the moment. Erik Erikson referred to “pseudo- speciation” as the human tendency to classify some individuals or social groups as less than fully human - a prerequisite to genocide and one that is carefully honed during the unremark- able peacetimes that precede the sudden, “seemingly unintelligible” outbreaks of mass violence. Collective denial and misrecognition are prerequisites for mass violence and genocide. But so are formal bureaucratic structures and professional roles. The practical technicians of everyday violence in the backlands of Northeast Brazil (Scheper-Hughes, Chapter 33), for example, include the clinic doctors who prescribe powerful tranquilizers to fretful and frightfully hungry babies, the Catholic priests who celebrate the death of “angel-babies,” and the municipal bureaucrats who dispense free baby coffins but no food to hungry families. Everyday violence encompasses the implicit, legitimate, and routinized forms of violence inherent in particular social, economic, and political formations. It is close to what Bourdieu (1977, 1996) means by “symbolic violence,” the violence that is often “nus-recognized” for something else, usually something good. Everyday violence is similar to what Taussig (1989) calls “terror as usual.” All these terms are meant to reveal a public secret - the hidden links between violence in war and violence in peace, and between war crimes and “peace-time crimes.” Bourdieu (1977) finds domination and violence in the least likely places - in courtship and marriage, in the exchange of gifts, in systems of classification, in style, art, and culinary taste- the various uses of culture. Violence, Bourdieu insists, is everywhere in social practice. It is misrecognized because its very everydayness and its familiarity render it invisible. Lacan identifies “rneconnaissance” as the prerequisite of the social. The exploitation of bachelor sons, robbing them of autonomy, independence, and progeny, within the structures of family farming in the European countryside that Bourdieu escaped is a case in point (Bourdieu, Chapter 42; see also Scheper-Hughes, 2000b; Favret-Saada, 1989). Following Gramsci, Foucault, Sartre, Arendt, and other modern theorists of power-vio- lence, Bourdieu treats direct aggression and physical violence as a crude, uneconomical mode of domination; it is less efficient and, according to Arendt (1969), it is certainly less legitimate. While power and symbolic domination are not to be equated with violence - and Arendt argues persuasively that violence is to be understood as a failure of power - violence, as we are presenting it here, is more than simply the expression of illegitimate physical force against a person or group of persons. Rather, we need to understand violence as encompassing all forms of “controlling processes” (Nader 1997b) that assault basic human freedoms and individual or collective survival. Our task is to recognize these gray zones of violence which are, by definition, not obvious. Once again, the point of bringing into the discourses on genocide everyday, normative experiences of reification, depersonalization, institutional confinement, and acceptable death is to help answer the question: What makes mass violence and genocide possible? In this volume we are suggesting that mass violence is part of a continuum, and that it is socially incremental and often experienced by perpetrators, collaborators, bystanders - and even by victims themselves - as expected, routine, even justified. The preparations for mass killing can be found in social sentiments and institutions from the family, to schools, churches, hospitals, and the military. They harbor the early “warning signs” (Charney 1991), the “priming” (as Hinton, ed., 2002 calls it), or the “genocidal continuum” (as we call it) that push social consensus toward devaluing certain forms of human life and lifeways from the refusal of social support and humane care to vulnerable “social parasites” (the nursing home elderly, “welfare queens,” undocumented immigrants, drug addicts) to the militarization of everyday life (super-maximum-security prisons, capital punishment; the technologies of heightened personal security, including the house gun and gated communities; and reversed feelings of victimization).
13,177
<h4><strong>Structural violence is the largest proximate cause of war- creates priming that psychologically structures escalation</h4><p>Scheper-Hughes and Bourgois ‘4</p><p></strong>(Prof of Anthropology @ Cal-Berkely; Prof of Anthropology @ UPenn) (Nancy and Philippe, Introduction: Making Sense of Violence, in Violence in War and Peace, pg. 19-22) **Answers no root cause- because there is no root cause we must be attentative to structural inequality of all kinds because it primes people for broader violence- our impact is about the scale of violence and the disproportionate relationship between that scale and warfare, not that one form of social exclusion comes first</p><p>This large and at first sight “messy” Part VII is central to this anthology’s thesis. It encompasses everything from the routinized, bureaucratized, and utterly banal violence of children dying of hunger and maternal despair in Northeast Brazil (Scheper-Hughes, Chapter 33) to elderly African Americans dying of heat stroke in Mayor Daly’s version of US apartheid in Chicago’s South Side (Klinenberg, Chapter 38) to the racialized class hatred expressed by British Victorians in their olfactory disgust of the “smelly” working classes (Orwell, Chapter 36). In these readings violence is located in the symbolic and social structures that overdetermine and allow the criminalized drug addictions, interpersonal bloodshed, and racially patterned incarcerations that characterize the US “inner city” to be normalized (Bourgois, Chapter 37 and Wacquant, Chapter 39). Violence also takes the form of class, racial, political self-hatred and adolescent self-destruction (Quesada, Chapter 35), as well as of useless (i.e. preventable), rawly embodied physical suffering, and death (Farmer, Chapter 34). <u>Absolutely <mark>central</mark> <mark>to our approach</mark> <mark>is a blurring of</mark> categories and distinctions between <mark>wartime and peacetime violence</mark>. <mark>Close attention to the “little” violences produced in</mark> the <mark>structures</mark>, habituses, and mentalites <mark>of everyday life shifts our attention to pathologies of class, race, and gender inequalities</mark>.</u> More important, it interrupts the voyeuristic tendencies of “violence studies” that risk publicly humiliating the powerless who are often forced into complicity with social and individual pathologies of power because suffering is often a solvent of human integrity and dignity. Thus, in this anthology we are positing a violence continuum comprised of a multitude of “small wars and invisible genocides” (see also Scheper- Hughes 1996; 1997; 2000b) conducted in the normative social spaces of public schools, clinics, emergency rooms, hospital wards, nursing homes, courtrooms, public registry offices, prisons, detention centers, and public morgues. <u>The violence continuum also refers to the ease with which <strong><mark>humans are capable of reducing the socially vulnerable into expendable nonpersons</strong></mark> and assuming the license - even the duty - to kill, maim, or soul-murder.</u> We realize that in referring to a violence and a genocide continuum we are flying in the face of a tradition of genocide studies that argues for the absolute uniqueness of the Jewish Holocaust and for vigilance with respect to restricted purist use of the term genocide itself (see Kuper 1985; Chaulk 1999; Fein 1990; Chorbajian 1999). But we hold an opposing and alternative view that, to the contrary, <u><mark>it is absolutely necessary to make</mark> just such <mark>existential leaps in purposefully linking violent acts in normal times to those of abnormal times.</u></mark> Hence the title of our volume: Violence in War and in Peace. If (as we concede) there is a moral risk in overextending the concept of “genocide” into spaces and corners of everyday life where we might not ordinarily think to find it (and <u>there is), <mark>an even greater</mark> <mark>risk</mark> <mark>lies in</mark> failing to sensitize ourselves, <mark>in misrecognizing protogenocidal practices</mark> and sentiments <mark>daily enacted</mark> as normative behavior <mark>by “ordinary”</mark> good-enough <mark>citizens</mark>. Peacetime crimes</u>, such as prison construction sold as economic development to impoverished communities in the mountains and deserts of California, or the evolution of the criminal industrial complex into the latest peculiar institution for managing race relations in the United States (Waquant, Chapter 39), <u>constitute the “small wars and invisible genocides”</u> to which we refer. This applies to African American and Latino youth mortality statistics in Oakland, California, Baltimore, Washington DC, and New York City. <u><mark>These are “invisible” genocides</mark> not <mark>because they are</mark> secreted away or hidden from view, but quite the opposite.</u> As Wittgenstein observed<u>, the things that are hardest to perceive are those which are <mark>right before our eyes and</mark> therefore taken for granted.</u> In this regard, Bourdieu’s partial and unfinished theory of violence (see Chapters 32 and 42) as well as his concept of misrecognition is crucial to our task. By including the normative everyday forms of violence hidden in the minutiae of “normal” social practices - in the architecture of homes, in gender relations, in communal work, in the exchange of gifts, and so forth - Bourdieu forces us to reconsider the broader meanings and status of violence, especially the links between the violence of everyday life and explicit political terror and state repression, Similarly, Basaglia’s notion of “peacetime crimes” - crimini di pace - imagines a direct relationship between wartime and peacetime violence. <u>Peacetime crimes suggests the possibility that <mark>war crimes are</mark> merely <mark>ordinary, everyday crimes of public consent applied systematically</mark> and dramatically <mark>in the extreme context of war</u></mark>. Consider the parallel uses of rape during peacetime and wartime, or the family resemblances between the legalized violence of US immigration and naturalization border raids on “illegal aliens” versus the US government- engineered genocide in 1938, known as the Cherokee “Trail of Tears.” Peacetime crimes suggests that everyday forms of state violence make a certain kind of domestic peace possible. Internal “stability” is purchased with the currency of peacetime crimes, many of which take the form of professionally applied “strangle-holds.” Everyday forms of state violence during peacetime make a certain kind of domestic “peace” possible. It is an easy-to-identify peacetime crime that is usually maintained as a public secret by the government and by a scared or apathetic populace. Most subtly, but no less politically or structurally, the phenomenal growth in the United States of a new military, postindustrial prison industrial complex has taken place in the absence of broad-based opposition, let alone collective acts of civil disobedience. <u>The public consensus is based primarily on a new mobilization of an old fear of the mob, the mugger, the rapist, the Black man, the undeserving poor. How many public executions of mentally deficient prisoners in the United States are needed to make life feel more secure for the affluent? </u>What can it possibly mean when incarceration becomes the “normative” socializing experience for ethnic minority youth in a society, i.e., over 33 percent of young African American men (Prison Watch 2002). In the end <u><mark>it is essential that we</mark> recognize the existence of a genocidal capacity among otherwise good-enough humans and that we need to <mark>exercise a defensive hypervigilance to the</mark> less dramatic, permitted, and even rewarded <mark>everyday acts of violence that render participation in genocidal acts</mark> <mark>and policies</mark> <mark>possible</u></mark> (under adverse political or economic conditions), perhaps more easily than we would like to recognize. <u>Under the violence continuum we include, therefore, all expressions of radical social exclusion, dehumanization, depersonal- ization, pseudospeciation, and reification which normalize atrocious behavior and violence toward others. A constant self-mobilization for alarm, a state of constant hyperarousal is, perhaps, a reasonable response to Benjamin’s view of late modern history as a chronic “state of emergency”</u> (Taussig, Chapter 31). We are trying to recover here the classic anagogic thinking that enabled Erving Goffman, Jules Henry, C. Wright Mills, and Franco Basaglia among other mid-twentieth-century radically critical thinkers, to perceive the symbolic and structural relations, i.e., between inmates and patients, between concentration camps, prisons, mental hospitals, nursing homes, and other “total institutions.” <u><mark>Making that decisive move to recognize the continuum of violence</mark> <mark>allows us to see the capacity</mark> and the willingness - if not enthusiasm - <mark>of ordinary people,</mark> the practical technicians of the social consensus, <mark>to enforce genocidal</mark>-<mark>like</mark> <mark>crimes</mark> against categories of rubbish people. <mark>There is no primary impulse out of which mass violence and genocide are born, it is ingrained in the common sense of everyday social life</mark>. The mad, the differently abled, the mentally vulnerable have often fallen into this category of the unworthy living, as have the very old and infirm, the sick-poor, and, of course, the despised racial, religious, sexual, and ethnic groups of the moment.</u> Erik Erikson referred to “pseudo- speciation” as the human tendency to classify some individuals or social groups as less than fully human - a prerequisite to genocide and one that is carefully honed during the unremark- able peacetimes that precede the sudden, “seemingly unintelligible” outbreaks of mass violence<u>. <mark>Collective denial and misrecognition are prerequisites for mass violence</mark> and genocide.</u> But so are formal bureaucratic structures and professional roles. The practical technicians of everyday violence in the backlands of Northeast Brazil (Scheper-Hughes, Chapter 33), for example, include the clinic doctors who prescribe powerful tranquilizers to fretful and frightfully hungry babies, the Catholic priests who celebrate the death of “angel-babies,” and the municipal bureaucrats who dispense free baby coffins but no food to hungry families. <u>Everyday violence encompasses the implicit, legitimate, and routinized forms of violence inherent in particular social, economic, and political formations.</u> It is close to what Bourdieu (1977, 1996) means by “symbolic violence,” the violence that is often “nus-recognized” for something else, usually something good. Everyday violence is similar to what Taussig (1989) calls “terror as usual.” All these terms are meant to reveal a public secret - the hidden links between violence in war and violence in peace, and between war crimes and “peace-time crimes.” Bourdieu (1977) finds domination and violence in the least likely places - in courtship and marriage, in the exchange of gifts, in systems of classification, in style, art, and culinary taste- the various uses of culture. Violence, Bourdieu insists, is everywhere in social practice. It is misrecognized because its very everydayness and its familiarity render it invisible. Lacan identifies “rneconnaissance” as the prerequisite of the social. The exploitation of bachelor sons, robbing them of autonomy, independence, and progeny, within the structures of family farming in the European countryside that Bourdieu escaped is a case in point (Bourdieu, Chapter 42; see also Scheper-Hughes, 2000b; Favret-Saada, 1989). Following Gramsci, Foucault, Sartre, Arendt, and other modern theorists of power-vio- lence, Bourdieu treats direct aggression and physical violence as a crude, uneconomical mode of domination; it is less efficient and, according to Arendt (1969), it is certainly less legitimate. While power and symbolic domination are not to be equated with violence - and Arendt argues persuasively that violence is to be understood as a failure of power - violence, as we are presenting it here, is more than simply the expression of illegitimate physical force against a person or group of persons. Rather, we need to understand violence as encompassing all forms of “controlling processes” (Nader 1997b) that assault basic human freedoms and individual or collective survival. Our task is to recognize these gray zones of violence which are, by definition, not obvious. Once again, the point of bringing into the discourses on genocide everyday, normative experiences of reification, depersonalization, institutional confinement, and acceptable death is to help answer the question: What makes mass violence and genocide possible? In this volume we are suggesting <u>that <mark>mass violence</mark> is part of a continuum, and that it <mark>is socially incremental and often experienced</mark> by perpetrators, collaborators, bystanders - and even by victims themselves - <mark>as expected, routine</mark>, even justified</u>. The preparations for mass killing can be found in social sentiments and institutions from the family, to schools, churches, hospitals, and the military. <u><mark>They harbor the</u></mark> early “warning signs” (Charney 1991), the <u>“<mark>priming</mark>”</u> (as Hinton, ed., 2002 calls it), or the “genocidal continuum” (as we call it) <u><mark>that push social consensus toward devaluing certain forms of human life</u></mark> and lifeways from the refusal of social support and humane care to vulnerable “social parasites” (the nursing home elderly, “welfare queens,” undocumented immigrants, drug addicts) to the militarization of everyday life (super-maximum-security prisons, capital punishment; the technologies of heightened personal security, including the house gun and gated communities; and reversed feelings of victimization).</p>
null
null
Contention 2 is the Illegal market
16,028
483
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,306
Dehydration isn’t painful, nurses have positive view of it
Andrews and Levine 89
Andrews and Levine 89 Maria R. Andrews, MS, RD, VA Medical Center in Wilkes Barre, PA; Department of Human Ecology, Levine AM, Alan M. Levine, PhD, RD, Foods and Nutrition Program at the Department of Human Ecology, The American Journal of Hospice Care [1989, 6(1):31-34], “Dehydration in the terminal patient: perception of hospice nurses”, http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/2713109 //jchen
Recent discussion about the care of the terminally ill patient has focused on the appropriateness of withholding and withdrawing food and fluid and on the discomfort of the dehydrated state. Evidence is mounting that suggests that dehydration in this group of people is not painful, The scores for the degree of positive perception of dehydration are compared for the experienced and nonexperienced groups of nurses This study suggests that those hospice nurses who have observed terminal dehydration have a more positive perception of this state than those who have not.
null
Recent discussion about the care of the terminally ill patient has focused on the appropriateness of withholding and withdrawing food and fluid and on the discomfort of the dehydrated state. Evidence is mounting that suggests that dehydration in this group of people is not painful, but rather may be more comfortable than hydration by means of IV fluids or enteral and parenteral feedings. This study examines the relationship between the experience of hospice nurses in observing terminal dehydration and their perception of this state. The scores for the degree of positive perception of dehydration are compared for the experienced and nonexperienced groups of nurses. This study suggests that those hospice nurses who have observed terminal dehydration have a more positive perception of this state than those who have not.
828
<h4><strong>Dehydration isn’t painful, nurses have positive view of it</h4><p>Andrews and Levine 89</p><p></strong>Maria R. Andrews, MS, RD, VA Medical Center in Wilkes Barre, PA; Department of Human Ecology, Levine AM, Alan M. Levine, PhD, RD, Foods and Nutrition Program at the Department of Human Ecology, The American Journal of Hospice Care [1989, 6(1):31-34], “Dehydration in the terminal patient: perception of hospice nurses”, http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/2713109 //<u>jchen</p><p>Recent discussion about the care of the terminally ill patient has focused on the appropriateness of withholding and withdrawing food and fluid and on the discomfort of the dehydrated state. Evidence is mounting that suggests that dehydration in this group of people is not painful,</u> but rather may be more comfortable than hydration by means of IV fluids or enteral and parenteral feedings. This study examines the relationship between the experience of hospice nurses in observing terminal dehydration and their perception of this state. <u>The scores for the degree of positive perception of dehydration are compared for the experienced and nonexperienced groups of nurses</u>. <u>This study suggests that those hospice nurses who have observed terminal dehydration have a more positive perception of this state than those who have not.</p></u>
null
Case
2NC Link Debate
430,644
2
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,307
Low probability impacts should not be evaluated-- even if there’s some risk, policy decisions can’t be justified by vanishingly small probabilities
Rescher 03
Rescher 03 (Nicholas, Prof of Philosophy at the University of Pittsburgh, Sensible Decisions: Issues of Rational Decision in Personal Choice and Public Policy, p. 49-50)
null
null
Problems with the DA—
21
<h4>Low probability impacts should not be evaluated-- even if there’s some risk, policy decisions can’t be justified by vanishingly small probabilities</h4><p><strong>Rescher 03</strong> (Nicholas, Prof of Philosophy at the University of Pittsburgh, Sensible Decisions: Issues of Rational Decision in Personal Choice and Public Policy, p. 49-50)</p><p>Problems with the DA—</p>
2AC
Case
Framing
430,645
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,308
gambling regulations are a TINY part of banking costs—they have to deal with the housing market, investment globally, and currency trade
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>gambling regulations are a TINY part of banking costs—they have to deal with the housing market, investment globally, and currency trade</h4>
WTO
Banks
AT: Inevitable
430,646
1
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,309
The United States should remove criminal and civil penalties on prostitution in the United States. The United States should extend labor regulations to prostitution. Employers of sex workers engaged in prostitution should be required to negotiate working conditions with their employers.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The United States should remove criminal and civil penalties on prostitution in the United States. The United States should extend labor regulations to prostitution. Employers of sex workers engaged in prostitution should be required to negotiate working conditions with their employers.</h4>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,647
1
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,310
non-compliance inev
Ikenson 13
Daniel J. Ikenson 13, director of Cato’s Herbert A. Stiefel Center for Trade Policy Studies, MA in economics from George Washington University, “Protectionist Antidumping Regime Is a Pox on America’s Glass House,” www.cato.org/publications/commentary/protectionist-antidumping-regime-pox-americas-glass-house
U.S. policies have been the subject of more W T O disputes 119 and have been found to violate WTO rules more frequently than any other government’s policies No government is more likely to be out of compliance with a final DSB ruling the U S remains out of compliance in cases involving U.S. subsidies to cotton farmers restrictions on Antigua’s gambling services, country of origin labeling requirements on meat products, the so-called Byrd Amendment, a variety of antidumping measures, and several other issues some of which were adjudicated more than a decade ago. , U.S. trade partners have either retaliated, or been authorized to retaliate yet non-compliance continues
U.S. policies have been the subject of more W T O disputes 119 and violate WTO rules more than any other government the U S remains out of compliance in subsidies to cotton farmers country of origin labeling requirements on meat products, the Byrd Amendment antidumping measures, and several other issues U.S. trade partners have retaliated, or been authorized to retaliate yet non-compliance continues
Other candidates come to mind when contemplating the world’s worst international trade scofflaw, but the United States makes a strong case for itself. A recent Commerce Department determination that foreign companies like Samsung, LG, and Electrolux engaged in “targeted dumping” by reducing prices on their washing machines for Black Friday sales confirms that the United States is actively seeking that ignominious distinction. U.S. policies have been the subject of more World Trade Organization disputes (119, followed by the EU with 73, then China with 30) and have been found to violate WTO rules more frequently than any other government’s policies. No government is more likely to be out of compliance with a final WTO Dispute Settlement Body (DSB) ruling — or for a longer period — than the U.S. government. To this day, the United States remains out of compliance in cases involving U.S. subsidies to cotton farmers, restrictions on Antigua’s provision of gambling services, country of origin labeling requirements on meat products, the so-called Byrd Amendment, a variety of antidumping measures, and several other issues, some of which were adjudicated more than a decade ago. In some of these cases, U.S. trade partners have either retaliated, or been authorized to retaliate, against U.S. exporters or asset holders, yet the non-compliance continues as though the United States considers itself above the rules.
1,425
<h4>non-compliance inev </h4><p>Daniel J. <strong>Ikenson 13</strong>, director of Cato’s Herbert A. Stiefel Center for Trade Policy Studies, MA in economics from George Washington University, “Protectionist Antidumping Regime Is a Pox on America’s Glass House,” www.cato.org/publications/commentary/protectionist-antidumping-regime-pox-americas-glass-house</p><p>Other candidates come to mind when contemplating the world’s worst international trade scofflaw, but the United States makes a strong case for itself. A recent Commerce Department determination that foreign companies like Samsung, LG, and Electrolux engaged in “targeted dumping” by reducing prices on their washing machines for Black Friday sales confirms that the United States is actively seeking that ignominious distinction.</p><p><u><mark>U.S. policies have been the subject of more</u> <u>W</u></mark>orld <u><mark>T</u></mark>rade <u><mark>O</u></mark>rganization <u><mark>disputes</u></mark> (<u><strong><mark>119</u></strong></mark>, followed by the EU with 73, then China with 30) <u><mark>and</mark> have been found to <mark>violate WTO rules more</mark> frequently <mark>than any other government</mark>’s policies</u>. <u>No government is more likely to be out of compliance with a final</u> WTO Dispute Settlement Body (<u>DSB</u>) <u>ruling</u> — or for a longer period — than the U.S. government. To this day, <u><mark>the U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates <u><mark>remains out of compliance in</mark> cases involving U.S. <mark>subsidies to cotton farmers</u></mark>, <u>restrictions on Antigua’s </u>provision of<u> gambling services, <mark>country of origin labeling requirements on meat products, the </mark>so-called <mark>Byrd Amendment</mark>, a variety of <mark>antidumping measures, and <strong>several other issues</u></strong></mark>, <u>some of which were adjudicated more than a decade ago. </u>In some of these cases<u>, <mark>U.S. trade partners <strong>have</strong></mark> either <strong><mark>retaliated</strong>, or been authorized to</mark> <mark>retaliate</u></mark>, against U.S. exporters or asset holders, <u><mark>yet</u></mark> the <u><mark>non-compliance continues</u><strong></mark> as though the United States considers itself above the rules.</p></strong>
null
null
1NC
97,365
55
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,311
Contracting solves certainty- provides safe harbor
Kleiman 2013 (Mark, professor of public policy at UCLA, “Federalism and cannabis policy: the terms of a bargain,” August 23rd, http://www.samefacts.com/2013/08/drug-policy/federalism-and-cannabis-policy-the-terms-of-a-bargain/)
Kleiman 2013 (Mark, professor of public policy at UCLA, “Federalism and cannabis policy: the terms of a bargain,” August 23rd, http://www.samefacts.com/2013/08/drug-policy/federalism-and-cannabis-policy-the-terms-of-a-bargain/)
I offer two alternatives to the options as to how the federal government can deal with state-level cannabis legalization. Washington and Colorado would like the feds to let their new commercial systems operate the Controlled Substances Act orders the Attorney General to cooperate with state and local officials in enforcing the law, and authorizes contractual arrangements with states formal deals in which the Justice Department would agree to keep hands off state-licensed businesses in return for the states’ active help in suppressing interstate trade That wouldn’t make the state-authorized activity legal but formalize a program of selective enforcement that would give state licensees an effective safe harbor.
two alternatives the Controlled Substances Act orders the Attorney General to cooperate with state and local officials contractual arrangements” with states in which the Justice Department would agree to keep hands off businesses in return for the states’ active help in suppressing interstate trade That wouldn’t make the state-authorized activity legal, but formalize selective enforcement that would give state licensees a safe harbor
The Journal of Drug Policy Analysis has just published a new paper (behind a paywall) in which I offer two alternatives to the options currently in public discussion as to how the federal government can deal with state-level cannabis legalization. This fall, Washington and Colorado intend to start licensing businesses to produce and sell cannabis under voter-passed initiatives, even though the stuff remains illegal under federal law. The federal government has not yet said what it plans to do about it, and its three obvious options – acquiescing, cracking down, and muddling through – all have fairly serious drawbacks. A number of what Keith calls Formerly Important Persons have demanded that the feds crush the state-legal Colorado and Washington markets. Since every participant in those markets needs a license, that wouldn’t be hard to do: any federal judge would cheerfully enjoin someone applying for license to commit a federal felony from doing so. But the state-legal commercial markets represent only one of three systems that can deliver cannabis to customers. The loosely-regulated “medical marijuana” markets would be a far tougher nut for the feds to crack. And the purely illicit system, which handles the vast bulk of transactions today, is way too big for 4000 DEA agents to suppress without help. More than 90% of arrests for growing and dealing marijuana are made by state and local cops. So the feds need state and local authorities in Washington and Colorado to maintain pressure on illegal growing. Constitutionally, the states have no mandate to even have drug laws, let alone enforce them. In this case, federalism is more than a legal doctrine: it’s a brute fact. So: Washington and Colorado would like the feds to let their new commercial systems operate. And the feds would like Washington and Colorado to suppress production for out-of-state sale. When each of two parties has something the other wants, that’s the basis for a bargain. And the Controlled Substances Act (Sec. 873, if you’re keeping score at home) orders the Attorney General to cooperate with state and local officials in enforcing the law, and authorizes him, “notwithstanding any other provision of law,” to enter into “contractual arrangements” with states and localities. The paper proposes that he use that authority to make formal deals with Colorado and Washington in which the Justice Department would agree to keep hands off state-licensed businesses in return for the states’ active help in suppressing interstate trade. That wouldn’t make the state-authorized activity legal, but it could formalize a program of targeted, selective enforcement that would give state licensees an effective safe harbor.
2,715
<h4>Contracting solves certainty- provides safe harbor</h4><p><strong>Kleiman 2013</strong> <u><strong>(Mark, professor of public policy at UCLA, “Federalism and cannabis policy: the terms of a bargain,” August 23rd, http://www.samefacts.com/2013/08/drug-policy/federalism-and-cannabis-policy-the-terms-of-a-bargain/)</p><p></u></strong>The Journal of Drug Policy Analysis has just published a new paper (behind a paywall) in which <u>I offer <mark>two alternatives</mark> to the options </u>currently in public discussion <u>as to how the federal government can deal with state-level cannabis legalization. </u>This fall, Washington and Colorado intend to start licensing businesses to produce and sell cannabis under voter-passed initiatives, even though the stuff remains illegal under federal law. The federal government has not yet said what it plans to do about it, and its three obvious options – acquiescing, cracking down, and muddling through – all have fairly serious drawbacks. A number of what Keith calls Formerly Important Persons have demanded that the feds crush the state-legal Colorado and Washington markets. Since every participant in those markets needs a license, that wouldn’t be hard to do: any federal judge would cheerfully enjoin someone applying for license to commit a federal felony from doing so. But the state-legal commercial markets represent only one of three systems that can deliver cannabis to customers. The loosely-regulated “medical marijuana” markets would be a far tougher nut for the feds to crack. And the purely illicit system, which handles the vast bulk of transactions today, is way too big for 4000 DEA agents to suppress without help. More than 90% of arrests for growing and dealing marijuana are made by state and local cops. So the feds need state and local authorities in Washington and Colorado to maintain pressure on illegal growing. Constitutionally, the states have no mandate to even have drug laws, let alone enforce them. In this case, federalism is more than a legal doctrine: it’s a brute fact. So: <u>Washington and Colorado would like the feds to let their new commercial systems operate</u>. And the feds would like Washington and Colorado to suppress production for out-of-state sale. When each of two parties has something the other wants, that’s the basis for a bargain. And <u><mark>the Controlled Substances Act</u></mark> (Sec. 873, if you’re keeping score at home) <u><mark>orders the Attorney General to cooperate with state and local officials</mark> in enforcing the law, and authorizes</u> him, “notwithstanding any other provision of law,” to enter into “<u><mark>contractual arrangements</u>” <u>with states</u></mark> and localities. The paper proposes that he use that authority to make <u>formal deals</u> with Colorado and Washington <u><mark>in which the Justice Department would agree to keep hands off</mark> state-licensed <mark>businesses in return for the states’ active help in suppressing interstate trade</u></mark>. <u><strong><mark>That wouldn’t make the state-authorized activity legal</u></strong>, <u><strong>but</u></strong></mark> it could <u><strong><mark>formalize</mark> a program of</u></strong> targeted, <u><strong><mark>selective enforcement</mark> <mark>that would give state licensees</mark> <mark>a</mark>n effective <mark>safe harbor</mark>.</p></u></strong>
null
null
Counteradvocacy
56,742
9
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,312
Planning for the future is futile. Only embracing the negativity projected onto the queer reveals the recurring violence of reproductive futurism. Refuse futurism to set the queer free of the figural Child, and the violent future it both replicates and intends.
Edelman ’04 , p. 2-7
Edelman ’04, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, p. 2-7
But what helped him most in these public appeals on behalf of children is impossible to refuse. logic compels us to submit to the framing of political debate as defined by the terms of what this book describes as reproductive futurism: terms that , impose an ideological limit on political discourse as such, preserving in the process the absolute privilege of heteronormativity by rendering un thinkable, by casting outside the political domain, the possibility of a queer resistance to this organizing principle of communal relations. however radical the means by which specific constituencies attempt to produce a more desirable social order, remains conservative insofar as it works to affirm a structure, to authenticate social order, which it then intends to transmit to the future in the form of its inner Child That Child remains the perpetual horizon of every acknowledged politics, the fantasmatic beneficiary of every political intervention. ow could one take the other ‘side,” when taking any side at all necessarily constrains one to take the side by virtue of taking a side within, a political order that returns to the Child as the image of the future it intends queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children,” the side outside the consensus by which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism queerness attains its ethical value precisely insofar as it accedes to that place, accepting its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure. the pervasive invocation of the Child as the emblem of futurity’s unquestioned value and propose against it the impossible project of queer oppositionality that would oppose itself to the structural determinants of politics as such, which is also to say, that would oppose itself to the logic of opposition. This paradoxical formulation suggests a refusal Far from partaking of this narrative movement toward a viable political future, far from per perpetuating the fantasy of meaning’s eventual realization, the queer comes to figure the bar to every realization of futurity, the resistance, internal to the social, to every social structure or form. Rather than rejecting, with liberal discourse, this ascription of negativity to the queer, we might do better to consider accepting and even embracing it. Not in the hope of forging thereby some more perfect social order such a hope, after all, would only reproduce the constraining mandate of futurism, just as any such order would equally occasion the negativity of the queer but rather to refuse the insistence of hope itself as affirmation, which is always affirmation of an order whose refusal will register as unthinkable, irresponsible, inhumane And the trump card of affirmation Always the question: if not this, what? — I do not intend to propose some “good” that will thereby be assured , I mean to insist that nothing, and certainly not what we call the “good,” can ever have any assurance at all in the order of the Symbolic The structuring optimism of politics to which the order of meaning commits us, installing as it does the perpetual hope of reaching meaning through signification, is always, I would argue, a negation of this primal, constitutive, and negative act taking the Symbolic’s negativity to the very letter of the law attending to the persistence of something internal to reason that reason refuses turning the force of queerness against all subjects, however queer, can afford an access to the jouissance that at once defines and negates us Or better: can expose the constancy, the inescapability, of such access to jouissance in the social order itself; even if that order can access its constant access to jouissance only in the process of abjecting that constancy of access onto the queer. does not have the character of a universal law but, on the contrary, of the most particular of laws —even if it is universal that this particularity is to be found in every human being.’ The embrace of queer negativity, then, can have no justification if justification requires it to reinforce some positive social value; its value, instead, resides in its challenge to value as defined by the social by figuring a refusal of the coercive belief in the paramount value of futurity the queer dispossesses the social order of the ground on which it rests: a faith in the consistent reality of the social—and by extension, of the social subject; a faith that politics, whether of the left or of the right, implicitly affirms , the queer insists that politics is always a politics of the signifier, or even of what Lacan will often refer to as “the letter It serves to shore up a reality always unmoored by signification and lacking any guarantee To say as much is not, of course, to deny the experiential violence that frequently troubles social reality or the apparent consistency with which it bears us al . It is to suggest that queerness exposes the obliquity of our relation to what we experience in and as social reality, alerting us to the fantasies structurally necessary in order to sustain it and engaging those fantasies through the figural logics, the linguistic structures that shape them. queer theory must always insist on its connection to the vicissitudes of the sign, to the tension between the signifier’s collapse into the letter’s cadaverous materiality and its participation in a system of reference wherein it generates meaning itself one that takes both the value and the burden of that failure upon itself, queer theory marks the “other” side of politics: the “side” where narrative realization and derealization overlap, where the energies of vitalization ceaselessly turn against themselves; the “side” outside all political sides, committed as they are, on every side, to futurism’s unquestioned good
appeal on behalf of children is impossible to refuse terms of reproductive futurism: impose an ideological limit on political discourse as such, preserving the absolute privilege of heteronormativity , by casting outside the political domain, queer resistance to this principle . politics however radical the attempt to produce a more desirable social order remains conservative insofar as it works to authenticate social order, to transmit to the future That Child remains the perpetual horizon of every acknowledged politics How could one take the other ‘side,” when taking any side returns to the Child as the image of the future it intends queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children queerness attains its ethical value insofar as it accept its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure. the impossible project of queer oppositionality would oppose itself to the logic of opposition Rather than rejecting, this ascription of negativity to the queer, we might consider embracing it. Not in the hope of forging some more perfect social order such hope would only reproduce the mandate of futurism, but rather to refuse the insistence of hope itself as affirmation, which is always affirmation of an order whose refusal will register as unthinkable, irresponsible, inhumane structuring optimism of politics , is always, a negation of this primal, constitutive, and negative act taking the Symbolic’s negativity can expose , the inescapability, of such access to jouissance in the social order itself; order can access jouissance only in the process of abjecting that constancy onto the queer. . The embrace of queer negativity can have no justification if justification requires it to reinforce some positive social value; its value, resides in its challenge to value as defined by the social by figuring a refusal in the value of futurity the queer dispossesses the social order of the ground on which it rests: a faith in the consistent reality of the social subject that politics affirms queer theory marks the “other” side of politics: the “side” outside all political sides, committed as they are, on every side, to futurism’s unquestioned good
But what helped him most in these public appeals on behalf of America’s children was the social consensus that such an appeal is impossible to refuse. Indeed, though these public service announcements concluded with the sort of rhetorical flourish associated with hard-fought political campaigns (“We’re fighting for the children. Whose side are you on”), that rhetoric was intended to avow that this issue, like an ideological Möbius strip, only permitted one side. Such “self-evident” one-sidedness— the affirmation of a value so unquestioned, because so obviously unquestionable, as that of the Child whose innocence solicits our defense— is precisely, of course, what distinguishes public service announcements from the partisan discourse of political argumentation. But it is also, I suggest, what makes such announcements so oppressively political— political not in the partisan terms implied by the media consultant, but political in a far more insidious way: political insofar as the fantasy sub- tending the image of the Child invariably shapes the logic within which the political itself must be thought. That logic compels us, to the extent that we would register as politically responsible, to submit to the framing of political debate —and, indeed, of the political field—as defined by the terms of what this book describes as reproductive futurism: terms that , impose an ideological limit on political discourse as such, preserving in the process the absolute privilege of heteronormativity by rendering un thinkable, by casting outside the political domain, the possibility of a queer resistance to this organizing principle of communal relations. For politics, however radical the means by which specific constituencies attempt to produce a more desirable social order, remains, at its core, conservative insofar as it works to affirm a structure, to authenticate social order, which it then intends to transmit to the future in the form of its inner Child. That Child remains the perpetual horizon of every acknowledged politics, the fantasmatic beneficiary of every political intervention. Even proponents of abortion rights, while promoting the freedom of women to control their own bodies through reproductive choice, recurrently frame their political struggle, mirroring their anti-abortion foes, as a “fight for our children — for our daughters and our sons,” and thus as a fight for the future.’ What, in that case, would it signify not to be “fighting for the children” How could one take the other ‘side,” when taking any side at all necessarily constrains one to take the side by virtue of taking a side within, a political order that returns to the Child as the image of the future it intends? Impossibly, against all reasons my project stakes its claim w the very space that politics” makes unthinkable: the space outside the framework within which politics as we know it appears and so outside the conflict of visions that share as their pre supposition that the body politic must survive. Indeed, at the heart of my polemical engagement with the cultural text of politics and the politics of cultural texts lies a simple provocation: that queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children,” the side outside the consensus by which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism. The ups and downs of political fortune may measure the social order’s pulse, but queerness, by contrast, figures, outside and beyond its political symptoms, the place of the social order’s death drive: a place, to be sure, of abjection expressed in the stigma, sometimes fatal, that follows from reading that figure literally, and hence a place from which liberal politics strives—and strives quite reasonably, given its unlimited faith in reason—to disassociate the queer. More radically, though, as I argue here, queerness attains its ethical value precisely insofar as it accedes to that place, accepting its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure. To make such a claim I examine in this book the pervasive invocation of the Child as the emblem of futurity’s unquestioned value and propose against it the impossible project of queer oppositionality that would oppose itself to the structural determinants of politics as such, which is also to say, that would oppose itself to the logic of opposition. This paradoxical formulation suggests a refusal —the appropriately perverse refusal that characterizes queer theory—of every substantialization of identity, which is always oppositionally defined and, by extension, of history as linear narrative (the poor man’s teleology) in which meaning succeeds in revealing itself—as itself—through time. Far from partaking of this narrative movement toward a viable political future, far from per perpetuating the fantasy of meaning’s eventual realization, the queer comes to figure the bar to every realization of futurity, the resistance, internal to the social, to every social structure or form. Rather than rejecting, with liberal discourse, this ascription of negativity to the queer, we might, as I argue, do better to consider accepting and even embracing it. Not in the hope of forging thereby some more perfect social order—such a hope, after all, would only reproduce the constraining mandate of futurism, just as any such order would equally occasion the negativity of the queer—but rather to refuse the insistence of hope itself as affirmation, which is always affirmation of an order whose refusal will register as unthinkable, irresponsible, inhumane. And the trump card of affirmation? Always the question: if not this, what? Always the demand to translate the insistence, the pulsive force, of negativity into some determinate stance or “position” whose determination would thus negate it: always the imperative to immure it in some stable and positive form. When I argue, then, that we might do well to attempt what is surely impossible — to withdraw our allegiance, however compulsory, from a reality based on the Ponzi scheme of reproductive futurism— I do not intend to propose some “good” that will thereby be assured. To toe contrary, I mean to insist that nothing, and certainly not what we call the “good,” can ever have any assurance at all in the order of the Symbolic. Abjuring fidelity to a futurism that’s always purchased at our expense, though bound, as Symbolic subjects consigned to figure the Symbolic’s undoing, to the necessary contradiction of trying to turn its intelligibility against itself, we might rather, figuratively, cast our vote for “none of the above,” for the primacy of a constant no in response to the law of the Symbolic, which would echo that law’s foundational act, its self- constituting negation. The structuring optimism of politics to which the order of meaning commits us, installing as it does the perpetual hope of reaching meaning through signification, is always, I would argue, a negation of this primal, constitutive, and negative act. And the various positivities produced in its wake by the logic of political hope depend on the mathematical illusion that negated negations might somehow escape, and not redouble, such negativity. My polemic thus stakes its fortunes on a truly hopeless wager: that taking the Symbolic’s negativity to the very letter of the law, that attending to the persistence of something internal to reason that reason refuses, that turning the force of queerness against all subjects, however queer, can afford an access to the jouissance that at once defines and negates us. Or better: can expose the constancy, the inescapability, of such access to jouissance in the social order itself; even if that order can access its constant access to jouissance only in the process of abjecting that constancy of access onto the queer. In contrast to what Theodor Adorno describes as the “grimness with which a man clings to himself, as to the immediately sure and substantial,” the queerness of which I speak would deliberately sever us from ourselves, from the assurance, that is, of knowing ourselves and hence of knowing our “good.”4 Such queerness proposes, in place of the good, something I want to call “better,” though it promises, in more than one sense of the phrase, absolutely nothing. ¡ connect this something better with Lacan’s characterization of what he calls “truth,” where truth does not assure happiness, or even, as Lacan makes clear, the good.5 Instead, it names only the insistent particularity of the subject, impossible fully to articulate and “tend[ing] toward the real.” Lacan, therefore, can write of this truth: The quality that best characterizes it is that of being the true Wunsch, which was at the origin of an aberrant or atypical behavior. We encounter this Wunsch with its particular, irreducible character as a modification that presupposes no other form of normalization than that of an experience of pleasure or of pain, but of a final experience from whence it springs and is subsequently preserved in the depths of the subject in an irreducible form. The Wunsch does not have the character of a universal law but, on the contrary, of the most particular of laws —even if it is universal that this particularity is to be found in every human being.’ Truth, like queerness, irreducibly linked to the “aberrant or atypical,” to what chafes against “normalization,” finds its value not in a good susceptible to generalization, but only in the stubborn particularity that voids every notion of a general good. The embrace of queer negativity, then, can have no justification if justification requires it to reinforce some positive social value; its value, instead, resides in its challenge to value as defined by the social, and thus in its radical challenge to the very value of the social itself. For by figuring a refusal of the coercive belief in the paramount value of futurity, while refusing as well any backdoor hope for dialectical access to meaning, the queer dispossesses the social order of the ground on which it rests: a faith in the consistent reality of the social—and by extension, of the social subject; a faith that politics, whether of the left or of the right, implicitly affirms. Divesting such politics of its thematic trappings, bracketing the particularity of its various proposals for social organization, the queer insists that politics is always a politics of the signifier, or even of what Lacan will often refer to as “the letter’ It serves to shore up a reality always unmoored by signification and lacking any guarantee. To say as much is not, of course, to deny the experiential violence that frequently troubles social reality or the apparent consistency with which it bears—and thereby bears down on— us all. It is, rather, to suggest that queerness exposes the obliquity of our relation to what we experience in and as social reality, alerting us to the fantasies structurally necessary in order to sustain it and engaging those fantasies through the figural logics, the linguistic structures that shape them. If it aims effectively to intervene in the reproduction of such a reality—an intervention that may well take the form of figuring that reality’s abortion— then queer theory must always insist on its connection to the vicissitudes of the sign, to the tension between the signifier’s collapse into the letter’s cadaverous materiality and its participation in a system of reference wherein it generates meaning itself. As a particular story, in other words, of why storytelling tells, one that takes both the value and the burden of that failure upon itself, queer theory, as I construe it, marks the “other” side of politics: the “side” where narrative realization and derealization overlap, where the energies of vitalization ceaselessly turn against themselves; the “side” outside all political sides, committed as they are, on every side, to futurism’s unquestioned good. The rest of this book attempts to explain the implications of this assertion, but first, let me sketch some connections between politics and the politics of the sign by establishing the psychoanalytic context within which my argument takes shape.
12,279
<h4>Planning for the future is futile. Only embracing the negativity projected onto the queer reveals the recurring violence of reproductive futurism. Refuse futurism to set the queer free of the figural Child, and the violent future it both replicates and intends. </h4><p><strong>Edelman ’04</strong>, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive<u><strong>, p. 2-7</p><p></strong>But what helped him most in these public <mark>appeal</mark>s<mark> on behalf of</u></mark> America’s <u><mark>children</u></mark> was the social consensus that such an appeal <u><mark>is impossible to refuse</mark>.</u> Indeed, though these public service announcements concluded with the sort of rhetorical flourish associated with hard-fought political campaigns (“We’re fighting for the children. Whose side are you on”), that rhetoric was intended to avow that this issue, like an ideological Möbius strip, only permitted one side. Such “self-evident” one-sidedness— the affirmation of a value so unquestioned, because so obviously unquestionable, as that of the Child whose innocence solicits our defense— is precisely, of course, what distinguishes public service announcements from the partisan discourse of political argumentation. But it is also, I suggest, what makes such announcements so oppressively political— political not in the partisan terms implied by the media consultant, but political in a far more insidious way: political insofar as the fantasy sub- tending the image of the Child invariably shapes the logic within which the political itself must be thought. That <u>logic compels us</u>, to the extent that we would register as politically responsible, <u><strong>to submit to the framing of political debate</u></strong> —and, indeed, of the political field—<u>as defined by the <mark>terms of</mark> what this book describes as <strong><mark>reproductive futurism: </mark>terms that , <mark>impose an ideological limit on political discourse as such, preserving </mark>in the process <mark>the absolute privilege of heteronormativity </mark>by rendering un thinkable<mark>, by casting outside the political domain, </mark>the possibility of a <mark>queer resistance to this</mark> organizing <mark>principle</mark> of communal relations<mark>.</p><p></u></strong></mark>For <mark>politics</mark>, <u><mark>however radical the </mark>means by which specific constituencies <mark>attempt to produce a more desirable social order</mark>, <mark>remains</u></mark>, at its core, <u><mark>conservative insofar as it works to</mark> affirm a structure, to <mark>authenticate social order, </mark>which it then intends <mark>to transmit to the future</mark> in the form of its inner Child</u>. <u><mark>That Child remains the perpetual horizon of every acknowledged politics</mark>, the fantasmatic beneficiary of every political intervention.</u> Even proponents of abortion rights, while promoting the freedom of women to control their own bodies through reproductive choice, recurrently frame their political struggle, mirroring their anti-abortion foes, as a “fight for our children — for our daughters and our sons,” and thus as a fight for the future.’ What, in that case, would it signify not to be “fighting for the children” <mark>H<u>ow could one take the other ‘side,” when taking any side</mark> at all necessarily constrains one to take the side by virtue of taking a side within, a political order that <mark>returns to the Child as the image of the future it intends</u></mark>? Impossibly, against all reasons my project stakes its claim w the very space that politics” makes unthinkable: the space outside the framework within which politics as we know it appears and so outside the conflict of visions that share as their pre supposition that the body politic must survive. Indeed, at the heart of my polemical engagement with the cultural text of politics and the politics of cultural texts lies a simple provocation: that <u><mark>queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children</mark>,” the side outside the consensus by which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism</u>. The ups and downs of political fortune may measure the social order’s pulse, but queerness, by contrast, figures, outside and beyond its political symptoms, the place of the social order’s death drive: a place, to be sure, of abjection expressed in the stigma, sometimes fatal, that follows from reading that figure literally, and hence a place from which liberal politics strives—and strives quite reasonably, given its unlimited faith in reason—to disassociate the queer. More radically, though, as I argue here, <u><mark>queerness attains its ethical value</mark> precisely <mark>insofar as it</mark> accedes to that place, <mark>accept</mark>ing <mark>its</mark> <mark>figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure.</mark> </p><p></u>To make such a claim I examine in this book <u>the pervasive invocation of the Child as the emblem of futurity’s unquestioned value and propose against it<mark> the impossible project of queer oppositionality</mark> that would oppose itself to the structural determinants of politics as such, which is also to say, that <mark>would oppose itself to the logic of opposition</mark>. This paradoxical formulation suggests a refusal</u> —the appropriately perverse refusal that characterizes queer theory—of every substantialization of identity, which is always oppositionally defined and, by extension, of history as linear narrative (the poor man’s teleology) in which meaning succeeds in revealing itself—as itself—through time. <u>Far from partaking of this narrative movement toward a viable political future, far from per perpetuating the fantasy of meaning’s eventual realization, the queer comes to figure the bar to every realization of futurity, the resistance, internal to the social, to every social structure or form. </p><p><strong><mark>Rather than rejecting, </mark>with liberal discourse, <mark>this ascription of negativity to the queer, we might</u></strong></mark>, as I argue, <u><strong>do better to <mark>consider </mark>accepting and even <mark>embracing it.</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>Not in the hope of forging </mark>thereby <mark>some more perfect social order</u></mark>—<u><mark>such</mark> a <mark>hope</mark>, after all, <mark>would only reproduce the</mark> constraining <mark>mandate of futurism,</mark> just as any such order would equally occasion the negativity of the queer</u>—<u><strong><mark>but rather to refuse the insistence of hope itself as affirmation, which is always affirmation of an order whose refusal will register as unthinkable, irresponsible, inhumane</u></strong></mark>. <u>And the trump card of affirmation</u>? <u>Always the question: if not this, what?</u> Always the demand to translate the insistence, the pulsive force, of negativity into some determinate stance or “position” whose determination would thus negate it: always the imperative to immure it in some stable and positive form. When I argue, then, that we might do well to attempt what is surely impossible — to withdraw our allegiance, however compulsory, from a reality based on the Ponzi scheme of reproductive futurism<u>— I do not intend to propose some “good” that will thereby be assured</u>. To toe contrary<u>, I mean to insist that nothing, and certainly not what we call the “good,” can ever have any assurance at all in the order of the Symbolic</u>. Abjuring fidelity to a futurism that’s always purchased at our expense, though bound, as Symbolic subjects consigned to figure the Symbolic’s undoing, to the necessary contradiction of trying to turn its intelligibility against itself, we might rather, figuratively, cast our vote for “none of the above,” for the primacy of a constant no in response to the law of the Symbolic, which would echo that law’s foundational act, its self- constituting negation. <u>The <mark>structuring optimism of politics</mark> to which the order of meaning commits us, installing as it does the perpetual hope of reaching meaning through signification<mark>, is always, </mark>I would argue,<mark> a negation of this primal, constitutive, and negative act</u></mark>. And the various positivities produced in its wake by the logic of political hope depend on the mathematical illusion that negated negations might somehow escape, and not redouble, such negativity. My polemic thus stakes its fortunes on a truly hopeless wager: that <u><mark>taking the Symbolic’s negativity</mark> to the very letter of the law</u>, that <u>attending to the persistence of something internal to reason that reason refuses</u>, that <u>turning the force of queerness against all subjects, however queer, can afford an access to the jouissance that at once defines and negates us</u>. <u>Or better: <mark>can expose </mark>the constancy<mark>, the inescapability, of such access to jouissance in the social order itself; </mark>even if that <mark>order can access</mark> its constant access to <mark>jouissance only in the process of abjecting that constancy </mark>of access <mark>onto the queer.</mark> </p><p></u>In contrast to what Theodor Adorno describes as the “grimness with which a man clings to himself, as to the immediately sure and substantial,” the queerness of which I speak would deliberately sever us from ourselves, from the assurance, that is, of knowing ourselves and hence of knowing our “good.”4 Such queerness proposes, in place of the good, something I want to call “better,” though it promises, in more than one sense of the phrase, absolutely nothing. ¡ connect this something better with Lacan’s characterization of what he calls “truth,” where truth does not assure happiness, or even, as Lacan makes clear, the good.5 Instead, it names only the insistent particularity of the subject, impossible fully to articulate and “tend[ing] toward the real.” Lacan, therefore, can write of this truth:</p><p>The quality that best characterizes it is that of being the true Wunsch, which was at the origin of an aberrant or atypical behavior. </p><p>We encounter this Wunsch with its particular, irreducible character as a modification that presupposes no other form of normalization than that of an experience of pleasure or of pain, but of a final experience from whence it springs and is subsequently preserved in the depths of the subject in an irreducible form. The Wunsch<u> does not have the character of a universal law but, on the contrary, of the most particular of laws —even if it is universal that this particularity is to be found in every human being.’</p><p></u>Truth, like queerness, irreducibly linked to the “aberrant or atypical,” to what chafes against “normalization,” finds its value not in a good susceptible to generalization, but only in the stubborn particularity that voids every notion of a general good<mark>. <u>The embrace of queer negativity</mark>, then, <mark>can have no justification if justification requires it to reinforce some positive social value; its value,</mark> instead, <mark>resides in its challenge to value as defined by the social</u></mark>, and thus in its radical challenge to the very value of the social itself.</p><p>For <u><mark>by figuring a refusal</mark> of the coercive belief <mark>in the</mark> paramount <mark>value of futurity</u></mark>, while refusing as well any backdoor hope for dialectical access to meaning, <u><mark>the queer dispossesses the social order of the ground on which it rests: a faith in the consistent reality of the </mark>social—and by extension, of the <mark>social subject</mark>; a faith <mark>that politics</mark>, whether of the left or of the right, implicitly <mark>affirms</u></mark>. Divesting such politics of its thematic trappings, bracketing the particularity of its various proposals for social organization<u>, the queer insists that politics is always a politics of the signifier, or even of what Lacan will often refer to as “the letter</u>’ <u>It serves to shore up a reality always unmoored by signification and lacking any guarantee</u>. <u>To say as much is not, of course, to deny the experiential violence that frequently troubles social reality or the apparent consistency with which it bears</u>—and thereby bears down on— <u>us al</u>l<u>. It is</u>, rather, <u>to suggest that queerness exposes the obliquity of our relation to what we experience in and as social reality, alerting us to the fantasies structurally necessary in order to sustain it and engaging those fantasies through the figural logics, the linguistic structures that shape them.</u> If it aims effectively to intervene in the reproduction of such a reality—an intervention that may well take the form of figuring that reality’s abortion— then <u>queer theory must always insist on its connection to the vicissitudes of the sign, to the tension between the signifier’s collapse into the letter’s cadaverous materiality and its participation in a system of reference wherein it generates meaning itself</u>. As a particular story, in other words, of why storytelling tells, <u>one that takes both the value and the burden of that failure upon itself, <mark>queer theory</u></mark>, as I construe it, <u><mark>marks the “other” side of politics: </mark>the “side” where narrative realization and derealization overlap, where the energies of vitalization ceaselessly turn against themselves;<mark> the “side” outside all political sides, committed as they are, on every side, to futurism’s unquestioned good</u><strong></mark>. The rest of this book attempts to explain the implications of this assertion, but first, let me sketch some connections between politics and the politics of the sign by establishing the psychoanalytic context within which my argument takes shape.</p></strong>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
41,708
457
17,077
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
565,297
A
tournament
4
Binghamton Cepin-Sehgal
Baker, Webster Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,313
The illegal market is also a threat to public health – spreads antibiotic-resistant bacteria
Kelly 13
Kelly 13 Emily Kelly, Executive Comment Editor for the Boston College International & Comparative Law Review. Boston College International and Comparative Law Review Spring, 2013 36 B.C. Int'l & Comp. L. Rev. 1317 NOTE: INTERNATIONAL ORGAN TRAFFICKING CRISIS: SOLUTIONS ADDRESSING THE HEART OF THE MATTER lexis
Because governmental disease control agencies do not monitor underground organ trafficking, recipients risk contracting infectious diseases like West Nile Virus and HIV Transplant tourism harms global public health policies Additionally, transplant tourism and broader medical tourism facilitate the spread of antibiotic-resistant bacteria. Because such bacteria are frequently found in hospitals, tourists are easily exposed and transmit these unique strains across borders upon returning to their home countries
Because governmental disease control agencies do not monitor underground organ trafficking, recipients risk contracting infectious diseases like West Nile Virus and HIV Transplant tourism harms global public health policies transplant tourism and broader medical tourism facilitate the spread of antibiotic-resistant bacteria Because such bacteria are frequently found in hospitals, tourists are easily exposed and transmit these unique strains across borders
[*1324] With regard to recipients, the dangers of receiving medical care in developing countries can outweigh the benefits of life-saving transplant tourism. n66 Because governmental disease control agencies do not monitor underground organ trafficking, recipients risk contracting infectious diseases like West Nile Virus and HIV. n67 Tragically, transplant tourists also have "a higher cumulative incidence of acute [organ] rejection in the first year after transplantation." n68 Transplant tourism also harms global public health policies. n69 Most notably, the underground market impedes the success of legal organ donation frameworks. n70 For example, Thai patients have difficulty accessing health care because local doctors are preoccupied with the lucrative practice of treating transplant tourists. n71 In 2007, China banned transplant tourism because wealthy foreigners--rather than the 1.5 million Chinese on the waiting list--received an overwhelming amount of organ transplants. n72 Grisly tales of transplant tourism and conspiracy theories surrounding organ theft may also discourage individuals from agreeing to altruistic donation upon death out of fear that their bodies may be exploited. n73 This further contributes to the global organ shortage and exacerbates the underlying causes of OTC trafficking. n74 Additionally, transplant tourism and broader medical tourism facilitate the spread of antibiotic-resistant bacteria. n75 Because such bacteria are frequently found in hospitals, tourists are easily exposed and transmit these unique strains across borders upon returning to their home countries. n76 As a result of these effects, transplant tourism has drawn increasing attention to the root of the problem: organ shortages. n77
1,754
<h4>The illegal market is also a threat to public health – spreads antibiotic-resistant bacteria</h4><p><strong>Kelly 13</strong> Emily Kelly, Executive Comment Editor for the Boston College International & Comparative Law Review. Boston College International and Comparative Law Review Spring, 2013 36 B.C. Int'l & Comp. L. Rev. 1317 NOTE: INTERNATIONAL ORGAN TRAFFICKING CRISIS: SOLUTIONS ADDRESSING THE HEART OF THE MATTER lexis</p><p> [*1324] With regard to recipients, the dangers of receiving medical care in developing countries can outweigh the benefits of life-saving transplant tourism. n66 <u><mark>Because governmental disease control agencies do not monitor underground organ trafficking, recipients risk contracting infectious diseases like West Nile Virus and HIV</u></mark>. n67 Tragically, transplant tourists also have "a higher cumulative incidence of acute [organ] rejection in the first year after transplantation." n68 <u><mark>Transplant tourism</u></mark> also <u><mark>harms global public health policies</u></mark>. n69 Most notably, the underground market impedes the success of legal organ donation frameworks. n70 For example, Thai patients have difficulty accessing health care because local doctors are preoccupied with the lucrative practice of treating transplant tourists. n71 In 2007, China banned transplant tourism because wealthy foreigners--rather than the 1.5 million Chinese on the waiting list--received an overwhelming amount of organ transplants. n72 Grisly tales of transplant tourism and conspiracy theories surrounding organ theft may also discourage individuals from agreeing to altruistic donation upon death out of fear that their bodies may be exploited. n73 This further contributes to the global organ shortage and exacerbates the underlying causes of OTC trafficking. n74 <u>Additionally, <mark>transplant tourism and broader medical tourism facilitate the spread of antibiotic-resistant bacteria</mark>.</u> n75 <u><mark>Because such bacteria are frequently found in hospitals, tourists are easily exposed and transmit these unique strains across borders</mark> upon returning to their home countries</u><strong>. n76 As a result of these effects, transplant tourism has drawn increasing attention to the root of the problem: organ shortages. n77</p></strong>
null
null
Contention 2 is the Illegal market
430,429
9
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,314
Dehydration isn’t painful, nurses have positive view of it
Andrews and Levine 89
Andrews and Levine 89 Maria R. Andrews, MS, RD, VA Medical Center in Wilkes Barre, PA; Department of Human Ecology, Levine AM, Alan M. Levine, PhD, RD, Foods and Nutrition Program at the Department of Human Ecology, The American Journal of Hospice Care [1989, 6(1):31-34], “Dehydration in the terminal patient: perception of hospice nurses”, http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/2713109 //jchen
null
null
Recent discussion about the care of the terminally ill patient has focused on the appropriateness of withholding and withdrawing food and fluid and on the discomfort of the dehydrated state. Evidence is mounting that suggests that dehydration in this group of people is not painful, but rather may be more comfortable than hydration by means of IV fluids or enteral and parenteral feedings. This study examines the relationship between the experience of hospice nurses in observing terminal dehydration and their perception of this state. The scores for the degree of positive perception of dehydration are compared for the experienced and nonexperienced groups of nurses. This study suggests that those hospice nurses who have observed terminal dehydration have a more positive perception of this state than those who have not.
828
<h4><strong>Dehydration isn’t painful, nurses have positive view of it</h4><p>Andrews and Levine 89</p><p>Maria R. Andrews, MS, RD, VA Medical Center in Wilkes Barre, PA; Department of Human Ecology, Levine AM, Alan M. Levine, PhD, RD, Foods and Nutrition Program at the Department of Human Ecology, The American Journal of Hospice Care [1989, 6(1):31-34], “Dehydration in the terminal patient: perception of hospice nurses”, http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/2713109 //jchen</p><p>Recent discussion about the care of the terminally ill patient has focused on the appropriateness of withholding and withdrawing food and fluid and on the discomfort of the dehydrated state. Evidence is mounting that suggests that dehydration in this group of people is not painful,</strong> but rather may be more comfortable than hydration by means of IV fluids or enteral and parenteral feedings. This study examines the relationship between the experience of hospice nurses in observing terminal dehydration and their perception of this state. <strong>The scores for the degree of positive perception of dehydration are compared for the experienced and nonexperienced groups of nurses</strong>. <strong>This study suggests that those hospice nurses who have observed terminal dehydration have a more positive perception of this state than those who have not.</p></strong>
null
null
Case
430,644
2
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,315
It's unkown whether incentives will increase donations
Gill 14
Gill 14 John S. Gill, MD, MS, University of British Columbia et al (6 others) Am J Kidney Dis. 2014;63(1):133-140 Financial Incentives to Increase Canadian Organ Donation:Quick Fix or Fallacy?
Pragmatic Considerations It is unknown whether financial incentives will increase the number of organs available for transplantation The extent of crowding out also is unknown. For example, it is unknown whether the introduction of financial incentives for one type of donation (ie, living donation) also would compromise existing unpaid deceased donations.
It is unknown whether financial incentives will increase the number of organs available for transplantation The extent of crowding out also is unknown. For example, it is unknown whether the introduction of financial incentives for one type of donation (ie, living donation) also would compromise existing unpaid deceased donations.
http://www.ajkd.org/article/S0272-6386%2813%2901226-2/abstract link to pdf Pragmatic Considerations It is unknown whether financial incentives will increase the number of organs available for transplantation in Canada. According to the crowding out motivation theory, payment for organs could compromise intrinsic motivation and decrease existing organ donations for which no payment currently is provided.18 The proposed standards for a regulated system of financial incentives excludes payment for directed donations to guard against the risk of corruption, increasing the likelihood that adoption of financial incentives could crowd out existing unpaid donations.2 The extent of crowding out also is unknown. For example, it is unknown whether the introduction of financial incentives for one type of donation (ie, living donation) also would compromise existing unpaid deceased donations.
892
<h4>It's unkown whether incentives will increase donations </h4><p><strong>Gill 14</strong> John S. Gill, MD, MS, University of British Columbia et al (6 others) Am J Kidney Dis. 2014;63(1):133-140 Financial Incentives to Increase Canadian Organ Donation:Quick Fix or Fallacy?</p><p>http://www.ajkd.org/article/S0272-6386%2813%2901226-2/abstract link to pdf</p><p><u>Pragmatic Considerations</p><p><mark>It is unknown whether financial incentives will increase the number of organs available for transplantation</mark> </u>in Canada. According to the crowding out motivation theory, payment for organs could compromise intrinsic motivation and decrease existing organ donations for which no payment currently is provided.18 The proposed standards for a regulated system of financial incentives excludes payment for directed donations to guard against the risk of corruption, increasing the likelihood that adoption of financial incentives could crowd out existing unpaid donations.2 <u><mark>The extent of crowding out also is unknown. For example, it is unknown whether the introduction of financial incentives for one type of donation (ie, living donation) also would compromise existing unpaid deceased donations.</p></u></mark>
2AC
Counterplan
Theirs
430,649
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,316
We solve the aff – revolution doesn’t hinge on legal praxis but on unveiling the unquestioned assumptions behind it
Kelly 2009
Kelly 2009 (Lecturer in Philosophy at Middlesex University Mark The Political Philosophy of Michel Foucault )
I don't think that criticism can be set against transformation, "ideal" criticism against "real" transformation A critique does not consist in saying that things aren't good the way they are. It consists in seeing on what type of assumptions, of familiar notions, of established, unexamined ways of thinking accepted practices are based Foucault's approach here answers two possible errors one to think that practice occurs without significant influence from theory the other to impose our theory without heeding the practical realities practice without strategic analysis is no good Foucault radically traverses the theory/practice dichotomy moreover by conceiving of thought as itself a form of practice, albeit a highly specific one which relates to other practices in specific ways Thought is not discourse, not a violence we do to things per se It's rather in the order of a preparation for such a violence, a step further away from things than language s relation is in a sense the opposite of that of language, in that where language is an irruptive intervention into the world, thought is a kind of withdrawal from it Foucault articulates an account of how epistemic change occurs, in which, between the codes which establish how a given culture divides up the world and the highest level philosophies which sanctify the bases of the culture is the domain in which culture deviates from the codes to the extent that its fundamental principles are called into question
I don't think that criticism can be set against transformation, "ideal" criticism against "real" transformation critique does not consist in saying that things aren't good the way they are. It consists in seeing on what type of assumptions of established, unexamined ways of thinking accepted practices are based Foucault radically traverses the theory/practice dichotomy moreover by conceiving of thought as itself a form of practice Foucault articulates an account of how epistemic change occurs, in which, is the domain in which culture deviates from the codes to the extent that its fundamental principles are called into question
Regarding the role of critique apropos of political practice, reflecting on the efficacy of his work in the light of the victory of the Left in the 1981 French national elections, Foucault said: I don't think that criticism can be set against transformation, "ideal" criticism against "real" transformation. A critique does not consist in saying that things aren't good the way they are. It consists in seeing on what type of assumptions, of familiar notions, of established, unexamined ways of thinking accepted practices are based. We need to free ourselves of the sacralization of the social and stop regarding that essential element in human life and social relations—I mean thought—as so much wind. (EW3 456) Foucault's approach here answers two possible errors: one to think that practice occurs without significant influence from theory (call this spontaneism), the other to impose our theory without heeding the practical realities. Deleuze refers to both these meta-theoretical errors in passing in conversation with Foucault in 1972, when he says that previous models were either of theory having to be created by practice or that theory was what had to be put into practice (FL 74; DEI 1175). Foucault avoids the first error by insisting on the necessity of critique, that practice without strategic analysis is no good, and the second by refusing to prescribe what should be done. Foucault radically traverses the theory/practice dichotomy moreover by conceiving of thought as itself a form of practice, albeit a highly specific one which relates to other practices in specific ways. Utopias, plans, critique, all involve thought, but in different modalities with different relations to other practices. Here we see Foucault's materialism of the incorporeal at work, seeing thought itself as material qua practice (OT 328). Thought is not discourse, not a violence we do to things per se (see Chapter 1). It's rather in the order of a preparation for such a violence, a step further away from things than language. Like language, it still has a fundamental connection to non-linguistic reality, but its relation is in a sense the opposite of that of language, in that where language is an irruptive intervention into the world, thought is a kind of withdrawal from it: Thought is not what inhabits a certain conduct and gives it its meaning; rather, it is what allows one to step back from this way of acting or reacting, to present it to oneself as an object of thought, and question it as to its meaning, its conditions, and its goals. Thought is freedom in relation to what one does, the motion by which one detaches oneself from it, establishes it as an object, and reflects on it as a problem. (EW1 117)" How is it possible to step back from things and reconsider them? On what basis can we proceed? We have already had Foucault's answer in our examination in Chapter 1 of Foucault's notion of a pure experience of things to be ordered as the basis for discursive mutation. As we saw there, albeit from a different angle, in the preface to The Order of Things, Foucault articulates an account of how epistemic change occurs, in which, between the codes which establish how a given culture divides up the world and the highest level philosophies which sanctify the bases of the culture, is the domain in which culture deviates from the codes to the extent that its fundamental principles are called into question. At that point, as we have seen, this culture then finds itself faced with the stark fact that there exists, below the level of its spontaneous orders, things that are in themselves capable of being ordered, that belong to a certain unspoken order; the fact, in short, that order exists. As though emancipating itself to some extent from its linguistic, perceptual, and practical grids, the culture superimposed on them another kind of grid which neutralized them, which by this superimposition both revealed and excluded them at the same time, so that the culture, by this very process, came face to face with order in its primary state. It is on the basis of this newly perceived order that the codes of language, perception, and practice are criticized and rendered partially invalid. It is on the basis of this order, taken as a firm foundation, that general theories as to the ordering of things, and the interpretation that such an ordering involves, will be constructed. Thus, between the already "encoded" eye and reflexive knowledge there is a middle region which liberates order itself. . . . This middle region, then, in so far as it makes manifest the modes of being of order, can be posited as the most fundamental of all: anterior to words, perceptions, and gestures, which are then taken to be more or less exact, more or less happy, expressions of it (which is why this experience of order in its pure primary state always plays a critical role); more solid, more archaic, less dubious, always more 'true' than the theories that attempt to give those expressions explicit form, exhaustive application, or philosophical foundation. Thus, in every culture, between the use of what one might call the ordering codes and reflections upon order itself, there is the pure experience of order and of its modes of being. (OT xx-xxi)
5,269
<h4>We solve the aff – revolution doesn’t hinge on legal praxis but on unveiling the unquestioned assumptions behind it</h4><p><strong>Kelly 2009</strong> (Lecturer in Philosophy at Middlesex University Mark The Political Philosophy of Michel Foucault )</p><p>Regarding the role of critique apropos of political practice, reflecting on the efficacy of his work in the light of the victory of the Left in the 1981 French national elections, Foucault said:</p><p><u><mark>I don't think that criticism can be set against transformation, "ideal" criticism against "real" transformation</u></mark>.</p><p><u>A <mark>critique does not consist in saying that things aren't good the way they are. It consists in seeing on what type of assumptions</mark>, of familiar notions, <mark>of established, unexamined ways of thinking accepted practices are based</u></mark>.</p><p>We need to free ourselves of the sacralization of the social and stop regarding that essential element in human life and social relations—I mean thought—as so much wind. (EW3 456)</p><p><u>Foucault's approach here answers two possible errors</u>: <u>one to think that practice occurs without significant influence from theory</u> (call this spontaneism), <u>the other to impose our theory without heeding the practical realities</u>. Deleuze refers to both these meta-theoretical errors in passing in conversation with Foucault in 1972, when he says that previous models were either of theory having to be created by practice or that theory was what had to be put into practice (FL 74; DEI 1175). Foucault avoids the first error by insisting on the necessity of critique, that <u>practice without strategic analysis is no good</u>, and the second by refusing to prescribe what should be done.</p><p><u><mark>Foucault radically traverses the theory/practice dichotomy moreover by conceiving of thought as itself a form of practice</mark>, albeit a highly specific one which relates to other practices in specific ways</u>. Utopias, plans, critique, all involve thought, but in different modalities with different relations to other practices.</p><p>Here we see Foucault's materialism of the incorporeal at work, seeing thought itself as material qua practice (OT 328). <u>Thought is not discourse, not a violence we do to things per se</u> (see Chapter 1). <u>It's rather in the order of a preparation for such a violence, a step further away from things than language</u>. Like language, it still has a fundamental connection to non-linguistic reality, but it<u>s relation is in a sense the opposite of that of language, in that where language is an irruptive intervention into the world, thought is a kind of withdrawal from it</u>:</p><p>Thought is not what inhabits a certain conduct and gives it its meaning; rather, it is what allows one to step back from this way of acting or reacting, to present it to oneself as an object of thought, and question it as to its meaning, its conditions, and its goals. Thought is freedom in relation to what one does, the motion by which one detaches oneself from it, establishes it as an object, and reflects on it as a problem. (EW1 117)"</p><p>How is it possible to step back from things and reconsider them? On what basis can we proceed? We have already had Foucault's answer in our examination in Chapter 1 of Foucault's notion of a pure experience of things to be ordered as the basis for discursive mutation. As we saw there, albeit from a different angle, in the preface to The Order of Things, <u><mark>Foucault articulates an account of how epistemic change occurs, in which,</mark> between the codes which establish how a given culture divides up the world and the highest level philosophies which sanctify the bases of the culture</u>, <u><mark>is the domain in which culture deviates from the codes to the extent that its fundamental principles are called into question</u></mark>. At that point, as we have seen,</p><p>this culture then finds itself faced with the stark fact that there exists, below the level of its spontaneous orders, things that are in themselves capable of being ordered, that belong to a certain unspoken order; the fact, in short, that order exists. As though emancipating itself to some extent from its linguistic, perceptual, and practical grids, the culture superimposed on them another kind of grid which neutralized them, which by this superimposition both revealed and excluded them at the same time, so that the culture, by this very process, came face to face with order in its primary state. It is on the basis of this newly perceived order that the codes of language, perception, and practice are criticized and rendered partially invalid. It is on the basis of this order, taken as a firm foundation, that general theories as to the ordering of things, and the interpretation that such an ordering involves, will be constructed. Thus, between the already "encoded" eye and reflexive knowledge there is a middle region which liberates order itself. . . . This middle region, then, in so far as it makes manifest the modes of being of order, can be posited as the most fundamental of all: anterior to words, perceptions, and gestures, which are then taken to be more or less exact, more or less happy, expressions of it (which is why this experience of order in its pure primary state always plays a critical role); more solid, more archaic, less dubious, always more 'true' than the theories that attempt to give those expressions explicit form, exhaustive application, or philosophical foundation. Thus, in every culture, between the use of what one might call the ordering codes and reflections upon order itself, there is the pure experience of order and of its modes of being. (OT xx-xxi)</p>
null
Case
2NC K
430,650
2
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,317
Individual sectors won’t cause recession
Rocky Mountain News 98
Rocky Mountain News 98 Rocky Mountain News 9/29/98, lexis
For a recession growth has to decline steadily for at least six months; the entire economy, not just individual sectors, has to be affected; and the decline has to be steep, not just changes of a few percentage points
For a recession growth has to decline steadily for at least six months; the economy, , has to be affected; and the decline has to be steep, not just a few percentage points
Those same economists think there's nothing to keep the economy from continuing on its roll, at least in the near future. For a recession to take place, according to its economic definition, growth has to decline steadily for at least six months; the entire economy, not just individual sectors, has to be affected; and the decline has to be steep, not just changes of a few percentage points.
393
<h4><u><strong>Individual sectors won’t cause recession</h4><p>Rocky Mountain News 98</p><p></u></strong>Rocky Mountain News 9/29/98, lexis</p><p>Those same economists think there's nothing to keep the economy from continuing on its roll, at least in the near future. <u><mark>For a recession</u></mark> to take place, according to its economic definition, <u><mark>growth has to decline steadily for at least six months; <strong>the </mark>entire<mark> economy, </mark>not just individual sectors</strong><mark>, has to be affected; and the decline has to be steep, not just</mark> changes of <mark>a few percentage points</u></mark>.</p>
WTO
Banks
AT: Inevitable
430,599
2
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,318
This plan creates the best possible conditions for sex workers
Leigh ’12
Leigh ’12, Carol Leigh, director of the Bay Area Sex Workers Advocacy Network, “Labor Laws, Not Criminal Laws, Are the Solution to Prostitution” http://www.nytimes.com/roomfordebate/2012/04/19/is-legalized-prostitution-safer/labor-laws-not-criminal-laws-are-the-solution-to-prostitution
The recent Canadian court decision helps establish social justice for sex workers in Canada. The court ruled against laws that put prostitutes at risk by preventing them from working indoors, screening clients or hiring bodyguards The United States should follow Canada's lead. Now, when a sex worker is raped, she or he is unlikely to go to the police, fearing arrest. Exploitation and danger are exacerbated when sex work is criminalized. Studies consistently show a reduction in violence when sex work is legal decriminalization is only a starting place In New Zealand, commercial sex is regulated not by criminal law, but by civil codes, business regulations and the range of fair labor protections. Prostitution prohibition campaigns often associate legal prostitution with increased trafficking. But academics, journalists and activists have debunked these claims as inaccurate the “Swedish model expose them to greater danger as they drive sex workers underground let us reject antique moralism that protected women from sex itself and used public order laws to control the poor
recent Canadian court decision helps establish social justice for sex workers The court ruled against laws preventing them from working indoors, screening clients or hiring bodyguards The U S should follow Canada's lead Now, when a sex worker is raped, she or he is unlikely to go to the police, fearing arrest Exploitation and danger are exacerbated Studies consistently show a reduction in violence when sex work is legal decriminalization is only a starting place In New Zealand commercial sex is regulated by civil codes, business regulations and labor protections prohibition campaigns often associate legal prostitution with trafficking But academics, journalists and activists have debunked these claims the “Swedish model expose them to greater danger as they drive sex workers underground
The recent Canadian court decision helps establish social justice for sex workers in Canada. The court ruled against laws that put prostitutes at risk by preventing them from working indoors, screening clients or hiring bodyguards. The decision also clarifies pimping laws so sex workers can enter business relationships, rent apartments, etc. An upcoming Canadian case challenges communication laws that endanger street workers. The United States should follow Canada's lead. Now, when a sex worker is raped, she or he is unlikely to go to the police, fearing arrest. Rapists are well aware of that vulnerability, even claiming to target sex workers because they know we have no recourse. Exploitation and danger are exacerbated when sex work is criminalized. Studies consistently show a reduction in violence when sex work is legal. Of course, decriminalization is not the answer to all the problems. It’s only a starting place, so that sex workers can begin to protect themselves, organize and advocate. In New Zealand, commercial sex is regulated not by criminal law, but by civil codes, business regulations and the range of fair labor protections. Prostitution prohibition campaigns often associate legal prostitution with increased trafficking. But academics, journalists and activists have debunked these claims as manipulative, inaccurate and unscientific. Contemporary prohibitionists prescribe the “Swedish model,” which criminalizes clients of sex workers. Although such laws are promoted as a solution to violence against prostitutes in Sweden, well-documented and independent studies have shown that these laws expose them to greater danger as they drive sex workers underground. Contrary to popular stereotypes, sex workers are valuable members of our communities who contribute a great deal to their families, and to the economy of their countries. Accepting this would create a practical and fair approach to sex worker safety, and let us reject antique moralism that protected women from sex itself and used public order laws to control the poor.
2,064
<h4>This plan creates the best possible conditions for sex workers</h4><p><strong>Leigh ’12</strong>, Carol Leigh, director of the Bay Area Sex Workers Advocacy Network, “Labor Laws, Not Criminal Laws, Are the Solution to Prostitution” http://www.nytimes.com/roomfordebate/2012/04/19/is-legalized-prostitution-safer/labor-laws-not-criminal-laws-are-the-solution-to-prostitution</p><p><u>The <mark>recent Canadian court decision helps establish social justice for sex workers</mark> in Canada. <mark>The court ruled against laws </mark>that put prostitutes at risk by <mark>preventing them from working indoors, screening clients or hiring bodyguards</u></mark>. The decision also clarifies pimping laws so sex workers can enter business relationships, rent apartments, etc. An upcoming Canadian case challenges communication laws that endanger street workers. <u><mark>The U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>should follow Canada's lead</mark>. <mark>Now, when a sex worker is raped, she or he is unlikely to go to the police, fearing arrest</mark>.</u> Rapists are well aware of that vulnerability, even claiming to target sex workers because they know we have no recourse. <u><mark>Exploitation and danger are exacerbated</mark> when sex work is criminalized. <mark>Studies consistently show a reduction in violence when sex work is legal</u></mark>. Of course, <u><mark>decriminalization</u></mark> <u><mark>is</u></mark> not the answer to all the problems. It’s <u><mark>only a starting place</u></mark>, so that sex workers can begin to protect themselves, organize and advocate. <u><mark>In New Zealand</mark>, <mark>commercial sex is regulated</mark> not by criminal law, but <mark>by civil codes, business regulations and</mark> the range of fair <mark>labor protections</mark>.</u> <u>Prostitution <mark>prohibition campaigns often associate legal prostitution with</mark> increased <mark>trafficking</mark>. <mark>But academics, journalists and activists have debunked these claims</mark> as</u> manipulative, <u>inaccurate</u> and unscientific. Contemporary prohibitionists prescribe <u><mark>the “Swedish model</u></mark>,” which criminalizes clients of sex workers. Although such laws are promoted as a solution to violence against prostitutes in Sweden, well-documented and independent studies have shown that these laws <u><mark>expose them to greater danger as they drive sex workers underground</u></mark>. Contrary to popular stereotypes, sex workers are valuable members of our communities who contribute a great deal to their families, and to the economy of their countries. Accepting this would create a practical and fair approach to sex worker safety, and <u>let us reject antique moralism that protected women from sex itself and used public order laws to control the poor</u>.</p>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,651
6
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,319
The WTO is dead already – aff can’t solve
Donnan 8/1
Donnan 8/1, Shawn, Financial Times' World Trade Editor, “WTO plunged into crisis as doubts grow over its future,” August 1st, http://www.ft.com/intl/cms/s/0/bac249d0-198c-11e4-9745-00144feabdc0.html
Azevêdo the new head of the W T O announced The WTO is back Azevêdo was speaking too soon. the WTO has been plunged into an existential crisis, after India blocked the centrepiece of the Bali deal Azevêdo is now facing doubts about the future of his organisation There are bound to be efforts to revive negotiations However, the Bali agreement already amounted to a rescue operation and its failure bodes badly for the system. There is significant dysfunction India carried out a threat this week to block a procedural measure to the trade facilitation agreement The Doha round was launched in 2001 and has since repeatedly broken down Putting it back on track would mean tackling much knottier issues such as agricultural subsidies in a new climate of distrust Several members have threatened to enact the trade facilitation agreement as a “plurilateral” deal outside the WTO, a move that would further marginalise the Geneva-based organisation its future looks bleak if the Doha negotiations go back into the coma that has been their dominant state in recent years there are going to be more and more disputes that cannot be resolved [at the WTO
the WTO has been plunged into an existential crisis after India blocked the Bali deal the Bali amounted to a rescue operation its failure bodes badly for the system There is significant dysfunction Doha has repeatedly broken down Putting it back would mean tackling knottier issues such as ag subsidies in a climate of distrust its future looks bleak more and more disputes cannot be resolved [at the WTO
Roberto Azevêdo, the new head of the World Trade Organisation, struck a triumphal tone in Bali last December when he announced that the body’s 159 members had reached the first global agreement in its 18-year history. “The WTO is back!” the visibly sleep-deprived Brazilian told delegates, drawing cheers from all around. Mr Azevêdo, it turns out, was speaking too soon. Seven months later, the WTO has been plunged into an existential crisis, after India’s new government this week blocked the centrepiece of the Bali deal: a seemingly benign arrangement to reduce customs red tape around the world. As a result, Mr Azevêdo is now facing doubts about both the future of his organisation and, more broadly, the liberal vision of a multilateral trading system that has guided the postwar era in the global economy. The WTO, which took over in 1995 from the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade, has grown out of the agreements struck at Bretton Woods in the US in 1944, which sought to keep world leaders from repeating the protectionist mistakes of the 1930s. There are bound to be efforts to revive negotiations. The government in New Delhi has already sought to play down the implications of its stand. Announcing the failure to reach a compromise to members on Thursday, Mr Azevedo urged them to use the August break to ponder the future and return in September with ideas. However, the Bali agreement already amounted to a rescue operation and its failure bodes badly for the system. “There is an element of significant dysfunction that you can’t hide,” said one senior official on Friday. India had originally given its blessing to the deal. But that was before a new government, led by Narendra Modi, came to power two months ago. New Delhi has in recent weeks insisted it wants to renegotiate deadlines set in Bali in order to bring forward negotiations to update the WTO rules that apply to subsidies it gives to farmers as part of a massive government programme to provide cheap food to poor people. In an effort to get what it wanted, India carried out a threat this week to block a procedural measure to the trade facilitation agreement from making the July 31 deadline set in Bali for its implementation. The failure to meet the deadline means the WTO’s members are even less likely to meet another in December to come up with a plan to deliver the rest of the Doha round of negotiations for a global trade deal. The Doha round was launched in 2001 and has since repeatedly broken down as a result of the failure of rich countries, such as the US, and emerging economies, like China and India, to narrow their differences. Putting it back on track would mean tackling much knottier issues such as agricultural subsidies in a new climate of distrust, say diplomats. The irony is that India and other developing countries are likely to suffer most from any collapse of the Doha round, say trade analysts. The US, EU and other key players such as Japan all have big regional trade initiatives under way, and are likely to find moving on much easier than India or smaller and more vulnerable states. Several members have threatened to enact the trade facilitation agreement as a “plurilateral” deal outside the WTO, a move that would further marginalise the Geneva-based organisation. The text to do so has already been drafted and translated into three languages. Up to 60 countries have indicated they are keen to see it implemented. But that is a narrower issue than what happens next at the WTO. Negotiations such as those now under way between the EU and US or between the US and 11 other countries to create a Trans-Pacific Partnership are increasingly focused on more complex, non-tariff barriers to trade. In Brussels and Washington, negotiators are also starting to tackle how to guarantee the free flow of data across borders or ease the way for the global supply chains so vital to modern business. These are discussions that are years beyond what is on the agenda at the WTO. The WTO will not come crashing down tomorrow, says Kimberly Elliott, a trade analyst at the Center for Global Development think-tank in Washington. But its future looks bleak if the Doha negotiations go back into the coma that has been their dominant state in recent years. While many celebrate the WTO’s place as a venue for settling disputes, that function will be eroded if it is not updating its rules to reflect new issues. Without any progress in negotiations, “there are going to be more and more disputes that cannot be resolved [at the WTO],” said Ms Elliott.
