id
int64
673k
4.14M
tag
stringlengths
1
39.7k
cite
stringlengths
1
8.39k
fullcite
stringlengths
1
50.9k
summary
stringlengths
1
47k
spoken
stringlengths
1
13.9k
fulltext
stringlengths
1
138k
textLength
float64
0
138k
markup
stringlengths
10
139k
pocket
stringlengths
1
863
hat
stringlengths
1
5.45k
block
stringlengths
1
16.5k
bucketId
int64
37
1.65M
duplicateCount
int64
1
3.81k
fileId
int64
14k
129k
filePath
stringlengths
60
188
roundId
int64
565k
915k
side
stringclasses
2 values
tournament
stringlengths
1
62
round
stringclasses
34 values
opponent
stringlengths
1
57
judge
stringlengths
1
87
report
stringlengths
1
612k
opensourcePath
stringlengths
48
176
caselistUpdatedAt
float64
teamId
int64
48.4k
77.9k
teamName
stringlengths
3
5
teamDisplayName
stringlengths
8
31
notes
float64
debater1First
stringclasses
164 values
debater1Last
stringclasses
183 values
debater2First
stringclasses
151 values
debater2Last
stringclasses
186 values
schoolId
int64
18.7k
26.1k
schoolName
stringclasses
306 values
schoolDisplayName
stringclasses
306 values
state
float64
chapterId
float64
caselistId
int64
1k
1.04k
caselistName
stringclasses
10 values
caselistDisplayName
stringclasses
10 values
year
int64
2.01k
2.02k
event
stringclasses
2 values
level
stringclasses
2 values
teamSize
int64
1
2
742,205
Lupovici votes neg—deterrence is culturally contingent and provokes conflict
Lupovici, 10
Lupovici, 10 – PhD, Department of International Relations, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, under the supervision of Professor Emanuel Adler. (Amir, Sept 7, 2010, The Emerging Fourth Wave of Deterrence Theory—Toward a New Research Agenda, Wiley)
deterrence is a textual field The language and discourse of deterrence includes rules and routines that allow for interpretation by a audience the discourse of deterrence represents this and constructs it the difficulty of translating the word “deterrence into different languages suggests concepts of deterrence are the outcome of a social process actors do not necessarily share the same notion of deterrence with their opponents while one actor declares that it aims to practice deterrence, the opponent may perceive it as a provocation discourse is part of the mechanism through which actors can become attached to their strategies Actors may act not only for strategic reasons, but also to (re)validate their identity as a deterrer actor this need to deter may enhance the practices of deterrence it aggravates the sense of insecurity and intensifies the need to use force (rather than to avoid violence social context is created through socialization and social constructions producing a discourse
deterrence is a textual field the difficulty of translating the word “deterrence into different languages suggests concepts of deterrence are the outcome of a social process actors do not necessarily share the same notion of deterrence with their opponents the opponent may perceive it as a provocation the practices of deterrence aggravates the sense of insecurity and intensifies the need to use force (rather than to avoid violence
It has been suggested that the discourse of deterrence is more than just a means of communication. As Jeonniemi argues, deterrence is a textual field. The language and discourse of deterrence includes rules and routines that allow for interpretation by a domestic and internal audience. In this manner, the discourse of deterrence both represents this practice and constructs it (Dillon 1989:97; Jeonniemi 1989:45; Dauber 1993; Gusterson 1996:2; see also Cohn 1987). The discourse of deterrence helps actors to better understand reality and better interpret their opponents’ actions. Moreover, while deterrence is self-evident in that it is used so widely in societies, this discourse as elaborated in theory and practice is affected by contemporary processes of learning, socialization, and social constructions. One of the fascinating facts about the language of deterrence is the difficulty of translating the word “deterrence” (and deter) into different languages (for example, French, German, Russian) (see Jukes 1975:484; Vigor 1975; Trofimenko 1980:53, note 29; Chilton 1985:104, 107–110).48 This suggests that concepts of deterrence are not the outcome of a neutral language but of a social process (Chilton 1985:116). The lack of this word in some languages demonstrates not only the difficulty of thinking in terms of deterrence, but the absence of a linguistic need for such a word. It is not merely that actors tend to see themselves as the defenders and their opponents as the aggressors (for example, Falk 1989:65; Lebow and Stein 1989:221, 223), but that actors do not necessarily share the same notion of deterrence with their opponents. In such cases, while one actor declares that it aims to practice deterrence, the opponent may perceive it as a provocation. Furthermore, because an actor’s identity depends upon discourse, discourse is also part of the mechanism through which actors can become attached to their strategies. By practicing the strategy of deterrence, actors shape their own and others’ perceptions of their role in the international arena. This constitutive effect, acknowledged to some extent by scholars (Wendt 1999:358–359; Bially-Mattern 2005:22–23; see also Tannenwald 2007:45–46), is closely related to the concept of role identity.49 Actors may thus act not only for strategic reasons, but also to (re)validate their identity (that is, as a deterrer actor). In some cases, this need to deter may enhance the practices of deterrence; however, in other cases, it aggravates the sense of insecurity and intensifies the need to use force (rather than to avoid violence).50 To sum up this section, social context is created through learning, socialization, and social constructions, producing a discourse and even constituting the actors themselves. Acknowledging the importance of this context allows us to better establish the connections between the strategy of deterrence and the avoidance of violence, and helps to clarify and explain contradictions in deterrence research. It also provides scholars with a richer framework through which to understand how deterrent threats may influence the behavior of actors.