4,566
<h4>The WTO is dead already – aff can’t solve</h4><p><strong>Donnan 8/1</strong>, Shawn, Financial Times' World Trade Editor, “WTO plunged into crisis as doubts grow over its future,” August 1st, http://www.ft.com/intl/cms/s/0/bac249d0-198c-11e4-9745-00144feabdc0.html</p><p>Roberto <u>Azevêdo</u>, <u>the new head of the W</u>orld <u>T</u>rade <u>O</u>rganisation, struck a triumphal tone in Bali last December when he <u>announced</u> that the body’s 159 members had reached the first global agreement in its 18-year history. “<u>The WTO is back</u>!” the visibly sleep-deprived Brazilian told delegates, drawing cheers from all around. Mr <u>Azevêdo</u>, it turns out, <u>was speaking too soon.</u> Seven months later, <u><strong><mark>the</mark> <mark>WTO has been plunged into an existential crisis</strong></mark>, <mark>after India</u></mark>’s new government this week <u><mark>blocked the</mark> centrepiece of the <mark>Bali deal</u></mark>: a seemingly benign arrangement to reduce customs red tape around the world. As a result, Mr <u>Azevêdo is now facing doubts about</u> both <u>the future of his organisation</u> and, more broadly, the liberal vision of a multilateral trading system that has guided the postwar era in the global economy. The WTO, which took over in 1995 from the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade, has grown out of the agreements struck at Bretton Woods in the US in 1944, which sought to keep world leaders from repeating the protectionist mistakes of the 1930s. <u>There are bound to be efforts to revive negotiations</u>. The government in New Delhi has already sought to play down the implications of its stand. Announcing the failure to reach a compromise to members on Thursday, Mr Azevedo urged them to use the August break to ponder the future and return in September with ideas. <u>However, <mark>the Bali</mark> agreement already <mark>amounted to a rescue operation</mark> and <mark>its</mark> <mark>failure bodes badly for the system</mark>. </u><strong>“<u></strong><mark>There is</u></mark> an element of <u><strong><mark>significant dysfunction</u></strong></mark> that you can’t hide,” said one senior official on Friday. India had originally given its blessing to the deal. But that was before a new government, led by Narendra Modi, came to power two months ago. New Delhi has in recent weeks insisted it wants to renegotiate deadlines set in Bali in order to bring forward negotiations to update the WTO rules that apply to subsidies it gives to farmers as part of a massive government programme to provide cheap food to poor people. In an effort to get what it wanted, <u>India carried out a threat this week to block a procedural measure to the trade facilitation agreement</u> from making the July 31 deadline set in Bali for its implementation. The failure to meet the deadline means the WTO’s members are even less likely to meet another in December to come up with a plan to deliver the rest of the Doha round of negotiations for a global trade deal. <u>The <mark>Doha</mark> round was launched in 2001 and <mark>has</mark> since <mark>repeatedly broken down</u></mark> as a result of the failure of rich countries, such as the US, and emerging economies, like China and India, to narrow their differences. <u><mark>Putting it back</mark> on track <mark>would mean tackling</mark> much <mark>knottier issues such as ag</mark>ricultural <mark>subsidies</mark> <mark>in a</mark> new <mark>climate of distrust</u><strong></mark>,</strong> say diplomats. The irony is that India and other developing countries are likely to suffer most from any collapse of the Doha round, say trade analysts. The US, EU and other key players such as Japan all have big regional trade initiatives under way, and are likely to find moving on much easier than India or smaller and more vulnerable states. <u>Several members have threatened to enact the trade facilitation agreement as a “plurilateral” deal outside the WTO, a move that would further marginalise the Geneva-based organisation</u>. The text to do so has already been drafted and translated into three languages. Up to 60 countries have indicated they are keen to see it implemented. But that is a narrower issue than what happens next at the WTO. Negotiations such as those now under way between the EU and US or between the US and 11 other countries to create a Trans-Pacific Partnership are increasingly focused on more complex, non-tariff barriers to trade. In Brussels and Washington, negotiators are also starting to tackle how to guarantee the free flow of data across borders or ease the way for the global supply chains so vital to modern business. These are discussions that are years beyond what is on the agenda at the WTO. The WTO will not come crashing down tomorrow, says Kimberly Elliott, a trade analyst at the Center for Global Development think-tank in Washington. But <u><strong><mark>its future looks bleak</strong></mark> if the Doha negotiations go back into the coma that has been their dominant state in recent years</u>. While many celebrate the WTO’s place as a venue for settling disputes, that function will be eroded if it is not updating its rules to reflect new issues. Without any progress in negotiations, “<u>there are going to be <mark>more and more disputes</mark> that <mark>cannot</mark> <mark>be resolved [at the WTO</u></mark>],” said Ms Elliott.</p>
null
null
1NC
430,392
9
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,320
Countries will stay within the treaty regime now despite push for change
Bewley-Taylor et al 2014
Bewley-Taylor et al 2014 (Dave Bewley-Taylor, Tom Blickman and Martin Jelsma, Professor of International Relations and Public Policy at Swansea University and founding Director of the Global Drug Policy Observatory, The Rise and Decline of Cannabis Prohibition, http://www.tni.org/sites/www.tni.org/files/download/rise_and_decline_intro.pdf)
All these policy practices were interpreted by the implementing countries as respecting the confines of treaty latitude. Most have a solid legal basis, others employ a certain legal creativity The strictures of the conventions and the near impossibility to amend them have impelled some countries to stretching their inbuilt flexibility and escape clauses while a fundamental change in cannabis policy is increasingly viewed as a legitimate option to consider in various parts of the world reputational costs of treaty breach are likely to deter most states from moving beyond soft defection
The strictures of the conventions and the near impossibility to amend them have impelled some countries to stretching their inbuilt flexibility and escape clauses while a fundamental change in cannabis policy is increasingly viewed as a legitimate option reputational costs of treaty breach are likely to deter most states from moving beyond soft defection
All these policy practices were interpreted by the implementing countries as respecting the confines of treaty latitude. Most have a solid legal basis, others employ a certain legal creativity, not always acknowledged by the INCB. And sometimes schemes perfectly justifiable in principle have been applied with a “pragmatic” dose of hypocrisy. The strictures of the conventions and the near impossibility to amend them have impelled some countries to stretching their inbuilt flexibility and escape clauses to questionable limits. Examples are the legal contradictions around the backdoor of the Dutch coffeeshops; the expansion of medical marijuana schemes in some U.S. states into recreational use; and the establishment of large-scale commercial cannabis social clubs in Spain. Indeed, while a fundamental change in cannabis policy is increasingly viewed as a legitimate option to consider in various parts of the world, the reputational (and possibly economic) costs of treaty breach are likely to deter most states from moving beyond some form of soft defection.
1,067
<h4>Countries will stay within the treaty regime now despite push for change</h4><p><strong>Bewley-Taylor et al 2014</strong> (Dave Bewley-Taylor, Tom Blickman and Martin Jelsma, Professor of International Relations and Public Policy at Swansea University and founding Director of the Global Drug Policy Observatory, The Rise and Decline of Cannabis Prohibition, http://www.tni.org/sites/www.tni.org/files/download/rise_and_decline_intro.pdf)</p><p><u>All these policy practices were interpreted by the implementing countries as respecting the confines of treaty latitude. Most have a solid legal basis, others employ a certain legal creativity</u>, not always acknowledged by the INCB. And sometimes schemes perfectly justifiable in principle have been applied with a “pragmatic” dose of hypocrisy. <u><mark>The</mark> <mark>strictures of the conventions and the near impossibility to amend them have impelled some countries to stretching their inbuilt flexibility and escape clauses</u></mark> to questionable limits. Examples are the legal contradictions around the backdoor of the Dutch coffeeshops; the expansion of medical marijuana schemes in some U.S. states into recreational use; and the establishment of large-scale commercial cannabis social clubs in Spain. Indeed, <u><mark>while a fundamental change in cannabis policy is increasingly viewed as a legitimate option</mark> to consider in various parts of the world</u>, the <u><strong><mark>reputational</u></strong></mark> (and possibly economic) <u><strong><mark>costs of treaty breach are likely to deter most states from moving beyond</u></strong></mark> some form of <u><strong><mark>soft defection</u></strong></mark>.</p>
null
null
Off
430,419
39
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,321
Infectious disease risks extinction Franca et al. 13 (R. Franca, Department of Pharmacology, School of Medicine of Ribeirao Preto, University of Sao Paulo, Brazil, C. C. de Silva, Department of General Biology, Federal University of Vicosa, Brazil, S.O. De Paula, Laboratory of Molecular Immunovirology, Federal University of Vicosa, Brazil, “Recent Advances in Molecular Medicine Techniques for the Diagnosis, Prevention, and Control of Infectious Diseases,” Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg, submitted November 26, 2012, published January 22, 2013, pg. 1)In recent years we have observed great advances in our ability to combat infectious diseases. Through the development of novel genetic methodologies, including a better understanding of pathogen biology, pathogenic mechanisms, advances in vaccine development, designing new therapeutic drugs, and optimization of diagnostic tools, significant infectious diseases are now better controlled. Here, we briefly describe recent reports in the literature concentrating on infectious disease control. The focus of this review is to describe the molecular methods widely used in the diagnosis, prevention, and control of infectious diseases with regard to the innovation of molecular techniques. Since the list of pathogenic microorganisms is extensive, we emphasize some of the major human infectious diseases (AIDS, tuberculosis, malaria, rotavirus, herpes virus, viral hepatitis, and dengue fever). As a consequence of these developments, infectious diseases will be more accurately and effectively treated; safe and effective vaccines are being developed and rapid detection of infectious agents now permits countermeasures to avoid potential outbreaks and epidemics. But, despite considerable progress, infectious diseases remain a strong challenge to human survival. Introduction Despite the great advances in medicine, particularly in new therapeutic drugs, diagnostic tools, and even ways to pre- vent diseases, the human species still faces serious health problems. Among these problems, those that draw the most attention are infectious diseases, especially in poor regions. An important feature of infectious disease is its potential to arise globally, as exemplified by known devastating past and present pandemics such as the bubonic–pneumonic plague, Spanish flu (1918 influenza pandemic), and the present pandemic of human immunodeficiency virus (HIV), in which an estimated 33.3 million persons were living with the HIV infection worldwide at the end of 2009 [1–3]. In addition, other non-viral diseases are significant public health problems, as exemplified by tuberculosis (TB). This infectious disease accounts for one third of the world’s bacterial infections (TB infected), and in 2010 a total of 8.8 million people worldwide became sick with TB [1, 4]. In recent years, new forms of infectious diseases have become significantly important to medical and scientific communities; these forms are now widely known as emergent and re-emergent infectious diseases. With the appearance of new transmissible diseases, such as SARS, West Nile and H5N1/H1N1 Influenza viruses, in addition to reemerging diseases like dengue fever, the concerns about a global epidemic are not unfounded [5]. Moreover, in the tropical and subtropical regions of the world, parasitic infections are a common cause of death. Since one of the major characteristics of infectious diseases is its inter-individual transmission, advances in personal protection, effective public policy, and immunological procedures are efficient means of controlling the spread of these diseases. Thus, improvement of pre-existing technologies commonly used to monitor, prevent, and treat infectious diseases is of crucial importance not only to the medical community, but also to humankind.
Franca et al. 13 [5]. Moreover, in the tropical and subtropical regions of the world, parasitic infections are a common cause of death. Since one of the major characteristics of infectious diseases is its inter-individual transmission, advances in personal protection, effective public policy, and immunological procedures are efficient means of controlling the spread of these diseases. Thus, improvement of pre-existing technologies commonly used to monitor, prevent, and treat infectious diseases is of crucial importance not only to the medical community, but also to humankind.
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Infectious disease risks extinction </h4><p><strong>Franca et al. 13</strong> (R. Franca, Department of Pharmacology, School of Medicine of Ribeirao Preto, University of Sao Paulo, Brazil, C. C. de Silva, Department of General Biology, Federal University of Vicosa, Brazil, S.O. De Paula, Laboratory of Molecular Immunovirology, Federal University of Vicosa, Brazil, “Recent Advances in Molecular Medicine Techniques for the Diagnosis, Prevention, and Control of Infectious Diseases,” Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg, submitted November 26, 2012, published January 22, 2013, pg. 1)In recent years we have observed great advances in our ability to combat infectious diseases. Through the development of novel genetic methodologies, including a better understanding of pathogen biology, pathogenic mechanisms, advances in vaccine development, designing new therapeutic drugs, and optimization of diagnostic tools, significant infectious diseases are now better controlled. Here, we briefly describe recent reports in the literature concentrating on infectious disease control. The focus of this review is to describe the molecular methods widely used in the diagnosis, prevention, and control of infectious diseases with regard to the innovation of molecular techniques. Since the list of pathogenic microorganisms is extensive, we emphasize some of the major human infectious diseases (AIDS, tuberculosis, malaria, rotavirus, herpes virus, viral hepatitis, and dengue fever). As a consequence of these developments, infectious diseases will be more accurately and effectively treated; safe and effective vaccines are being developed and rapid detection of infectious agents now permits countermeasures to avoid potential outbreaks and epidemics. But, despite considerable progress<u>, <mark>infectious diseases remain a strong challenge to human survival</u>.</mark> Introduction Despite the great advances in medicine, particularly in new therapeutic drugs, diagnostic tools, and even ways to pre- vent diseases, the human species still faces serious health problems. <u>Among these problems, those that draw the most attention are infectious diseases, especially in poor regions. <mark>An important feature of infectious disease is its potential to arise globally, as exemplified by known devastating past and present pandemics such</mark> as the bubonic</u>–pneumonic <u>plague,</u> Spanish flu (1918 influenza pandemic), <u>and the present pandemic of</u> human immunodeficiency virus <u>(<mark>HIV)</mark>,</u> in which an estimated 33.3 million persons were living with the HIV infection worldwide at the end of 2009 [1–3]. In addition, other non-viral diseases are significant public health problems, as exemplified by tuberculosis (TB). This infectious disease accounts for one third of the world’s bacterial infections (TB infected), and in 2010 a total of 8.8 million people worldwide became sick with TB [1, 4]. In recent years, new forms of infectious diseases have become significantly important to medical and scientific communities; these forms are now widely known as emergent and re-emergent infectious diseases. With the appearance of new transmissible diseases, such as SARS, West Nile and H5N1/H1N1 Influenza viruses, <u><mark>in addition to reemerging diseases</mark> like dengue fever, <mark>the concerns about a global epidemic are not unfounded</mark> </u><strong>[5]. Moreover, in the tropical and subtropical regions of the world, parasitic infections are a common cause of death. Since one of the major characteristics of infectious diseases is its inter-individual transmission, advances in personal protection, effective public policy, and immunological procedures are efficient means of controlling the spread of these diseases. Thus, improvement of pre-existing technologies commonly used to monitor, prevent, and treat infectious diseases is of crucial importance not only to the medical community, but also to humankind.</p></strong>
null
null
Contention 2 is the Illegal market
430,652
1
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,322
Demanding the future stops here may seem politically self-destructive; however, this act establishes an anti-politic divorced from the futurity of the Child. Anything else retains the structural position of the queer—denying the negativity of queerness only shifts the figural burden of queerness onto someone else. We do not promise a better future or a brighter tomorrow, but an end to the sacralization of the Child and the ensuing sacrifice of the queer.
Edelman ’04
Edelman ’04, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, p. 35-31
Queerness is never a matter of being or becoming but, embodying the Real internal to the Symbolic jouissance enjoyment a movement beyond pleasure and pain violent passage beyond the bounds of identity, meaning, and law. jouissance dissolves investments, undoing the consistency of a social reality that relies on identifications The death drive manifests itself, in jouissance jouissance tears the fabric of Symbolic reality as we know it, unraveling the solidity of every object, including the object as which the subject necessarily takes itself, jouissance evokes the death drive that always insists as the void in and of the subject, beyond its fantasy of self- realization, beyond the pleasure principle. Bound up with the death drive is the Child enacting of repetition that fixes identity through identification with the future of the social order Bound up is the figure of the queer, embodying that order’s traumatic encounter with its own inescapable failure, its encounter with the illusion of the future as suture to bind the constitutive wound of the subject’s subjection to the signifier queer sexualities, in extricable from the emergence of the subject in the Symbolic, mark the place of the gap in which the Symbolic confronts what its discourse is in capable of knowing, which is also the place of a jouissance the queer may provide the Symbolic with a sort of necessary reassurance by seeming to give a name to what, as Real, remains unnameable. But repudiations of that figural identity, reflecting a liberal faith in the abstract universality of the subject, though better enabling the extension of rights to those who are still denied them, must similarly reassure by attesting to the seamless coherence of the Symbolic whose dominant narrative would thus supersede the corrosive force of queer irony. If the queer’s abjectified difference, that is, secures normativity’s identity, the1 queer’s disavowal of that difference affirms normativity’s singular truth,, For every refusal of the figural status to which queers are distinctively called reproduces the triumph of narrative as the e9onzatwai of irony, as the logic of a temporality that always serves to “straighten” it out, and thus proclaims the universality of reproductive futurism. Such refusals perform, despite themselves, subservience to the law that effectively imposes politics as the only game in town, exacting as the price of admission the subject’s (hetero)normalization, which is accomplished, regardless of sexual practice or sexual “orientation,” through compulsory abjuration of the future-negating queer. It may seem the Symbolic can only win but that would ignore the correlative fact that it also can only lose. For the division on which the subject rests can never be spirited away and the signifying order will always necessitate the production of some figural repository for the excess that precludes its ultimate realization of the One De-idealizing the metaphorics of meaning on which heteroreproduction takes its stand, queerness exposes sexuality’s inevitable coloration by the drive: its insistence on repetition, its stubborn denial of teleology, its resistance to determinations of meaning and its rejection of spiritualization through marriage to reproductive futurism Queerness as name may well reinforce the Symbolic order of naming, but it names what resists, as signifier, absorption into the Imaginary identity of the name Empty, excessive, and irreducible, it designates the letter animating futurity as a name for the death drive that always informs the Symbolic order, it also names the jouissance forbidden by, but permeating, the Symbolic order itself. By denying our identification with the negativity of this drive those of us in habiting the place of the queer may be able to cast off that queerness but only by shifting the figural burden of queerness to someone else The structural position of queerness and the need to fill it remain. By choosing to accept that position we might undertake the impossible project of imagining an oppositional political stance exempt from the imperative to reproduce the politics of signification which can only return us, byway of the Child, to the politics of reproduction Queerness thus comes to mean nothing for both: for the right wing the nothingness always at war with the positivity of civil society; for the left, nothing more than a sexual practice in need of demystification. reason must fail Sexuality refuses demystification as the Symbolic refuses the queer; for sexuality and the Symbolic become what they are by virtue of such refusals. Beyond the resonance of fantasy lies neither law nor reason The sacralization of the Child thus necessitates the sacrifice of the queer. Queers must respond by insisting on our equal right to the social order’s prerogatives by saying explicitly what Law and the Pope and the whole of the Symbolic order for which they stand hear any way in each and every expression or manifestation of queer sexuality: Fuck the social order and the Child fuck Annie ; fuck Laws fuck the whole network of Symbolic relations and the future that serves as its prop. We might like believe that generous contributions to lobbying groups or generous participation in activist groups or generous doses of legal savvy and electoral sophistication, the future will hold a place for us a place at the political table that won’t have to come at the cost of the places we seek in the bed But there are no queers in that future as there can be no future for queers, chosen as they are to bear the bad tidings that there can be no future at all Those queered by the social order that projects its death drive onto them are no doubt positioned to recognize the structuring fantasy that so defines them. But they’re positioned as well to recognize the irreducibility of that fantasy and the cost of construing it as contingent to the logic of social organization as such. Acceding to this figural identification with the undoing of identity which is also toy with the disarticulation of social and Symbolic form, might well be described as “politically self-destructive But politics and the self as mere prosthesis maintaining the future for the figural Child are what queerness, again as figure, necessarily destroys—necessarily insofar as this “self” is the agent of reproductive futurism and this “politics” the means of its promulgation as the order of social reality , political self-destruction inheres in the only act that counts as one: the act of resisting enslavement to the future in the name of having a life. , if the jouissance , intrinsic to queer (non)identity annihilates the jouissance that works to consolidate identity by allowing reality to coagulate around its ritual reproduction then the only oppositional status to which our queerness could ever lead would depend on our taking seriously the place of the death drive ‘we’re led on to figure and insisting, against the cult of the Child and the political order it enforces, that we are “not the signifier of what might become a new form of ‘social organisation,’ we do not intend a new politics a better society a brighter tomorrow since all of these fantasies reproduce the past through displacement, in the form of the future We choose not to choose the Child it delights in that mortality as the negation of everything that would define itself, moralistically, as pro-life. we must bury the subject in the tomb-like hollow of the signifier, pronouncing at last the words for which we’re condemned should we speak them or not the Child as futurity’s emblem must die the future is mere repetition and just as lethal as the past. And so what is queerest about us, queerest within us, and queerest despite us is this willingness to insist intransitively—to insist that the future stop here.
Queerness is a matter of embodying the Real internal to the Symbolic jouissance dissolves the consistency of a social reality that relies on identifications the Child, enacting repetition fixes identity through identification Bound up is the figure of the queer, embodying that order’s traumatic encounter with its own inescapable failure queer sexualities mark the place of the gap in which the Symbolic confronts what its discourse is in capable of knowing the Symbolic can only lose the division on which the subject rests can never be spirited away signifying order will always necessitate the production of some figural repository for the excess that precludes its ultimate realization of the One Queerness it names what resists, as signifier, absorption into the Imaginary identity of the name it also names the jouissance forbidden by, but permeating, the Symbolic order By denying our identification with the negativity of this drive those of us in habiting the place of the queer may be able to cast off that queerness but only by shifting the figural burden of queerness to someone else structural position of queerness and the need to fill it remain. By choosing to accept that position we might undertake the impossible project of imagining an oppositional political stance exempt from the imperative to reproduce the politics of signification which can only return us, to the politics of reproduction reason must fail Sexuality refuses demystification Beyond the resonance of fantasy lies neither law nor reason Queers must respond by saying explicitly what Law and the Symbolic order hear any way in each expression of queer sexuality: Fuck the social order and the Child fuck Laws We might believe that in activist groups or and electoral sophistication, the future will hold a place for us But there are no queers in that future as there can be no future for queers, chosen as they are to bear the bad tidings that there can be no future at all Acceding to this figural identification with the undoing of identity , might be described as “politically self-destructive But politics and the self as mere prosthesis maintaining the future for the Child are what queerness necessarily destroys the only oppositional status to which our queerness could ever lead would depend the place of the death drive against the cult of the Child we do not intend a new politics a better society a brighter tomorrow since all of these fantasies reproduce the past through displacement, in the form of the future We choose not to choose the Child the Child as futurity’s emblem must die the future is mere repetition and just as lethal as the past. And so what is queerest about us to insist that the future stop here
Queerness, therefore, is never a matter of being or becoming but, embodying the remainder of the Real internal to the Symbolic order. One name for this unnameable remainder, as Lacan describes it, is jouissance, sometimes translated as “enjoyment”: a movement beyond the pleasure principle, beyond the distinctions of pleasure and pain, a violent passage beyond the bounds of identity, meaning, and law. This passage, toward which the pulsion of the drives continuously impels us, may have the effect, insofar as it gets attached to a particular object or end, of congealing identity around the fantasy of satisfaction or fulfillment by means of that object At the same time, however, this jouissance dissolves such fetishistic investments, undoing the consistency of a social reality that relies on Imaginary identifications, on the structures of Symbolic law, and on the paternal metaphor of the name.28 Hence, for Lacan there is another name that designates the unnameability to which jouissance would give us access: “Behind what is named, there is the unnameable,” he writes. “It is in fact because it is unnameable, with all the resonances you can give to this name, that it is akin to the quintessential unnameable, that is to say to death.” The death drive, therefore, manifests itself, though in radically different guises, in both versions of jouissance. To the extent that jouissance, as fantasmatic escape from the alienation intrinsic to meaning, lodges itself in a given object on which identity comes to depend, it produces identity as mortification, reenacting the very constraint of meaning it was intended to help us escape. But to the extent that it tears the fabric of Symbolic reality as we know it, unraveling the solidity of every object, including the object as which the subject necessarily takes itself, jouissance evokes the death drive that always insists as the void in and of the subject, beyond its fantasy of self- realization, beyond the pleasure principle. Bound up with the first of these death drives is the figure of the Child, enacting a logic of repetition that fixes identity through identification with the future of the social order. Bound up with the second is the figure of the queer, embodying that order’s traumatic encounter with its own inescapable failure, its encounter with the illusion of the future as suture to bind the constitutive wound of the subject’s subjection to the signifier, which divides it, paradoxically, both from and into itself. In the preface to Homographesis I wrote that the signifier “gay,” understood “as a figure for the textuality, the rhetoricity, of the sexual... designates the gap or incoherence that every discourse of ‘sexuality’ or ‘sexual identity’ would master.” Extending that claim, I now suggest that queer sexualities, in extricable from the emergence of the subject in the Symbolic, mark the place of the gap in which the Symbolic confronts what its discourse is in capable of knowing, which is also the place of a jouissance from which it can never escape. As a figure for what it can neither fully articulate nor acknowledge, the queer may provide the Symbolic with a sort of necessary reassurance by seeming to give a name to what, as Real, remains unnameable. But repudiations of that figural identity, reflecting a liberal faith in the abstract universality of the subject, though better enabling the extension of rights to those who are still denied them, must similarly reassure by attesting to the seamless coherence of the Symbolic whose dominant narrative would thus supersede the corrosive force of queer irony. If the queer’s abjectified difference, that is, secures normativity’s identity, the1 queer’s disavowal of that difference affirms normativity’s singular truth,, For every refusal of the figural status to which queers are distinctively called reproduces the triumph of narrative as the e9onzatwai of irony, as the logic of a temporality that always serves to “straighten” it out, and thus proclaims the universality of reproductive futurism. Such refusals perform, despite themselves, subservience to the law that effectively imposes politics as the only game in town, exacting as the price of admission the subject’s (hetero)normalization, which is accomplished, regardless of sexual practice or sexual “orientation,” through compulsory abjuration of the future-negating queer. It may seem, from within this structure, that the Symbolic can only win; but that would ignore the correlative fact that it also can only lose. For the division on which the subject rests can never be spirited away and the signifying order will always necessitate the production of some figural repository for the excess that precludes its ultimate realization of the One. In apolitical field whose limit and horizon is reproductive futurism, queerness embodies this death drive, this intransigent jouissance, by figuring sexuality’s implication in the senseless pulsions of that drive. De-idealizing the metaphorics of meaning on which heteroreproduction takes its stand, queerness exposes sexuality’s inevitable coloration by the drive: its insistence on repetition, its stubborn denial of teleology, its resistance to determinations of meaning (except insofar as it means this refusal to admit such determinations of meaning), and, above all, its rejection of spiritualization through marriage to reproductive futurism. Queerness as name may well reinforce the Symbolic order of naming, but it names what resists, as signifier, absorption into the Imaginary identity of the name. Empty, excessive, and irreducible, it designates the letter, the formal element, the lifeless machinery responsible for animating the “spirit” of futurity. And as such, as a name for the death drive that always informs the Symbolic order, it also names the jouissance forbidden by, but permeating, the Symbolic order itself. By denying our identification with the negativity of this drive, and hence our disidentification from the promise of futurity, those of us in habiting the place of the queer may be able to cast off that queerness and enter the properly political sphere, but only by shifting the figural burden of queerness to someone else. The structural position of queerness, after all, and the need to fill it remain. By choosing to accept that position, however, by assuming the “truth” of our queer capacity to figure the undoing of the Symbolic, and of the Symbolic subject as well, we might undertake the impossible project of imagining an oppositional political stance exempt from the imperative to reproduce the politics of signification (the politics aimed at closing the gap opened up by the signifier itself), which can only return us, byway of the Child, to the politics of reproduction. For the liberal’s view of society, which seems to accord the queer a place, endorses no more than the conservative right’s the queer ness of resistance to futurism and thus the queerness of the queer. While the right wing imagines the elimination of queers (or of the need to confront their existence), the left would eliminate queerness by shining the cool light of reason upon it, hoping thereby to expose it as merely a mode of sexual expression free of the all-pervasive coloring, the determining fantasy formation, by means of which it can seem to portend, and not for the right alone, the undoing of the social order and its cynosure, the Child. Queerness thus comes to mean nothing for both: for the right wing the nothingness always at war with the positivity of civil society; for the left, nothing more than a sexual practice in need of demystification. But this is where reason must fail. Sexuality refuses demystification as the Symbolic refuses the queer; for sexuality and the Symbolic become what they are by virtue of such refusals. Ironically— but irony, as I’ve argued, always characterizes queer theory—the demystification of queerness and so, by extension, of sexuality itself, the demystification inherent in the position of liberal rationality, could achieve its realization only by traversing the collective fantasy that invests the social order with mean: ing by way of reproductive futurism. Taken at its word, that is, liberalism’s abstract reason, rescuing queerness for sociality, dissolves, like queerness, the very investments on which sociality rests by doing away with its underlying and sustaining libidinal fantasies. Beyond the resonance of fantasy, after all, lies neither law nor reason. In the beyond of demystification, in that neutral, democratic literality that marks the futurism of the left, one could only encounter a queer dismantling of futurism itself as fantasy and a derealization of the order of meaning that futurism reproduces. Intent on the end, not the ends, of the social, queerness insists that the drive toward that end, which liberalism refuses to imagine, can never be excluded from the structuring fantasy of the social order itself. The sacralization of the Child thus necessitates the sacrifice of the queer. Bernard Law, the former cardinal of Boston, mistaking (or maybe understanding too well) the degree of authority bestowed on him by the signifier of his patronymic, denounced in 1996 proposed legislation giving health care benefits to same-sex partners of municipal employees. He did so by proclaiming, in a noteworthy instance of piety in the sky, that bestowing such access to health care would profoundly diminish the marital bond. “Society,” he opined, “has a special interest in the protection, care and upbringing of children. Because marriage remains the principal, and the best, framework for the nurture, education and socialization of children, the state has a special interest in marriage.”31 With this fatal embrace of a futurism so blindly committed to the figure of the Child that it will justify refusing health care benefits to the adults that some children become, Law lent his voice to the mortifying mantra of a communal jouissance that depends on the fetishization of the Child at the expense of whatever such fetishization must inescapably queer. Some seven years later, after Law had resigned for his failure to protect Catholic children from sexual assault by pedophile priests, Pope John Paul II returned to this theme, condemning state-recognized same-sex unions as parodic versions of authentic families, “based on individual egoism” rather than genuine love. Justifying that condemnation, he observed, “Such a ‘caricature’ has no future and cannot give future to any society.”3 Queers must respond to the violent force of such constant provocations not only by insisting on our equal right to the social order’s prerogatives, not only by avowing our capacity to promote that order’s coherence and integrity, but also by saying explicitly what Law and the Pope and the whole of the Symbolic order for which they stand hear any way in each and every expression or manifestation of queer sexuality: Fuck the social order and the Child in whose name we’re collectively terrorized; fuck Annie; fuck the waif from Les Mis; fuck the poor, innocent kid on the Net; fuck Laws both with capital ls and with small; fuck the whole network of Symbolic relations and the future that serves as its prop. We might like believe that with patience, with work, with generous contributions to lobbying groups or generous participation in activist groups or generous doses of legal savvy and electoral sophistication, the future will hold a place for us—a place at the political table that won’t have to come at the cost of the places we seek in the bed or the bar or the baths. But there are no queers in that future as there can be no future for queers, chosen as they are to bear the bad tidings that there can be no future at all; that the future, as Annie’s hymn to the hope of “Tomorrow” understands, is “always/ A day/ Away.” Like the lovers on Keats’s Grecian urn, forever “near the goal” of a union they’ll never in fact achieve, we’re held in thrall by a future continually deferred by time itself, constrained to pursue the dream of a day when today and tomorrow are one. That future is nothing but kid stuff, reborn each day to screen out the grave that gapes from within the lifeless letter, luring us into, ensnaring us in, reality’s gossamer web. Those queered by the social order that projects its death drive onto them are no doubt positioned to recognize the structuring fantasy that so defines them. But they’re positioned as well to recognize the irreducibility of that fantasy and the cost of construing it as contingent to the logic of social organization as such. Acceding to this figural identification with the undoing of identity, which is also toy with the disarticulation of social and Symbolic form, might well be described, in John Brenkman’s words, as “politically self-destructive.” But politics (as the social elaboration of reality) and the self as mere prosthesis maintaining the future for the figural Child), are what queerness, again as figure, necessarily destroys—necessarily insofar as this “self” is the agent of reproductive futurism and this “politics” the means of its promulgation as the order of social reality. But perhaps, as Lacan’s engagement with Antigone in Seminar7 suggests, political self-destruction inheres in the only act that counts as one: the act of resisting enslavement to the future in the name of having a life. If the fate of the queer is to figure the fate that cub the thread of futurity, if the jouissance, the corrosive enjoyment, intrinsic to queer (non)identity annihilates the fetishistic jouissance that works to consolidate identity by allowing reality to coagulate around its ritual reproduction, then the only oppositional status to which our queerness could ever lead would depend on our taking seriously the place of the death drive ‘we’re led on to figure and insisting, against the cult of the Child and the political order it enforces, that we, as Guy Hocquenghem made clear, are “not the signifier of what might become a new form of ‘social organisation,’ that we do not intend a new politics, a better society, a brighter tomorrow, since all of these fantasies reproduce the past through displacement, in the form of the future. We choose, instead, not to choose the Child, as disciplinary image of the Imaginary past or as site of a projective identification with an always impossible future. The queerness we propose, in Hocquenghem’s words, “is unaware of the passing of generations as stages on the road to better living. It knows nothing about ‘sacrifice now for the sake of future generations’ . . . lit) knows that civilisation alone is mortal.” Even more: it delights in that mortality as the negation of everything that would define itself, moralistically, as pro-life. It is we who must bury the subject in the tomb-like hollow of the signifier, pronouncing at last the words for which we’re condemned should we speak them or not: that we are the advocates of abortion; that the Child as futurity’s emblem must die; that the future is mere repetition and just as lethal as the past. Our queerness has nothing to offer a Symbolic that lives by denying that nothingness except an insistence on the haunting excess that this nothingness entails, an insistence on the negativity that pierces the fantasy screen of futurity, shattering narrative temporality with irony’s always explosive force. And so what is queerest about us, queerest within us, and queerest despite us is this willingness to insist intransitively—to insist that the future stop here.
15,605
<h4><strong>Demanding the future stops here may seem politically self-destructive; however, this act establishes an anti-politic divorced from the futurity of the Child. Anything else retains the structural position of the queer—denying the negativity of queerness only shifts the figural burden of queerness onto someone else. We do not promise a better future or a brighter tomorrow, but an end to the sacralization of the Child and the ensuing sacrifice of the queer.</h4><p>Edelman ’04</strong>, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive<u>, p. 35-31</p><p><mark>Queerness</u></mark>, therefore, <u><mark>is </mark>never <mark>a matter of </mark>being or becoming but, <mark>embodying</mark> <mark>the</u></mark> remainder of the <u><mark>Real internal to the Symbolic</u></mark> order. One name for this unnameable remainder, as Lacan describes it, is <u><strong>jouissance</u></strong>, sometimes translated as “<u>enjoyment</u>”: <u>a movement beyond</u> the pleasure principle, beyond the distinctions of <u>pleasure and pain</u>, a <u>violent passage beyond the bounds of identity, meaning, and law.</u> This passage, toward which the pulsion of the drives continuously impels us, may have the effect, insofar as it gets attached to a particular object or end, of congealing identity around the fantasy of satisfaction or fulfillment by means of that object At the same time, however, this <u><mark>jouissance</mark> <mark>dissolves</u></mark> such fetishistic <u>investments, undoing <mark>the consistency of a social reality that relies on</mark> </u>Imaginary<u> <mark>identifications</u></mark>, on the structures of Symbolic law, and on the paternal metaphor of the name.28 Hence, for Lacan there is another name that designates the unnameability to which jouissance would give us access: “Behind what is named, there is the unnameable,” he writes. “It is in fact because it is unnameable, with all the resonances you can give to this name, that it is akin to the quintessential unnameable, that is to say to death.” <u>The death drive</u>, therefore, <u>manifests itself, </u>though in radically different guises,<u> in </u>both versions of<u> jouissance</u>. To the extent that <u>jouissance</u>, as fantasmatic escape from the alienation intrinsic to meaning, lodges itself in a given object on which identity comes to depend, it produces identity as mortification, reenacting the very constraint of meaning it was intended to help us escape. But to the extent that it <u>tears the fabric of Symbolic reality as we know it, unraveling the solidity of every object, including the object as which the subject necessarily takes itself,<mark> </mark>jouissance evokes the death drive that always insists as the void in and of the subject, beyond its fantasy of self- realization, beyond the pleasure principle.</p><p>Bound up with the </u>first of these<u> death drive</u>s<u> is </u>the figure of <u><mark>the Child</u>,</mark> <u><mark>enacting</u></mark> a logic <u>of <mark>repetition </mark>that <mark>fixes identity through</mark> <mark>identification</mark> with the future of the social order</u>. <u><mark>Bound up</u></mark> with the second <u><mark>is</mark> <mark>the figure of the queer, embodying that order’s traumatic encounter with its own inescapable failure</mark>, its encounter with the illusion of the future as suture to bind the constitutive wound of the subject’s subjection to the signifier</u>, which divides it, paradoxically, both from and into itself. In the preface to Homographesis I wrote that the signifier “gay,” understood “as a figure for the textuality, the rhetoricity, of the sexual... designates the gap or incoherence that every discourse of ‘sexuality’ or ‘sexual identity’ would master.” Extending that claim, I now suggest that <u><mark>queer sexualities</mark>, in extricable from the emergence of the subject in the Symbolic, <mark>mark the place of the gap in which the Symbolic confronts what its discourse is in capable of knowing</mark>, which is also the place of a jouissance</u> from which it can never escape. As a figure for what it can neither fully articulate nor acknowledge, <u>the queer may provide the Symbolic with a sort of necessary reassurance by seeming to give a name to what, as Real, remains unnameable. But repudiations of that figural identity, reflecting a liberal faith in the abstract universality of the subject, though better enabling the extension of rights to those who are still denied them, must similarly reassure by attesting to the seamless coherence of the Symbolic whose dominant narrative would thus supersede the corrosive force of queer irony. If the queer’s abjectified difference, that is, secures normativity’s identity, the1 queer’s disavowal of that difference affirms normativity’s singular truth,, For every refusal of the figural status to which queers are distinctively called reproduces the triumph of narrative as the e9onzatwai of irony, as the logic of a temporality that always serves to “straighten” it out, and thus proclaims the universality of reproductive futurism. Such refusals perform, despite themselves, subservience to the law that effectively imposes politics as the only game in town, exacting as the price of admission the subject’s (hetero)normalization, which is accomplished, regardless of sexual practice or sexual “orientation,” through compulsory abjuration of the future-negating queer.</p><p>It may seem</u>, from within this structure, that <u><mark>the Symbolic</mark> can only win</u>; <u><strong>but that would ignore the correlative fact that it also <mark>can only lose</strong></mark>. For <mark>the division on which the subject rests can never be spirited away</mark> and the <mark>signifying order</mark> <mark>will always necessitate the production of some figural repository for the excess that precludes its ultimate realization of the One</u></mark>. In apolitical field whose limit and horizon is reproductive futurism, queerness embodies this death drive, this intransigent jouissance, by figuring sexuality’s implication in the senseless pulsions of that drive. <u>De-idealizing the metaphorics of meaning on which heteroreproduction takes its stand, queerness exposes sexuality’s inevitable coloration by the drive: its insistence on repetition, its stubborn denial of teleology, its resistance to determinations of meaning </u>(except insofar as it means this refusal to admit such determinations of meaning), <u>and</u>, above all, <u>its rejection of spiritualization through marriage to reproductive futurism</u>. <u><strong><mark>Queerness </mark>as name may well reinforce the Symbolic order of naming, but <mark>it names what resists, as signifier, absorption into the Imaginary identity of the name</u></strong></mark>. <u>Empty, excessive, and irreducible, it designates the letter</u>, the formal element, the lifeless machinery responsible for <u>animating</u> the “spirit” of <u>futurity</u>. And as such, <u>as a name for the death drive that always informs the Symbolic order,<mark> it also names the jouissance forbidden by, but permeating, the Symbolic order </mark>itself.</p><p><strong><mark>By denying our identification with the negativity of this drive</u></strong></mark>, and hence our disidentification from the promise of futurity, <u><strong><mark>those of us in habiting the place of the queer may be able to cast off that queerness</u></strong></mark> and enter the properly political sphere, <u><strong><mark>but only by shifting the figural burden of queerness to someone else</u></strong></mark>. <u>The <mark>structural position of queerness</u></mark>, after all, <u><mark>and the need to fill it remain. By choosing to accept that position</u></mark>, however, by assuming the “truth” of our queer capacity to figure the undoing of the Symbolic, and of the Symbolic subject as well, <u><mark>we might undertake the impossible project of imagining an oppositional political stance exempt from the imperative to reproduce the politics of signification</u></mark> (the politics aimed at closing the gap opened up by the signifier itself), <u><mark>which can only return us, </mark>byway of the Child,<mark> to the politics of reproduction</u></mark>. For the liberal’s view of society, which seems to accord the queer a place, endorses no more than the conservative right’s the queer ness of resistance to futurism and thus the queerness of the queer. While the right wing imagines the elimination of queers (or of the need to confront their existence), the left would eliminate queerness by shining the cool light of reason upon it, hoping thereby to expose it as merely a mode of sexual expression free of the all-pervasive coloring, the determining fantasy formation, by means of which it can seem to portend, and not for the right alone, the undoing of the social order and its cynosure, the Child. <u>Queerness thus comes to mean nothing for both: for the right wing the nothingness always at war with the positivity of civil society; for the left, nothing more than a sexual practice in need of demystification.</p><p></u>But this is where <u><mark>reason must fail</u></mark>. <u><mark>Sexuality refuses demystification</mark> as the Symbolic refuses the queer; for sexuality and the Symbolic become what they are by virtue of such refusals.</u> Ironically— but irony, as I’ve argued, always characterizes queer theory—the demystification of queerness and so, by extension, of sexuality itself, the demystification inherent in the position of liberal rationality, could achieve its realization only by traversing the collective fantasy that invests the social order with mean: ing by way of reproductive futurism. Taken at its word, that is, liberalism’s abstract reason, rescuing queerness for sociality, dissolves, like queerness, the very investments on which sociality rests by doing away with its underlying and sustaining libidinal fantasies. <u><mark>Beyond the resonance of fantasy</u></mark>, after all, <u><mark>lies neither law nor reason</u></mark>. In the beyond of demystification, in that neutral, democratic literality that marks the futurism of the left, one could only encounter a queer dismantling of futurism itself as fantasy and a derealization of the order of meaning that futurism reproduces. Intent on the end, not the ends, of the social, queerness insists that the drive toward that end, which liberalism refuses to imagine, can never be excluded from the structuring fantasy of the social order itself. <u>The sacralization of the Child thus necessitates the sacrifice of the queer.</p><p></u>Bernard Law, the former cardinal of Boston, mistaking (or maybe understanding too well) the degree of authority bestowed on him by the signifier of his patronymic, denounced in 1996 proposed legislation giving health care benefits to same-sex partners of municipal employees. He did so by proclaiming, in a noteworthy instance of piety in the sky, that bestowing such access to health care would profoundly diminish the marital bond. “Society,” he opined, “has a special interest in the protection, care and upbringing of children. Because marriage remains the principal, and the best, framework for the nurture, education and socialization of children, the state has a special interest in marriage.”31 With this fatal embrace of a futurism so blindly committed to the figure of the Child that it will justify refusing health care benefits to the adults that some children become, Law lent his voice to the mortifying mantra of a communal jouissance that depends on the fetishization of the Child at the expense of whatever such fetishization must inescapably queer. Some seven years later, after Law had resigned for his failure to protect Catholic children from sexual assault by pedophile priests, Pope John Paul II returned to this theme, condemning state-recognized same-sex unions as parodic versions of authentic families, “based on individual egoism” rather than genuine love. Justifying that condemnation, he observed, “Such a ‘caricature’ has no future and cannot give future to any society.”3 <u><mark>Queers must respond</mark> </u>to the violent force of such constant provocations not only <u>by insisting on our equal right to the social order’s prerogatives</u>, not only by avowing our capacity to promote that order’s coherence and integrity, but also<u> <mark>by saying explicitly what Law</mark> and the Pope <mark>and </mark>the whole of <mark>the Symbolic order </mark>for which they stand <mark>hear any way in each </mark>and every <mark>expression </mark>or manifestation <mark>of queer sexuality:</u> <u>Fuck the social order and the Child</u></mark> in whose name we’re collectively terrorized; <u>fuck Annie</u>; fuck the waif from Les Mis; fuck the poor, innocent kid on the Net<u>; <mark>fuck Laws</u></mark> both with capital ls and with small; <u>fuck the whole network of Symbolic relations and the future that serves as its prop.</p><p><strong><mark>We might </mark>like <mark>believe that</u></strong></mark> with patience, with work, with <u><strong>generous contributions to lobbying groups or generous participation <mark>in</mark> <mark>activist groups or </mark>generous doses of legal savvy <mark>and</mark> <mark>electoral sophistication, the future will hold a place for us</u></strong></mark>—<u>a place at the political table that won’t have to come at the cost of the places we seek in the bed</u> or the bar or the baths. <u><mark>But there are no queers in that future as there can be no future for queers, chosen as they are to bear the bad tidings that there can be no future at all</u></mark>; that the future, as Annie’s hymn to the hope of “Tomorrow” understands, is “always/ A day/ Away.” Like the lovers on Keats’s Grecian urn, forever “near the goal” of a union they’ll never in fact achieve, we’re held in thrall by a future continually deferred by time itself, constrained to pursue the dream of a day when today and tomorrow are one. That future is nothing but kid stuff, reborn each day to screen out the grave that gapes from within the lifeless letter, luring us into, ensnaring us in, reality’s gossamer web. <u>Those queered by the social order that projects its death drive onto them are no doubt positioned to recognize the structuring fantasy that so defines them. But they’re positioned as well to recognize the irreducibility of that fantasy and the cost of construing it as contingent to the logic of social organization as such<strong>. <mark>Acceding to this figural identification with the undoing of identity</u></strong></mark>, <u>which is also toy with the disarticulation of social and Symbolic form<mark>, might </mark>well <mark>be described</u></mark>, in John Brenkman’s words, <u><mark>as “politically self-destructive</u></mark>.” <u><mark>But politics</u></mark> (as the social elaboration of reality) <u><mark>and the self as mere prosthesis</mark> <mark>maintaining the future for the </mark>figural <mark>Child</u></mark>), <u><mark>are what queerness</mark>, again as figure, <mark>necessarily destroys</mark>—necessarily insofar as this “self” is the agent of reproductive futurism and this “politics” the means of its promulgation as the order of social reality</u>. But perhaps, as Lacan’s engagement with Antigone in Seminar7 suggests<u>, political self-destruction inheres in the only act that counts as one: the act of resisting enslavement to the future in the name of having a life.</p><p></u>If the fate of the queer is to figure the fate that cub the thread of futurity<u>, if the jouissance</u>, the corrosive enjoyment<u>, intrinsic to queer (non)identity annihilates the</u> fetishistic <u>jouissance that works to consolidate identity by allowing reality to coagulate around its ritual reproduction</u>, <u>then <mark>the only oppositional status to which our queerness could ever lead would depend </mark>on our taking seriously <mark>the place of the death drive</mark> ‘we’re led on to figure and insisting, <mark>against the cult of the Child</mark> and the political order it enforces, that we</u>, as Guy Hocquenghem made clear, <u>are “not the signifier of what might become a new form of ‘social organisation,’ </u>that <u><mark>we do not intend a new politics</u></mark>, <u><mark>a better society</u></mark>, <u><mark>a brighter tomorrow</u></mark>, <u><mark>since all of these fantasies reproduce the past through displacement, in the form of the future</u></mark>. <u><strong><mark>We choose</u></strong></mark>, instead, <u><strong><mark>not to choose the Child</u></strong></mark>, as disciplinary image of the Imaginary past or as site of a projective identification with an always impossible future. The queerness we propose, in Hocquenghem’s words, “is unaware of the passing of generations as stages on the road to better living. It knows nothing about ‘sacrifice now for the sake of future generations’ . . . lit) knows that civilisation alone is mortal.” Even more: <u>it delights in that mortality as the negation of everything that would define itself, moralistically, as pro-life.</u> It is <u>we</u> who <u>must bury the subject in the tomb-like hollow of the signifier, pronouncing at last the words for which we’re condemned should we speak them or not</u>: that we are the advocates of abortion; that <u><mark>the Child as futurity’s emblem must die</u></mark>; that <u><mark>the future is mere repetition and just as lethal as the past.</u></mark> Our queerness has nothing to offer a Symbolic that lives by denying that nothingness except an insistence on the haunting excess that this nothingness entails, an insistence on the negativity that pierces the fantasy screen of futurity, shattering narrative temporality with irony’s always explosive force. <u><mark>And so what is queerest about us</mark>, queerest within us, and queerest despite us is this willingness to insist intransitively—<strong><mark>to insist that the future stop here</mark>.</p></u></strong>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
1,296,740
28
17,077
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
565,297
A
tournament
4
Binghamton Cepin-Sehgal
Baker, Webster Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,323
Medicalization controls their impacts – if they don’t solve it they don’t solve any part of the aff
Elden 2
Stuart Elden, politics at University of Warwick, 2/29/2002 “The War of Races and the Constitution of the State: Foucault's «Il faut défendre la société» and the Politics of Calculation,” Boundary,http://boundary2.dukejournals.org/content/29/1/125.full.pdf
null
Racism as biologizing, as tied to a state, takes shape where the procedures of intervention ‘‘at the level of the body, conduct, health, and everyday life, received justification from the mythical concern with protecting the purity of the blood Because certain groups in society are conceived of in medical terms, society is no longer in need of being defended from the outsider but from the insider: the abnormal in behavior, species, or race What is novel is not the mentality of power but the technology of power hen coupled with the mechanisms of mathematics and medicine in bio-power, this can be conceived of in entirely different ways. Bio-power is able to establish, between my life and the death of the other, a relation that is not warlike or confrontational but biological abnormal individuals can be eliminated the death of the other, of the bad, inferior race or the degenerate or abnormal, makes life purer This holds for indirect death—the exposure to death—as much as for direct killing The theme of the political enemy is extrapolated biologically war is no longer simply a way of securing one race by eliminating the other but of regenerating that race In Nazism Eugenics and medical/mathematical techniques are coupled with the fantasy of blood and the ideal of the purity of the race the old sovereign power of killing traversed the entire society
The reverse side is the power to allow death. State racism is a recoding of the old mechanisms of blood through the new procedures of regulation. Racism, as biologizing, as tied to a state, takes shape where the procedures of intervention ‘‘at the level of the body, conduct, health, and everyday life, received their color and their justification from the mythical concern with protecting the purity of the blood and ensuring the triumph of the race’’ (VS, 197; WK, 149).37 For example, the old anti-Semitism based on religion is reused under the new rubric of state racism. The integrity and purity of the race is threatened, and the state apparatuses are introduced against the race that has infiltrated and introduced noxious elements into the body. The Jews are characterized as the race present in the middle of all races (FDS, 76).38 The use of medical language is important. Because certain groups in society are conceived of in medical terms, society is no longer in need of being defended from the outsider but from the insider: the abnormal in behavior, species, or race. What is novel is not the mentality of power but the technology of power (FDS, 230). The recoding of old problems is made possible through new techniques.2 A break or cut (coupure) is fundamental to racism: a division or incision between those who must live and those who must die. The ‘‘biological continuum of the human species’’ is fragmented by the apparition of races, which are seen as distinguished, hierarchized, qualified as good or inferior, and so forth. The species is subdivided into subgroups that are thought of as races. In a sense, then, just as the continuum of geometry becomes divisible in Descartes,39 the human continuum is divided, that is, made calculable and orderable, two centuries later. As Anderson has persuasively argued, to suggest that racism has its roots in nationalism is a mistake. He suggests that ‘‘the dreams of racism actually have their origin in ideologies of class, rather than in those of nation: above all in claims to divinity among rulers and to ‘blue’ or ‘white’ blood and breeding among aristocracies.’’40 As Stoler has noted, for Foucault, it is the other way around: ‘‘A discourse of class derives from an earlier discourse of races.’’41 But it is a more subtle distinction than that. What Foucault suggests is that discourses of class have their roots in the war of races, but so, too, does modern racism; what is different is the biological spin put on the concepts.42 But as well as emphasizing the biological, modern racism puts this another way: to survive, to live, one must be prepared to massacre one’s enemies, a relation of war. As a relation of war, this is no different from the earlier war of races that Foucault has spent so much of the course explaining. But when coupled with the mechanisms of mathematics and medicine in bio-power, this can be conceived of in entirely different ways. Bio-power is able to establish, between my life and the death of the other, a relation that is not warlike or confrontational but biological: ‘‘The more inferior species tend to disappear, the more abnormal individuals can be eliminated, the less the species will be degenerated, the more I— not as an individual but as a species—will live, will be strong, will be vigorous, will be able to proliferate.’’ The death of the other does not just make me safer personally, but the death of the other, of the bad, inferior race or the degenerate or abnormal, makes life in general healthier and purer (FDS, 227–28). ‘‘The existence in question is no longer of sovereignty, juridical; but that of the population, biological. If genocide is truly the dream of modern powers, this is not because of a return today of the ancient right to kill; it is because power is situated and exercised at the level of life, the species, the race, and the large-scale phenomena of population’’ (VS, 180; WK, 136). ‘‘If the power of normalization wishes to exercise the ancient sovereign right of killing, it must pass through racism. And if, inversely, a sovereign power, that is to say a power with the right of life and death, wishes to function with the instruments, mechanisms, and technology of normalization, it must also pass through racism’’ (FDS, 228). This holds for indirect death—the exposure to death—as much as for direct killing. While not Darwinism, this biological sense of power is based on evolutionism and enables a thinking of colonial relations, the necessity of wars, criminality, phenomena of madness and mental illness, class divisions, and so forth. The link to colonialism is central: This form of modern state racism develops first with colonial genocide. The theme of the political enemy is extrapolated biologically. But what is important in the shift at the end of the nineteenth century is that war is no longer simply a way of securing one race by eliminating the other but of regenerating that race (FDS, 228–30). As Foucault puts it in La volonté de savoir: Wars are no longer waged in the name of a sovereign who must be defended; they are waged on behalf of the existence of all; entire populations are mobilized for the purpose of wholesale slaughter in the name of life necessity. Massacres have become vital [vitaux— understood in a dual sense, both as essential and biological]. It is as managers of life and survival, of bodies and the race, that so many regimes have been able to wage so many wars, causing so many men to be killed. (VS, 180; WK, 136) The shift Foucault thinks is interesting is what might be called a shift from sanguinity to sexuality: sanguinity, in that it had an instrumental role (the shedding of blood) and a symbolic role (purity of blood, differences of blood); sexuality, when mechanisms of power are directed to the body, to life. The theme of race is present in both, but in a different form (VS, 194; WK, 147). We have moved from ‘‘a symbolics of blood to an analytics of sexuality. Clearly, nothing was more on the side of the law, death, transgression, the symbolic, and sovereignty than blood; just as sexuality was on the side of the norm, knowledge, life, meaning, the disciplines and regulations’’ (VS, 195; WK, 148). In Nazism, the two are combined. Eugenics and medical/mathematical techniques are coupled with the fantasy of blood and the ideal of the purity of the race. Foucault notes that there was immediate control of procreation and genetics in the Nazi regime, and that regulation, security, and assurance were imposed over the disciplined, ordered society; but at the same time, the old sovereign power of killing traversed the entire society. This was not simply confined to the state, nor simply to the SA or the SS, but ultimately to everyone, as, through denunciation, everyone could have this power over their neighbor (FDS, 231).
6,840
<h4><strong>Medicalization controls their impacts – if they don’t solve it they don’t solve any part of the aff</h4><p></strong>Stuart <strong>Elden</strong>, politics at University of Warwick, 2/29/200<strong>2</strong> “The War of Races and the Constitution of the State: Foucault's «Il faut défendre la société» and the Politics of Calculation,” Boundary,http://boundary2.dukejournals.org/content/29/1/125.full.pdf </p><p>The reverse side is the power to allow death. State racism is a recoding of the old mechanisms of blood through the new procedures of regulation. <mark>Racism</mark>, <mark>as biologizing, as tied to a state, takes shape where the procedures of intervention ‘‘at the level of the body, conduct, health, and everyday life,</mark> <mark>received</mark> their color and their <mark>justification from the mythical concern with protecting the purity of the blood</mark> and ensuring the triumph of the race’’ (VS, 197; WK, 149).37 For example, the old anti-Semitism based on religion is reused under the new rubric of state racism. The integrity and purity of the race is threatened, and the state apparatuses are introduced against the race that has infiltrated and introduced noxious elements into the body. The Jews are characterized as the race present in the middle of all races (FDS, 76).38 The use of medical language is important. <mark>Because certain groups in society are conceived of in medical terms, society is no longer in need of being defended from the outsider but from the insider: the abnormal in behavior, species, or race</mark>. <mark>What is novel is not the mentality of power but the technology of power</mark> (FDS, 230). The recoding of old problems is made possible through new techniques.2 A break or cut (coupure) is fundamental to racism: a division or incision between those who must live and those who must die. The ‘‘biological continuum of the human species’’ is fragmented by the apparition of races, which are seen as distinguished, hierarchized, qualified as good or inferior, and so forth. The species is subdivided into subgroups that are thought of as races. In a sense, then, just as the continuum of geometry becomes divisible in Descartes,39 the human continuum is divided, that is, made calculable and orderable, two centuries later. As Anderson has persuasively argued, to suggest that racism has its roots in nationalism is a mistake. He suggests that ‘‘the dreams of racism actually have their origin in ideologies of class, rather than in those of nation: above all in claims to divinity among rulers and to ‘blue’ or ‘white’ blood and breeding among aristocracies.’’40 As Stoler has noted, for Foucault, it is the other way around: ‘‘A discourse of class derives from an earlier discourse of races.’’41 But it is a more subtle distinction than that. What Foucault suggests is that discourses of class have their roots in the war of races, but so, too, does modern racism; what is different is the biological spin put on the concepts.42 But as well as emphasizing the biological, modern racism puts this another way: to survive, to live, one must be prepared to massacre one’s enemies, a relation of war. As a relation of war, this is no different from the earlier war of races that Foucault has spent so much of the course explaining. But w<mark>hen coupled with the mechanisms of mathematics and medicine in bio-power, this can be conceived of in entirely different ways. Bio-power is able to establish, between my life and the death of the other, a relation that is not warlike or confrontational but biological</mark>: ‘‘The more inferior species tend to disappear, the more <mark>abnormal individuals can be eliminated</mark>, the less the species will be degenerated, the more I— not as an individual but as a species—will live, will be strong, will be vigorous, will be able to proliferate.’’ The death of the other does not just make me safer personally, but <mark>the death of the other, of the bad, inferior race or the degenerate or abnormal, makes life</mark> in general healthier and <mark>purer</mark> (FDS, 227–28). ‘‘The existence in question is no longer of sovereignty, juridical; but that of the population, biological. If genocide is truly the dream of modern powers, this is not because of a return today of the ancient right to kill; it is because power is situated and exercised at the level of life, the species, the race, and the large-scale phenomena of population’’ (VS, 180; WK, 136). ‘‘If the power of normalization wishes to exercise the ancient sovereign right of killing, it must pass through racism. And if, inversely, a sovereign power, that is to say a power with the right of life and death, wishes to function with the instruments, mechanisms, and technology of normalization, it must also pass through racism’’ (FDS, 228). <mark>This holds for indirect death—the exposure to death—as much as for direct killing</mark>. While not Darwinism, this biological sense of power is based on evolutionism and enables a thinking of colonial relations, the necessity of wars, criminality, phenomena of madness and mental illness, class divisions, and so forth. The link to colonialism is central: This form of modern state racism develops first with colonial genocide. <mark>The theme of the political enemy is extrapolated biologically</mark>. But what is important in the shift at the end of the nineteenth century is that <mark>war is no longer simply a way of securing one race by eliminating the other but of regenerating that race</mark> (FDS, 228–30). As Foucault puts it in La volonté de savoir: Wars are no longer waged in the name of a sovereign who must be defended; they are waged on behalf of the existence of all; entire populations are mobilized for the purpose of wholesale slaughter in the name of life necessity. Massacres have become vital [vitaux— understood in a dual sense, both as essential and biological]. It is as managers of life and survival, of bodies and the race, that so many regimes have been able to wage so many wars, causing so many men to be killed. (VS, 180; WK, 136) The shift Foucault thinks is interesting is what might be called a shift from sanguinity to sexuality: sanguinity, in that it had an instrumental role (the shedding of blood) and a symbolic role (purity of blood, differences of blood); sexuality, when mechanisms of power are directed to the body, to life. The theme of race is present in both, but in a different form (VS, 194; WK, 147). We have moved from ‘‘a symbolics of blood to an analytics of sexuality. Clearly, nothing was more on the side of the law, death, transgression, the symbolic, and sovereignty than blood; just as sexuality was on the side of the norm, knowledge, life, meaning, the disciplines and regulations’’ (VS, 195; WK, 148). <mark>In Nazism</mark>, the two are combined. <mark>Eugenics and medical/mathematical techniques are coupled with the fantasy of blood and the ideal of the purity of the race</mark>. Foucault notes that there was immediate control of procreation and genetics in the Nazi regime, and that regulation, security, and assurance were imposed over the disciplined, ordered society; but at the same time, <mark>the old sovereign power of killing traversed the entire society</mark>. This was not simply confined to the state, nor simply to the SA or the SS, but ultimately to everyone, as, through denunciation, everyone could have this power over their neighbor (FDS, 231).</p>
null
null
Case
55,906
45
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,324
Link magnifier to any K of PAS – biopower doesn’t stop at the management of life, it also creates the conditions of suicide
Stoneman 5
Stoneman 5 Scott, “Suicide and Biopower: Foucault, Derrida, and Deconstruction,” Fall, http://www.scribd.com/doc/230752001/774-Long-Paper-Stoneman-Foucault-Derrida-and-Suicide#scribd
Where I find the treatment of suicide too lean is in dissociating of the effects of biopower from suicidality ucault is invested in the symbolic preservation of suicide, in deliberately belying those modes of suicidality which are the regulated result of biopower Foucault is never concerned about the possibility that it is an event in the lives of the broke, broken and berated bound by those operations of biopower which constitute a subject whose life is inscribed not worth living Were he to treat the two forces (suicidal and biopolitical) contiguously, he would be forced to account for situations in which power is less troubled by than responsible for suicidal ideation
Where I find the treatment of suicide too lean is in dissociating of the effects of biopower from suicidality Foucault is never concerned about the possibility that it is an event in the lives of the broke, broken and berated bound by those operations of biopower which constitute a subject whose life is inscribed not worth living Were he to treat the two forces contiguously, he would be forced to account for situations in which power is less troubled by than responsible for suicidal ideation
Where precisely in Foucault I find the treatment of suicide too lean is in his (no doubt strategic) dissociating of the effects of biopower from suicidality, or the contemplation and/or completion of suicide. Like Maurice Blanchot, Foucault is invested in the symbolic preservation of suicide, in deliberately belying those modes of suicidality which are the regulated result of biopower. Where he is concerned with suicide Foucault is never concerned about suicide, about the possibility that it is an event in the lives of the broke, broken and berated bound by those operations of biopower which constitute a subject whose life is inscribed not worth living, whose subjectivity consists precisely in exclusion and execration. Were he to treat the two forces (suicidal and biopolitical) contiguously, he would be forced to account for situations in which power is less troubled by than responsible for suicidal ideation and commitment—which he does not precisely do. I will argue later that Blanchot, while he shares much of Foucault’s heartened attitude towards suicide, in fact provides the dialectical thinking about the subject that the discourse on what I have elected to call autodestruction in Foucault ostensibly lacks. What Blanchot’s capacious consideration of the question makes most apparent, though, is the extent to which Foucault’s calculated deferral of a dialectical consideration of suicide is precisely that, a calculation. But we must then ask, what is the object of this rhetorical and political calculation, and what are its rhetorical and political consequences?
1,587
<h4>Link magnifier to any K of PAS – biopower doesn’t stop at the management of life, it also creates the conditions of suicide</h4><p><strong>Stoneman 5</strong> Scott, “Suicide and Biopower: Foucault, Derrida, and Deconstruction,” Fall, http://www.scribd.com/doc/230752001/774-Long-Paper-Stoneman-Foucault-Derrida-and-Suicide#scribd</p><p><u><mark>Where</u></mark> precisely in Foucault <u><mark>I find the treatment of suicide too lean is in</mark> </u>his (no doubt strategic) <u><mark>dissociating of the effects of biopower from suicidality</u></mark>, or the contemplation and/or completion of suicide. Like Maurice Blanchot, Fo<u>ucault is invested in the symbolic preservation of suicide, in deliberately belying those modes of suicidality which are the regulated result of biopower</u>. Where he is concerned with suicide <u><mark>Foucault is never concerned about</u></mark> suicide, about <u><mark>the possibility that it is an event in the lives of the broke, broken and berated bound by those operations of biopower which constitute a subject whose life is inscribed not worth living</u></mark>, whose subjectivity consists precisely in exclusion and execration. <u><mark>Were he to treat the two forces</mark> (suicidal and biopolitical) <mark>contiguously, he would be forced to account for situations in which power is less troubled by than responsible for suicidal ideation</u></mark> and commitment—which he does not precisely do. I will argue later that Blanchot, while he shares much of Foucault’s heartened attitude towards suicide, in fact provides the dialectical thinking about the subject that the discourse on what I have elected to call autodestruction in Foucault ostensibly lacks. What Blanchot’s capacious consideration of the question makes most apparent, though, is the extent to which Foucault’s calculated deferral of a dialectical consideration of suicide is precisely that, a calculation. But we must then ask, what is the object of this rhetorical and political calculation, and what are its rhetorical and political consequences? </p>
null
Case
2NC K
430,354
8
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,325
Economic modeling proves central purchasing would increase supply
Matas 13
Matas 13 A. J. Matas, University of Minnesota, American Journal of Transplantation 2013; 13: 1926–1927 Book Review - The Global Organ Shortage: Economic Causes, Human Consequences, Policy Responses , by T. Randolph Beard, David L. Kaserman and Rigmar Osterkamp. Stanford University Press, 2013. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ajt.12273/pdf
three economists one, David Kaserman show through economic modeling how incentives would increase both living and deceased donation their proposal a Public Monopsony for Organ Acquisition
three economis one, David Kaserman show through economic modeling how incentives would increase both living deceased donation their proposal for a Public Monopsony for Organ Acquisition
The Global Organ Shortage: Economic Causes, Human Consequences, Policy Responses was written by three economists. Given that one, David Kaserman, has previously championed incentives for donation, it is not surprising that the authors’ conclusion favors incentives. The book starts, ‘‘The organ transplantation policies by the vast majority of the world’s nations have failed.’’ That said, the authors have made a superb attempt to acknowledge and present detailed strengths of arguments both for and against incentives (1–3). Their stated goal is to focus attention on the problem and provoke further discussion of solutions. The book has excellent flow, with each of its nine chapters building on momentum from previous ones. The first chapter (Introduction) defines the problem of a global shortage of organs and outlines the format of the book; the last (Conclusions) reviews the authors’ arguments. Chapter 2 describes the evolution of transplant policies throughout the world and their almost universal basis in the concept of ‘altruism.’ Chapter 3 states the human consequences of these policies—an organ shortage with thousands of candidates dying or becoming too sick to transplant each year while waiting on the list for a transplant. Chapter 4 discusses the social costs and benefits of transplantation versus alternate therapies. As noted in previous publications, transplantation can save health care systems billions (4). Consequently, the authors believe that reforms increasing the number of transplants would be advantageous for both patient outcomes and society. They show through economic modeling how incentives would increase both living (LDs) and deceased (DDs) donation. Although cost–benefit analysis is most clear for kidneys, they note that with increased DDs, candidates on all lists could benefit. Chapter 5 outlines the consequences of a ‘‘zero (dollar/euro) point price for organs’’ and the causes of a lack of system reform. Although the authors believe that the major cause of the organ shortage is that compensation is illegal, they acknowledge other contributing factors, and comment that those opposed to incentives favor other reforms to increase donation, albeit ‘‘within the current paradigm.’’ Chapter 6 provides a history of attempts to reform the donation system to increase both living and deceased donation. The authors note that some—e.g. Spanish Model, use of ECDs—have made an impact, but a severe shortage persists. They conclude, ‘‘In our view, the introduction of more radical reforms, including [compensation for LDs and DDs], is imperative.’’ Chapter 7 addresses the moral basis of objections to compensation. The authors portray these objections realistically, stating that the organ shortage is ‘‘perhaps the most complex and morally controversial medical issue aside from abortion and euthanasia.’’ Each previously described concern is addressed; ultimately the authors believe that the possibility of saving lives outweighs any other argument. Chapter 8 provides their proposal for a Public Monopsony for Organ Acquisition (for both LDs and DDs) (4,5). Again, acknowledging counterarguments, the authorsstate, ‘‘The reformwe proposetriesto advancethe policy of preserving life while respecting important social taboos and taking seriously widely shared moral convictions.’’ Their modeling shows how a variety of incentive systems could increase both LDs and DDs, and they comment that different systems may work better for different countries.
3,498
<h4>Economic modeling proves central purchasing would increase supply</h4><p><strong>Matas 13 </strong> A. J. Matas, University of Minnesota, American Journal of Transplantation 2013; 13: 1926–1927 Book Review - The Global Organ Shortage: Economic Causes, Human Consequences, Policy Responses , by T. Randolph Beard, David L. Kaserman and Rigmar Osterkamp. Stanford University Press, 2013. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ajt.12273/pdf</p><p>The Global Organ Shortage: Economic Causes, Human Consequences, Policy Responses was written by <u><mark>three economis</mark>ts</u>. Given that <u><mark>one, David</u> <u>Kaserman</u></mark>, has previously championed incentives for donation, it is not surprising that the authors’ conclusion favors incentives. The book starts, ‘‘The organ transplantation policies by the vast majority of the world’s nations have failed.’’ That said, the authors have made a superb attempt to acknowledge and present detailed strengths of arguments both for and against incentives (1–3). Their stated goal is to focus attention on the problem and provoke further discussion of solutions.</p><p>The book has excellent flow, with each of its nine chapters building on momentum from previous ones.</p><p>The first chapter (Introduction) defines the problem of a global shortage of organs and outlines the format of the book; the last (Conclusions) reviews the authors’ arguments.</p><p>Chapter 2 describes the evolution of transplant policies throughout the world and their almost universal basis in the concept of ‘altruism.’ Chapter 3 states the human consequences of these policies—an organ shortage with thousands of candidates dying or becoming too sick to transplant each year while waiting on the list for a transplant.</p><p>Chapter 4 discusses the social costs and benefits of transplantation versus alternate therapies. As noted in</p><p>previous publications, transplantation can save health care systems billions (4). Consequently, the authors believe that reforms increasing the number of transplants would be advantageous for both patient outcomes and society. They <u><mark>show through economic modeling how incentives would increase both living</u></mark> (LDs) <u>and <mark>deceased</u></mark> (DDs) <u><mark>donation</u></mark>. Although cost–benefit analysis is most clear for kidneys, they note that with increased DDs, candidates on all lists could benefit. Chapter 5 outlines the consequences of a ‘‘zero (dollar/euro) point price for organs’’ and the causes of a lack of system reform. Although the authors believe that the major cause of the organ shortage is that compensation is illegal, they acknowledge other contributing factors, and comment that those opposed to incentives favor other</p><p>reforms to increase donation, albeit ‘‘within the current paradigm.’’ Chapter 6 provides a history of attempts to reform the donation system to increase both living and deceased donation. The authors note that some—e.g. Spanish Model, use of ECDs—have made an impact, but a severe shortage persists. They conclude, ‘‘In our view, the introduction of more radical reforms, including [compensation for LDs and DDs], is imperative.’’</p><p>Chapter 7 addresses the moral basis of objections to compensation. The authors portray these objections</p><p>realistically, stating that the organ shortage is ‘‘perhaps the most complex and morally controversial medical issue aside from abortion and euthanasia.’’ Each previously described concern is addressed; ultimately the authors believe that the possibility of saving lives outweighs any other argument. Chapter 8 provides <u><mark>their proposal</u> for <u>a Public Monopsony</mark> <mark>for Organ Acquisition</u></mark> (for both LDs and DDs) (4,5). Again, acknowledging counterarguments, the authorsstate, ‘‘The reformwe proposetriesto advancethe</p><p>policy of preserving life while respecting important social taboos and taking seriously widely shared moral convictions.’’ Their modeling shows how a variety of incentive systems could increase both LDs and DDs, and they comment that different systems may work better for different countries.</p>
2AC
Counterplan
Theirs
430,653
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,326
Specific sectors not key
Boston Globe 97
Boston Globe 97 Boston Globe 11/12/97, lexis
Cognetics measures business trends to identify the fastest-growing sectors its findings suggest analysis of sectors might be obsolete for forecasting growth. "Economic growth is no longer driven, nor even dominated, by any particular sector
Cognetics measures business trends to identify the fastest-growing sectors findings suggest analysis of sectors might be obsolete for forecasting growth. "Economic growth is no longer driven, nor even dominated, by any particular sector
That's the word from Cambridge-based Cognetics Inc., which measures business trends to identify the fastest-growing sectors or companies. Cognetics calls such companies "gazelles." The latest Cognetics report, published last week, is titled "Hot Industries" and looked at growth by individual companies between 1992 and 1996. The data, from Dun & Bradstreet, were then shuffled to show the percentage of companies in each industrial or business sector that grew fastest during that time. Only one of these industries, rubber and plastics manufacturing, can be considered a high-growth field, Cognetics said. The others have been low-growth for many years - consistent with the fact that almost no new manufacturing jobs overall have been created in the United States for 50 years. In contrast, Cognetics ranked the much-touted communications industry 44th, with 3.1 percent of companies pegged as gazelles. Health services was in 46th place, with 3.0 percent; the recreation and amusements industry was in 64th place, at 1.9 percent. Cognetics said its findings suggest analysis of entire sectors might be obsolete for forecasting growth. "Economic growth is no longer driven, nor even dominated, by any particular sector," the authors said, and local and state economic development officials could be misguided in focusing on specific sectors.
1,349
<h4><u><strong>Specific sectors not key</h4><p>Boston Globe 97</p><p></u></strong>Boston Globe 11/12/97, lexis</p><p>That's the word from Cambridge-based <u><mark>Cognetics</u></mark> Inc., which <u><mark>measures business trends to identify the fastest-growing sectors</u></mark> or companies. Cognetics calls such companies "gazelles." The latest Cognetics report, published last week, is titled "Hot Industries" and looked at growth by individual companies between 1992 and 1996. The data, from Dun & Bradstreet, were then shuffled to show the percentage of companies in each industrial or business sector that grew fastest during that time. Only one of these industries, rubber and plastics manufacturing, can be considered a high-growth field, Cognetics said. The others have been low-growth for many years - consistent with the fact that almost no new manufacturing jobs overall have been created in the United States for 50 years. In contrast, Cognetics ranked the much-touted communications industry 44th, with 3.1 percent of companies pegged as gazelles. Health services was in 46th place, with 3.0 percent; the recreation and amusements industry was in 64th place, at 1.9 percent. Cognetics said <u>its <mark>findings suggest analysis of</mark> </u>entire <u><mark>sectors might be <strong>obsolete</strong> for forecasting growth. "Economic growth is no longer driven, nor even dominated, by any particular sector</u></mark>," the authors said, and local and state economic development officials could be misguided in focusing on specific sectors.</p>
WTO
Banks
AT: Inevitable
430,654
1
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,327
It’s a dead issue---it’s been settled
Grahmann 9
Grahmann 9 – Kraig P. Grahmann, Attorney at the Law Firm of Haynes and Boone, LLP, “Betting on Prohibition: The Federal Government's Approach to Internet Gambling”, Northwestern Journal of Technology and Intellectual Property, Spring, 7 Nw. J. Tech. & Intell. Prop. 162, Lexis
there is significant international pressure to take a regulatory approach But the U S settled current and potential trade disputes surrounding its prohibition of online gambling by granting concessions in other sectors to the complaining countries
there is international pressure to take a regulatory approach But the U S settled current and potential trade disputes surrounding its prohibition of online gambling by granting concessions in other sectors to complaining countries
3. WTO Issues Challenges to the United States' prohibition of Internet gambling do not just come from the domestic front--there is significant international pressure to take a regulatory approach. In 2003, before the enactment of the UIGEA, a foreign country--Antigua and Barbuda--filed a complaint against the United States with the World Trade Organization. n128 It alleges that the Wire and Travel Acts, n129 read in conjunction with the laws of several states, n130 amount to a prohibition of foreign online gaming providers in violation of the General Agreement on Trade in Services (GATS). n131 The WTO's Dispute Settlement Panel agreed with the complainant and determined that U.S. law at [*176] the time of the ruling prohibited certain forms of Internet gambling in a discriminatory manner. n132 Exceptions in anti-gambling laws that allow limited online betting from domestic operators under the Interstate Horseracing Act are the main source of discrimination. n133 These same exceptions are found in the UIGEA, providing a ground for foreign countries to object with the World Trade Organization to this more encompassing prohibition. n134 But the United States settled current and potential trade disputes surrounding its prohibition of online gambling by granting concessions in other sectors to the complaining countries. n135 The White House refused to disclose what those concessions were, and they are currently the subject of a Freedom of Information Act lawsuit. n136
1,489
<h4>It’s a dead issue---it’s been settled</h4><p><strong>Grahmann 9</strong> – Kraig P. Grahmann, Attorney at the Law Firm of Haynes and Boone, LLP, “Betting on Prohibition: The Federal Government's Approach to Internet Gambling”, Northwestern Journal of Technology and Intellectual Property, Spring, 7 Nw. J. Tech. & Intell. Prop. 162, Lexis</p><p>3. WTO Issues Challenges to the United States' prohibition of Internet gambling do not just come from the domestic front--<u><mark>there is</mark> significant <strong><mark>international</strong> pressure to take a regulatory approach</u></mark>. In 2003, before the enactment of the UIGEA, a foreign country--Antigua and Barbuda--filed a complaint against the United States with the World Trade Organization. n128 It alleges that the Wire and Travel Acts, n129 read in conjunction with the laws of several states, n130 amount to a prohibition of foreign online gaming providers in violation of the General Agreement on Trade in Services (GATS). n131 The WTO's Dispute Settlement Panel agreed with the complainant and determined that U.S. law at [*176] the time of the ruling prohibited certain forms of Internet gambling in a discriminatory manner. n132 Exceptions in anti-gambling laws that allow limited online betting from domestic operators under the Interstate Horseracing Act are the main source of discrimination. n133 These same exceptions are found in the UIGEA, providing a ground for foreign countries to object with the World Trade Organization to this more encompassing prohibition. n134 <u><mark>But the <strong>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><strong><mark>settled</strong> current and potential trade disputes surrounding its prohibition of online gambling by granting concessions in other sectors to</mark> the <mark>complaining countries</u></mark>. n135 The White House refused to disclose what those concessions were, and they are currently the subject of a Freedom of Information Act lawsuit. n136</p>
null
null
1NC
430,601
2
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,328
Absent an explicit rejection of reproductive futurism there can be no meaningful reform – you should evaluate solvency around the reasons for a policy
Alexander 10, Associate Professor of Law
Alexander 10, Associate Professor of Law [2010, Michelle Alexander, is an associate professor of law at Ohio State University, a civil rights advocate and a writer. “New Jim Crow : Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness” ProQuest ebrary, pp. 221-224]
The central question for racial justice advocates is this: are we serious about ending this system of control there is a tremendous amount of work to be done The notion that all of these reforms can be accomplished piecemeal through disconnected advocacy strategies— seems deeply misguided needed reforms have less to do with failed policies than a deeply flawed public consensus one that is indifferent, at best to the experience of poor people of color it was far more important to engage in mass mobilizations than file lawsuits, “We’re trying to win the right to vote and we have to focus the attention of the world on that. We can’t do that making legal cases We have to make the case in the court of public opinion.” King appreciated the contributions of civil rights lawyers he opposed the tendency of civil rights lawyers to identify a handful of individuals who could make great plaintiffs in a court of law, then file isolated cases what was necessary was to mobilize thousands to make their case in the court of public opinion it was a flawed public consensus— not merely flawed policy— that was at the root of racial oppression. a flawed public consensus lies at the core of the prevailing caste system When people think about crime they do not think about suburban housewives violating laws regulating prescription drugs or white frat boys using ecstasy Drug crime is understood to be black and brown it is because drug crime is racially defined in the public consciousness that the electorate has not cared much what happens to drug criminals at least not the way they would have cared if the criminals were understood to be white It is this failure that lies at the core of this system of control and every racial caste system that has existed in the United States or anywhere else in the world Those who believe that advocacy challenging mass incarceration can be successful without overturning the public consensus are engaging in fanciful thinking, a form of denial Isolated victories can be won but in the absence of a fundamental shift in public consciousness, the system as a whole will remain intact To the extent that major changes are achieved without a complete shift, the system will rebound. The caste system will reemerge in a new form, just as convict leasing replaced slavery, or it will be reborn, just as mass incarceration replaced Jim Crow. Sociologists Omi and Winant attribute the cyclical nature of racial progress to the “unstable equilibrium” that characterizes the United States’ racial order Under “normal” condition state institutions are able to normalize the organization and enforcement of the prevailing racial order and the system functions relatively automatically. Challenges to the racial order during these periods are easily marginalized or suppressed the prevailing system of racial meanings, identity, and ideology seems “natural.” When the equilibrium is disrupted the state initially resists, then attempts to absorb the challenge through a series of reforms “that are, if not entirely symbolic, at least not critical to the operation of the racial order In the ab-sence of a truly egalitarian racial consensus, these predictable cycles inevitably give rise to new, extraordinarily comprehensive systems of racialized social control One example is the infamous aftermath of the Brown v. Board of Education decision The statistics from the Southern states are truly amazing. For ten years, 1954– 1964, virtually nothing happened Across the South as a whole, a mere 1 percent of black school children were attending school with whites in 1964 Brown did not end Jim Crow; a mass movement had to emerge first one that aimed to create a new public consensus opposed to the evils of Jim Crow Brown gave critical legitimacy to the demands of civil rights activists who risked their lives to end Jim Crow and it helped to inspire the movement But standing alone, Brown accomplished for African Americans little more than Abraham Lincoln’s Emancipation Proclamation Those who imagine that far less is required to dismantle mass incarceration and build a new, egalitarian racial consensus reflecting a compassionate rather than punitive impulse toward poor people of color fail to appreciate the distance between King Jr.’s dream and the ongoing racial nightmare for those locked up and locked out of American society The foregoing should not be read as a call for movement building to the exclusion of reform work reform work is the work of movement building provided that it is done consciously as movement-building work If all the reforms mentioned above were actually adopted, a radical transformation in our society would have taken place. The relevant question is not whether to engage in reform work, but how. There is no shortage of worthy reform efforts it is critical to keep in mind that the question of how we do reform work is even more important than the specific reforms we seek. the way we pursue reforms does not contribute to the building of a movement to dismantle the system of mass incarceration our advocacy does not upset the prevailing public consensus that supports the new caste system, none of the reforms, even if won, will successfully disrupt the nation’s racial equilibrium Challenges to the system will be easily absorbed or deflected, and the accommodations made will serve primarily to legitimate the system, not undermine it. We run the risk of winning isolated battles but losing the larger war.