3,154
<h4>Lupovici votes neg—deterrence is culturally contingent and provokes conflict</h4><p><strong>Lupovici, 10</strong> – PhD, Department of International Relations, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, under the supervision of Professor Emanuel Adler. (Amir, Sept 7, 2010, The Emerging Fourth Wave of Deterrence Theory—Toward a New Research Agenda, Wiley)</p><p>It has been suggested that the discourse of deterrence is more than just a means of communication. As Jeonniemi argues, <u><mark>deterrence is a textual field</u></mark>. <u>The language and discourse of deterrence includes rules and routines that allow for interpretation by a</u> domestic and internal <u>audience</u>. In this manner, <u>the discourse of deterrence</u> both <u>represents this</u> practice <u>and constructs it</u> (Dillon 1989:97; Jeonniemi 1989:45; Dauber 1993; Gusterson 1996:2; see also Cohn 1987). The discourse of deterrence helps actors to better understand reality and better interpret their opponents’ actions. Moreover, while deterrence is self-evident in that it is used so widely in societies, this discourse as elaborated in theory and practice is affected by contemporary processes of learning, socialization, and social constructions. One of the fascinating facts about the language of deterrence is <u><mark>the difficulty of translating the word “deterrence</u></mark>” (and deter) <u><mark>into different languages</u></mark> (for example, French, German, Russian) (see Jukes 1975:484; Vigor 1975; Trofimenko 1980:53, note 29; Chilton 1985:104, 107–110).48 This <u><mark>suggests</u></mark> that <u><mark>concepts of deterrence are</mark> </u>not<u> <mark>the outcome of</mark> </u>a neutral language but of<u> <mark>a social process</u></mark> (Chilton 1985:116). The lack of this word in some languages demonstrates not only the difficulty of thinking in terms of deterrence, but the absence of a linguistic need for such a word. It is not merely that actors tend to see themselves as the defenders and their opponents as the aggressors (for example, Falk 1989:65; Lebow and Stein 1989:221, 223), but that <u><mark>actors do not necessarily share the same notion of deterrence with their opponents</u></mark>. In such cases, <u>while one actor declares that it aims to practice deterrence, <mark>the opponent may perceive it as a provocation</u></mark>. Furthermore, because an actor’s identity depends upon discourse, <u>discourse is</u> also <u>part of the mechanism through which actors can become attached to their strategies</u>. By practicing the strategy of deterrence, actors shape their own and others’ perceptions of their role in the international arena. This constitutive effect, acknowledged to some extent by scholars (Wendt 1999:358–359; Bially-Mattern 2005:22–23; see also Tannenwald 2007:45–46), is closely related to the concept of role identity.49 <u>Actors may</u> thus <u>act not only for strategic reasons, but also to (re)validate their identity</u> (that is, <u>as a deterrer actor</u>). In some cases, <u>this need to deter may enhance <mark>the practices of deterrence</u></mark>; however, in other cases, <u>it <strong><mark>aggravates the sense of insecurity</strong> and <strong>intensifies the need to use force (rather than to avoid violence</u></strong></mark>).50 To sum up this section, <u>social context is created through</u> learning, <u>socialization</u>, <u>and social constructions</u>, <u>producing a discourse</u> and even constituting the actors themselves. Acknowledging the importance of this context allows us to better establish the connections between the strategy of deterrence and the avoidance of violence, and helps to clarify and explain contradictions in deterrence research. It also provides scholars with a richer framework through which to understand how deterrent threats may influence the behavior of actors. </p>
Block
AT: Empirics
AT: Lupovici
430,610
1
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,206
We affirm the legalization of suicide within the generative context of a symbolic reorientation of death
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>We affirm the legalization of suicide within the generative context of a symbolic reorientation of death</h4>
null
Off
CP
430,609
1
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,207
Our alternative is to vote negative to refuse to participate in activities which support capitalism. We must hollow out capitalist structures by refusing to invest our energy in reforms and rescue operations
Herod 2004
Herod 2004
) destroying capitalism calls for pulling time, energy, and resources out of capitalist civilization of emptying out capitalist structures, hollowing them out, by draining wealth, power, and meaning out of them until there is nothing left but shells. This is definitely an aggressive strategy. It requires great militancy, and constitutes an attack on the existing order. The strategy clearly recognizes that capitalism is the enemy and must be destroyed, but it is not a frontal attack aimed at overthrowing the system, but an inside attack aimed at gutting it, while simultaneously replacing it with something better, something we want. capitalist structures are not seized so much as simply abandoned. Capitalist relations are not fought so much as they are simply rejected. We stop participating in activities that support the capitalist world In this way our new democratic , non-commodified relations can eventually overwhelm the capitalist relations and force them out of existence. This is how it has to be done. This is a , realistic strategy Our new social world must grow in opposition until it is strong enough to dismantle and abolish capitalist relations. It will happen because we want it to Capitalism must be explicitly refused . This constitutes War a war fought on a daily basis, on the level of everyday life