The notion that reforms can be accomplished piecemeal through disconnected advocacy strategies— seems misguided reforms have less to do with failed policies than a deeply flawed public consensus it was more important to engage in mass mobilizations We have to make the case in the court of public opinion in the absence of a fundamental shift in public consciousness, the system will rebound in a new form state institutions are able to normalize the racial order Challenges are easily suppressed these cycles give rise to new systems of racialized social control Brown did not end Jim Crow; a mass movement had to emerge first Brown gave critical legitimacy to the demands of civil rights activists the movement But standing alone, Brown accomplished little The foregoing should not be read as a call for movement building to the exclusion of reform work reform work is the work of movement building, provided that it is done consciously the question of how we do reform work is even more important than the specific reforms we seek. If the way we pursue reforms does not contribute to a movement to dismantle Challenges to the system will be easily absorbed and the accommodations will legitimate the system, not undermine it. We run the risk of winning isolated battles but losing the larger war.
The list could go on, of course, but the point has been made. The central question for racial justice advocates is this: are we serious about ending this system of control, or not? If we are, there is a tremendous amount of work to be done. The notion that all of these reforms can be accomplished piecemeal— one at a time, through disconnected advocacy strategies— seems deeply misguided. All of the needed reforms have less to do with failed policies than a deeply flawed public consensus, one that is indifferent, at best, to the experience of poor people of color. As Martin Luther King Jr. explained back in 1965, when describing why it was far more important to engage in mass mobilizations than file lawsuits, “We’re trying to win the right to vote and we have to focus the attention of the world on that. We can’t do that making legal cases. We have to make the case in the court of public opinion.” 21 King certainly appreciated the contributions of civil rights lawyers (he relied on them to get him out of jail), but he opposed the tendency of civil rights lawyers to identify a handful of individuals who could make great plaintiffs in a court of law, then file isolated cases. He believed what was necessary was to mobilize thousands to make their case in the court of public opinion. In his view, it was a flawed public consensus— not merely flawed policy— that was at the root of racial oppression. Today, no less than fifty years ago, a flawed public consensus lies at the core of the prevailing caste system. When people think about crime, especially drug crime, they do not think about suburban housewives violating laws regulating prescription drugs or white frat boys using ecstasy. Drug crime in this country is understood to be black and brown, and it is because drug crime is racially defined in the public consciousness that the electorate has not cared much what happens to drug criminals— at least not the way they would have cared if the criminals were understood to be white. It is this failure to care, really care across color lines, that lies at the core of this system of control and every racial caste system that has existed in the United States or anywhere else in the world. Those who believe that advocacy challenging mass incarceration can be successful without overturning the public consensus that gave rise to it are engaging in fanciful thinking, a form of denial. Isolated victories can be won— even a string of victories— but in the absence of a fundamental shift in public consciousness, the system as a whole will remain intact. To the extent that major changes are achieved without a complete shift, the system will rebound. The caste system will reemerge in a new form, just as convict leasing replaced slavery, or it will be reborn, just as mass incarceration replaced Jim Crow. Sociologists Michael Omi and Howard Winant make a similar point in their book Racial Formation in the United States. They attribute the cyclical nature of racial progress to the “unstable equilibrium” that characterizes the United States’ racial order. 22 Under “normal” conditions, they argue, state institutions are able to normalize the organization and enforcement of the prevailing racial order, and the system functions relatively automatically. Challenges to the racial order during these periods are easily marginalized or suppressed, and the prevailing system of racial meanings, identity, and ideology seems “natural.” These conditions clearly prevailed during slavery and Jim Crow. When the equilibrium is disrupted, however, as in Reconstruction and the Civil Rights Movement, the state initially resists, then attempts to absorb the challenge through a series of reforms “that are, if not entirely symbolic, at least not critical to the operation of the racial order.” In the ab-sence of a truly egalitarian racial consensus, these predictable cycles inevitably give rise to new, extraordinarily comprehensive systems of racialized social control. One example of the way in which a well established racial order easily absorbs legal challenges is the infamous aftermath of the Brown v. Board of Education decision. After the Supreme Court declared separate schools inherently unequal in 1954, segregation persisted unabated. One commentator notes: “The statistics from the Southern states are truly amazing. For ten years, 1954– 1964, virtually nothing happened.” 23 Not a single black child attended an integrated public grade school in South Carolina, Alabama, or Mississippi as of the 1962– 1963 school year. Across the South as a whole, a mere 1 percent of black school children were attending school with whites in 1964— a full decade after Brown was decided. 24 Brown did not end Jim Crow; a mass movement had to emerge first—one that aimed to create a new public consensus opposed to the evils of Jim Crow. This does not mean Brown v. Board was meaningless, as some commentators have claimed. 25 Brown gave critical legitimacy to the demands of civil rights activists who risked their lives to end Jim Crow, and it helped to inspire the movement (as well as a fierce backlash). 26 But standing alone, Brown accomplished for African Americans little more than Abraham Lincoln’s Emancipation Proclamation. A civil war had to be waged to end slavery; a mass movement was necessary to bring a formal end to Jim Crow. Those who imagine that far less is required to dismantle mass incarceration and build a new, egalitarian racial consensus reflecting a compassionate rather than punitive impulse toward poor people of color fail to appreciate the distance between Martin Luther King Jr.’s dream and the ongoing racial nightmare for those locked up and locked out of American society. The foregoing should not be read as a call for movement building to the exclusion of reform work. To the contrary, reform work is the work of movement building, provided that it is done consciously as movement-building work. If all the reforms mentioned above were actually adopted, a radical transformation in our society would have taken place. The relevant question is not whether to engage in reform work, but how. There is no shortage of worthy reform efforts and goals. Differences of opinion are inevitable about which reforms are most important and in what order of priority they should be pursued. These debates are worthwhile, but it is critical to keep in mind that the question of how we do reform work is even more important than the specific reforms we seek. If the way we pursue reforms does not contribute to the building of a movement to dismantle the system of mass incarceration, and if our advocacy does not upset the prevailing public consensus that supports the new caste system, none of the reforms, even if won, will successfully disrupt the nation’s racial equilibrium. Challenges to the system will be easily absorbed or deflected, and the accommodations made will serve primarily to legitimate the system, not undermine it. We run the risk of winning isolated battles but losing the larger war.
7,048
<h4><strong>Absent an explicit rejection of reproductive futurism there can be no meaningful reform – you should evaluate solvency around the reasons for a policy</h4><p>Alexander 10, Associate Professor of Law</p><p></strong>[2010, Michelle Alexander, is an associate professor of law at Ohio State University, a civil rights advocate and a writer. “New Jim Crow : Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness” ProQuest ebrary, pp. 221-224]</p><p>The list could go on, of course, but the point has been made. <u>The central question for racial justice advocates is this: are we <strong>serious about ending this system of control</u></strong>, or not? If we are, <u>there is a <strong>tremendous amount of work to be done</u></strong>. <u><mark>The notion that</mark> all of these <mark>reforms can be accomplished piecemeal</u></mark>— one at a time, <u><mark>through disconnected advocacy strategies— seems </mark>deeply <mark>misguided</u></mark>. All of the <u>needed <mark>reforms have less to do with failed policies than a <strong>deeply flawed public consensus</u></strong></mark>, <u>one that is <strong>indifferent, at best</u></strong>, <u>to the experience of poor people of color</u>. As Martin Luther King Jr. explained back in 1965, when describing why <u><mark>it was</mark> far <mark>more important to engage in mass mobilizations</mark> than file lawsuits,</u> <u>“We’re trying to win the right to vote and we <strong>have to focus the attention of the world on that.</u></strong> <u>We can’t do that making legal cases</u>. <u><mark>We have to make the case in the <strong>court of public opinion</mark>.”</u></strong> 21 <u>King</u> certainly <u>appreciated the contributions of civil rights lawyers</u> (he relied on them to get him out of jail), but <u>he opposed the tendency of civil rights lawyers to identify a handful of individuals who could make great plaintiffs in a court of law, then <strong>file isolated cases</u></strong>. He believed <u>what was necessary was <strong>to mobilize thousands</strong> to make their case in the court of public opinion</u>. In his view, <u><strong>it was a flawed public consensus</strong>— <strong>not merely flawed policy— that was at the root of racial oppression. </u></strong>Today, no less than fifty years ago, <u>a flawed public consensus lies at the core of the prevailing caste system</u>. <u>When people think about crime</u>, especially drug crime, <u>they do not think about suburban housewives violating laws regulating prescription drugs or white frat boys using ecstasy</u>. <u>Drug crime</u> in this country <u><strong>is understood to be black and brown</u></strong>, and <u>it is because drug crime is racially defined in the public consciousness that the electorate has not cared much what happens to drug criminals</u>— <u>at least not the way they would have cared if the criminals were understood to be white</u>. <u>It is this failure</u> to care, really care across color lines, <u><strong>that lies at the core of this system of control and every racial caste system that has existed in the United States or anywhere else in the world</u></strong>. <u>Those who believe that advocacy challenging mass incarceration can be successful without overturning the public consensus </u>that gave rise to it <u>are <strong>engaging in fanciful thinking, a form of denial</u></strong>. <u>Isolated victories can be won</u>— even a string of victories— <u>but <strong><mark>in the absence of a fundamental shift in public consciousness, </mark>the system as a whole will remain intact</u></strong>. <u>To the extent that major changes are achieved without a complete shift, <strong><mark>the system will rebound</mark>.</u></strong> <u>The caste system will <strong>reemerge <mark>in a new form</strong></mark>, just as convict leasing replaced slavery, or it will be reborn, just as mass incarceration replaced Jim Crow.</u> <u>Sociologists</u> Michael <u>Omi and</u> Howard <u>Winant</u> make a similar point in their book Racial Formation in the United States. They <u>attribute the cyclical nature of racial progress to the “<strong>unstable equilibrium</strong>” that characterizes the United States’ racial order</u>. 22 <u>Under “normal” condition</u>s, they argue, <u><mark>state institutions are able to <strong>normalize the</mark> organization and enforcement of the prevailing <mark>racial order</u></strong></mark>, <u>and the system functions relatively automatically.</u> <u><mark>Challenges </mark>to the racial order during these periods <mark>are easily</mark> marginalized or <mark>suppressed</u></mark>, and <u>the prevailing system of racial meanings, identity, and ideology seems “natural.” </u>These conditions clearly prevailed during slavery and Jim Crow. <u>When the equilibrium is disrupted</u>, however, as in Reconstruction and the Civil Rights Movement, <u>the state initially resists, then attempts to absorb the challenge through a series of reforms “that are, if not entirely symbolic, at least not critical to the operation of the racial order</u>.” <u>In the ab-sence of a truly egalitarian racial consensus, <mark>these</mark> predictable <mark>cycles</mark> inevitably <strong><mark>give rise to new</mark>, extraordinarily comprehensive <mark>systems of racialized social control</u></strong></mark>. <u>One example</u> of the way in which a well established racial order easily absorbs legal challenges <u>is the infamous aftermath of the Brown v. Board of Education decision</u>. After the Supreme Court declared separate schools inherently unequal in 1954, segregation persisted unabated. One commentator notes: “<u>The statistics from the Southern states are truly amazing. For ten years, 1954– 1964, virtually nothing happened</u>.” 23 Not a single black child attended an integrated public grade school in South Carolina, Alabama, or Mississippi as of the 1962– 1963 school year. <u>Across the South as a whole, a mere 1 percent of black school children were attending school with whites in 1964</u>— a full decade after Brown was decided. 24 <u><mark>Brown did not end Jim Crow; a <strong>mass movement had to emerge first</u></strong></mark>—<u><strong>one that aimed to create a new public consensus opposed to the evils of Jim Crow</u></strong>. This does not mean Brown v. Board was meaningless, as some commentators have claimed. 25 <u><strong><mark>Brown gave critical legitimacy to the demands of civil rights activists</mark> who risked their lives to end Jim Crow</u></strong>, <u>and it helped to inspire <mark>the movement</u></mark> (as well as a fierce backlash). 26 <u><mark>But standing alone, Brown <strong>accomplished </mark>for African Americans <mark>little</strong></mark> more than Abraham Lincoln’s Emancipation Proclamation</u>. A civil war had to be waged to end slavery; a mass movement was necessary to bring a formal end to Jim Crow. <u>Those who imagine that far less is required to dismantle mass incarceration and build a new, egalitarian racial consensus reflecting a compassionate rather than punitive impulse toward poor people of color fail to appreciate the distance between</u> Martin Luther <u>King Jr.’s dream and the ongoing racial nightmare for those locked up and locked out of American society</u>. <u><strong><mark>The foregoing should not be read as a call for movement building to the exclusion of reform work</u></strong></mark>. To the contrary, <u><strong><mark>reform work is the work of movement building</u></strong>, <u><strong>provided that it is done consciously </strong></mark>as movement-building work</u>. <u>If all the reforms mentioned above were actually adopted, <strong>a radical transformation in our society would have taken place. The relevant question is not whether to engage in reform work, but how.</u></strong> <u>There is no shortage of worthy reform efforts</u> and goals. Differences of opinion are inevitable about which reforms are most important and in what order of priority they should be pursued. These debates are worthwhile, but <u>it is critical to keep in mind that <mark>the question of how we do reform work is even more important than the specific reforms we seek.</u> If <u>the way we pursue reforms <strong>does not contribute to</mark> the building of <mark>a movement to dismantle</mark> the system of mass incarceration</u></strong>, and if <u><strong>our advocacy does not upset the prevailing public consensus that supports the new caste system,</u></strong> <u>none of the reforms, even if won, will successfully disrupt the nation’s racial equilibrium</u>. <u><strong><mark>Challenges to the system will be easily absorbed</mark> or deflected, <mark>and the accommodations</mark> made <mark>will</mark> serve primarily to <mark>legitimate the system, not undermine it. We run the risk of winning isolated battles but losing the larger war.</p></u></strong></mark>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
45,037
47
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,329
Federal legalization violates the 1961 Single Convention
Rico 2014 Americas Quarterly8.1 (Winter 2014): 40-45, proquest)
Rico 2014 (Bernardo, international banker and Central America development specialist, INROADS OR DETOURS in the Drug Debate?, Americas Quarterly8.1 (Winter 2014): 40-45, proquest)
marijuana remains on the U.S. federal government's list of "controlled substances" as an illegal narcotic marijuana legalization violates UN drug treaties, primarily the 1961 Single Convention on Narcotic Drugs.
marijuana legalization violates UN drug treaties, primarily the 1961 Single Convention on Narcotic Drugs
It's important, first of all, to understand that neither of these options has anything to do with "legalization." Legalizing a drug removes the prohibition on its production, sale or consumption, albeit with government regulation. Uruguay is the only nation to have recently approved legislation to legalize marijuana, which will allow the government to control most of the stages from production to consumption. Colorado and Washington are the only U.S. states to have legalized the recreational use of marijuana; possession and sale for medical purposes is permitted in 20 other states. However, marijuana remains on the U.S. federal government's list of "controlled substances" as an illegal narcotic. Even though the U.S. Department of Justice has indicated it is reconsidering whether it will enforce federal penalties, marijuana legalization still violates UN drug treaties, primarily the 1961 Single Convention on Narcotic Drugs.
936
<h4>Federal legalization violates the 1961 Single Convention</h4><p><strong>Rico 2014</strong> (Bernardo, international banker and Central America development specialist, INROADS OR DETOURS in the Drug Debate?,<u><strong> Americas Quarterly8.1 (Winter 2014): 40-45, proquest)</p><p></u></strong>It's important, first of all, to understand that neither of these options has anything to do with "legalization." Legalizing a drug removes the prohibition on its production, sale or consumption, albeit with government regulation. Uruguay is the only nation to have recently approved legislation to legalize marijuana, which will allow the government to control most of the stages from production to consumption. Colorado and Washington are the only U.S. states to have legalized the recreational use of marijuana; possession and sale for medical purposes is permitted in 20 other states. However, <u>marijuana remains on the U.S. federal government's list of "controlled substances" as an illegal narcotic</u>. Even though the U.S. Department of Justice has indicated it is reconsidering whether it will enforce federal penalties, <u><mark>marijuana legalization</u></mark> still <u><strong><mark>violates UN drug treaties, primarily the 1961 Single Convention on Narcotic Drugs</strong></mark>.</p></u>
null
null
Off
430,420
24
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,330
antibiotic-resistance takes out defense
MacKenzie 13
MacKenzie 13 Debora MacKenzie 13 March 2013 New Scientist Antibiotic resistance an 'apocalyptic threat' http://www.newscientist.com/article/mg21729084.000-antibiotic-resistance-an-apocalyptic-threat.html
ANTIBIOTIC resistance poses an "apocalyptic" threat to human health. We are facing "nightmare bacteria our predicament is even worse than these words suggest, with antibiotic-resistant bacteria out of control in some areas. More transplantation procedures are being performed annually, resulting in an increase in the number of immunocompromised hosts in the last decade, there has been a growing identification of tropical infectious diseases occurring in transplant hosts in endemic and non-endemic settings The epidemiologic reasons for the growing number of reports of tropical infections appearing in transplant recipients include increasing numbers of transplantation procedures taking place in tropical countries and ( many individuals traveling overseas for ‘transplant tourism’ in countries with high prevalence of tropical infectious diseases
ANTIBIOTIC resistance poses an "apocalyptic" threat to human health. We are facing "nightmare bacteria our predicament is even worse with antibiotic-resistant bacteria out of control More transplantation procedures are being performed annually, resulting in an increase in immunocompromised hosts there has been a growing identification of tropical infectious diseases occurring in transplant hosts in endemic and non-endemic settings The epidemiologic reasons include increasing numbers of transplantation procedures taking place in tropical countries and transplant tourism’
ANTIBIOTIC resistance poses an "apocalyptic" threat to human health. We are facing "nightmare bacteria" and are losing a "war" against them. Such language, in statements made over the past week by the top UK and US medical authorities – normally a very cautious breed – reflects the enormity of the situation they feel we must now confront. In fact, our predicament is even worse than these words suggest, with antibiotic-resistant bacteria out of control in some areas. What's more, New Scientist can reveal that effective new drugs may already exist – but are stuck in the final stages of development because they cannot overcome economic and regulatory hurdles. Increasing reliance on the illegal market means the threat is serious Franco-Paredes 10 Carlos Franco-Paredes, Jesse T. Jacob. Alicia Hidrona, Alfonso J. Rodriguez-Morales,David Kuhara, and Angela M. Caliendoa all with Division of Infectious Diseases, Emory University School of Medicine except Redriguez-Morales at Division of Immunoparasitology, Tropical Medicine Institute, Universidad Central de Venezuela International Journal of Infectious Diseases Volume 14, Issue 3, March 2010, Pages e189–e196 Transplantation and tropical infectious diseases http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S1201971209002045 More transplantation procedures are being performed annually, resulting in an increase in the number of immunocompromised hosts.1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 and 7 Most of the literature in infectious diseases in transplantation has focused on common pathogens prevalent in industrialized Western countries, where most transplantation surgeries occur.1, 2, 4, 5, 6 and 7 However, in the last decade, there has been a growing identification of tropical infectious diseases occurring in transplant hosts in endemic and non-endemic settings.3, 4, 7, 8, 9, 10 and 11 The epidemiologic reasons for the growing number of reports of tropical infections appearing in transplant recipients include: (1) increasing travel of transplanted patients to the tropics and subtropics;8, 12 and 13 (2) increasing population immigration from endemic areas for tropical infections to non-endemic settings;6, 14 and 15 (3) increasing numbers of transplantation procedures taking place in tropical countries;11, 16, 17, 18 and 19 and (4) many individuals traveling overseas for ‘transplant tourism’ in countries with high prevalence of tropical infectious diseases.20 and 21 In general, transmission of these infections occurs through three main routes: donor-derived infections,3, 4, 6, 15 and 22 reactivation or recrudescence of latent infections,16, 22, 23 and 24 or transmission de novo during the post-transplant period.4 and 16 Infectious pathogens may be carried by the graft or the infection may be acquired through transfusion of blood products during or after the transplantation.3, 4
2,859
<h4>antibiotic-resistance takes out defense</h4><p><strong>MacKenzie 13</strong> Debora MacKenzie 13 March 2013 New Scientist Antibiotic resistance an 'apocalyptic threat' http://www.newscientist.com/article/mg21729084.000-antibiotic-resistance-an-apocalyptic-threat.html </p><p><u><mark>ANTIBIOTIC resistance poses an "apocalyptic" threat to human health. We are facing "nightmare bacteria</u></mark>" and are losing a "war" against them. Such language, in statements made over the past week by the top UK and US medical authorities – normally a very cautious breed – reflects the enormity of the situation they feel we must now confront. In fact, <u><mark>our predicament is even worse</mark> than these words suggest, <mark>with antibiotic-resistant bacteria out of control</mark> in some areas.</u> What's more, New Scientist can reveal that effective new drugs may already exist – but are <strong>stuck in the final stages of development because they cannot overcome economic and regulatory hurdles. </p><p>Increasing reliance on the illegal market means the threat is serious</p><p>Franco-Paredes</strong> <strong>10 </strong> Carlos Franco-Paredes, Jesse T. Jacob. Alicia Hidrona, Alfonso J. Rodriguez-Morales,David Kuhara, and Angela M. Caliendoa all with Division of Infectious Diseases, Emory University School of Medicine except Redriguez-Morales at Division of Immunoparasitology, Tropical Medicine Institute, Universidad Central de Venezuela International Journal of Infectious Diseases Volume 14, Issue 3, March 2010, Pages e189–e196 Transplantation and tropical infectious diseases http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S1201971209002045</p><p><u><mark>More transplantation procedures are being performed annually, resulting in an increase in</mark> the number of <mark>immunocompromised hosts</u></mark>.1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 and 7 Most of the literature in infectious diseases in transplantation has focused on common pathogens prevalent in industrialized Western countries, where most transplantation surgeries occur.1, 2, 4, 5, 6 and 7 However, <u>in the last decade, <mark>there has been a growing identification of tropical infectious diseases occurring in transplant hosts in endemic and non-endemic settings</u></mark>.3, 4, 7, 8, 9, 10 and 11 <u><mark>The epidemiologic reasons</mark> for the growing number of reports of tropical infections appearing in transplant recipients <mark>include</u></mark>: (1) increasing travel of transplanted patients to the tropics and subtropics;8, 12 and 13 (2) increasing population immigration from endemic areas for tropical infections to non-endemic settings;6, 14 and 15 (3) <u><mark>increasing numbers of transplantation procedures taking place in tropical countries</u></mark>;11, 16, 17, 18 and 19 <u><mark>and</mark> (</u>4) <u>many individuals traveling overseas for ‘<mark>transplant tourism’</mark> in countries with high prevalence of tropical infectious diseases</u>.20 and 21 In general, transmission of these infections occurs through three main routes: donor-derived infections,3, 4, 6, 15 and 22 reactivation or recrudescence of latent infections,16, 22, 23 and 24 or transmission de novo during the post-transplant period.4 and 16 Infectious pathogens may be carried by the graft or the infection may be acquired through transfusion of blood products during or after the transplantation.3, 4</p>
null
null
Contention 2 is the Illegal market
430,319
6
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,331
Concede Kelly – it’s not about death – he says that analysis of power relations is necessary to reconstitute the self – they prevent that and leave the individual subservient to broader determinations of value which turns the aff
Salem 99
Salem 99 Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full
null
institutionalization of death has extended physicians’ role in regulating death doctors share end-of-life decisions and choices with patients and families one of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dyin medicalization of death, is so deeply embedded in our culture that it goes unnoticed The sway of medicine should not be understood as a Machiavellian strategy devised by doctors physicians themselves are under medicine's power and not always aware of their critical role in the cultural construction of death and dying Physician-assisted suicide is widely but incorrectly represented as a further step in the demedicalization of death begun by the patients’ rights movements It ultimately extends the power of physicians in regulating death, now under the guise of “assisting” suicide
There is a certain consensus that the institutionalization of death, its transference from the community to the hospital setting and its medicalization, has extended physicians’ role in regulating death. Today some 80 percent of deaths in the United States take place in health care facilities, while as recently as fifty years ago only a small minority of people died in hospitals or long-term care facilities. In the wake of the “right to die” movement, today in theory—and to some extent in actual practice—doctors share end-of-life decisions and choices with patients and families. In this sense, all contrive to consolidate “managed death” as the predominant way of dying in the United States. Indeed, the American Hospital Association reported that about 70 percent of deaths in the hospital occur after a decision has been made to withhold treatment.30 Despite the space ceded to patients’ autonomous choices, one of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dying. This intangible aspect of medicine's power, such a crucial facet of the medicalization of death, is so deeply embedded in our culture that it goes unnoticed. The sway of medicine should not be understood as a Machiavellian strategy devised by doctors to dominate various domains of contemporary life; physicians themselves are under medicine's power and not always aware of their critical role in the cultural construction of death and dying. There is a paradox in our attitude toward modern medicine: on the one hand, we criticize and wish to counterbalance medicine's power through the enhancement of the patient's autonomy, and on the other, we open up the doors for physicians in the domain of suicide. Yet from another perspective the paradox dissolves, when we recognize it as a facet of how thoroughly public conscience is imbued with medical ideology. Physician-assisted suicide is widely but incorrectly represented as a further step in the demedicalization of death begun by the patients’ rights and right to die movements. It ultimately extends the power of physicians in regulating death, now under the guise of “assisting” suicide.
2,230
<h4>Concede Kelly – it’s not about death – he says that analysis of power relations is necessary to reconstitute the self – they prevent that and leave the individual subservient to broader determinations of value which turns the aff</h4><p><strong>Salem 99</strong> Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full</p><p><strong>There is a certain consensus that</strong> the <strong><mark>institutionalization of death</strong></mark>, its transference from the community to the hospital setting and its medicalization, <strong><mark>has extended physicians’ role in regulating death</strong></mark>. Today some 80 percent of deaths in the United States take place in health care facilities, while as recently as fifty years ago only a small minority of people died in hospitals or long-term care facilities.</p><p><strong>In the wake of the “right to die” movement</strong>, today in theory—and to some extent in actual practice—<strong><mark>doctors share end-of-life decisions and choices with patients and families</strong></mark>. In this sense, all contrive to consolidate “managed death” as the predominant way of dying in the United States. Indeed, the American Hospital Association reported that about <strong>70 percent of deaths in the hospital occur after a decision has been made to withhold treatment</strong>.30</p><p>Despite the space ceded to patients’ autonomous choices, <strong><mark>one of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dyin</mark>g</strong>. This intangible aspect of medicine's power, such a crucial facet of the <strong><mark>medicalization of death, is so deeply embedded in our culture that it goes unnoticed</strong></mark>. <strong><mark>The sway of medicine should not be understood as a Machiavellian strategy devised by doctors</strong></mark> to dominate various domains of contemporary life; <strong><mark>physicians themselves are under medicine's power and not always aware of their critical role in the cultural construction of death and dying</strong></mark>.</p><p>There is a paradox in our attitude toward modern medicine: on the one hand, we criticize and wish to counterbalance medicine's power through the enhancement of the patient's autonomy, and on the other, we open up the doors for physicians in the domain of suicide. Yet from another perspective <strong>the paradox dissolves, when we recognize it as a facet of how thoroughly public conscience is imbued with medical ideology</strong>.</p><p><strong><mark>Physician-assisted suicide is widely but incorrectly represented as a further step in the demedicalization of death begun by the patients’ rights</mark> and right to die <mark>movements</mark>. <mark>It ultimately extends the power of physicians in regulating death, now under the guise of “assisting” suicide</strong></mark>.</p>
null
null
Case
430,351
7
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,332
Ableism makes ongoing eugenics and extermination inevitable—complexity and diversity are erased in the name of purifying society into a state of sameness. That’s Brown.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><strong>Ableism makes <u>ongoing eugenics and extermination inevitable</u>—complexity and diversity are erased in the name of purifying society into a state of sameness. That’s Brown. </h4></strong>
Ableism
Impact
2NC K
430,655
1
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,333
They say offshoring
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>They say offshoring</h4>
WTO
Banks
AT: Inevitable
430,656
1
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,334
Worst climate impacts take decades to arrive and don’t assume adaptation
Mendelsohn 9
Robert O. Mendelsohn 9, the Edwin Weyerhaeuser Davis Professor, Yale School of Forestry and Environmental Studies, Yale University, June 2009, “Climate Change and Economic Growth,” online: http://www.growthcommission.org/storage/cgdev/documents/gcwp060web.pdf
Proponents argue that there is no time to waste ). These statements are largely alarmist and misleading society’s immediate behavior has an extremely low probability of leading to catastrophic conse- quences. emissions over the next few decades will lead to only mild consequences severe impacts predicted by alarmists require a century (or two of no mitigation acts assume that there will be no or little adaptation. Most of the more severe impacts will take more than a century or millennium and many of these will never occur because people will adapt. It is not at all apparent that immediate and dramatic policies need to be develope
that there is no time to wast are largely alarmist and misleading immediate behavior has an extremely low probability of leading to catastrophic conse- quences emissions over decades will lead to only mild consequences severe impacts require a century (or two no mitigation impacts assume no adaptation severe impacts will take more than a century or millennium and will never occur because people adapt
The heart of the debate about climate change comes from numerous warnings from scientists and others that give the impression that human- induced climate change is an immediate threat to society (IPCC 2007a, 2007c; Stern 2006). Millions of people might be vulnerable to health effects (IPCC 2007a), crop production might fall in the low latitudes (IPCC 2007a), water supplies might dwindle (IPCC 2007a), precipitation might fall in arid regions (IPCC 2007a), extreme events will grow exponentially (Stern 2006), and between 20 and 30 percent of species will risk extinction (IPCC 2007a). Even worse, there may be catastrophic events such as the melting of Greenland or Antarctic ice sheets, causing severe sea-level rise, which would inundate hundreds of millions of people (Dasgupta and others 2009). Proponents argue that there is no time to waste. Unless greenhouse gases are cut dramatically today, economic growth and well-being may be at risk (Stern 2006). These statements are largely alarmist and misleading. Although climate change is a serious problem that deserves attention, society’s immediate behavior has an extremely low probability of leading to catastrophic conse- quences. The science and economics of climate change are quite clear that emissions over the next few decades will lead to only mild consequences. The severe impacts predicted by alarmists require a century (or two, accord- ing to Stern 2006) of no mitigation. Many of the predicted impacts assume that there will be no or little adaptation. The net economic impacts from climate change over the next 50 years will be small regardless. Most of the more severe impacts will take more than a century or even a millennium to unfold, and many of these “potential” impacts will never occur because people will adapt. It is not at all apparent that immediate and dramatic policies need to be developed to thwart long-range climate risks. What is needed are long-run balanced responses.
1,962
<h4>Worst climate impacts take decades to arrive and don’t assume adaptation</h4><p>Robert O. <strong>Mendelsohn 9</strong>, the Edwin Weyerhaeuser Davis Professor, Yale School of Forestry and Environmental Studies, Yale University, June 2009, “Climate Change and Economic Growth,” online: http://www.growthcommission.org/storage/cgdev/documents/gcwp060web.pdf</p><p>The heart of the debate about climate change comes from numerous warnings from scientists and others that give the impression that human- induced climate change is an immediate threat to society (IPCC 2007a, 2007c; Stern 2006). Millions of people might be vulnerable to health effects (IPCC 2007a), crop production might fall in the low latitudes (IPCC 2007a), water supplies might dwindle (IPCC 2007a), precipitation might fall in arid regions (IPCC 2007a), extreme events will grow exponentially (Stern 2006), and between 20 and 30 percent of species will risk extinction (IPCC 2007a). Even worse, there may be catastrophic events such as the melting of Greenland or Antarctic ice sheets, causing severe sea-level rise, which would inundate hundreds of millions of people (Dasgupta and others 2009). <u>Proponents argue <mark>that there is no time to wast</mark>e</u>. Unless greenhouse gases are cut dramatically today, economic growth and well-being may be at risk (Stern 2006<u>). These statements <mark>are largely alarmist and misleading</u></mark>. Although climate change is a serious problem that deserves attention, <u>society’s <mark>immediate behavior has an</u> <u><strong>extremely low probability</u></strong> <u>of leading to</mark> <mark>catastrophic conse- quences</mark>.</u> The science and economics of climate change are quite clear that <u><mark>emissions over</mark> the next few <mark>decades will lead to only mild consequences</u></mark>. The <u><mark>severe impacts</mark> predicted by alarmists <mark>require</u> <u><strong>a century (or two</u></strong></mark>, accord- ing to Stern 2006) <u>of <mark>no mitigation</u></mark>. Many of the predicted <mark>imp<u>acts assume</mark> that there will be <mark>no</mark> or little <mark>adaptation</mark>. </u>The net economic impacts from climate change over the next 50 years will be small regardless. <u>Most of the more <mark>severe impacts will take more than a century or</u></mark> even a <u><mark>millennium</u></mark> to unfold, <u><mark>and</mark> many of these</u> “potential” impacts <u><mark>will never occur because people</mark> will <mark>adapt</mark>. It is not at all apparent that immediate and dramatic policies need to be develope</u>d to thwart long-range climate risks. What is needed are long-run balanced responses.</p>
2AC
Politics DA
TPA – 2AC – NDT
45,412
381
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,335
Trade war articles are hype – zero risk – China doesn’t retaliate
Alden 12
Edward Alden, Bernard L. Schwartz Senior Fellow at the Council on Foreign Relations, 10/31/12, A U.S.-China “Trade War”: Time to Abolish a Silly Notion, thediplomat.com/pacific-money/2012/10/31/a-u-s-china-trade-war-time-to-abolish-a-silly-notion/
it is time to bury the concept of a “trade war The phrase is so ubiquitous it is almost a reflex that every time the U S takes any action that restricts imports in any fashion, reporters jump to their keyboards to warn that a trade war is looming. it is a canard The closest historical example is Smoot-Hawley what are the chances of a “trade war zero for two big reasons in 1930, there was no W T O no N A F T A no E U – in short, no rules Today unilateral action is largely forbidden tit-for-tat measures we have seen have all been taken within the framework of WTO rules When Obama curbed purchases of Chinese steel China responded with an “anti-dumping” case the U S challenged that action in the WTO No trade war instead see you in court every nation in the world seems fully aware of the dangers of aggressive protectionism trade plunging by 12 percent in 2009 the biggest drop since World War II is how little protectionism that is permitted under WTO rules actually occurred no trade war – just an unfavorable WTO decision a administration would quickly comply. The “trade war” threat stifles reasonable debate, because every trade action – however modest — is assumed to cause a self-destructive over-reaction
it is time to bury the concept of a “trade war what are the chances of a “trade war” zero in 1930, there was no W T O N A F T A E U no rules Today tit-for-tat measures have all been within WTO rules China responded with anti-dumping the U S challenged that action No war – instead court every nation seems aware of the dangers of aggressive protectionism every trade action is assumed to cause self-destructive over-reaction
I have a suggestion for everyone who writes about international trade: it is time to bury, once and for all, the concept of a “trade war.” The phrase is so ubiquitous that it will be awfully hard to abolish; I have probably been guilty of this myself from time to time. Indeed, it is almost a reflex that every time the United States or some other nation takes any action that restricts imports in any fashion, reporters and editorial writers jump to their keyboards to warn that a trade war is looming. But it is a canard that makes it far harder to have a sensible discussion about U.S. trade policy. No sooner had President Obama and Mitt Romney finished their latest round of “who’s tougher on trade with China?” in their final debate than the New York Times – to take one of many possible examples – warned that “formally citing Beijing as a currency manipulator may backfire, economic and foreign-policy experts have said. In the worst case, it could set off a trade war, leading to falling American exports to China and more expensive Chinese imports.” But what exactly is a “trade war”? To take the U.S.-China example, the notion seems to be that, if the United States restricts Chinese imports, China will respond by restricting imports of U.S. goods, in turn leading to further U.S. restrictions and so on and so on until trade between the two countries plummets. The closest historical example is the reaction to the infamous Smoot-Hawley tariff act of 1930, which raised the average U.S. tariff on imports to historically high levels. As trade historian Douglas Irwin of Dartmouth has shown persuasively, Smoot-Hawley did not cause the Great Depression, and probably did not even exacerbate it very much since trade was a tiny part of the U.S. economy. But Smoot-Hawley did result in Great Britain, Canada and other U.S. trading partners raising their own tariffs in response. Irwin suggests that the higher tariffs were probably responsible for about a third of the 40 percent drop in imports between 1929 and 1932, and perhaps a slightly higher percentage of export losses. And the new trade barriers put in place took many decades to dismantle. With imports and exports today comprising roughly a third of the U.S. economy, and the few remaining tariffs mostly in the single digits, the consequences of similar tit-for-tat tariff increases today would be far more severe. But what are the chances of such a “trade war” actually occurring? Pretty close to zero, for two big reasons. First, in 1930, there was no World Trade Organization, no North American Free Trade Agreement, no European Community/Union – in short, no rules to prevent countries from jacking up tariffs or imposing quotas whenever governments felt domestic political pressure to do so. Today, such unilateral action is largely forbidden. Indeed, the tit-for-tat measures we have seen in the U.S.-China trade relationship have all been taken within the framework of WTO rules. When the Obama administration curbed purchases of Chinese steel in 2009 under the “Buy America” provisions of the stimulus, for example, China responded with an “anti-dumping” case which led to tariffs on imports of U.S. steel. But the United States challenged that action in the WTO, and earlier this month the WTO ordered China to lift the duties. No trade war – instead the phrase “see you in court” comes to mind. Secondly, almost every nation in the world seems fully aware of the dangers of aggressive protectionism. One of the striking things about the Great Recession– which resulted in global trade volumes plunging by more than 12 percent in 2009, the biggest drop since World War II – is how little of the protectionism that is permitted under WTO rules actually occurred. Chad Bown of the World Bank has documented the surprising low level of new trade barriers imposed during the recession and its aftermath. The danger of competitive currency devaluations – which are not clearly covered under WTO rules – is a greater threat than tariffs. This is one of the reasons that Romney’s pledge to label China a currency manipulator could be playing with fire, particularly after more than seven years in which the value of the renminbi has been creeping up steadily against the dollar. And his suggestion that the United States would impose tariffs in response is just silly – it would be a blatant violation of WTO rules and would quickly be slapped down as such. Again, however, no trade war – just an unfavorable WTO decision with which a Romney administration would quickly comply. The real questions about trade restrictions should be practical ones – are the gains to the economy worth the costs? Generally, the answer is no, because free competition is a good thing for consumers and competitive businesses. But sometimes protecting a viable domestic industry temporarily against a flood of low-priced imports makes sense, which is why the WTO has rules permitting temporary safeguards. Sometimes foreign subsidies make fair competition impossible, which is why the WTO permits tariffs against dumped or subsidized imports. Such actions raise prices for U.S. consumers, but may still on balance bring benefits to the U.S. economy. The “trade war” threat stifles reasonable debate, because every trade action – however modest — is assumed to cause a self-destructive over-reaction by trading partners. So I hereby pledge to abolish the phrase from all my future writings on the subject. I hope others will do the same.
5,491
<h4>Trade war articles are hype – zero risk – China doesn’t retaliate</h4><p>Edward <strong>Alden</strong>, Bernard L. Schwartz Senior Fellow at the Council on Foreign Relations, 10/31/<strong>12</strong>, A U.S.-China “Trade War”: Time to Abolish a Silly Notion, thediplomat.com/pacific-money/2012/10/31/a-u-s-china-trade-war-time-to-abolish-a-silly-notion/</p><p>I have a suggestion for everyone who writes about international trade: <u><mark>it is time to bury</u></mark>, once and for all, <u><mark>the concept of a “trade war</u></mark>.” <u>The phrase is so ubiquitous </u>that it will be awfully hard to abolish; I have probably been guilty of this myself from time to time. Indeed, <u>it is</u> <u>almost a reflex that every time the U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates or some other nation <u>takes any action that restricts imports in any fashion, reporters</u> and editorial writers <u>jump to their keyboards to warn that a trade war is looming.</u> But <u>it is a canard</u> that makes it far harder to have a sensible discussion about U.S. trade policy. No sooner had President Obama and Mitt Romney finished their latest round of “who’s tougher on trade with China?” in their final debate than the New York Times – to take one of many possible examples – warned that “formally citing Beijing as a currency manipulator may backfire, economic and foreign-policy experts have said. In the worst case, it could set off a trade war, leading to falling American exports to China and more expensive Chinese imports.” But what exactly is a “trade war”? To take the U.S.-China example, the notion seems to be that, if the United States restricts Chinese imports, China will respond by restricting imports of U.S. goods, in turn leading to further U.S. restrictions and so on and so on until trade between the two countries plummets. <u>The closest historical example is</u> the reaction to the infamous <u>Smoot-Hawley</u> tariff act of 1930, which raised the average U.S. tariff on imports to historically high levels. As trade historian Douglas Irwin of Dartmouth has shown persuasively, Smoot-Hawley did not cause the Great Depression, and probably did not even exacerbate it very much since trade was a tiny part of the U.S. economy. But Smoot-Hawley did result in Great Britain, Canada and other U.S. trading partners raising their own tariffs in response. Irwin suggests that the higher tariffs were probably responsible for about a third of the 40 percent drop in imports between 1929 and 1932, and perhaps a slightly higher percentage of export losses. And the new trade barriers put in place took many decades to dismantle. With imports and exports today comprising roughly a third of the U.S. economy, and the few remaining tariffs mostly in the single digits, the consequences of similar tit-for-tat tariff increases today would be far more severe. But <u><mark>what are the chances of</u></mark> such <u><mark>a “trade war</u>”</mark> actually occurring? Pretty close to <u><strong><mark>zero</u></strong></mark>, <u>for two big reasons</u>. First, <u><mark>in 1930, there was no W</u></mark>orld <u><mark>T</u></mark>rade <u><mark>O</u></mark>rganization, <u>no <mark>N</u></mark>orth <u><mark>A</u></mark>merican <u><mark>F</u></mark>ree <u><mark>T</u></mark>rade <u><mark>A</u></mark>greement, <u>no <mark>E</u></mark>uropean Community/<u><mark>U</u></mark>nion <u>– in short, <mark>no rules</u></mark> to prevent countries from jacking up tariffs or imposing quotas whenever governments felt domestic political pressure to do so. <u><mark>Today</u></mark>, such <u>unilateral action is largely forbidden</u>. Indeed, the <u><mark>tit-for-tat measures</mark> we have seen</u> in the U.S.-China trade relationship <u><mark>have all been</mark> taken <mark>within</mark> the framework of <mark>WTO rules</u></mark>. <u>When</u> the <u>Obama</u> administration <u>curbed purchases of Chinese steel</u> in 2009 under the “Buy America” provisions of the stimulus, for example, <u><mark>China responded with</mark> an “<mark>anti-dumping</mark>” case</u> which led to tariffs on imports of U.S. steel. But <u><mark>the U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates <u><mark>challenged that action</mark> in the WTO</u>, and earlier this month the WTO ordered China to lift the duties. <u><mark>No</mark> trade <mark>war</u> – <u>instead</u></mark> the phrase “<u>see you in <mark>court</u></mark>” comes to mind. Secondly, almost <u><mark>every nation</mark> in the world <mark>seems</mark> fully <mark>aware of the dangers of aggressive protectionism</u></mark>. One of the striking things about the Great Recession– which resulted in global <u>trade</u> volumes <u>plunging by</u> more than <u>12 percent in 2009</u>, <u>the biggest drop since World War II</u> – <u>is how little</u> of the <u>protectionism that is permitted under WTO rules actually occurred</u>. Chad Bown of the World Bank has documented the surprising low level of new trade barriers imposed during the recession and its aftermath. The danger of competitive currency devaluations – which are not clearly covered under WTO rules – is a greater threat than tariffs. This is one of the reasons that Romney’s pledge to label China a currency manipulator could be playing with fire, particularly after more than seven years in which the value of the renminbi has been creeping up steadily against the dollar. And his suggestion that the United States would impose tariffs in response is just silly – it would be a blatant violation of WTO rules and would quickly be slapped down as such. Again, however, <u>no trade war – just an unfavorable WTO decision</u> with which <u>a</u> Romney <u>administration would quickly comply. </u>The real questions about trade restrictions should be practical ones – are the gains to the economy worth the costs? Generally, the answer is no, because free competition is a good thing for consumers and competitive businesses. But sometimes protecting a viable domestic industry temporarily against a flood of low-priced imports makes sense, which is why the WTO has rules permitting temporary safeguards. Sometimes foreign subsidies make fair competition impossible, which is why the WTO permits tariffs against dumped or subsidized imports. Such actions raise prices for U.S. consumers, but may still on balance bring benefits to the U.S. economy. <u>The “trade war” threat stifles reasonable debate, because <mark>every trade action</mark> – however modest — <mark>is assumed to cause</mark> a <mark>self-destructive over-reaction</u></mark> by trading partners. So I hereby pledge to abolish the phrase from all my future writings on the subject. I hope others will do the same.</p>
null
null
AT: China Trade War
39,143
61
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,336
Planning for the future is futile. Only embracing the negativity projected onto the queer reveals the recurring violence of reproductive futurism. Refuse futurism to set the queer free of the figural Child, and the violent future it both replicates and intends.
Edelman ’04 , p. 2-7
Edelman ’04, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, p. 2-7
But what helped him most in these public appeals on behalf of children is impossible to refuse. logic compels us to submit to the framing of political debate as defined by the terms of what this book describes as reproductive futurism: terms that , impose an ideological limit on political discourse as such, preserving in the process the absolute privilege of heteronormativity by rendering un thinkable, by casting outside the political domain, the possibility of a queer resistance to this organizing principle of communal relations. however radical the means by which specific constituencies attempt to produce a more desirable social order, remains conservative insofar as it works to affirm a structure, to authenticate social order, which it then intends to transmit to the future in the form of its inner Child That Child remains the perpetual horizon of every acknowledged politics, the fantasmatic beneficiary of every political intervention. ow could one take the other ‘side,” when taking any side at all necessarily constrains one to take the side by virtue of taking a side within, a political order that returns to the Child as the image of the future it intends queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children,” the side outside the consensus by which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism queerness attains its ethical value precisely insofar as it accedes to that place, accepting its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure. the pervasive invocation of the Child as the emblem of futurity’s unquestioned value and propose against it the impossible project of queer oppositionality that would oppose itself to the structural determinants of politics as such, which is also to say, that would oppose itself to the logic of opposition. This paradoxical formulation suggests a refusal Far from partaking of this narrative movement toward a viable political future, far from per perpetuating the fantasy of meaning’s eventual realization, the queer comes to figure the bar to every realization of futurity, the resistance, internal to the social, to every social structure or form. Rather than rejecting, with liberal discourse, this ascription of negativity to the queer, we might do better to consider accepting and even embracing it. Not in the hope of forging thereby some more perfect social order such a hope, after all, would only reproduce the constraining mandate of futurism, just as any such order would equally occasion the negativity of the queer but rather to refuse the insistence of hope itself as affirmation, which is always affirmation of an order whose refusal will register as unthinkable, irresponsible, inhumane And the trump card of affirmation Always the question: if not this, what? — I do not intend to propose some “good” that will thereby be assured , I mean to insist that nothing, and certainly not what we call the “good,” can ever have any assurance at all in the order of the Symbolic The structuring optimism of politics to which the order of meaning commits us, installing as it does the perpetual hope of reaching meaning through signification, is always, I would argue, a negation of this primal, constitutive, and negative act taking the Symbolic’s negativity to the very letter of the law attending to the persistence of something internal to reason that reason refuses turning the force of queerness against all subjects, however queer, can afford an access to the jouissance that at once defines and negates us Or better: can expose the constancy, the inescapability, of such access to jouissance in the social order itself; even if that order can access its constant access to jouissance only in the process of abjecting that constancy of access onto the queer. does not have the character of a universal law but, on the contrary, of the most particular of laws —even if it is universal that this particularity is to be found in every human being.’ The embrace of queer negativity, then, can have no justification if justification requires it to reinforce some positive social value; its value, instead, resides in its challenge to value as defined by the social by figuring a refusal of the coercive belief in the paramount value of futurity the queer dispossesses the social order of the ground on which it rests: a faith in the consistent reality of the social—and by extension, of the social subject; a faith that politics, whether of the left or of the right, implicitly affirms , the queer insists that politics is always a politics of the signifier, or even of what Lacan will often refer to as “the letter It serves to shore up a reality always unmoored by signification and lacking any guarantee To say as much is not, of course, to deny the experiential violence that frequently troubles social reality or the apparent consistency with which it bears us al . It is to suggest that queerness exposes the obliquity of our relation to what we experience in and as social reality, alerting us to the fantasies structurally necessary in order to sustain it and engaging those fantasies through the figural logics, the linguistic structures that shape them. queer theory must always insist on its connection to the vicissitudes of the sign, to the tension between the signifier’s collapse into the letter’s cadaverous materiality and its participation in a system of reference wherein it generates meaning itself one that takes both the value and the burden of that failure upon itself, queer theory marks the “other” side of politics: the “side” where narrative realization and derealization overlap, where the energies of vitalization ceaselessly turn against themselves; the “side” outside all political sides, committed as they are, on every side, to futurism’s unquestioned good
appeal on behalf of children is impossible to refuse terms of reproductive futurism: impose an ideological limit on political discourse as such, preserving the absolute privilege of heteronormativity , by casting outside the political domain, queer resistance to this principle . politics however radical the attempt to produce a more desirable social order remains conservative insofar as it works to authenticate social order, to transmit to the future That Child remains the perpetual horizon of every acknowledged politics How could one take the other ‘side,” when taking any side returns to the Child as the image of the future it intends queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children queerness attains its ethical value insofar as it accept its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure. the impossible project of queer oppositionality would oppose itself to the logic of opposition Rather than rejecting, this ascription of negativity to the queer, we might consider embracing it. Not in the hope of forging some more perfect social order such hope would only reproduce the mandate of futurism, but rather to refuse the insistence of hope itself as affirmation, which is always affirmation of an order whose refusal will register as unthinkable, irresponsible, inhumane structuring optimism of politics , is always, a negation of this primal, constitutive, and negative act taking the Symbolic’s negativity can expose , the inescapability, of such access to jouissance in the social order itself; order can access jouissance only in the process of abjecting that constancy onto the queer. . The embrace of queer negativity can have no justification if justification requires it to reinforce some positive social value; its value, resides in its challenge to value as defined by the social by figuring a refusal in the value of futurity the queer dispossesses the social order of the ground on which it rests: a faith in the consistent reality of the social subject that politics affirms queer theory marks the “other” side of politics: the “side” outside all political sides, committed as they are, on every side, to futurism’s unquestioned good
But what helped him most in these public appeals on behalf of America’s children was the social consensus that such an appeal is impossible to refuse. Indeed, though these public service announcements concluded with the sort of rhetorical flourish associated with hard-fought political campaigns (“We’re fighting for the children. Whose side are you on”), that rhetoric was intended to avow that this issue, like an ideological Möbius strip, only permitted one side. Such “self-evident” one-sidedness— the affirmation of a value so unquestioned, because so obviously unquestionable, as that of the Child whose innocence solicits our defense— is precisely, of course, what distinguishes public service announcements from the partisan discourse of political argumentation. But it is also, I suggest, what makes such announcements so oppressively political— political not in the partisan terms implied by the media consultant, but political in a far more insidious way: political insofar as the fantasy sub- tending the image of the Child invariably shapes the logic within which the political itself must be thought. That logic compels us, to the extent that we would register as politically responsible, to submit to the framing of political debate —and, indeed, of the political field—as defined by the terms of what this book describes as reproductive futurism: terms that , impose an ideological limit on political discourse as such, preserving in the process the absolute privilege of heteronormativity by rendering un thinkable, by casting outside the political domain, the possibility of a queer resistance to this organizing principle of communal relations. For politics, however radical the means by which specific constituencies attempt to produce a more desirable social order, remains, at its core, conservative insofar as it works to affirm a structure, to authenticate social order, which it then intends to transmit to the future in the form of its inner Child. That Child remains the perpetual horizon of every acknowledged politics, the fantasmatic beneficiary of every political intervention. Even proponents of abortion rights, while promoting the freedom of women to control their own bodies through reproductive choice, recurrently frame their political struggle, mirroring their anti-abortion foes, as a “fight for our children — for our daughters and our sons,” and thus as a fight for the future.’ What, in that case, would it signify not to be “fighting for the children” How could one take the other ‘side,” when taking any side at all necessarily constrains one to take the side by virtue of taking a side within, a political order that returns to the Child as the image of the future it intends? Impossibly, against all reasons my project stakes its claim w the very space that politics” makes unthinkable: the space outside the framework within which politics as we know it appears and so outside the conflict of visions that share as their pre supposition that the body politic must survive. Indeed, at the heart of my polemical engagement with the cultural text of politics and the politics of cultural texts lies a simple provocation: that queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children,” the side outside the consensus by which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism. The ups and downs of political fortune may measure the social order’s pulse, but queerness, by contrast, figures, outside and beyond its political symptoms, the place of the social order’s death drive: a place, to be sure, of abjection expressed in the stigma, sometimes fatal, that follows from reading that figure literally, and hence a place from which liberal politics strives—and strives quite reasonably, given its unlimited faith in reason—to disassociate the queer. More radically, though, as I argue here, queerness attains its ethical value precisely insofar as it accedes to that place, accepting its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure. To make such a claim I examine in this book the pervasive invocation of the Child as the emblem of futurity’s unquestioned value and propose against it the impossible project of queer oppositionality that would oppose itself to the structural determinants of politics as such, which is also to say, that would oppose itself to the logic of opposition. This paradoxical formulation suggests a refusal —the appropriately perverse refusal that characterizes queer theory—of every substantialization of identity, which is always oppositionally defined and, by extension, of history as linear narrative (the poor man’s teleology) in which meaning succeeds in revealing itself—as itself—through time. Far from partaking of this narrative movement toward a viable political future, far from per perpetuating the fantasy of meaning’s eventual realization, the queer comes to figure the bar to every realization of futurity, the resistance, internal to the social, to every social structure or form. Rather than rejecting, with liberal discourse, this ascription of negativity to the queer, we might, as I argue, do better to consider accepting and even embracing it. Not in the hope of forging thereby some more perfect social order—such a hope, after all, would only reproduce the constraining mandate of futurism, just as any such order would equally occasion the negativity of the queer—but rather to refuse the insistence of hope itself as affirmation, which is always affirmation of an order whose refusal will register as unthinkable, irresponsible, inhumane. And the trump card of affirmation? Always the question: if not this, what? Always the demand to translate the insistence, the pulsive force, of negativity into some determinate stance or “position” whose determination would thus negate it: always the imperative to immure it in some stable and positive form. When I argue, then, that we might do well to attempt what is surely impossible — to withdraw our allegiance, however compulsory, from a reality based on the Ponzi scheme of reproductive futurism— I do not intend to propose some “good” that will thereby be assured. To toe contrary, I mean to insist that nothing, and certainly not what we call the “good,” can ever have any assurance at all in the order of the Symbolic. Abjuring fidelity to a futurism that’s always purchased at our expense, though bound, as Symbolic subjects consigned to figure the Symbolic’s undoing, to the necessary contradiction of trying to turn its intelligibility against itself, we might rather, figuratively, cast our vote for “none of the above,” for the primacy of a constant no in response to the law of the Symbolic, which would echo that law’s foundational act, its self- constituting negation. The structuring optimism of politics to which the order of meaning commits us, installing as it does the perpetual hope of reaching meaning through signification, is always, I would argue, a negation of this primal, constitutive, and negative act. And the various positivities produced in its wake by the logic of political hope depend on the mathematical illusion that negated negations might somehow escape, and not redouble, such negativity. My polemic thus stakes its fortunes on a truly hopeless wager: that taking the Symbolic’s negativity to the very letter of the law, that attending to the persistence of something internal to reason that reason refuses, that turning the force of queerness against all subjects, however queer, can afford an access to the jouissance that at once defines and negates us. Or better: can expose the constancy, the inescapability, of such access to jouissance in the social order itself; even if that order can access its constant access to jouissance only in the process of abjecting that constancy of access onto the queer. In contrast to what Theodor Adorno describes as the “grimness with which a man clings to himself, as to the immediately sure and substantial,” the queerness of which I speak would deliberately sever us from ourselves, from the assurance, that is, of knowing ourselves and hence of knowing our “good.”4 Such queerness proposes, in place of the good, something I want to call “better,” though it promises, in more than one sense of the phrase, absolutely nothing. ¡ connect this something better with Lacan’s characterization of what he calls “truth,” where truth does not assure happiness, or even, as Lacan makes clear, the good.5 Instead, it names only the insistent particularity of the subject, impossible fully to articulate and “tend[ing] toward the real.” Lacan, therefore, can write of this truth: The quality that best characterizes it is that of being the true Wunsch, which was at the origin of an aberrant or atypical behavior. We encounter this Wunsch with its particular, irreducible character as a modification that presupposes no other form of normalization than that of an experience of pleasure or of pain, but of a final experience from whence it springs and is subsequently preserved in the depths of the subject in an irreducible form. The Wunsch does not have the character of a universal law but, on the contrary, of the most particular of laws —even if it is universal that this particularity is to be found in every human being.’ Truth, like queerness, irreducibly linked to the “aberrant or atypical,” to what chafes against “normalization,” finds its value not in a good susceptible to generalization, but only in the stubborn particularity that voids every notion of a general good. The embrace of queer negativity, then, can have no justification if justification requires it to reinforce some positive social value; its value, instead, resides in its challenge to value as defined by the social, and thus in its radical challenge to the very value of the social itself. For by figuring a refusal of the coercive belief in the paramount value of futurity, while refusing as well any backdoor hope for dialectical access to meaning, the queer dispossesses the social order of the ground on which it rests: a faith in the consistent reality of the social—and by extension, of the social subject; a faith that politics, whether of the left or of the right, implicitly affirms. Divesting such politics of its thematic trappings, bracketing the particularity of its various proposals for social organization, the queer insists that politics is always a politics of the signifier, or even of what Lacan will often refer to as “the letter’ It serves to shore up a reality always unmoored by signification and lacking any guarantee. To say as much is not, of course, to deny the experiential violence that frequently troubles social reality or the apparent consistency with which it bears—and thereby bears down on— us all. It is, rather, to suggest that queerness exposes the obliquity of our relation to what we experience in and as social reality, alerting us to the fantasies structurally necessary in order to sustain it and engaging those fantasies through the figural logics, the linguistic structures that shape them. If it aims effectively to intervene in the reproduction of such a reality—an intervention that may well take the form of figuring that reality’s abortion— then queer theory must always insist on its connection to the vicissitudes of the sign, to the tension between the signifier’s collapse into the letter’s cadaverous materiality and its participation in a system of reference wherein it generates meaning itself. As a particular story, in other words, of why storytelling tells, one that takes both the value and the burden of that failure upon itself, queer theory, as I construe it, marks the “other” side of politics: the “side” where narrative realization and derealization overlap, where the energies of vitalization ceaselessly turn against themselves; the “side” outside all political sides, committed as they are, on every side, to futurism’s unquestioned good. The rest of this book attempts to explain the implications of this assertion, but first, let me sketch some connections between politics and the politics of the sign by establishing the psychoanalytic context within which my argument takes shape.
12,279
<h4>Planning for the future is futile. Only embracing the negativity projected onto the queer reveals the recurring violence of reproductive futurism. Refuse futurism to set the queer free of the figural Child, and the violent future it both replicates and intends. </h4><p><strong>Edelman ’04</strong>, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive<u><strong>, p. 2-7</p><p></strong>But what helped him most in these public <mark>appeal</mark>s<mark> on behalf of</u></mark> America’s <u><mark>children</u></mark> was the social consensus that such an appeal <u><mark>is impossible to refuse</mark>.</u> Indeed, though these public service announcements concluded with the sort of rhetorical flourish associated with hard-fought political campaigns (“We’re fighting for the children. Whose side are you on”), that rhetoric was intended to avow that this issue, like an ideological Möbius strip, only permitted one side. Such “self-evident” one-sidedness— the affirmation of a value so unquestioned, because so obviously unquestionable, as that of the Child whose innocence solicits our defense— is precisely, of course, what distinguishes public service announcements from the partisan discourse of political argumentation. But it is also, I suggest, what makes such announcements so oppressively political— political not in the partisan terms implied by the media consultant, but political in a far more insidious way: political insofar as the fantasy sub- tending the image of the Child invariably shapes the logic within which the political itself must be thought. That <u>logic compels us</u>, to the extent that we would register as politically responsible, <u><strong>to submit to the framing of political debate</u></strong> —and, indeed, of the political field—<u>as defined by the <mark>terms of</mark> what this book describes as <strong><mark>reproductive futurism: </mark>terms that , <mark>impose an ideological limit on political discourse as such, preserving </mark>in the process <mark>the absolute privilege of heteronormativity </mark>by rendering un thinkable<mark>, by casting outside the political domain, </mark>the possibility of a <mark>queer resistance to this</mark> organizing <mark>principle</mark> of communal relations<mark>.</p><p></u></strong></mark>For <mark>politics</mark>, <u><mark>however radical the </mark>means by which specific constituencies <mark>attempt to produce a more desirable social order</mark>, <mark>remains</u></mark>, at its core, <u><mark>conservative insofar as it works to</mark> affirm a structure, to <mark>authenticate social order, </mark>which it then intends <mark>to transmit to the future</mark> in the form of its inner Child</u>. <u><mark>That Child remains the perpetual horizon of every acknowledged politics</mark>, the fantasmatic beneficiary of every political intervention.</u> Even proponents of abortion rights, while promoting the freedom of women to control their own bodies through reproductive choice, recurrently frame their political struggle, mirroring their anti-abortion foes, as a “fight for our children — for our daughters and our sons,” and thus as a fight for the future.’ What, in that case, would it signify not to be “fighting for the children” <mark>H<u>ow could one take the other ‘side,” when taking any side</mark> at all necessarily constrains one to take the side by virtue of taking a side within, a political order that <mark>returns to the Child as the image of the future it intends</u></mark>? Impossibly, against all reasons my project stakes its claim w the very space that politics” makes unthinkable: the space outside the framework within which politics as we know it appears and so outside the conflict of visions that share as their pre supposition that the body politic must survive. Indeed, at the heart of my polemical engagement with the cultural text of politics and the politics of cultural texts lies a simple provocation: that <u><mark>queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children</mark>,” the side outside the consensus by which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism</u>. The ups and downs of political fortune may measure the social order’s pulse, but queerness, by contrast, figures, outside and beyond its political symptoms, the place of the social order’s death drive: a place, to be sure, of abjection expressed in the stigma, sometimes fatal, that follows from reading that figure literally, and hence a place from which liberal politics strives—and strives quite reasonably, given its unlimited faith in reason—to disassociate the queer. More radically, though, as I argue here, <u><mark>queerness attains its ethical value</mark> precisely <mark>insofar as it</mark> accedes to that place, <mark>accept</mark>ing <mark>its</mark> <mark>figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure.</mark> </p><p></u>To make such a claim I examine in this book <u>the pervasive invocation of the Child as the emblem of futurity’s unquestioned value and propose against it<mark> the impossible project of queer oppositionality</mark> that would oppose itself to the structural determinants of politics as such, which is also to say, that <mark>would oppose itself to the logic of opposition</mark>. This paradoxical formulation suggests a refusal</u> —the appropriately perverse refusal that characterizes queer theory—of every substantialization of identity, which is always oppositionally defined and, by extension, of history as linear narrative (the poor man’s teleology) in which meaning succeeds in revealing itself—as itself—through time. <u>Far from partaking of this narrative movement toward a viable political future, far from per perpetuating the fantasy of meaning’s eventual realization, the queer comes to figure the bar to every realization of futurity, the resistance, internal to the social, to every social structure or form. </p><p><strong><mark>Rather than rejecting, </mark>with liberal discourse, <mark>this ascription of negativity to the queer, we might</u></strong></mark>, as I argue, <u><strong>do better to <mark>consider </mark>accepting and even <mark>embracing it.</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>Not in the hope of forging </mark>thereby <mark>some more perfect social order</u></mark>—<u><mark>such</mark> a <mark>hope</mark>, after all, <mark>would only reproduce the</mark> constraining <mark>mandate of futurism,</mark> just as any such order would equally occasion the negativity of the queer</u>—<u><strong><mark>but rather to refuse the insistence of hope itself as affirmation, which is always affirmation of an order whose refusal will register as unthinkable, irresponsible, inhumane</u></strong></mark>. <u>And the trump card of affirmation</u>? <u>Always the question: if not this, what?</u> Always the demand to translate the insistence, the pulsive force, of negativity into some determinate stance or “position” whose determination would thus negate it: always the imperative to immure it in some stable and positive form. When I argue, then, that we might do well to attempt what is surely impossible — to withdraw our allegiance, however compulsory, from a reality based on the Ponzi scheme of reproductive futurism<u>— I do not intend to propose some “good” that will thereby be assured</u>. To toe contrary<u>, I mean to insist that nothing, and certainly not what we call the “good,” can ever have any assurance at all in the order of the Symbolic</u>. Abjuring fidelity to a futurism that’s always purchased at our expense, though bound, as Symbolic subjects consigned to figure the Symbolic’s undoing, to the necessary contradiction of trying to turn its intelligibility against itself, we might rather, figuratively, cast our vote for “none of the above,” for the primacy of a constant no in response to the law of the Symbolic, which would echo that law’s foundational act, its self- constituting negation. <u>The <mark>structuring optimism of politics</mark> to which the order of meaning commits us, installing as it does the perpetual hope of reaching meaning through signification<mark>, is always, </mark>I would argue,<mark> a negation of this primal, constitutive, and negative act</u></mark>. And the various positivities produced in its wake by the logic of political hope depend on the mathematical illusion that negated negations might somehow escape, and not redouble, such negativity. My polemic thus stakes its fortunes on a truly hopeless wager: that <u><mark>taking the Symbolic’s negativity</mark> to the very letter of the law</u>, that <u>attending to the persistence of something internal to reason that reason refuses</u>, that <u>turning the force of queerness against all subjects, however queer, can afford an access to the jouissance that at once defines and negates us</u>. <u>Or better: <mark>can expose </mark>the constancy<mark>, the inescapability, of such access to jouissance in the social order itself; </mark>even if that <mark>order can access</mark> its constant access to <mark>jouissance only in the process of abjecting that constancy </mark>of access <mark>onto the queer.</mark> </p><p></u>In contrast to what Theodor Adorno describes as the “grimness with which a man clings to himself, as to the immediately sure and substantial,” the queerness of which I speak would deliberately sever us from ourselves, from the assurance, that is, of knowing ourselves and hence of knowing our “good.”4 Such queerness proposes, in place of the good, something I want to call “better,” though it promises, in more than one sense of the phrase, absolutely nothing. ¡ connect this something better with Lacan’s characterization of what he calls “truth,” where truth does not assure happiness, or even, as Lacan makes clear, the good.5 Instead, it names only the insistent particularity of the subject, impossible fully to articulate and “tend[ing] toward the real.” Lacan, therefore, can write of this truth:</p><p>The quality that best characterizes it is that of being the true Wunsch, which was at the origin of an aberrant or atypical behavior. </p><p>We encounter this Wunsch with its particular, irreducible character as a modification that presupposes no other form of normalization than that of an experience of pleasure or of pain, but of a final experience from whence it springs and is subsequently preserved in the depths of the subject in an irreducible form. The Wunsch<u> does not have the character of a universal law but, on the contrary, of the most particular of laws —even if it is universal that this particularity is to be found in every human being.’</p><p></u>Truth, like queerness, irreducibly linked to the “aberrant or atypical,” to what chafes against “normalization,” finds its value not in a good susceptible to generalization, but only in the stubborn particularity that voids every notion of a general good<mark>. <u>The embrace of queer negativity</mark>, then, <mark>can have no justification if justification requires it to reinforce some positive social value; its value,</mark> instead, <mark>resides in its challenge to value as defined by the social</u></mark>, and thus in its radical challenge to the very value of the social itself.</p><p>For <u><mark>by figuring a refusal</mark> of the coercive belief <mark>in the</mark> paramount <mark>value of futurity</u></mark>, while refusing as well any backdoor hope for dialectical access to meaning, <u><mark>the queer dispossesses the social order of the ground on which it rests: a faith in the consistent reality of the </mark>social—and by extension, of the <mark>social subject</mark>; a faith <mark>that politics</mark>, whether of the left or of the right, implicitly <mark>affirms</u></mark>. Divesting such politics of its thematic trappings, bracketing the particularity of its various proposals for social organization<u>, the queer insists that politics is always a politics of the signifier, or even of what Lacan will often refer to as “the letter</u>’ <u>It serves to shore up a reality always unmoored by signification and lacking any guarantee</u>. <u>To say as much is not, of course, to deny the experiential violence that frequently troubles social reality or the apparent consistency with which it bears</u>—and thereby bears down on— <u>us al</u>l<u>. It is</u>, rather, <u>to suggest that queerness exposes the obliquity of our relation to what we experience in and as social reality, alerting us to the fantasies structurally necessary in order to sustain it and engaging those fantasies through the figural logics, the linguistic structures that shape them.</u> If it aims effectively to intervene in the reproduction of such a reality—an intervention that may well take the form of figuring that reality’s abortion— then <u>queer theory must always insist on its connection to the vicissitudes of the sign, to the tension between the signifier’s collapse into the letter’s cadaverous materiality and its participation in a system of reference wherein it generates meaning itself</u>. As a particular story, in other words, of why storytelling tells, <u>one that takes both the value and the burden of that failure upon itself, <mark>queer theory</u></mark>, as I construe it, <u><mark>marks the “other” side of politics: </mark>the “side” where narrative realization and derealization overlap, where the energies of vitalization ceaselessly turn against themselves;<mark> the “side” outside all political sides, committed as they are, on every side, to futurism’s unquestioned good</u><strong></mark>. The rest of this book attempts to explain the implications of this assertion, but first, let me sketch some connections between politics and the politics of the sign by establishing the psychoanalytic context within which my argument takes shape.</p></strong>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
41,708
457
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,337
CP keeps the treaty regime intact but the plan the destroys it
Bewley-Taylor et al 2014
Bewley-Taylor et al 2014 (Dave Bewley-Taylor, Tom Blickman and Martin Jelsma, Professor of International Relations and Public Policy at Swansea University and founding Director of the Global Drug Policy Observatory, The Rise and Decline of Cannabis Prohibition, http://www.tni.org/sites/www.tni.org/files/download/rise_and_decline_web.pdf)
The United States invested more effort than any other nation to influence the design of the global control regime If the U.S. now proclaims it can no longer live by the regime’s rules, it risks undermining the legal instrument Officials in Washington have been trying to develop a legal argument regarding enforcement priorities claiming that the U.S. is not violating the treaties because cultivation, trade and possession are still criminal offences under federal drug law and because the treaty provisions allow flexibility regarding law enforcement practices, especially when there are conflicts with a party’s constitution and domestic legal system. if, the U.S. interpretation attracted political acceptance and became part of an extended practice of flexible treaty interpretation significantly more room for manoeuvre would open up Other countries would be able to apply similar arguments Accepting such an argumentation would come close to a de facto amendment by means of broad interpretation If the U.S. now asserts that the treaties are sufficiently flexible to allow state control and taxed regulation the Netherlands could comfortably extend the expediency principle to include coffeeshops
The United States invested more than any other nation to influence the global control regime If the U.S. proclaims it can no longer live by the regime’s rules, it risks undermining the legal instrument Officials in Washington have been trying to develop a legal argument that the U.S. is not violating the treaties because cultivation, trade and possession are still criminal offences under federal drug law and because the treaty provisions allow flexibility regarding law enforcement practices when there are conflicts with a party’s constitution if, the U.S. interpretation attracted ceptance and became part of an extended practice of flexible treaty interpretation, significantly more room for manoeuvre would open up the Netherlands could comfortably extend the expediency principle to include coffeeshops
The United States has invested probably more effort than any other nation over the past century to influence the design of the global control regime and enforce its almost universal adherence. If the U.S. now proclaims it can no longer live by the regime’s rules, it risks undermining the legal instrument it has used so often in the past to coerce other countries to operate in accordance with U.S. drug control policies and principles. Officials in Washington have been trying to develop a legal argument, based on the August 2013 memorandum from the Justice Department regarding enforcement priorities, claiming that the U.S. is not violating the treaties because cultivation, trade and possession of cannabis are still criminal offences under federal drug law; and because the treaty provisions allow for considerable flexibility regarding law enforcement practices, especially when there are conflicts with a party’s constitution and domestic legal system. Using the expediency principle, the argument continues, federal law enforcement intervention in state-level cannabis regulation is simply not high priority; but by allowing states de facto to regulate the cannabis market, the federal government would not be violating its international treaty obligations because the approaches pursued in Washington and Colorado are still prohibited under federal law. In legal terms, such a line of argumentation is easily contestable. The INCB has pointed out in recent annual reports in reference to cannabis developments at state level in the U.S., a party is obliged “to ensure the full implementation of the international drug control treaties on its entire territory”. Hence law enforcement priority isn’t a valid consideration; rather the law needs to be in conformity with the treaties at all levels of jurisdiction. Any reference regarding treaty flexibility based on the premise that the manner in which a party implements the provisions is “subject to its constitutional principles and the basic concepts of its legal system” is also very problematic. While that principle applied to the 1961 Convention as a whole, the escape clause was deliberately deleted from the 1988 Convention with regard to the obligation to establish cultivation, trade and possession as a criminal offence, except in relation to personal consumption mainly due to U.S. pressure during the negotiations. Washington’s rationale was that it wanted to limit the flexibility the preceding conventions had left to nation states. And finally (as mentioned in the section on Dutch coffeeshops in the previous chapter), the 1988 Convention restricted the use of discretionary legal powers regarding cultivation and trafficking offences (article 3, paragraph 6). All that notwithstanding, if, the U.S. interpretation attracted a certain level of political acceptance and became part of an extended practice of flexible treaty interpretation, significantly more room for manoeuvre would open up. Other countries would be able to apply similar arguments, not only to legally justify cannabis regulation, but for other currently contested policies as well, such as drug consumption rooms or legally regulated markets for coca leaf. Accepting such an argumentation would come close to a de facto amendment by means of broad interpretation that would restore the escape clause for the entire 1988 Convention (including for article 3, paragraph 1 (a) and (b) offences), and simultaneously annul the restrictions placed on the exercise of discretionary powers under domestic law. The Netherlands, for example, made a special reservation upon ratification of the 1988 Convention, exempting the country from the limitations on prosecutorial discretion the treaty intended to impose. Even with such a reservation in hand, however, the Dutch government has maintained thus far that the expediency principle under which the coffeeshops are operating, could not be used to justify non-enforcement guidelines with regard to cannabis cultivation. That position has often been challenged in the domestic policy debate as an excessively restrictive legal interpretation of existing treaty flexibility. If the U.S. now asserts that the treaties are sufficiently flexible to allow state control and taxed regulation of cultivation and trade for non-medical purposes on its territory, accordingly the Netherlands could comfortably extend the expediency principle to include the cultivation of cannabis destined to supply the coffeeshops by issuing additional nonprosecution guidelines.
4,540
<h4>CP keeps the treaty regime intact but the plan the destroys it</h4><p><strong>Bewley-Taylor et al 2014</strong> (Dave Bewley-Taylor, Tom Blickman and Martin Jelsma, Professor of International Relations and Public Policy at Swansea University and founding Director of the Global Drug Policy Observatory, The Rise and Decline of Cannabis Prohibition, http://www.tni.org/sites/www.tni.org/files/download/rise_and_decline_web.pdf)</p><p><u><mark>The United States</u></mark> has <u><mark>invested</u></mark> probably <u><mark>more</mark> effort <mark>than any other nation</u></mark> over the past century <u><mark>to</u> <u>influence the</mark> design of the <mark>global control regime</u></mark> and enforce its almost universal adherence. <u><strong><mark>If the U.S.</mark> now <mark>proclaims it can no longer live by the regime’s rules, it risks undermining the legal instrument</u></strong></mark> it has used so often in the past to coerce other countries to operate in accordance with U.S. drug control policies and principles. <u><mark>Officials in Washington have been trying to develop a legal argument</u></mark>, based on the August 2013 memorandum from the Justice Department <u>regarding</u> <u><strong>enforcement priorities</u></strong>, <u>claiming <mark>that the U.S. is not violating the treaties</mark> <mark>because</mark> <mark>cultivation, trade and possession</u></mark> of cannabis <u><mark>are <strong>still criminal offences under federal drug law</u></strong></mark>; <u><mark>and</mark> <mark>because the treaty provisions allow</u></mark> for considerable <u><mark>flexibility regarding law enforcement practices</mark>, especially <mark>when there are conflicts with a party’s constitution</mark> and domestic legal system.</u> Using the expediency principle, the argument continues, federal law enforcement intervention in state-level cannabis regulation is simply not high priority; but by allowing states de facto to regulate the cannabis market, the federal government would not be violating its international treaty obligations because the approaches pursued in Washington and Colorado are still prohibited under federal law. In legal terms, such a line of argumentation is easily contestable. The INCB has pointed out in recent annual reports in reference to cannabis developments at state level in the U.S., a party is obliged “to ensure the full implementation of the international drug control treaties on its entire territory”. Hence law enforcement priority isn’t a valid consideration; rather the law needs to be in conformity with the treaties at all levels of jurisdiction. Any reference regarding treaty flexibility based on the premise that the manner in which a party implements the provisions is “subject to its constitutional principles and the basic concepts of its legal system” is also very problematic. While that principle applied to the 1961 Convention as a whole, the escape clause was deliberately deleted from the 1988 Convention with regard to the obligation to establish cultivation, trade and possession as a criminal offence, except in relation to personal consumption mainly due to U.S. pressure during the negotiations. Washington’s rationale was that it wanted to limit the flexibility the preceding conventions had left to nation states. And finally (as mentioned in the section on Dutch coffeeshops in the previous chapter), the 1988 Convention restricted the use of discretionary legal powers regarding cultivation and trafficking offences (article 3, paragraph 6). All that notwithstanding, <u><mark>if, the U.S. interpretation attracted</mark> </u>a certain level of <u>political ac<mark>ceptance</u> <u>and</u> <u>became part of an extended practice of flexible treaty interpretation</u>, <u><strong>significantly more room for manoeuvre would open up</u></strong></mark>. <u>Other countries would be able to apply similar arguments</u>, not only to legally justify cannabis regulation, but for other currently contested policies as well, such as drug consumption rooms or legally regulated markets for coca leaf. <u>Accepting such an argumentation would come close to a <strong>de facto amendment</strong> by means of broad interpretation</u> that would restore the escape clause for the entire 1988 Convention (including for article 3, paragraph 1 (a) and (b) offences), and simultaneously annul the restrictions placed on the exercise of discretionary powers under domestic law. The Netherlands, for example, made a special reservation upon ratification of the 1988 Convention, exempting the country from the limitations on prosecutorial discretion the treaty intended to impose. Even with such a reservation in hand, however, the Dutch government has maintained thus far that the expediency principle under which the coffeeshops are operating, could not be used to justify non-enforcement guidelines with regard to cannabis cultivation. That position has often been challenged in the domestic policy debate as an excessively restrictive legal interpretation of existing treaty flexibility. <u>If the U.S. now asserts that the treaties are sufficiently flexible to allow state control and taxed regulation</u> of cultivation and trade for non-medical purposes on its territory, accordingly <u><mark>the Netherlands could comfortably extend the expediency principle to include</u></mark> the cultivation of cannabis destined to supply the <u><mark>coffeeshops</u></mark> by issuing additional nonprosecution guidelines.</p>
null
null
Off
430,422
43
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,338
The availability of organs in the US would dry up demand in the illegal market
Upchurch 12
Upchurch 12 Ryan Upchurch, Seton Hall Law 1-1-12 Seton Hall Law eRepository "The Man who Removes a Mountain Begins by Carrying Away Small Stones: Flynn v. Holder and a Re-Examination of The National Organ Transplantation Act of 1984" (2012). http://erepository.law.shu.edu/student_scholarship/18
By increasing the supply of available organs in the U S through compensation, citizens would have less reason to travel elsewhere to pay for an organ If demand dried up transplant tourism in these countries would take a major hit presumably American citizens make up a substantial percentage of the tourist patients seeking a new organ they cannot attain domestically. As one report stated, “Most of those organs ended up transplanted into American citizens If those American citizens with the means to purchase were not forced abroad to find an organ, it is very
By increasing the supply of available organs in the U S citizens would have less reason to travel elsewhere If demand dried up , transplant tourism in these countries would take a major hit presumably American citizens make up a substantial percentage of the tourist patients Most of those organs ended up transplanted into American citizens
By increasing the supply of available organs in the United States through compensation, American citizens would have less reason to travel elsewhere to pay for an organ. For example, Aadil Hospital in Lahore, Pakistan advertises two transplant packages catered towards foreign patients: $14,000 for the first transplant and $16,000 for the second if the first organ fails.118 If demand dried up from foreign citizens, transplant tourism in these countries would take a major hit because brokers would fetch lower sums for organs they procure. Statistical information is difficult to come by for obvious reasons, but presumably American citizens make up a substantial percentage of the tourist patients seeking a new organ they cannot attain domestically. As one report about impoverished Bangladeshi villagers taken advantage of for their organs succinctly stated, “Most of those organs ended up transplanted into American citizens.”119 The black market for organs in other countries is not fueled by local patients. Rather, it is driven upwards and out of control by those American as well as European citizens who cannot acquire what they need domestically.120 One estimate is that the black market accounts for as high as twenty percent of all kidney transplants worldwide.121 Nadley Hakim, transplant surgeon for St. Mary’s Hospital in London, offered an interesting take on this problem of the black market when he said, “this trade is going on anyway, why not have a controlled trade where if someone wants to donate a kidney for a particular price, that would be acceptable? If it is done safely, the donor will not suffer.”122 Within the past month, an indigent Chinese teenager sold his kidney so that he could purchase an iPad and iPhone.123 The unnamed teenager now suffers from renal deficiency.124 Sadly, the boy received roughly ten percent of what the buyer paid, with the rest going to the surgeon and others involved in coordinating the operation.125 If those American citizens with the means to purchase were not forced abroad to find an organ, it is very possible that stories like this would become much less commonplace.
2,141
<h4>The availability of organs in the US would dry up demand in the illegal market</h4><p><strong>Upchurch 12</strong> Ryan Upchurch, Seton Hall Law 1-1-12 Seton Hall Law eRepository "The Man who Removes a Mountain Begins by Carrying Away Small Stones: Flynn v. Holder and a Re-Examination of <u>The National Organ Transplantation Act of 1984" (2012). http://erepository.law.shu.edu/student_scholarship/18</p><p><mark>By increasing the supply of available organs in the U</u></mark>nited<u> <mark>S</u></mark>tates<u> through compensation, </u>American<u> <mark>citizens would have less reason to travel elsewhere</mark> to pay for an organ</u>. For example, Aadil Hospital in Lahore, Pakistan advertises two transplant packages catered towards foreign patients: $14,000 for the first transplant and $16,000 for the second if the first organ fails.118 <u><mark>If demand dried up</u> </mark>from foreign citizens<mark>, <u>transplant tourism in these countries would take a major hit</u></mark> because brokers would fetch lower sums for organs they procure. Statistical information is difficult to come by for obvious reasons, but <u><mark>presumably American citizens make up a substantial percentage of the tourist patients</mark> seeking a new organ they cannot attain domestically. As one report </u>about impoverished Bangladeshi villagers taken advantage of for their organs<u> </u>succinctly <u>stated, “<mark>Most of those organs ended up transplanted into American citizens</u></mark>.”119 The<u> </u>black market for organs in other countries is not fueled by local patients. Rather, it is driven<u> </u>upwards and out of control by those American as well as European citizens who cannot acquire<u> </u>what they need domestically.120 One estimate is that the black market accounts for as high as twenty percent of all kidney transplants worldwide.121 Nadley Hakim, transplant surgeon for St. Mary’s Hospital in London, offered an interesting take on this problem of the black market when he said, “this trade is going on anyway, why not have a controlled trade where if someone wants to donate a kidney for a particular price, that would be acceptable? If it is done safely, the donor will not suffer.”122 Within the past month, an indigent Chinese teenager sold his kidney so that he could purchase an iPad and iPhone.123 The unnamed teenager now suffers from renal deficiency.124 Sadly, the boy received roughly ten percent of what the buyer paid, with the rest going to the surgeon and others involved in coordinating the operation.125 <u>If those American citizens with the means to purchase were not forced abroad to find an organ, it is very </u>possible that stories like this would become much less commonplace.</p>
null
null
Contention 2 is the Illegal market
430,262
14
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,339
Didn’t contest the impact—we have defense to case.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><strong>Didn’t contest the impact—we have defense to case.</h4></strong>
Ableism
Impact
2NC K
430,657
1
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,340
And their recentering of individual autonomy prevents an analysis of medicine as a system of power relations – turns case even if they’re right about the act of PAS
Salem 99
Salem 99 Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full
null
institutionalization of death has extended physicians’ role in regulating death doctors share end-of-life decisions and choices with patients and families one of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dyin medicalization of death, is so deeply embedded in our culture that it goes unnoticed The sway of medicine should not be understood as a Machiavellian strategy devised by doctors physicians themselves are under medicine's power and not always aware of their critical role in the cultural construction of death and dying Physician-assisted suicide is widely but incorrectly represented as a further step in the demedicalization of death begun by the patients’ rights movements It ultimately extends the power of physicians in regulating death, now under the guise of “assisting” suicide
There is a certain consensus that the institutionalization of death, its transference from the community to the hospital setting and its medicalization, has extended physicians’ role in regulating death. Today some 80 percent of deaths in the United States take place in health care facilities, while as recently as fifty years ago only a small minority of people died in hospitals or long-term care facilities. In the wake of the “right to die” movement, today in theory—and to some extent in actual practice—doctors share end-of-life decisions and choices with patients and families. In this sense, all contrive to consolidate “managed death” as the predominant way of dying in the United States. Indeed, the American Hospital Association reported that about 70 percent of deaths in the hospital occur after a decision has been made to withhold treatment.30 Despite the space ceded to patients’ autonomous choices, one of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dying. This intangible aspect of medicine's power, such a crucial facet of the medicalization of death, is so deeply embedded in our culture that it goes unnoticed. The sway of medicine should not be understood as a Machiavellian strategy devised by doctors to dominate various domains of contemporary life; physicians themselves are under medicine's power and not always aware of their critical role in the cultural construction of death and dying. There is a paradox in our attitude toward modern medicine: on the one hand, we criticize and wish to counterbalance medicine's power through the enhancement of the patient's autonomy, and on the other, we open up the doors for physicians in the domain of suicide. Yet from another perspective the paradox dissolves, when we recognize it as a facet of how thoroughly public conscience is imbued with medical ideology. Physician-assisted suicide is widely but incorrectly represented as a further step in the demedicalization of death begun by the patients’ rights and right to die movements. It ultimately extends the power of physicians in regulating death, now under the guise of “assisting” suicide.
2,230
<h4>And their recentering of individual autonomy prevents an analysis of medicine as a system of power relations – turns case even if they’re right about the act of PAS</h4><p><strong>Salem 99</strong> Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full</p><p><strong>There is a certain consensus that</strong> the <strong><mark>institutionalization of death</strong></mark>, its transference from the community to the hospital setting and its medicalization, <strong><mark>has extended physicians’ role in regulating death</strong></mark>. Today some 80 percent of deaths in the United States take place in health care facilities, while as recently as fifty years ago only a small minority of people died in hospitals or long-term care facilities.</p><p><strong>In the wake of the “right to die” movement</strong>, today in theory—and to some extent in actual practice—<strong><mark>doctors share end-of-life decisions and choices with patients and families</strong></mark>. In this sense, all contrive to consolidate “managed death” as the predominant way of dying in the United States. Indeed, the American Hospital Association reported that about <strong>70 percent of deaths in the hospital occur after a decision has been made to withhold treatment</strong>.30</p><p>Despite the space ceded to patients’ autonomous choices, <strong><mark>one of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dyin</mark>g</strong>. This intangible aspect of medicine's power, such a crucial facet of the <strong><mark>medicalization of death, is so deeply embedded in our culture that it goes unnoticed</strong></mark>. <strong><mark>The sway of medicine should not be understood as a Machiavellian strategy devised by doctors</strong></mark> to dominate various domains of contemporary life; <strong><mark>physicians themselves are under medicine's power and not always aware of their critical role in the cultural construction of death and dying</strong></mark>.</p><p>There is a paradox in our attitude toward modern medicine: on the one hand, we criticize and wish to counterbalance medicine's power through the enhancement of the patient's autonomy, and on the other, we open up the doors for physicians in the domain of suicide. Yet from another perspective <strong>the paradox dissolves, when we recognize it as a facet of how thoroughly public conscience is imbued with medical ideology</strong>.</p><p><strong><mark>Physician-assisted suicide is widely but incorrectly represented as a further step in the demedicalization of death begun by the patients’ rights</mark> and right to die <mark>movements</mark>. <mark>It ultimately extends the power of physicians in regulating death, now under the guise of “assisting” suicide</strong></mark>.</p>
null
null
Case
430,351
7
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,341
Obama’s not involved and there’s no agreement
Politico 4/2/2015 (http://www.politico.com/story/2015/04/trade-promotion-authority-tpa-bill-timeline-could-push-senate-to-act-116640.html)
Politico 4/2/2015 (http://www.politico.com/story/2015/04/trade-promotion-authority-tpa-bill-timeline-could-push-senate-to-act-116640.html)
Negotiations between Hatch Wyden and Ryan are taking place at the staff level over the spring congressional break and “continue to make progress Hatch spokesman said, confirming only that the senator hopes to move legislation “this spring.” Wyden has sought to include provisions to give Congress more power and oversight over the fast-tracking of trade deals Quick movement on the bill could send McConnell the signal to carve out floor time in the upcoming six-week legislative period a session that will be jammed with fallout over Iran tentative dates for introducing and marking up the bill doesn’t solve your issue of floor time Hatch and Wyden have winnowed down their differences to a handful of issues, including a provision Wyden is pushing that would make it easier to remove trade deals from fast-track procedures if lawmakers’ negotiating priorities aren’t met. McConnell initially promised floor time for the measure in the last legislative session, but took it away Hatch expressed worry as late as last week that if he and Wyden couldn’t strike a deal in April the fast-track bill might not get passed at all this year. When asked this week how quickly the bill could move, McConnell’s spokesman said I don’t have timing yet.”
confirming only that the senator hopes to move legislation “this spring.” Quick movement on the bill could send McConnell a session that will be jammed with fallout over Iran doesn’t solve your issue of floor time McConnell initially promised floor time for the measure in the last legislative session, but took it away When asked this week how quickly the bill could move, McConnell’s spokesman said I don’t have timing yet.”
Negotiations between Hatch (R-Utah), who chairs the committee, its ranking member Wyden (D-Ore.) and House Ways and Means Committee Chairman Paul Ryan (R-Wis.) are taking place at the staff level over the spring congressional break and “continue to make progress,” Hatch spokesman Julia Lawless said, confirming only that the senator hopes to move legislation “this spring.” Wyden has sought to include provisions to give Congress more power and oversight over the fast-tracking of trade deals. Quick movement on the bill, which the White House is seeking to expedite congressional consideration of a sprawling Asia-Pacific trade deal, could send Senate Majority Leader Mitch McConnell the signal to carve out floor time in the upcoming six-week legislative period — a session that will be jammed with major issues ranging from the budget reconciliation process to political fallout over the nuclear energy deal with Iran, and from cybersecurity legislation — a priority of the Kentucky Republican — to the highway funding bill. Meanwhile, the fate of Trans-Pacific Partnership with Japan and 10 other Asia-Pacific countries hangs in the balance. The legislation is considered vital for easing congressional passage of the deal, which would be the biggest in world history, because it would shield it from amendments and put it to a simple up-or-down vote. Before countries put their final offers on the table, they’ve said they want assurance through the legislation that lawmakers won’t be able to tear the agreement apart during congressional debate — and their trade ministers have been growing more vocal about the need for the bill as a TPP gathering meant to wrap up the deal approaches in late-May. Japan, the world’s third-largest economy, in particular has been at an impasse with the United States over agricultural and auto tariff cuts. Its economic minister, Akira Amari, told the Financial Times this week that President Barack Obama needs to step up his efforts to win support for fast track legislation from fellow Democrats. Chile’s deputy trade minister, Andres Rebolledo, echoed the point in an interview with POLITICO, saying that negotiations could continue in parallel, “But of course we are aware that it’s important to have TPA before the last minute of the negotiation.” The tentative dates for introducing and marking up the bill could be an effort to create some momentum for its consideration, a trade lobbyist who is following the issue closely said. And, because Hatch scheduled and then postponed a hearing on the bill in late February, he won’t have to comply with the seven-day notification requirement for hearings. But “that doesn’t solve your issue of floor time,” the lobbyist said. Since negotiations began after the midterm elections, Hatch and Wyden have winnowed down their differences to a handful of issues, including a provision Wyden is pushing that would make it easier to remove trade deals from fast-track procedures if lawmakers’ negotiating priorities aren’t met. The two sides are also discussing the content of and process for amendments, with Hatch seeking to make the bill’s path to passage as smooth as possible, congressional aides said. The Utah Republican wants not only to protect the bill, but also to give certain vulnerable Republican committee members, such as Rob Portman of Ohio, opportunities for political cover as they go into elections in 2016 where trade could be a sensitive issue, lobbyists and aides said. At least one opponent, former Ohio Gov. Ted Strickland, is expected to attack Portman for his pro-trade stance, which could resonate in the manufacturing state. Giving Portman, a former U.S. trade representative under George W. Bush, an opportunity to offer an amendment on currency manipulation or another worker-friendly issue — without substantively changing what Hatch wants in a final bill — could provide the Ohio Republican with some political cover. Wyden, too, wants to reach an agreement by the end of this recess, a Democratic aide said. But if the two sides can’t reach one then or fairly soon after, observers say the window for passing a bill in the six-week legislative period could close. McConnell initially promised floor time for the measure in the last legislative session, but took it away when it became clear Hatch and the Oregon Democrat couldn’t reach a deal, trade lobbyists said. “[T]hat floor time was pretty much given away,” one of the lobbyists said. On the House side, Ryan was undeterred as recently as last week by the Senate Finance panel leaders’ delay in reaching an agreement on the fast-track bill, telling reporters at a pen-and-pad briefing that he planned to move it and other trade legislation in the upcoming session. “My goal is to mark up as many trade bills as I can in the spring,” the Wisconsin Republican said, ticking off bills to renew tariff-cuts under the Generalized System of Preferences program, which expired in July 2013, and the African Growth and Opportunity Act, which expires in September. Right now, several Republicans — some of whom are high-ranking — say they have been left out of the substance of the fast-track talks and are leaning against voting for the legislation, another trade lobbyist said. That means the House Republican leadership will need to do some legwork to bring the conference in line once a bill is introduced, the lobbyist said, adding that intense, coordinated lobbying would have to happen to get sufficient votes in just a few weeks. But a Republican aide said the votes will be there when the bill comes to the floor. “A lot of members — on both sides of the aisle — are hesitant to throw their support behind something right now because legislation doesn’t exist yet,” the aide said, noting that outside lobbying groups have made a significant push in favor of the bill theory. “I expect that it [a vote] will be close but will feel much more confident once language actually exists and is introduced,” the aide said. Still, Hatch expressed worry as late as last week that if he and Wyden couldn’t strike a deal in April the fast-track bill might not get passed at all this year. When asked this week how quickly the bill could move, McConnell’s spokesman Don Stewart said, “It’s a priority for the leader, but I don’t have timing yet.”
6,309
<h4>Obama’s not involved and there’s no agreement</h4><p><strong>Politico 4/2<u>/2015 (http://www.politico.com/story/2015/04/trade-promotion-authority-tpa-bill-timeline-could-push-senate-to-act-116640.html)</p><p></strong>Negotiations between Hatch</u> (R-Utah), who chairs the committee, its ranking member <u>Wyden</u> (D-Ore.) <u>and</u> House Ways and Means Committee Chairman Paul <u>Ryan</u> (R-Wis.) <u>are taking place at the staff level over the spring congressional break and “continue to make progress</u>,” <u>Hatch spokesman</u> Julia Lawless <u>said, <strong><mark>confirming only that the senator hopes to move legislation “this spring.”</mark> </strong>Wyden has sought to include provisions to give Congress more power and oversight over the fast-tracking of trade deals</u>.<u> <mark>Quick movement on the bill</u></mark>, which the White House is seeking to expedite congressional consideration of a sprawling Asia-Pacific trade deal, <u><mark>could send</u></mark> Senate Majority Leader Mitch <u><mark>McConnell</mark> the signal to carve out floor time in the upcoming six-week legislative period</u> — <u><strong><mark>a session that will be jammed with</u></strong></mark> major issues ranging from the budget reconciliation process to political <u><strong><mark>fallout over</u></strong></mark> the nuclear energy deal with <u><strong><mark>Iran</u></strong></mark>, and from cybersecurity legislation — a priority of the Kentucky Republican — to the highway funding bill. Meanwhile, the fate of Trans-Pacific Partnership with Japan and 10 other Asia-Pacific countries hangs in the balance. The legislation is considered vital for easing congressional passage of the deal, which would be the biggest in world history, because it would shield it from amendments and put it to a simple up-or-down vote. Before countries put their final offers on the table, they’ve said they want assurance through the legislation that lawmakers won’t be able to tear the agreement apart during congressional debate — and their trade ministers have been growing more vocal about the need for the bill as a TPP gathering meant to wrap up the deal approaches in late-May. Japan, the world’s third-largest economy, in particular has been at an impasse with the United States over agricultural and auto tariff cuts. Its economic minister, Akira Amari, told the Financial Times this week that President Barack Obama needs to step up his efforts to win support for fast track legislation from fellow Democrats. Chile’s deputy trade minister, Andres Rebolledo, echoed the point in an interview with POLITICO, saying that negotiations could continue in parallel, “But of course we are aware that it’s important to have TPA before the last minute of the negotiation.” The <u>tentative dates for introducing and marking up the bill</u> could be an effort to create some momentum for its consideration, a trade lobbyist who is following the issue closely said. And, because Hatch scheduled and then postponed a hearing on the bill in late February, he won’t have to comply with the seven-day notification requirement for hearings. But “that <u><strong><mark>doesn’t solve your issue of floor time</u></strong></mark>,” the lobbyist said. Since negotiations began after the midterm elections, <u>Hatch and Wyden have winnowed down their differences to a handful of issues, including a provision Wyden is pushing that would make it easier to remove trade deals from fast-track procedures if lawmakers’ negotiating priorities aren’t met. </u>The two sides are also discussing the content of and process for amendments, with Hatch seeking to make the bill’s path to passage as smooth as possible, congressional aides said. The Utah Republican wants not only to protect the bill, but also to give certain vulnerable Republican committee members, such as Rob Portman of Ohio, opportunities for political cover as they go into elections in 2016 where trade could be a sensitive issue, lobbyists and aides said. At least one opponent, former Ohio Gov. Ted Strickland, is expected to attack Portman for his pro-trade stance, which could resonate in the manufacturing state. Giving Portman, a former U.S. trade representative under George W. Bush, an opportunity to offer an amendment on currency manipulation or another worker-friendly issue — without substantively changing what Hatch wants in a final bill — could provide the Ohio Republican with some political cover. Wyden, too, wants to reach an agreement by the end of this recess, a Democratic aide said. But if the two sides can’t reach one then or fairly soon after, observers say the window for passing a bill in the six-week legislative period could close. <u><mark>McConnell initially promised floor time for the measure in the last legislative session, but took it away</u></mark> when it became clear Hatch and the Oregon Democrat couldn’t reach a deal, trade lobbyists said. “[T]hat floor time was pretty much given away,” one of the lobbyists said. On the House side, Ryan was undeterred as recently as last week by the Senate Finance panel leaders’ delay in reaching an agreement on the fast-track bill, telling reporters at a pen-and-pad briefing that he planned to move it and other trade legislation in the upcoming session. “My goal is to mark up as many trade bills as I can in the spring,” the Wisconsin Republican said, ticking off bills to renew tariff-cuts under the Generalized System of Preferences program, which expired in July 2013, and the African Growth and Opportunity Act, which expires in September. Right now, several Republicans — some of whom are high-ranking — say they have been left out of the substance of the fast-track talks and are leaning against voting for the legislation, another trade lobbyist said. That means the House Republican leadership will need to do some legwork to bring the conference in line once a bill is introduced, the lobbyist said, adding that intense, coordinated lobbying would have to happen to get sufficient votes in just a few weeks. But a Republican aide said the votes will be there when the bill comes to the floor. “A lot of members — on both sides of the aisle — are hesitant to throw their support behind something right now because legislation doesn’t exist yet,” the aide said, noting that outside lobbying groups have made a significant push in favor of the bill theory. “I expect that it [a vote] will be close but will feel much more confident once language actually exists and is introduced,” the aide said. Still, <u>Hatch expressed worry as late as last week that if he and Wyden couldn’t strike a deal in April the fast-track bill might not get passed at all this year. <mark>When asked this week how quickly the bill could move, McConnell’s spokesman</u></mark> Don Stewart <u><mark>said</u></mark>, “It’s a priority for the leader, but <u><strong><mark>I don’t have timing yet.”</p></u></strong></mark>
2AC
Politics DA
TPA – 2AC – NDT
430,658
7
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,342
That doesn’t matter at all—the global economy is just a pie, innovation anywhere effects it everywhere
Bhide 8
Bhide 8 [Amar, Glaubinger Professor of Business at Columbia University, editor of Capitalism and Society, member of the Council on Foreign Relations, and author of The Origin and Evolution of New Businesses, VOLUME 21 | NUMBER 1 | WINTER 2009 APPLIED CORPORATE FINANCE Journal of A MORGAN STANLEY PUBLICATION The Venturesome Economy: How Innovation Sustains Prosperity in a More Connected World]
apprehensions about the offshoring of R&D and the growth of scientific capabilities in China and India are greatly exaggerated, stemming from a failure to appreciate the complex nature of the modern innovation system and globalization. the U S is not locked into a “winnertake- all” race for scientific and technological leadership, and the growth of research capabilities in China and India—and thus their share of cutting-edge research—does not reduce U.S. prosperity. my analysis suggests the opposite advances abroad will improve living standards in the U S cutting-edge research developed abroad benefits production and consumption in the U.S. service sector.
null
Of course, the U.S. can’t count on the same ending to every episode of the Losing Our Lead serial. The integration of China and India into the global economy is a seminal development, unprecedented in its scale. Could it be different this time? Is the U.S. finally on the verge of being pummeled by a technological hurricane? In my view, apprehensions about the offshoring of R&D and the growth of scientific capabilities in China and India are greatly exaggerated, stemming from a failure to appreciate the complex nature of the modern innovation system and its interactions with globalization. Techno-nationalists, I argue, have a narrow conception of innovation and its relationship to globalization. In the pages that follow, I present a more realistic and complex picture of innovation and its effects that leads to a very different prognosis. In my view, the United States is not locked into a “winnertake- all” race for scientific and technological leadership, and the growth of research capabilities in China and India—and thus their share of cutting-edge research—does not reduce U.S. prosperity. Indeed my analysis suggests the opposite— that advances abroad will improve living standards in the United States. Moreover, the benefits I identify aren’t the usual ones by which prosperity abroad increases opportunities for U.S. exporters. Instead, I show that cutting-edge research developed abroad benefits production and consumption in the U.S. service sector.
1,471
<h4>That doesn’t matter at all—the global economy is just a pie, innovation anywhere effects it everywhere</h4><p><u><strong>Bhide 8</u></strong> [Amar, Glaubinger Professor of Business at Columbia University, editor of Capitalism and Society, member of the Council on Foreign Relations, and author of The Origin and Evolution of New Businesses, <u>VOLUME 21 | NUMBER 1 | WINTER 2009 APPLIED CORPORATE FINANCE Journal of A MORGAN STANLEY PUBLICATION The Venturesome Economy: How Innovation Sustains Prosperity in a More Connected World]</p><p></u>Of course, the U.S. can’t count on the same ending to every episode of the Losing Our Lead serial. The integration of China and India into the global economy is a seminal development, unprecedented in its scale. Could it be different this time? Is the U.S. finally on the verge of being pummeled by a technological hurricane? In my view, <u>apprehensions about the offshoring of R&D and the growth of scientific capabilities in China and India are <strong>greatly exaggerated</strong>, stemming from a failure to appreciate the complex nature of the modern innovation system and</u> its interactions with <u>globalization.</u> Techno-nationalists, I argue, have a narrow conception of innovation and its relationship to globalization. In the pages that follow, I present a more realistic and complex picture of innovation and its effects that leads to a very different prognosis. In my view, <u>the U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates <u>is not locked into a “winnertake- all” race for scientific and technological leadership, and the growth of research capabilities in China and India—and thus their share of cutting-edge research—does not reduce U.S. prosperity.</u> Indeed <u>my analysis suggests the opposite</u>— that <u>advances abroad will <strong>improve living standards</strong> in the U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates. Moreover, the benefits I identify aren’t the usual ones by which prosperity abroad increases opportunities for U.S. exporters. Instead, I show that <u>cutting-edge research developed abroad benefits production and consumption in the U.S. service sector.</p></u>
WTO
Banks
AT: Inevitable
430,659
1
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,343
China has no incentive to rise violently
White 13
White 13 (Hugh, Professor of Strategic Studies at the Strategic and Defence Studies Centre, Australian National University, 6/24/13, “The new security order,” http://epress.anu.edu.au/wp-content/uploads/2013/06/EAFQ-5.2-WEB-FINAL.pdf)
any rising power must inevitably aim to overturn the preexisting order many people fear that China too has these ambitions but this fear underestimates China’s immense stake in many aspects of the current order of which it has been by far the biggest beneficiary. it is very unlike the disruptive rising powers of the 20th century there is no evidence that China has territorial ambitions It has no political or ideological agendas, and no reason to change the economic order. China seems to want to change very little about the global or regional order and its ambitions seem limited to Asia
any rising power must overturn the preexisting order people fear China has these ambitions. but this underestimates China’s stake in the current order it is unlike rising powers of the 20th century there is no evidence China has territorial ambitions It has no political or ideological agendas, and no reason to change the economic order China ambitions seem limited to Asia.
The second view of China’s ambitions is that they are far-reaching. The examples of nazi Germany, Imperial Japan and stalinist Russia lead some to assume that any rising power must inevitably aim to overturn every aspect of the preexisting order—territorial, economic, political, ideological, even moral. many people fear that China too has these ambitions. but this fear underestimates China’s immense stake in many aspects of the current order of which it has been by far the biggest beneficiary. In this way, it is very unlike the disruptive rising powers of the 20th century—there is no evidence that China has territorial ambitions, notwithstanding its assertiveness in the south China sea. It has no political or ideological agendas, and no reason to change the economic order. In fact, China seems to want to change very little about the global or regional order except its own role in it, and even there its leadership ambitions seem primarily limited to Asia.
968
<h4>China has no incentive to rise violently </h4><p><strong>White 13</strong> (Hugh, Professor of Strategic Studies at the Strategic and Defence Studies Centre, Australian National University, 6/24/13, “The new security order,” http://epress.anu.edu.au/wp-content/uploads/2013/06/EAFQ-5.2-WEB-FINAL.pdf)</p><p>The second view of China’s ambitions is that they are far-reaching. The examples of nazi Germany, Imperial Japan and stalinist Russia lead some to assume that <u><mark>any rising power must</mark> inevitably aim to <mark>overturn</u></mark> every aspect of <u><mark>the preexisting order</u></mark>—territorial, economic, political, ideological, even moral. <u>many <mark>people fear</mark> that <mark>China</mark> too <mark>has these ambitions</u>. <u>but this</mark> fear <strong><mark>underestimates China’s</mark> immense <mark>stake </strong>in</mark> many aspects of <mark>the current order</mark> of which it has been by far the biggest beneficiary.</u> In this way, <u><strong><mark>it is</mark> very <mark>unlike</mark> the disruptive <mark>rising powers of the 20th century</u></strong></mark>—<u><mark>there is no evidence</mark> that <mark>China has territorial ambitions</u></mark>, notwithstanding its assertiveness in the south China sea. <u><mark>It has no political</mark> <mark>or ideological agendas, and no reason to change the economic order</mark>.</u> In fact, <u><mark>China</mark> seems to want to change very little about the global or regional order</u> except its own role in it, <u>and</u> even there <u>its</u> leadership <u><mark>ambitions seem</u></mark> primarily <u><mark>limited to Asia</u>.</p></mark>
null
null
AT: China Real War
430,409
12
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,344
Demanding the future stops here may seem politically self-destructive; however, this act establishes an anti-politic divorced from the futurity of the Child. Anything else retains the structural position of the queer—denying the negativity of queerness only shifts the figural burden of queerness onto someone else. We do not promise a better future or a brighter tomorrow, but an end to the sacralization of the Child and the ensuing sacrifice of the queer.
Edelman ’04
Edelman ’04, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, p. 35-31
Queerness is never a matter of being or becoming but, embodying the Real internal to the Symbolic jouissance enjoyment a movement beyond pleasure and pain violent passage beyond the bounds of identity, meaning, and law. jouissance dissolves investments, undoing the consistency of a social reality that relies on identifications The death drive manifests itself, in jouissance jouissance tears the fabric of Symbolic reality as we know it, unraveling the solidity of every object, including the object as which the subject necessarily takes itself, jouissance evokes the death drive that always insists as the void in and of the subject, beyond its fantasy of self- realization, beyond the pleasure principle. Bound up with the death drive is the Child enacting of repetition that fixes identity through identification with the future of the social order Bound up is the figure of the queer, embodying that order’s traumatic encounter with its own inescapable failure, its encounter with the illusion of the future as suture to bind the constitutive wound of the subject’s subjection to the signifier queer sexualities, in extricable from the emergence of the subject in the Symbolic, mark the place of the gap in which the Symbolic confronts what its discourse is in capable of knowing, which is also the place of a jouissance the queer may provide the Symbolic with a sort of necessary reassurance by seeming to give a name to what, as Real, remains unnameable. But repudiations of that figural identity, reflecting a liberal faith in the abstract universality of the subject, though better enabling the extension of rights to those who are still denied them, must similarly reassure by attesting to the seamless coherence of the Symbolic whose dominant narrative would thus supersede the corrosive force of queer irony. If the queer’s abjectified difference, that is, secures normativity’s identity, the1 queer’s disavowal of that difference affirms normativity’s singular truth,, For every refusal of the figural status to which queers are distinctively called reproduces the triumph of narrative as the e9onzatwai of irony, as the logic of a temporality that always serves to “straighten” it out, and thus proclaims the universality of reproductive futurism. Such refusals perform, despite themselves, subservience to the law that effectively imposes politics as the only game in town, exacting as the price of admission the subject’s (hetero)normalization, which is accomplished, regardless of sexual practice or sexual “orientation,” through compulsory abjuration of the future-negating queer. It may seem the Symbolic can only win but that would ignore the correlative fact that it also can only lose. For the division on which the subject rests can never be spirited away and the signifying order will always necessitate the production of some figural repository for the excess that precludes its ultimate realization of the One De-idealizing the metaphorics of meaning on which heteroreproduction takes its stand, queerness exposes sexuality’s inevitable coloration by the drive: its insistence on repetition, its stubborn denial of teleology, its resistance to determinations of meaning and its rejection of spiritualization through marriage to reproductive futurism Queerness as name may well reinforce the Symbolic order of naming, but it names what resists, as signifier, absorption into the Imaginary identity of the name Empty, excessive, and irreducible, it designates the letter animating futurity as a name for the death drive that always informs the Symbolic order, it also names the jouissance forbidden by, but permeating, the Symbolic order itself. By denying our identification with the negativity of this drive those of us in habiting the place of the queer may be able to cast off that queerness but only by shifting the figural burden of queerness to someone else The structural position of queerness and the need to fill it remain. By choosing to accept that position we might undertake the impossible project of imagining an oppositional political stance exempt from the imperative to reproduce the politics of signification which can only return us, byway of the Child, to the politics of reproduction Queerness thus comes to mean nothing for both: for the right wing the nothingness always at war with the positivity of civil society; for the left, nothing more than a sexual practice in need of demystification. reason must fail Sexuality refuses demystification as the Symbolic refuses the queer; for sexuality and the Symbolic become what they are by virtue of such refusals. Beyond the resonance of fantasy lies neither law nor reason The sacralization of the Child thus necessitates the sacrifice of the queer. Queers must respond by insisting on our equal right to the social order’s prerogatives by saying explicitly what Law and the Pope and the whole of the Symbolic order for which they stand hear any way in each and every expression or manifestation of queer sexuality: Fuck the social order and the Child fuck Annie ; fuck Laws fuck the whole network of Symbolic relations and the future that serves as its prop. We might like believe that generous contributions to lobbying groups or generous participation in activist groups or generous doses of legal savvy and electoral sophistication, the future will hold a place for us a place at the political table that won’t have to come at the cost of the places we seek in the bed But there are no queers in that future as there can be no future for queers, chosen as they are to bear the bad tidings that there can be no future at all Those queered by the social order that projects its death drive onto them are no doubt positioned to recognize the structuring fantasy that so defines them. But they’re positioned as well to recognize the irreducibility of that fantasy and the cost of construing it as contingent to the logic of social organization as such. Acceding to this figural identification with the undoing of identity which is also toy with the disarticulation of social and Symbolic form, might well be described as “politically self-destructive But politics and the self as mere prosthesis maintaining the future for the figural Child are what queerness, again as figure, necessarily destroys—necessarily insofar as this “self” is the agent of reproductive futurism and this “politics” the means of its promulgation as the order of social reality , political self-destruction inheres in the only act that counts as one: the act of resisting enslavement to the future in the name of having a life. , if the jouissance , intrinsic to queer (non)identity annihilates the jouissance that works to consolidate identity by allowing reality to coagulate around its ritual reproduction then the only oppositional status to which our queerness could ever lead would depend on our taking seriously the place of the death drive ‘we’re led on to figure and insisting, against the cult of the Child and the political order it enforces, that we are “not the signifier of what might become a new form of ‘social organisation,’ we do not intend a new politics a better society a brighter tomorrow since all of these fantasies reproduce the past through displacement, in the form of the future We choose not to choose the Child it delights in that mortality as the negation of everything that would define itself, moralistically, as pro-life. we must bury the subject in the tomb-like hollow of the signifier, pronouncing at last the words for which we’re condemned should we speak them or not the Child as futurity’s emblem must die the future is mere repetition and just as lethal as the past. And so what is queerest about us, queerest within us, and queerest despite us is this willingness to insist intransitively—to insist that the future stop here.
Queerness is a matter of embodying the Real internal to the Symbolic jouissance dissolves the consistency of a social reality that relies on identifications the Child, enacting repetition fixes identity through identification Bound up is the figure of the queer, embodying that order’s traumatic encounter with its own inescapable failure queer sexualities mark the place of the gap in which the Symbolic confronts what its discourse is in capable of knowing the Symbolic can only lose the division on which the subject rests can never be spirited away signifying order will always necessitate the production of some figural repository for the excess that precludes its ultimate realization of the One Queerness it names what resists, as signifier, absorption into the Imaginary identity of the name it also names the jouissance forbidden by, but permeating, the Symbolic order By denying our identification with the negativity of this drive those of us in habiting the place of the queer may be able to cast off that queerness but only by shifting the figural burden of queerness to someone else structural position of queerness and the need to fill it remain. By choosing to accept that position we might undertake the impossible project of imagining an oppositional political stance exempt from the imperative to reproduce the politics of signification which can only return us, to the politics of reproduction reason must fail Sexuality refuses demystification Beyond the resonance of fantasy lies neither law nor reason Queers must respond by saying explicitly what Law and the Symbolic order hear any way in each expression of queer sexuality: Fuck the social order and the Child fuck Laws We might believe that in activist groups or and electoral sophistication, the future will hold a place for us But there are no queers in that future as there can be no future for queers, chosen as they are to bear the bad tidings that there can be no future at all Acceding to this figural identification with the undoing of identity , might be described as “politically self-destructive But politics and the self as mere prosthesis maintaining the future for the Child are what queerness necessarily destroys the only oppositional status to which our queerness could ever lead would depend the place of the death drive against the cult of the Child we do not intend a new politics a better society a brighter tomorrow since all of these fantasies reproduce the past through displacement, in the form of the future We choose not to choose the Child the Child as futurity’s emblem must die the future is mere repetition and just as lethal as the past. And so what is queerest about us to insist that the future stop here
Queerness, therefore, is never a matter of being or becoming but, embodying the remainder of the Real internal to the Symbolic order. One name for this unnameable remainder, as Lacan describes it, is jouissance, sometimes translated as “enjoyment”: a movement beyond the pleasure principle, beyond the distinctions of pleasure and pain, a violent passage beyond the bounds of identity, meaning, and law. This passage, toward which the pulsion of the drives continuously impels us, may have the effect, insofar as it gets attached to a particular object or end, of congealing identity around the fantasy of satisfaction or fulfillment by means of that object At the same time, however, this jouissance dissolves such fetishistic investments, undoing the consistency of a social reality that relies on Imaginary identifications, on the structures of Symbolic law, and on the paternal metaphor of the name.28 Hence, for Lacan there is another name that designates the unnameability to which jouissance would give us access: “Behind what is named, there is the unnameable,” he writes. “It is in fact because it is unnameable, with all the resonances you can give to this name, that it is akin to the quintessential unnameable, that is to say to death.” The death drive, therefore, manifests itself, though in radically different guises, in both versions of jouissance. To the extent that jouissance, as fantasmatic escape from the alienation intrinsic to meaning, lodges itself in a given object on which identity comes to depend, it produces identity as mortification, reenacting the very constraint of meaning it was intended to help us escape. But to the extent that it tears the fabric of Symbolic reality as we know it, unraveling the solidity of every object, including the object as which the subject necessarily takes itself, jouissance evokes the death drive that always insists as the void in and of the subject, beyond its fantasy of self- realization, beyond the pleasure principle. Bound up with the first of these death drives is the figure of the Child, enacting a logic of repetition that fixes identity through identification with the future of the social order. Bound up with the second is the figure of the queer, embodying that order’s traumatic encounter with its own inescapable failure, its encounter with the illusion of the future as suture to bind the constitutive wound of the subject’s subjection to the signifier, which divides it, paradoxically, both from and into itself. In the preface to Homographesis I wrote that the signifier “gay,” understood “as a figure for the textuality, the rhetoricity, of the sexual... designates the gap or incoherence that every discourse of ‘sexuality’ or ‘sexual identity’ would master.” Extending that claim, I now suggest that queer sexualities, in extricable from the emergence of the subject in the Symbolic, mark the place of the gap in which the Symbolic confronts what its discourse is in capable of knowing, which is also the place of a jouissance from which it can never escape. As a figure for what it can neither fully articulate nor acknowledge, the queer may provide the Symbolic with a sort of necessary reassurance by seeming to give a name to what, as Real, remains unnameable. But repudiations of that figural identity, reflecting a liberal faith in the abstract universality of the subject, though better enabling the extension of rights to those who are still denied them, must similarly reassure by attesting to the seamless coherence of the Symbolic whose dominant narrative would thus supersede the corrosive force of queer irony. If the queer’s abjectified difference, that is, secures normativity’s identity, the1 queer’s disavowal of that difference affirms normativity’s singular truth,, For every refusal of the figural status to which queers are distinctively called reproduces the triumph of narrative as the e9onzatwai of irony, as the logic of a temporality that always serves to “straighten” it out, and thus proclaims the universality of reproductive futurism. Such refusals perform, despite themselves, subservience to the law that effectively imposes politics as the only game in town, exacting as the price of admission the subject’s (hetero)normalization, which is accomplished, regardless of sexual practice or sexual “orientation,” through compulsory abjuration of the future-negating queer. It may seem, from within this structure, that the Symbolic can only win; but that would ignore the correlative fact that it also can only lose. For the division on which the subject rests can never be spirited away and the signifying order will always necessitate the production of some figural repository for the excess that precludes its ultimate realization of the One. In apolitical field whose limit and horizon is reproductive futurism, queerness embodies this death drive, this intransigent jouissance, by figuring sexuality’s implication in the senseless pulsions of that drive. De-idealizing the metaphorics of meaning on which heteroreproduction takes its stand, queerness exposes sexuality’s inevitable coloration by the drive: its insistence on repetition, its stubborn denial of teleology, its resistance to determinations of meaning (except insofar as it means this refusal to admit such determinations of meaning), and, above all, its rejection of spiritualization through marriage to reproductive futurism. Queerness as name may well reinforce the Symbolic order of naming, but it names what resists, as signifier, absorption into the Imaginary identity of the name. Empty, excessive, and irreducible, it designates the letter, the formal element, the lifeless machinery responsible for animating the “spirit” of futurity. And as such, as a name for the death drive that always informs the Symbolic order, it also names the jouissance forbidden by, but permeating, the Symbolic order itself. By denying our identification with the negativity of this drive, and hence our disidentification from the promise of futurity, those of us in habiting the place of the queer may be able to cast off that queerness and enter the properly political sphere, but only by shifting the figural burden of queerness to someone else. The structural position of queerness, after all, and the need to fill it remain. By choosing to accept that position, however, by assuming the “truth” of our queer capacity to figure the undoing of the Symbolic, and of the Symbolic subject as well, we might undertake the impossible project of imagining an oppositional political stance exempt from the imperative to reproduce the politics of signification (the politics aimed at closing the gap opened up by the signifier itself), which can only return us, byway of the Child, to the politics of reproduction. For the liberal’s view of society, which seems to accord the queer a place, endorses no more than the conservative right’s the queer ness of resistance to futurism and thus the queerness of the queer. While the right wing imagines the elimination of queers (or of the need to confront their existence), the left would eliminate queerness by shining the cool light of reason upon it, hoping thereby to expose it as merely a mode of sexual expression free of the all-pervasive coloring, the determining fantasy formation, by means of which it can seem to portend, and not for the right alone, the undoing of the social order and its cynosure, the Child. Queerness thus comes to mean nothing for both: for the right wing the nothingness always at war with the positivity of civil society; for the left, nothing more than a sexual practice in need of demystification. But this is where reason must fail. Sexuality refuses demystification as the Symbolic refuses the queer; for sexuality and the Symbolic become what they are by virtue of such refusals. Ironically— but irony, as I’ve argued, always characterizes queer theory—the demystification of queerness and so, by extension, of sexuality itself, the demystification inherent in the position of liberal rationality, could achieve its realization only by traversing the collective fantasy that invests the social order with mean: ing by way of reproductive futurism. Taken at its word, that is, liberalism’s abstract reason, rescuing queerness for sociality, dissolves, like queerness, the very investments on which sociality rests by doing away with its underlying and sustaining libidinal fantasies. Beyond the resonance of fantasy, after all, lies neither law nor reason. In the beyond of demystification, in that neutral, democratic literality that marks the futurism of the left, one could only encounter a queer dismantling of futurism itself as fantasy and a derealization of the order of meaning that futurism reproduces. Intent on the end, not the ends, of the social, queerness insists that the drive toward that end, which liberalism refuses to imagine, can never be excluded from the structuring fantasy of the social order itself. The sacralization of the Child thus necessitates the sacrifice of the queer. Bernard Law, the former cardinal of Boston, mistaking (or maybe understanding too well) the degree of authority bestowed on him by the signifier of his patronymic, denounced in 1996 proposed legislation giving health care benefits to same-sex partners of municipal employees. He did so by proclaiming, in a noteworthy instance of piety in the sky, that bestowing such access to health care would profoundly diminish the marital bond. “Society,” he opined, “has a special interest in the protection, care and upbringing of children. Because marriage remains the principal, and the best, framework for the nurture, education and socialization of children, the state has a special interest in marriage.”31 With this fatal embrace of a futurism so blindly committed to the figure of the Child that it will justify refusing health care benefits to the adults that some children become, Law lent his voice to the mortifying mantra of a communal jouissance that depends on the fetishization of the Child at the expense of whatever such fetishization must inescapably queer. Some seven years later, after Law had resigned for his failure to protect Catholic children from sexual assault by pedophile priests, Pope John Paul II returned to this theme, condemning state-recognized same-sex unions as parodic versions of authentic families, “based on individual egoism” rather than genuine love. Justifying that condemnation, he observed, “Such a ‘caricature’ has no future and cannot give future to any society.”3 Queers must respond to the violent force of such constant provocations not only by insisting on our equal right to the social order’s prerogatives, not only by avowing our capacity to promote that order’s coherence and integrity, but also by saying explicitly what Law and the Pope and the whole of the Symbolic order for which they stand hear any way in each and every expression or manifestation of queer sexuality: Fuck the social order and the Child in whose name we’re collectively terrorized; fuck Annie; fuck the waif from Les Mis; fuck the poor, innocent kid on the Net; fuck Laws both with capital ls and with small; fuck the whole network of Symbolic relations and the future that serves as its prop. We might like believe that with patience, with work, with generous contributions to lobbying groups or generous participation in activist groups or generous doses of legal savvy and electoral sophistication, the future will hold a place for us—a place at the political table that won’t have to come at the cost of the places we seek in the bed or the bar or the baths. But there are no queers in that future as there can be no future for queers, chosen as they are to bear the bad tidings that there can be no future at all; that the future, as Annie’s hymn to the hope of “Tomorrow” understands, is “always/ A day/ Away.” Like the lovers on Keats’s Grecian urn, forever “near the goal” of a union they’ll never in fact achieve, we’re held in thrall by a future continually deferred by time itself, constrained to pursue the dream of a day when today and tomorrow are one. That future is nothing but kid stuff, reborn each day to screen out the grave that gapes from within the lifeless letter, luring us into, ensnaring us in, reality’s gossamer web. Those queered by the social order that projects its death drive onto them are no doubt positioned to recognize the structuring fantasy that so defines them. But they’re positioned as well to recognize the irreducibility of that fantasy and the cost of construing it as contingent to the logic of social organization as such. Acceding to this figural identification with the undoing of identity, which is also toy with the disarticulation of social and Symbolic form, might well be described, in John Brenkman’s words, as “politically self-destructive.” But politics (as the social elaboration of reality) and the self as mere prosthesis maintaining the future for the figural Child), are what queerness, again as figure, necessarily destroys—necessarily insofar as this “self” is the agent of reproductive futurism and this “politics” the means of its promulgation as the order of social reality. But perhaps, as Lacan’s engagement with Antigone in Seminar7 suggests, political self-destruction inheres in the only act that counts as one: the act of resisting enslavement to the future in the name of having a life. If the fate of the queer is to figure the fate that cub the thread of futurity, if the jouissance, the corrosive enjoyment, intrinsic to queer (non)identity annihilates the fetishistic jouissance that works to consolidate identity by allowing reality to coagulate around its ritual reproduction, then the only oppositional status to which our queerness could ever lead would depend on our taking seriously the place of the death drive ‘we’re led on to figure and insisting, against the cult of the Child and the political order it enforces, that we, as Guy Hocquenghem made clear, are “not the signifier of what might become a new form of ‘social organisation,’ that we do not intend a new politics, a better society, a brighter tomorrow, since all of these fantasies reproduce the past through displacement, in the form of the future. We choose, instead, not to choose the Child, as disciplinary image of the Imaginary past or as site of a projective identification with an always impossible future. The queerness we propose, in Hocquenghem’s words, “is unaware of the passing of generations as stages on the road to better living. It knows nothing about ‘sacrifice now for the sake of future generations’ . . . lit) knows that civilisation alone is mortal.” Even more: it delights in that mortality as the negation of everything that would define itself, moralistically, as pro-life. It is we who must bury the subject in the tomb-like hollow of the signifier, pronouncing at last the words for which we’re condemned should we speak them or not: that we are the advocates of abortion; that the Child as futurity’s emblem must die; that the future is mere repetition and just as lethal as the past. Our queerness has nothing to offer a Symbolic that lives by denying that nothingness except an insistence on the haunting excess that this nothingness entails, an insistence on the negativity that pierces the fantasy screen of futurity, shattering narrative temporality with irony’s always explosive force. And so what is queerest about us, queerest within us, and queerest despite us is this willingness to insist intransitively—to insist that the future stop here.
15,605
<h4><strong>Demanding the future stops here may seem politically self-destructive; however, this act establishes an anti-politic divorced from the futurity of the Child. Anything else retains the structural position of the queer—denying the negativity of queerness only shifts the figural burden of queerness onto someone else. We do not promise a better future or a brighter tomorrow, but an end to the sacralization of the Child and the ensuing sacrifice of the queer.</h4><p>Edelman ’04</strong>, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive<u>, p. 35-31</p><p><mark>Queerness</u></mark>, therefore, <u><mark>is </mark>never <mark>a matter of </mark>being or becoming but, <mark>embodying</mark> <mark>the</u></mark> remainder of the <u><mark>Real internal to the Symbolic</u></mark> order. One name for this unnameable remainder, as Lacan describes it, is <u><strong>jouissance</u></strong>, sometimes translated as “<u>enjoyment</u>”: <u>a movement beyond</u> the pleasure principle, beyond the distinctions of <u>pleasure and pain</u>, a <u>violent passage beyond the bounds of identity, meaning, and law.</u> This passage, toward which the pulsion of the drives continuously impels us, may have the effect, insofar as it gets attached to a particular object or end, of congealing identity around the fantasy of satisfaction or fulfillment by means of that object At the same time, however, this <u><mark>jouissance</mark> <mark>dissolves</u></mark> such fetishistic <u>investments, undoing <mark>the consistency of a social reality that relies on</mark> </u>Imaginary<u> <mark>identifications</u></mark>, on the structures of Symbolic law, and on the paternal metaphor of the name.28 Hence, for Lacan there is another name that designates the unnameability to which jouissance would give us access: “Behind what is named, there is the unnameable,” he writes. “It is in fact because it is unnameable, with all the resonances you can give to this name, that it is akin to the quintessential unnameable, that is to say to death.” <u>The death drive</u>, therefore, <u>manifests itself, </u>though in radically different guises,<u> in </u>both versions of<u> jouissance</u>. To the extent that <u>jouissance</u>, as fantasmatic escape from the alienation intrinsic to meaning, lodges itself in a given object on which identity comes to depend, it produces identity as mortification, reenacting the very constraint of meaning it was intended to help us escape. But to the extent that it <u>tears the fabric of Symbolic reality as we know it, unraveling the solidity of every object, including the object as which the subject necessarily takes itself,<mark> </mark>jouissance evokes the death drive that always insists as the void in and of the subject, beyond its fantasy of self- realization, beyond the pleasure principle.</p><p>Bound up with the </u>first of these<u> death drive</u>s<u> is </u>the figure of <u><mark>the Child</u>,</mark> <u><mark>enacting</u></mark> a logic <u>of <mark>repetition </mark>that <mark>fixes identity through</mark> <mark>identification</mark> with the future of the social order</u>. <u><mark>Bound up</u></mark> with the second <u><mark>is</mark> <mark>the figure of the queer, embodying that order’s traumatic encounter with its own inescapable failure</mark>, its encounter with the illusion of the future as suture to bind the constitutive wound of the subject’s subjection to the signifier</u>, which divides it, paradoxically, both from and into itself. In the preface to Homographesis I wrote that the signifier “gay,” understood “as a figure for the textuality, the rhetoricity, of the sexual... designates the gap or incoherence that every discourse of ‘sexuality’ or ‘sexual identity’ would master.” Extending that claim, I now suggest that <u><mark>queer sexualities</mark>, in extricable from the emergence of the subject in the Symbolic, <mark>mark the place of the gap in which the Symbolic confronts what its discourse is in capable of knowing</mark>, which is also the place of a jouissance</u> from which it can never escape. As a figure for what it can neither fully articulate nor acknowledge, <u>the queer may provide the Symbolic with a sort of necessary reassurance by seeming to give a name to what, as Real, remains unnameable. But repudiations of that figural identity, reflecting a liberal faith in the abstract universality of the subject, though better enabling the extension of rights to those who are still denied them, must similarly reassure by attesting to the seamless coherence of the Symbolic whose dominant narrative would thus supersede the corrosive force of queer irony. If the queer’s abjectified difference, that is, secures normativity’s identity, the1 queer’s disavowal of that difference affirms normativity’s singular truth,, For every refusal of the figural status to which queers are distinctively called reproduces the triumph of narrative as the e9onzatwai of irony, as the logic of a temporality that always serves to “straighten” it out, and thus proclaims the universality of reproductive futurism. Such refusals perform, despite themselves, subservience to the law that effectively imposes politics as the only game in town, exacting as the price of admission the subject’s (hetero)normalization, which is accomplished, regardless of sexual practice or sexual “orientation,” through compulsory abjuration of the future-negating queer.</p><p>It may seem</u>, from within this structure, that <u><mark>the Symbolic</mark> can only win</u>; <u><strong>but that would ignore the correlative fact that it also <mark>can only lose</strong></mark>. For <mark>the division on which the subject rests can never be spirited away</mark> and the <mark>signifying order</mark> <mark>will always necessitate the production of some figural repository for the excess that precludes its ultimate realization of the One</u></mark>. In apolitical field whose limit and horizon is reproductive futurism, queerness embodies this death drive, this intransigent jouissance, by figuring sexuality’s implication in the senseless pulsions of that drive. <u>De-idealizing the metaphorics of meaning on which heteroreproduction takes its stand, queerness exposes sexuality’s inevitable coloration by the drive: its insistence on repetition, its stubborn denial of teleology, its resistance to determinations of meaning </u>(except insofar as it means this refusal to admit such determinations of meaning), <u>and</u>, above all, <u>its rejection of spiritualization through marriage to reproductive futurism</u>. <u><strong><mark>Queerness </mark>as name may well reinforce the Symbolic order of naming, but <mark>it names what resists, as signifier, absorption into the Imaginary identity of the name</u></strong></mark>. <u>Empty, excessive, and irreducible, it designates the letter</u>, the formal element, the lifeless machinery responsible for <u>animating</u> the “spirit” of <u>futurity</u>. And as such, <u>as a name for the death drive that always informs the Symbolic order,<mark> it also names the jouissance forbidden by, but permeating, the Symbolic order </mark>itself.</p><p><strong><mark>By denying our identification with the negativity of this drive</u></strong></mark>, and hence our disidentification from the promise of futurity, <u><strong><mark>those of us in habiting the place of the queer may be able to cast off that queerness</u></strong></mark> and enter the properly political sphere, <u><strong><mark>but only by shifting the figural burden of queerness to someone else</u></strong></mark>. <u>The <mark>structural position of queerness</u></mark>, after all, <u><mark>and the need to fill it remain. By choosing to accept that position</u></mark>, however, by assuming the “truth” of our queer capacity to figure the undoing of the Symbolic, and of the Symbolic subject as well, <u><mark>we might undertake the impossible project of imagining an oppositional political stance exempt from the imperative to reproduce the politics of signification</u></mark> (the politics aimed at closing the gap opened up by the signifier itself), <u><mark>which can only return us, </mark>byway of the Child,<mark> to the politics of reproduction</u></mark>. For the liberal’s view of society, which seems to accord the queer a place, endorses no more than the conservative right’s the queer ness of resistance to futurism and thus the queerness of the queer. While the right wing imagines the elimination of queers (or of the need to confront their existence), the left would eliminate queerness by shining the cool light of reason upon it, hoping thereby to expose it as merely a mode of sexual expression free of the all-pervasive coloring, the determining fantasy formation, by means of which it can seem to portend, and not for the right alone, the undoing of the social order and its cynosure, the Child. <u>Queerness thus comes to mean nothing for both: for the right wing the nothingness always at war with the positivity of civil society; for the left, nothing more than a sexual practice in need of demystification.</p><p></u>But this is where <u><mark>reason must fail</u></mark>. <u><mark>Sexuality refuses demystification</mark> as the Symbolic refuses the queer; for sexuality and the Symbolic become what they are by virtue of such refusals.</u> Ironically— but irony, as I’ve argued, always characterizes queer theory—the demystification of queerness and so, by extension, of sexuality itself, the demystification inherent in the position of liberal rationality, could achieve its realization only by traversing the collective fantasy that invests the social order with mean: ing by way of reproductive futurism. Taken at its word, that is, liberalism’s abstract reason, rescuing queerness for sociality, dissolves, like queerness, the very investments on which sociality rests by doing away with its underlying and sustaining libidinal fantasies. <u><mark>Beyond the resonance of fantasy</u></mark>, after all, <u><mark>lies neither law nor reason</u></mark>. In the beyond of demystification, in that neutral, democratic literality that marks the futurism of the left, one could only encounter a queer dismantling of futurism itself as fantasy and a derealization of the order of meaning that futurism reproduces. Intent on the end, not the ends, of the social, queerness insists that the drive toward that end, which liberalism refuses to imagine, can never be excluded from the structuring fantasy of the social order itself. <u>The sacralization of the Child thus necessitates the sacrifice of the queer.</p><p></u>Bernard Law, the former cardinal of Boston, mistaking (or maybe understanding too well) the degree of authority bestowed on him by the signifier of his patronymic, denounced in 1996 proposed legislation giving health care benefits to same-sex partners of municipal employees. He did so by proclaiming, in a noteworthy instance of piety in the sky, that bestowing such access to health care would profoundly diminish the marital bond. “Society,” he opined, “has a special interest in the protection, care and upbringing of children. Because marriage remains the principal, and the best, framework for the nurture, education and socialization of children, the state has a special interest in marriage.”31 With this fatal embrace of a futurism so blindly committed to the figure of the Child that it will justify refusing health care benefits to the adults that some children become, Law lent his voice to the mortifying mantra of a communal jouissance that depends on the fetishization of the Child at the expense of whatever such fetishization must inescapably queer. Some seven years later, after Law had resigned for his failure to protect Catholic children from sexual assault by pedophile priests, Pope John Paul II returned to this theme, condemning state-recognized same-sex unions as parodic versions of authentic families, “based on individual egoism” rather than genuine love. Justifying that condemnation, he observed, “Such a ‘caricature’ has no future and cannot give future to any society.”3 <u><mark>Queers must respond</mark> </u>to the violent force of such constant provocations not only <u>by insisting on our equal right to the social order’s prerogatives</u>, not only by avowing our capacity to promote that order’s coherence and integrity, but also<u> <mark>by saying explicitly what Law</mark> and the Pope <mark>and </mark>the whole of <mark>the Symbolic order </mark>for which they stand <mark>hear any way in each </mark>and every <mark>expression </mark>or manifestation <mark>of queer sexuality:</u> <u>Fuck the social order and the Child</u></mark> in whose name we’re collectively terrorized; <u>fuck Annie</u>; fuck the waif from Les Mis; fuck the poor, innocent kid on the Net<u>; <mark>fuck Laws</u></mark> both with capital ls and with small; <u>fuck the whole network of Symbolic relations and the future that serves as its prop.</p><p><strong><mark>We might </mark>like <mark>believe that</u></strong></mark> with patience, with work, with <u><strong>generous contributions to lobbying groups or generous participation <mark>in</mark> <mark>activist groups or </mark>generous doses of legal savvy <mark>and</mark> <mark>electoral sophistication, the future will hold a place for us</u></strong></mark>—<u>a place at the political table that won’t have to come at the cost of the places we seek in the bed</u> or the bar or the baths. <u><mark>But there are no queers in that future as there can be no future for queers, chosen as they are to bear the bad tidings that there can be no future at all</u></mark>; that the future, as Annie’s hymn to the hope of “Tomorrow” understands, is “always/ A day/ Away.” Like the lovers on Keats’s Grecian urn, forever “near the goal” of a union they’ll never in fact achieve, we’re held in thrall by a future continually deferred by time itself, constrained to pursue the dream of a day when today and tomorrow are one. That future is nothing but kid stuff, reborn each day to screen out the grave that gapes from within the lifeless letter, luring us into, ensnaring us in, reality’s gossamer web. <u>Those queered by the social order that projects its death drive onto them are no doubt positioned to recognize the structuring fantasy that so defines them. But they’re positioned as well to recognize the irreducibility of that fantasy and the cost of construing it as contingent to the logic of social organization as such<strong>. <mark>Acceding to this figural identification with the undoing of identity</u></strong></mark>, <u>which is also toy with the disarticulation of social and Symbolic form<mark>, might </mark>well <mark>be described</u></mark>, in John Brenkman’s words, <u><mark>as “politically self-destructive</u></mark>.” <u><mark>But politics</u></mark> (as the social elaboration of reality) <u><mark>and the self as mere prosthesis</mark> <mark>maintaining the future for the </mark>figural <mark>Child</u></mark>), <u><mark>are what queerness</mark>, again as figure, <mark>necessarily destroys</mark>—necessarily insofar as this “self” is the agent of reproductive futurism and this “politics” the means of its promulgation as the order of social reality</u>. But perhaps, as Lacan’s engagement with Antigone in Seminar7 suggests<u>, political self-destruction inheres in the only act that counts as one: the act of resisting enslavement to the future in the name of having a life.</p><p></u>If the fate of the queer is to figure the fate that cub the thread of futurity<u>, if the jouissance</u>, the corrosive enjoyment<u>, intrinsic to queer (non)identity annihilates the</u> fetishistic <u>jouissance that works to consolidate identity by allowing reality to coagulate around its ritual reproduction</u>, <u>then <mark>the only oppositional status to which our queerness could ever lead would depend </mark>on our taking seriously <mark>the place of the death drive</mark> ‘we’re led on to figure and insisting, <mark>against the cult of the Child</mark> and the political order it enforces, that we</u>, as Guy Hocquenghem made clear, <u>are “not the signifier of what might become a new form of ‘social organisation,’ </u>that <u><mark>we do not intend a new politics</u></mark>, <u><mark>a better society</u></mark>, <u><mark>a brighter tomorrow</u></mark>, <u><mark>since all of these fantasies reproduce the past through displacement, in the form of the future</u></mark>. <u><strong><mark>We choose</u></strong></mark>, instead, <u><strong><mark>not to choose the Child</u></strong></mark>, as disciplinary image of the Imaginary past or as site of a projective identification with an always impossible future. The queerness we propose, in Hocquenghem’s words, “is unaware of the passing of generations as stages on the road to better living. It knows nothing about ‘sacrifice now for the sake of future generations’ . . . lit) knows that civilisation alone is mortal.” Even more: <u>it delights in that mortality as the negation of everything that would define itself, moralistically, as pro-life.</u> It is <u>we</u> who <u>must bury the subject in the tomb-like hollow of the signifier, pronouncing at last the words for which we’re condemned should we speak them or not</u>: that we are the advocates of abortion; that <u><mark>the Child as futurity’s emblem must die</u></mark>; that <u><mark>the future is mere repetition and just as lethal as the past.</u></mark> Our queerness has nothing to offer a Symbolic that lives by denying that nothingness except an insistence on the haunting excess that this nothingness entails, an insistence on the negativity that pierces the fantasy screen of futurity, shattering narrative temporality with irony’s always explosive force. <u><mark>And so what is queerest about us</mark>, queerest within us, and queerest despite us is this willingness to insist intransitively—<strong><mark>to insist that the future stop here</mark>.</p></u></strong>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
1,296,740
28
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,345
Disregarding drug control treaties spills over- destroys international law
Bewley-Taylor 2003
Bewley-Taylor 2003 (David, Department of American Studies, Vnireraty of Wales Swansea Challenging the UN drug control conventions: problems and Possibilities International Journal of Drug Policy 14 (2003) 171/179, http://www.unawestminster.org.uk/pdf/drugs/UNdrugsBewley_Taylor_IJDP14.pdf)
Another strategy would be for Parties to simply ignore the treaties they could institute any policies deemed to be necessary including legalisation of cannabis Disregarding the treaties raises serious issues beyond the realm of drug control The possibility of nations unilaterally ignoring drug control treaty commitments could threaten the stability of the entire treaty system selective application would call into question the validity of many and varied conventions.
Disregarding the treaties raises serious issues nations unilaterally ignoring drug control treaty commitments could threaten the stability of the entire treaty system selective application would call into question the validity of many and varied conventions.
Another strategy would be for Parties to simply ignore the treaties or certain parts of them. In this way they could institute any policies deemed to be necessary at the national level, including for example the legalisation of cannabis and the introduction of a licensing system for domestic producers. This option has been gaining support amongst many opponents of the prohibition based international system for some time. Disregarding all or selected components of the treaties, however, raises serious issues beyond the realm of drug control. The possibility of nations unilaterally ignoring drug control treaty commitments could threaten the stability of the entire treaty system. As a consequence states may be wary of opting out. Some international lawyers argue that all treaties can naturally cease to be binding when a fundamental change of circumstances has occurred since the time of signing (Starke, 1989, pp. 473/474). Bearing in mind the dramatic changes in the nature and extent of the drug problem since the 1960s, this doctrine of rebus sic stantibus could probably be applied to the drug treaties. Yet the selective application of such a principle would call into question the validity of many and varied conventions.
1,236
<h4>Disregarding drug control treaties spills over- destroys international law</h4><p><strong>Bewley-Taylor 2003</strong> <u>(David, Department of American Studies, Vnireraty of Wales Swansea Challenging the UN drug control conventions: problems and Possibilities International Journal of Drug Policy 14 (2003) 171/179, http://www.unawestminster.org.uk/pdf/drugs/UNdrugsBewley_Taylor_IJDP14.pdf)</p><p>Another strategy would be for Parties to simply ignore the treaties</u> or certain parts of them. In this way <u>they could institute any policies deemed to be necessary</u> at the national level, <u>including</u> for example the <u>legalisation of cannabis</u> and the introduction of a licensing system for domestic producers. This option has been gaining support amongst many opponents of the prohibition based international system for some time. <u><mark>Disregarding</u></mark> all or selected components of <u><mark>the treaties</u></mark>, however, <u><mark>raises serious issues</mark> beyond the realm of drug control</u>. <u>The possibility of <mark>nations unilaterally ignoring drug control treaty commitments could <strong>threaten the stability of the entire treaty system</u></strong></mark>. As a consequence states may be wary of opting out. Some international lawyers argue that all treaties can naturally cease to be binding when a fundamental change of circumstances has occurred since the time of signing (Starke, 1989, pp. 473/474). Bearing in mind the dramatic changes in the nature and extent of the drug problem since the 1960s, this doctrine of rebus sic stantibus could probably be applied to the drug treaties. Yet the <u><mark>selective application</u></mark> of such a principle <u><mark>would <strong>call into question the validity of many and varied conventions</strong>.</p></u></mark>
null
null
Off
193,806
47
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,346
Legalizing sales in the US would take down the illegal market
Calandrillo 4
Calandrillo 4 Steve P. Calandrillo, Associate Professor, Univ. of Washington School of Law. J.D., Harvard Law School. B.A. in Economics, Univ. of California at Berkeley. George Mason Law Review Fall, 2004 13 Geo. Mason L. Rev. 69 ARTICLE: Cash for Kidneys? Utilizing Incentives to End America's Organ Shortage lexis
if we cannot prevent the black markets in human organs that continue to thrive worldwide today, a thoughtful and responsible regulatory solution in America might be the best response a well-regulated legalized market in the U.S. may not completely eliminate black markets worldwide However, it is reasonable to suspect that an American market would significantly reduce the demand for black market organs, especially given the ability of a regulated market to better ensure the quality of its product. Furthermore, a legalized market in the U.S. (with appropriate safeguards to prevent abuse of sellers) may lead to similar structures abroad.
a thoughtful and responsible regulatory solution in America might be the best response it is reasonable to suspect that an American market would significantly reduce the demand for black market organs, especially given the ability of a regulated market to better ensure the quality of its product. Furthermore, a legalized market in the U.S. may lead to similar structures abroad
Moreover, if we cannot prevent the black markets in human organs that continue to thrive worldwide today, a thoughtful and responsible regulatory solution in America might be the best response. Many scholars have chronicled the reality that today's black markets lead to a host of abuses, provide for no follow-up health care, and generally exploit the poor to the wealthy's advantage. n180 Stephen Spurr details the potential for misrepresentation and fraud against both buyers and sellers today, as prices spiral out of control for organs that are of dubious quality. n181 Gloria Banks decries the exploitation of society's most vulnerable individuals in the organ sale trade, and urges legal and ethical safeguards for their protection. n182 Susan Hankin Denise adds that a properly regulated organ market may therefore be a better solution to the problem of scarcity than the outright ban we witness today. n183 FOOTNOTE ATTACHED n183 See Denise, supra note 72, at 1035-36 (arguing that regulated markets are superior to the existing ban on organ sales in the U.S.). Of course, even a well-regulated legalized market in the U.S. may not completely eliminate black markets worldwide if patients can still find organs more cheaply abroad. However, it is reasonable to suspect that an American market would significantly reduce the demand for black market organs, especially given the ability of a regulated market to better ensure the quality of its product. Furthermore, a legalized market in the U.S. (with appropriate safeguards to prevent abuse of sellers) may lead to similar structures abroad. On the other hand, one might argue that competing markets might lead to a "race to the bottom" in terms of regulatory standards, as each country tries to gain more market share.
1,779
<h4>Legalizing sales in the US would take down the illegal market </h4><p><strong>Calandrillo 4</strong> Steve P. Calandrillo, Associate Professor, Univ. of Washington School of Law. J.D., Harvard Law School. B.A. in Economics, Univ. of California at Berkeley. George Mason Law Review Fall, 2004 13 Geo. Mason L. Rev. 69 ARTICLE: Cash for Kidneys? Utilizing Incentives to End America's Organ Shortage lexis</p><p>Moreover, <u>if we cannot prevent the black markets in human organs that continue to thrive worldwide today, <mark>a thoughtful and responsible regulatory solution in America might be the best response</u></mark>. Many scholars have chronicled the reality that today's black markets lead to a host of abuses, provide for no follow-up health care, and generally exploit the poor to the wealthy's advantage. n180 Stephen Spurr details the potential for misrepresentation and fraud against both buyers and sellers today, as prices spiral out of control for organs that are of dubious quality. n181 Gloria Banks decries the exploitation of society's most vulnerable individuals in the organ sale trade, and urges legal and ethical safeguards for their protection. n182 Susan Hankin Denise adds that a properly regulated organ market may therefore be a better solution to the problem of scarcity than the outright ban we witness today. n183 FOOTNOTE ATTACHED n183 See Denise, supra note 72, at 1035-36 (arguing that regulated markets are superior to the existing ban on organ sales in the U.S.). Of course, even <u>a well-regulated legalized market in the U.S. may not completely eliminate black markets worldwide </u>if patients can still find organs more cheaply abroad. <u>However, <mark>it is reasonable to suspect that an American market would <strong>significantly reduce the demand for black market organs</strong>, especially given the ability of a regulated market to better ensure the quality of its product. Furthermore, a legalized market in the U.S.</mark> (with appropriate safeguards to prevent abuse of sellers) <strong><mark>may lead to similar structures abroad</strong></mark>.</u> On the other hand, one might argue that competing markets might lead to a "race to the bottom" in terms of regulatory standards, as each country tries to gain more market share. </p>
null
null
Contention 2 is the Illegal market
430,264
17
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,347
O/Ws the aff—
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><strong>O/Ws the aff—</h4></strong>
Ableism
Impact
2NC K
430,660
1
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,348
Comprehensive arg – they medicalize suicide on three registers – the act, the practice, and the social ethos of death – it’s not just a question of doctors
Salem 99
Salem 99 Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full
null
Medicalizing suicide encompasses three facets the medicalization of an act, of a practice, and above all of the social ethos of death as long as the physician is in charge physician-assisted suicide entails the medicalization of the act of suicide as physician-assisted suicide presupposes medical assistance it cannot be conceived as immersed in the realm of self-determination Assisted suicide does not even require medical skill…. If freeing up patients truly is the goal, then assisted suicide's advocates disserve patients when they do not advocate ending the physician's exclusive power to prescribe medication advocates of patients’ rights end up empowering doctors more than patients idealization and the willingness to delegate to physicians the exclusive right to assist suicide bespeaks the social and symbolic power already conferred on medicine and medical professionals in our societies. even the most radical advocates of physician-assisted suicide recognize the need to establish protocols and guidelines to prevent abuses Medical authority, that is, is assumed to have the proper ability to unveil the “real truth” behind the request to die The insult to autonomy is not exerted through repression it is exercised through normalization” of suicide, the subordination to medical scrutiny of this event and the person making the request medicalizing (assisted) suicide jeopardizes autonomy not only when the patient's request is denied if one does not wish to submit to those rules, “do it yourself” remains a way out this seems to admit that ultimately assisted suicide has to do with something beyond strict self-determination physician-assisted suicide ends up reinforcing a power external to the self. It reinforces medical power at the expense of the individual in a very sensitive realm: one's decision to die
Medicalizing suicide encompasses three different (though interrelated) facets: the medicalization of an act, of a practice, and above all of the social ethos of death and suicide. Medicalizing the act of suicide In the typical physician-assisted suicide scenario, the patient is responsible both for requesting aid in dying and for performing the final deed, and she or he construes the act basically as suicide. Yet as long as the physician is in charge of assisting the patient—either by his or her physical presence or by supplying the medical means to perform the act—physician-assisted suicide entails the medicalization of the act of suicide. Ideally, for the physician to assist a patient's suicide the physician must be physically present—as attested in Timothy Quill's regrets for “abandoning” Diane, leaving her to take the prescribed lethal medication alone.15 Thus what is intriguing in physician-assisted suicide is not that ventilators, tubes, CPR, and so on are supplanted by “lethal drugs,” but that even in this context the physician and medicine are overwhelmingly present in the setting of death. Even without the doctor's physical presence in the last scene, as long as physician-assisted suicide presupposes medical assistance it cannot be conceived as immersed in the realm of self-determination. Unless doctors are reduced strictly to being instruments to fulfill their patients’ desires, physician-assisted suicide enacts what must be seen as a mutual decision. But what kind of questions are at stake in this joint decision? Proponents of assisted suicide suggest that patient and physician discuss the patient's medical condition and explore alternatives for alleviating pain and suffering. If it comes to it, the physician should provide a prescription for a lethal drug that leads to a “rapid” and “painless” death.16 That is, the decision to die by suicide is treated precisely as if it were a set of clinical problems to be solved medically—the “private,” “intimate,” “self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event. Medicalizing suicide as professional practice Medicalizing suicide also points to the fact that if legalized, physician-assisted suicide as a legitimate practice would become the prerogative of physicians. Indeed, Jack Kevorkian has seen the exclusive right as the foundation for a new medical subspeciality of “obitiatry.”17 This monopoly leads to the more general question of why aid in dying should be provided only by a medical practitioner. Why, that is, should assistance in suicide be understood as requiring medical authority rather than, for instance, a community of family or friends? The most obvious answer is that physicians—and only physicians—have the necessary technical skills to ensure a “rapid” and “painless” death. But as some critics have noted, “Assisted suicide does not even require medical skill…. If freeing up patients truly is the goal, then assisted suicide's advocates disserve patients when they do not advocate ending the physician's exclusive power to prescribe medication. Ironically, the advocates of patients’ rights end up empowering doctors more than they do patients.”18 Yet even those who maintain that technical knowledge is imperative do not confine their justification of physician-assisted suicide to this reason. Placing suicide under the stewardship of medicine is further defended as a way of “enhancing public accountability of the practice” and “protecting against abuse.”19 From the patient's perspective, the request for aid in dying may mean a “desire for companionship in pursuing a difficult course of action, a wish for confirmation of a decision about which the patient is unsure or simply a cry for help” (pp. 88–89, note 42). Moreover, since suicide is still stigmatized, “seeking a physician's assistance may be a way of trying to remove that stigma.”20 But inasmuch as cultural preconceptions and loneliness (whatever its source) are far from being exclusively medical issues, we must ask why we expect doctors to respond to them. Two possible answers come to mind: either medicine is moving beyond its proper role, or the scope of medical competence has already been extended beyond appropriate boundaries. It seems reasonable to conclude that ceding monopoly of assistance in suicide to doctors is anchored in an inflation of the physician's role, as well as in the extreme idealization of physicians’ character and the relationships they establish with patients. The bond physicians establish with patients is supposedly effective, collaborative, and committed.21 Both this idealization and the willingness to delegate to physicians the exclusive right to assist suicide bespeaks the social and symbolic power already conferred on medicine and medical professionals in our societies. In other words, it is not (or not only) the need for technical expertise that impels us to physician-assisted suicide. Rather, our culture, so impregnated by medicalization, takes for granted that assisted suicide should fall under the control and supervision of medicine. Medicalizing the morality of suicide As a legitimate domain of professional practice, then, physician-assisted suicide necessarily involves medicalizing the moral questions surrounding suicide. Physician-assisted suicide presupposes, and ultimately is, a medical judgment about death or suicide; it is a medical evaluation of the fairness and legitimacy of a person's (not simply a patient's) desire or choice to end his or her life. With some few exceptions, even the most radical advocates of physician-assisted suicide recognize the need to establish protocols and guidelines to prevent abuses, protect the vulnerable, guarantee public accountability, and even to assure the autonomous character of the patient's choice. Surely these aims are respectable and the setting up of criteria just and reasonable. Yet establishing medical guidelines also introduces tensions into the value of autonomy in several ways. The requisites for physician-assisted suicide (must the patient be terminally ill? which medical specialists are best qualified as consultants?) are still being debated. There is, however, agreement about the moral attributes that the patient and his or her request must evince: the decision to die must be “informed,” “rational,” “stable,” and “fully free” or “voluntary.”22 And there is broad agreement that to ensure that these conditions are fulfilled the patient must submit to screening by a team of doctors (the treating physician, a consulting physician, and a psychiatrist) who would evaluate the request for aid in dying. This requirement assumes that besides undue external influences, some impulses or dispositions emanating from the patient herself or himself—such as depression or guilt—may threaten “pure choice.” “Voluntariness” in this sense must be safeguarded from undue influence stemming not only from outside, but also from within. Ultimately, this is to assume that the inner world may be obscure to the individual, that she or he may be half blind to her or his own choice, desire, or personal truth. The presumption that the inner world is or may be opaque to the individual suggests a second underlying presupposition: someone other than the person requesting aid in dying has greater expertise in judging the appropriateness of that request. Medical authority, that is, is assumed to have the proper ability to unveil the “real truth” behind the request to die. The patient's treating physician, along with psychiatric and/or palliative care consultants, is charged to distinguish authentic from distorted choices; that is, to discern whether the request is pertinent or pathological (and if so, whether it is “curable” by medical means). Both these premises obviously collide with the principles of autonomy and self-determination. Both displace the final decision concerning suicide from the patient to the physician's judgment that the request is appropriate and free from “undue influence.” The insult to autonomy is not exerted through repression, as was the criminalization of suicide. Rather, it is exercised through what Foucault would call the “normalization” of suicide, the subordination to medical scrutiny of this event and the person making the request.23 The “patient” is subjected to observation, examination, and inquiry to confirm the “rationality” and “voluntariness” of his or her request. Thus medicalizing (assisted) suicide jeopardizes autonomy not only when the patient's request is denied for one reason or another. Requiring that the patient submit to medical surveillance is, in itself, an outrage to autonomy as this value is classically defined.24 To illustrate how complex is the apparatus through which suicide is normalized, consider guidelines suggested by Frank Miller, Howard Brody, and Timothy Quill, for example. To ensure public accountability for physician-assisted suicide, to guarantee that the procedure is used only as a “last resort,” and to assure that the patient's decision is genuinely voluntary, the authors suggest palliative care consultants and regional palliative care committees as the core of a whole supervising system.25 Thus the primary physician would be prohibited from providing lethal drugs without prior consultation with a palliative care expert who, based on “examination of medical records and interviews with the treating physician, the patient and the interested members of the patient's family” (p. 121), would assess the authenticity of the request to die. Patients and their physicians would have the right to appeal the consultant's denial of requests for assisted suicide to regional palliative care committees. The bureaucratization of suicide built into such proposals entails serious constraints on patients’ self-determination. Subjecting individuals who request aid in dying to this kind of scrutiny further affronts their dignity in putting all such requests under suspicion. In the name of protecting individuals from irreversible self-harm all are in principle treated as moral patients rather than moral agents and are presumed to be mentally incompetent. The capacity to make autonomous decisions, which is presumed in all other cases unless demonstrated otherwise, is stood on its head in physician-assisted suicide. Patients must prove their decisionmaking capacity from the outset. One of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dying. Subjecting the individual to medical norms in this way also introduces a tension for one of the central questions of liberal philosophers. If, as the liberal argument claims, the morality or immorality of decisions at the end of life rests on the competent patient's wishes rather than on a distinction between killing and allowing to die,26 protocols that may ultimately deny a patient's request for assistance in dying assert, in effect, that moral authority resides outside the patient's choice. And if medicine may, morally, reject patients’ autonomous requests for aid, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the value of patient autonomy becomes more rhetorical than real. Admittedly, even liberal theorists emphasize that there are limits to autonomy, and that like other important rights, the right to physician-assisted suicide is not absolute and can properly be restricted under certain circumstances. Indeed, Ronald Dworkin and others argue precisely that because autonomy must be protected and preserved physician-assisted suicide must be regulated. Under certain conditions the state has the power to override individual rights to protect patients from undue pressures, even internal ones. The tension remains, however. In the context of assisted suicide, how is it possible to reconcile the assertion that paternalistic influences are unacceptable with the concept that in some situations the state (or the medical establishment) may deny assistance in suicide in the name of “what it reasonably judges to be the best interest of the potential suicide”?27 Alexander Capron has argued that decisions on behalf of others should rest on a best interest standard of what the “‘average reasonable person’ would do under the given circumstances.”28 Doesn't this permit the tyranny of the majority over the individual? Doesn't this menace the right, so praised by liberal theorists, to exercise our singularities in a radical way? As Yale Kamisar has asked, “[I]f self-determination and autonomy is the major force driving the right to assisted suicide, why should a competent person's firm conclusion that life has become unendurable for her have to be ‘objectively reasonable’? Why should not a competent person's own evaluation of her situation suffice?”29 To phrase this in terms of the argument I make here, is it ever possible to reconcile medicalizing suicide with autonomy? It could reasonably be argued that guidelines for physician-assisted suicide do not injure the patient's self-determination since the request emanates from a patient who supposedly knows the rules of the game in advance. And, the argument would continue, if one does not wish to submit to those rules, “do it yourself” remains a way out. But this seems to admit that ultimately assisted suicide has to do with something beyond strict self-determination, that autonomy is not the primary moral foundation, or at least that if autonomy is to be exercised it demands constant external oversight. In sum, although advocated in the name of self-sovereignty, physician-assisted suicide ends up reinforcing a power external to the self. It reinforces medical power at the expense of the individual in a very sensitive realm: one's decision to die. There are implications for society in this as well.