destroying capitalism calls for pulling time, energy, and resources out of capitalist civilization emptying out capitalist structures draining meaning out of them We stop participating in activities that support the capitalist world This is a realistic strategy Our new social world must grow in opposition to capitalist relations This constitutes a war fought on a daily basis, on the level of everyday life,
(James, Getting Free, http://site.www.umb.edu/faculty/salzman_g/Strate/GetFre/06.htm) It is time to try to describe, at first abstractly and later concretely, a strategy for destroying capitalism. This strategy, at its most basic, calls for pulling time, energy, and resources out of capitalist civilization and putting them into building a new civilization. The image then is one of emptying out capitalist structures, hollowing them out, by draining wealth, power, and meaning out of them until there is nothing left but shells. This is definitely an aggressive strategy. It requires great militancy, and constitutes an attack on the existing order. The strategy clearly recognizes that capitalism is the enemy and must be destroyed, but it is not a frontal attack aimed at overthrowing the system, but an inside attack aimed at gutting it, while simultaneously replacing it with something better, something we want. Thus capitalist structures (corporations, governments, banks, schools, etc.) are not seized so much as simply abandoned. Capitalist relations are not fought so much as they are simply rejected. We stop participating in activities that support (finance, condone) the capitalist world and start participating in activities that build a new world while simultaneously undermining the old. We create a new pattern of social relations alongside capitalist relations and then we continually build and strengthen our new pattern while doing every thing we can to weaken capitalist relations. In this way our new democratic, non-hierarchical, non-commodified relations can eventually overwhelm the capitalist relations and force them out of existence. This is how it has to be done. This is a plausible, realistic strategy. To think that we could create a whole new world of decent social arrangements overnight, in the midst of a crisis, during a so-called revolution, or during the collapse of capitalism, is foolhardy. Our new social world must grow within the old, and in opposition to it, until it is strong enough to dismantle and abolish capitalist relations. Such a revolution will never happen automatically, blindly, determinably, because of the inexorable, materialist laws of history. It will happen, and only happen, because we want it to, and because we know what we’re doing and know how we want to live, and know what obstacles have to be overcome before we can live that way, and know how to distinguish between our social patterns and theirs. But we must not think that the capitalist world can simply be ignored, in a live and let live attitude, while we try to build new lives elsewhere. (There is no elsewhere.) There is at least one thing, wage-slavery, that we can’t simply stop participating in (but even here there are ways we can chip away at it). Capitalism must be explicitly refused and replaced by something else. This constitutes War, but it is not a war in the traditional sense of armies and tanks, but a war fought on a daily basis, on the level of everyday life, by millions of people. It is a war nevertheless because the accumulators of capital will use coercion, brutality, and murder, as they have always done in the past, to try to block any rejection of the system. They have always had to force compliance; they will not hesitate to continue doing so. Nevertheless, there are many concrete ways that individuals, groups, and neighborhoods can gut capitalism, which I will enumerate shortly. We must always keep in mind how we became slaves; then we can see more clearly how we can cease being slaves. We were forced into wage-slavery because the ruling class slowly, systematically, and brutally destroyed our ability to live autonomously. By driving us off the land, changing the property laws, destroying community rights, destroying our tools, imposing taxes, destroying our local markets, and so forth, we were forced onto the labor market in order to survive, our only remaining option being to sell, for a wage, our ability to work. It’s quite clear then how we can overthrow slavery. We must reverse this process. We must begin to reacquire the ability to live without working for a wage or buying the products made by wage-slaves (that is, we must get free from the labor market and the way of living based on it), and embed ourselves instead in cooperative labor and cooperatively produced goods.
4,358
<h4><strong>Our alternative is to vote negative to refuse to participate in activities which support capitalism. We must hollow out capitalist structures by refusing to invest our energy in reforms and rescue operations</h4><p>Herod 2004</p><p></strong>(James, Getting Free, http://site.www.umb.edu/faculty/salzman_g/Strate/GetFre/06.htm<u>)</p><p></u>   It is time to try to describe, at first abstractly and later concretely, a strategy for <u><strong><mark>destroying capitalism</u></strong></mark>. This strategy, at its most basic, <u><strong><mark>calls for pulling time, energy, and resources out of capitalist civilization</u></strong></mark> and putting them into building a new civilization. The image then is one <u><strong>of <mark>emptying out capitalist structures</mark>, hollowing them out, by <mark>draining</mark> wealth, power, and <mark>meaning out of them</mark> until there is nothing left but shells.</p><p>      This is definitely an aggressive strategy. It requires great militancy, and constitutes an attack on the existing order. The strategy clearly recognizes that capitalism is the enemy and must be destroyed, but it is not a frontal attack aimed at overthrowing the system, but an inside attack aimed at gutting it, while simultaneously replacing it with something better, something we want.</p><p></u></strong>      Thus <u><strong>capitalist structures</u></strong> (corporations, governments, banks, schools, etc.) <u><strong>are not seized so much as simply abandoned. Capitalist relations are not fought so much as they are simply rejected. <mark>We stop participating in activities that support</u></strong></mark> (finance, condone) <u><strong><mark>the capitalist world</u></strong></mark> and start participating in activities that build a new world while simultaneously undermining the old. We create a new pattern of social relations alongside capitalist relations and then we continually build and strengthen our new pattern while doing every thing we can to weaken capitalist relations. <u><strong>In this way our new democratic</u></strong>, non-hierarchical<u><strong>, non-commodified relations can eventually overwhelm the capitalist relations and force them out of existence.</p><p></u></strong>      <u><strong>This is how it has to be done. <mark>This is a</u></strong></mark> plausible<u><strong>, <mark>realistic strategy</u></strong></mark>. To think that we could create a whole new world of decent social arrangements overnight, in the midst of a crisis, during a so-called revolution, or during the collapse of capitalism, is foolhardy. <u><strong><mark>Our new social world must grow</u></strong></mark> within the old, and <u><strong><mark>in opposition</u></strong></mark> to it, <u><strong>until it is strong enough <mark>to</mark> dismantle and abolish <mark>capitalist relations</mark>.</u></strong> Such a revolution will never happen automatically, blindly, determinably, because of the inexorable, materialist laws of history. <u><strong>It will happen</u></strong>, and only happen, <u><strong>because we want it to</u></strong>, and because we know what we’re doing and know how we want to live, and know what obstacles have to be overcome before we can live that way, and know how to distinguish between our social patterns and theirs.</p><p>      But we must not think that the capitalist world can simply be ignored, in a live and let live attitude, while we try to build new lives elsewhere. (There is no elsewhere.) There is at least one thing, wage-slavery, that we can’t simply stop participating in (but even here there are ways we can chip away at it). <u><strong>Capitalism must be explicitly refused</u></strong> and replaced by something else<u><strong>. <mark>This constitutes</mark> War</u></strong>, but it is not a war in the traditional sense of armies and tanks, but <u><strong><mark>a war fought on a daily basis, on the level of everyday life</u></strong>,</mark> by millions of people. It is a war nevertheless because the accumulators of capital will use coercion, brutality, and murder, as they have always done in the past, to try to block any rejection of the system. They have always had to force compliance; they will not hesitate to continue doing so. Nevertheless, there are many concrete ways that individuals, groups, and neighborhoods can gut capitalism, which I will enumerate shortly.</p><p>      We must always keep in mind how we became slaves; then we can see more clearly how we can cease being slaves. We were forced into wage-slavery because the ruling class slowly, systematically, and brutally destroyed our ability to live autonomously. By driving us off the land, changing the property laws, destroying community rights, destroying our tools, imposing taxes, destroying our local markets, and so forth, we were forced onto the labor market in order to survive, our only remaining option being to sell, for a wage, our ability to work.</p><p>      It’s quite clear then how we can overthrow slavery. We must reverse this process. We must begin to reacquire the ability to live without working for a wage or buying the products made by wage-slaves (that is, we must get free from the labor market and the way of living based on it), and embed ourselves instead in cooperative labor and cooperatively produced goods.</p>