13,869
<h4>Comprehensive arg – they medicalize suicide on three registers – the act, the practice, and the social ethos of death – it’s not just a question of doctors</h4><p><strong>Salem 99</strong> Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full</p><p><strong><mark>Medicalizing suicide encompasses three</mark> different</strong> (though interrelated) <strong><mark>facets</strong></mark>: <strong><mark>the medicalization of an act, of a practice, and above all of the social ethos of death</strong></mark> and suicide.</p><p>Medicalizing the act of suicide</p><p>In the typical physician-assisted suicide scenario, the patient is responsible both for requesting aid in dying and for performing the final deed, and she or he construes the act basically as suicide. Yet <strong><mark>as long as the physician is in charge</mark> of assisting the patient</strong>—<strong>either by his or her physical presence or by supplying the medical means to perform the act</strong>—<strong><mark>physician-assisted suicide entails the medicalization of the act of suicide</strong></mark>.</p><p>Ideally, for the physician to assist a patient's suicide the physician must be physically present—as attested in Timothy Quill's regrets for “abandoning” Diane, leaving her to take the prescribed lethal medication alone.15 Thus what is intriguing in physician-assisted suicide is not that ventilators, tubes, CPR, and so on are supplanted by “lethal drugs,” but that even in this context the physician and medicine are overwhelmingly present in the setting of death.</p><p><strong>Even without the doctor's physical presence in the last scene, as long <mark>as physician-assisted suicide presupposes medical assistance it cannot be conceived as immersed in the realm of self-determination</strong></mark>. <strong>Unless doctors are reduced strictly to being instruments to fulfill their patients’ desires, physician-assisted suicide enacts what must be seen as a mutual decision</strong>. But what kind of questions are at stake in this joint decision? Proponents of assisted suicide suggest that patient and physician discuss the patient's medical condition and explore alternatives for alleviating pain and suffering. If it comes to it, the physician should provide a prescription for a lethal drug that leads to a “rapid” and “painless” death.16 That is, the decision to die by suicide is treated precisely as if it were a set of clinical problems to be solved medically—the “private,” “intimate,” “self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event.</p><p>Medicalizing suicide as professional practice</p><p>Medicalizing suicide also points to the fact that <strong>if legalized, physician-assisted suicide as a legitimate practice would become the prerogative of physicians</strong>. Indeed, Jack Kevorkian has seen the exclusive right as the foundation for a new medical subspeciality of “obitiatry.”17</p><p>This <strong>monopoly leads to the more general question of why aid in dying should be provided only by a medical practitioner</strong>. Why, that is, should assistance in suicide be understood as requiring medical authority rather than, for instance, a community of family or friends? <strong>The most obvious answer is that physicians—and only physicians—have the necessary technical skills to ensure a “rapid” and “painless” death</strong>. <strong>But</strong> as some critics have noted, “<strong><mark>Assisted suicide does not even require medical skill…. If freeing up patients truly is the goal, then assisted suicide's advocates disserve patients when they do not advocate ending the physician's exclusive power to prescribe medication</strong></mark>. Ironically, the <strong><mark>advocates of patients’ rights end up empowering doctors more</strong> <strong>than</strong></mark> they do <strong><mark>patients</strong></mark>.”18</p><p>Yet even those who maintain that technical knowledge is imperative do not confine their justification of physician-assisted suicide to this reason. Placing suicide under the stewardship of medicine is further defended as a way of “enhancing public accountability of the practice” and “protecting against abuse.”19 From the patient's perspective, the request for aid in dying may mean a “desire for companionship in pursuing a difficult course of action, a wish for confirmation of a decision about which the patient is unsure or simply a cry for help” (pp. 88–89, note 42). Moreover, since suicide is still stigmatized, “seeking a physician's assistance may be a way of trying to remove that stigma.”20 But inasmuch as cultural preconceptions and loneliness (whatever its source) are far from being exclusively medical issues, we must ask why we expect doctors to respond to them. Two possible answers come to mind: <strong>either medicine is moving beyond its proper role, or the scope of medical competence has already been extended beyond appropriate boundaries</strong>.</p><p>It seems reasonable to conclude that ceding monopoly of assistance in suicide to doctors is anchored in an inflation of the physician's role, as well as in the extreme idealization of physicians’ character and the relationships they establish with patients. The bond physicians establish with patients is supposedly effective, collaborative, and committed.21 Both this <strong><mark>idealization and the willingness to delegate to physicians the exclusive right to assist suicide bespeaks the social and symbolic power already conferred on medicine and medical professionals in our societies</strong>.</mark> In other words, <strong>it is not</strong> (or not only) <strong>the need for technical expertise that impels us to physician-assisted suicide</strong>. <strong>Rather</strong>, <strong>our culture</strong>, so impregnated by medicalization, <strong>takes for granted that assisted suicide should fall under the control and supervision of medicine</strong>.</p><p>Medicalizing the morality of suicide</p><p>As a legitimate domain of professional practice, then, <strong>physician-assisted suicide necessarily involves medicalizing the moral questions surrounding suicide</strong>. Physician-assisted suicide presupposes, and ultimately is, a medical judgment about death or suicide; <strong>it is a medical evaluation of the fairness and legitimacy of a person's </strong>(not simply a patient's) <strong>desire or choice to end his or her life</strong>.</p><p>With some few exceptions, <strong><mark>even the most radical advocates of physician-assisted suicide recognize the need to establish protocols and guidelines to prevent abuses</strong></mark>, <strong>protect the vulnerable</strong>, guarantee public accountability, and even to assure the autonomous character of the patient's choice. Surely these aims are respectable and the setting up of criteria just and reasonable. Yet <strong>establishing medical guidelines also introduces tensions into the value of autonomy in several ways</strong>.</p><p>The <strong>requisites for physician-assisted suicide</strong> (must the patient be terminally ill? which medical specialists are best qualified as consultants?) <strong>are still being debated</strong>. <strong>There is, however, agreement about the moral attributes that the patien</strong>t and his or her request <strong>must evince</strong>: <strong>the decision</strong> to die <strong>must be “informed,” “rational</strong>,” “stable,” and “fully free” or “<strong>voluntary</strong>.”22 And there is broad agreement that to ensure that these conditions are fulfilled the patient must submit to screening by a team of doctors (the treating physician, a consulting physician, and a psychiatrist) who would evaluate the request for aid in dying.</p><p>Th<strong>is requirement assumes that </strong>besides undue external influences, some impulses or <strong>dispositions emanating from the patient herself or himself</strong>—such as depression or guilt—<strong>may threaten “pure choice</strong>.” “Voluntariness” in this sense must be safeguarded from undue influence stemming not only from outside, but also from within. Ultimately, this is to assume that the inner world may be obscure to the individual, that she or he may be half blind to her or his own choice, desire, or personal truth.</p><p>The presumption that the inner world is or may be opaque to the individual suggests a second underlying presupposition: someone other than the person requesting aid in dying has greater expertise in judging the appropriateness of that request. <strong><mark>Medical authority, that is, is assumed to have the proper ability to unveil the “real truth” behind the request to die</strong></mark>. The patient's treating physician, along with psychiatric and/or palliative care consultants, is charged to distinguish authentic from distorted choices; that is, to discern whether the request is pertinent or pathological (and if so, whether it is “curable” by medical means).</p><p>Both these premises obviously collide with the principles of autonomy and self-determination. Both displace the final decision concerning suicide from the patient to the physician's judgment that the request is appropriate and free from “undue influence.”</p><p><strong><mark>The insult to autonomy is not exerted through repression</mark>, as was the criminalization of suicide</strong>. Rather, <strong><mark>it is exercised through</strong></mark> what Foucault would call the “<strong><mark>normalization” of suicide, the subordination to medical scrutiny of this event and the person making the request</strong></mark>.23 <strong>The “patient” is subjected to observation, examination, and inquiry to confirm the “rationality” and “voluntariness” of his or her request. Thus <mark>medicalizing</strong> <strong>(assisted) suicide jeopardizes autonomy not only when the patient's request is denied</strong></mark> for one reason or another. <strong>Requiring that the patient submit to medical surveillance is, in itself, an outrage to autonomy</strong> as this value is classically defined.24</p><p>To illustrate how complex is the apparatus through which suicide is normalized, consider guidelines suggested by Frank Miller, Howard Brody, and Timothy Quill, for example. To ensure public accountability for physician-assisted suicide, to guarantee that the procedure is used only as a “last resort,” and to assure that the patient's decision is genuinely voluntary, the authors suggest palliative care consultants and regional palliative care committees as the core of a whole supervising system.25 Thus the primary physician would be prohibited from providing lethal drugs without prior consultation with a palliative care expert who, based on “examination of medical records and interviews with the treating physician, the patient and the interested members of the patient's family” (p. 121), would assess the authenticity of the request to die. Patients and their physicians would have the right to appeal the consultant's denial of requests for assisted suicide to regional palliative care committees. The bureaucratization of suicide built into such proposals entails serious constraints on patients’ self-determination.</p><p>Subjecting individuals who request aid in dying to this kind of scrutiny further affronts their dignity in putting all such requests under suspicion. In the name of protecting individuals from irreversible self-harm all are in principle treated as moral patients rather than moral agents and are presumed to be mentally incompetent. The capacity to make autonomous decisions, which is presumed in all other cases unless demonstrated otherwise, is stood on its head in physician-assisted suicide. Patients must prove their decisionmaking capacity from the outset.</p><p>One of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dying.</p><p>Subjecting the individual to medical norms in this way also introduces a tension for one of the central questions of liberal philosophers. If, as the liberal argument claims, the morality or immorality of decisions at the end of life rests on the competent patient's wishes rather than on a distinction between killing and allowing to die,26 protocols that may ultimately deny a patient's request for assistance in dying assert, in effect, that moral authority resides outside the patient's choice. And if medicine may, morally, reject patients’ autonomous requests for aid, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the value of patient autonomy becomes more rhetorical than real.</p><p>Admittedly, even liberal theorists emphasize that there are limits to autonomy, and that like other important rights, the right to physician-assisted suicide is not absolute and can properly be restricted under certain circumstances. Indeed, Ronald Dworkin and others argue precisely that because autonomy must be protected and preserved physician-assisted suicide must be regulated. Under certain conditions the state has the power to override individual rights to protect patients from undue pressures, even internal ones.</p><p>The tension remains, however. In the context of assisted suicide, how is it possible to reconcile the assertion that paternalistic influences are unacceptable with the concept that in some situations the state (or the medical establishment) may deny assistance in suicide in the name of “what it reasonably judges to be the best interest of the potential suicide”?27 Alexander Capron has argued that decisions on behalf of others should rest on a best interest standard of what the “‘average reasonable person’ would do under the given circumstances.”28 Doesn't this permit the tyranny of the majority over the individual? Doesn't this menace the right, so praised by liberal theorists, to exercise our singularities in a radical way? As Yale Kamisar has asked, “[I]f self-determination and autonomy is the major force driving the right to assisted suicide, why should a competent person's firm conclusion that life has become unendurable for her have to be ‘objectively reasonable’? Why should not a competent person's own evaluation of her situation suffice?”29 To phrase this in terms of the argument I make here, is it ever possible to reconcile medicalizing suicide with autonomy?</p><p><strong>It could reasonably be argued that guidelines for physician-assisted suicide do not injure the patient's self-determination since the request emanates from a patient who supposedly knows the rules of the game in advance</strong>. And, <strong>the argument would continue, <mark>if one does not wish to submit to those rules, “do it yourself” remains a way out</mark>. But <mark>this seems to admit that ultimately assisted suicide has to do with something beyond strict self-determination</strong></mark>, that autonomy is not the primary moral foundation, or at least that if autonomy is to be exercised it demands constant external oversight.</p><p>In sum, although advocated in the name of self-sovereignty, <strong><mark>physician-assisted suicide ends up reinforcing a power external to the self. It reinforces medical power at the expense of the individual in a very sensitive realm: one's decision to die</strong></mark>.</p><p>There are implications for society in this as well.</p>
null
null
2NC Link Debate
429,689
14
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,349
Banks do illegal stuff all the time – if regulations are really gonna make Goldman go under, they’ll just ignore those regulations
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Banks do illegal stuff all the time – if regulations are really gonna make Goldman go under, they’ll just ignore those regulations</h4>
WTO
Banks
AT: Inevitable
430,661
1
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,350
Won’t pass and even if it does- conditions and controversy sink TPP
WSJ 3/30
WSJ 3/30/2015 (http://www.wsj.com/articles/divisions-in-congress-hamper-pacific-trade-deal-1427739980)
Wavering support in Congress has emerged as the biggest obstacle holding up a Pacific trade pact The Obama administration’s push to win fast-track has stalled amid disagreements among lawmakers over how much leverage they should have over the pact’s final form. uncertainty is stirring fear among the 11 countries negotiating most lawmakers in Obama’s own party look set to oppose it out of concern that American workers will have to compete with low-wage counterparts Hearing about the political debate in Congress makes people worried
Wavering support in Congress has emerged as the biggest obstacle holding up a Pacific trade pact The Obama administration’s push has stalled amid disagreements among lawmakers over how much leverage they should have over the pact’s final form uncertainty is stirring fear amon the 11 countries negotiating most lawmakers in Obama’s own party look set to oppose it out of concern that American workers will have to compete with low-wage counterparts Hearing about the political debate in Congress makes people worried
Wavering support in Congress has emerged as the biggest obstacle holding up completion of a 12-nation Pacific trade pact under negotiation for nearly a decade. The Obama administration’s push to win fast-track powers from Congress to expedite the deal’s passage has stalled amid disagreements among lawmakers over how much leverage they should have over the pact’s final form. That uncertainty is stirring fear among many of the 11 countries negotiating the Trans-Pacific Partnership with the U.S., who say they need proof Congress is on board before agreeing to final conditions in the deal. Passing the legislation, also known as trade promotion authority, would let negotiators finalize outstanding issues such as auto-industry tariffs, dairy-market access and sensitive rules on intellectual property, areas where negotiators need to get a final signoff from top political leaders. “We can get this deal done, but we’re not going to get there without the U.S. Congress declaring its formal support through an appropriately drafted TPA,” New Zealand Trade Minister Tim Groser said in a recent interview. Australia’s trade minister, Andrew Robb, said the Pacific pact could be wrapped up in a month if there is sufficient political will. But “unless the TPA is completed in the U.S., there won’t be the political will,” he told reporters last week. The TPP pact would lower tariffs and other barriers at the border and set commercial rules of the road for everything from the drug patents to the arbitration of disputes with governments. Countries negotiating the deal include Japan, Australia and New Zealand, as well as less developed economies such as Vietnam and Malaysia. The agreement is the economic centerpiece of President Barack Obama’s efforts to rebalance foreign policy toward fast-growing Asia, and Mr. Obama is selling the deal as a way to ensure that Washington writes the trade rules of the region rather than China. While Republicans in Congress largely back the deal, most lawmakers in Mr. Obama’s own party look set to oppose it out of concern that American workers will have to compete with low-wage counterparts in countries with lower standards. Mr. Obama says the deal will level the playing field with workers in these countries. A similar tension exists in Japan, where farmers in the party of Prime Minister Shinzo Abe oppose the deal out of concern they will have to compete with more efficient American agriculture. Previously, U.S. officials complained about a lack of Japanese political support to strike a deal, but now all eyes are on Washington. The U.S. has been working out final provisions with Japan on automobile tariffs, regulatory trade barriers for cars and access to Japan’s agricultural markets. The U.S. has agreed to lower its tariff on Japanese imports over time, but Tokyo also wants Washington lower its duties on car parts. In exchange, the U.S. is seeking easier access to the Japanese market for Detroit auto makers and a substantial lifting of Japanese barriers to pork and other agricultural goods. American and Japanese official would like to get a two-way deal covering cars, agriculture and other market issues in the TPP by the time Mr. Abe visits Washington at the end of April, but officials say the divisions in Congress are weighing on the bilateral talks. “Hearing about the political debate in Congress makes people worried,” said Takeo Mori, the Japanese official handling the auto negotiations, in Washington Friday.
3,484
<h4>Won’t pass and even if it does- conditions and controversy sink TPP</h4><p><strong>WSJ 3/30</strong>/2015 (http://www.wsj.com/articles/divisions-in-congress-hamper-pacific-trade-deal-1427739980)</p><p><u><mark>Wavering support in Congress has emerged as the biggest obstacle holding up</u></mark> completion of <u><mark>a</u></mark> 12-nation <u><mark>Pacific trade pact</u></mark> under negotiation for nearly a decade. <u><mark>The Obama administration’s push</mark> to win fast-track</u> powers from Congress to expedite the deal’s passage <u><strong><mark>has stalled</u></strong> <u>amid disagreements among lawmakers over how much leverage they should have over the pact’s final form</mark>. </u>That <u><mark>uncertainty</u></mark> <u><mark>is stirring fear amon</mark>g</u> many of <u><mark>the 11 countries negotiating</u></mark> the Trans-Pacific Partnership with the U.S., who say they need proof Congress is on board before agreeing to final conditions in the deal. Passing the legislation, also known as trade promotion authority, would let negotiators finalize outstanding issues such as auto-industry tariffs, dairy-market access and sensitive rules on intellectual property, areas where negotiators need to get a final signoff from top political leaders. “We can get this deal done, but we’re not going to get there without the U.S. Congress declaring its formal support through an appropriately drafted TPA,” New Zealand Trade Minister Tim Groser said in a recent interview. Australia’s trade minister, Andrew Robb, said the Pacific pact could be wrapped up in a month if there is sufficient political will. But “unless the TPA is completed in the U.S., there won’t be the political will,” he told reporters last week. The TPP pact would lower tariffs and other barriers at the border and set commercial rules of the road for everything from the drug patents to the arbitration of disputes with governments. Countries negotiating the deal include Japan, Australia and New Zealand, as well as less developed economies such as Vietnam and Malaysia. The agreement is the economic centerpiece of President Barack Obama’s efforts to rebalance foreign policy toward fast-growing Asia, and Mr. Obama is selling the deal as a way to ensure that Washington writes the trade rules of the region rather than China. While Republicans in Congress largely back the deal, <u><mark>most lawmakers in</u></mark> Mr. <u><mark>Obama’s own party look set to oppose it out of concern that American workers will have to compete with low-wage counterparts</mark> </u>in countries with lower standards. Mr. Obama says the deal will level the playing field with workers in these countries. A similar tension exists in Japan, where farmers in the party of Prime Minister Shinzo Abe oppose the deal out of concern they will have to compete with more efficient American agriculture. Previously, U.S. officials complained about a lack of Japanese political support to strike a deal, but now all eyes are on Washington. The U.S. has been working out final provisions with Japan on automobile tariffs, regulatory trade barriers for cars and access to Japan’s agricultural markets. The U.S. has agreed to lower its tariff on Japanese imports over time, but Tokyo also wants Washington lower its duties on car parts. In exchange, the U.S. is seeking easier access to the Japanese market for Detroit auto makers and a substantial lifting of Japanese barriers to pork and other agricultural goods. American and Japanese official would like to get a two-way deal covering cars, agriculture and other market issues in the TPP by the time Mr. Abe visits Washington at the end of April, but officials say the divisions in Congress are weighing on the bilateral talks. “<u><mark>Hearing about the political debate in Congress makes people worried</u></mark>,” said Takeo Mori, the Japanese official handling the auto negotiations, in Washington Friday.</p>
2AC
Politics DA
TPA – 2AC – NDT
430,662
2
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,351
No China war - they'll be restrained
Stutter 3/19/14
Stutter 3/19/14
Robert Sutter is Professor of Practice of International Affairs at George Washington University, China-US Focus, March 19, 2014, "Why China Avoids Confronting the U.S. in Asia", http://www.chinausfocus.com/foreign-policy/why-china-avoids-confronting-the-u-s-in-asia-2/ Forecasts talk of an inevitable U.S.-China conflict However, enduring circumstances hold back Chinese leaders from confronting America Chinese economic growth and one-party rule require stability protecting Chinese security and sovereignty remains a top concern Though China has regional ambitions domestic concerns get overall priority. Xi is preoccupied with uncertain leadership legitimacy pervasive corruption, widespread mass protests, and unsustainable economic practices. Beijing’s reform agenda requires strong leadership for many years Under these circumstances, Xi was unusually accommodating in meeting Obama Xi also presides over China’s greater assertiveness on territorial issues but Chinese probes avoid direct confrontation with the superpower. Growing economic and other U.S.-China interdependence reinforces constructive relations “Gulliver strategies” tie down aggressive, assertive policy tendencies through interdependence in bilateral relationships Asian stability is essential for China’s economic growth—the lynch pin of Communist rule. Facing formidable American presence and influence and lacking a secure periphery China almost certainly calculates that seriously confronting the U S poses grave dangers.
enduring circumstances hold Chinese leaders from confronting America Chinese growth and party rule require stability Though China has regional ambitions, domestic concerns get priority Xi is preoccupied with leadership legitimacy Beijing’s reform agenda requires strong leadership Under these circumstances, Xi was unusually accommodating in meeting Obama Growing economic interdependence reinforces constructive relations. Gulliver strategies” tie down aggressive tendencies through bilateral relationships Asian stability is essential for China’s growth—the lynch pin of Communist rule China certainly calculates confronting the U S poses grave dangers.
Robert Sutter is Professor of Practice of International Affairs at George Washington University, China-US Focus, March 19, 2014, "Why China Avoids Confronting the U.S. in Asia", http://www.chinausfocus.com/foreign-policy/why-china-avoids-confronting-the-u-s-in-asia-2/ Forecasts talk of U.S. retreat from domineering China or an inevitable U.S.-China conflict. However, enduring circumstances hold back Chinese leaders from confronting America, the regional leader. Domestic preoccupations Chinese economic growth and one-party rule require stability. And protecting Chinese security and sovereignty remains a top concern. Though China also has regional and global ambitions, domestic concerns get overall priority. President Xi Jinping is preoccupied with uncertain leadership legitimacy, pervasive corruption, widespread mass protests, and unsustainable economic practices. Beijing’s reform agenda requires strong leadership for many years. Under these circumstances, Xi was unusually accommodating in meeting President Obama in California in 2013; he seeks a new kind of major power relationship. Xi also presides over China’s greater assertiveness on territorial issues that involve the United States, but thus far Chinese probes avoid direct confrontation with the superpower. Mutual interdependence Growing economic and other U.S.-China interdependence reinforces constructive relations. Respective “Gulliver strategies” tie down aggressive, assertive, or other negative policy tendencies through webs of interdependence in bilateral and multilateral relationships. China’s insecurity in Asia Nearby Asia is China’s top foreign priority. It contains security and sovereignty issues (e.g. Taiwan) of highest importance. It is the main arena of interaction with the United States. Its economic importance far surpasses the rest of world (China is Africa’s biggest trader but it does more trade with South Korea). Asian stability is essential for China’s economic growth—the lynch pin of Communist rule. Facing formidable American presence and influence and lacking a secure periphery, China almost certainly calculates that seriously confronting the United States poses grave dangers.
2,188
<h4><strong>No China war - they'll be restrained</h4><p>Stutter 3/19/14</p><p><u>Robert Sutter is Professor of Practice of International Affairs at George Washington University, China-US Focus, March 19, 2014, "Why China Avoids Confronting the U.S. in Asia", http://www.chinausfocus.com/foreign-policy/why-china-avoids-confronting-the-u-s-in-asia-2/</p><p></strong>Forecasts talk of</u> U.S. retreat from domineering China or <u>an inevitable U.S.-China conflict</u>. <u><strong>However, <mark>enduring circumstances hold</mark> back <mark>Chinese leaders from confronting America</u></strong></mark>, the regional leader. Domestic preoccupations <u><mark>Chinese</mark> economic <mark>growth and</mark> one-<mark>party rule require stability</u></mark>. And <u><strong>protecting Chinese security and sovereignty remains a top concern</u></strong>. <u><mark>Though China</u></mark> also <u><mark>has regional</u></mark> and global <u><mark>ambitions</u>, <u><strong>domestic concerns get</mark> overall <mark>priority</mark>. </u></strong>President <u><mark>Xi</u></mark> Jinping <u><mark>is</u> <u><strong>preoccupied with</mark> uncertain <mark>leadership legitimacy</u></strong></mark>, <u>pervasive corruption, widespread mass protests, and unsustainable economic practices. <mark>Beijing’s reform agenda requires strong leadership</mark> for many years</u>. <u><strong><mark>Under these circumstances, Xi was unusually accommodating in meeting</u></strong></mark> President <u><strong><mark>Obama</u></strong></mark> in California in 2013; he seeks a new kind of major power relationship. <u>Xi also presides over China’s greater assertiveness on territorial issues</u> that involve the United States, <u><strong>but</u></strong> thus far <u><strong>Chinese probes avoid direct confrontation with the superpower. </u></strong>Mutual interdependence <u><strong><mark>Growing economic</mark> and other U.S.-China <mark>interdependence reinforces constructive relations</u></strong>.</mark> Respective <u><strong>“<mark>Gulliver strategies” tie down aggressive</mark>, assertive</u></strong>, or other negative <u><strong>policy <mark>tendencies through</u></strong></mark> webs of <u><strong>interdependence in <mark>bilateral</u></strong></mark> and multilateral <u><strong><mark>relationships</u></strong></mark>. China’s insecurity in Asia Nearby Asia is China’s top foreign priority. It contains security and sovereignty issues (e.g. Taiwan) of highest importance. It is the main arena of interaction with the United States. Its economic importance far surpasses the rest of world (China is Africa’s biggest trader but it does more trade with South Korea). <u><strong><mark>Asian stability is essential for China’s</mark> economic <mark>growth—the lynch pin of Communist rule</mark>.</u></strong> <u>Facing formidable American presence and influence and lacking a secure periphery</u>, <u><strong><mark>China</mark> almost <mark>certainly calculates</mark> that seriously <mark>confronting the U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><strong><mark>poses grave dangers.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
AT: China Real War
95,968
92
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,352
The United States Federal Government should amend the National Organ Transplant Act to permit regulated sale of human organs. A government agency should be established to purchase organs, paying cash or vouchers at an adjusted market-clearing price. Organs should be placed in the Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The United States Federal Government should amend the National Organ Transplant Act to permit regulated sale of human organs. A government agency should be established to purchase organs, paying cash or vouchers at an adjusted market-clearing price. Organs should be placed in the Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network</h4>
null
null
Plan
430,663
1
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,353
Eugenics opens the door to genocide and totalitarianism. Shmuel Vaknin 6, Ph.D. in the Philosophy of Physics, “Racing Down: Eugenics and the Future of the Human Species,” Last Mod 11-16-2006, samvak.tripod.com/eugenics.html
Vaknin 6, Ph.D. in the Philosophy of Physics, “Racing Down: Eugenics and the Future of the Human Species,” Last Mod 11-16-2006, samvak.tripod.com/eugenics.html
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Eugenics opens the door to genocide and totalitarianism.</h4><p>Shmuel <strong>Vaknin 6, Ph.D. in the Philosophy of Physics, “Racing Down: Eugenics and the Future of the Human Species,” Last Mod 11-16-2006, samvak.tripod.com/eugenics.html</p></strong>
Ableism
Impact
2NC K
430,664
1
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,354
International treaty system solves great power war
Muller 2000
Muller 2000 (Dr. Harold Muller is the Director of the Peace Research Institute-Frankfurt and Professor of International Relations at Goethe University Compliance Politics: A Critical Analysis of Multilateral Arms Control Treaty Enforcement http://cns.miis.edu/npr/pdfs/72muell.pdf)
As long as the risk of great power rivalry and competition exists constructing barriers against a degeneration of this competition into major violence remains a pivotal task Things may be more complicated than during the bipolar age arms races are likely stabilization remains a key a web of interlocking agreements may even create enough of a sense of security and confidence to overcome past confrontations and enable transitions towards more cooperative relationships. arms limitation agreement are needed to ban existential dangers for global stability, ecological safety, and maybe the very survival of human life on earth Global agreements also reduce the chances that regional conflicts will escalate the normative frameworks that they enshrine may engender a feeling of community and shared security interests that help reduce the general level of conflict and assist in ushering in new relations of global cooperation it will serve these worthwhile purposes only if means are available to ensure compliance
as the risk of great power rivalry and competition exists constructing barriers against major violence remains a pivotal task arms races are likely interlocking agreements create enough of a sense of security and confidence to overcome confrontations and enable transitions towards cooperative relationships arms limitation agreements are needed to ban existential dangers ecological safety, and the survival of human life Global agreements reduce the chances that conflicts will escalate. , it will serve these worthwhile purposes only if means are available to ensure compliance
In this author's view,3 at least four distinct missions continue to make arms control, disarmament, and non-proliferation agreements useful, even indispensable parts of a stable and reliable world security structure: • As long as the risk of great power rivalry and competition exists—and it exists today—constructing barriers against a degeneration of this competition into major violence remains a pivotal task of global security policy. Things may be more complicated than during the bipolar age since asymmetries loom larger and more than one pair of competing major powers may exist. With overlapping rivalries among these powers, arms races are likely to be interconnected, and the stability of any one pair of rivals might be affected negatively by developments in other dyads. Because of this greater risk of instability, the increased political complexity of the post-bipolar world calls for more rather than less arms control. For these competitive relationships, stability or stabilization remains a key goal, and effectively verified agreements can contribute much to establish such stability. • Arms control also has a role to play in securing regional stability. At the regional level, arms control agreements can create balances of forces that reassure regional powers that their basic security is certain, and help build confidence in the basically non-aggressive policies of neighbors. Over time, a web of interlocking agreements may even create enough of a sense of security and confidence to overcome past confrontations and enable transitions towards more cooperative relationships. At the global level, arms limitation or prohibition agreements, notably in the field of weapons of mass destruction, are needed to ban existential dangers for global stability, ecological safety, and maybe the very survival of human life on earth. In an age of increasing interdependence and ensuing complex networks that support the satisfaction of basic needs, international cooperation is needed to secure the smooth working of these networks. Arms control can create underlying conditions of security and stability that reduce distrust and enable countries to commit them-selves to far-reaching cooperation in other sectors without perceiving undesirable risks to their national security. Global agreements also affect regional balances and help, if successful, to reduce the chances that regional conflicts will escalate. Under opportune circumstances, the normative frameworks that they enshrine may engender a feeling of community and shared security interests that help reduce the general level of conflict and assist in ushering in new relations of global cooperation. • Finally, one aspect that is rarely discussed in the arms control context is arms control among friends and partners. It takes the innocent form of military cooperation; joint staffs, commands, and units; common procurement planning; and broad and far-reaching transparency. While these relations serve at the surface to enhance a country's military capability by linking it with others, they are conducive as well to creating a sense of irreversibility in current friendly relations, by making unthinkable a return to previous, possibly more conflictual times. European defense cooperation is a case in point.1 Whatever the particular mission of a specific agreement, it will serve these worthwhile purposes only if it is implemented appropriately and, if not, means are available to ensure compliance. In other words, the enduring value of arms control rests very much on the ability to assure compliance.5 Despite the reasons given above for the continuing utility of arms control, the skeptics may still have the last word if agreements are made empty shells by repeated breaches and a lack of effective enforcement.
3,802
<h4>International treaty system solves great power war</h4><p><strong>Muller 2000 </strong>(Dr. Harold Muller is the Director of the Peace Research Institute-Frankfurt and Professor of International Relations at Goethe University Compliance Politics: A Critical Analysis of Multilateral Arms Control Treaty Enforcement http://cns.miis.edu/npr/pdfs/72muell.pdf)</p><p>In this author's view,3 at least four distinct missions continue to make arms control, disarmament, and non-proliferation agreements useful, even indispensable parts of a stable and reliable world security structure: • <u>As long <mark>as the risk of <strong>great power rivalry</strong> and <strong>competition</strong> exists</u></mark>—and it exists today—<u><mark>constructing barriers</mark> <mark>against</mark> a degeneration of this competition into <strong><mark>major violence</strong> remains a pivotal task</u></mark> of global security policy. <u>Things may be more complicated than during the bipolar age</u> since asymmetries loom larger and more than one pair of competing major powers may exist. With overlapping rivalries among these powers, <u><mark>arms races are <strong>likely</u></strong></mark> to be interconnected, and the stability of any one pair of rivals might be affected negatively by developments in other dyads. Because of this greater risk of instability, the increased political complexity of the post-bipolar world calls for more rather than less arms control. For these competitive relationships, stability or <u>stabilization remains a key</u> goal, and effectively verified agreements can contribute much to establish such stability. • Arms control also has a role to play in securing regional stability. At the regional level, arms control agreements can create balances of forces that reassure regional powers that their basic security is certain, and help build confidence in the basically non-aggressive policies of neighbors. Over time, <u>a web of <strong><mark>interlocking agreements</strong></mark> may even <mark>create enough of a sense of <strong>security</strong> and <strong>confidence</strong> to overcome</mark> past <mark>confrontations and enable transitions towards</mark> more <mark>cooperative relationships</mark>.</u> At the global level, <u><mark>arms limitation</u></mark> or prohibition <u><mark>agreement</u>s</mark>, notably in the field of weapons of mass destruction, <u><mark>are needed to ban <strong>existential dangers</strong></mark> for global stability, <strong><mark>ecological</strong> safety, and</mark> maybe <strong><mark>the</mark> very <mark>survival of human life</mark> on earth</u></strong>. In an age of increasing interdependence and ensuing complex networks that support the satisfaction of basic needs, international cooperation is needed to secure the smooth working of these networks. Arms control can create underlying conditions of security and stability that reduce distrust and enable countries to commit them-selves to far-reaching cooperation in other sectors without perceiving undesirable risks to their national security. <u><mark>Global agreements</mark> also</u> affect regional balances and help, if successful, to <u><strong><mark>reduce the chances</strong> that</mark> regional <mark>conflicts will escalate</u>.</mark> Under opportune circumstances, <u>the normative frameworks that they enshrine may engender a feeling of community and shared security interests that help reduce the general level of conflict and assist in ushering in new relations of global cooperation</u>. • Finally, one aspect that is rarely discussed in the arms control context is arms control among friends and partners. It takes the innocent form of military cooperation; joint staffs, commands, and units; common procurement planning; and broad and far-reaching transparency. While these relations serve at the surface to enhance a country's military capability by linking it with others, they are conducive as well to creating a sense of irreversibility in current friendly relations, by making unthinkable a return to previous, possibly more conflictual times. European defense cooperation is a case in point.1 Whatever the particular mission of a specific agreement<mark>, <u>it will serve these worthwhile purposes <strong>only if</u></strong></mark> it is implemented appropriately and, if not, <u><mark>means are available to ensure <strong>compliance</u></strong></mark>. In other words, the enduring value of arms control rests very much on the ability to assure compliance.5 Despite the reasons given above for the continuing utility of arms control, the skeptics may still have the last word if agreements are made empty shells by repeated breaches and a lack of effective enforcement.</p><p> </p><p><u><strong> </p></u></strong>
null
null
Off
65,123
59
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,355
Both the AMA and the American Society of Transplant Surgeons support sales—link doesn’t turn case
Cline no date
Austin Cline no date, Is it ethical to let organs be sold on the open market?, http://atheism.about.com/library/FAQs/phil/blphil_ethbio_organsale.htm
Should people be allowed to sell their organs? Currently, exchanging organs for money is illegal, but some members of the medical and business communities would like to change that. One of those is the A M A they would like the laws to change, The American Society of Transplant Surgeons has already endorsed giving money for organs to the families of the deceased
Currently, exchanging organs for money is illegal, but the medical and business communities would like to change that the A M A would like the laws to change The American Society of Transplant Surgeons has already endorsed giving money for organs
Should people be allowed to sell their organs? Currently, exchanging organs for money or other "valuable considerations" is illegal, but some members of the medical and business communities would like to change that. One of those is the American Medical Association's influential Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs. Convinced that the balance of moral and ethical concerns favors the ability to sell organs, they would like the laws to change, and the AMA's governing house of delegates is scheduled to vote in June on whether to support a pilot program. The American Society of Transplant Surgeons has already endorsed giving money for cadaveric organs to the families of the deceased.
691
<h4>Both the AMA and the American Society of Transplant Surgeons support sales—link doesn’t turn case</h4><p>Austin <strong>Cline no date</strong>, Is it ethical to let organs be sold on the open market?, http://atheism.about.com/library/FAQs/phil/blphil_ethbio_organsale.htm </p><p><u>Should people be allowed to sell their organs?</u> <u><mark>Currently, exchanging organs for money</u></mark> or other "valuable considerations" <u><mark>is illegal, but</mark> some members of <mark>the medical and business communities would like to change that</mark>. One of those is <mark>the</u> <u><strong>A</u></strong></mark>merican <u><strong><mark>M</u></strong></mark>edical <u><strong><mark>A</u></strong></mark>ssociation's influential Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs. Convinced that the balance of moral and ethical concerns favors the ability to sell organs, <u>they <mark>would like the laws to change</mark>,</u> and the AMA's governing house of delegates is scheduled to vote in June on whether to support a pilot program. <u><mark>The American Society of Transplant Surgeons has already endorsed giving money for</mark> </u>cadaveric<u> <mark>organs</mark> to the families of the deceased</u>.</p>
2AC
Politics DA
TPA – 2AC – NDT
430,665
3
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,356
And it returns power to the doctor
Salem 99
Salem 99 Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full
null
null
Let us assume that from the point of view of particular patients who will eventually undergo assisted suicide the practice does demedicalize their dying: as long as it hastens death, it liberates them not only from pain and suffering but from the hands of medicine and its paraphernalia as well. This liberation is achieved through torturous ways, however: first, it is precisely physicians who are in charge of freeing patients from medicine. Second, this emancipation presupposes and is achieved at the cost of the individual's submission to medical norms and scrutiny. What the patients’ rights movement still struggles to recapture from medicine—control over the decision to die—is being returned to medicine through physician-assisted suicide. Eventually, people will have physician-assisted suicide not only because they want it, but because physicians agree they can have it. At the societal level too physician-assisted suicide in fact extends the medicalization of death. First, physician-assisted suicide radicalizes the right of the medical profession to make life and death decisions, for now even (assisted) suicide must surrender to its hands. Second, physician-assisted suicide translates one more sphere of personal and intimate meaning into a medical event. Moreover, placing assisted suicide under physicians’ control and supervision ends up transforming moral categories (such as “rationality” and “voluntariness”) into medical ones. Perhaps submitting to medical scrutiny individually and to the increasing medicalization of death and dying societally are lesser evils than the agony some people endure at the end of life. Nevertheless, this trade-off should not obscure the price being paid. It urges us, further, to re-examine the claims of honoring personal autonomy and demedicalizing death and dying as the argumentative basis on which physician-assisted suicide rests.
1,894
<h4>And it returns power to the doctor</h4><p><strong>Salem 99</strong> Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full</p><p><strong>Let us assume that from the point of view of </strong>particular <strong>patients</strong> who will eventually undergo <strong>assisted suicide</strong> the practice <strong>does demedicalize their dying</strong>: as long as it hastens death, <strong>it liberates them </strong>not only <strong>from pain</strong> <strong>and</strong> suffering but from <strong>the hands of medicine and its paraphernalia</strong> as well. <strong>This liberation is achieved through torturous ways, however</strong>: first, <strong>it is precisely physicians who are in charge of freeing patients from medicine</strong>. <strong>Second, this emancipation presupposes and is achieved at the cost of the individual's submission to medical norms and scrutiny</strong>. What the patients’ rights movement still struggles to recapture from medicine—control over the decision to die—is being returned to medicine through physician-assisted suicide. Eventually, <strong>people will have physician-assisted suicide not only because they want it, but because physicians agree they can have it</strong>.</p><p>At the societal level too physician-assisted suicide in fact extends the medicalization of death. First, <strong>physician-assisted suicide radicalizes the right of the medical profession to make life and death decisions</strong>, <strong>for now even (assisted) suicide must surrender to its hands</strong>. <strong>Second, physician-assisted suicide translates one more sphere of personal and intimate meaning into a medical event</strong>. Moreover, placing assisted suicide under physicians’ control and supervision ends up transforming moral categories (such as “rationality” and “voluntariness”) into medical ones.</p><p>Perhaps submitting to medical scrutiny individually and to the increasing medicalization of death and dying societally are lesser evils than the agony some people endure at the end of life. Nevertheless, <strong>this trade-off should not obscure the price being paid. It urges us, further, to re-examine the claims of honoring personal autonomy and demedicalizing death and dying as the argumentative basis on which physician-assisted suicide rests</strong>.</p>
null
null
2NC Link Debate
430,635
4
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,357
A lot of alt causes to know-your-customer regulations, banks ignore the law a lot, and there’s no impact
Evans-Pritchard 14
Evans-Pritchard 14 Blake Evans Pritchard, Staff at Insurance Risk, 6/17/14, “Banks struggle to meet know-your-customer requirements,” https://www.risk.net/asia-risk/feature/2350277/banks-struggle-to-meet-know-your-customer-requirements
BNP Paribas is the latest in a long list of institutions to have fallen foul of US sanctions rules It's a question of who they are going to come after next, In the UK, penalties are being imposed on banks that fail to properly safeguard against criminal activity the F C A fined Standard Bank £7.6 million for "serious weaknesses" in its AML policy Financial institutions in Asia look at the fines being imposed in Europe and the US with a certain amount of trepidation, wondering what this might mean for them With potential multibillion dollar fines on the table for dealing with the wrong firms, it's simply much easier not to do the business It isn't only Asian corporates with uncertain provenance that are feeling the impact of the emphasis on KYC The US, and to a lesser extent the UK, are not the only jurisdictions taking a hard look at KYC In 2013 the RBI fined three regional banks for KYC lapses the RBI fined a further 22 banks for a slew of regulatory failings, including the violation of KYC rules It is not only the possibility of being fined that worries banks. There is also a great deal of concern about increased regulatory scrutiny which is likely to follow any KYC failings Banks are keen to demonstrate good and robust adherence to AML procedures for fear of attracting greater scrutiny the data needed for efficient compliance is not always easy to dig up While KYC legislation has become a particularly hot topic over the past couple of years it has been around for a lot longer Several years ago, many financial institutions saw an efficient KYC process as a way of gaining a competitive edge, in terms of faster onboarding of clients and getting business first now KYC compliance has become so labour-intensive and most financial institutions now view it as something that just has to be done successful companies in this area will be those that not only manage to meet all the new requirements from regulators, but do so in such a way that adds value to their business the bank that can crack this will have an advantage when we come out of this [regulatory] cycle in a few years' time
BNP Paribas is the latest in a long list of institutions to have fallen foul of US sanctions rules Financial institutions in Asia look at the fines being imposed in Europe and the US with a certain amount of trepidation, wondering what this might mean for them With potential multibillion dollar fines on the table for dealing with the wrong firms, it's simply much easier not to do the business the RBI fined a further 22 banks for a slew of regulatory failings, including the violation of KYC rules. It is not only the possibility of being fined that worries banks. There is also a great deal of concern about increased regulatory scrutiny Banks are keen to demonstrate good and robust adherence to AML procedures, for fear of attracting greater scrutiny many financial institutions saw an efficient KYC process as a way of gaining a competitive edge, KYC compliance has become so labour-intensive and most financial institutions now view it as something that just has to be done the bank that can crack this will have an advantage when we come out of this [regulatory] cycle in a few years' time
Not knowing who you are doing business with can be costly if you happen to be a bank. BNP Paribas is facing $9 billion worth of reasons to know your customer (KYC) as US authorities close in on alleged sanction-busting with clients in Sudan between 2002 and 2009, and other European banks are looking nervously over their shoulders, according to one Hong Kong-based executive. BNP Paribas is the latest in a long list of institutions to have fallen foul of US sanctions rules. At the end of 2012, HSBC had to pay a record $1.9 billion to US authorities for allowing itself to be used to launder drug money out of Mexico. Earlier that year, the authorities hit Standard Chartered Bank with a fine of $340 million for allowing its customers to trade with Iran, which is under US sanctions. As a result of the move against BNP Paribas, European banks are poring over their back books to see if they could be in the firing line. "It's a question of who they are going to come after next," says the Hong Kong executive. In the UK, penalties are being imposed on banks that fail to properly safeguard against criminal activity. In January, the Financial Conduct Authority fined Standard Bank £7.6 million for "serious weaknesses" in its internal anti-money laundering (AML) policy. Financial institutions in Asia look at the fines being imposed in Europe and the US with a certain amount of trepidation, wondering what this might mean for them. For the Hong Kong-based executive it means turning down deals, in the short term at least. In the case of that particular firm, it declined $300,000 worth of business with a China-based corporate because it was impossible to carry out all the due diligence on its ownership structure in the time available to complete the deal. "With potential multibillion dollar fines on the table for dealing with the wrong firms, it's simply much easier not to do the business," says the executive. It isn't only Asian corporates with uncertain provenance that are feeling the impact of the emphasis on KYC, says Michael Dawson, Washington-based managing director of consultancy Promontory Financial Group. "We've had banks in Asia come to us and say they've lost their clearing relationship with the US, and to get it back they need to demonstrate [to their US counterparty] they have enhanced their controls. The banks in Asia know this can happen to them and so they are, in my experience, taking this seriously." The US, and to a lesser extent the UK, are not the only jurisdictions taking a hard look at KYC. Asian countries are starting to come up with their own flavour of regulation, complete with punitive sanctions. In June 2013, the Reserve Bank of India (RBI) fined three regional banks – ICICI, HDFC and Axis – for KYC lapses. None of these institutions were prepared to talk to Asia Risk about the steps they were taking to address the failings highlighted by the RBI, in common with the eight or so global banks that declined to go on the record about the issue. A month after inflicting this initial penalty, the RBI fined a further 22 banks for a slew of regulatory failings, including the violation of KYC rules. Other regulators in Asia have yet to levy any such fines, but some believe the first may be on the way in Hong Kong or Singapore, two jurisdictions where stringent rules on AML and KYC have been drawn up recently. Regulatory scrutiny It is not only the possibility of being fined that worries banks. There is also a great deal of concern about increased regulatory scrutiny which is likely to follow any KYC failings. In March 2013, the US Federal Reserve stopped short of fining Citigroup for lacking effective controls over money laundering, but it did instruct the firm to get its house in order. "Banks are keen to demonstrate good and robust adherence to AML procedures, for fear of attracting greater scrutiny by alerting regulators to possible deficiencies in their practices and having to deal with the associated fallout," says Hugo Williamson, the London-based managing director of Risk Resolution Group, a consultancy. When JP Morgan agreed to pay $2.6 billion to settle civil and criminal charges for ignoring warnings about the fraudulent activities of investment adviser Bernard Madoff, the main concern was not the size of the payment but the additional scrutiny its transactions might face. Williamson says the cost of reviewing thousands of historical transactions in order to show regulators they are not tainted by the same level of bribery and corruption can be huge, and may result in expenditure far exceeding the original payout. "[KYC compliance] is of grave concern to financial organisations in India," says Vimala Jose, head of compliance at Geojit BNP Paribas, based in the Indian town of Kochi. "Non-compliance can attract penalties and lead to reputational damage. If the case relates to other incidents, such as money laundering, the penalty could be determined on a case-by-case basis and the reputational damage could be huge." Banks in the region have been exploring ways of tightening up their KYC and AML procedures. "The market regulator has given very clear guidelines on what is expected from an intermediary... to identify the client and to ensure the authenticity of the documents provided by the client," says Jose. "By putting processes in place, we ensure the guidelines are complied with and identification is done as per requirement." But, doing everything required to comply with the emerging raft of KYC legislation is proving a challenge for many financial institutions in Asia. Yasmeen Jaffer, director, European product manager at Markit, a financial information provider, says: "Regulators are becoming far more prescriptive about how banks identify clients and maintain client data. Those that have fallen short have faced heavy fines and today unless a bank is fully confident in its KYC process, there can be an element of doubt in starting to trade with new clients." One of the key issues is that the data needed for efficient compliance is not always easy to dig up. "Very often, clients do not provide or are unable to provide the documents required by the regulator, which leads to a lot of time and effort being spent, both by the intermediary and the investor, before an account is opened," says Jose. "While the Securities and Exchange Board of India (Sebi) has initiated some measures to simplify the process, ensuring KYC compliance is still a tedious and expensive process for the intermediaries and investor." Sebi has made it mandatory for those opening an account to provide a permanent account number (Pan) card, identifying them as a taxpayer. But the problem, says Jose, is that only a very small percentage of people on the subcontinent have such a card. A similar issue exists in Indonesia, where more than 20% of customers in rural areas lack any kind of formal ID, according to Michael Joyce, a KYC consultant based in the country. "You have to give a lot of thought to the operational implications of how you design your customer-onboarding KYC process. What looks good on paper might not work in the field," he says. Indonesia is often regarded as higher risk for money laundering, which means many regional and international banks operating in the country will need to perform extra due diligence where their customers are concerned. This makes the need to be able to obtain formal documentation all the more important, adds Joyce. A question of culture Beyond the logistical challenges of data gathering, cultural sensitivities to sharing personal information are also proving a barrier to successful implementation of AML measures. Under Indian KYC laws, the regulator requires the financial details of clients – such as their annual income and net worth – to be provided. However, while this information is used by the intermediary to monitor money-laundering activities, current regulations do not require institutions to authenticate it, which could point to a hole in the system. "Culturally, in most Asian countries, people shy away from declaring their wealth, income and so forth. In many cases this information may be incorrectly given by the client by mistake or intentionally, and the surveillance performed by the intermediary may not be serving the purpose," says Jose. Recently, Markit teamed up with Genpact, a services provider, to launch a new KYC data management service to help financial institutions streamline their client onboarding. "Companies are struggling with all the different KYC requirements in the various jurisdictions, and there are huge inefficiencies around all of the banks trying to get the same information from underlying clients," Jaffer says. Markit is not the only service provider seeking to capitalise on all the confusion. Dozens of others have come forward with solutions purporting to make the transition to KYC compliance less painful. Thomson Reuters provides a centralised database of high-risk individuals around the world, which financial organisations can consult in order to decide whether there is a need to step up their due diligence with any of their customers. Financial messaging service provider Swift's centralised KYC database was launched in January and is now being rolled out in Asia. "KYC regulation [in the region] means that banks have to be able to support a huge management of information, but at the same time their business requires speedy onboarding of clients," says Tom Golding, vice-president of product and proposition at Thomson Reuters. "It is difficult for organisations to get economies of scale if they do all the onboarding in-house, which is why they are increasingly looking at how they can outsource the process." However, with so many solutions coming on to the market, it is unclear to what extent the various platforms will communicate with one another. Patrick Pang, managing director and head of fixed income, compliance and tax at the Asia Securities Industry & Financial Markets Association (Asifma), says: "We would encourage industry and regulators to think about having some kind of KYC utility, where someone – this could be a third-party service provider or government – sets up a central database where banks or financial organisations can access the data. So they only have to do one KYC exercise rather than multiple times [per transaction]." There are huge challenges to overcome, however, before information can be shared around the region freely. A particular issue is the restriction placed by some governments on data leaving their jurisdictions. "This is a problem that people have been grappling with for years. If you can't get the data out of the country, what else can you do?" says Jaffer. "There are very few solutions around this and no one [that we spoke to] had a clear idea of how to efficiently cope with these data challenges." Singapore, Hong Kong, Malaysia, South Korea and Japan all have fairly rigid data-protection rules in place, but Indonesia is highlighted as causing particular difficulties for pan-regional players. "Indonesia is often seen as the tough customer and the country that probably causes the most hassle in terms of onshoring requirements," says Joyce. "Singapore also has a lot of restrictions in this respect, but it doesn't matter quite as much because regional banks are more likely to opt for Singapore as their hub." Joyce believes data-protection rules in Indonesia are likely to get tougher rather than easier. "This is a big problem for anyone looking to get access to Indonesia," he says. "Firms need to make sure they have their data centres housed in the country and they will have to go to great pains to get their systems onshore. This is an issue for many international and regional banks, which prefer to have centralised, hub-based models." There may be ways of circumventing the restrictive data-protection rules. Singapore, for example, allows personal information to be shared with foreign parties as long as the recipient has adequate levels of protection in place to prevent it being misused. Hong Kong has also introduced such exemptions. Golding of Thomson Reuters says it is possible to "anonymise" data before taking it out of a particular jurisdiction. "Initial scrutiny of the data can be done at local level and then, in cases where a heightened risk is detected, personal details can be stripped out of the data before it is pushed back to head office," he says, although he concedes such solutions represent an additional overhead for firms wishing to operate in the region. While KYC legislation has become a particularly hot topic over the past couple of years, as an idea, it has been around for a lot longer. "Several years ago, many financial institutions saw an efficient KYC process as a way of gaining a competitive edge, in terms of faster onboarding of clients and getting business first," says Pang from Asifma. "I think that kind of mind-set has pretty much gone now, because KYC compliance has become so labour-intensive and most financial institutions now view it as something that just has to be done." Pang thinks this change in mind-set could encourage industry participants to work together towards a more harmonised KYC compliance system across the region. However, Paul McSheaffrey, head of banking (Hong Kong) at KPMG, believes the successful companies in this area will be those that not only manage to meet all the new requirements from regulators, but do so in such a way that adds value to their business. "The majority of institutions may not be able or willing to seek the competitive advantage, but I think this is an opportunity that is being missed," says McSheaffrey. "Intellectually, I can understand why financial institutions take this position, and very often it is a conscious decision for a variety of reasons, but I think the bank that can crack this will have an advantage when we come out of this [regulatory] cycle in a few years' time. Right now the focus is on ‘let's fix the problem', because the risk of not getting it right is too great."
14,094
<h4>A lot of alt causes to know-your-customer regulations, banks ignore the law a lot, and there’s no impact</h4><p><strong>Evans-Pritchard 14</strong> Blake Evans Pritchard, Staff at Insurance Risk, 6/17/14, “Banks struggle to meet know-your-customer requirements,” https://www.risk.net/asia-risk/feature/2350277/banks-struggle-to-meet-know-your-customer-requirements</p><p>Not knowing who you are doing business with can be costly if you happen to be a bank. BNP Paribas is facing $9 billion worth of reasons to know your customer (KYC) as US authorities close in on alleged sanction-busting with clients in Sudan between 2002 and 2009, and other European banks are looking nervously over their shoulders, according to one Hong Kong-based executive.</p><p><u><mark>BNP Paribas is the latest in a long list of institutions to have fallen foul of US sanctions rules</u></mark>. At the end of 2012, HSBC had to pay a record $1.9 billion to US authorities for allowing itself to be used to launder drug money out of Mexico. Earlier that year, the authorities hit Standard Chartered Bank with a fine of $340 million for allowing its customers to trade with Iran, which is under US sanctions.</p><p>As a result of the move against BNP Paribas, European banks are poring over their back books to see if they could be in the firing line. "<u>It's a question of who they are going to come after next,</u>" says the Hong Kong executive.</p><p><u>In the UK, penalties are being imposed on banks that fail to properly safeguard against criminal activity</u>. In January, <u>the F</u>inancial <u>C</u>onduct <u>A</u>uthority <u>fined Standard Bank £7.6 million for "serious weaknesses" in its</u> internal anti-money laundering (<u>AML</u>) <u>policy</u>.</p><p><u><mark>Financial institutions in Asia look at the fines being imposed in Europe and the US with a certain amount of trepidation, wondering what this might mean for them</u></mark>. For the Hong Kong-based executive it means turning down deals, in the short term at least. In the case of that particular firm, it declined $300,000 worth of business with a China-based corporate because it was impossible to carry out all the due diligence on its ownership structure in the time available to complete the deal.</p><p>"<u><mark>With potential multibillion dollar fines on the table for dealing with the wrong firms, it's simply much easier not to do the business</u></mark>," says the executive.</p><p><u>It isn't only Asian corporates with uncertain provenance that are feeling the impact of the emphasis on KYC</u>, says Michael Dawson, Washington-based managing director of consultancy Promontory Financial Group.</p><p>"We've had banks in Asia come to us and say they've lost their clearing relationship with the US, and to get it back they need to demonstrate [to their US counterparty] they have enhanced their controls. The banks in Asia know this can happen to them and so they are, in my experience, taking this seriously."</p><p><u>The US, and to a lesser extent the UK, are not the only jurisdictions taking a hard look at KYC</u>. Asian countries are starting to come up with their own flavour of regulation, complete with punitive sanctions.</p><p><u>In</u> June <u>2013</u>, <u>the</u> Reserve Bank of India (<u>RBI</u>) <u>fined three regional banks</u> – ICICI, HDFC and Axis – <u>for KYC lapses</u>. None of these institutions were prepared to talk to Asia Risk about the steps they were taking to address the failings highlighted by the RBI, in common with the eight or so global banks that declined to go on the record about the issue. A month after inflicting this initial penalty, <u><mark>the RBI fined a further 22 banks for a slew of regulatory failings, including the violation of KYC rules</u>.</p><p></mark>Other regulators in Asia have yet to levy any such fines, but some believe the first may be on the way in Hong Kong or Singapore, two jurisdictions where stringent rules on AML and KYC have been drawn up recently.</p><p>Regulatory scrutiny</p><p><u><mark>It is not only the possibility of being fined that worries banks. There is also a great deal of concern about increased regulatory scrutiny</mark> which is likely to follow any KYC failings</u>. In March 2013, the US Federal Reserve stopped short of fining Citigroup for lacking effective controls over money laundering, but it did instruct the firm to get its house in order.</p><p>"<u><mark>Banks are keen to demonstrate good and robust adherence to AML procedures</u>, <u>for fear of attracting greater scrutiny</u></mark> by alerting regulators to possible deficiencies in their practices and having to deal with the associated fallout," says Hugo Williamson, the London-based managing director of Risk Resolution Group, a consultancy.</p><p>When JP Morgan agreed to pay $2.6 billion to settle civil and criminal charges for ignoring warnings about the fraudulent activities of investment adviser Bernard Madoff, the main concern was not the size of the payment but the additional scrutiny its transactions might face. Williamson says the cost of reviewing thousands of historical transactions in order to show regulators they are not tainted by the same level of bribery and corruption can be huge, and may result in expenditure far exceeding the original payout.</p><p>"[KYC compliance] is of grave concern to financial organisations in India," says Vimala Jose, head of compliance at Geojit BNP Paribas, based in the Indian town of Kochi. "Non-compliance can attract penalties and lead to reputational damage. If the case relates to other incidents, such as money laundering, the penalty could be determined on a case-by-case basis and the reputational damage could be huge."</p><p>Banks in the region have been exploring ways of tightening up their KYC and AML procedures. "The market regulator has given very clear guidelines on what is expected from an intermediary... to identify the client and to ensure the authenticity of the documents provided by the client," says Jose. "By putting processes in place, we ensure the guidelines are complied with and identification is done as per requirement."</p><p>But, doing everything required to comply with the emerging raft of KYC legislation is proving a challenge for many financial institutions in Asia.</p><p>Yasmeen Jaffer, director, European product manager at Markit, a financial information provider, says: "Regulators are becoming far more prescriptive about how banks identify clients and maintain client data. Those that have fallen short have faced heavy fines and today unless a bank is fully confident in its KYC process, there can be an element of doubt in starting to trade with new clients."</p><p>One of the key issues is that <u>the data needed for efficient compliance is not always easy to dig up</u>.</p><p>"Very often, clients do not provide or are unable to provide the documents required by the regulator, which leads to a lot of time and effort being spent, both by the intermediary and the investor, before an account is opened," says Jose. "While the Securities and Exchange Board of India (Sebi) has initiated some measures to simplify the process, ensuring KYC compliance is still a tedious and expensive process for the intermediaries and investor."</p><p>Sebi has made it mandatory for those opening an account to provide a permanent account number (Pan) card, identifying them as a taxpayer. But the problem, says Jose, is that only a very small percentage of people on the subcontinent have such a card.</p><p>A similar issue exists in Indonesia, where more than 20% of customers in rural areas lack any kind of formal ID, according to Michael Joyce, a KYC consultant based in the country. "You have to give a lot of thought to the operational implications of how you design your customer-onboarding KYC process. What looks good on paper might not work in the field," he says. Indonesia is often regarded as higher risk for money laundering, which means many regional and international banks operating in the country will need to perform extra due diligence where their customers are concerned. This makes the need to be able to obtain formal documentation all the more important, adds Joyce.</p><p>A question of culture</p><p>Beyond the logistical challenges of data gathering, cultural sensitivities to sharing personal information are also proving a barrier to successful implementation of AML measures. Under Indian KYC laws, the regulator requires the financial details of clients – such as their annual income and net worth – to be provided. However, while this information is used by the intermediary to monitor money-laundering activities, current regulations do not require institutions to authenticate it, which could point to a hole in the system.</p><p>"Culturally, in most Asian countries, people shy away from declaring their wealth, income and so forth. In many cases this information may be incorrectly given by the client by mistake or intentionally, and the surveillance performed by the intermediary may not be serving the purpose," says Jose.</p><p>Recently, Markit teamed up with Genpact, a services provider, to launch a new KYC data management service to help financial institutions streamline their client onboarding.</p><p>"Companies are struggling with all the different KYC requirements in the various jurisdictions, and there are huge inefficiencies around all of the banks trying to get the same information from underlying clients," Jaffer says.</p><p>Markit is not the only service provider seeking to capitalise on all the confusion. Dozens of others have come forward with solutions purporting to make the transition to KYC compliance less painful. Thomson Reuters provides a centralised database of high-risk individuals around the world, which financial organisations can consult in order to decide whether there is a need to step up their due diligence with any of their customers. Financial messaging service provider Swift's centralised KYC database was launched in January and is now being rolled out in Asia.</p><p>"KYC regulation [in the region] means that banks have to be able to support a huge management of information, but at the same time their business requires speedy onboarding of clients," says Tom Golding, vice-president of product and proposition at Thomson Reuters. "It is difficult for organisations to get economies of scale if they do all the onboarding in-house, which is why they are increasingly looking at how they can outsource the process."</p><p>However, with so many solutions coming on to the market, it is unclear to what extent the various platforms will communicate with one another.</p><p>Patrick Pang, managing director and head of fixed income, compliance and tax at the Asia Securities Industry & Financial Markets Association (Asifma), says: "We would encourage industry and regulators to think about having some kind of KYC utility, where someone – this could be a third-party service provider or government – sets up a central database where banks or financial organisations can access the data. So they only have to do one KYC exercise rather than multiple times [per transaction]."</p><p>There are huge challenges to overcome, however, before information can be shared around the region freely. A particular issue is the restriction placed by some governments on data leaving their jurisdictions. "This is a problem that people have been grappling with for years. If you can't get the data out of the country, what else can you do?" says Jaffer. "There are very few solutions around this and no one [that we spoke to] had a clear idea of how to efficiently cope with these data challenges."</p><p>Singapore, Hong Kong, Malaysia, South Korea and Japan all have fairly rigid data-protection rules in place, but Indonesia is highlighted as causing particular difficulties for pan-regional players.</p><p>"Indonesia is often seen as the tough customer and the country that probably causes the most hassle in terms of onshoring requirements," says Joyce. "Singapore also has a lot of restrictions in this respect, but it doesn't matter quite as much because regional banks are more likely to opt for Singapore as their hub."</p><p>Joyce believes data-protection rules in Indonesia are likely to get tougher rather than easier. "This is a big problem for anyone looking to get access to Indonesia," he says. "Firms need to make sure they have their data centres housed in the country and they will have to go to great pains to get their systems onshore. This is an issue for many international and regional banks, which prefer to have centralised, hub-based models."</p><p>There may be ways of circumventing the restrictive data-protection rules. Singapore, for example, allows personal information to be shared with foreign parties as long as the recipient has adequate levels of protection in place to prevent it being misused. Hong Kong has also introduced such exemptions.</p><p>Golding of Thomson Reuters says it is possible to "anonymise" data before taking it out of a particular jurisdiction. "Initial scrutiny of the data can be done at local level and then, in cases where a heightened risk is detected, personal details can be stripped out of the data before it is pushed back to head office," he says, although he concedes such solutions represent an additional overhead for firms wishing to operate in the region.</p><p><u>While KYC legislation has become a particularly hot topic</u> <u>over the past couple of years</u>, as an idea, <u>it has been around for a lot longer</u>.</p><p>"<u>Several years ago, <mark>many financial institutions saw an efficient KYC process as a way of gaining a competitive edge,</mark> in terms of faster onboarding of clients and getting business first</u>," says Pang from Asifma. "I think that kind of mind-set has pretty much gone <u>now</u>, because <u><mark>KYC compliance has become so labour-intensive and most financial institutions now view it as something that just has to be done</u></mark>."</p><p>Pang thinks this change in mind-set could encourage industry participants to work together towards a more harmonised KYC compliance system across the region.</p><p>However, Paul McSheaffrey, head of banking (Hong Kong) at KPMG, believes the <u>successful companies in this area will be those that not only manage to meet all the new requirements from regulators, but do so in such a way that adds value to their business</u>.</p><p>"The majority of institutions may not be able or willing to seek the competitive advantage, but I think this is an opportunity that is being missed," says McSheaffrey. "Intellectually, I can understand why financial institutions take this position, and very often it is a conscious decision for a variety of reasons, but I think <u><mark>the bank that can crack this will have an advantage when we come out of this [regulatory] cycle in a few years' time</u></mark>. Right now the focus is on ‘let's fix the problem', because the risk of not getting it right is too great."</p>
WTO
Banks
AT: Inevitable
430,598
2
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,358
“Social movement” fails- specific to their advocate
Atwell 2012
Atwell 2012 (Mary Welek, Radford University, The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness, The Journal of Southern History78.1 (Feb 2012): 240-241, proquest)
Alexander's book slides to a disappointing conclusion when the author attempts to address a remedy for the injustices she has described. Her recommendation is that opponents of the new Jim Crow must begin "challenging the basic structure of society," a lofty and amorphous suggestion indeed
null
All of Alexander's points about the discriminatory impact of the drug laws are valid and generally acknowledged. Where she moves outside the mainstream is in her apparent claim that the criminal justice system is intentionally, universally, and inevitably malign. Her support for such assertions generally comes from popular journalism and the work of advocacy groups. Finally, the book slides to a disappointing conclusion when the author attempts to address a remedy for the injustices she has described. Her recommendation is that opponents of the new Jim Crow must begin "challenging the basic structure of society," a lofty and amorphous suggestion indeed (p. 246).
670
<h4><strong>“Social movement” fails- specific to their advocate</h4><p>Atwell 2012</strong> (Mary Welek, Radford University, The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness, The Journal of Southern History78.1 (Feb 2012): 240-241, proquest)</p><p>All of <u>Alexander's</u> points about the discriminatory impact of the drug laws are valid and generally acknowledged. Where she moves outside the mainstream is in her apparent claim that the criminal justice system is intentionally, universally, and inevitably malign. Her support for such assertions generally comes from popular journalism and the work of advocacy groups. Finally, the <u>book slides to a disappointing conclusion when the author attempts to address a remedy for the injustices she has described. Her recommendation is that opponents of the new Jim Crow must begin "challenging the basic structure of society," a lofty and amorphous suggestion indeed</u> <strong>(p. 246).</p></strong>
null
null
Solvency
430,666
3
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,359
No risk of money laundering and even if there was, the plan can’t solve – regulated environments are just as susceptible and patchworks of international regulation make enforcement impossible
Banks 14
Banks 14 (James, professor of criminology at Sheffield Hallam University, “Online Gambling and Crime: Causes, Controls and Controversies”, google books)
There is little evidence of money laundering through regulated gambling environments Levi in his assessment of the money laundering risks questions the likelihood of significant sums of money being laundered through such sites, noting that e- gaming ‘does not directly feature significantly, or indeed at all’ in published threat assessments of the policing priorities of European policing organisations generalised and understandable expressions of concern about money laundering risks posed by the Internet have not been accompanied by evidence of significant laundering via e-gaming’ This viewpoint is echoed by Sparrow, Bazelon and Jackson who note that: ‘There is little documentation by which to gauge the extent of actual money laundering in online gambling’. a 2005 report undertaken on behalf of the Interactive Gaming Council noted that there was ‘scant’ evidence of the existence of money laundering in online gambling. With no complaints of laundering having ever been recorded by the Internet Crine Complaint Centre’ the report suggests that Internet gaming does not, contribute to money laundering This suggests that ‘the risks associated with the sector are modest, due to the high traceability of e-gaming transactions and customer identification controls in the regulated sector’ (Levi, 2009: 4). Levi suggests that e-gaming does present money laundering risks, but due to the high traceability of transactions, customer identification controls and betting limits in the regulated sector these risks are significantly lower than in land based gaming online gambling operators may credit gambling profits or unused funds back to a different account than the one from which the gambling account was funded Second, gaming transactions may be completed by ‘front people’ Third, in peer-to-peer games, money may be transferred between both electronic and human players through deliberate losses Fourth, payment to and from gambling establishments may be undertaken via financial intermediaries that adhere to anti-money laundering directives but whose Know Your Customer procedures are of modest or variable quality Fifth, laundering may occur via legal betting The Financial Action Task Force in their report Money Laundering through the Football Sector, suggest that laundering through betting is a ‘huge and increasing problem’ sports betting is a far more attractive approach to laundering money as payout rates have increased from less than 80 per cent for land based establishments to over 92 per cent it is also possible to bet with a host of different online bookmakers With money laundering costs typically exceeding 30 per cent, Internet sports betting offers an extremely attractive means of laundering money with supply costs reduced the profitability and prevalence of laundering and organised crime is increased FATF suggest that: [The use of the Internet for online betting further increases the risk of money laundering Due to the fact that most countries have different gambling regulations, the gambling market is non-transparent Providers are established ¡n countries which allow the organisation of gambling activities or in countries that do not regulate or supervise gambling. it is however not easy to take legal action against providers who offer their services online and are established abroad This in combination with the non-transparency of the gambling market makes betting a laundering vehicle for criminals
There is little evidence of significant sums of money being laundered through e- gaming ‘There is little documentation by which to gauge laundering in online gambling’ With no complaints of laundering having ever been recorded e-gaming money laundering risks due to the high traceability of transactions, customer identification controls and betting limits are significantly lower than in land based gaming operators may credit profits back to a different account laundering may occur via legal betting sports betting is a far more attractive approach as payout rates have increased to over 92 per cent Internet sports betting an extremely attractive means of laundering Due to the fact that most countries have different gambling regulations, the market is non-transparent regulate or supervise gambling. it is however not easy to take legal action against providers who offer their services online and are established
There is, in fact, little evidence of money laundering through regulated gambling environments. Levi (2009: 4), in his European overview and assessment of the money laundering risks of e-gaming, questions the likelihood of significant sums of money — ‘in the billions of Euros’ — being laundered through such sites, noting that e- gaming ‘does not directly feature significantly, or indeed at all’ in published threat assessments of the policing priorities of Europol or other European policing organisations. Moreover, ‘generalised and understandable expressions of concern by Europol and by the Financial Action Task Force about money laundering risks posed by the Internet have not been accompanied by evidence of significant laundering via e-gaming’ (Levi, 2009: 4, emphasis in original). This viewpoint is echoed by Sparrow, Bazelon and Jackson (2009: 38) who note that: ‘There is little documentation by which to gauge the extent of actual money laundering in online gambling’. Examining the vulnerability of online gambling to money laundering, the US General Accounting Office (2002) concluded that the ‘views on the vulnerability of Internet gambling to money laundering are mixed’, whilst a 2005 report (NFC Global, 2005) undertaken on behalf of the Interactive Gaming Council also noted that there was ‘scant’ evidence of the existence of money laundering in online gambling. With no complaints of laundering having ever been recorded by the Internet Crine Complaint Centre’ (1C3)the report suggests that: ‘Internet gaming does not, in and of itself, contribute to money laundering. Rather, it is the financial transactions that are used to move money on the Internet that may be susceptible to money laundering’ (NFC Global, 2005: 4). This suggests that ‘the risks associated with the sector are comparatively modest, due to the high traceability of e-gaming transactions and customer identification controls in the regulated sector’ (Levi, 2009: 4). Levi (2009), however, suggests that e-gaming does present money laundering risks, but due to the high traceability of transactions, customer identification controls and betting limits in the regulated sector these risks are significantly lower than in land based gaming and cash operated businesses. Levi identifies five areas of risk to regulated e-gaming markets. First, online gambling operators may credit gambling profits or unused funds back to a different account than the one from which the gambling account was funded. Although many operators do not allow winnings or cash-ins to be credited to a different account to that that is used for the funding of gaming transactions, they may be obliged to do so at the request of the customer. Second, gaming transactions may be completed by ‘front people’. Such individuals can undertake gaming transactions for undisclosed principals or act as ‘mules’ by allowing their personal accounts to be employed as conduits for financial transactions. Third, in peer-to-peer games, money may be transferred between both electronic and human players through deliberate losses, with little cost to the players. Despite the fact that such laundering poses little financial risk to operators, reputational and punitive damages imposed by regulators may result if such activities are identified. Fourth, payment to and from gambling establishments may be undertaken via financial intermediaries that adhere to anti-money laundering directives but whose Know Your Customer (KYC) procedures are of modest or variable quality. Fifth, laundering may occur via legal (and illegal) betting. The Financial Action Task Force (2009: 8), in their report Money Laundering through the Football Sector, suggest that laundering through betting is a ‘huge and increasing problem’. Today, sports betting is a far more attractive approach to laundering money than it was 15 years ago, as payout rates have increased from less than 80 per cent for land based establishments to over 92 per cent for many of the online companies (SportsAccord, 2011). In many countries, it is also possible to bet with a host of different online bookmakers. By spreading bets between bookmakers with the best odds, payouts of over loo per cent can be achieved (ibid.). With money laundering costs typically exceeding 30 per cent, Internet sports betting offers an extremely attractive means of laundering money. Fiedler (2013) claims that with supply costs reduced the profitability and prevalence of laundering and organised crime is increased. Although there is little empirical evidence to support such a claim, FATF suggest that: [The use of the Internet for online betting further increases the risk of money laundering ... Due to the fact that most countries have different gambling regulations, the gambling market is non-transparent and is a heterogeneous market with a mix of private and state companies acting both nationally and internationally. Providers are often established ¡n countries which allow the organisation of gambling activities or in countries that do not regulate or supervise gambling. it is however not easy to take legal action against providers who offer their services online and are established abroad. This in combination with the non-transparency of the gambling market makes betting an interesting money laundering vehicle for criminals. (Financial Action Task Force, 2009b: 24—25)
5,383
<h4>No risk of money laundering and <u>even if</u> there was, the plan can’t solve – regulated environments are just as susceptible and patchworks of international regulation make enforcement impossible</h4><p><strong>Banks 14 </strong>(James, professor of criminology at Sheffield Hallam University, “Online Gambling and Crime: Causes, Controls and Controversies”, google books)</p><p><u><mark>There is</u></mark>, in fact, <u><mark>little evidence of </mark>money laundering through regulated gambling environments</u>. <u>Levi</u> (2009: 4), <u>in his</u> European overview and <u>assessment of the money laundering risks</u> of e-gaming, <u>questions the likelihood of <mark>significant sums of money</u></mark> — ‘in the billions of Euros’ — <u><mark>being laundered through</mark> such sites, noting that <mark>e- gaming</mark> ‘does not directly feature significantly, or indeed at all’ in published threat assessments of the policing priorities of</u> Europol or other <u>European policing organisations</u>. Moreover, ‘<u>generalised and understandable expressions of concern</u> by Europol and by the Financial Action Task Force <u>about money laundering risks posed by the Internet have not been accompanied by evidence of significant laundering via e-gaming’</u> (Levi, 2009: 4, emphasis in original). <u>This viewpoint is echoed by Sparrow, Bazelon and Jackson</u> (2009: 38) <u>who note that: <strong><mark>‘There is little documentation by which to gauge</mark> the extent of actual money <mark>laundering</mark> <mark>in online gambling’</mark>.</u></strong> Examining the vulnerability of online gambling to money laundering, the US General Accounting Office (2002) concluded that the ‘views on the vulnerability of Internet gambling to money laundering are mixed’, whilst <u>a 2005 report</u> (NFC Global, 2005) <u>undertaken on behalf of the Interactive Gaming Council</u> also <u>noted that</u> <u><strong>there was ‘scant’ evidence of the existence of money laundering in online gambling.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>With no complaints of laundering having ever been recorded</u></strong></mark> <u>by the Internet Crine Complaint Centre’</u> (1C3)<u>the report suggests that</u>: ‘<u>Internet gaming does not,</u> in and of itself, <u>contribute to money laundering</u>. Rather, it is the financial transactions that are used to move money on the Internet that may be susceptible to money laundering’ (NFC Global, 2005: 4). <u>This suggests that ‘the risks associated with the sector are</u> comparatively <u>modest, due to the high traceability of e-gaming transactions and customer identification controls in the regulated sector’ (Levi, 2009: 4).</p><p>Levi</u> (2009), however, <u>suggests that <mark>e-gaming</mark> does present <mark>money laundering risks</mark>, but <mark>due to the high traceability of transactions, customer identification controls and betting limits</u></mark> <u><strong>in the regulated sector these risks <mark>are significantly lower than in land based gaming</u></strong></mark> and cash operated businesses. Levi identifies five areas of risk to regulated e-gaming markets. First, <u>online gambling <mark>operators may credit</mark> gambling <mark>profits</mark> or unused funds <mark>back to a different account</mark> than the one from which the gambling account was funded</u>. Although many operators do not allow winnings or cash-ins to be credited to a different account to that that is used for the funding of gaming transactions, they may be obliged to do so at the request of the customer. <u>Second, gaming transactions may be completed by ‘front people’</u>. Such individuals can undertake gaming transactions for undisclosed principals or act as ‘mules’ by allowing their personal accounts to be employed as conduits for financial transactions. <u>Third, in peer-to-peer games, money may be transferred between both electronic and human players through deliberate losses</u>, with little cost to the players. Despite the fact that such laundering poses little financial risk to operators, reputational and punitive damages imposed by regulators may result if such activities are identified. <u>Fourth, payment to and from gambling establishments may be undertaken via financial intermediaries that adhere to anti-money laundering directives but whose Know Your Customer</u> (KYC) <u>procedures are of modest or variable quality</u>. <u>Fifth, <mark>laundering may occur via legal</u></mark> (and illegal) <u><mark>betting</u></mark>. <u>The Financial Action Task Force</u> (2009: 8), <u>in their report Money Laundering through the Football Sector, suggest that</u> <u><strong>laundering through betting is a ‘huge and increasing problem’</u></strong>. Today, <u><strong><mark>sports betting is a far more attractive approach</mark> to laundering money</u></strong> than it was 15 years ago, <u><strong><mark>as payout rates have increased</mark> from less than 80 per cent for land based establishments <mark>to over 92 per cent</u></strong></mark> for many of the online companies (SportsAccord, 2011). In many countries, <u>it is also possible to bet with a host of different online bookmakers</u>. By spreading bets between bookmakers with the best odds, payouts of over loo per cent can be achieved (ibid.). <u>With money laundering costs typically exceeding 30 per cent, <strong><mark>Internet sports betting </mark>offers <mark>an extremely attractive means of laundering </mark>money</u></strong>. Fiedler (2013) claims that <u>with supply costs reduced the profitability and prevalence of laundering and organised crime is increased</u>. Although there is little empirical evidence to support such a claim, <u>FATF suggest that:</p><p>[The use of the Internet for online betting further increases the risk of money laundering</u> ... <u><mark>Due to the fact that most countries have different gambling regulations,</mark> <mark>the</mark> gambling <mark>market is non-transparent</u></mark> and is a heterogeneous market with a mix of private and state companies acting both nationally and internationally. <u>Providers are</u> often <u>established ¡n countries which allow the organisation of gambling activities or in countries that do not <mark>regulate or supervise gambling<strong>. it is however not easy to take legal action against providers who offer their services online and are established</mark> abroad</u></strong>. <u>This in combination with the non-transparency of the gambling market makes betting a</u>n interesting money <u>laundering vehicle for criminals</u><strong>. (Financial Action Task Force, 2009b: 24—25)</p></strong>
null
null
Costa Rica
429,741
21
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,360
A program with a government intermediary is viable means for "organ sales"
Wilkinson 11
Wilkinson 11 Stephen Wilkinson, Professor of Bioethics, Lancaster University (UK) 10-17-11 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, "The Sale of Human Organs" http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/organs-sale/
The expression ‘organ sale’ covers a wide range of different practices. People most readily associate it with the case in which one individual sells to another But there are other possibilities too One noteworthy policy proposal comes from Erin and Harris who suggest that a market in human organs should have a central public body responsible for making (and funding) all purchases and for allocating organs fairly in accordance with clinical criteria. Prices are set at a reasonably generous level to attract people voluntarily into the market.
One noteworthy policy proposal comes from Erin and Harris who suggest that a market in human organs should have a central public body responsible for making (and funding) all purchases and for allocating organs fairly in accordance with clinical criteria Prices are set at a reasonably generous level to attract people voluntarily into the market.
1. Different Kinds of Organ Sale System The expression ‘organ sale’ covers a wide range of different practices. People most readily associate it with the case in which one individual (who needs or wants money) sells his or her kidney to another (who needs a kidney). But there are other possibilities too. One (in countries where the prior consent of the deceased is required for cadaveric organ donation) is to pay people living now for rights over their body after death. Another (in countries where the consent of relatives is required for cadaveric organ donation) is to pay relatives for transplant rights over their recently deceased loved ones' bodies. Since the kidney is the most commonly transplanted organ and since the ethics literature on organ sale is mainly about kidney sale from live donors, that is the practice on which this entry will focus. ‘Organ sale’ as the term is used here does not include the sale of body products (a category which includes blood, eggs, hair, and sperm) since this is different in some important respects. For example, the risk of permanent harm is generally much less in the case of blood and hair donation; while, the donation of eggs and sperm raises additional issues relating to the creation and parenting of additional future people. That said, many of the fundamental issues are similar and the very same concerns about (for example) exploitation and consent arise in both cases. An important preliminary point is that almost all serious advocates of allowing payment for human organs argue not for an unfettered ‘free market’ but for a regulated one. Radcliffe Richards et al. (1998, 1950) for example, in their paper “The Case for Allowing Kidney Sales” say: It must be stressed that we are not arguing for the positive conclusion that organ sales must always be acceptable, let alone that there should be an unfettered market. While Wilkinson (2003, 132) is typical of organ sale defenders in wishing to distance himself from today's (largely ‘underground’) organ trade: … far from being a reason to continue the ban on sale, the dreadfulness of present practice may be a reason to discontinue prohibition, so that the organ trade can be brought ‘overground’ and properly regulated. Different scholars have different views about the precise scope and extent of the regulation required, but most support the requirements that organ sellers give valid consent, are paid a reasonable fee, and are provided with adequate medical care. Taylor (2005, 110) for example, says that: At minimum … a market should require that vendors give their informed consent to the sale of their kidneys, that they not be coerced into selling their kidneys by a third party and that they receive adequate post-operative care. One noteworthy policy proposal comes from Erin and Harris (1994; 2003) who suggest that a market in human organs should have the following features: It is limited to a particular geopolitical area, such as a state or the European Union, with only citizens or residents of that area being allowed to sell or to receive organs. There is a central public body responsible for making (and funding) all purchases and for allocating organs fairly in accordance with clinical criteria. Direct sales are banned. Prices are set at a reasonably generous level to attract people voluntarily into the market.
3,355
<h4>A program with a government intermediary is viable means for "organ sales"</h4><p><strong>Wilkinson 11</strong> Stephen Wilkinson, Professor of Bioethics, Lancaster University (UK) 10-17-11 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, "The Sale of Human Organs" <u>http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/organs-sale/</p><p></u>1. Different Kinds of Organ Sale System <u>The expression ‘organ sale’ covers a wide range of different practices. People most readily associate it with the case in which one individual</u> (who needs or wants money) <u>sells </u>his or her kidney <u>to another</u> (who needs a kidney). <u>But there are other possibilities too</u>. One (in countries where the prior consent of the deceased is required for cadaveric organ donation) is to pay people living now for rights over their body after death. Another (in countries where the consent of relatives is required for cadaveric organ donation) is to pay relatives for transplant rights over their recently deceased loved ones' bodies. Since the kidney is the most commonly transplanted organ and since the ethics literature on organ sale is mainly about kidney sale from live donors, that is the practice on which this entry will focus. ‘Organ sale’ as the term is used here does not include the sale of body products (a category which includes blood, eggs, hair, and sperm) since this is different in some important respects. For example, the risk of permanent harm is generally much less in the case of blood and hair donation; while, the donation of eggs and sperm raises additional issues relating to the creation and parenting of additional future people. That said, many of the fundamental issues are similar and the very same concerns about (for example) exploitation and consent arise in both cases. An important preliminary point is that almost all serious advocates of allowing payment for human organs argue not for an unfettered ‘free market’ but for a regulated one. Radcliffe Richards et al. (1998, 1950) for example, in their paper “The Case for Allowing Kidney Sales” say: It must be stressed that we are not arguing for the positive conclusion that organ sales must always be acceptable, let alone that there should be an unfettered market. While Wilkinson (2003, 132) is typical of organ sale defenders in wishing to distance himself from today's (largely ‘underground’) organ trade: … far from being a reason to continue the ban on sale, the dreadfulness of present practice may be a reason to discontinue prohibition, so that the organ trade can be brought ‘overground’ and properly regulated. Different scholars have different views about the precise scope and extent of the regulation required, but most support the requirements that organ sellers give valid consent, are paid a reasonable fee, and are provided with adequate medical care. Taylor (2005, 110) for example, says that: At minimum … a market should require that vendors give their informed consent to the sale of their kidneys, that they not be coerced into selling their kidneys by a third party and that they receive adequate post-operative care. <u><mark>One noteworthy policy proposal comes from Erin and Harris</u></mark> (1994; 2003) <u><mark>who suggest that a market in human organs should have</mark> </u>the following features: It is limited to a particular geopolitical area, such as a state or the European Union, with only citizens or residents of that area being allowed to sell or to receive organs. There is <u><mark>a central public body responsible for making (and funding) all purchases and for allocating organs fairly in accordance with clinical criteria</mark>. </u>Direct sales are banned. <u><mark>Prices are set at a reasonably generous level to attract people voluntarily into the market.</p></u></mark>
null
null
Contention 3 The Plan solves
429,540
21
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,361
New sanctions destroy the Iran deal- causes prolif and Israel strikes- extinction
We control time frame and magnitude – deal failure draws in global powers and goes nuclear within months
We control time frame and magnitude – deal failure draws in global powers and goes nuclear within months
Global nuclear conflict between US, Russia, China likely if Iran talks fail A global conflict between the US, Russia, and China is likely in months should the world powers fail to reach a nuclear deal with Iran If the talks fail then there would be enormous international pressure to drive towards a conflict with Iran before Obama leaves office The United States could find itself on one side and Russia and China on the other and those are the kinds of conditions that can lead to miscalculation we could be facing a global conflict in the coming months that’s got to be avoided at all costs when you’ve got countries like the United States, Russia, and China with” their arsenals of “nuclear weapons failure in talks with Iran could lead to war
Global nuclear conflict between US, Russia, China likely if Iran talks fail A global conflict between the US, Russia, and China is likely in months should the world powers fail to reach a deal with Iran If the talks fail there would be enormous international pressure to drive towards a conflict with Iran The U S could find itself on one side and Russia and China on the other those conditions can lead to miscalculation
PressTV 13 Global nuclear conflict between US, Russia, China likely if Iran talks fail, 11/13/13, http://www.presstv.ir/detail/2013/11/13/334544/global-nuclear-war-likely-if-iran-talks-fail/ A global conflict between the US, Russia, and China is likely in the coming months should the world powers fail to reach a nuclear deal with Iran, an American analyst says.¶ “If the talks fail, if the agreements being pursued are not successfully carried forward and implemented, then there would be enormous international pressure to drive towards a conflict with Iran before [US President Barack] Obama leaves office and that’s a very great danger that no one can underestimate the importance of,” senior editor at the Executive Intelligence Review Jeff Steinberg told Press TV on Wednesday. ¶ “The United States could find itself on one side and Russia and China on the other and those are the kinds of conditions that can lead to miscalculation and general roar,” Steinberg said. ¶ “So the danger in this situation is that if these talks don’t go forward, we could be facing a global conflict in the coming months and years and that’s got to be avoided at all costs when you’ve got countries like the United States, Russia, and China with” their arsenals of “nuclear weapons,” he warned. ¶ The warning came one day after the White House told Congress not to impose new sanctions against Tehran because failure in talks with Iran could lead to war.
1,442
<h4><strong>New sanctions destroy the Iran deal- causes prolif and Israel strikes- extinction</h4><p>We control time frame and magnitude – deal failure draws in global powers and goes nuclear within months </p><p>PressTV 13</p><p><u></strong><mark>Global nuclear conflict between US, Russia, China likely if Iran talks fail</u></mark>, 11/13/13, http://www.presstv.ir/detail/2013/11/13/334544/global-nuclear-war-likely-if-iran-talks-fail/</p><p><u><mark>A <strong>global conflict between the US, Russia, and China is likely in </u></strong></mark>the coming<u><strong><mark> months should the world powers fail to reach a</mark> nuclear <mark>deal with Iran</u></strong></mark>, an American analyst says.¶ “<u><mark>If the talks fail</u></mark>, if the agreements being pursued are not successfully carried forward and implemented, <u>then <mark>there would be enormous international pressure to drive towards a conflict with Iran</mark> before</u> [US President Barack] <u>Obama leaves office</u> and that’s a very great danger that no one can underestimate the importance of,” senior editor at the Executive Intelligence Review Jeff Steinberg told Press TV on Wednesday. ¶ “<u><mark>The U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>could find itself on one side and Russia and China on the other</mark> and <mark>those</mark> are the kinds of <mark>conditions</mark> that <mark>can <strong>lead to miscalculation</u></strong></mark> and general roar,” Steinberg said. ¶ “So the danger in this situation is that if these talks don’t go forward, <u>we could be facing a global conflict in the coming months</u> and years and <u>that’s got to be avoided at all costs when you’ve got countries like the United States, Russia, and China with” their arsenals of “nuclear weapons</u>,” he warned. ¶ The warning came one day after the White House told Congress not to impose new sanctions against Tehran because <u>failure in talks with Iran could lead to war</u><strong>.</p></strong>
null
null
O/V
188,942
22
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,362
Does the evolutionary process culminate in a being that transcends its genetic baggage, that programs and charts its future, and that allows its weakest and sickest to survive? Supplanting the imperative of the survival of the fittest with a culturally-sensitive principle may be the hallmark of a successful evolution, rather than the beginning of an inexorable decline. The eugenics movement turns this argument on its head. They accept the premise that the contribution of natural selection to the makeup of future human generations is glacial and negligible. But they reject the conclusion that, having ridden ourselves of its tyranny, we can now let the weak and sick among us survive and multiply. Rather, they propose to replace natural selection with eugenics. But who, by which authority, and according to what guidelines will administer this man-made culling and decide who is to live and who is to die, who is to breed and who may not? Why select by intelligence and not by courtesy or altruism or church-going - or al of them together? It is here that eugenics fails miserably. Should the criterion be physical, like in ancient Sparta? Should it be mental? Should IQ determine one's fate - or social status or wealth? Different answers yield disparate eugenic programs and target dissimilar groups in the population. Aren't eugenic criteria liable to be unduly influenced by fashion and cultural bias? Can we agree on a universal eugenic agenda in a world as ethnically and culturally diverse as ours? If we do get it wrong - and the chances are overwhelming - will we not damage our gene pool irreparably and, with it, the future of our species? And even if many will avoid a slippery slope leading from eugenics to active extermination of "inferior" groups in the general population - can we guarantee that everyone will? How to prevent eugenics from being appropriated by an intrusive, authoritarian, or even murderous state? Modern eugenicists distance themselves from the crude methods adopted at the beginning of the last century by 29 countries, including Germany, The United States, Canada, Switzerland, Austria, Venezuela, Estonia, Argentina, Norway, Denmark, Sweden (until 1976), Brazil, Italy, Greece, and Spain. They talk about free contraceptives for low-IQ women, vasectomies or tubal ligations for criminals, sperm banks with contributions from high achievers, and incentives for college students to procreate. Modern genetic engineering and biotechnology are readily applicable to eugenic projects. Cloning can serve to preserve the genes of the fittest. Embryo selection and prenatal diagnosis of genetically diseased embryos can reduce the number of the unfit. But even these innocuous variants of eugenics fly in the face of liberalism. Inequality, claim the proponents of hereditary amelioration, is genetic, not environmental. All men are created unequal and as much subject to the natural laws of heredity as are cows and bees. Inferior people give birth to inferior offspring and, thus, propagate their inferiority. Even if this were true - which is at best debatable - the question is whether the inferior specimen of our species possess the inalienable right to reproduce? If society is to bear the costs of over-population - social welfare, medical care, daycare centers - then society has the right to regulate procreation. But does it have the right to act discriminately in doing so? Another dilemma is whether we have the moral right - let alone the necessary knowledge - to interfere with natural as well as social and demographic trends. Eugenicists counter that contraception and indiscriminate medicine already do just that. Yet, studies show that the more affluent and educated a population becomes - the less fecund it is. Birth rates throughout the world have dropped dramatically already. Instead of culling the great unwashed and the unworthy - wouldn't it be a better idea to educate them (or their off-spring) and provide them with economic opportunities (euthenics rather than eugenics)? Human populations seem to self-regulate. A gentle and persistent nudge in the right direction - of increased affluence and better schooling - might achieve more than a hundred eugenic programs, voluntary or compulsory. That eugenics presents itself not merely as a biological-social agenda, but as a panacea, ought to arouse suspicion. The typical eugenics text reads more like a catechism than a reasoned argument. Previous all-encompassing and omnicompetent plans tended to end traumatically - especially when they contrasted a human elite with a dispensable underclass of persons. Above all, eugenics is about human hubris. To presume to know better than the lottery of life is haughty.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Does the evolutionary process culminate in a being that transcends its genetic baggage, that programs and charts its future, and that allows its weakest and sickest to survive? Supplanting the imperative of the survival of the fittest with <u>a culturally-sensitive principle may be the hallmark of a successful evolution, rather than the beginning of an inexorable decline.</u> The eugenics movement turns this argument on its head. They accept the premise that the contribution of natural selection to the makeup of future human generations is glacial and negligible. But they reject the conclusion that, having ridden ourselves of its tyranny, we can now let the weak and sick among us survive and multiply. Rather, they propose to replace natural selection with eugenics. But who, by which authority, and according to what guidelines will administer this man-made culling and decide who is to live and who is to die, who is to breed and who may not? Why select by intelligence and not by courtesy or altruism or church-going - or al of them together? It is here that eugenics fails miserably. Should the criterion be physical, like in ancient Sparta? Should it be mental? Should IQ determine one's fate - or social status or wealth? Different answers yield disparate eugenic programs and target dissimilar groups in the population. <u><mark>Aren't eugenic criteria liable to be unduly influenced by fashion and cultural bias</u></mark>? Can we agree on a universal eugenic agenda in a world as ethnically and culturally diverse as ours<u>? <mark>If we</mark> do <mark>get it wrong</mark> - and the chances are overwhelming - will <mark>we</mark> not <mark>damage our gene pool irreparably and</mark>, with it, <mark>the future of our species</u></mark>? <u>And <mark>even if many will avoid a <strong>slippery slope</strong></mark> leading from eugenics <mark>to active extermination of "inferior" groups</mark> in the general population - <mark>can we guarantee</mark> that <mark>everyone will?</mark> How to prevent eugenics from being appropriated by</u> <u>an intrusive,</u> authoritarian, <u>or even murderous state</u>? Modern eugenicists distance themselves from the crude methods adopted at the beginning of the last century by 29 countries, including Germany, The United States, Canada, Switzerland, Austria, Venezuela, Estonia, Argentina, Norway, Denmark, Sweden (until 1976), Brazil, Italy, Greece, and Spain. They talk about free contraceptives for low-IQ women, vasectomies or tubal ligations for criminals, sperm banks with contributions from high achievers, and incentives for college students to procreate. Modern genetic engineering and biotechnology are readily applicable to eugenic projects. Cloning can serve to preserve the genes of the fittest. Embryo selection and prenatal diagnosis of genetically diseased embryos can reduce the number of the unfit. But even these innocuous variants of eugenics fly in the face of liberalism. Inequality, claim the proponents of hereditary amelioration, is genetic, not environmental. All men are created unequal and as much subject to the natural laws of heredity as are cows and bees. Inferior people give birth to inferior offspring and, thus, propagate their inferiority. Even if this were true - which is at best debatable - the question is whether the inferior specimen of our species possess the inalienable right to reproduce? If society is to bear the costs of over-population - social welfare, medical care, daycare centers - then society has the right to regulate procreation. But does it have the right to act discriminately in doing so? Another dilemma is whether we have the moral right - let alone the necessary knowledge - to interfere with natural as well as social and demographic trends. Eugenicists counter that contraception and indiscriminate medicine already do just that. Yet, studies show that the more affluent and educated a population becomes - the less fecund it is. Birth rates throughout the world have dropped dramatically already. Instead of culling the great unwashed and the unworthy - wouldn't it be a better idea to educate them (or their off-spring) and provide them with economic opportunities (euthenics rather than eugenics)? Human populations seem to self-regulate. A gentle and persistent nudge in the right direction - of increased affluence and better schooling - might achieve more than a hundred eugenic programs, voluntary or compulsory. <u>That eugenics presents itself not merely as a biological-social agenda, but as a panacea, ought to arouse suspicion</u>. The typical eugenics text reads more like a catechism than a reasoned argument<u>. <mark>Previous</mark> all-encompassing and omnicompetent <mark>plans tended to end traumatically</mark> - <mark>especially when they contrasted a human elite with</mark> a <mark>dispensable</mark> underclass of <mark>persons</u></mark>. Above all, eugenics is about human hubris. To presume to know better than the lottery of life is haughty.</h4>
Ableism
Impact
2NC K
430,667
1
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,363
Legal sale is popular
Nagro 14
Nagro 14 Jessica Nagro, Health Policy and Management student at NYU Wagner Graduate School of Public Service, She currently serves as the Philanthropy Fellow in the area of Health and People with Special Needs at the New York Community Trust and, before coming to Wagner, worked in political communications and health care policy on Capitol Hill and at Washington DC-based nonprofits. The Wagner Review / December 17, 2014
Compensation for organ donation is also a fairly popular idea in the U.S. An NPR-Thomson Reuters Health Poll conducted in 2012 showed that approximately 60 percent of Americans would support some type of moderate compensation for living organ donors.
Compensation for organ donation is also a fairly popular idea in the U.S. An NPR-Thomson Reuters Health Poll conducted in 2012 showed that approximately 60 percent of Americans would support some type of moderate compensation for living organ donors.
Is it time to start paying for organs?Is it time to start paying for organs? http://www.thewagnerreview.org/2014/12/is-it-time-start-paying-for-organs/ Compensation for organ donation is also a fairly popular idea in the U.S. An NPR-Thomson Reuters Health Poll conducted in 2012 showed that approximately 60 percent of Americans would support some type of moderate compensation for living organ donors. Specifically, 60 percent supported compensation in the form of credits for health care needs and even 41 percent viewed cash payments favorably.
547
<h4>Legal sale is popular</h4><p><strong>Nagro 14 </strong> Jessica Nagro, Health Policy and Management student at NYU Wagner Graduate School of Public Service, She currently serves as the Philanthropy Fellow in the area of Health and People with Special Needs at the New York Community Trust and, before coming to Wagner, worked in political communications and health care policy on Capitol Hill and at Washington DC-based nonprofits. The Wagner Review / December 17, 2014</p><p>Is it time to start paying for organs?Is it time to start paying for organs?</p><p>http://www.thewagnerreview.org/2014/12/is-it-time-start-paying-for-organs/</p><p><u><mark>Compensation for organ donation is also a fairly popular idea in the U.S. An NPR-Thomson Reuters Health Poll conducted in 2012 showed that approximately 60 percent of Americans would support some type of moderate compensation for living organ donors.</u></mark> Specifically, 60 percent supported compensation in the form of credits for health care needs and even 41 percent viewed cash payments favorably.</p>
2AC
Politics DA
TPA – 2AC – NDT
430,668
2
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,364
Seriously those regs were caused by Bernie Madoff – takes out their entire internal link because you can’t screen for just gambling connections
Economist 14
Economist 14 The Economist, 1/11/14, “Know your customer, or else…” http://www.economist.com/blogs/schumpeter/2014/01/jpmorgan-chase-and-madoff-case
A consequence of the Madoff case will be that all banks will need to be far tougher on their clients—and not just crooks America’s Bank Secrecy Act requires reporting anything that could have “a high degree of usefulness in criminal, tax or regulatory investigations Should a checking account mean a bank must know all? The Madoff settlement suggests, strongly, that the answer is yes. say goodbye to financial privacy. There could be other consequences adding armies to monitor transactions and pass them on to regulators Banks will become less like an efficient coffee shop competing with new products and more like airports, with oppressive security
A consequence of the Madoff case will be that all banks will need to be far tougher on their clients—and not just crooks. America requires reporting anything that could have “a high degree of usefulness in criminal, tax or regulatory investigations Should a checking account mean a bank must know all? The Madoff settlement suggests, strongly, that the answer is yes. say goodbye to financial privacy
“JPMORGAN as an institution failed and failed miserably,” said Preet Bharara, New York’s federal attorney, when explaining earlier this week a $1.7 billion settlement in the case of the bank’s failure to detect horrendous fraud of Bernard Madoff (pictured). A more intellectually honest announcement might have included indignation about the various government enforcement agencies which were explicitly and repeatedly warned of Mr Madoff’s scam by, among others, another major bank—and then utterly blew inspections without any individual or entity facing censure. A consequence of the Madoff case will be that all banks will need to be far tougher on their clients—and not just crooks. The 40 plus pages released along with the settlement do not make for easy reading, but the government’s case is built around two components. One is the relationship of Mr Madoff with JPMorgan Chase’s investment office in London. At times it invested with Mr Madoff through “feeder” funds, but never directly. It ultimately developed concerns about how these generated returns, and alerted British authorities. Less well known, JPMorgan’s primary relationship with Mr Madoff in America was two large checking accounts. Which raises the question whether, because of these checking accounts, JPMorgan had an obligation to alert American authorities as well? In agreeing to the settlement, JPMorgan has said it should have—though it was not in a position to argue (the simple issuance of a criminal indictment would have been devastating, regardless of whether it succeeded in court). The government’s case rests on the notion that America’s Bank Secrecy Act requires reporting anything that could have “a high degree of usefulness in criminal, tax or regulatory investigations.” Given the expansiveness of America’s laws, that could be almost anything. The government’s information document cites the report sent to British authorities, which says that “the investment performance achieved…appear to be too good to be true—meaning that it probably is.” If that is the standard, American regulatory agencies should be prepared for an electronic tsunami of alerts. There is, apparently, no penalty for over-reporting. The government statement is scathing about JPMorgan’s misunderstanding of Mr Madoff’s business. Banks are required to know their customers, but to what extent? Successful investment-management firms are often secretive about their approach, and rightly so: it is, after all, their secret sauce. Most businesses are complex. Should a checking account in America mean a company must spill all, or even that a bank must know all? The Madoff settlement suggests, strongly, that the answer is yes. So say goodbye to financial privacy. The government will see all. There could be lots of other consequences. Beyond adding armies to monitor transactions and pass them on to regulators, banks will start firing clients because they happen to do business in newly suspect categories. The reasons may not be explained. They may not even be understood by the bank employee relaying the news to the fired customer. Among them will be pursuing business activities abroad in places thought to have activities that violate American law. Or it could be because of a relationship with a politician (making a bank liable to accusations of politically-induced lending) or because of employment with a government of a country that is accused of money laundering. The Madoff settlement will be just one reason for this worrying trend, but it is an important one. The payment of a $1.7 billion for having a toxic client will mean the imposition of rules everywhere. And because they are rules, they won’t merely cover toxic clients. For non-crooks, these will seem arbitrary. Banks will become less like an efficient coffee shop competing with new products and more like airports, with oppressive security. The Madoff settlement may not be JPMorgan’s biggest, but it will have large implications—and not just for the bank. We will all pay.
4,019
<h4>Seriously those regs were caused by Bernie Madoff – takes out their entire internal link because you can’t screen for just gambling connections</h4><p><strong>Economist 14</strong> The Economist, 1/11/14, “Know your customer, or else…” http://www.economist.com/blogs/schumpeter/2014/01/jpmorgan-chase-and-madoff-case</p><p>“JPMORGAN as an institution failed and failed miserably,” said Preet Bharara, New York’s federal attorney, when explaining earlier this week a $1.7 billion settlement in the case of the bank’s failure to detect horrendous fraud of Bernard Madoff (pictured). A more intellectually honest announcement might have included indignation about the various government enforcement agencies which were explicitly and repeatedly warned of Mr Madoff’s scam by, among others, another major bank—and then utterly blew inspections without any individual or entity facing censure. <u><mark>A consequence of the Madoff case will be that all banks will need to be far tougher on their clients—and not just crooks</u>.</mark> The 40 plus pages released along with the settlement do not make for easy reading, but the government’s case is built around two components. One is the relationship of Mr Madoff with JPMorgan Chase’s investment office in London. At times it invested with Mr Madoff through “feeder” funds, but never directly. It ultimately developed concerns about how these generated returns, and alerted British authorities. Less well known, JPMorgan’s primary relationship with Mr Madoff in America was two large checking accounts. Which raises the question whether, because of these checking accounts, JPMorgan had an obligation to alert American authorities as well? In agreeing to the settlement, JPMorgan has said it should have—though it was not in a position to argue (the simple issuance of a criminal indictment would have been devastating, regardless of whether it succeeded in court). The government’s case rests on the notion that <u><mark>America</mark>’s Bank Secrecy Act <mark>requires reporting anything that could have “a high degree of usefulness in criminal, tax or regulatory investigations</u></mark>.” Given the expansiveness of America’s laws, that could be almost anything. The government’s information document cites the report sent to British authorities, which says that “the investment performance achieved…appear to be too good to be true—meaning that it probably is.” If that is the standard, American regulatory agencies should be prepared for an electronic tsunami of alerts. There is, apparently, no penalty for over-reporting. The government statement is scathing about JPMorgan’s misunderstanding of Mr Madoff’s business. Banks are required to know their customers, but to what extent? Successful investment-management firms are often secretive about their approach, and rightly so: it is, after all, their secret sauce. Most businesses are complex. <u><mark>Should a checking account</u></mark> in America <u><mark>mean</u></mark> a company must spill all, or even that <u><mark>a bank must know all? The Madoff settlement suggests, strongly, that the answer is yes.</u></mark> So <u><mark>say goodbye to financial privacy</mark>.</u> The government will see all. <u>There could be</u> lots of <u>other consequences</u>. Beyond <u>adding armies to monitor transactions and pass them on to regulators</u>, banks will start firing clients because they happen to do business in newly suspect categories. The reasons may not be explained. They may not even be understood by the bank employee relaying the news to the fired customer. Among them will be pursuing business activities abroad in places thought to have activities that violate American law. Or it could be because of a relationship with a politician (making a bank liable to accusations of politically-induced lending) or because of employment with a government of a country that is accused of money laundering. The Madoff settlement will be just one reason for this worrying trend, but it is an important one. The payment of a $1.7 billion for having a toxic client will mean the imposition of rules everywhere. And because they are rules, they won’t merely cover toxic clients. For non-crooks, these will seem arbitrary. <u>Banks will become less like an efficient coffee shop competing with new products and more like airports, with oppressive security</u>. The Madoff settlement may not be JPMorgan’s biggest, but it will have large implications—and not just for the bank. We will all pay.</p>
WTO
Banks
AT: Inevitable
430,040
3
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,365
Legalized online gambling causes proliferation of terrorist money laundering, causing catastrophic terrorism – only prohibition solves
Thackston 14 http://www.tampabay.com/opinion/columns/column-online-gambling-is-a-strategic-national-threat/2151317
Thackston 14, James Thackston, is a Florida-based independent software engineer with a background in the aerospace, manufacturing and energy industries. Earl L. Grinols is distinguished professor of economics at Baylor University, former senior economist for the President's Council of Economic Advisers, and author of "Gambling In America: Costs and Benefits.", http://www.tampabay.com/opinion/columns/column-online-gambling-is-a-strategic-national-threat/2151317
Remote gambling is fundamentally different from brick-and-mortar casino gambling Using tech undetectable to operators and regulators, House Commerce Committee witnessed a demonstration in which a single remote computer took control of two computers and used them as alias machines to play poker online. The demonstration showed tech and techniques terror and crime use to operate untraceable money laundering built on a highly liquid legalized online poker industry — just the environment that will result from the spread of poker online A drug cartel could arrange for buyers' machines to be remotely linked and lose to the aliased cartel machines. Drug buyers would not even need to play from their own machines. Illegal drug money would appear to be legal online winnings. A single poker game takes just a few hours to transfer $5 million An established al-Qaida poker network could extract from the U S enough untraceable money in six days to fund an operation like 9/11 The threat is real gambling regulations are no match for determined terrorists and criminals it is possible to make money laundering undetectable. Gambling should be firmly restricted to stay offline.
Remote gambling Using tech undetectable to regulators a demonstration a single remote computer took control of computers and used them to play poker The demo showed tech terror and crime use to operate untraceable laundering built on a highly liquid legalized online poker industry — just the environment that will result from spread of poker online. An established al-Qaida poker network could extract enough untraceable money in six days to fund 9/11 gambling regulations are no match for determined terrorists and criminals, it is possible to make money laundering undetectable. Gambling should be firmly restricted to stay offline.
Remote gambling is fundamentally different from brick-and-mortar casino gambling because the website operator never has complete control. Using technology undetectable to website operators and their regulators, it is possible for gamblers to play games from physical locations that are not what they seem. We know, because we have done it. Recently, House Energy and Commerce Committee staff and others in the Capitol Hill office of U.S. Rep. Gregg Harper, R-Miss., witnessed a demonstration in which a single remote computer took control of two computers and used them as alias machines to play poker online. The Harper demonstration showed the technology and techniques that terror and crime organizations could use to operate untraceable money laundering built on a highly liquid legalized online poker industry — just the environment that will result from the spread of poker online. One of us set up a website — undetectablelaundering.com — to help communicate the problem to a broader audience. No one should doubt the ability of criminals to exploit the inherent weakness in online gambling. A drug cartel could arrange for buyers' machines to be remotely linked and lose to the aliased cartel machines. Drug buyers would not even need to play from their own machines. Illegal drug money would appear to be legal online winnings. A single poker game takes just a few hours to transfer $5 million as was recently demonstrated — legally — by American player Brian Hastings with his Swedish competitor half a world away. An established al-Qaida poker network could extract from the United States enough untraceable money in six days to fund an operation like the 9/11 attack on the World Trade Center. The threat is real. Last month a Texas lawyer was found guilty of trying to launder $600 million in drug money for a Mexican cartel. Caesar's Entertainment is currently under investigation by the Justice Department and IRS, accused of money laundering and Bank Secrecy Act violations. In December 2012, the FBI's Tampa field office asked us to take down the website explaining the threat. We complied. This May, special agents at FBI headquarters in Washington responsible for enforcing the Wire Act and all other federal gambling laws were briefed on the vulnerability. In July, a Senate Commerce Committee hearing seemed to reinforce concerns. Rep. C.W. Bill Young wrote a letter of concern to FBI director Robert Mueller on Aug. 7. But since then action seems to have stalled. And the threat moves on. With the passing of Young, we have put the website back up and joined together in hopes of spurring action. Since it remains true that gambling regulations in Nevada, Delaware and New Jersey are no match for determined terrorists and criminals, we feel duty-bound as responsible citizens to ensure knowledge of the threat reaches as many policymakers as possible. We have proved it is possible to make money laundering undetectable. Gambling should be firmly restricted to stay offline.
2,997
<h4><strong>Legalized online gambling causes <u>proliferation</u> of <u>terrorist money laundering</u>, causing <u>catastrophic terrorism</u> – only prohibition solves</h4><p>Thackston 14</strong>, James Thackston, is a Florida-based independent software engineer with a background in the aerospace, manufacturing and energy industries. Earl L. Grinols is distinguished professor of economics at Baylor University, former senior economist for the President's Council of Economic Advisers, and author of "Gambling In America: Costs and Benefits.",<u><strong> http://www.tampabay.com/opinion/columns/column-online-gambling-is-a-strategic-national-threat/2151317</p><p><mark>Remote gambling</mark> is fundamentally different from brick-and-mortar casino gambling</u></strong> because the website operator never has complete control. <u><strong><mark>Using tech</u></strong></mark>nology <u><strong><mark>undetectable to</u></strong></mark> website <u><strong>operators and</u></strong> their <u><strong><mark>regulators</mark>,</u></strong> it is possible for gamblers to play games from physical locations that are not what they seem. We know, because we have done it. Recently, <u><strong>House</u></strong> Energy and <u><strong>Commerce Committee</u></strong> staff and others in the Capitol Hill office of U.S. Rep. Gregg Harper, R-Miss., <u><strong>witnessed <mark>a demonstration </mark>in which <mark>a single remote computer took control of </mark>two <mark>computers and used them</mark> as alias machines <mark>to play poker </mark>online. <mark>The</u></strong></mark> Harper <u><strong><mark>demo</mark>nstration <mark>showed</u></strong></mark> the <u><strong><mark>tech</u></strong></mark>nology <u><strong>and techniques</u></strong> that <u><strong><mark>terror and crime</u></strong></mark> organizations could <u><strong><mark>use to operate untraceable</mark> money <mark>laundering built on a highly liquid legalized online poker industry — just the environment that will result from</mark> the <mark>spread of poker online</u></strong>.</mark> One of us set up a website — undetectablelaundering.com — to help communicate the problem to a broader audience. No one should doubt the ability of criminals to exploit the inherent weakness in online gambling. <u><strong>A drug cartel could arrange for buyers' machines to be remotely linked and lose to the aliased cartel machines. Drug buyers would not even need to play from their own machines. Illegal drug money would appear to be legal online winnings. A single poker game takes just a few hours to transfer $5 million </u></strong>as was recently demonstrated — legally — by American player Brian Hastings with his Swedish competitor half a world away. <u><strong><mark>An established al-Qaida poker network could extract</mark> from the U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u><strong><mark>enough untraceable money in six days to fund</mark> an operation like </u></strong>the <u><strong><mark>9/11</mark> </u></strong>attack on the World Trade Center. <u><strong>The threat is real</u></strong>. Last month a Texas lawyer was found guilty of trying to launder $600 million in drug money for a Mexican cartel. Caesar's Entertainment is currently under investigation by the Justice Department and IRS, accused of money laundering and Bank Secrecy Act violations. In December 2012, the FBI's Tampa field office asked us to take down the website explaining the threat. We complied. This May, special agents at FBI headquarters in Washington responsible for enforcing the Wire Act and all other federal gambling laws were briefed on the vulnerability. In July, a Senate Commerce Committee hearing seemed to reinforce concerns. Rep. C.W. Bill Young wrote a letter of concern to FBI director Robert Mueller on Aug. 7. But since then action seems to have stalled. And the threat moves on. With the passing of Young, we have put the website back up and joined together in hopes of spurring action. Since it remains true that <u><strong><mark>gambling regulations</mark> </u></strong>in Nevada, Delaware and New Jersey <u><strong><mark>are no match for determined terrorists and criminals</u></strong>,</mark> we feel duty-bound as responsible citizens to ensure knowledge of the threat reaches as many policymakers as possible. We have proved <u><strong><mark>it is possible to make money laundering undetectable. Gambling should be firmly restricted to stay offline.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
Costa Rica
429,685
23
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,366
Their social movement is stupid and useless
Hauhart 2011
Hauhart 2011 (Robert, Saint Martin’s University, Contemporary Sociology40.5 (Sep 2011): 557-559, proquest)
Alexander shies away from proposing a potentially successful strategy for redressing the dilemma she depicts Alexander offers conversation starters Alexander suggests we talk explicitly about race Alexander questions the success of the strategy to infiltrate elite institutions In lieu of traditional approaches Alexander offers little but platitudes and clichés she suggests that blacks and whites must lay down racial bribes join hands as sociologists everywhere recognize, to make a job "everyone's" responsibility is to make it "no one's" responsibility without irony, Alexander advises us that, "All of this is easier said than done her call upon the civil rights community to re-frame itself and get to work is not a call to arms but an invitation to snore Alexander's review evades the hard work of developing a potentially effective strategy for mobilizing progressive social action that is required.
null
In The New Jim Crow, civil rights lawyer and Ohio State University law professor Michelle Alexander examines the legal and social framework that supports the regime of mass incarceration of black men in the United States. As Alexander carefully recounts, beginning in the early 1980s with President Reagan's declaration of a "War on Drugs," a number of poticy initiatives, Supreme Court decisions, and vested interests, aided and abetted by political divisiveness and pubtic apathy, coalesced to create the social, legal, and political environment that has supported mass incarceration ever since. Alexander's analysis reveals disturbing parallels between the racial caste systems of slavery, Jim Crow, and today's mass incarceration of black men in our country. In the end, however, Alexander shies away from proposing a potentially successful strategy for redressing the dilemma she so carefully depicts. Rather, she "punts," or "cops out," as we would have said in earlier eras. Alexander begins her analysis with a brief history of the several hundred years of variously oppressive race relations between whites and blacks in the United States. Quite correctly, Alexander observes that this history may be f ruitfully understood as a sequence of renascent forms of social control refashioned to the new tenor of the times. Thus, Alexander traces the history of American political rhetoric in the latter hati of the twentieth century where "law and order" comes to constitute code for "the race problem" and a policy of matign neglect toward African Americans is transmuted into an active political strategy devised to develop Republican political dominance in the southern states. Ultimately, as we know, the twin themes of crime and welfare propelled Ronald Reagan into the presidency. Searching for a f ollow-up initiative to define his early presidency, Reagan settled on increased attention to street crune, especially drug law enforcement. In short, the War on Drugs was not some disembodied social agenda, nor was it driven by public demand, as only two percent of Americans believed crime was an important issue at the time. Rather, as Alexander shows, the War on Drugs was a direct outgrowth of race-based politics and therefore the fact that it has had a disproportionate impact on young black men should come as no surprise. Alexander next turns her attention to the interwoven details of the social, legal, and political fabric that wrap the War on Drugs in supportive garb. As Alexander recites, the War on Drugs is the cornerstone on which the current regime of race-based mass incarceration rests because: (a) convictions for drug offenses are the single most important cause of the explosion in incarceration rates since 1980, and (b) black Americans are disproportionately arrested, convicted, and subjected to lengthy sentences for drug offenses when compared to white Americans, even though drug use rates among white Americans have been consistently shown to be higher than for black Americans. Thus, any practices or policies that support the execution of the War on Drugs support the continuation of our movement toward mass incarceration of an entire category of Americans. Among the many developments Alexander reviews, one may note: changes in Supreme Court doctrine with respect to police stops, warrantless searches, consent searches, and suspicionless potice sweeps for drug activity; federal initiatives to offer grants to support narcotics task forces; the development and expansion of modern drug forfeiture laws which permitted state and local law enforcement agencies to keep the vast majority of seized cash and assets in drug raids; and the legislative enactment of mandatory minimum and "three strikes" sentencing schemes, and their ready acceptance by the Supreme Court. Alexander is at her masterful best when elucidating in concise form the emergence of each of these trends and their consequent impact on increased arrest, conviction, and incarceration for primarily young black men over the last thirty years. She is, of course, quite correct to be indignant about the fact that the Supreme Court upheld a sentence of forty years imprisonment for possession and an attempt to sell nine ounces of marijuana in 1982 (Hutto v. Davis, 454 U.S. 370). Moreover, as Alexander further explains, the debilitating impact of our country's War on Drugs does not end once a person convicted for a drug offense serves his or her sentence. Rather, an increasingly long and punitive Hst of collateral consequences now extends a person's assignment to second-class status nearly permanently. Thus, offenders may be ineligible (for Hfe) for federally-funded health and welfare benefits, food stamps, public housing, and federal educational assistance; denied admission and licensure to many forms of employment and professional occupations; denied the ability to enlist in the military, purchase a firearm, obtain a federal security clearance, and restricted from voting. The result, as Alexander compellingly depicts, is not that drug law offenders face "problems of reentry into society" as the current rhetoric of criminal justice exhorts, but rather that convicted offenders are "boxed in" (by having to admit their conviction on forms) and thereby forced out, often permanently, from many legitimate relationships with society. Alexander's analysis of these developments is pithy and nearly flawless. She falters occasionally, however, when she attempts to place some of these events in a political context and chart the political landscape that will need to emerge to put an end to The New Jim Crow. Alexander begins her final chapter by discussing what she calls the "relative quiet" of the civil rights community in the face of the mass incarceration of the people of color she describes. She wonders - given the magnitude and unfairness of the present system - why the War on Drugs has not become ". . .the top priority of every civil rights organization in the country" (p. 212). In answering her own question, Alexander notes that subsequent to Brown v. Board of Education in 1954 civil rights organizations became increasingly professionalized -primarily by lawyers. Consequently, many of the civil rights issues were framed in legal terms, pursued in the legal arena, and reduced to legally achievable solutions. By doing so, Alexander believes that the civil rights advocacy groups disconnected themselves from the community and relinquished the grassroots source of their moral strength. They also foreswore the goal of actively mobilizing public opinion against the oppressive laws and social conditions they deplored. In the end, Alexander offers a number of what she calls "conversation starters." First, she states unequivocally that "tinkering" with the present arrangements will not likely achieve notable results; rather, she believes we must end the War on Drugs. Second, in doing so, Alexander suggests we must talk explicitly about race and oppose the tendency to obfuscate the situation with a retreat into denial behind the official veil of colorblindness. Third, Alexander suggests that it may be time for civil rights groups to step away from affirmative action because of its tendency to shield the racial caste system from scrutiny and redress. Finally, Alexander questions the success of the African American strategy to infiltrate elite institutions, including President Obama's ascendance to the presidency, and thereby let civil rights "trickle down" to the mass of the black community. In lieu of these traditional approaches, unfortunately, Alexander offers little but platitudes, wishful bromides, and clichés. Thus, for example, she suggests that ". . . . [blacks and whites alike] must lay down our racial bribes, join hands with people of all colors who are not content to wait for change to trickle down, and say to those who would stand in our way: Accept all of us or none" (p. 245). However, as sociologists everywhere recognize, to make a job "everyone's" responsibility is to make it "no one's" responsibility. Apparently without irony, Alexander also soberly advises us that, "All of this is easier said than done" (p. 247). For a lawyer who has retreated from the entrenched fray of overturning the Supreme Court's precedents on sentencing, which she abhors, her call upon the civil rights community to re-frame itself and get to work is not a call to arms but an invitation to snore. In sum, like many other indignant analyses of the highly objectionable War on Drugs offered over the last thirty years, Alexander's superb historical and legal review evades the hard work of developing a potentially effective strategy for mobilizing progressive social action that is required.
8,753
<h4><strong>Their social movement is stupid and useless</h4><p>Hauhart 2011</strong> (Robert, Saint Martin’s University, Contemporary Sociology40.5 (Sep 2011): 557-559, proquest)</p><p>In The New Jim Crow, civil rights lawyer and Ohio State University law professor Michelle Alexander examines the legal and social framework that supports the regime of mass incarceration of black men in the United States. As Alexander carefully recounts, beginning in the early 1980s with President Reagan's declaration of a "War on Drugs," a number of poticy initiatives, Supreme Court decisions, and vested interests, aided and abetted by political divisiveness and pubtic apathy, coalesced to create the social, legal, and political environment that has supported mass incarceration ever since. Alexander's analysis reveals disturbing parallels between the racial caste systems of slavery, Jim Crow, and today's mass incarceration of black men in our country. In the end, however, <u>Alexander shies away from proposing a potentially successful strategy for redressing</u> <u>the dilemma she</u> so carefully <u>depicts</u>. Rather, she "punts," or "cops out," as we would have said in earlier eras. Alexander begins her analysis with a brief history of the several hundred years of variously oppressive race relations between whites and blacks in the United States. Quite correctly, Alexander observes that this history may be f ruitfully understood as a sequence of renascent forms of social control refashioned to the new tenor of the times. Thus, Alexander traces the history of American political rhetoric in the latter hati of the twentieth century where "law and order" comes to constitute code for "the race problem" and a policy of matign neglect toward African Americans is transmuted into an active political strategy devised to develop Republican political dominance in the southern states. Ultimately, as we know, the twin themes of crime and welfare propelled Ronald Reagan into the presidency. Searching for a f ollow-up initiative to define his early presidency, Reagan settled on increased attention to street crune, especially drug law enforcement. In short, the War on Drugs was not some disembodied social agenda, nor was it driven by public demand, as only two percent of Americans believed crime was an important issue at the time. Rather, as Alexander shows, the War on Drugs was a direct outgrowth of race-based politics and therefore the fact that it has had a disproportionate impact on young black men should come as no surprise. Alexander next turns her attention to the interwoven details of the social, legal, and political fabric that wrap the War on Drugs in supportive garb. As Alexander recites, the War on Drugs is the cornerstone on which the current regime of race-based mass incarceration rests because: (a) convictions for drug offenses are the single most important cause of the explosion in incarceration rates since 1980, and (b) black Americans are disproportionately arrested, convicted, and subjected to lengthy sentences for drug offenses when compared to white Americans, even though drug use rates among white Americans have been consistently shown to be higher than for black Americans. Thus, any practices or policies that support the execution of the War on Drugs support the continuation of our movement toward mass incarceration of an entire category of Americans. Among the many developments Alexander reviews, one may note: changes in Supreme Court doctrine with respect to police stops, warrantless searches, consent searches, and suspicionless potice sweeps for drug activity; federal initiatives to offer grants to support narcotics task forces; the development and expansion of modern drug forfeiture laws which permitted state and local law enforcement agencies to keep the vast majority of seized cash and assets in drug raids; and the legislative enactment of mandatory minimum and "three strikes" sentencing schemes, and their ready acceptance by the Supreme Court. Alexander is at her masterful best when elucidating in concise form the emergence of each of these trends and their consequent impact on increased arrest, conviction, and incarceration for primarily young black men over the last thirty years. She is, of course, quite correct to be indignant about the fact that the Supreme Court upheld a sentence of forty years imprisonment for possession and an attempt to sell nine ounces of marijuana in 1982 (Hutto v. Davis, 454 U.S. 370). Moreover, as Alexander further explains, the debilitating impact of our country's War on Drugs does not end once a person convicted for a drug offense serves his or her sentence. Rather, an increasingly long and punitive Hst of collateral consequences now extends a person's assignment to second-class status nearly permanently. Thus, offenders may be ineligible (for Hfe) for federally-funded health and welfare benefits, food stamps, public housing, and federal educational assistance; denied admission and licensure to many forms of employment and professional occupations; denied the ability to enlist in the military, purchase a firearm, obtain a federal security clearance, and restricted from voting. The result, as Alexander compellingly depicts, is not that drug law offenders face "problems of reentry into society" as the current rhetoric of criminal justice exhorts, but rather that convicted offenders are "boxed in" (by having to admit their conviction on forms) and thereby forced out, often permanently, from many legitimate relationships with society. Alexander's analysis of these developments is pithy and nearly flawless. She falters occasionally, however, when she attempts to place some of these events in a political context and chart the political landscape that will need to emerge to put an end to The New Jim Crow. Alexander begins her final chapter by discussing what she calls the "relative quiet" of the civil rights community in the face of the mass incarceration of the people of color she describes. She wonders - given the magnitude and unfairness of the present system - why the War on Drugs has not become ". . .the top priority of every civil rights organization in the country" (p. 212). In answering her own question, Alexander notes that subsequent to Brown v. Board of Education in 1954 civil rights organizations became increasingly professionalized -primarily by lawyers. Consequently, many of the civil rights issues were framed in legal terms, pursued in the legal arena, and reduced to legally achievable solutions. By doing so, Alexander believes that the civil rights advocacy groups disconnected themselves from the community and relinquished the grassroots source of their moral strength. They also foreswore the goal of actively mobilizing public opinion against the oppressive laws and social conditions they deplored. In the end, <u>Alexander offers</u> a number of what she calls "<u>conversation starters</u>." First, she states unequivocally that "tinkering" with the present arrangements will not likely achieve notable results; rather, she believes we must end the War on Drugs. Second, in doing so, <u>Alexander suggests we</u> must <u>talk</u> <u>explicitly about race</u> and oppose the tendency to obfuscate the situation with a retreat into denial behind the official veil of colorblindness. Third, Alexander suggests that it may be time for civil rights groups to step away from affirmative action because of its tendency to shield the racial caste system from scrutiny and redress. Finally, <u>Alexander questions the success of</u> <u>the</u> African American <u>strategy to infiltrate elite institutions</u>, including President Obama's ascendance to the presidency, and thereby let civil rights "trickle down" to the mass of the black community. <u>In lieu of</u> these <u>traditional approaches</u>, unfortunately, <u>Alexander offers little but platitudes</u>, wishful bromides, <u>and clichés</u>. Thus, for example, <u>she suggests that</u> ". . . . [<u>blacks and whites</u> alike] <u>must lay down</u> our <u>racial bribes</u>, <u>join hands</u> with people of all colors who are not content to wait for change to trickle down, and say to those who would stand in our way: Accept all of us or none" (p. 245). However, <u>as sociologists everywhere recognize, to make a job "everyone's" responsibility is to make it "no one's" responsibility</u>. Apparently <u>without irony, Alexander</u> also soberly <u>advises us that, "All of this is easier said than done</u>" (p. 247). For a lawyer who has retreated from the entrenched fray of overturning the Supreme Court's precedents on sentencing, which she abhors, <u>her call upon the civil rights community to re-frame itself and get to work is not a call to arms but an invitation to snore</u>. In sum, like many other indignant analyses of the highly objectionable War on Drugs offered over the last thirty years, <u>Alexander's</u> superb historical and legal <u>review evades the hard work of developing a potentially effective strategy for mobilizing progressive social action that is required<strong>.</p></u></strong>
null
null
Solvency
430,669
3
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,367
This would maximize organ sales
Erin and Harris 3
Erin and Harris 3 Charles A Erin and John Harris, Institute of Medicine, Law and Bioethics, School of Law, University of Manchester J Med Ethics 2003; 29 :141 Janet Radcliffe Richards on our modest proposal http://jme.bmj.com/content/29/3/138.full.pdf+html
We have proposed a scheme that would maximise organ sales by meeting the most common and persistent objections to commerce in body parts.
We have proposed a scheme that would maximise organ sales by meeting the most common and persistent objections to commerce in body parts
Thus when Radcliffe Richards says: “Of course there is something undesirable about a one way international traffic from poor to rich; but that is not enough to settle the all things considered question of whether it should be allowed” she is again right. It is not enough to settle that question. Our paper was not trying to settle that question. 2 We have proposed a scheme that would maximise organ sales by meeting the most common and persistent objections to commerce in body parts. In our paper we note that:“In 1994, we made a proposal in which we outlined possibly the only circumstances in which a market in donor organs could be achieved ethically, and in a way that minimises the dangers normally envisaged for such a scheme” and this is the proposal that we repeat in abbreviated form. The claim we make, which it seems Radcliffe Richards judges tobe too strong, is that our proposal outlines “possibly the only circumstances in which a market in donor organs could be achieved ethically”; but note that there is a qualification to this claim, namely that if the first part of our claim is true it is so because it defends organ sales “in a way that minimises the dangers normally envisaged for such a scheme”. It may be that organ sales could be defended (possibly by Janet Radcliffe Richards and for that matter by the present authors) in a way that does not minimise such dangers. But that is not what we were trying to do in our paper.
1,450
<h4>This <strong>would maximize organ sales</h4><p>Erin and Harris 3 </strong>Charles A Erin and John Harris, Institute of Medicine, Law and Bioethics, School of Law, University of Manchester J Med Ethics 2003; 29 :141<strong> </strong>Janet Radcliffe Richards on our modest<strong> </strong>proposal</p><p>http://jme.bmj.com/content/29/3/138.full.pdf+html</p><p>Thus when Radcliffe Richards says: “Of course there is something undesirable about a one way international traffic from poor to rich; but that is not enough to settle the all things considered question of whether it should be allowed” she is again right. It is not enough to settle that question. Our paper was not trying to settle that question. 2 <u><mark>We have proposed a scheme that would <strong>maximise organ sales</strong> by meeting the most common and persistent objections to commerce in body parts</mark>.</u> In our paper we note that:“In 1994, we made a proposal in which we outlined possibly the only circumstances in which a market in donor organs could be achieved ethically, and in a way that minimises the dangers normally envisaged for such a scheme” and this is the proposal that we repeat in abbreviated form. The claim we make, which it seems Radcliffe Richards judges tobe too strong, is that our proposal outlines “possibly the only circumstances in which a market in donor organs could be achieved ethically”; but note that there is a qualification to this claim, namely that if the first part of our claim is true it is so because it defends organ sales “in a way that minimises the dangers normally envisaged for such a scheme”. It may be that organ sales could be defended (possibly by Janet Radcliffe Richards and for that matter by the present authors) in a way that does not minimise such dangers. But that is not what we were trying to do in our paper.</p>
null
null
Contention 3 The Plan solves
430,338
11
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,368
Our Middle East scholarship is good
Halliday 93
Halliday 93 Fred Halliday, IR at LSE, 93, “ ‘Orientalism’ and its Critics” British Journal of Middle Eastern Studies 20(2) pp.145-146
social science never be completed, and each specific issue, or country poses questions for it we are no more precluded from understanding the Middle East than in addressing any other area of the world we have allowed the discussion to be too inffected by relativism in the face of a often self-interested, critique of imperialism and Western norms neither westoxification nor eastoxification Let us go beyond this unnecessarily polarized and methodologically impoverished debate and continue studying these societies
social science will never be complete each specific issue poses questions we are no more precluded from understanding the Middle East than in addressing any other area we have, allowed the discussion to be too inffected by relativism in the face of a interested, critique of Western norms Let u go beyond this polarized and methodologically impoverished debate
The Middle East is not unique, except possibly in the content of the myths that are propagated about it, from within and without. The political, economic, social and cultural activities of the peoples of this region have their peculiarities and differences, as much between each other , as in terms of one Middle East contrasted with the outside world. Material concerns, jokes, the pleasures of good food, and the horrors of political oppression, are theirs as much as any other peoples in the world. The development of social science in general will never be completed, and each specific issue, or country, or incident, poses questions for it. But we are no more precluded by our concepts from understanding the Middle East, and no more limited in our ideas, whatever their origins, than in addressing any other area of the world. In normative terms, we have, perhaps, allowed the discussion to be too inffected by relativism and doubt as to the validity of universal standards, in the face of a mistaken, and often self-interested, critique of imperialism and Western norms. Perhaps I could sum this up by adapting a slogan: na gharbzadegi, na sharqzadegi, neither westoxification nor eastoxification. Let us therefore go beyond this unnecessarily polarized and in some ways methodologically impoverished debate and continue with the job of studying these societies. I have warned against the perils of tafsir, but I will end with the words from the Qur’an that can be easily and I hope not too arbitrarily interpreted to justify this enterprise, wa ja’alnakum shu’uban wa-qaba’ila li-ta’arafu. ‘And I have created peoples and trives so that they could get to know each other.’42 That could be the motto for our necessarily unfinished, and unfinishable, endavour.
1,766
<h4><strong>Our Middle East scholarship is good</h4><p>Halliday 93</p><p></strong>Fred Halliday, IR at LSE, 93, “ ‘Orientalism’ and its Critics” British Journal of Middle Eastern Studies 20(2) pp.145-146</p><p>The Middle East is not unique, except possibly in the content of the myths that are propagated about it, from within and without. The political, economic, social and cultural activities of the peoples of this region have their peculiarities and differences, as much between each other , as in terms of one Middle East contrasted with the outside world. Material concerns, jokes, the pleasures of good food, and the horrors of political oppression, are theirs as much as any other peoples in the world. The development of <u><mark>social science</u></mark> in general <mark>will <u>never be complete</mark>d, and <mark>each specific issue</mark>, or country</u>, or incident, <u><mark>poses</mark> <mark>questions</mark> for it</u>. But <u><mark>we are no more precluded</u></mark> by our concepts <u><mark>from understanding the Middle East</u></mark>, and no more limited in our ideas, whatever their origins, <u><mark>than in addressing any other area</mark> of the world</u>. In normative terms, <u><mark>we have</u>,</mark> perhaps, <u><mark>allowed the discussion to be too inffected by relativism</u></mark> and doubt as to the validity of universal standards, <u><mark>in the face of a</u></mark> mistaken, and <u>often self-<mark>interested, critique of</mark> imperialism and <mark>Western norms</u></mark>. Perhaps I could sum this up by adapting a slogan: na gharbzadegi, na sharqzadegi, <u>neither westoxification nor eastoxification</u>. <u><mark>Let u</mark>s</u> therefore <u><mark>go beyond this</mark> unnecessarily <mark>polarized and</u></mark> in some ways <u><mark>methodologically impoverished debate</mark> and continue</u> with the job of <u>studying these societies</u>. I have warned against the perils of tafsir, but I will end with the words from the Qur’an that can be easily and I hope not too arbitrarily interpreted to justify this enterprise, wa ja’alnakum shu’uban wa-qaba’ila li-ta’arafu. ‘And I have created peoples and trives so that they could get to know each other.’42 That could be the motto for our necessarily unfinished, and unfinishable, endavour.</p>
null
null
O/V
430,670
1
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,369
Deval from PAS is worse that deval from lack of autonomy—
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Deval from PAS is worse that deval from lack of autonomy—</h4>
Ableism
A2: Autonomy
2NC K
430,671
1
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,370
No internal link – zero evidence that organs causes swing senators to vote switch
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>No internal link – zero evidence that organs causes swing senators to vote switch</h4>
2AC
Politics DA
TPA – 2AC – NDT
430,672
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,371
Economic decline doesn’t cause war. The Great Recession proves leaders turn to trade and institutional cooperation, not armies. Prefer Jervis – professor writing in a peer-reviewed study.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Economic decline doesn’t cause war. The Great Recession proves leaders turn to trade and institutional cooperation, not armies. Prefer Jervis – professor writing in a peer-reviewed study.</h4>
WTO
War
AT: Inevitable
430,673
1
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,372
Plan doesn’t solve laundering
Fiedler 13
Fiedler 13 – Post Doc Researcher at the Division on Gambling at the Institute of Law & Economics, University of Hamburg
All forms of money laundering in online gambling involve unregulated or illegal operators as they do not have to oblige to anti-money laundering directives but can hide in regulatory havens The obvious way to tackle money laundering in unregulated/illegal online gambling is to introduce legal markets. But this is far from sufficient. Legal operators are far less attractive to customers due to lower payout ratios which result from taxes and fees the operators have to pay. Even in regulated markets like France the illegal operators still play an important role. The reason is a lack of law enforcement against unregulated/illegal operators the first and most important step in tackling money laundering in online gaming is to enforce the law against illegal/unregulated operators.
All forms of money laundering in online gambling involve unregulated or illegal operators as they can hide in regulatory havens The obvious way to tackle money laundering is to introduce legal markets. But this is far from sufficient. Legal operators are far less attractive to customers due to lower payout ratios Even in regulated markets like France the illegal operators still play an important role. The reason is a lack of law enforcement against unregulated operators the most important step is to enforce the law against illegal/unregulated operators
Ingo, Online Gambling as a Game Changer to Money Laundering?, 4/30/13, http://www.wiso.uni-hamburg.de/fileadmin/bwl/rechtderwirtschaft/institut/Ingo_Fiedler/Online_Gambling_as_a_Game_Changer_to_Money_Laundering_01.pdf All forms of money laundering in online gambling involve unregulated or illegal operators as they do not have to oblige to anti-money laundering directives but can hide in regulatory havens. Legal operators, in contrast, are not prone to money laundering (Brooks 2012), especially because of the much lower payout ratios. However, the online gambling market is still dominated by illegal operators; legal ones play only a minor role. This leaves penty of opportunities of money laundering.¶ The obvious way to tackle money laundering in unregulated/illegal online gambling is to introduce legal markets. But this is far from sufficient. Legal operators are far less attractive to customers due to lower payout ratios which result from taxes and fees the operators have to pay. Even in regulated markets like France the illegal operators still play an important role. The reason is a lack of law enforcement against unregulated/illegal operators. For example, Germany is the largest online poker market worldwide although it is illegal (Fiedler and Wilcke 2012). Thus, the first and most important step in tackling money laundering in online gaming and preventing it from increasing the prevalence of organized crime in our society is to enforce the law against illegal/unregulated operators.
1,509
<h4>Plan doesn’t solve laundering </h4><p><strong>Fiedler 13</strong> – Post Doc Researcher at the Division on Gambling at the Institute of Law & Economics, University of Hamburg</p><p>Ingo, Online Gambling as a Game Changer to Money Laundering?, 4/30/13, http://www.wiso.uni-hamburg.de/fileadmin/bwl/rechtderwirtschaft/institut/Ingo_Fiedler/Online_Gambling_as_a_Game_Changer_to_Money_Laundering_01.pdf</p><p><u><mark>All forms of money laundering in online gambling involve unregulated or illegal operators as they</mark> do not have to oblige to anti-money laundering directives but <mark>can <strong>hide in regulatory havens</u></strong></mark>. Legal operators, in contrast, are not prone to money laundering (Brooks 2012), especially because of the much lower payout ratios. However, the online gambling market is still dominated by illegal operators; legal ones play only a minor role. This leaves penty of opportunities of money laundering.¶ <u><mark>The obvious way to tackle money laundering</mark> in unregulated/illegal online gambling <mark>is to introduce legal markets. But <strong>this is far from sufficient</strong>. Legal operators are far less attractive to customers due to lower payout ratios</mark> which result from taxes and fees the operators have to pay. <strong><mark>Even in regulated markets like France the illegal operators still play an important role</strong>. The reason is a lack of law enforcement against unregulated</mark>/illegal <mark>operators</u></mark>. For example, Germany is the largest online poker market worldwide although it is illegal (Fiedler and Wilcke 2012). Thus, <u><mark>the</mark> first and <mark>most important step</mark> in tackling money laundering in online gaming</u> and preventing it from increasing the prevalence of organized crime in our society <u><mark>is to enforce the law against illegal/unregulated operators<strong></mark>. </p></u></strong>
null
null
Costa Rica
430,674
49
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,373
Their “movement” started 40 years ago. Either SQ solves or they accomplish nothing
Richardson 2013
Richardson 2013 (George, Contributing Scribe, New York Beacon, 'The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness', New York Beacon [New York, N.Y] 10 Oct 2013: 20, proquest)
For former NJ Assemblyman Richardson The New Jim Crow" crystallized his decades long battle against the War on Drugs In 1975 he and his partner, Ingrid Frank wrote "Get Up! You're Not Dead Their goal was the same as Alexander's "The New Jim Crow to demonstrate the counter-productive social effects of the nations war on drugs, Get Up! You're Not Dead" won the endorsement of many major national leaders including Kennedy and Móndale and it became the catalyst for a national drug policy reform movement.
null
For former NJ Assemblyman George Richardson, in 1961 the only Black member of the NJ Legislature, and spearhead of the United Free- dom Party, political arm of the NJ civil rights movement, "The New Jim Crow" crystallized his decades long battle against the police poli- cies of the War on Drugs. In 1975,45 years ago, he and his partner, Ingrid Frank, both life-long civil rights activists, wrote "Get Up! You're Not Dead"(Norton'75). Their goal was the same as MichelleAlexander's "The New Jim Crow" is now, to demonstrate the counter-productive social effects of the nations war on drugs, and to steer United States drug policy directions away from treating drugs as a law enforcement problem to- wards understanding drugs as a social health problem. "Get Up! You're Not Dead" won the endorsement of many major national leaders, including Senator Ted Kennedy and Vice President Walter Móndale and it became the catalyst for a national drug policy reform movement.. Claiming that today's drug policies have a social effect akin to slavery is strong stuff, the two civil rights veterans, now in their mid-80s, admit, but then they had a personal experience with the system. It showed them that Professor Alexander's language may be strong, but her logic is unarguable."
1,270
<h4><strong>Their “movement” started 40 years ago. Either SQ solves or they accomplish nothing</h4><p>Richardson 2013</strong> (George, Contributing Scribe, New York Beacon, 'The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness', New York Beacon [New York, N.Y] 10 Oct 2013: 20, proquest)</p><p><u>For former NJ Assemblyman </u>George <u>Richardson</u>, in 1961 the only Black member of the NJ Legislature, and spearhead of the United Free- dom Party, political arm of the NJ civil rights movement, "<u>The New Jim Crow" crystallized his decades long battle against the</u> police poli- cies of the <u>War on Drugs</u>. <u>In 1975</u>,45 years ago, <u>he and his partner, Ingrid Frank</u>, both life-long civil rights activists, <u>wrote "Get Up! You're Not Dead</u>"(Norton'75). <u>Their goal was the same as<strong> </u></strong>Michelle<u>Alexander's<strong> </strong>"The New Jim Crow</u>" is now, <u>to demonstrate the counter-productive social effects of the nations war on drugs,</u> and to steer United States drug policy directions away from treating drugs as a law enforcement problem to- wards understanding drugs as a social health problem. "<u>Get Up! You're Not Dead" won the endorsement of many major national leaders</u>, <u>including</u> Senator Ted <u>Kennedy and</u> Vice President Walter <u>Móndale</u> <u>and it became the catalyst for a national drug policy reform movement.</u>. Claiming that today's drug policies have a social effect akin to slavery is strong stuff, the two civil rights veterans, now in their mid-80s, admit, but then they had a personal experience with the system. It showed them that Professor Alexander's language may be strong, but her <strong>logic is unarguable."</p></strong>
null
null
Solvency
430,675
2
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,374
government purchaser avoids exploitation
Erin and Harris 3
Erin and Harris 3 Charles A Erin and John Harris, Institute of Medicine, Law and Bioethics, School of Law, University of Manchester, J Med Ethics 2003;29:137-138 An ethical market in human organs http://jme.bmj.com/content/29/3/137.full
While people’s lives continue to be put at risk by the dearth of organs available for transplantation, we must give urgent consideration to any option that may make up the shortfall. The market should be ethically supportable, and have built into it, for example, safeguards against wrongful exploitation. This can be accomplished by establishing a single purchaser system within a confined marketplace.
we must give urgent consideration to any option that may make up the shortfall. .
While people’s lives continue to be put at risk by the dearth of organs available for transplantation, we must give urgent consideration to any option that may make up the shortfall. A market in organs from living donors is one such option. The market should be ethically supportable, and have built into it, for example, safeguards against wrongful exploitation. This can be accomplished by establishing a single purchaser system within a confined marketplace.
461
<h4>government purchaser avoids exploitation</h4><p><strong>Erin and Harris 3</strong> Charles A Erin and John Harris, Institute of Medicine, Law and Bioethics, School of Law, University of Manchester, <strong> </strong>J Med Ethics 2003;29:137-138 An ethical market in human organs</p><p><u>http://jme.bmj.com/content/29/3/137.full</p><p>While people’s lives continue to be put at risk by the dearth of organs available for transplantation, <mark>we must give urgent consideration to any option that may make up the shortfall.</mark> </u>A market in organs from living donors is one such option<mark>.<u></mark> The market should be ethically supportable, and have built into it, for example, safeguards against wrongful exploitation. This can be accomplished by establishing a single purchaser system within a confined marketplace.</p></u>
null
null
Contention 3 The Plan solves
430,342
13
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,375
Medical autonomy is a myth---coercion and diagnosis failure
Arras 97 =1364&context=jchlp
John D. Arras 97, Porterfield Professor of Biomedical Ethics and Director of Bioethics Minor Program (PhD from Northwestern), 1997, Physician-Assisted Suicide: A Tragic View, Journal of Contemporary Health Law & Policy, Volume 13 Issue 2, http://scholarship.law.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1364&context=jchlp
With regard to the voluntariness requirement many requests would not be sufficiently voluntary In addition to the coercive influences of physicians and family members the ¶ most slippery aspect of this slope is the highly predictable failure of most physicians to diagnose reliably and treat reversible clinical depression, particularly in the elderly population one geriatric psychiatrist we now live in the "golden age" of treating depression, but the "lead age" of diagnosing it physicians are not adequately trained and motivated Unless dramatic changes are effected in the practice of medicine we can predict with confidence that many instances of PAS will constitute abuses of the original criterion of voluntariness. ¶
many requests would not be voluntary In addition to coercive influences of physicians and family members the ¶ most slippery aspect of this slope is the failure of physicians to diagnose depression physicians are not adequately trained and motivated we can predict with confidence that many instances of PAS will constitute abuses of the original criterion of voluntariness
With regard to the voluntariness requirement, we pessimists contend ¶ that many requests would not be sufficiently voluntary. In addition to the ¶ subtly coercive influences of physicians and family members, perhaps the ¶ most slippery aspect of this slope is the highly predictable failure of most ¶ physicians to diagnose reliably and treat reversible clinical depression, ¶ particularly in the elderly population. As one geriatric psychiatrist testified before the New York Task Force, we now live in the "golden age" of ¶ treating depression, but the "lead age" of diagnosing it.34 We have the ¶ tools, but physicians are not adequately trained and motivated to use ¶ them. Unless dramatic changes are effected in the practice of medicine, ¶ we can predict with confidence that many instances of PAS and active ¶ euthanasia will constitute abuses of the original criterion of voluntariness. ¶
896
<h4>Medical autonomy is a myth---coercion and diagnosis failure</h4><p>John D. <strong>Arras 97</strong>, Porterfield Professor of Biomedical Ethics and Director of Bioethics Minor Program (PhD from Northwestern), 1997, Physician-Assisted Suicide: A Tragic View, Journal of Contemporary Health Law & Policy, Volume 13 Issue 2, http://scholarship.law.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article<u><strong>=1364&context=jchlp</p><p>With regard to the voluntariness requirement</u></strong>, we pessimists contend ¶ that <u><mark>many requests would not be</mark> sufficiently <mark>voluntary</u></mark>. <u><mark>In addition to</mark> the</u> ¶ subtly <u><strong><mark>coercive influences</u></strong> <u>of physicians and family members</u></mark>, perhaps <u><strong><mark>the ¶ most slippery aspect of this </strong>slope is the</mark> highly predictable <mark>failure of</mark> most </u>¶<u> <mark>physicians to diagnose</mark> reliably and treat reversible clinical <mark>depression</mark>, </u>¶<u> particularly in the elderly population</u>. As <u>one geriatric psychiatrist</u> testified before the New York Task Force, <u>we now live in the "golden age" of </u>¶<u> treating depression, but the "lead age" of diagnosing it</u>.34 We have the ¶ tools, but <u><strong><mark>physicians are not adequately trained and motivated</u></strong></mark> to use ¶ them. <u>Unless dramatic changes are effected in the practice of medicine</u>, ¶ <u><strong><mark>we can predict with confidence that many instances of PAS</mark> </u></strong>and active ¶ euthanasia<u><strong> <mark>will constitute abuses of the original criterion of voluntariness</mark>. ¶</p></u></strong>
Ableism
A2: Autonomy
2NC K
430,676
2
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,376
Iran deal thumps-
NYT 4/2
NYT 4/2/2015 (New York Times, Iran Agrees to Detailed Nuclear Outline, First Step Toward a Wider Deal, http://www.nytimes.com/2015/04/03/world/middleeast/iran-nuclear-talks.html?_r=0)
attention will shift to Obama selling the agreement at home The White House has promised a lobbying campaign by the president unlike any seen since he pushed through health care legislation
attention will shift to Obama selling the agreement at home The White House has promised a lobbying campaign by the president unlike any seen since he pushed through health care legislation.
Now, attention will shift to Mr. Obama and Hassan Rouhani, the Iranian president, who was elected on a platform of ending sanctions. They share a common task: selling the agreement at home to constituencies deeply suspicious of both the deal and the prospect of signing any accord with an avowed enemy. The White House has promised a lobbying campaign by the president unlike any seen since he pushed through health care legislation.
433
<h4>Iran deal thumps- </h4><p><strong>NYT 4/2</strong>/2015 (New York Times, Iran Agrees to Detailed Nuclear Outline, First Step Toward a Wider Deal, http://www.nytimes.com/2015/04/03/world/middleeast/iran-nuclear-talks.html?_r=0)</p><p>Now, <u><mark>attention will shift to</u></mark> Mr. <u><mark>Obama</u></mark> and Hassan Rouhani, the Iranian president, who was elected on a platform of ending sanctions. They share a common task: <u><mark>selling the agreement at home</u></mark> to constituencies deeply suspicious of both the deal and the prospect of signing any accord with an avowed enemy. <u><strong><mark>The White House has promised a lobbying campaign by the president unlike any seen since he pushed through health care legislation</u></strong>.</p></mark>
2AC
Politics DA
TPA – 2AC – NDT
430,677
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,377
No impact to another recession.
Keystone Research 11
Keystone Research 11 [Main Street Newsletter, “3 Ways the Next Recession Will Be Different”, http://keystoneresearch.org/media-center/media-coverage/3-ways-next-recession-will-be-different]
even if we enter another recession it won’t be nearly as damaging as 08 it wouldn’t be as severe and would also be shorter,” says senior economist at Moody’s a lot of the imbalances that drove the previous recession have been corrected.” banks are better capitalized the housing market has shed delinquent homeowners and corporations are sitting on ample cash reserves to weather another storm.
even if we enter another recession it won’t be nearly as damaging as 08 it wouldn’t be as severe and would also be shorter,” says senior economist at Moody’s a lot of the imbalances that drove the previous recession have been corrected.” banks are better capitalized the housing market has shed delinquent homeowners and corporations are sitting on ample cash reserves to weather another storm.
All of this has only renewed concerns among analysts and average Americans that the U.S. would suffer a dreaded double-dip recession, but according to several economists MainStreet spoke with, even if we do enter into another recession later this year or in early 2012, it won’t be nearly as damaging as the Great Recession of 2008.“If there is another recession, I think it wouldn’t be as severe and it would also be shorter,” says Gus Faucher, senior economist at Moody’s Analytics. “And the reason for that is a lot of the imbalances that drove the previous recession have been corrected.” As Faucher and others point out, banks are better capitalized now, the housing market has shed (however painfully) many delinquent homeowners who signed up forsubprime mortgages before the recession and U.S. corporations have trimmed their payrolls and are sitting on ample cash reserves to help weather another storm. At the same time, consumers have gradually improved their own balance sheets by spending less and paying off more of their debt.
1,041
<h4>No impact to another recession.</h4><p><u><strong>Keystone Research 11</u></strong> [Main Street Newsletter, “3 Ways the Next Recession Will Be Different”, http://keystoneresearch.org/media-center/media-coverage/3-ways-next-recession-will-be-different]</p><p>All of this has only renewed concerns among analysts and average Americans that the U.S. would suffer a dreaded double-dip recession, but according to several economists MainStreet spoke with, <u><mark>even if we</u></mark> do <u><mark>enter</u></mark> into <u><mark>another recession</u></mark> later this year or in early 2012, <u><mark>it won’t be nearly as damaging as</u></mark> the Great Recession of 20<u><mark>08</u></mark>.“If there is another recession, I think <u><mark>it wouldn’t be as severe and</u></mark> it <u><mark>would also be shorter,” says</u></mark> Gus Faucher, <u><mark>senior economist at Moody’s</u></mark> Analytics. “And the reason for that is <u><mark>a lot of the imbalances that drove the previous recession have been corrected.”</u></mark> As Faucher and others point out, <u><mark>banks are better capitalized</u></mark> now, <u><mark>the housing market has shed</u></mark> (however painfully) many <u><mark>delinquent homeowners</u></mark> who signed up forsubprime mortgages before the recession <u><mark>and</u></mark> U.S. <u><mark>corporations</u></mark> have trimmed their payrolls and <u><mark>are sitting on ample cash reserves to</u></mark> help <u><mark>weather another storm.</u></mark> At the same time, consumers have gradually improved their own balance sheets by spending less and paying off more of their debt.</p>
WTO
War
AT: Inevitable
190,802
3
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,378
Deal will succeed now- multiple pressures on Iran
CNN 1/1
CNN 1/1/2015 (What (not) to look forward to in 2015: ISIS, life on Mars, Europe's mood, http://www.cnn.com/2014/12/31/world/lister-2015-predictions/)
A common enemy -- ISIS -- has led to a tacit understanding between the United States and Iran. Whether that opens the window to a broader relationship -- and whether negotiations on Iran's nuclear program will succeed -- is one of the big questions of 2015 Deadlines for agreement on limiting Iran's nuclear program have come and gone: the next is July Obama has invested heavily in seeking a deal Rouhani is keen to show the Iranian people he can end their economic and political isolation Hardliners in Iran may see such an opening as undermining their influence The momentum appears to be flowing against them but the gaps between Tehran and the international community remain formidable. Iran is taking further action to comply with the terms of an extended interim agreement with six world powers over its disputed atomic activities, a U.N. nuclear watchdog report showed The findings though no major surprise may be seen as positive by the West as negotiations resumed in New York this week on ending the decade-old nuclear stand-off. Iran is continuing to meet its commitments In addition, as agreed when the deal was extended by four months in July, it is using some of its higher-grade enriched uranium in oxide form to produce fuel a step that experts say would make it more difficult to use the material for any bombs. After years of escalating tensions between Iran and the West, the election in mid-2013 of Hassan Rouhani, a pragmatist as Iranian president on a platform of ending Tehran's international isolation created new room for diplomacy that ultimately led to last year's breakthrough nuclear deal. Under the preliminary accord, Iran halted its most contested nuclear work It also converted its stockpile of the material into oxide from gas. it agreed to take some additional nuclear steps, including making nuclear fuel for a research reactor and diluting a large amount of low-enriched uranium. IAEA has inspectors on the ground in Iran who are monitoring its enrichment sites on a daily basis. Its monthly reports on the implementation of the nuclear agreement are issued to its member states and not made public. rhetoric new deal between Iran and six superpowers. the United States, Great Britain, France, Germany, Russia and China (the P5+1 group) reached an interim deal with Iran to stop their nuclear weapons program. Four key provisions were obtained no enrichment of U above 5% U-235 ) no additional centrifuges are to be installed or produced stop all work on the heavy-water reactor at Arak provide design details on the reactor and do not develop the reprocessing facilities needed to separate Pu from used fuel,¶ full access by IAEA inspectors to all nuclear facilities including daily visitation to Natanz and Fordow, and continuous camera surveillance of key sites.¶ Despite all the rhetoric of horror and claims that this deal is a mistake, this deal is just what we all hoped for as the first step to resolving the Iranian nuclear weapons issue It is the first step to bringing Iran into the world’s nuclear community as a partner instead of an adversary, Iran’s theocracy embodied by their new President has decided that the cost/benefit of maintaining an expensive, useless nuclear program that is still a long way from producing a reliable weapon, while being starved by a barrage of sanctions, on the heels of a global economic meltdown, has now gone into the too-much-cost-and-not-enough-benefit category.¶ there is now an opening to change the game.¶ I’m not sure what the naysayers of this deal think the sanctions were suppose to do. The purpose of sanctions is to get a specific party to the negotiating table. Sanctions are not meant to destroy a nation, cause widespread poverty of its people and destruction of their economy, or topple governments. As much as some leaders in Israel and Saudi Arabia want to use the U.S. to decapitate their nemesis, this is not the point of these talks We need nuclear energy to spread around the world without proliferating weapons. How we handle Iran will determine the future of nuclear energy in many countries outside of the developed world, and we better get it right All other rhetoric is posturing. Isolation is the worst strategy for bringing a country into the civil world’s fold And while discussions focus on 20% U-235 as sufficiently enriched to make an atomic weapon, that is only theoretically correct. No one has made a weapon from such lowly-enriched materials and no one ever will.¶
A common enemy -- ISIS -- has led to a tacit understanding between the United States and Iran. Whether that opens the window to a broader relationship -- and whether negotiations on Iran's nuclear program will succeed -- is one of the big questions of 2015. Deadlines for agreement on limiting Iran's nuclear program have come and gone: the next is July Obama has invested heavily in seeking a deal Rouhani is keen to show the Iranian people he can end their economic and political isolation Hardliners in Iran may see such an opening as undermining their influence The momentum appears to be flowing against them, but the gaps between Tehran and the international community remain formidable Iran is taking further action to comply with the agreement , a U.N. nuclear report showed findings may b positive as negotiations resumed this week , it is using high grade uranium to produce fuel - a step experts say would make it more difficult to use material for bombs the election of Rouhani, a pragmatist created new diplomacy IAEA has inspectors monthly reports are issued new deal stop their nuclear program. Four key provisions were obtained no enrichment above 5% no additional centrifuges stop heavy-water reacto full access by IAEA inspectors to all facilities, including continuous surveillance Despite rhetoric of horror this deal is the first step to resolving Iranian nuclear issue It is the first step to bringing Iran into nuclear community as a partner The purpose of sanctions is to get a party to the table As much as some leaders in Israel want to use the U.S. this is not the point All rhetoric is posturing Isolation is the worst strategy
Obama also spoke of "strategic patience" -- which is very much on show in Washington's gradual reaching-out to Tehran. A common enemy -- ISIS -- has led to a tacit understanding between the United States and Iran. Whether that opens the window to a broader relationship -- and whether negotiations on Iran's nuclear program will succeed -- is one of the big questions of 2015. Deadlines for agreement on limiting Iran's nuclear program have come and gone: the next is July. The Obama administration has invested heavily in seeking a deal since President Hassan Rouhani's election in 2013, and Rouhani is keen to show the Iranian people he can end their economic and political isolation. Obama, in his year-end interview with NPR, said he believed "there are elements inside of Iran that recognize the opportunity and want to take it." Hardliners in Iran may see such an opening as undermining their influence and opening the door to all sorts of Western influences. The momentum appears to be flowing against them, but the gaps between Tehran and the international community remain formidable. Perhaps the best to be expected is an interim deal that further eases sanctions. Yes compliance Dahl 9/19/14 --- Reuters (Fredrik, “Iran moving to comply with extended nuclear deal with powers-IAEA”, http://af.reuters.com/article/worldNews/idAFKBN0HE1RG20140919)//trepka (Reuters) - Iran is taking further action to comply with the terms of an extended interim agreement with six world powers over its disputed atomic activities, a U.N. nuclear watchdog report obtained by Reuters on Friday showed. The findings in a monthly update by the International Atomic Energy Agency (IAEA) - though no major surprise - may be seen as positive by the West as negotiations resumed in New York this week on ending the decade-old nuclear stand-off. The IAEA document made clear that Iran is continuing to meet its commitments under the preliminary accord that it reached with the United States, France, Germany, Britain, China and Russia late last year and that took effect in January. In addition, as agreed when the deal was extended by four months in July, it is using some of its higher-grade enriched uranium in oxide form to produce fuel - a step that experts say would make it more difficult to use the material for any bombs. The IAEA is tasked with checking that Iran is living up to its part of the temporary agreement, which was designed to buy time for the current talks on a comprehensive settlement of the dispute that would dispel fears of a new Middle East war. Iran denies Western allegations that it has been working to develop a capability to make atomic bombs, saying it is refining uranium to fuel a planned network of nuclear power plants. After years of escalating tensions between Iran and the West, the election in mid-2013 of Hassan Rouhani, a pragmatist, as Iranian president on a platform of ending Tehran's international isolation created new room for diplomacy that ultimately led to last year's breakthrough nuclear deal. The initial aim was for Iran and the six powers to reach a long-term agreement by a self-imposed July 20 deadline. But the talks and the interim deal were extended until Nov. 24 in view of persistently wide differences over the future size of Iran's uranium enrichment program, activity which can have both civilian and military purposes. NUCLEAR FUEL Under the preliminary accord, Iran halted its most contested nuclear work - enrichment of uranium to a higher fissile concentration of 20 percent - in exchange for a limited easing of sanctions that are hurting its oil-dependent economy. It also converted its stockpile of the material into oxide from gas. Over the four months of the deal's extension, Iran is to receive $2.8 billion in previously frozen oil revenue held in banks abroad, in addition to the $4.2 billion it got during the January-July period. In exchange, it agreed to take some additional nuclear steps, including making nuclear fuel for a research reactor and diluting a large amount of low-enriched uranium. Friday's IAEA report said Iran since July 24 had used 12.5 kg (28 lbs) of its 20 percent uranium in oxide form for manufacturing fuel. It also said Iran had begun preparatory work for diluting more than four tonnes of uranium gas enriched to up to two percent. Uranium can be used for atomic energy plants, Iran's stated aim, but can also provide material for bombs if processed to a high degree, which the West fears may be the ultimate aim. The Vienna-based IAEA has inspectors on the ground in Iran who are monitoring its enrichment sites on a daily basis. Its monthly reports on the implementation of the nuclear agreement are issued to its member states and not made public. Prefer it --- all their ev is rhetoric Forbes 11/30 (The Iranian Nuclear Deal Is A Good One http://www.forbes.com/sites/jamesconca/2013/11/30/the-iranian-nuclear-deal-is-a-good-one/ James Conca 11/30/13 This Thanksgiving had an extra reason to be thankful – the new deal between Iran and six superpowers. Last week, the United States, Great Britain, France, Germany, Russia and China (the P5+1 group) reached an interim deal with Iran to stop their nuclear weapons program. Four key provisions were obtained in this deal:¶ 1) no enrichment of U above 5% U-235, and all highly-enriched materials, some as high as 20% U-235, must be blended down to less than 5% or altered to a form not usable for weapons.¶ 2) no additional centrifuges are to be installed or produced, and three-fourths of the centrifuges at Fordow and half of the centrifuges at Natanz will be inoperable,¶ 3) stop all work on the heavy-water reactor at Arak, provide design details on the reactor (which could be used to produce Pu for the other type of atomic weapon) and do not develop the reprocessing facilities needed to separate Pu from used fuel,¶ 4) full access by IAEA inspectors to all nuclear facilities, including daily visitation to Natanz and Fordow, and continuous camera surveillance of key sites.¶ Despite all the rhetoric of horror and claims that this deal is a mistake, this deal is just what we all hoped for as the first step to resolving the Iranian nuclear weapons issue, the structure of which we’ve been proposing for years. It is the first step to bringing Iran into the world’s nuclear community as a partner instead of an adversary, making Iran a compliant signatory of the Non-Proliferation Treaty. While this may make some of its neighbors nervous, there is no real alternative that does not involve lots of destruction and death.¶ Old orders are falling in the Middle East. The region is in upheaval, Shia and Sunni are as far apart as ever, and Iran’s theocracy, embodied by their new President Hassan Rouhani, has decided that the cost/benefit of maintaining an expensive, useless nuclear program that is still a long way from producing a reliable weapon, while being starved by a barrage of sanctions, on the heels of a global economic meltdown, has now gone into the too-much-cost-and-not-enough-benefit category.¶ Thus, there is now an opening to change the game.¶ This deal is not about trust, as the last point above about access addresses. No one trusts governments, even supposedly good ones. There must be unfettered access to verify that the nuclear facilities are not being used to produce weapons and that is what this deal allows, and it will be easy to determine when Iran breaks this deal (The Economist; The Guardian; Fox News).¶ But the facilities can, and will, be used to support nuclear power, as was the original purpose of Iran’s nuclear program when the United States set it up under the Shah in the 1960s, and that is the actual end point of this whole deal. Not the end of Iran’s nuclear program or the destruction of their facilities, their country or their people.¶ I’m not sure what the naysayers of this deal think the sanctions were suppose to do. The purpose of sanctions is to get a specific party to the negotiating table. Sanctions are not meant to destroy a nation, cause widespread poverty of its people and destruction of their economy, or topple governments. The fear of these happening, not the reality of them, is what gets a government to the table.¶ As much as some leaders in Israel and Saudi Arabia want to use the U.S. to decapitate their nemesis, this is not the point of these talks. And what happens here goes far beyond just Iran. We need nuclear energy to spread around the world without proliferating weapons. How we handle Iran will determine the future of nuclear energy in many countries outside of the developed world, and we better get it right. There will always be pressures to develop weapons and we need strategies and experience in diverting these programs away from weapons.¶ Besides, the art of diplomacy is the art of finding a win-win for all parties. It’s significant that the Obama Administration knows how to use diplomacy the way only the U.S. can. It is in both our and the world’s best interest, to find a solution that allows Iran nuclear energy without weapons.¶ All other rhetoric is posturing. Isolation is the worst strategy for bringing a country into the civil world’s fold. Just look at North Korea. Rouhani has to move forward in a way that does not shame Iran. The celebration in Iran over this deal is a strong indication of the win-win nature of this deal, not the ridiculous charge of the opposition that the U.S. was taken for a ride. Iran wants to, and according to international law can, have a nuclear energy program, including enrichment and production, as long as it falls under the appropriate international controls and is not producing weapons.¶ It is no wonder that Iran wants this deal as badly as it seems. It is a way out of a very tricky and dangerous situation. Countries having the bomb never seem to get attacked, but those that give up their nuclear programs completely tend to end badly. Just ask Iraq and Libya. To avoid this fate, Iran has to back away from nuclear weapons while retaining a nuclear energy program.¶ The U.S. understands that this deal is a good step toward that end. A final deal will include a structure that precludes the ability to make a weapon, such as abandoning or altering the reactor at Arak, and closing the Fordow enrichment facility because it is basically immune from attack being under a mountain. But the whole deal doesn’t have to be done all at once.¶ All things considered, this deal with Iran is a good one for the world.¶ Technical Endnotes – Just a few technical clarifications since science rarely enters media coverage of nuclear issues, yet is extremely important. The original level of U-235 in the uranium ore, that is mined like any other ore, is 0.7% U-235. 5% U-235 is the level of enrichment for nuclear fuel for power reactors. Although some reactor designs can use anything from natural uranium to highly-enriched material, most power reactor fuel is between 3% and 5% enriched as is used in Iran’s Bushehr reactor, a reactor no one cares much about for this reason. You can’t make a bomb out of these materials. This is the basis for the first key provision of the deal.¶ And while discussions focus on 20% U-235 as sufficiently enriched to make an atomic weapon, that is only theoretically correct. No one has made a weapon from such lowly-enriched materials and no one ever will.¶ Enrichment needs to be >90% to make a reliable weapon. Reliability in this case is not like having a reliable flashlight. Reliable in this case means the atomic weapon will work when you want it to. It’s why there’s so much testing associated with a weapons program. If you’re going to make the fatal decision to field a nuke, it better work, and everyone knows it has to be over 90% U-235 to be really useful.¶ Finally, an atomic weapon is fission-based such as U-235 and Pu-239 whose nuclei split to change a bit of matter into a huge amount of energy. These are what was dropped during WWII, what Iran was working towards with U, and what North Korea has developed with Pu. In contrast, a nuclear weapon is fusion-based such as a hydrogen bomb, whose nuclei fuse to change a bit of matter into even more energy.
12,199
<h4>Deal will succeed now- multiple pressures on Iran</h4><p><strong>CNN 1/1</strong>/2015 (What (not) to look forward to in 2015: ISIS, life on Mars, Europe's mood, http://www.cnn.com/2014/12/31/world/lister-2015-predictions/)</p><p>Obama also spoke of "strategic patience" -- which is very much on show in Washington's gradual reaching-out to Tehran. <u><mark>A common enemy -- ISIS -- has led to a tacit understanding between the United States and Iran. Whether that opens the window to a broader relationship -- and whether negotiations on Iran's nuclear program will succeed -- is one of the big questions of 2015</u>. <u>Deadlines for agreement on limiting Iran's nuclear program have come and gone: the next is July</u></mark>. The <u><mark>Obama</u></mark> administration <u><mark>has invested heavily in seeking a deal</u></mark> since President Hassan Rouhani's election in 2013, and <u><mark>Rouhani is keen to show the Iranian people he can end their economic and political isolation</u></mark>. Obama, in his year-end interview with NPR, said he believed "there are elements inside of Iran that recognize the opportunity and want to take it." <u><mark>Hardliners in Iran may see such an opening as undermining their influence</u></mark> and opening the door to all sorts of Western influences. <u><strong><mark>The momentum appears to be flowing against them</u></strong>, <u>but the gaps between Tehran and the international community remain formidable</mark>.</u><strong> Perhaps the best to be expected is an interim deal that further eases sanctions.</p><p>Yes compliance </p><p>Dahl 9/19/14 </strong>--- Reuters (Fredrik, “Iran moving to comply with extended nuclear deal with powers-IAEA”, http://af.reuters.com/article/worldNews/idAFKBN0HE1RG20140919)//trepka</p><p>(Reuters) - <u><mark>Iran is taking <strong>further action</strong> to <strong>comply</strong> with the</mark> terms of an extended interim <mark>agreement</mark> with six world powers over its disputed atomic activities<mark>, a U.N. nuclear</mark> watchdog <mark>report</u></mark> obtained by Reuters on Friday <u><mark>showed</u></mark>. <u>The <mark>findings</u></mark> in a monthly update by the International Atomic Energy Agency (IAEA) - <u>though no major surprise</u> - <u><mark>may b</mark>e seen as <strong><mark>positive</u></strong></mark> <u>by the West <mark>as negotiations resumed</mark> in New York <mark>this week</mark> on ending the decade-old nuclear stand-off. </u>The IAEA document made clear that <u>Iran is <strong>continuing to meet its commitments</u></strong> under the preliminary accord that it reached with the United States, France, Germany, Britain, China and Russia late last year and that took effect in January. <u>In addition, as agreed when the deal was extended by four months in July<mark>, it is using</mark> some of its <mark>high</mark>er-<mark>grade</mark> enriched <mark>uranium</mark> in oxide form <mark>to produce fuel</u> - <u>a step</mark> that <strong><mark>experts say</strong> would make it more difficult to use</mark> the <mark>material for</mark> <strong>any <mark>bombs</strong></mark>. </u>The IAEA is tasked with checking that Iran is living up to its part of the temporary agreement, which was designed to buy time for the current talks on a comprehensive settlement of the dispute that would dispel fears of a new Middle East war. Iran denies Western allegations that it has been working to develop a capability to make atomic bombs, saying it is refining uranium to fuel a planned network of nuclear power plants. <u>After years of escalating tensions between Iran and the West, <mark>the election</mark> in mid-2013 <mark>of</mark> Hassan <mark>Rouhani, a <strong>pragmatist</u></strong></mark>, <u>as Iranian president on a platform of ending Tehran's international isolation <mark>created new</mark> room for <mark>diplomacy</mark> that ultimately led to last year's breakthrough nuclear deal. </u>The initial aim was for Iran and the six powers to reach a long-term agreement by a self-imposed July 20 deadline. But the talks and the interim deal were extended until Nov. 24 in view of persistently wide differences over the future size of Iran's uranium enrichment program, activity which can have both civilian and military purposes. NUCLEAR FUEL <u>Under the preliminary accord, Iran halted its most contested nuclear work</u> - enrichment of uranium to a higher fissile concentration of 20 percent - in exchange for a limited easing of sanctions that are hurting its oil-dependent economy. <u>It also converted its stockpile of the material into oxide from gas. </u>Over the four months of the deal's extension, Iran is to receive $2.8 billion in previously frozen oil revenue held in banks abroad, in addition to the $4.2 billion it got during the January-July period. In exchange, <u>it agreed to take some additional nuclear steps, including making nuclear fuel for a research reactor and diluting a large amount of low-enriched uranium. </u>Friday's IAEA report said Iran since July 24 had used 12.5 kg (28 lbs) of its 20 percent uranium in oxide form for manufacturing fuel. It also said Iran had begun preparatory work for diluting more than four tonnes of uranium gas enriched to up to two percent. Uranium can be used for atomic energy plants, Iran's stated aim, but can also provide material for bombs if processed to a high degree, which the West fears may be the ultimate aim. The Vienna-based <u><mark>IAEA</u> <u>has inspectors</mark> on the ground in Iran who are monitoring its enrichment sites on a daily basis. Its <strong><mark>monthly reports</strong></mark> on the implementation of the nuclear agreement <mark>are issued</mark> to its member<strong> states and not made public.</p><p></u>Prefer it --- all their ev is <u>rhetoric</p><p></u>Forbes 11/30 </strong>(The Iranian Nuclear Deal Is A Good One http://www.forbes.com/sites/jamesconca/2013/11/30/the-iranian-nuclear-deal-is-a-good-one/ James Conca 11/30/13 </p><p>This Thanksgiving had an extra reason to be thankful – the <u><mark>new deal </mark>between Iran and six superpowers.</u> Last week, <u>the United States, Great Britain, France, Germany, Russia and China (the P5+1 group) reached an interim deal with Iran to <mark>stop their nuclear </mark>weapons</u> <u><mark>program. Four key provisions were obtained</u></mark> in this deal:¶ 1) <u><mark>no enrichment </mark>of U <mark>above 5% </mark>U-235</u>, and all highly-enriched materials, some as high as 20% U-235, must be blended down to less than 5% or altered to a form not usable for weapons.¶ 2<u>) <mark>no additional centrifuges</mark> are to be installed or produced</u>, and three-fourths of the centrifuges at Fordow and half of the centrifuges at Natanz will be inoperable,¶ 3) <u><mark>stop </mark>all work on the <mark>heavy-water reacto</mark>r at Arak</u>, <u>provide design details on the reactor</u> (which could be used to produce Pu for the other type of atomic weapon) <u>and do not develop the reprocessing facilities needed to separate Pu from used fuel,¶ </u>4) <u><mark>full access by IAEA inspectors to all </mark>nuclear <mark>facilities</u>, <u>including </mark>daily visitation to Natanz and Fordow, and <mark>continuous </mark>camera <mark>surveillance</mark> of key sites.¶ <mark>Despite</mark> all the <mark>rhetoric of</mark> <mark>horror </mark>and claims that this deal is a mistake, <mark>this deal is</mark> just what we all hoped for as <mark>the first step to resolving</mark> the <mark>Iranian nuclear </mark>weapons <mark>issue</u></mark>, the structure of which we’ve been proposing for years. <u><mark>It is the first step to bringing Iran into</mark> the world’s <mark>nuclear community as a partner</mark> instead of an adversary, </u>making Iran a compliant signatory of the Non-Proliferation Treaty. While this may make some of its neighbors nervous, there is no real alternative that does not involve lots of destruction and death.¶ Old orders are falling in the Middle East. The region is in upheaval, Shia and Sunni are as far apart as ever, and <u>Iran’s theocracy</u>, <u>embodied by their new President</u> Hassan Rouhani, <u>has decided that the cost/benefit of maintaining an expensive, useless nuclear program that is still a long way from producing a reliable weapon, while being starved by a barrage of sanctions, on the heels of a global economic meltdown, has now gone into the too-much-cost-and-not-enough-benefit category.¶ </u>Thus, <u>there is now an opening to change the game.¶</u> This deal is not about trust, as the last point above about access addresses. No one trusts governments, even supposedly good ones. There must be unfettered access to verify that the nuclear facilities are not being used to produce weapons and that is what this deal allows, and it will be easy to determine when Iran breaks this deal (The Economist; The Guardian; Fox News).¶ But the facilities can, and will, be used to support nuclear power, as was the original purpose of Iran’s nuclear program when the United States set it up under the Shah in the 1960s, and that is the actual end point of this whole deal. Not the end of Iran’s nuclear program or the destruction of their facilities, their country or their people.¶ <u>I’m not sure what the naysayers of this deal think the sanctions were suppose to do. <mark>The purpose of sanctions is to get a </mark>specific <mark>party to the </mark>negotiating <mark>table</mark>. Sanctions are not meant to destroy a nation, cause widespread poverty of its people and destruction of their economy, or topple governments.</u> The fear of these happening, not the reality of them, is what gets a government to the table.¶ <u><mark>As much as some leaders in Israel </mark>and Saudi Arabia <mark>want to use the U.S. </mark>to decapitate their nemesis, <mark>this is not the point</mark> of these talks</u>. And what happens here goes far beyond just Iran. <u>We need nuclear energy to spread around the world without proliferating weapons. How we handle Iran will determine the future of nuclear energy in many countries outside of the developed world, and we better get it right</u>. There will always be pressures to develop weapons and we need strategies and experience in diverting these programs away from weapons.¶ Besides, the art of diplomacy is the art of finding a win-win for all parties. It’s significant that the Obama Administration knows how to use diplomacy the way only the U.S. can. It is in both our and the world’s best interest, to find a solution that allows Iran nuclear energy without weapons.¶ <u><mark>All</mark> other <mark>rhetoric is posturing</mark>.</u> <u><mark>Isolation is the worst strategy</u></mark> <u>for bringing a country into the civil world’s fold</u>. Just look at North Korea. Rouhani has to move forward in a way that does not shame Iran. The celebration in Iran over this deal is a strong indication of the win-win nature of this deal, not the ridiculous charge of the opposition that the U.S. was taken for a ride. Iran wants to, and according to international law can, have a nuclear energy program, including enrichment and production, as long as it falls under the appropriate international controls and is not producing weapons.¶ It is no wonder that Iran wants this deal as badly as it seems. It is a way out of a very tricky and dangerous situation. Countries having the bomb never seem to get attacked, but those that give up their nuclear programs completely tend to end badly. Just ask Iraq and Libya. To avoid this fate, Iran has to back away from nuclear weapons while retaining a nuclear energy program.¶ The U.S. understands that this deal is a good step toward that end. A final deal will include a structure that precludes the ability to make a weapon, such as abandoning or altering the reactor at Arak, and closing the Fordow enrichment facility because it is basically immune from attack being under a mountain. But the whole deal doesn’t have to be done all at once.¶ All things considered, this deal with Iran is a good one for the world.¶ Technical Endnotes – Just a few technical clarifications since science rarely enters media coverage of nuclear issues, yet is extremely important. The original level of U-235 in the uranium ore, that is mined like any other ore, is 0.7% U-235. 5% U-235 is the level of enrichment for nuclear fuel for power reactors. Although some reactor designs can use anything from natural uranium to highly-enriched material, most power reactor fuel is between 3% and 5% enriched as is used in Iran’s Bushehr reactor, a reactor no one cares much about for this reason. You can’t make a bomb out of these materials. This is the basis for the first key provision of the deal.¶ <u>And while discussions focus on 20% U-235 as sufficiently enriched to make an atomic weapon, that is only theoretically correct.</u> <u>No one has made a weapon from such lowly-enriched materials and no one ever will.¶ </u>Enrichment needs to be >90% to make a reliable weapon. Reliability in this case is not like having a reliable flashlight. Reliable in this case means the atomic weapon will work when you want it to. It’s why there’s so much testing associated with a weapons program. If you’re going to make the fatal decision to field a nuke, it better work, and everyone knows it has to be over 90% U-235 to be really useful.¶ Finally, an atomic weapon is fission-based such as U-235 and Pu-239 whose nuclei split to change a bit of matter into a huge amount of energy. These are what was dropped during WWII, what Iran was working towards with U, and what North Korea has developed with Pu. In contrast, a nuclear weapon is fusion-based such as a hydrogen bomb, whose nuclei fuse to change a bit of matter into even more energy.</p>
null
null
at: deal fails/prolif inevitable
218,942
8
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,379
Politics isn’t inherently racist or inclined toward mass incarceration- the Justice Department is actively committed to addressing it
Bouie 9/25
Bouie 9/25/2014 (Jamelle, Slate staff writer covering politics, policy, and race, From Good to Great, http://www.slate.com/articles/news_and_politics/politics/2014/09/eric_holder_resigning_as_attorney_general_his_justice_department_was_a_staunch.1.html)
Holder pushed for retroactive enforcement of the Fair Sentencing Act He’s backed away from mandatory drug sentences, ensuring that federal prosecutors avoid the draconian punishments of the last few decades widespread incarceration at the federal, state, and local levels is both ineffective and unsustainable,” he said. Holder has supported a change from the U.S. Sentencing Commission that would shorten incarceration for thousands of nonviolent inmates and keep many more people out of prison for long periods. More broadly, he’s criticized the “school-to-prison pipeline”—threatening lawsuits for schools that use criminal punishments for routine misbehavior
null
Other parts of Holder’s civil rights record are mixed. In his early years as attorney general, he increased prosecution of marijuana dispensaries and refused to reschedule the drug from its current classification, where it sits with heroin and LSD. At the same time, however,Holder pushed for retroactive enforcement of the Fair Sentencing Act—which narrowed the crack cocaine sentencing disparity tenfold—and has refrained from challenging the marijuana legalization experiments in Colorado and Washington. He’s backed away from mandatory drug sentences, ensuring that federal prosecutors avoid the draconian punishments of the last few decades. “Although incarceration has a role to play in our justice system, widespread incarceration at the federal, state, and local levels is both ineffective and unsustainable,” he said. “It imposes a significant economic burden—totaling $80 billion in 2010 alone—and it comes with human and moral costs that are impossible to calculate.” Indeed, Holder has supported a change from the U.S. Sentencing Commission that would shorten incarceration for thousands of nonviolent inmates and keep many more people out of prison for long periods. More broadly, he’s criticized the “school-to-prison pipeline”—threatening lawsuits for schools that use criminal punishments for routine misbehavior.
1,329
<h4><strong>Politics isn’t inherently racist or inclined toward mass incarceration- the Justice Department is actively committed to addressing it</h4><p>Bouie 9/25</strong>/2014 (Jamelle, Slate staff writer covering politics, policy, and race, From Good to Great, http://www.slate.com/articles/news_and_politics/politics/2014/09/eric_holder_resigning_as_attorney_general_his_justice_department_was_a_staunch.1.html)</p><p>Other parts of Holder’s civil rights record are mixed. In his early years as attorney general, he increased prosecution of marijuana dispensaries and refused to reschedule the drug from its current classification, where it sits with heroin and LSD. At the same time, however,<u>Holder pushed for retroactive enforcement of the Fair Sentencing Act</u>—which narrowed the crack cocaine sentencing disparity tenfold—and has refrained from challenging the marijuana legalization experiments in Colorado and Washington. <u>He’s backed away from mandatory drug sentences, ensuring that federal prosecutors avoid the draconian punishments of the last few decades</u>. “Although incarceration has a role to play in our justice system, <u>widespread incarceration at the federal, state, and local levels is both ineffective and unsustainable,” he said.</u> “It imposes a significant economic burden—totaling $80 billion in 2010 alone—and it comes with human and moral costs that are impossible to calculate.” Indeed, <u>Holder has supported a change from the U.S. Sentencing Commission that would shorten incarceration for thousands of nonviolent inmates and keep many more people out of prison for long periods. More broadly, he’s criticized the “school-to-prison pipeline”—threatening lawsuits for schools that use criminal punishments for routine misbehavior</u>.</p><p> </p>
null
null
Solvency
430,678
2
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,380
Laundering through illegal gambling makes no sense
Duhaime 14
Christine Duhaime 14, BA, JD, Certified Financial Crime and Anti-Money Laundering Law Specialist, Jackpot or not? Report says online gambling sites and Bitcoin facilitate money laundering but the Report has inaccuracies, www.antimoneylaunderinglaw.com/2014/04/jackpot-or-not-report-says-online-gambling-sites-and-bitcoin-facilitate-money-laundering-but-the-report-is-inaccurate.html
According to a report the global online gambling sector appears to be rife with money laundering problems The Report is incorrect written without consultation with anti-money laundering experts, gambling law experts or people knowledgeable about online gambling The Report claims that the global online gambling sector will grow 30% That seems doubtful since it is based on projections in the US in respect of online gambling growth that are not materializing and most online gambling companies are saying that there is a current retraction in the market The Report purportedly looked at licensed online gambling around the globe it stated that Canada has a whopping 120 online regulated gambling websites. Actually, it only has three regulated online gambling sites money laundering occurs purportedly by minimal play gamblers go online and invest proceeds of crime in “minimal play” transactions then cash out, presumably with cleaned funds; or in a second scenario, they play online and with the gambling wins they purchase illegal goods likely drugs) which allows the seller of the illegal goods to earn revenue tax free and the purchaser to acquire goods online illegally. Both scenarios are preposterous gamblers who engage in minimal play then cash out online have gained no money laundering benefit because they have not structured or washed the funds at all – all they have done is moved funds online and the remainder comes right back to them from the casino operator in the same form. Money launderers need to move money through multiple sources to hide its origins – it defeats the purpose when the recipient of it remits it back to the launderer. In the second scenario, most money launderers would not use proceeds of crime to acquire illegal goods, such as drugs, as a money laundering method and expose themselves to additional risk of detection by law enforcement. They almost always use proceeds of crime to buy something legal – that’s how it gets cleaned The Report states that the use of digital currencies makes it less likely that transactions will be subject to scrutiny there are no licensed and regulated gambling entities in the world that accept digital currencies as a payment method
online gambling appears rife with money laundering problems The Report is incorrect written without anti-money laundering experts, gamblers go online and invest proceeds in “minimal play” transactions then cash out with cleaned funds they play online and with the gambling wins purchase illegal goods Both scenarios are preposterous all they have done is moved funds online the remainder comes right back to them from the casino operator in the same form Money launderers need to move money through multiple sources it defeats the purpose when the recipient remits it back launderers would not use proceeds of crime to acquire illegal goods and expose themselves to additional risk They use proceeds of crime to buy something legal – that’s how it gets cleaned.
According to a report released by McAfee Labs, available here entitled “Jackpot! Money Laundering Through Online Gambling,” the global online gambling sector appears to be rife with money laundering problems and Bitcoin facilitates the use money laundering in online gambling. The Report is incorrect. It is based on numerous factual errors and appears to have been written without consultation with anti-money laundering experts, gambling law experts or people knowledgeable about Bitcoin and the online gambling environment. Here are the six most salient errors or incorrect assumptions in the Report: 1. The Report claims that the global online gambling sector will grow 30% in three years starting in 2013 (hence the problem of money laundering online will allegedly get worse, not better). That seems doubtful since it is based on projections in the US in respect of online gambling growth that are not materializing and most online gambling companies are saying that there is a current retraction in the market, especially in Europe. 2. The Report says that as between poker, casinos, betting and bingo, in the online gambling environment only poker and casinos are money laundering risks – an inaccurate statement not based on fact or supported by any evidence. There is no greater inherent risk with poker or casinos than with betting or bingo. 3. The Report purportedly looked at licensed online gambling around the globe which it described as “regulated gambling” and with respect to Canada, for example, it stated that Canada has a whopping 120 online regulated gambling websites. Actually, it only has three regulated online gambling sites – those operated and managed pursuant to the Criminal Code of Canada and provincial gaming control legislation by the provincial governments in British Columbia, Quebec and Manitoba. Canada never had and does not have 120 regulated online gambling websites. 4. The Report describes how money laundering at online gambling sites occurs – purportedly by what we call in the industry “minimal play” whereby in the land based environment for example, a person feeds a slot machine with say $100,000 and cashes out after minimal play for a casino cheque. According to the Report, gamblers go online and invest proceeds of crime in “minimal play” transactions then cash out, presumably with cleaned funds; or in a second scenario, they play online and with the gambling wins (the Report assumes gamblers always wins whereas the reality is that the house always wins) they purchase illegal goods (likely drugs) which allows the seller of the illegal goods to earn revenue tax free and the purchaser to acquire goods online illegally. Both scenarios are preposterous. In the first scenario, gamblers who engage in minimal play then cash out online have gained no money laundering benefit because they have not structured or washed the funds at all – all they have done is moved funds online and the remainder comes right back to them from the casino operator in the same form. Money launderers need to move money through multiple sources to hide its origins – it defeats the purpose when the recipient of it remits it back to the launderer. In the second scenario, most money launderers would not use proceeds of crime to acquire illegal goods, such as drugs, as a money laundering method and expose themselves to additional risk of detection by law enforcement. They almost always use proceeds of crime to buy something legal – that’s how it gets cleaned. To suggest otherwise would be to suggest that money launderers are double dirtying the funds as a money laundering method rather than attempting to launder funds. 5. The Report states that the use of digital currencies such as Bitcoin at licensed online gambling sites makes it less likely that transactions will be subject to scrutiny of deposits and withdrawals, increasing money laundering risks. However, at the present time, there are no licensed and regulated gambling entities in the world that accept digital currencies directly as a payment method – that is because no gambling regulator has approved the use of digital currencies for gambling purposes. It is not possible, therefore, for the acceptance of Bitcoin as a payment method at regulated online gambling sites to cause an increase in the risk of money laundering – simply because Bitcoin cannot even be accepted at regulated gambling sites. Until Bitcoin companies are vetted, registered and found suitable by gaming regulators to be engaged in legalized gambling, this will not change and we are at least a year away from that potentially occurring.
4,620
<h4>Laundering through illegal gambling makes no sense</h4><p>Christine <strong>Duhaime 14</strong>, BA, JD, Certified Financial Crime and Anti-Money Laundering Law Specialist, Jackpot or not? Report says online gambling sites and Bitcoin facilitate money laundering but the Report has inaccuracies, www.antimoneylaunderinglaw.com/2014/04/jackpot-or-not-report-says-online-gambling-sites-and-bitcoin-facilitate-money-laundering-but-the-report-is-inaccurate.html</p><p><u>According to a report</u> released by McAfee Labs, available here entitled “Jackpot! Money Laundering Through Online Gambling,” <u>the global <mark>online gambling</u></mark> <u>sector <mark>appears</mark> to be <mark>rife with money laundering problems</u></mark> and Bitcoin facilitates the use money laundering in online gambling.</p><p><u><strong><mark>The Report is incorrect</u></strong></mark>. It is based on numerous factual errors and appears to have been <u><mark>written without</mark> consultation with <strong><mark>anti-money laundering experts,</strong></mark> <strong>gambling law experts</strong> or people knowledgeable about</u> Bitcoin and the <u>online gambling</u> environment.</p><p>Here are the six most salient errors or incorrect assumptions in the Report:</p><p>1. <u>The Report claims that the global online gambling sector will grow 30% </u>in three years starting in 2013 (hence the problem of money laundering online will allegedly get worse, not better). <u>That seems doubtful since it is based on projections in the US in respect of online gambling growth that are not materializing and most online gambling companies are saying that there is a current retraction in the market</u>, especially in Europe.</p><p>2. The Report says that as between poker, casinos, betting and bingo, in the online gambling environment only poker and casinos are money laundering risks – an inaccurate statement not based on fact or supported by any evidence. There is no greater inherent risk with poker or casinos than with betting or bingo.</p><p>3. <u>The Report purportedly looked at licensed online gambling around the globe</u> which it described as “regulated gambling” and with respect to Canada, for example, <u>it stated that Canada has a whopping 120 online regulated gambling websites.</u> <u>Actually, it only has three regulated online gambling sites</u> – those operated and managed pursuant to the Criminal Code of Canada and provincial gaming control legislation by the provincial governments in British Columbia, Quebec and Manitoba. Canada never had and does not have 120 regulated online gambling websites.</p><p>4. The Report describes how <u>money laundering</u> at online gambling sites <u>occurs</u> – <u>purportedly by</u> what we call in the industry “<u>minimal play</u>” whereby in the land based environment for example, a person feeds a slot machine with say $100,000 and cashes out after minimal play for a casino cheque. According to the Report, <u><mark>gamblers go online and invest proceeds</mark> of crime <mark>in “minimal play” transactions then cash out</mark>, presumably <mark>with cleaned funds</mark>; or in a second scenario, <mark>they play online and with the gambling wins</u></mark> (the Report assumes gamblers always wins whereas the reality is that the house always wins) <u>they <mark>purchase illegal goods</mark> </u>(<u>likely drugs) which allows the seller of the illegal goods to earn revenue tax free and the purchaser to acquire goods online illegally.</u> <u><strong><mark>Both scenarios are preposterous</u></strong></mark>. In the first scenario, <u>gamblers who engage in minimal play then cash out online have gained no money laundering benefit because they have not structured or washed the funds at all – <mark>all they have done is moved funds online</mark> and <mark>the remainder comes right back to them from the casino operator <strong>in the same form</strong></mark>. <mark>Money launderers need to move money through multiple sources</mark> to hide its origins – <mark>it defeats the purpose when the recipient</mark> of it <mark>remits it back </mark>to the launderer.</u> <u>In the second scenario, most money <mark>launderers would not use proceeds of crime to acquire illegal goods</mark>, such as drugs, as a money laundering method <mark>and expose</mark> <mark>themselves to additional risk </mark>of detection by law enforcement. <mark>They</mark> almost always <mark>use proceeds of crime to buy something legal – that’s how it gets cleaned</u>.</mark> To suggest otherwise would be to suggest that money launderers are double dirtying the funds as a money laundering method rather than attempting to launder funds.</p><p>5. <u>The Report states that the use of digital currencies</u> such as Bitcoin at licensed online gambling sites <u>makes it less likely that transactions will be subject to scrutiny</u> of deposits and withdrawals, increasing money laundering risks. However, at the present time, <u>there are no licensed and regulated gambling entities in the world that accept digital currencies</u> directly <u>as a payment method</u> – that is because no gambling regulator has approved the use of digital currencies for gambling purposes. It is not possible, therefore, for the acceptance of Bitcoin as a payment method at regulated online gambling sites to cause an increase in the risk of money laundering – simply because Bitcoin cannot even be accepted at regulated gambling sites. Until Bitcoin companies are vetted, registered and found suitable by gaming regulators to be engaged in legalized gambling, this will not change and we are at least a year away from that potentially occurring.</p>
null
null
Costa Rica
430,679
5
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,381
Vote in the next few weeks
Reuters 1/15
Reuters 1/15/2015 (Iran bill debate seen in Senate by early February, http://www.reuters.com/article/2015/01/15/us-usa-congress-iran-idUSKBN0KO26U20150115)
The chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee said he expected a bill addressing Iran's nuclear program to come to the Senate floor in early February, if not sooner toward the end of January or the first part of February, you’ll see something on the floor
null
The new chairman of the U.S. Senate Foreign Relations Committee said on Thursday he expected a bill addressing Iran's nuclear program to come to the U.S. Senate floor for debate ahead of a vote in early February, if not sooner. "I think sometime toward the end of January or the first part of February, you’ll see something being debated on the Senate floor," Republican Senator Bob Corker told reporters at a retreat for Republican lawmakers in Hershey, Pennsylvania.
468
<h4>Vote in the next few weeks</h4><p><strong>Reuters 1/15</strong>/2015 (Iran bill debate seen in Senate by early February, http://www.reuters.com/article/2015/01/15/us-usa-congress-iran-idUSKBN0KO26U20150115)</p><p><u>The</u> new <u>chairman</u> <u>of the</u> U.S. <u>Senate Foreign Relations Committee said</u> on Thursday <u>he expected a bill addressing Iran's nuclear program to come to the</u> U.S. <u>Senate floor</u> for debate ahead of a vote <u>in early February, if not sooner</u>. "I think sometime <u>toward the end of January or the first part of February, you’ll see something</u> being debated <u>on the</u> Senate <u>floor</u>," Republican Senator Bob Corker told reporters at a retreat for Republican lawmakers in Hershey, Pennsylvania.</p>
null
null
Top of Agenda
430,680
4
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,382
We legalize sales, not purchases – their turns don’t apply
Gill 2
Gill 2 Michael Gill, Ph.D., Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, College of Charleston AND Robert Sade, M.D.,Professor in the Department of Surgery and Director of the Institute of Human Values in Health Care, Medical University of South Carolina. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12.1 (2002) 17-45
of_ethics_journal/v012/12.1gill.html it ought to be legal for a person to be paid for one of his or her kidneys. We are not arguing that it ought to be legal for a potential recipient to buy a kidney in an open market. We propose that the buyers of kidneys be the agencies in charge of kidney procurement or transplantation; We assume that allocation of kidneys will be based on medical criteria, as in the existing allocation system for cadaveric organs. Kidneys will not be traded in an unregulated market. A similar system is currently in place for blood products: a person can receive money for providing blood products the legalization of kidney sales will increase the number of kidneys that are transplanted each year and thus save the lives of people who would otherwise die. Our proposed kidney sales are more like the sale of blood products in that both involve the market only in acquisition and not in allocation: the current system pays people for plasma while continuing to distribute blood products without regard to patients' economic status, just as we propose for kidneys Our proposal does not address the purchase of kidneys, which is a separate question. Many of the arguments against legalizing the purchase of kidneys do not apply to the sale of kidneys. For example, one argument against permitting the buying of kidneys is that it will reduce the number of donated kidneys and harm the poor who will not be able to afford to buy a kidney. Both arguments rest on empirical claims that are often stated as fact, yet have no supporting evidence. Even if the empirical claims were accurate The important point is that our proposal will not be affected either way. our proposal can be reasonably expected both to increase the overall number of kidneys for transplantation and to increase the chances that a poor person who needs a kidney will receive one. Therefore, in arguing for the legalization of kidney sales, we put aside the separate question of whether buying kidneys ought to be legal as well.
are not arguing that it ought to be legal to buy a kidney in an open market. We propose that buyers be the agencies in charge of procurement allocation of kidneys will be based on medical criteria not an unregulated market the purchase of kidneys, is a separate question. Many arguments against legalizing the purchase do not apply to the sale . , one argument against permitting buying kidneys is that it will reduce the number of donated kidneys and harm the poor who will not be able to afford a kidney. Both arguments rest on empirical claims that have no supporting evidence. our proposal will increase the overall number of kidneys for transplantation and increase the chances that a poor person who needs a kidney will receive one
Paying for Kidneys: The Case against Prohibition http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/kennedy_institute_ of_ethics_journal/v012/12.1gill.html First, we are arguing for the claim that it ought to be legal for a person to be paid for one of his or her kidneys. We are not arguing that it ought to be legal for a potential recipient to buy a kidney in an open market. We propose that the buyers of kidneys be the agencies in charge of kidney procurement or transplantation; that is, we propose that such agencies should be allowed to use financial incentives to acquire kidneys. We assume that allocation of kidneys will be based on medical criteria, as in the existing allocation system for cadaveric organs. Kidneys will not be traded in an unregulated market. 2 A similar system is currently in place for blood products: a person can receive money for providing blood products, but one's chances of receiving blood are distinct from one's financial status. We further note that transplant recipients or their agents—e.g., insurance companies, Medicaid—pay for organs now, compensating the organ procurement organization that organizes the organ retrieval, the surgeon who removes the organ, the hospital where the organ is procured, and so forth. The only component of the organ procurement process not currently paid is the most critical component, the possessor of the kidney, who is sine qua non for organ availability. Second, we believe the legalization of kidney sales will increase the number of kidneys that are transplanted each year and thus save the lives of people who would otherwise die. We base this belief on two views that seem to us very plausible: first, that financial incentives will induce some people to give up a kidney for transplantation who would otherwise not have done so; and second, that the existence of financial incentives will not decrease significantly the current level of live kidney donations. The first view seems to us to follow from the basic idea that people are more likely to do something if they are going to get paid for it. The second view seems to us to follow from the fact that a very large majority of live kidney donations occur between family members and the idea that the motivation of a sister who donates a kidney to a brother, or a parent who donates a kidney to a child, will not be altered by the existence of financial incentives. Although we think these views are plausible, we acknowledge that there is no clear evidence that they are true. If subsequent research were to establish that the legalization of kidney sales would lead to a decrease in the number of kidneys that are transplanted each year, some of the arguments we make would be substantially weakened. 3 Third, we are arguing for allowing payment to living kidney donors, but many of the kidneys available for transplantation come from cadavers. [End Page 19] We believe that payment for cadaveric organs also ought to be legalized, but we will not discuss that issue here. If we successfully make the case for allowing payment to living donors, the case for payment for cadaveric kidneys should follow easily. The Prima Facie Case for Kidney Sales With these preliminary points in mind, we will proceed to the initial argument for permitting payment for kidneys. 4 This argument is based on two claims: the "good donor claim" and the "sale of tissue claim." The good donor claim contends that it is and ought to be legal for a living person to donate one of his or her kidneys to someone else who needs a kidney in order to survive. These donations typically consist of someone giving a kidney to a sibling, spouse, or child, but there are also cases of individuals donating to strangers. Such donations account for about half of all kidney transplants. 5 Our society, moreover, does not simply allow such live kidney donations. Rather, we actively praise and encourage them. 6 We typically take them to be morally unproblematic cases of saving a human life. The sale of tissue claim contends that it is and ought to be legal for living persons to sell parts of their bodies. We can sell such tissues as hair, sperm, and eggs, but the body parts we focus on here are blood products. A kidney is more like blood products than other tissues because both are physical necessities: people need them in order to survive. Our proposed kidney sales are more like the sale of blood products in that both involve the market only in acquisition and not in allocation: the current system pays people for plasma while continuing to distribute blood products without regard to patients' economic status, just as we propose for kidneys. We do not typically praise people who sell their plasma as we do people who donate a kidney to save the life of a sibling. At the same time, most people do not brand commercial blood banks as moral abominations. We generally take them to be an acceptable means of acquiring a resource that is needed to save lives. 7 It is doubtful, for instance, that there would be widespread support for the abolition of payment for plasma if the result were a reduction in supply so severe that thousands of people died every year for lack of blood products. If both the good donor claim and the sale of tissue claim are true, we have at least an initial argument, or prima facie grounds, for holding that payment for kidneys ought to be legal. The good donor claim implies that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer one of his or [End Page 20] her kidneys to someone else, while the sale of tissue claim implies that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer part of his or her body to someone else for money. It thus seems initially plausible to hold that the two claims together imply that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer one of his or her kidneys to someone else for money. Of course, there seems to be an obvious difference between donating a kidney and selling one: motive. Those who donate typically are motivated by benevolence or altruism, while those who sell typically are motivated by monetary self-interest. 8 The sale of tissue claim suggests, however, that this difference on its own is irrelevant to the question of whether kidney sales ought to be legal, because the sale of tissue claim establishes that it ought to be legal to transfer a body part in order to make money. If donating a kidney ought to be legal (the good donor claim), and if the only difference between donating a kidney and selling one is the motive of monetary self-interest, and if the motive of monetary self-interest does not on its own warrant legal prohibition (the sale of tissue claim), then the morally relevant part of the analogy between donating and selling should still obtain and we still have grounds for holding that selling kidneys ought to be legal. There is also an obvious difference between selling a kidney and selling plasma: the invasiveness of the procedure. Phlebotomy for sale of plasma is simple and quick, with no lasting side effects, while parting with a kidney involves major surgery and living with only one kidney thereafter. It is very unlikely, however, that there will be any long-term ill effects from the surgery itself or from life with a single kidney. 9 Indeed, the laws allowing live kidney donations presuppose that the risk to donors is very small and thus morally acceptable. The good donor claim implies, then, that the invasiveness of the procedure of transferring a kidney is not in and of itself a sufficient reason to legally prohibit live kidney transfer. If the only difference between selling plasma and selling a kidney is the risk of the procedure, and if that risk does not constitute grounds for prohibiting live kidney transfers, then the morally relevant part of the analogy between selling plasma and selling a kidney still should obtain and we still have grounds for holding that kidney sales ought to be legal. The point of the preceding two paragraphs is this: if we oppose the sale of kidneys because we think it is too dangerous, then we also should oppose live kidney donations. But we do not oppose live kidney donations because we realize that the risks are acceptably low and worth taking [End Page 21] in order to save lives. So, it is inconsistent to oppose selling kidneys because of the possible dangers while at the same time endorsing the good donor claim. Similarly, if we oppose kidney sales because we think people should not sell body parts, then we should also oppose commercial blood banks. But most people do not oppose blood banks because they realize that the banks play an important role in saving lives. So, it is inconsistent to oppose selling kidneys because it involves payment while at the same time endorsing the sale of tissue claim. 10 The considerable emotional resistance to permitting kidney sales may be based on a combination of distaste for payment and worry about risk. But if neither of these concerns on its own constitutes defensible grounds for opposing payment, then it seems unlikely that the two of them together will do so. This initial argument does not imply that we should legalize the sale of hearts and livers. The initial argument holds only that, if it is medically safe for living people to donate an organ, then people should also be allowed to sell that organ. But it is not medically safe for a living person to donate his or her heart or liver. Our reliance on the good donor claim does, however, commit us to the idea that if it is morally correct to allow someone to donate an organ or part of an organ, then it is morally correct to allow someone to sell that organ or organ part. If, therefore, it is morally correct to allow people to donate liver lobes and parts of lungs, then, according to our initial argument, it ought to be legal for a person to sell a liver lobe or part of a lung as well. Our proposal does not address the purchase of kidneys, which is a separate question. Many of the arguments against legalizing the purchase of kidneys do not apply to the sale of kidneys. For example, one argument against permitting the buying of kidneys is that it will lead to fewer kidneys for transplantation overall. Another argument is that while allowing individuals to purchase kidneys might not reduce the overall number of kidneys available for transplantation, it will reduce the number of donated kidneys and harm the poor who will not be able to afford to buy a kidney. Both arguments rest on empirical claims that are often stated as fact, yet have no supporting evidence. Even if the empirical claims were accurate, moreover, their moral importance could be disputed. Perhaps there are powerful moral reasons to legalize the buying of organs even if doing so leads to fewer organs overall or reduces the chances of a poor person's receiving a kidney transplant. Then again, perhaps a negative effect on the overall supply of kidneys or on the transplantation prospects [End Page 22] for the poor will turn out to be a conclusive reason not to legalize the buying of kidneys. The important point is that our proposal will not be affected either way. As already noted in our preliminary points, our proposal can be reasonably expected both to increase the overall number of kidneys for transplantation and to increase the chances that a poor person who needs a kidney will receive one. Therefore, in arguing for the legalization of kidney sales, we put aside the separate question of whether buying kidneys ought to be legal as well.
11,563
<h4>We legalize sales, not purchases – their turns don’t apply</h4><p><strong>Gill 2</strong> Michael Gill, Ph.D., Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, College of Charleston AND Robert Sade, M.D.,Professor in the Department of Surgery and Director of the Institute of Human Values in Health Care, Medical University of South Carolina. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12.1 (2002) 17-45</p><p>Paying for Kidneys: The Case against Prohibition http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/kennedy_institute_<u> of_ethics_journal/v012/12.1gill.html</p><p></u>First, we are arguing for the claim that<u> it ought to be legal for a person to be paid for one of his or her kidneys. We <mark>are not arguing that it ought to be legal </mark>for a potential recipient <mark>to buy a kidney in an open market. We propose that </mark>the <mark>buyers </mark>of kidneys <mark>be the agencies in charge of </mark>kidney <mark>procurement </mark>or transplantation; </u>that is, we propose that such agencies should be allowed to use financial incentives to acquire kidneys. <u>We assume that <mark>allocation of kidneys will be based on medical criteria</mark>, as in the existing allocation system for cadaveric organs. Kidneys will <mark>not </mark>be traded in <mark>an unregulated market</mark>.</u> 2 <u>A similar system is currently in place for blood products: a person can receive money for providing blood products</u>, but one's chances of receiving blood are distinct from one's financial status. We further note that transplant recipients or their agents—e.g., insurance companies, Medicaid—pay for organs now, compensating the organ procurement organization that organizes the organ retrieval, the surgeon who removes the organ, the hospital where the organ is procured, and so forth. The only component of the organ procurement process not currently paid is the most critical component, the possessor of the kidney, who is sine qua non for organ availability. Second, we believe <u>the legalization of kidney sales will increase the number of kidneys that are transplanted each year and thus save the lives of people who would otherwise die.</u> We base this belief on two views that seem to us very plausible: first, that financial incentives will induce some people to give up a kidney for transplantation who would otherwise not have done so; and second, that the existence of financial incentives will not decrease significantly the current level of live kidney donations. The first view seems to us to follow from the basic idea that people are more likely to do something if they are going to get paid for it. The second view seems to us to follow from the fact that a very large majority of live kidney donations occur between family members and the idea that the motivation of a sister who donates a kidney to a brother, or a parent who donates a kidney to a child, will not be altered by the existence of financial incentives. Although we think these views are plausible, we acknowledge that there is no clear evidence that they are true. If subsequent research were to establish that the legalization of kidney sales would lead to a decrease in the number of kidneys that are transplanted each year, some of the arguments we make would be substantially weakened. 3 Third, we are arguing for allowing payment to living kidney donors, but many of the kidneys available for transplantation come from cadavers. [End Page 19] We believe that payment for cadaveric organs also ought to be legalized, but we will not discuss that issue here. If we successfully make the case for allowing payment to living donors, the case for payment for cadaveric kidneys should follow easily. The Prima Facie Case for Kidney Sales With these preliminary points in mind, we will proceed to the initial argument for permitting payment for kidneys. 4 This argument is based on two claims: the "good donor claim" and the "sale of tissue claim." The good donor claim contends that it is and ought to be legal for a living person to donate one of his or her kidneys to someone else who needs a kidney in order to survive. These donations typically consist of someone giving a kidney to a sibling, spouse, or child, but there are also cases of individuals donating to strangers. Such donations account for about half of all kidney transplants. 5 Our society, moreover, does not simply allow such live kidney donations. Rather, we actively praise and encourage them. 6 We typically take them to be morally unproblematic cases of saving a human life. The sale of tissue claim contends that it is and ought to be legal for living persons to sell parts of their bodies. We can sell such tissues as hair, sperm, and eggs, but the body parts we focus on here are blood products. A kidney is more like blood products than other tissues because both are physical necessities: people need them in order to survive. <u>Our proposed kidney sales are more like the sale of blood products in that both involve the market only in acquisition and not in allocation: the current system pays people for plasma while continuing to distribute blood products without regard to patients' economic status, just as we propose for kidneys</u>. We do not typically praise people who sell their plasma as we do people who donate a kidney to save the life of a sibling. At the same time, most people do not brand commercial blood banks as moral abominations. We generally take them to be an acceptable means of acquiring a resource that is needed to save lives. 7 It is doubtful, for instance, that there would be widespread support for the abolition of payment for plasma if the result were a reduction in supply so severe that thousands of people died every year for lack of blood products. If both the good donor claim and the sale of tissue claim are true, we have at least an initial argument, or prima facie grounds, for holding that payment for kidneys ought to be legal. The good donor claim implies that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer one of his or [End Page 20] her kidneys to someone else, while the sale of tissue claim implies that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer part of his or her body to someone else for money. It thus seems initially plausible to hold that the two claims together imply that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer one of his or her kidneys to someone else for money. Of course, there seems to be an obvious difference between donating a kidney and selling one: motive. Those who donate typically are motivated by benevolence or altruism, while those who sell typically are motivated by monetary self-interest. 8 The sale of tissue claim suggests, however, that this difference on its own is irrelevant to the question of whether kidney sales ought to be legal, because the sale of tissue claim establishes that it ought to be legal to transfer a body part in order to make money. If donating a kidney ought to be legal (the good donor claim), and if the only difference between donating a kidney and selling one is the motive of monetary self-interest, and if the motive of monetary self-interest does not on its own warrant legal prohibition (the sale of tissue claim), then the morally relevant part of the analogy between donating and selling should still obtain and we still have grounds for holding that selling kidneys ought to be legal. There is also an obvious difference between selling a kidney and selling plasma: the invasiveness of the procedure. Phlebotomy for sale of plasma is simple and quick, with no lasting side effects, while parting with a kidney involves major surgery and living with only one kidney thereafter. It is very unlikely, however, that there will be any long-term ill effects from the surgery itself or from life with a single kidney. 9 Indeed, the laws allowing live kidney donations presuppose that the risk to donors is very small and thus morally acceptable. The good donor claim implies, then, that the invasiveness of the procedure of transferring a kidney is not in and of itself a sufficient reason to legally prohibit live kidney transfer. If the only difference between selling plasma and selling a kidney is the risk of the procedure, and if that risk does not constitute grounds for prohibiting live kidney transfers, then the morally relevant part of the analogy between selling plasma and selling a kidney still should obtain and we still have grounds for holding that kidney sales ought to be legal. The point of the preceding two paragraphs is this: if we oppose the sale of kidneys because we think it is too dangerous, then we also should oppose live kidney donations. But we do not oppose live kidney donations because we realize that the risks are acceptably low and worth taking [End Page 21] in order to save lives. So, it is inconsistent to oppose selling kidneys because of the possible dangers while at the same time endorsing the good donor claim. Similarly, if we oppose kidney sales because we think people should not sell body parts, then we should also oppose commercial blood banks. But most people do not oppose blood banks because they realize that the banks play an important role in saving lives. So, it is inconsistent to oppose selling kidneys because it involves payment while at the same time endorsing the sale of tissue claim. 10 The considerable emotional resistance to permitting kidney sales may be based on a combination of distaste for payment and worry about risk. But if neither of these concerns on its own constitutes defensible grounds for opposing payment, then it seems unlikely that the two of them together will do so. This initial argument does not imply that we should legalize the sale of hearts and livers. The initial argument holds only that, if it is medically safe for living people to donate an organ, then people should also be allowed to sell that organ. But it is not medically safe for a living person to donate his or her heart or liver. Our reliance on the good donor claim does, however, commit us to the idea that if it is morally correct to allow someone to donate an organ or part of an organ, then it is morally correct to allow someone to sell that organ or organ part. If, therefore, it is morally correct to allow people to donate liver lobes and parts of lungs, then, according to our initial argument, it ought to be legal for a person to sell a liver lobe or part of a lung as well. <u>Our proposal does not address <mark>the purchase of kidneys, </mark>which <mark>is a separate question. Many </mark>of the <mark>arguments against legalizing the purchase </mark>of kidneys <mark>do not apply to the sale </mark>of kidneys<mark>.</u> <u></mark>For example<mark>, one argument against permitting </mark>the <mark>buying </mark>of <mark>kidneys is that it</u></mark> will lead to fewer kidneys for transplantation overall. Another argument is that while allowing individuals to purchase kidneys might not reduce the overall number of kidneys available for transplantation, it <u><mark>will reduce the number of donated kidneys and harm the poor who will not be able to afford </mark>to buy <mark>a kidney.</u> <u>Both arguments rest on empirical claims that </mark>are often stated as fact, yet<mark> have no supporting evidence. </mark>Even if the empirical claims were accurate</u>, moreover, their moral importance could be disputed. Perhaps there are powerful moral reasons to legalize the buying of organs even if doing so leads to fewer organs overall or reduces the chances of a poor person's receiving a kidney transplant. Then again, perhaps a negative effect on the overall supply of kidneys or on the transplantation prospects [End Page 22] for the poor will turn out to be a conclusive reason not to legalize the buying of kidneys. <u>The important point is that <mark>our proposal will </mark>not be affected either way.</u> As already noted in our preliminary points, <u>our proposal can be reasonably expected both to<mark> increase the overall number of kidneys for transplantation and </mark>to <mark>increase the chances that a poor person who needs a kidney will receive one</mark>. Therefore, in arguing for the legalization of kidney sales, we put aside the separate question of whether buying kidneys ought to be legal as well. </p></u>
null
null
Contention 3 The Plan solves
430,594
8
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,383
The system will be abused
Arras 97
John D. Arras 97, Porterfield Professor of Biomedical Ethics and Director of Bioethics Minor Program (PhD from Northwestern), 1997, Physician-Assisted Suicide: A Tragic View, Journal of Contemporary Health Law & Policy, Volume 13 Issue 2, http://scholarship.law.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1364&context=jchlp
The slippery slope argument argues that whatever criteria for justifiable PAS and active euthanasia ultimately are chosen, abuse of the system is highly likely to follow patients who fall outside the ambit of our justifiable criteria will soon be candidates for death This resembles an empirical slope argument as it is based on an empirical prediction of what is likely to happen when we insert a particular social practice into our existing social system proponents of PAS concur that any policy must meet requirements given social reality all three assumptions are ¶ problematic
The slippery slope argues that whatever criteria for justifiable PAS are chosen abuse of the system is highly likely to follow patients who fall outside the ambit of justifiable criteria will soon be candidates This resembles an empirical slope argument based on an empirical prediction of what is likely to happen when we insert a social practice into our existing system proponents of PAS concur that any policy must meet requirements given social reality all three are ¶ problematic
The second prong of the slippery slope argument argues that whatever criteria for justifiable PAS and active euthanasia ultimately are chosen, abuse of the system is highly likely to follow. In other words, patients who fall outside the ambit of our justifiable criteria will soon be candidates for death. This prong resembles what I have elsewhere called an 32 "empirical slope argument, as it is based not on the close logical re- semblance of concepts or justifications, but rather on an empirical prediction of what is likely to happen when we insert a particular social practice into our existing social system. ¶ In order to reassure skeptics, the proponents of PAS/euthanasia concur ¶ that any potentially justifiable social policy in this area must meet at least ¶ the following three requirements.33 The policy would have to insist: first, ¶ that all requests for death be truly voluntary; second, that all reasonable ¶ alternatives to PAS and active euthanasia must be explored before acceding to a patient's wishes; and, third, that a reliable system of reporting all ¶ cases must be established in order to effectively monitor these practices ¶ and respond to abuses. As a social pessimist on these matters, I worry, ¶ given social reality as we know it, that all three assumptions are ¶ problematic.
1,312
<h4>The system will be abused</h4><p>John D. <strong>Arras 97</strong>, Porterfield Professor of Biomedical Ethics and Director of Bioethics Minor Program (PhD from Northwestern), 1997, Physician-Assisted Suicide: A Tragic View, Journal of Contemporary Health Law & Policy, Volume 13 Issue 2, http://scholarship.law.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1364&context=jchlp</p><p><u><mark>The</u></mark> second prong of the <u><mark>slippery slope</mark> argument <mark>argues that whatever criteria for justifiable PAS</mark> and active euthanasia ultimately <mark>are chosen</mark>, <mark>abuse of the system is highly likely to follow</u></mark>. In other words, <u><mark>patients who fall outside the ambit of</mark> our <mark>justifiable criteria will soon be candidates</mark> for death</u>. <u><mark>This</u></mark> prong <u><mark>resembles</u></mark> what I have elsewhere called <u><mark>an</u></mark> 32 "<u><strong><mark>empirical slope argument</u></strong></mark>, <u>as it is <mark>based</mark> </u>not on the close logical re- semblance of concepts or justifications, but rather <u><mark>on</mark> <mark>an empirical prediction of what is likely to happen when we insert a</mark> particular <mark>social practice into our existing</mark> social <mark>system</u></mark>. ¶ In order to reassure skeptics, the <u><mark>proponents of PAS</u></mark>/euthanasia <u><mark>concur</mark> </u>¶<u> <mark>that any</mark> </u>potentially justifiable social <u><mark>policy</u></mark> in this area <u><mark>must meet</u></mark> at least ¶ the following three <u><mark>requirements</u></mark>.33 The policy would have to insist: first, ¶ that all requests for death be truly voluntary; second, that all reasonable ¶ alternatives to PAS and active euthanasia must be explored before acceding to a patient's wishes; and, third, that a reliable system of reporting all ¶ cases must be established in order to effectively monitor these practices ¶ and respond to abuses. As a social pessimist on these matters, I worry, ¶<u> <mark>given social reality</u></mark> as we know it, that <u><strong><mark>all three</mark> assumptions <mark>are ¶ problematic</u></strong></mark>.</p>
Ableism
A2: Autonomy
2NC K
430,682
2
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,384
Nonintrinsic – a logical policymaker could do the plan and not sanction Iran – condo justifies
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Nonintrinsic – a logical policymaker could do the plan and not sanction Iran – condo justifies</h4>
2AC
Politics DA
TPA – 2AC – NDT
430,681
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,385
Econ resilient.
Barnett 9
Barnett 9 [Thomas P.M., is senior managing director of Enterra Solutions LLC and a contributing editor/online columnist for Esquire magazin e His latest book is "Great Powers: America and the World After Bush" (2009). His weekly WPR column, The New Rules, appears every Monday The New Rules: Security Remains Stable Amid Financial Crisis 25/08/2009 http://www.aprodex.com/the-new-rules--security-remains-stable-amid-financial-crisis-398-bl.aspx]
globalization's first worldwide recession has had no impact on international security major economies remain governed by center-left or center-right factions that remain friendly to markets and trade. in a world of globally integrated production chains and interconnected financial markets "diverging interests" hardly constitute signposts for wars up ahead this crisis has proven the great resilience of America's international liberal trade order.
globalization's first worldwide recession has had no impact on international security major economies remain governed by center-left or center-right factions that remain friendly to markets and trade. in a world of globally integrated production chains and interconnected financial markets "diverging interests" hardly constitute signposts for wars up ahead this crisis has proven the great resilience of America's international liberal trade order.
When the global financial crisis struck roughly a year ago, the blogosphere was ablaze with all sorts of scary predictions of, and commentary regarding, ensuing conflict and wars -- a rerun of the Great Depression leading to world war, as it were. Now, as global economic news brightens and recovery -- surprisingly led by China and emerging markets -- is the talk of the day, it's interesting to look back over the past year and realize how globalization's first truly worldwide recession has had virtually no impact whatsoever on the international security landscape. None of the more than three-dozen ongoing conflicts listed by GlobalSecurity.org can be clearly attributed to the global recession. Indeed, the last new entry (civil conflict between Hamas and Fatah in the Palestine) predates the economic crisis by a year, and three quarters of the chronic struggles began in the last century. Ditto for the 15 low-intensity conflicts listed by Wikipedia (where the latest entry is the Mexican "drug war" begun in 2006). Certainly, the Russia-Georgia conflict last August was specifically timed, but by most accounts the opening ceremony of the Beijing Olympics was the most important external trigger (followed by the U.S. presidential campaign) for that sudden spike in an almost two-decade long struggle between Georgia and its two breakaway regions. Looking over the various databases, then, we see a most familiar picture: the usual mix of civil conflicts, insurgencies, and liberation-themed terrorist movements. Besides the recent Russia-Georgia dust-up, the only two potential state-on-state wars (North v. South Korea, Israel v. Iran) are both tied to one side acquiring a nuclear weapon capacity -- a process wholly unrelated to global economic trends. And with the United States effectively tied down by its two ongoing major interventions (Iraq and Afghanistan-bleeding-into-Pakistan), our involvement elsewhere around the planet has been quite modest, both leading up to and following the onset of the economic crisis: e.g., the usual counter-drug efforts in Latin America, the usual military exercises with allies across Asia, mixing it up with pirates off Somalia's coast). Everywhere else we find serious instability we pretty much let it burn, occasionally pressing the Chinese -- unsuccessfully -- to do something. Our new Africa Command, for example, hasn't led us to anything beyond advising and training local forces. So, to sum up: * No significant uptick in mass violence or unrest (remember the smattering of urban riots last year in places like Greece, Moldova and Latvia?); * The usual frequency maintained in civil conflicts (in all the usual places); * Not a single state-on-state war directly caused (and no great-power-on-great-power crises even triggered); * No great improvement or disruption in great-power cooperation regarding the emergence of new nuclear powers (despite all that diplomacy); * A modest scaling back of international policing efforts by the system's acknowledged Leviathan power (inevitable given the strain); and * No serious efforts by any rising great power to challenge that Leviathan or supplant its role. (The worst things we can cite are Moscow's occasional deployments of strategic assets to the Western hemisphere and its weak efforts to outbid the United States on basing rights in Kyrgyzstan; but the best include China and India stepping up their aid and investments in Afghanistan and Iraq.) Sure, we've finally seen global defense spending surpass the previous world record set in the late 1980s, but even that's likely to wane given the stress on public budgets created by all this unprecedented "stimulus" spending. If anything, the friendly cooperation on such stimulus packaging was the most notable great-power dynamic caused by the crisis. Can we say that the world has suffered a distinct shift to political radicalism as a result of the economic crisis? Indeed, no. The world's major economies remain governed by center-left or center-right political factions that remain decidedly friendly to both markets and trade. In the short run, there were attempts across the board to insulate economies from immediate damage (in effect, as much protectionism as allowed under current trade rules), but there was no great slide into "trade wars." Instead, the World Trade Organization is functioning as it was designed to function, and regional efforts toward free-trade agreements have not slowed. Can we say Islamic radicalism was inflamed by the economic crisis? If it was, that shift was clearly overwhelmed by the Islamic world's growing disenchantment with the brutality displayed by violent extremist groups such as al-Qaida. And looking forward, austere economic times are just as likely to breed connecting evangelicalism as disconnecting fundamentalism. At the end of the day, the economic crisis did not prove to be sufficiently frightening to provoke major economies into establishing global regulatory schemes, even as it has sparked a spirited -- and much needed, as I argued last week -- discussion of the continuing viability of the U.S. dollar as the world's primary reserve currency. Naturally, plenty of experts and pundits have attached great significance to this debate, seeing in it the beginning of "economic warfare" and the like between "fading" America and "rising" China. And yet, in a world of globally integrated production chains and interconnected financial markets, such "diverging interests" hardly constitute signposts for wars up ahead. Frankly, I don't welcome a world in which America's fiscal profligacy goes undisciplined, so bring it on -- please! Add it all up and it's fair to say that this global financial crisis has proven the great resilience of America's post-World War II international liberal trade order.
5,860
<h4>Econ resilient.</h4><p><u><strong>Barnett 9</u></strong> [Thomas P.M., is senior managing director of Enterra Solutions LLC and a contributing editor/online columnist for Esquire magazin e His latest book is "Great Powers: America and the World After Bush" (2009). His weekly WPR column, The New Rules, appears every Monday The New Rules: Security Remains Stable Amid Financial Crisis 25<u><mark>/08/2009 http://www.aprodex.com/the-new-rules--security-remains-stable-amid-financial-crisis-398-bl.aspx]</p><p></u></mark>When the global financial crisis struck roughly a year ago, the blogosphere was ablaze with all sorts of scary predictions of, and commentary regarding, ensuing conflict and wars -- a rerun of the Great Depression leading to world war, as it were. Now, as global economic news brightens and recovery -- surprisingly led by China and emerging markets -- is the talk of the day, it's interesting to look back over the past year and realize how <u><mark>globalization's first</u></mark> truly <u><mark>worldwide recession has had</u></mark> virtually <u><strong><mark>no impact</u></strong></mark> whatsoever <u><mark>on</u></mark> the <u><mark>international security</u></mark> landscape. None of the more than three-dozen ongoing conflicts listed by GlobalSecurity.org can be clearly attributed to the global recession. Indeed, the last new entry (civil conflict between Hamas and Fatah in the Palestine) predates the economic crisis by a year, and three quarters of the chronic struggles began in the last century. Ditto for the 15 low-intensity conflicts listed by Wikipedia (where the latest entry is the Mexican "drug war" begun in 2006). Certainly, the Russia-Georgia conflict last August was specifically timed, but by most accounts the opening ceremony of the Beijing Olympics was the most important external trigger (followed by the U.S. presidential campaign) for that sudden spike in an almost two-decade long struggle between Georgia and its two breakaway regions. Looking over the various databases, then, we see a most familiar picture: the usual mix of civil conflicts, insurgencies, and liberation-themed terrorist movements. Besides the recent Russia-Georgia dust-up, the only two potential state-on-state wars (North v. South Korea, Israel v. Iran) are both tied to one side acquiring a nuclear weapon capacity -- a process wholly unrelated to global economic trends. And with the United States effectively tied down by its two ongoing major interventions (Iraq and Afghanistan-bleeding-into-Pakistan), our involvement elsewhere around the planet has been quite modest, both leading up to and following the onset of the economic crisis: e.g., the usual counter-drug efforts in Latin America, the usual military exercises with allies across Asia, mixing it up with pirates off Somalia's coast). Everywhere else we find serious instability we pretty much let it burn, occasionally pressing the Chinese -- unsuccessfully -- to do something. Our new Africa Command, for example, hasn't led us to anything beyond advising and training local forces. So, to sum up: * No significant uptick in mass violence or unrest (remember the smattering of urban riots last year in places like Greece, Moldova and Latvia?); * The usual frequency maintained in civil conflicts (in all the usual places); * Not a single state-on-state war directly caused (and no great-power-on-great-power crises even triggered); * No great improvement or disruption in great-power cooperation regarding the emergence of new nuclear powers (despite all that diplomacy); * A modest scaling back of international policing efforts by the system's acknowledged Leviathan power (inevitable given the strain); and * No serious efforts by any rising great power to challenge that Leviathan or supplant its role. (The worst things we can cite are Moscow's occasional deployments of strategic assets to the Western hemisphere and its weak efforts to outbid the United States on basing rights in Kyrgyzstan; but the best include China and India stepping up their aid and investments in Afghanistan and Iraq.) Sure, we've finally seen global defense spending surpass the previous world record set in the late 1980s, but even that's likely to wane given the stress on public budgets created by all this unprecedented "stimulus" spending. If anything, the friendly cooperation on such stimulus packaging was the most notable great-power dynamic caused by the crisis. Can we say that the world has suffered a distinct shift to political radicalism as a result of the economic crisis? Indeed, no. The world's <u><mark>major economies remain governed by center-left or center-right</u></mark> political <u><mark>factions that remain</u></mark> decidedly <u><mark>friendly to</u></mark> both <u><mark>markets and trade.</u></mark> In the short run, there were attempts across the board to insulate economies from immediate damage (in effect, as much protectionism as allowed under current trade rules), but there was no great slide into "trade wars." Instead, the World Trade Organization is functioning as it was designed to function, and regional efforts toward free-trade agreements have not slowed. Can we say Islamic radicalism was inflamed by the economic crisis? If it was, that shift was clearly overwhelmed by the Islamic world's growing disenchantment with the brutality displayed by violent extremist groups such as al-Qaida. And looking forward, austere economic times are just as likely to breed connecting evangelicalism as disconnecting fundamentalism. At the end of the day, the economic crisis did not prove to be sufficiently frightening to provoke major economies into establishing global regulatory schemes, even as it has sparked a spirited -- and much needed, as I argued last week -- discussion of the continuing viability of the U.S. dollar as the world's primary reserve currency. Naturally, plenty of experts and pundits have attached great significance to this debate, seeing in it the beginning of "economic warfare" and the like between "fading" America and "rising" China. And yet, <u><mark>in a world of globally integrated production chains and interconnected financial markets</u></mark>, such <u><mark>"diverging interests" hardly constitute signposts for wars up ahead</u></mark>. Frankly, I don't welcome a world in which America's fiscal profligacy goes undisciplined, so bring it on -- please! Add it all up and it's fair to say that <u><mark>this</u></mark> global financial <u><mark>crisis has proven the great resilience of America's</u></mark> post-World War II <u><strong><mark>international liberal trade order.</p></u></strong></mark>
WTO
War
AT: Inevitable
63,397
282
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,386
No nuclear terror.
Chapman 12
Chapman 12 [Stephen, columnist and editorial writer for the Chicago Tribune, CHAPMAN: Nuclear terrorism unlikely May 22, 2012 6:00 AM http://www.oaoa.com/articles/chapman-87719-nuclear-terrorism.html]
Given their inability to do something simple Ohio State University professor John Mueller “the likelihood a terrorist group will come up with an atomic bomb seems vanishingly small.” Russia’s devices are no longer a danger, since weapons that are not maintained quickly become what one expert calls “radioactive scrap metal.” If terrorists were able to steal a Pakistani bomb, they would still have to defeat the arming codes and other safeguards building a bomb requires millions a safe haven and advanced equipment — plus specialized skills Assuming jihadists vault over those Himalayas, they would have to deliver the weapon onto American soil. every step means expanding the circle of people who know what’s going on, multiplying the chance someone will blab, back out or screw up. al-Qaida has only a minuscule chance Given the formidable odds, it won’t bother.
Given their inability to do something simple “the likelihood a terrorist group will come up with an atomic bomb seems vanishingly small.” building a bomb requires millions a safe haven and advanced equipment — plus specialized skills Assuming jihadists vault over those Himalayas, they would have to deliver the weapon onto American soil. every step means expanding the circle of people who know what’s going on, multiplying the chance someone will blab, back out or screw up. al-Qaida has only a minuscule chance Given the formidable odds, it won’t bother.
Given their inability to do something simple — say, shoot up a shopping mall or set off a truck bomb — it’s reasonable to ask whether they have a chance at something much more ambitious. Far from being plausible, argued Ohio State University professor John Mueller in a presentation at the University of Chicago, “the likelihood that a terrorist group will come up with an atomic bomb seems to be vanishingly small.” The events required to make that happen comprise a multitude of Herculean tasks. First, a terrorist group has to get a bomb or fissile material, perhaps from Russia’s inventory of decommissioned warheads. If that were easy, one would have already gone missing. Besides, those devices are probably no longer a danger, since weapons that are not maintained quickly become what one expert calls “radioactive scrap metal.” If terrorists were able to steal a Pakistani bomb, they would still have to defeat the arming codes and other safeguards designed to prevent unauthorized use. As for Iran, no nuclear state has ever given a bomb to an ally — for reasons even the Iranians can grasp. Stealing some 100 pounds of bomb fuel would require help from rogue individuals inside some government who are prepared to jeopardize their own lives. Then comes the task of building a bomb. It’s not something you can gin up with spare parts and power tools in your garage. It requires millions of dollars, a safe haven and advanced equipment — plus people with specialized skills, lots of time and a willingness to die for the cause. Assuming the jihadists vault over those Himalayas, they would have to deliver the weapon onto American soil. Sure, drug smugglers bring in contraband all the time — but seeking their help would confront the plotters with possible exposure or extortion. This, like every other step in the entire process, means expanding the circle of people who know what’s going on, multiplying the chance someone will blab, back out or screw up. That has heartening implications. If al-Qaida embarks on the project, it has only a minuscule chance of seeing it bear fruit. Given the formidable odds, it probably won’t bother.
2,150
<h4>No nuclear terror.</h4><p><u><strong>Chapman 12</u></strong> [Stephen, columnist and editorial writer for the Chicago Tribune, CHAPMAN: Nuclear terrorism unlikely May 22, 2012 6:00 AM http://www.oaoa.com/articles/chapman-87719-nuclear-terrorism.html<u><mark>]</p><p>Given their inability to do something simple</u></mark> — say, shoot up a shopping mall or set off a truck bomb — it’s reasonable to ask whether they have a chance at something much more ambitious. Far from being plausible, argued <u>Ohio State University professor John Mueller</u> in a presentation at the University of Chicago, <u><mark>“the likelihood</u></mark> that <u><mark>a terrorist group will come up with an atomic bomb seems</u></mark> to be <u><strong><mark>vanishingly small.”</u></strong></mark> The events required to make that happen comprise a multitude of Herculean tasks. First, a terrorist group has to get a bomb or fissile material, perhaps from <u>Russia’s</u> inventory of decommissioned warheads. If that were easy, one would have already gone missing. Besides, those <u>devices are</u> probably <u>no longer a danger, since weapons that are not maintained quickly become what one expert calls “radioactive scrap metal.” If terrorists were able to steal a Pakistani bomb, they would still have to defeat the arming codes and other safeguards</u> designed to prevent unauthorized use. As for Iran, no nuclear state has ever given a bomb to an ally — for reasons even the Iranians can grasp. Stealing some 100 pounds of bomb fuel would require help from rogue individuals inside some government who are prepared to jeopardize their own lives. Then comes the task of <u><mark>building a bomb</u></mark>. It’s not something you can gin up with spare parts and power tools in your garage. It <u><mark>requires millions </u></mark>of dollars, <u><mark>a safe haven and advanced equipment — plus</u></mark> people with <u><mark>specialized skills</u></mark>, lots of time and a willingness to die for the cause. <u><mark>Assuming</u></mark> the <u><mark>jihadists vault over those Himalayas, they would have to deliver the weapon onto American soil.</u></mark> Sure, drug smugglers bring in contraband all the time — but seeking their help would confront the plotters with possible exposure or extortion. This, like <u><mark>every</u></mark> other <u><mark>step</u></mark> in the entire process, <u><mark>means expanding the circle of people who know what’s going on, multiplying the chance someone will blab, back out or screw up.</u></mark> That has heartening implications. If <u><mark>al-Qaida </u></mark>embarks on the project, it <u><mark>has <strong>only a minuscule chance</u></strong></mark> of seeing it bear fruit. <u><mark>Given the formidable odds, <strong>it</u></strong></mark> probably <u><strong><mark>won’t bother.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
*****1NC Nuclear Terror
18,931
81
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,387
Review of literature concludes that sales will increase supply
Beard et al 13
Beard et al 13 T. Randolph "Randy" Beard, Professor of Economics at Auburn University.; Rigmar Osterkamp, Fellow at the School for Political Studies at University of Munich.; And David L. Kaserman, Torchmark Professor of Economics at Auburn University.2013 The Global Organ Shortage: Economic Causes, Human Consequences, Policy Responses
On balance, a fair-minded reading of the evidence suggests that compensation for donors, if done correctly and sensibly, would increase, probably substantially, the number of organs available for transplant. In the cases of both deceased donors (and their families) and living donors, available evidence confirms the observation that people respond to incentives.
On balance a fair reading of the evidence suggests that compensation for donors would increase substantially the number of organs available for transplant both deceased donors (and their families) and living donors respond to incentives
On balance, a fair-minded reading of the evidence suggests that compensation for donors, if done correctly and sensibly, would increase, probably substantially, the number of organs available for transplant. In the cases of both deceased donors (and their families) and living donors, available evidence confirms the observation that people respond to incentives.
363
<h4>Review of literature concludes that sales will increase supply</h4><p><strong>Beard et al 13</strong> T. Randolph "Randy" Beard, Professor of Economics at Auburn University.; Rigmar Osterkamp, Fellow at the School for Political Studies at University of Munich.; And David L. Kaserman, Torchmark Professor of Economics at Auburn University.2013 The Global Organ Shortage: Economic Causes, Human Consequences, Policy Responses</p><p><u><mark>On balance</mark>, <mark>a fair</mark>-minded <mark>reading of</mark> <mark>the evidence suggests that compensation for donors</mark>, if done correctly and sensibly, <mark>would increase</mark>, probably <mark>substantially</mark>, <mark>the number of organs available for transplant</mark>. In the cases of <mark>both deceased donors (and their families) and living donors</mark>, available evidence confirms the observation that people <mark>respond to incentives<strong></mark>.</p></u></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 The Plan solves
430,350
6
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,388
Vote before State of the Union
Jerusalem Post 1/14
Jerusalem Post 1/14/2015 (Nuclear talks resume with warnings to Congress over Iran sanctions, http://www.jpost.com/Middle-East/Nuclear-talks-resume-with-warnings-to-Congress-over-Iran-sanctions-387753)
aides on Capitol Hill continue to work on the final touches of a bill that would "trigger" new sanctions on Iran Leadership plans to introduce the bill by the president's State of the Union address. a bill from Congress could "very well lead to a breakdown in these negotiations."
null
The US, United Kingdom, France, Russia, China and Germany seek to end international concerns over the nature of Iran's nuclear program, which many suspect is military in nature. In Washington, however, aides on Capitol Hill continue to work on the final touches of a bill that would "trigger" new sanctions on Iran should talks ultimately fail, or should Tehran violate terms of an interim deal that laid the groundwork for negotiations, formally known as the Joint Plan of Action. Leadership in Congress, now under full Republican control, plans to introduce the bill by the president's State of the Union address. But any bill from Congress regarding new, nuclear-related sanctions on Iran during international talks over its nuclear program will be vetoed by US President Barack Obama, the State Department said this week. "Even with a trigger, if there's a bill that's signed into law, and it is US law, in our mind it is a violation of the Joint Plan of Action— which, as we've said, could encourage Iran to violate it," State Department deputy spokeswoman Marie Harf said on Tuesday. "A sanctions bill, trigger or not, that is passed and signed into law by the president, which we've said we will not do... would be a violation of the JPOA," she continued. If a deal does not come to pass, Harf said, "we could put initial sanctions on Iran in 24 hours." Harf added on Wednesday that a bill from Congress could "very well lead to a breakdown in these negotiations."
1,471
<h4>Vote before State of the Union</h4><p><strong>Jerusalem Post 1/14<u></strong>/2015 (Nuclear talks resume with warnings to Congress over Iran sanctions, http://www.jpost.com/Middle-East/Nuclear-talks-resume-with-warnings-to-Congress-over-Iran-sanctions-387753)</p><p></u>The US, United Kingdom, France, Russia, China and Germany seek to end international concerns over the nature of Iran's nuclear program, which many suspect is military in nature. In Washington, however, <u>aides on Capitol Hill continue to work on the final touches of a bill that would "trigger" new sanctions on Iran</u> should talks ultimately fail, or should Tehran violate terms of an interim deal that laid the groundwork for negotiations, formally known as the Joint Plan of Action. <u>Leadership</u> in Congress, now under full Republican control, <u><strong>plans to introduce the bill by the president's State of the Union address. </u></strong>But any bill from Congress regarding new, nuclear-related sanctions on Iran during international talks over its nuclear program will be vetoed by US President Barack Obama, the State Department said this week. "Even with a trigger, if there's a bill that's signed into law, and it is US law, in our mind it is a violation of the Joint Plan of Action— which, as we've said, could encourage Iran to violate it," State Department deputy spokeswoman Marie Harf said on Tuesday. "A sanctions bill, trigger or not, that is passed and signed into law by the president, which we've said we will not do... would be a violation of the JPOA," she continued. If a deal does not come to pass, Harf said, "we could put initial sanctions on Iran in 24 hours." Harf added on Wednesday that <u>a bill from Congress could "very well lead to a breakdown in these negotiations."</p></u>
null
null
Top of Agenda
430,683
5
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,389
Once legalized, PAS will expand uncontrollably---regulations are a myth
Callahan 2
Daniel Callahan 2, Ph.D.—Senior Research Scholar and President Emeritus of the Hastings Center and co-director of the Yale-Hastings Program in Ethics and Health Policy, “Reason, Self-Determination, and Physician-Assisted Suicide”, 2002, found in “The Case against Assisted Suicide For the Right to End-of-Life Care” by Kathleen Foley and Herbert Hendin, 2002, Johns Hopkins Press, e-book, http://site.ebrary.com.turing.library.northwestern.edu/lib/northwestern/docDetail.action?docID=10021569&ppg=1
Physical pain and psychological suffering are great evils to relieve them by assisted suicide is an even greater evil. Those practices threaten the future security of the living Once a society allows one person to take the life of another based on their mutual private standards of a life worth living, there can be no safe or sure way to contain the deadly virus thus introduced. It will go where it will thereafter The belief that physician-assisted suicide can be safely regulated is a myth confidentiality of the doctor-patient relationship makes it impossible to provide adequate oversight we cannot know what goes on in the privacy of the doctor-patient encounter, we can never know whether, and to what extent, laws regulating physician-assisted suicide will be violated or ignored physicians will have enormous discretion but no way of knowing how to make a definitive evaluation of the extent of, or the legitimacy of, the suffering the patient reports.
pain and suffering are great evils assisted suicide is an even greater evil The belief that p a s can be regulated is a myth confidentiality of the doctor-patient relationship makes it impossible to provide adequate oversight we can never know what laws will be violated physicians will have discretion but no way to make a definitive evaluation of suffering
Physical pain and psychological suffering among those who are critically ill and dying are great evils. The attempt to relieve them by the introduction of euthanasia and assisted suicide is an even greater evil. Those practices threaten the future security of the living. They no less threaten the dying themselves. Once a society allows one person to take the life of another based on their mutual private standards of a life worth living, there can be no safe or sure way to contain the deadly virus thus introduced. It will go where it will thereafter. The belief that physician-assisted suicide can be safely regulated is a myth—the confidentiality of the doctor-patient relationship makes it impossible to provide adequate oversight. Since we cannot know what goes on in the privacy of the doctor-patient encounter, we can never know whether, and to what extent, laws regulating physician-assisted suicide (and euthanasia as well) will be violated or ignored. The lack of any correlation between suffering and a desire for suicide means, of necessity, that physicians will have enormous discretion in assisting in suicide—but no way of knowing how to make a definitive evaluation of the extent of, or the legitimacy of, the suffering the patient reports.
1,259
<h4>Once legalized, PAS will expand uncontrollably---regulations are a myth</h4><p>Daniel <strong>Callahan 2</strong>, Ph.D.—Senior Research Scholar and President Emeritus of the Hastings Center and co-director of the Yale-Hastings Program in Ethics and Health Policy, “Reason, Self-Determination, and Physician-Assisted Suicide”, 2002, found in “The Case against Assisted Suicide For the Right to End-of-Life Care” by Kathleen Foley and Herbert Hendin, 2002, Johns Hopkins Press, e-book, http://site.ebrary.com.turing.library.northwestern.edu/lib/northwestern/docDetail.action?docID<u>=10021569&ppg=1</p><p>Physical <mark>pain and</mark> psychological <mark>suffering</mark> </u>among those who are critically ill and dying <u><mark>are great evils</u></mark>. The attempt <u>to relieve them by</u> the introduction of euthanasia and <u><mark>assisted suicide is an <strong>even greater evil</strong></mark>.</u> <u>Those practices threaten the future security of the living</u>. They no less threaten the dying themselves. <u>Once a society allows one person to take the life of another based on their mutual private standards of a life worth living, there can be no safe or sure way to contain the deadly virus thus introduced.</u> <u>It will go where it will thereafter</u>. <u><mark>The belief that <strong>p</strong></mark>hysician-<strong><mark>a</strong></mark>ssisted <strong><mark>s</strong></mark>uicide <mark>can be</mark> safely <mark>regulated <strong>is a myth</u></strong></mark>—the <u><mark>confidentiality of the doctor-patient relationship makes it <strong>impossible</strong> to provide <strong>adequate oversight</u></strong></mark>. Since <u>we cannot know what goes on in the privacy of the doctor-patient encounter, <mark>we can never know</mark> whether, and to <mark>what</mark> extent, <mark>laws</mark> regulating physician-assisted suicide</u> (and euthanasia as well) <u><mark>will be violated</mark> or ignored</u>. The lack of any correlation between suffering and a desire for suicide means, of necessity, that <u><mark>physicians will have</mark> enormous <mark>discretion</u></mark> in assisting in suicide—<u><mark>but no way</mark> of knowing how <mark>to make a definitive evaluation of</mark> the extent of, or the legitimacy of, the <mark>suffering</mark> the patient reports. </p></u>
Ableism
A2: Autonomy
2NC K
429,677
7
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,390
Obama doesn’t push the plan– empirics
AP 13
AP 13 Associated Press Health24 Updated 27 November 2013 US keeps ban on organ sales intact
The US government has proposed legislation to keep the ban on buying or selling organs intact. Could paying for bone marrow cells really boost the number of donors? The Obama administration is taking steps to block a federal court ruling that had opened a way to find out. Because it's legal to pay plasma donors court ruling said donors could be paid, too, as Not so fast, say Obama The government now has proposed a regulation to keep the ban intact
The US proposed legislation to keep the ban on selling organs Obama is taking steps to block a court ruling that had opened a way to find out. Because it's legal to pay plasma donors court ruling said donors could be paid, too, as Not so fast, say Obama The government proposed a regulation to keep the ban intact
http://www.health24.com/News/US-keeps-ban-on-organ-sales-intact-20131127 The US government has proposed legislation to keep the ban on buying or selling organs intact. Could paying for bone marrow cells really boost the number of donors? The Obama administration is taking steps to block a federal court ruling that had opened a way to find out. Buying or selling organs has long been illegal, punishable by five years in jail. The 1984 National Organ Transplantation Act that set the payment ban didn't just refer to solid organs it included bone marrow transplants, too. Thousands of people with leukaemia and other blood diseases are saved each year by bone marrow transplants. Thousands more, particularly minorities, still have trouble finding a genetically compatible match even though millions of volunteers have registered as potential donors under the current altruistic system. Rewrite of legal definitions A few years ago, the libertarian Institute for Justice sued the government to challenge that system. It argued that more people with rare marrow types might register to donate and not back out later if they're found to be a match if they had a financial incentive such as a scholarship paid by a non-profit group. Ultimately, a panel of the 9th US Circuit Court of Appeals ruled that some, not all, marrow donors could be compensated citing a technological reason. Years ago, the only way to get marrow cells was to extract them from inside bone. Today, a majority of donors give marrow-producing cells through a blood-filtering process that's similar to donating blood plasma. Because it's legal to pay plasma donors, the December 2011 court ruling said marrow donors could be paid, too, as long as they give in that newer way. "They're not even transplanting your bone marrow. They're transplanting these baby blood cells," said Jeff Rowes, an attorney with the Institute for Justice. It represented some families who'd had trouble finding donors, and was pushing for a study of compensation as a next step. Not so fast, says the Obama administration. The government now has proposed a regulation to keep the ban intact by rewriting some legal definitions to clarify that it covers marrow-producing stem cells no matter how they're derived.
2,259
<h4>Obama doesn’t push the plan– empirics </h4><p><strong>AP 13</strong> Associated Press Health24 Updated 27 November 2013 US keeps ban on organ sales intact</p><p>http://www.health24.com/News/US-keeps-ban-on-organ-sales-intact-20131127</p><p><u><mark>The</mark> <mark>US</mark> government has <mark>proposed legislation to keep the ban on</mark> buying or <mark>selling organs</mark> intact. Could paying for bone marrow cells really boost the number of donors? The <mark>Obama</mark> administration <mark>is taking steps to block a</mark> federal <mark>court ruling that had opened a way to find out.</mark> </u>Buying or selling organs has long been illegal, punishable by five years in jail. The 1984 National Organ Transplantation Act that set the payment ban didn't just refer to solid organs it included bone marrow transplants, too. Thousands of people with leukaemia and other blood diseases are saved each year by bone marrow transplants. Thousands more, particularly minorities, still have trouble finding a genetically compatible match even though millions of volunteers have registered as potential donors under the current altruistic system. Rewrite of legal definitions A few years ago, the libertarian Institute for Justice sued the government to challenge that system. It argued that more people with rare marrow types might register to donate and not back out later if they're found to be a match if they had a financial incentive such as a scholarship paid by a non-profit group. Ultimately, a panel of the 9th US Circuit Court of Appeals ruled that some, not all, marrow donors could be compensated citing a technological reason. Years ago, the only way to get marrow cells was to extract them from inside bone. Today, a majority of donors give marrow-producing cells through a blood-filtering process that's similar to donating blood plasma. <u><mark>Because it's legal to pay plasma donors</u></mark>, the December 2011 <u><mark>court ruling said</u></mark> marrow <u><mark>donors could be paid, too, as</u></mark> long as they give in that newer way. "They're not even transplanting your bone marrow. They're transplanting these baby blood cells," said Jeff Rowes, an attorney with the Institute for Justice. It represented some families who'd had trouble finding donors, and was pushing for a study of compensation as a next step. <u><strong><mark>Not so fast</strong>, say</u></mark>s the <u><mark>Obama</u></mark> administration. <u><mark>The government</mark> now has <mark>proposed a regulation to keep the ban intact</mark> </u>by rewriting some legal definitions to clarify that it covers marrow-producing stem cells no matter how they're derived.</p>
2AC
Politics DA
TPA – 2AC – NDT
430,684
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,391
Prefer conventional weapons.
Craig 11
Craig 11 [Campbell, professor of international relations at the University of Southampton Special Issue: Bringing Critical Realism and Historical Materialism into Critical Terrorism Studies Atomic obsession: nuclear alarmism from Hiroshima to al-Qaeda Critical Studies on Terrorism Volume 4, Issue 1, 2011, April, pages 115-124]
the risk of nuclear terrorism is exceptionally small, along the lines of an asteroid hitting earth. terrorist groups are widely scattered and disorganized – precisely the wrong arrangement for the sustained and centralized project of building an atomic bomb. Looking for immediate results, terrorist groups are likely to go with what works today, rather than committing to a long-term and likely futile project.
the risk of nuclear terrorism is , along the lines of an asteroid hitting earth. terrorist groups are – precisely the wrong arrangement for the sustained and centralized project of building an atomic bomb. Looking for immediate results, terrorist groups are likely to go with what works today, rather than committing to a long-term and likely futile project.
Let us address each of his claims, in reverse order. Mueller suggests that the risk of an act of major nuclear terrorism is exceptionally small, along the lines of an asteroid hitting the earth. Drawing upon his powerful book against terrorism alarmism, Overblown (2006), he shows that serious anti-Western terrorist groups are today widely scattered and disorganized – precisely the wrong kind of arrangement for the sustained and centralized project of building an atomic bomb. Looking for immediate results, terrorist groups are likely to go with what works today, rather than committing to a long-term and likely futile project. He points out, as have other authors, that so-called ‘rogue’ nations, even if they obtain a bomb, are never going to hand it over to terrorists: to do so would utterly negate everything they had worked so hard for. A nation such as Iran that somehow decided to give its bomb to al-Qaeda (leaving aide their completely different objectives) would not only be handing over a weapon that it had spent years and billions to build, and giving up the prestige and deterrence the bomb supposedly confers, it would also be putting itself at acute risk of being on the receiving end of a retaliatory strike once the terrorists did their work. By what rationale would any leader make such a move? The potential costs would be astronomical, the benefits non-existent.
1,389
<h4>Prefer conventional weapons.</h4><p><u><strong>Craig 11</u></strong> [Campbell, professor of international relations at the University of Southampton Special Issue: Bringing Critical Realism and Historical Materialism into Critical Terrorism Studies Atomic obsession: nuclear alarmism from Hiroshima to al-Qaeda Critical Studies on Terrorism Volume 4, Issue 1, 2011, April, pages 115-124]</p><p>Let us address each of his claims, in reverse order. Mueller suggests that <u><mark>the risk of</u></mark> an act of major <u><mark>nuclear terrorism is <strong></mark>exceptionally small</strong><mark>, along the lines of an asteroid hitting</u></mark> the <u><mark>earth.</u></mark> Drawing upon his powerful book against terrorism alarmism, Overblown (2006), he shows that serious anti-Western<u><mark> terrorist groups are</u></mark> today <u><strong>widely scattered and disorganized</strong><mark> – precisely the wrong</u></mark> kind of <u><mark>arrangement for the sustained and centralized project of building an atomic bomb. Looking for immediate results, terrorist groups are likely to go with what works today, rather than committing to a long-term and likely futile project.</u></mark> He points out, as have other authors, that so-called ‘rogue’ nations, even if they obtain a bomb, are never going to hand it over to terrorists: to do so would utterly negate everything they had worked so hard for. A nation such as Iran that somehow decided to give its bomb to al-Qaeda (leaving aide their completely different objectives) would not only be handing over a weapon that it had spent years and billions to build, and giving up the prestige and deterrence the bomb supposedly confers, it would also be putting itself at acute risk of being on the receiving end of a retaliatory strike once the terrorists did their work. By what rationale would any leader make such a move? The potential costs would be astronomical, the benefits non-existent.</p>
null
null
*****1NC Nuclear Terror
267,753
5
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,392
Coercion of the poor does not apply to central purchasing –egg donations prove
Sobota 4
Sobota 4 Margaret R. Sobota, J.D. Candidate (2005), Washington University School of Law. Washington University Law Quarterly Fall, 2004 82 Wash. U. L. Q. 1225 NOTE: THE PRICE OF LIFE: $ 50,000 FOR AN EGG, WHY NOT $ 1,500 FOR A KIDNEY? AN ARGUMENT TO ESTABLISH A MARKET FOR ORGAN PROCUREMENT SIMILAR TO THE CURRENT MARKET FOR HUMAN EGG PROCUREMENT lexis
, the economic coercion argument is based on the false premise that the prices donors will be paid for their organs will be high enough to override their doubts and ethical concerns In the proposed market system for organ procurement, the state will be paying the donors; thus preventing potential wealthy recipients from driving up the prices . With only moderate prices being paid , economic incentives would likely not outweigh a donor's moral objections , and thus no economic coercion would occur. Additionally, the current market system for egg donation suggests that economic coercion would not be a problem in a market for organ procurement. A majority of egg donors are not poor or minority women, and the amounts paid to them for their donations are usually not an "undue inducement to undergo the medical risks involved." These facts suggest that if a system of financial compensation for organ donation were established, comparable to the system already in place for egg donation, there would similarly be no economic coercion of donors
economic coercion argument is based on the false premise that the prices donors will be paid for their organs will be high enough to override their doubts and ethical concerns the state will be paying the donors; thus preventing potential wealthy recipients from driving up the prices With only moderate prices being paid economic incentives would likely not outweigh a donor's moral objections thus no economic coercion dditionally arket for egg donation suggests that economic coercion would not be a problem in a market for organ procurement majority of egg donors are not poor or minority women
A. Arguments Opposing a Market for Organ Procurement The main argument against establishing a market for organ procurement is economic coercion. n141 Market opponents insist that poor, destitute people from around the world will be forced into selling their organs without making an in-formed decision. n142 There are several flaws with this argument. n143 First, the economic coercion argument is based on the false premise that the prices donors will be paid for their organs will be high enough to override their doubts and ethical concerns about becoming a donor. n144 In the proposed market system for organ procurement, either OPOs or the state will be paying the donors; thus preventing potential wealthy recipients from driving up the prices paid for organs. n145 With only moderate prices being paid to organ donors, economic incentives would likely not outweigh a donor's moral objections to donation, and thus no economic coercion would occur. n146 Additionally, the current market system for egg donation suggests that economic coercion would not be a problem in a market for organ procurement. n147 A majority of egg donors are not poor or minority women, and the amounts paid to them for their donations are usually not an "undue inducement to undergo the medical [*1246] risks involved." n148 These facts suggest that if a system of financial compensation for organ donation were established, comparable to the system already in place for egg donation, there would similarly be no economic coercion of donors.
1,526
<h4><strong>Coercion of the poor does not apply to central purchasing –egg donations prove</h4><p>Sobota 4</strong> Margaret R. Sobota, J.D. Candidate (2005), Washington University School of Law. Washington University Law Quarterly Fall, 2004 82 Wash. U. L. Q. 1225 NOTE: THE PRICE OF LIFE: $ 50,000 FOR AN EGG, WHY NOT $ 1,500 FOR A KIDNEY? AN ARGUMENT TO ESTABLISH A MARKET FOR ORGAN PROCUREMENT SIMILAR TO THE CURRENT MARKET FOR HUMAN EGG PROCUREMENT lexis</p><p>A. Arguments Opposing a Market for Organ Procurement</p><p>The main argument against establishing a market for organ procurement is economic coercion. n141 Market opponents insist that poor, destitute people from around the world will be forced into selling their organs without making an in-formed decision. n142 There are several flaws with this argument. n143 First<u>, the <mark>economic coercion argument is based on the false premise that the prices donors will be paid for their organs will be high enough to override their doubts and ethical concerns</mark> </u>about becoming a donor. n144 <u>In the proposed market system for organ procurement, </u>either OPOs or<u> <mark>the state will be paying the donors; thus preventing potential wealthy recipients from driving up the prices</mark> </u>paid for organs<u>.</u> n145 <u><mark>With only moderate prices being paid</mark> </u>to organ donors<u>, <mark>economic incentives would likely not outweigh a donor's moral objections</mark> </u>to donation<u>, and <mark>thus no economic coercion</mark> would occur.</u> n146 <u>A<mark>dditionally</mark>, the current m<mark>arket</mark> system <mark>for egg donation suggests that economic coercion would not be a problem in a market for organ procurement</mark>.</u> n147 <u><strong>A <mark>majority of egg donors are not poor or minority women</strong></mark>, and the amounts paid to them for their donations are usually not an "undue inducement to undergo the medical</u> [*1246] <u>risks involved." </u>n148<u> These facts suggest that if a system of financial compensation for organ donation were established, comparable to the system already in place for egg donation, there would similarly be no economic coercion of donors</u><strong>.</p></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 The Plan solves
430,597
8
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,393
Obama’s using PC on sanctions- top of the agenda, uniqueness doesn’t overwhelm
Politico 1/12
Politico 1/12/2015 (Samantha Power urges GOP Congress not to pursue Iran sanctions, http://www.politico.com/story/2015/01/samantha-power-iran-sanctions-gop-congress-114175.html)
The Obama administration is stepping up its push to stave off sanctions on Iran McConnell is expected to pursue new sanctions in the coming weeks Republicans have taken the Senate and are much less inclined to heed requests for delays sanctions legislation stands a chance of garnering a veto-proof majority
null
The Obama administration is stepping up its push to stave off a bipartisan congressional effort to enact new economic sanctions on Iran as the United States tries to secure a permanent deal to wind down the country’s nuclear program. At a University of Louisville event alongside new Senate Majority Leader Mitch McConnell (R-Ky.), whose chamber is expected to pursue new sanctions in the coming weeks, U.S. Ambassador to the United Nations Samantha Power argued that new congressional sanctions will upset ongoing negotiations with Iran and turn off a multilateral international coalition that has worked together to isolate Iran politically and economically. Power’s remarks carry new urgency: Senate Democratic Leader Harry Reid held off a bipartisan Iran sanctions push during the last Congress, but Republicans have taken the Senate and are much less inclined to heed President Barack Obama’s requests for delays on new sanctions votes. And though Republicans have moved quickly on other policy changes that Obama opposes, like approving the Keystone XL Pipeline and changing Obamacare, Iran sanctions legislation stands a reasonable chance of garnering a veto-proof majority in Congress given the multitude of Iran hawks on Capitol Hill.
1,243
<h4>Obama’s using PC on sanctions- top of the agenda, uniqueness doesn’t overwhelm</h4><p><strong>Politico 1/12</strong>/2015 (Samantha Power urges GOP Congress not to pursue Iran sanctions, http://www.politico.com/story/2015/01/samantha-power-iran-sanctions-gop-congress-114175.html)</p><p><u>The Obama administration is stepping up its push to stave off</u> a bipartisan congressional effort to enact new economic <u>sanctions on Iran</u> as the United States tries to secure a permanent deal to wind down the country’s nuclear program. At a University of Louisville event alongside new Senate Majority Leader Mitch <u>McConnell</u> (R-Ky.), whose chamber <u>is expected to pursue new sanctions in the coming weeks</u>, U.S. Ambassador to the United Nations Samantha Power argued that new congressional sanctions will upset ongoing negotiations with Iran and turn off a multilateral international coalition that has worked together to isolate Iran politically and economically. Power’s remarks carry new urgency: Senate Democratic Leader Harry Reid held off a bipartisan Iran sanctions push during the last Congress, but <u>Republicans have taken the Senate and are much less inclined to heed</u> President Barack Obama’s <u>requests for delays</u> on new sanctions votes. And though Republicans have moved quickly on other policy changes that Obama opposes, like approving the Keystone XL Pipeline and changing Obamacare, Iran <u>sanctions</u> <u>legislation stands a</u> reasonable <u>chance of garnering</u> <u>a veto-proof majority</u> in Congress given the multitude of Iran hawks on Capitol Hill.</p>
null
null
Top of Agenda
430,685
3
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,394
Winners win and political capital’s not key
Hirsch 13 =1)
Hirsch 13 (Michael, Michael Hirsh is chief correspondent for National Journal. He also contributes to 2012 Decoded. Hirsh previously served as the senior editor and national economics correspondent for Newsweek, based in its Washington bureau. He was also Newsweek’s Washington web editor and authored a weekly column for Newsweek.com, “The World from Washington.” Earlier on, he was Newsweek’s foreign editor, guiding its award-winning coverage of the September 11 attacks and the war on terror. He has done on-the-ground reporting in Iraq, Afghanistan, and other places around the world, and served as the Tokyo-based Asia Bureau Chief for Institutional Investor from 1992 to 1994.  “There’s No Such Thing as Political Capital,” http://www.nationaljournal.com/magazine/there-s-no-such-thing-as-political-capital-20130207?page=1)
immigration and gun-control issues illustrates how suddenly shifts in mood can occur and how political interests can align in new ways just as suddenly the pseudo-concept of political capital masks a larger truth about Washington that is kindergarten simple: You just don’t know what you can do until you try. Winning wins.” In theory, and in practice, depending on Obama’s handling of any particular issue, even in a polarized time, he could still deliver on a lot of his second-term goals, depending on his skill and the breaks Unforeseen catalysts can appear, like Newtown Epiphanies can dawn, such as when many Republican Party leaders suddenly woke up in panic to the huge disparity in the Hispanic vote. political scientists who study the elusive calculus of how to pass legislation and run successful presidencies say that political capital is, at best, an empty concept, and that almost nothing in the academic literature successfully quantifies or even defines it. “It can refer to a very abstract thing, like a president’s popularity, but there’s no mechanism there. That makes it kind of useless,” says Richard Bensel, a government professor at Cornell University Even Ornstein concedes that the calculus is far more complex than the term suggests. Winning on one issue often changes the calculation for the next issue; there is never any known amount of capital. The idea here is, if an issue comes up where the conventional wisdom is that president is not going to get what he wants, and he gets it, then each time that happens, it changes the calculus of the other actors” Ornstein says. “If they think he’s going to win, they may change positions to get on the winning side. It’s a bandwagon effect.”
“Winning wins.” Obama’s handling of any issue, even in a polarized time such as huge disparity in the Hispanic vote political capital nothing in the academic literature quantifies it That makes it useless,” Winning on one issue changes the calculation for the next president is not going to get what he wants, and he gets it, then It’s a bandwagon effect.”
Naturally, any president has practical and electoral limits. Does he have a majority in both chambers of Congress and a cohesive coalition behind him? Obama has neither at present. And unless a surge in the economy—at the moment, still stuck—or some other great victory gives him more momentum, it is inevitable that the closer Obama gets to the 2014 election, the less he will be able to get done. Going into the midterms, Republicans will increasingly avoid any concessions that make him (and the Democrats) stronger. But the abrupt emergence of the immigration and gun-control issues illustrates how suddenly shifts in mood can occur and how political interests can align in new ways just as suddenly. Indeed, the pseudo-concept of political capital masks a larger truth about Washington that is kindergarten simple: You just don’t know what you can do until you try. Or as Ornstein himself once wrote years ago, “Winning wins.” In theory, and in practice, depending on Obama’s handling of any particular issue, even in a polarized time, he could still deliver on a lot of his second-term goals, depending on his skill and the breaks. Unforeseen catalysts can appear, like Newtown. Epiphanies can dawn, such as when many Republican Party leaders suddenly woke up in panic to the huge disparity in the Hispanic vote. Some political scientists who study the elusive calculus of how to pass legislation and run successful presidencies say that political capital is, at best, an empty concept, and that almost nothing in the academic literature successfully quantifies or even defines it. “It can refer to a very abstract thing, like a president’s popularity, but there’s no mechanism there. That makes it kind of useless,” says Richard Bensel, a government professor at Cornell University. Even Ornstein concedes that the calculus is far more complex than the term suggests. Winning on one issue often changes the calculation for the next issue; there is never any known amount of capital. “The idea here is, if an issue comes up where the conventional wisdom is that president is not going to get what he wants, and he gets it, then each time that happens, it changes the calculus of the other actors” Ornstein says. “If they think he’s going to win, they may change positions to get on the winning side. It’s a bandwagon effect.”
2,331
<h4><u>Winners win and political capital’s not key</h4><p></u><strong>Hirsch 13</strong> (Michael, Michael Hirsh is chief correspondent for National Journal. He also contributes to 2012 Decoded. Hirsh previously served as the senior editor and national economics correspondent for Newsweek, based in its Washington bureau. He was also Newsweek’s Washington web editor and authored a weekly column for Newsweek.com, “The World from Washington.” Earlier on, he was Newsweek’s foreign editor, guiding its award-winning coverage of the September 11 attacks and the war on terror. He has done on-the-ground reporting in Iraq, Afghanistan, and other places around the world, and served as the Tokyo-based Asia Bureau Chief for Institutional Investor from 1992 to 1994.  “There’s No Such Thing as Political Capital,” http://www.nationaljournal.com/magazine/there-s-no-such-thing-as-political-capital-20130207?page<u><strong>=1)</p><p></u></strong>Naturally, any president has practical and electoral limits. Does he have a majority in both chambers of Congress and a cohesive coalition behind him? Obama has neither at present. And unless a surge in the economy—at the moment, still stuck—or some other great victory gives him more momentum, it is inevitable that the closer Obama gets to the 2014 election, the less he will be able to get done. Going into the midterms, Republicans will increasingly avoid any concessions that make him (and the Democrats) stronger. But the abrupt emergence of the <u>immigration and gun-control issues illustrates how suddenly shifts in mood can occur and how political interests can align in new ways just as suddenly</u>. Indeed, <u>the pseudo-concept of political capital masks a larger truth about Washington that is kindergarten simple: You just don’t know what you can do until you try.</u> Or as Ornstein himself once wrote years ago, <mark>“<u><strong>Winning wins.”</strong></mark> In theory, and in practice, depending on <mark>Obama’s handling of any</mark> particular <mark>issue, <strong>even in a polarized time</strong></mark>, he could still deliver on a lot of his second-term goals, depending on his skill and the breaks</u>. <u>Unforeseen catalysts can appear, like Newtown</u>. <u>Epiphanies can dawn, <mark>such as</mark> when many Republican Party leaders suddenly woke up in panic to the <mark>huge disparity in the Hispanic vote</mark>. </u>Some <u>political scientists who study the elusive calculus of how to pass legislation and run successful presidencies say that <mark>political capital </mark>is, at best, an <strong>empty concept</strong>, and that almost <strong><mark>nothing</strong> in the <strong>academic literature</strong> </mark>successfully <mark>quantifies</mark> or even defines <mark>it</mark>.</u> <u>“It can refer to a very abstract thing, like a president’s popularity, but there’s no mechanism there. <mark>That makes it </mark>kind of <strong><mark>useless</strong>,”</mark> says Richard Bensel, a government professor at Cornell University</u>. <u>Even Ornstein concedes that the calculus is far more complex than the term suggests. <mark>Winning on one issue </mark>often <mark>changes the calculation for the next</mark> issue; there is never any known amount of capital.</u> “<u>The idea here is, if an issue comes up where the conventional wisdom is that <mark>president is not going to get what he wants, and he gets it, then</mark> each time that happens, it changes the calculus of the other actors” Ornstein says. “If they think he’s going to win, they may change positions to get on the winning side. <mark>It’s a <strong>bandwagon effect.”</p></u></strong></mark>
2AC
Politics DA
TPA – 2AC – NDT
23,293
350
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,395
That justifies euthanasia---there’s no way to hold the line
Callahan 2
Daniel Callahan 2, Ph.D.—Senior Research Scholar and President Emeritus of the Hastings Center and co-director of the Yale-Hastings Program in Ethics and Health Policy, “Reason, Self-Determination, and Physician-Assisted Suicide”, 2002, found in “The Case against Assisted Suicide For the Right to End-of-Life Care” by Kathleen Foley and Herbert Hendin, 2002, Johns Hopkins Press, e-book, http://site.ebrary.com.turing.library.northwestern.edu/lib/northwestern/docDetail.action?docID=10021569&ppg=1
We come to a striking pitfall of the arguments for physician-assisted suicide there will remain no logical way to hold the line against euthanasia take care of those unable to take their own lives deny euthanasia to any person who requests it and deny euthanasia physician-assisted suicide to those who suffer but are incompetent even if they do not request it arguments given in favor of euthanasia logically entail the possibility We can erect legal safeguards and specify required procedures to keep that scenario from coming to pass, but over time they will provide poor protection if the logic of the moral premises on which they are based is fatally flawed. The safeguards will appear arbitrary and flimsy and will invite covert evasion or outright rejection.
We come to a striking pitfall of the arguments for p a s there will remain no way to hold the line against euthanasia take care of those unable to take their own lives deny euthanasia to any person who requests it and deny p a s to those who suffer but are incompetent, even if they do not request it safeguards and required procedures will provide poor protection safeguards will appear arbitrary and flimsy and will invite covert evasion or outright rejection.
We come here to a striking pitfall of the common arguments for physician-assisted suicide. Once the key premises of that argument are accepted, there will remain no logical way in the future to (1) for long hold the line against euthanasia, to take care of those physically or psycho- logically unable to take their own lives; (2) deny euthanasia to any competent person who requests it for whatever reason, terminal illness or not; and (3) deny euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide to those who suffer but are incompetent, even if they do not request it. I am not saying that such a scenario will in fact take place, but only that the arguments given in favor of euthanasia logically entail the possibility. We can erect legal safeguards and specify required procedures to keep that scenario from coming to pass, but over time they will provide poor protection if the logic of the moral premises on which they are based is fatally flawed. The safeguards will appear arbitrary and flimsy and will invite covert evasion or outright rejection.
1,046
<h4>That justifies euthanasia---there’s no way to hold the line</h4><p>Daniel <strong>Callahan 2</strong>, Ph.D.—Senior Research Scholar and President Emeritus of the Hastings Center and co-director of the Yale-Hastings Program in Ethics and Health Policy, “Reason, Self-Determination, and Physician-Assisted Suicide”, 2002, found in “The Case against Assisted Suicide For the Right to End-of-Life Care” by Kathleen Foley and Herbert Hendin, 2002, Johns Hopkins Press, e-book, http://site.ebrary.com.turing.library.northwestern.edu/lib/northwestern/docDetail.action?docID<u>=10021569&ppg=1</p><p><mark>We come</u></mark> here <u><mark>to a striking pitfall of the</u></mark> common <u><mark>arguments for <strong>p</strong></mark>hysician-<strong><mark>a</strong></mark>ssisted <strong><mark>s</strong></mark>uicide</u>. Once the key premises of that argument are accepted, <u><mark>there will remain no</mark> logical <mark>way</u></mark> in the future <u><mark>to</u></mark> (1) for long <u><mark>hold the line against euthanasia</u></mark>, to <u><mark>take care of those</u></mark> physically or psycho- logically <u><mark>unable to take their own lives</u></mark>; (2) <u><mark>deny euthanasia to any</u></mark> competent <u><mark>person who requests it</u></mark> for whatever reason, terminal illness or not; <u><mark>and</u></mark> (3) <u><mark>deny</mark> euthanasia</u> and <u><strong><mark>p</strong></mark>hysician-<strong><mark>a</strong></mark>ssisted <strong><mark>s</strong></mark>uicide</u> <u><mark>to those who suffer but are incompetent</u>, <u><strong>even if they do not request it</u></strong></mark>. I am not saying that such a scenario will in fact take place, but only that the <u>arguments given in favor of euthanasia logically entail the possibility</u>. <u>We can erect legal <mark>safeguards and</mark> specify <mark>required procedures</mark> to keep that scenario from coming to pass, but over time they <mark>will provide poor protection</mark> if the logic of the moral premises on which they are based is fatally flawed. The <mark>safeguards will appear <strong>arbitrary and flimsy</strong> and will invite <strong>covert evasion or outright rejection</strong>.</mark> </p></u>
Ableism
A2: Autonomy
2NC K
429,679
6
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,396
The reasons for doing a policy are key to that policy
Hill, 91
Thomas E. Hill, Jr., Professor of Philosophy at the University of North Carolina, 1991 (“The Message of Affirmative Action,” The Affirmative Action Debate (1995), edited by Steven M. Cahn, Published by Routledge, Reprinted from Social Philosophy & Policy, p. 169-170)
What our actions say to others depends largely upon our avowed reasons for acting "the same act" can have very different consequences, depending upon how we choose to justify it. In a sense, acts done for different reasons are not "the same act" even if otherwise similar, and so not merely the consequences but also the moral nature of our acts depend in part on our decisions about the reasons for doing them the message of an act or policy is almost always a relevant factor in the moral assessment of the act or policy Who, for example, does not know the importance of the message expressed in offering money to another person, as well as the dangers of misunderstanding? What is superficially "the same act" can be an offer to buy, an admission of guilt, an expression of gratitude, a contribution to a common cause, a condescending display of superiority, or an outrageous insult. Because all this is so familiar, the extent to which these elementary points are ignored in discussions of the pros and cons of social policies is surprising. The usual presumption is that social policies can be settled entirely by debating the rights involved or by estimating the consequences, narrowly conceived apart from the messages that we want to give and the messages that are likely to be received
What our actions say depends largely on our reasons for acting; the same act" can have different consequences, depending upon how we justify it acts done for different reasons are not "the same act" even if otherwise similar the moral nature of our acts depend on our reasons for doing them. the message of policy is always relevant What is superficially "the same act" can be an admission of guilt gratitude, a contribution the extent to which these elementary points are ignored in discussions of policies is surprising
Actions, as the saying goes, often speak louder than words. There are times, too, when only actions can effectively communicate the message we want to convey, and times when giving a message is a central part of the purpose of action. What our actions say to others depends largely, though not entirely, upon our avowed reasons for acting; and this is a matter for reflective [end page 169] decision, not something we discover later by looking back at what we did and its effects. The decision is important because "the same act" can have very different consequences, depending upon how we choose to justify it. In a sense, acts done for different reasons are not "the same act" even if otherwise similar, and so not merely the consequences but also the moral nature of our acts depend in part on our decisions about the reasons for doing them. Unfortunately, the message actually conveyed by our actions does not depend only on our intentions and reasons, for our acts may have a meaning for others quite at odds with what we hoped to express. Others may misunderstand our intentions, doubt our sincerity, or discern a subtext that undermines the primary message. Even if sincere, well-intended, and successfully conveyed, the message of an act or policy does not by itself justify the means by which it is conveyed; it is almost always a relevant factor, however, in the moral assessment of the act or policy. These remarks may strike you as too obvious to be worth mentioning; for, even if we do not usually express the ideas so abstractly, we are all familiar with them in our daily interactions with our friends, families, and colleagues. Who, for example, does not know the importance of the message expressed in offering money to another person, as well as the dangers of misunderstanding? What is superficially "the same act" can be an offer to buy, an admission of guilt, an expression of gratitude, a contribution to a common cause, a condescending display of superiority, or an outrageous insult. Because all this is so familiar, the extent to which these elementary points are ignored in discussions of the pros and cons of social policies such as affirmative action is surprising. The usual presumption is that social policies can be settled entirely by debating the rights involved or by estimating the consequences, narrowly conceived apart from the messages that we want to give and the messages that are likely to be received.
2,455
<h4>The reasons for doing a policy are key to that policy</h4><p>Thomas E. <strong><mark>Hill</mark>, </strong>Jr., Professor of Philosophy at the University of North Carolina, 19<strong><mark>91</strong></mark> (“The Message of Affirmative Action,” The Affirmative Action Debate (1995), edited by Steven M. Cahn, Published by Routledge, Reprinted from Social Philosophy & Policy, p. 169-170)</p><p>Actions, as the saying goes, often speak louder than words. There are times, too, when only actions can effectively communicate the message we want to convey, and times when giving a message is a central part of the purpose of action. <u><mark>What our actions say</mark> to others <mark>depends largely</u></mark>, though not entirely, <u>up<mark>on our</mark> avowed <mark>reasons for acting</u>;</mark> and this is a matter for reflective [end page 169] decision, not something we discover later by looking back at what we did and its effects. The decision is important because <u>"<mark>the same act" can have </mark>very <mark>different consequences, depending upon how we</mark> choose to <mark>justify it</mark>. In a sense, <mark>acts done for different reasons are not "the same act"</mark> <mark>even if otherwise similar</mark>, and so not merely the consequences but also <mark>the moral nature of our acts depend</mark> in part <mark>on our</mark> decisions about the <mark>reasons for doing them</u>.</mark> Unfortunately, the message actually conveyed by our actions does not depend only on our intentions and reasons, for our acts may have a meaning for others quite at odds with what we hoped to express. Others may misunderstand our intentions, doubt our sincerity, or discern a subtext that undermines the primary message. Even if sincere, well-intended, and successfully conveyed, <u><mark>the message of</mark> an act or <mark>policy</u></mark> does not by itself justify the means by which it is conveyed; it <u><mark>is</mark> almost <mark>always</mark> a <mark>relevant</mark> factor</u>, however, <u>in the moral assessment of the act or policy</u>. These remarks may strike you as too obvious to be worth mentioning; for, even if we do not usually express the ideas so abstractly, we are all familiar with them in our daily interactions with our friends, families, and colleagues. <u>Who, for example, does not know the importance of the message expressed in offering money to another person, as well as the dangers of misunderstanding? <mark>What is superficially "the same act" can be</mark> an offer to buy, <mark>an admission of guilt</mark>, an expression of <mark>gratitude, a contribution</mark> to a common cause, a condescending display of superiority, or an outrageous insult. Because all this is so familiar, <mark>the extent to which these</mark> <mark>elementary points are ignored in discussions of</mark> the pros and cons of social <mark>policies</u></mark> such as affirmative action <u><mark>is surprising</mark>. The usual presumption is that social policies can be settled entirely by debating the rights involved or by estimating the consequences, narrowly conceived apart from the messages that we want to give and the messages that are likely to be received</u>. </p>
null
null
*****1NC Nuclear Terror
234,324
9
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,397
Obama’s PC will sustain the veto now
Einhorn 1/14
Einhorn 1/14/2015 (Robert, senior fellow at the Brookings Institution. From 2009 to 2013, while serving as the State Department’s Special Advisor for Nonproliferation and Arms Control, he was a senior member of the U.S. delegation to the Iran nuclear negotiations, National Interest, http://nationalinterest.org/feature/will-iran-play-ball-nuke-talks-12031?page=show)
If Congress passes new sanctions Obama is very likely to veto administration officials would then go into overdrive in finding the 34 Senate votes necessary to sustain the veto some Democrats will not want to be seen as undermining the best prospect for resolving the nuclear issue peacefully It is therefore likely that the administration will have the votes to sustain the veto
null
If the Congress passes a new sanctions bill that the administration considers damaging to prospects for negotiations, President Obama is very likely to veto it. Senior administration officials would then go into overdrive in finding the 34 Senate votes necessary to sustain the veto, focusing heavily on Senate Democrats. Although some Democrats can be expected to vote to override the veto, a substantial number, including some who have reservations about the negotiations, will not want to be seen as undermining the best prospect for resolving the nuclear issue peacefully or as undercutting their party’s president on a matter of such high priority. It is therefore likely that the administration will have the votes to sustain the veto and prevent legislation potentially damaging to the negotiations from being enacted. So while the Republican-controlled Congress will undoubtedly give the administration a tough time, it is likely that President Obama will be able, without legislative interference, to continue negotiating an agreement that he believes is in the U.S. interest.
1,085
<h4>Obama’s PC will sustain the veto now</h4><p><strong>Einhorn 1/14</strong>/2015 (Robert, senior fellow at the Brookings Institution. From 2009 to 2013, while serving as the State Department’s Special Advisor for Nonproliferation and Arms Control, he was a senior member of the U.S. delegation to the Iran nuclear negotiations, National Interest, http://nationalinterest.org/feature/will-iran-play-ball-nuke-talks-12031?page=show)</p><p><u>If</u> the <u>Congress</u> <u>passes</u> a <u>new sanctions</u> bill that the administration considers damaging to prospects for negotiations, President <u>Obama</u> <u>is very likely to veto</u> it. Senior <u>administration officials would then go into overdrive in finding the 34 Senate votes necessary to sustain the veto</u>, focusing heavily on Senate Democrats. Although <u>some</u> <u>Democrats</u> can be expected to vote to override the veto, a substantial number, including some who have reservations about the negotiations, <u>will not want to be seen as undermining the best prospect for resolving the nuclear issue peacefully </u>or as undercutting their party’s president on a matter of such high priority. <u>It is therefore likely that the administration <strong>will have the votes to sustain the veto</u></strong> and prevent legislation potentially damaging to the negotiations from being enacted. So while the Republican-controlled Congress will undoubtedly give the administration a tough time, it is likely that President Obama will be able, without legislative interference, to continue negotiating an agreement that he believes is in the U.S. interest.</p>
null
null
Link
430,686
4
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,398
With sales limited to government purchasing transplants under the plan would be based on medical need
Gill 2
Gill 2 Michael Gill, Ph.D., Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, College of Charleston AND Robert Sade, M.D.,Professor in the Department of Surgery and Director of the Institute of Human Values in Health Care, Medical University of South Carolina. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12.1 (2002) 17-45
of_ethics_journal/v012/12.1gill.html The international market in kidneys is worthy of moral condemnation But the horrible stories do not constitute justification for a blanket rejection of payment for kidneys in this country because there are two crucial differences between the international black market and the legal domestic program we propose. First, in our proposal the medical setting in which legal kidney transfer would take place is that of contemporary transplantation, safe and medically sophisticated Second, the domestic program we propose involves money only in the acquisition of kidneys, unlike the international market. Allocation of kidneys would be based on medical criteria, as it is today. No private individual would be able to buy a kidney outside the system. Poor individuals will have just as much chance of receiving one of the kidneys.
horrible stories do not constitute justification for a blanket rejection of payment for kidneys in this country because there are two crucial differences between the international black market and the legal domestic program First, in the medical setting in which legal kidney transfer would take place is that of contemporary transplantation, safe and medically sophisticated Second, involves money only in the acquisition of kidneys, unlike the international market. Allocation of kidneys would be based on medical criteria,
Paying for Kidneys: The Case against Prohibition http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/kennedy_institute_ of_ethics_journal/v012/12.1gill.html The international black market in kidneys is worthy of moral condemnation, and the popular press has been right to expose it. But the horrible stories do not constitute justification for a blanket rejection of payment for kidneys in this country because there are two crucial differences between the international black market and the legal domestic program we propose. First, in our proposal the medical setting in which legal kidney transfer would take place is that of contemporary transplantation, safe and medically sophisticated. Screening would select only potential kidney sellers whose kidneys are suitable for transfer and whose medical condition predicts minimal risk. Follow-up care would be scrupulous. Sellers would receive exactly the same medical attention and treatment that living kidney donors now receive in this country. The people to whom the kidneys are transferred will also receive the same medical attention and treatment that kidney recipients currently receive. Second, the domestic program we propose involves money only in the acquisition of kidneys, unlike the international black market. Allocation of kidneys would be based on medical criteria, as it is today. No private individual would be able to buy a kidney outside the system. Poor individuals will have just as much chance of receiving one of the kidneys.
1,480
<h4><strong>With sales limited to government purchasing transplants under the plan would be based on medical need </h4><p>Gill 2</strong> Michael Gill, Ph.D., Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, College of Charleston AND Robert Sade, M.D.,Professor in the Department of Surgery and Director of the Institute of Human Values in Health Care, Medical University of South Carolina. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12.1 (2002) 17-45</p><p>Paying for Kidneys: The Case against Prohibition http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/kennedy_institute_<u> of_ethics_journal/v012/12.1gill.html</p><p>The international</u> black <u>market in kidneys is worthy of moral condemnation</u>, and the popular press has been right to expose it. <u>But the <mark>horrible stories do not constitute justification for a blanket rejection of payment for kidneys in this country because there are two crucial differences between the international black market and the legal domestic program</mark> we propose.</p><p><mark>First, in</mark> our proposal <mark>the medical setting in which legal kidney transfer would take place is that of contemporary transplantation, safe and medically sophisticated</u></mark>. Screening would select only potential kidney sellers whose kidneys are suitable for transfer and whose medical condition predicts minimal risk. Follow-up care would be scrupulous. Sellers would receive exactly the same medical attention and treatment that living kidney donors now receive in this country. The people to whom the kidneys are transferred will also receive the same medical attention and treatment that kidney recipients currently receive.</p><p><u><mark>Second,</mark> the domestic program we propose <mark>involves money only in the acquisition of kidneys, unlike the international</u></mark> black <u><mark>market.</mark> <mark>Allocation of kidneys would be based on medical criteria,</mark> as it is today. No private individual would be able to buy a kidney outside the system. Poor individuals will have just as much chance of receiving one of the kidneys.</p></u>
null
null
Contention 3 The Plan solves
430,687
5
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,399
Physician assisted suicide is vulnerable to changing cultural contexts – justifying a legal right to die in an ableist society guarantees extermination of disabled people and the elderly – prefer a pragmatic approach
Wright, 2K
Wright, 2K (Walter Wright - Associate Professor and Chair of Philosophy at Clark University, Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, Historical analogies, slippery slopes, and the question of euthanasia, EBSCO)
quality of life” is not a simple property i It is rather a relational property describing how we as a society care for one another, especially the most vulnerable The low quality of life ascribed to many people with differences is less a result of clinical medical facts than of social attitudes until every seriously ill or disabled person has a right to the health care and support services necessary to provide a good quality of life, talk about their “right to die” is dangerous, discriminatory, and unjust. When phy- sicians kill, it causes confusion as to their appropriate role as healers distrust under- mines die capacity of physicians to serve their healing role Considerations like these suggest that prudence and a sense of history should keep us from hastening toward what might seem like an abstractly reasonable social policy. The lessons of history are real lessons. Abstract reasoning is too frail a reed to support ignoring them The burden of proof that euthanasia is permissible on a limited basis lies with its ad- vocates
quality of life” is not a simple property It is rather a relational property describing how we as a society care for one another, especially the most vulnerable The low quality of life ascribed to many people with differences is less a result of clinical medical facts than of social attitudes until every seriously ill or disabled person has a right to the health care and support services necessary to provide a good quality of life, talk about their “right to die” is dangerous, discriminatory, and unjust. distrust under- mines die capacity of physicians to serve their healing role. Considerations like these suggest that prudence and a sense of history should keep us from hastening toward what might seem like an abstractly reasonable social policy The lessons of history are real lessons. Abstract reasoning is too frail a reed to support ignoring them. The burden of proof that euthanasia is permissible on a limited basis lies with its ad- vocates
I want to mention two further points. (1) Singer and other euthanasia advocates often miss the fact that “quality of life” is not a simple property inherent in individuals. It is rather a relational property describing how we as a society care for one another, especially the most vulnerable among us. The low quality of life ascribed to many people with differences is less a result of clinical medical facts than of social attitudes and policies towards those people.69 In particular, until every seriously ill or disabled person has a right to the health care and support services necessary to provide a good quality of life, talk about their “right to die” is dangerous, discriminatory, and unjust.70 (2) When phy- sicians kill, it causes confusion as to their appropriate role as healers. In 1993, the Protestant Christian Elderly Soci- ety in Holland surveyed several thousand elders on health care issues. The survey did not mention euthanasia. Nev- ertheless, 10% of the respondents said that they were afraid that they would be killed without their consent. The Society’s Direaor Hans Holmans said, “They are afraid that at a certain moment, on the basis of age, a treatment will be considered no longer economically viable, and an early end to their lives will be made.”7' Such distrust under- mines die capacity of physicians to serve their healing role. Considerations like these suggest that prudence and a sense of history should keep us from hastening toward what might seem like an abstractly reasonable social policy. Slip- pery slope arguments may not establish a conncction of logical necessity between their premises and conclusions, but they are not for that reason fallacious. The lessons of history are real lessons. Abstract reasoning is too frail a reed to support ignoring them. The burden of proof that euthanasia is permissible on a limited basis lies with its ad- vocates. It is a burden, I contend, that has not yet been met.
1,955
<h4>Physician assisted suicide is vulnerable to changing cultural contexts – justifying a legal right to die in an ableist society guarantees extermination of disabled people and the elderly – prefer a pragmatic approach </h4><p><strong>Wright, 2K </strong>(Walter Wright - Associate Professor and Chair of Philosophy at Clark University, Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, Historical analogies, slippery slopes, and the question of euthanasia, EBSCO)</p><p>I want to mention two further points. (1) Singer and other euthanasia advocates often miss the fact that “<u><mark>quality of life” is not a simple property</mark> i</u>nherent in individuals. <u><mark>It is rather a relational property describing how we as a society care for one another, especially the most vulnerable</u></mark> among us. <u><mark>The low quality of life ascribed to many people with differences is <strong>less a result of clinical medical facts than of social attitudes</u></strong></mark> and policies towards those people.69 In particular, <u><strong><mark>until every seriously ill or disabled person has a right to the health care and support services necessary to provide a good quality of life, talk about their “right to die” is dangerous, discriminatory, and unjust.</u></strong></mark>70 (2) <u>When phy- sicians kill, it causes confusion as to their appropriate role as healers</u>. In 1993, the Protestant Christian Elderly Soci- ety in Holland surveyed several thousand elders on health care issues. The survey did not mention euthanasia. Nev- ertheless, 10% of the respondents said that they were afraid that they would be killed without their consent. The Society’s Direaor Hans Holmans said, “They are afraid that at a certain moment, on the basis of age, a treatment will be considered no longer economically viable, and an early end to their lives will be made.”7' Such<u> <mark>distrust under- mines die capacity of physicians to serve their healing role</u>. <u>Considerations like these suggest that prudence and a sense of history should keep us from hastening toward what might seem like an abstractly reasonable social policy</mark>.</u> Slip- pery slope arguments may not establish a conncction of logical necessity between their premises and conclusions, but they are not for that reason fallacious. <u><strong><mark>The lessons of history are real lessons. Abstract reasoning is too frail a reed to support ignoring them</u></strong>. <u>The burden of proof that euthanasia is permissible on a limited basis lies with its ad- vocates</u></mark>. It is a burden, I contend, that has not yet been met.</p>
Ableism
Body Norms/A2: Smith
2NC K
430,688
7
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,400
Property link does not apply to our plan. Government buyer would not establish a property right – courts have ruled that way
Ghosh 14
Ghosh 14 Samantak Ghosh, Ph.D. in Chemistry, Stanford University; J.D., University of California, Berkeley, School of Law April, 2014 California Law Review 102 Calif. L. Rev. 511 COMMENT: The Taking of Human Biological Products
According to Moore, government regulation limiting personal rights in excised body parts militates against finding property rights in them. if property rights were dictated by government regulations alone, then the takings jurisprudence would be made wholly irrelevant since the government regulates the sale and disposal of body parts, they are not private property;
null
A number of commentators have "appropriately criticized" Moore's logic. n71 Indeed, the California Supreme Court's assurance that fiduciary duties would sufficiently protect tissue donors' interests proved mistaken when a number of other state courts dismissed such causes of action on very similar sets of facts. n72 Regardless of whether doctors' fiduciary duties can sufficiently [*522] protect patients' rights, Moore's circular reasoning for denying property rights needs further examination. According to Moore, government regulation limiting personal rights in excised body parts militates against finding property rights in them. n73 But if property rights were dictated by government regulations alone, then the takings jurisprudence would be made wholly irrelevant. The circularity of Moore's reasoning is obvious: since the government regulates the sale and disposal of body parts, they are not private property; and since they are not private property, the government can subject them to additional regulatory regimes such as the patent system. But ""property' cannot be defined by the procedures provided for its deprivation." n74
1,145
<h4>Property link does not apply to our plan. Government buyer would not establish a property right – courts have ruled that way</h4><p><strong>Ghosh 14</strong> Samantak Ghosh, Ph.D. in Chemistry, Stanford University; J.D., University of California, Berkeley, School of Law April, 2014 California Law Review 102 Calif. L. Rev. 511 COMMENT: The Taking of Human Biological Products</p><p>A number of commentators have "appropriately criticized" Moore's logic. n71 Indeed, the California Supreme Court's assurance that fiduciary duties would sufficiently protect tissue donors' interests proved mistaken when a number of other state courts dismissed such causes of action on very similar sets of facts. n72 Regardless of whether doctors' fiduciary duties can sufficiently <strong>[*522]</strong> protect patients' rights, Moore's circular reasoning for denying property rights needs further examination. <u>According to Moore, government regulation limiting personal rights in excised body parts militates against finding property rights in them.</u> n73 But <u>if property rights were dictated by government regulations alone, then the takings jurisprudence would be made wholly irrelevant</u>. The circularity of Moore's reasoning is obvious: <u>since the government regulates the sale and disposal of body parts, they are not private property; </u>and since they are not private property, the government can subject them to additional regulatory regimes such as the patent system. But ""property' cannot be defined by the procedures provided for its deprivation." n74</p>
2AC
Property DA
Property – 2AC - NDT
430,689
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,401
Their divorce of personal and political kills agency and turns the aff
Kappeler 95
Kappeler 95 (Susanne is an associate professor at al-akhawayn university, “the will to violence: the politics of personal behavior”, pg. 10-11)
null
we regard mega action as the only worthwhile ones question of what I would do tends to peter out We are this war’ even if we do not command the troops
Which is why many of those not yet entirely disillusioned with politics tend to engage in a form of mental deputy politics, in the style of ‘What would I do if I were the general, the prime minister, the president, the foreign minister or the minister of defence?’ Since we seem to regard their mega spheres of action as the only worthwhile and truly effective ones, and since our political analyses tend to dwell there first of all, any question of what I would do if I were indeed myself tends to peter out in the comparative insignificance of having what is perceived as ‘virtually no possibilities’: what I could do seems petty and futile. For my own action I obviously desire the range of action of a general, a prime minister, or a General Secretary of the UN — finding expression in ever more prevalent formulations like ‘I want to stop this war’, ‘I want military intervention’, ‘I want to stop this backlash’, or ‘I want a moral revolution.’7 ‘We are this war’, however, even if we do not command the troops or participate in so—called peace talks, namely as Drakuli~ says, in our non-comprehension’: our willed refusal to feel responsible for our own thinking and for working out our own understanding, preferring innocently to drift along the ideological current of prefabricated arguments or less than innocently taking advantage of the advantages these offer. And we ‘are’ the war in our ‘unconscious cruelty towards you’, our tolerance of the ‘fact that you have a yellow form for refugees and I don’t’ — our readiness, in other words, to build identities, one for ourselves and one for refugees, one of our own and one for the ‘others’. We share in the responsibility for this war and its violence in the way we let them grow inside us, that is, in the way we shape ‘our feelings, our relationships, our values’ according to the structures and the values of war and violence.
1,890
<h4><strong>Their divorce of personal and political kills agency and turns the aff</h4><p>Kappeler 95</strong> (Susanne is an associate professor at al-akhawayn university, “the will to violence: the politics of personal behavior”, pg. 10-11)</p><p>                  </p><p>Which is why many of those not yet entirely disillusioned with politics tend to engage in a form of mental deputy politics, in the style of ‘What would I do if I were the general, the prime minister, the president, the foreign minister or the minister of defence?’ Since <mark>we</mark> seem to <mark>regard</mark> their <mark>mega</mark> spheres of <mark>action as the only worthwhile</mark> and truly effective <mark>ones</mark>, and since our political analyses tend to dwell there first of all, any <mark>question of what I would do</mark> if I were indeed myself <mark>tends to</mark> <mark>peter out</mark> in the comparative insignificance of having what is perceived as ‘virtually no possibilities’: what I could do seems petty and futile. For my own action I obviously desire the range of action of a general, a prime minister, or a General Secretary of the UN — finding expression in ever more prevalent formulations like ‘I want to stop this war’, ‘I want military intervention’, ‘I want to stop this backlash’, or ‘I want a moral revolution.’7 ‘<mark>We are this war’</mark>, however, <mark>even if we do not command the troops</mark> or participate in so—called peace talks, namely as Drakuli~ says, in our non-comprehension’: our willed refusal to feel responsible for our own thinking and for working out our own understanding, preferring innocently to drift along the ideological current of prefabricated arguments or less than innocently taking advantage of the advantages these offer. And we ‘are’ the war in our ‘unconscious cruelty towards you’, our tolerance of the ‘fact that you have a yellow form for refugees and I don’t’ — our readiness, in other words, to build identities, one for ourselves and one for refugees, one of our own and one for the ‘others’. We share in the responsibility for this war and its violence in the way we let them grow inside us, that is, in the way we shape ‘our feelings, our relationships, our values’ according to the structures and the values of war and violence.</p>
null
null
*****1NC Nuclear Terror
11,742
82
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,402
Great power war is obsolete – globalization, nuclear deterrence, and the cooperative liberal order ensure no conflict
Ikenberry and Deudney 9
Ikenberry and Deudney 9 (Daniel – Professor of Politics and International Affairs at Princeton University, and G. John – professor of political science at Johns Hopkins University, Jan/Feb, “The Myth of the Autocratic Revival,” Foreign Affairs, Vol. 88, Issue 1, p. 8)
the picture of an international system marked by conflict and competition is an exaggeration and ignores powerful countervailing factors and forces , the most striking features of the contemporary international landscape are globalization institutions and shared problems of interdependence. The overall structure is quite unlike that of the nineteenth century the contemporary liberal-centered international order provides constraints and opportunities that reduce the likelihood of severe conflict while creating strong imperatives for cooperative problem solving. great-power expansion has become obsolete. nuclear weapons have transformed great-power war into an exercise in national suicide. With all of the great powers possessing nuclear weapons and ample means to rapidly expand their deterrent forces The prospect of such great losses has instilled in the great powers a level of caution and restraint that effectively precludes major revisionist efforts the diffusion of small arms and the near universality of nationalism have severely limited the ability of great powers to conquer and occupy territory density of trade, investment, and production networks across international borders raises even more the costs of war. in the twenty-first century the status quo is much more difficult to overturn. Simple comparisons between China and the U S with regard to aggregate economic size and capability do not reflect the fact that the United States does not stand alone but rather is the head of a coalition of liberal capitalist states whose aggregate assets far exceed those of China revisionist states notably China and Russia are stakeholders in an ensemble of global institutions that make up the status quo, not least the UN Security Council (in which they have permanent seats and veto power Many other global institutions are configured in such a way that rising states can increase their voice only by buying into the institutions The pathway to modernity is not outside and against the status quo but rather inside the liberal international order. The viability of regimes hinges on their ability to sustain economic growth which is crucially dependent on international trade Not only have these states joined the world economy, but their people have increasingly joined the world community citizens of autocratic states are participating in transnational networks. the values of "us versus them" become difficult to generate and sustain. These social and diplomatic processes and developments suggest that there are strong tendencies toward normalization operating here China Europe, India, Japan, the United States Iran and Russia share a common interest in security . The declining utility of war and emerging environmental interdependencies undercut scenarios of international conflict and instability the conditions of the twenty-first century point to the renewed value of international integration and cooperation
the picture of an international system marked by conflict and competition is an exaggeration and ignores powerful countervailing factors the most striking features are globalization institutions and interdependence The overall structure provides constraints that reduce the likelihood of severe conflict while creating strong imperatives for cooperative problem solving. great-power expansion has become obsolete nuclear weapons have transformed great-power war into an exercise in national suicide. With all of the powers possessing nuclear weapons The prospect of losses has instilled level of restraint that effectively precludes major revisionist efforts trade, investment, and production across international borders raises the costs of war revisionist states, are stakeholders in an ensemble of global institutions that make up the status quo institution are configured in such a way that rising states can increase their voice only by buying into the institutions their people have increasingly joined the world community the values of us versus them" become difficult to generate China Europe, India, Japan Iran and Russia share a common interest in security The declining utility of and emerging environmental interdependencies undercut scenarios of international conflict and instability the conditions of the twenty-first century point to the renewed value of cooperation.
It is in combination with these factors that the regime divergence between autocracies and democracies will become increasingly dangerous. If all the states in the world were democracies, there would still be competition, but a world riven by a democratic-autocratic divergence promises to be even more conflictual. There are even signs of the emergence of an "autocrats international" in the Shanghai Cooperation Organization, made up of China, Russia, and the poorer and weaker Central Asian dictatorships. Overall, the autocratic revivalists paint the picture of an international system marked by rising levels of conflict and competition, a picture quite unlike the "end of history" vision of growing convergence and cooperation. This bleak outlook is based on an exaggeration of recent developments and ignores powerful countervailing factors and forces. Indeed, contrary to what trhe revivalists describe, the most striking features of the contemporary international landscape are the intensification of economic globalization, thickening institutions, and shared problems of interdependence. The overall structure of the international system today is quite unlike that of the nineteenth century. Compared to older orders, the contemporary liberal-centered international order provides a set of constraints and opportunities — of pushes and pulls — that reduce the likelihood of severe conflict while creating strong imperatives for cooperative problem solving. Those invoking the nineteenth century as a model for the twenty-first also fail to acknowledge the extent to which war as a path to conflict resolution and great-power expansion has become largely obsolete. Most important, nuclear weapons have transformed great-power war from a routine feature of international politics into an exercise in national suicide. With all of the great powers possessing nuclear weapons and ample means to rapidly expand their deterrent forces, warfare among these states has truly become an option of last resort. The prospect of such great losses has instilled in the great powers a level of caution and restraint that effectively precludes major revisionist efforts. Furthermore, the diffusion of small arms and the near universality of nationalism have severely limited the ability of great powers to conquer and occupy territory inhabited by resisting populations (as Algeria, Vietnam, Afghanistan, and now Iraq have demonstrated). Unlike during the days of empire building in the nineteenth century, states today cannot translate great asymmetries of power into effective territorial control; at most, they can hope for loose hegemonic relationships that require them to give something in return. Also unlike in the nineteenth century, today the density of trade, investment, and production networks across international borders raises even more the costs of war. A Chinese invasion of Taiwan, to take one of the most plausible cases of a future interstate war, would pose for the Chinese communist regime daunting economic costs, both domestic and international. Taken together, these changes in the economy of violence mean that the international system is far more primed for peace than the autocratic revivalists acknowledge. The autocratic revival thesis neglects other key features of the international system as well. In the nineteenth century, rising states faced an international environment in which they could reasonably expect to translate their growing clout into geopolitical changes that would benefit themselves. But in the twenty-first century, the status quo is much more difficult to overturn. Simple comparisons between China and the United States with regard to aggregate economic size and capability do not reflect the fact that the United States does not stand alone but rather is the head of a coalition of liberal capitalist states in Europe and East Asia whose aggregate assets far exceed those of China or even of a coalition of autocratic states. Moreover, potentially revisionist autocratic states, most notably China and Russia, are already substantial players and stakeholders in an ensemble of global institutions that make up the status quo, not least the UN Security Council (in which they have permanent seats and veto power). Many other global institutions, such as the International Monetary Fund and the World Bank, are configured in such a way that rising states can increase their voice only by buying into the institutions. The pathway to modernity for rising states is not outside and against the status quo but rather inside and through the flexible and accommodating institutions of the liberal international order. The fact that these autocracies are capitalist has profound implications for the nature of their international interests that point toward integration and accommodation in the future. The domestic viability of these regimes hinges on their ability to sustain high economic growth rates, which in turn is crucially dependent on international trade and investment; today's autocracies may be illiberal, but they remain fundamentally dependent on a liberal international capitalist system. It is not surprising that China made major domestic changes in order to join the WTO or that Russia is seeking to do so now. The dependence of autocratic capitalist states on foreign trade and investment means that they have a fundamental interest in maintaining an open, rulebased economic system. (Although these autocratic states do pursue bilateral trade and investment deals, particularly in energy and raw materials, this does not obviate their more basic dependence on and commitment to the WTO order.) In the case of China, because of its extensive dependence on industrial exports, the WTO may act as a vital bulwark against protectionist tendencies in importing states. Given their position in this system, which so serves their interests, the autocratic states are unlikely to become champions of an alternative global or regional economic order, let alone spoilers intent on seriously damaging the existing one. The prospects for revisionist behavior on the part of the capitalist autocracies are further reduced by the large and growing social networks across international borders. Not only have these states joined the world economy, but their people — particularly upwardly mobile and educated elites — have increasingly joined the world community. In large and growing numbers, citizens of autocratic capitalist states are participating in a sprawling array of transnational educational, business, and avocational networks. As individuals are socialized into the values and orientations of these networks, stark: "us versus them" cleavages become more difficult to generate and sustain. As the Harvard political scientist Alastair Iain Johnston has argued, China's ruling elite has also been socialized, as its foreign policy establishment has internalized the norms and practices of the international diplomatic community. China, far from cultivating causes for territorial dispute with its neighbors, has instead sought to resolve numerous historically inherited border conflicts, acting like a satisfied status quo state. These social and diplomatic processes and developments suggest that there are strong tendencies toward normalization operating here. Finally, there is an emerging set of global problems stemming from industrialism and economic globalization that will create common interests across states regardless of regime type. Autocratic China is as dependent on imported oil as are democratic Europe, India, Japan, and the United States, suggesting an alignment of interests against petroleum-exporting autocracies, such as Iran and Russia. These states share a common interest in price stability and supply security that could form the basis for a revitalization of the International Energy Agency, the consumer association created during the oil turmoil of the 1970s. The emergence of global warming and climate change as significant problems also suggests possibilities for alignments and cooperative ventures cutting across the autocratic-democratic divide. Like the United States, China is not only a major contributor to greenhouse gas accumulation but also likely to be a major victim of climate-induced desertification and coastal flooding. Its rapid industrialization and consequent pollution means that China, like other developed countries, will increasingly need to import technologies and innovative solutions for environmental management. Resource scarcity and environmental deterioration pose global threats that no state will be able to solve alone, thus placing a further premium on political integration and cooperative institution building. Analogies between the nineteenth century and the twenty-first are based on a severe mischaracterization of the actual conditions of the new era. The declining utility of war, the thickening of international transactions and institutions, and emerging resource and environmental interdependencies together undercut scenarios of international conflict and instability based on autocratic-democratic rivalry and autocratic revisionism. In fact, the conditions of the twenty-first century point to the renewed value of international integration and cooperation.
9,298
<h4><strong>Great power war is obsolete – globalization, nuclear deterrence, and the cooperative liberal order ensure no conflict </h4><p>Ikenberry and Deudney 9 </strong>(Daniel – Professor of Politics and International Affairs at Princeton University, and G. John – professor of political science at Johns Hopkins University, Jan/Feb, “The Myth of the Autocratic Revival,” Foreign Affairs, Vol. 88, Issue 1, p. 8)</p><p>It is in combination with these factors that the regime divergence between autocracies and democracies will become increasingly dangerous. If all the states in the world were democracies, there would still be competition, but a world riven by a democratic-autocratic divergence promises to be even more conflictual. There are even signs of the emergence of an "autocrats international" in the Shanghai Cooperation Organization, made up of China, Russia, and the poorer and weaker Central Asian dictatorships. Overall, the autocratic revivalists paint <u><mark>the picture of an international system marked by</u></mark> rising levels of <u><mark>conflict and competition</u></mark>, a picture quite unlike the "end of history" vision of growing convergence and cooperation. This bleak outlook <u><mark>is</u></mark> based on <u><strong><mark>an exaggeration</u></strong></mark> of recent developments <u><mark>and ignores powerful <strong>countervailing factors</mark> and forces</u></strong>. Indeed, contrary to what trhe revivalists describe<u>, <mark>the most striking features</mark> of the contemporary international landscape <mark>are</u></mark> the intensification of economic <u><strong><mark>globalization</u></strong></mark>, thickening <u><strong><mark>institutions</u></strong></mark>, <u><mark>and</u></mark> <u><strong>shared problems of <mark>interdependence</strong></mark>. <mark>The</u> <u>overall structure</u></mark> of the international system today <u>is quite unlike that of the nineteenth century</u>. Compared to older orders,<u> the contemporary liberal-centered international order <mark>provides</u></mark> a set of <u><mark>constraints</mark> and opportunities</u> — of pushes and pulls — <u><mark>that reduce the likelihood of severe conflict while creating strong imperatives for cooperative problem solving.</u></mark> Those invoking the nineteenth century as a model for the twenty-first also fail to acknowledge the extent to which war as a path to conflict resolution and <u><mark>great-power expansion has become</u></mark> largely <u><strong><mark>obsolete</strong></mark>.</u> Most important, <u><strong><mark>nuclear weapons</u></strong> <u>have transformed great-power war</mark> </u>from a routine feature of international politics <u><mark>into an exercise in <strong>national suicide.</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>With all of the</mark> great <mark>powers possessing nuclear weapons</mark> and ample means to rapidly expand their deterrent forces</u>, warfare among these states has truly become an option of last resort. <u><mark>The prospect of</mark> such great <mark>losses has instilled</mark> in the great powers a <mark>level <strong>of</mark> caution and <mark>restraint</strong> that <strong>effectively precludes major revisionist efforts</u></strong></mark>. Furthermore, <u>the diffusion of small arms and the near universality of nationalism have severely limited the ability of great powers to conquer and occupy territory</u> inhabited by resisting populations (as Algeria, Vietnam, Afghanistan, and now Iraq have demonstrated). Unlike during the days of empire building in the nineteenth century, states today cannot translate great asymmetries of power into effective territorial control; at most, they can hope for loose hegemonic relationships that require them to give something in return. Also unlike in the nineteenth century, today the<u> density of <mark>trade, investment, and production</mark> networks <mark>across international borders <strong>raises</mark> even more <mark>the costs of war</strong></mark>. </u>A Chinese invasion of Taiwan, to take one of the most plausible cases of a future interstate war, would pose for the Chinese communist regime daunting economic costs, both domestic and international. Taken together, these changes in the economy of violence mean that the international system is far more primed for peace than the autocratic revivalists acknowledge. The autocratic revival thesis neglects other key features of the international system as well. In the nineteenth century, rising states faced an international environment in which they could reasonably expect to translate their growing clout into geopolitical changes that would benefit themselves. But <u>in the twenty-first century</u>, <u>the status quo is much more difficult to overturn. Simple comparisons between China and the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>with regard to aggregate economic size and capability do not reflect the fact that the United States does not stand alone but rather is the head of a coalition of liberal capitalist states</u> in Europe and East Asia <u>whose aggregate assets far exceed those of China</u> or even of a coalition of autocratic states. Moreover, potentially <u><mark>revisionist</u></mark> autocratic <u><mark>states</u>,</mark> most <u>notably China and Russia</u>, <u><mark>are</u></mark> already substantial players and <u><strong><mark>stakeholders</strong> in</u></mark> <u><mark>an</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>ensemble of global institutions</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>that make up the status quo</mark>, not least the UN Security Council (in which they have permanent seats and veto power</u>). <u>Many other global <mark>institution</mark>s</u>, such as the International Monetary Fund and the World Bank, <u><mark>are configured in such a way that rising states can increase their voice <strong>only by buying into the institutions</u></strong></mark>. <u>The pathway to modernity</u> for rising states <u>is not outside and against the status quo but rather inside</u> and through the flexible and accommodating institutions of <u>the liberal international order.</u> The fact that these autocracies are capitalist has profound implications for the nature of their international interests that point toward integration and accommodation in the future. <u>The </u>domestic <u>viability of</u> these <u>regimes hinges on their ability to sustain</u> high <u>economic growth</u> rates, <u>which</u> in turn <u>is crucially dependent on international trade</u> and investment; today's autocracies may be illiberal, but they remain fundamentally dependent on a liberal international capitalist system. It is not surprising that China made major domestic changes in order to join the WTO or that Russia is seeking to do so now. The dependence of autocratic capitalist states on foreign trade and investment means that they have a fundamental interest in maintaining an open, rulebased economic system. (Although these autocratic states do pursue bilateral trade and investment deals, particularly in energy and raw materials, this does not obviate their more basic dependence on and commitment to the WTO order.) In the case of China, because of its extensive dependence on industrial exports, the WTO may act as a vital bulwark against protectionist tendencies in importing states. Given their position in this system, which so serves their interests, the autocratic states are unlikely to become champions of an alternative global or regional economic order, let alone spoilers intent on seriously damaging the existing one. The prospects for revisionist behavior on the part of the capitalist autocracies are further reduced by the large and growing social networks across international borders. <u>Not only have these states joined the world economy, but <mark>their people</u></mark> — particularly upwardly mobile and educated elites — <u><mark>have increasingly joined the world community</u></mark>. In large and growing numbers, <u>citizens of autocratic</u> capitalist <u>states are participating in</u> a sprawling array of <u>transnational </u>educational, business, and avocational <u>networks.</u> As individuals are socialized into <u><mark>the values</u></mark> and orientations <u><mark>of</u></mark> these networks, stark: <u>"<mark>us versus them"</u></mark> cleavages <u><mark>become</u></mark> more <u><strong><mark>difficult to generate</mark> and sustain</strong>.</u> As the Harvard political scientist Alastair Iain Johnston has argued, China's ruling elite has also been socialized, as its foreign policy establishment has internalized the norms and practices of the international diplomatic community. China, far from cultivating causes for territorial dispute with its neighbors, has instead sought to resolve numerous historically inherited border conflicts, acting like a satisfied status quo state. <u>These social and diplomatic processes and developments suggest that there are strong tendencies toward normalization operating here</u>. Finally, there is an emerging set of global problems stemming from industrialism and economic globalization that will create common interests across states regardless of regime type. Autocratic <u><strong><mark>China</u></strong></mark> is as dependent on imported oil as are democratic <u><strong><mark>Europe</strong>, <strong>India</strong>, <strong>Japan</strong></mark>,</u> and <u>the United States</u>, suggesting an alignment of interests against petroleum-exporting autocracies, such as <u><strong><mark>Iran</strong> and <strong>Russia</u></strong></mark>. These states <u><strong><mark>share a common interest</strong> in</u></mark> price stability and supply <u><mark>security</u></mark> that could form the basis for a revitalization of the International Energy Agency, the consumer association created during the oil turmoil of the 1970s. The emergence of global warming and climate change as significant problems also suggests possibilities for alignments and cooperative ventures cutting across the autocratic-democratic divide. Like the United States, China is not only a major contributor to greenhouse gas accumulation but also likely to be a major victim of climate-induced desertification and coastal flooding. Its rapid industrialization and consequent pollution means that China, like other developed countries, will increasingly need to import technologies and innovative solutions for environmental management. Resource scarcity and environmental deterioration pose global threats that no state will be able to solve alone, thus placing a further premium on political integration and cooperative institution building<u>.</u> Analogies between the nineteenth century and the twenty-first are based on a severe mischaracterization of the actual conditions of the new era. <u><strong><mark>The declining utility of</mark> war</u></strong>, the thickening of international transactions and institutions, <u><mark>and emerging</u></mark> resource and <u><mark>environmental interdependencies</u></mark> together <u><strong><mark>undercut scenarios of international conflict and instability</u></strong></mark> based on autocratic-democratic rivalry and autocratic revisionism. In fact, <u><mark>the conditions of the twenty-first century <strong>point to the renewed value</strong> of</mark> international integration and <mark>cooperation</u>.</p></mark>
null
Contention 4 is risk calculus
Contention 3 The Plan solves
18,192
80
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,403
Instances of actual benefit are extremely rare – mostly people would be pressured into it.
NYDHS 11
NYDHS 11
assisted suicide and euthanasia are legalized, the autonomy of some patients would be extended while the autonomy of others would be compromised by the pressures to exercise these new options.
assisted suicide and euthanasia are legalized, the autonomy of some patients would be extended while the autonomy of others would be compromised by the pressures to exercise these new options.
New York State Department of Health, Task Force, “When Death is Sought”, April 2011, “Chapter 6 - Crafting Public Policy on Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia”, https://www.health.ny.gov/regulations/task_force/reports_publications/when_death_is_sought/chap6.htm //jchen Support for legalizing assisted suicide and euthanasia rests in part on the belief that individuals should have the right to assistance to end their lives at a time and in a manner they choose. None of the Task Force members believes that respect for autonomy dictates the legalization of assisted suicide and euthanasia. The moral claim to autonomy is weakened by both the overall risks of the practice and the extraordinary nature of the remedy sought. Moreover, if assisted suicide and euthanasia are legalized, the autonomy of some patients would be extended while the autonomy of others would be compromised by the pressures to exercise these new options. The legalization of assisted suicide and euthanasia is also urged on grounds of mercy and the alleviation of suffering. Some of the Task Force members believe that the practices offer clear benefits to certain patients who are dying or otherwise suffering greatly. They recognize that providing a quick, less prolonged death for some patients can be a compassionate act. These members, however, regard the number of cases when assisted suicide or euthanasia are medically and ethically appropriate as extremely rare. They do not believe that the benefits incurred for this small number of patients can justify a major shift in public policy or the serious risks that legalizing the practice would entail.
1,632
<h4><strong>Instances of actual benefit are extremely rare – mostly people would be pressured into it.</h4><p>NYDHS 11</p><p></strong>New York State Department of Health, Task Force, “When Death is Sought”, April 2011, “Chapter 6 - Crafting Public Policy on Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia”, https://www.health.ny.gov/regulations/task_force/reports_publications/when_death_is_sought/chap6.htm //jchen</p><p>Support for legalizing assisted suicide and euthanasia rests in part on the belief that individuals should have the right to assistance to end their lives at a time and in a manner they choose. None of the Task Force members believes that respect for autonomy dictates the legalization of assisted suicide and euthanasia. The moral claim to autonomy is weakened by both the overall risks of the practice and the extraordinary nature of the remedy sought. Moreover, if <u><mark>assisted suicide and euthanasia are legalized, the autonomy of some patients would be extended while the autonomy of others would be compromised by the pressures to exercise these new options.</u></mark> The legalization of assisted suicide and euthanasia is also urged on grounds of mercy and the alleviation of suffering. Some of the Task Force members believe that the practices offer clear benefits to certain patients who are dying or otherwise suffering greatly. They recognize that providing a quick, less prolonged death for some patients can be a compassionate act. These members, however, regard the number of cases when assisted suicide or euthanasia are medically and ethically appropriate as extremely rare. They do not believe that the benefits incurred for this small number of patients can justify a major shift in public policy or the serious risks that legalizing the practice would entail. </p>
Ableism
Body Norms/A2: Smith
2NC K
430,370
2
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,404
Transplant organs are treated as a "service"
Boyer 12
Boyer 12 J. Randall Boyer, J.D. candidate, April 2012, J. Reuben Clark Law School, Brigham Young University. 2012 Brigham Young University Law Review 2012 B.Y.U.L. Rev. 313 COMMENT: Gifts of the Heart ... and Other Tissues: Legalizing the Sale of Human Organs and Tissues lexis
Statutes categorically treat the transfer of organs from one individual to another as a service rather than a transaction for goods or products even though a tangible, physical item (the organ) is traded when the end recipient enters the equation, the organ is deemed a service. The jurisprudence underpinning the legal status of human body parts is, at best, confused this debate implicates recent doctrines of the constitutional right of privacy, adding yet another wrinkle to the legal framework.
Statutes treat the transfer of organs as a service rather than a transaction for goods even though a the organ) is traded when the end recipient enters the equation, the organ is deemed a service
In addition to the common law, statutes specifically regulating organ transfers have resulted in similar unintended consequences. Blood Shield Statutes n59 and other state health and safety legislation categorically treat the transfer of organs from one individual to another as a service rather than a transaction for goods or products. n60 In other words, even though a tangible, physical item (the organ) is traded between doctors, hospitals, and medical companies, and is [*322] treated as a good for the purposes of those transactions, when the end recipient enters the equation, the organ is deemed a service. n61 The end result of this classification is to preclude products liability claims, essentially exculpating tissue banks whose negligence may result in contaminated products. n62 Because the tissue is not a good, tissue recipients are not protected by the standard product warranties that might otherwise deter tissue banks from negligently supplying infected tissue. n63 Further, because the tissue is a service, an injured party's primary recourse is through medical malpractice suits against the doctors and hospitals involved in the transplant. n64 Thus, the law shifts the burden of ensuring that tissue is safe for implantation from tissue banks and other suppliers, who are in the best position to test for disease and ensure proper handling of tissues, to doctors and hospitals, who have much less control over the quality of tissues they receive. n65 Such negligent treatment of tissue transplants can result in tragic consequences. n66 Bryan Lykins stands as a poign-ant example. Bryan received a cadaveric tendon as part of a knee surgery. n67 Although the surgery was common, and in many ways routine, the tendon Bryan received was from a cadaver that had been unrefrigerated for nineteen hours. n68 The bacteria that had been allowed to grow during that time resulted in Bryan's death only four days after the surgery. n69 Even worse is the fact that Bryan's story is not a singular or isolated incident. n70 Yet, even though tissue banks may negligently place contaminated tissue on the market, they cannot be held liable if their products result in illness or even death. n71 Further, insofar as lawmakers have been slow to act, n72 tissue banks have little incentive [*323] to change their behavior, and some have been continually careless in the products and "services" they are providing. n73 Privacy right would be sufficient for judicial doctrine Boyer 12 J. Randall Boyer, J.D. candidate, April 2012, J. Reuben Clark Law School, Brigham Young University. 2012 Brigham Young University Law Review 2012 B.Y.U.L. Rev. 313 COMMENT: Gifts of the Heart ... and Other Tissues: Legalizing the Sale of Human Organs and Tissues lexis The jurisprudence underpinning the legal status of human body parts is, at best, confused. This, in part, is due to the various legal theories that interact when discussing the transfer of human organs. The common law tradition that has protected some interests in body parts is now inadequate since the value in a dead body has only recently been - and is continually being - established by modern technology. Additionally, statutes concerned with tissue transfer have sought to preserve a distinction between the body and property, but with unintended consequences. Finally, this debate implicates recent doctrines of the constitutional right of privacy, adding yet another wrinkle to the legal framework.
3,484
<h4>Transplant organs are treated as a "service"</h4><p><strong>Boyer 12</strong> J. Randall Boyer, J.D. candidate, April 2012, J. Reuben Clark Law School, Brigham Young University. 2012 Brigham Young University Law Review 2012 B.Y.U.L. Rev. 313 COMMENT: Gifts of the Heart ... and Other Tissues: Legalizing the Sale of Human Organs and Tissues lexis</p><p>In addition to the common law, statutes specifically regulating organ transfers have resulted in similar unintended consequences. Blood Shield <u><mark>Statutes</mark> </u>n59 and other state health and safety legislation <u>categorically <mark>treat the transfer of organs</mark> from one individual to another <mark>as a <strong>service</strong> rather than a transaction for goods</mark> or products</u>. n60 In other words, <u><mark>even though a</mark> tangible, physical item (<mark>the organ) is traded</u></mark> between doctors, hospitals, and medical companies, and is [*322] treated as a good for the purposes of those transactions, <u><mark>when the end recipient enters the equation, the organ is deemed a service</mark>.</u> n61 The end result of this classification is to preclude products liability claims, essentially exculpating tissue banks whose negligence may result in contaminated products. n62 Because the tissue is not a good, tissue recipients are not protected by the standard product warranties that might otherwise deter tissue banks from negligently supplying infected tissue. n63 Further, because the tissue is a service, an injured party's primary recourse is through medical malpractice suits against the doctors and hospitals involved in the transplant. n64 Thus, the law shifts the burden of ensuring that tissue is safe for implantation from tissue banks and other suppliers, who are in the best position to test for disease and ensure proper handling of tissues, to doctors and hospitals, who have much less control over the quality of tissues they receive. n65</p><p>Such negligent treatment of tissue transplants can result in tragic consequences. n66 Bryan Lykins stands as a poign-ant example. Bryan received a cadaveric tendon as part of a knee surgery. n67 Although the surgery was common, and in many ways routine, the tendon Bryan received was from a cadaver that had been unrefrigerated for nineteen hours. n68 The bacteria that had been allowed to grow during that time resulted in Bryan's death only four days after the surgery. n69 Even worse is the fact that Bryan's story is not a singular or isolated incident. n70 Yet, even though tissue banks may negligently place contaminated tissue on the market, they cannot be held liable if their products result in illness or even death. n71 Further, insofar as lawmakers have been slow to act, n72 tissue banks have little incentive [*323] to change their behavior, and some have been continually careless in the products and "services" they are providing. <strong>n73</p><p>Privacy right would be sufficient for judicial doctrine</p><p>Boyer 12</strong> J. Randall Boyer, J.D. candidate, April 2012, J. Reuben Clark Law School, Brigham Young University. 2012 Brigham Young University Law Review 2012 B.Y.U.L. Rev. 313 COMMENT: Gifts of the Heart ... and Other Tissues: Legalizing the Sale of Human Organs and Tissues lexis</p><p> <u>The jurisprudence underpinning the legal status of human body parts is, at best, confused</u>. This, in part, is due to the various legal theories that interact when discussing the transfer of human organs. The common law tradition that has protected some interests in body parts is now inadequate since the value in a dead body has only recently been - and is continually being - established by modern technology. Additionally, statutes concerned with tissue transfer have sought to preserve a distinction between the body and property, but with unintended consequences. Finally, <u>this debate implicates recent doctrines of the constitutional right of privacy, adding yet another wrinkle to the legal framework.</p></u>
2AC
Property DA
Property – 2AC - NDT
430,690
3
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2