null
null
Cap
48,655
185
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,208
We legalize sales, not purchases – their turns don’t apply
Gill 2
Gill 2 Michael Gill, Ph.D., Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, College of Charleston AND Robert Sade, M.D.,Professor in the Department of Surgery and Director of the Institute of Human Values in Health Care, Medical University of South Carolina. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12.1 (2002) 17-45
/v012/12.1gill.html it ought to be legal for a person to be paid for one of his or her kidneys. We are not arguing that it ought to be legal for a potential recipient to buy a kidney in an open market. We propose that the buyers of kidneys be the agencies in charge of kidney procurement or transplantation; We assume that allocation of kidneys will be based on medical criteria, as in the existing allocation system for cadaveric organs. Kidneys will not be traded in an unregulated market. A similar system is currently in place for blood products: a person can receive money for providing blood products the legalization of kidney sales will increase the number of kidneys that are transplanted each year and thus save the lives of people who would otherwise die. Our proposed kidney sales are more like the sale of blood products in that both involve the market only in acquisition and not in allocation: the current system pays people for plasma while continuing to distribute blood products without regard to patients' economic status, just as we propose for kidneys Our proposal does not address the purchase of kidneys, which is a separate question. Many of the arguments against legalizing the purchase of kidneys do not apply to the sale of kidneys. For example, one argument against permitting the buying of kidneys is that it will reduce the number of donated kidneys and harm the poor who will not be able to afford to buy a kidney. Both arguments rest on empirical claims that are often stated as fact, yet have no supporting evidence. Even if the empirical claims were accurate The important point is that our proposal will not be affected either way. our proposal can be reasonably expected both to increase the overall number of kidneys for transplantation and to increase the chances that a poor person who needs a kidney will receive one. Therefore, in arguing for the legalization of kidney sales, we put aside the separate question of whether buying kidneys ought to be legal as well.
are not arguing that it ought to be legal to buy a kidney in an open market. We propose that buyers be the agencies in charge of procurement allocation of kidneys will be based on medical criteria not an unregulated market the purchase of kidneys, is a separate question. Many arguments against legalizing the purchase do not apply to the sale . , one argument against permitting buying kidneys is that it will reduce the number of donated kidneys and harm the poor who will not be able to afford a kidney. Both arguments rest on empirical claims that have no supporting evidence. our proposal will increase the overall number of kidneys for transplantation and increase the chances that a poor person who needs a kidney will receive one
Paying for Kidneys: The Case against Prohibition http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/kennedy_institute_ of_ethics_journal/v012/12.1gill.html First, we are arguing for the claim that it ought to be legal for a person to be paid for one of his or her kidneys. We are not arguing that it ought to be legal for a potential recipient to buy a kidney in an open market. We propose that the buyers of kidneys be the agencies in charge of kidney procurement or transplantation; that is, we propose that such agencies should be allowed to use financial incentives to acquire kidneys. We assume that allocation of kidneys will be based on medical criteria, as in the existing allocation system for cadaveric organs. Kidneys will not be traded in an unregulated market. 2 A similar system is currently in place for blood products: a person can receive money for providing blood products, but one's chances of receiving blood are distinct from one's financial status. We further note that transplant recipients or their agents—e.g., insurance companies, Medicaid—pay for organs now, compensating the organ procurement organization that organizes the organ retrieval, the surgeon who removes the organ, the hospital where the organ is procured, and so forth. The only component of the organ procurement process not currently paid is the most critical component, the possessor of the kidney, who is sine qua non for organ availability. Second, we believe the legalization of kidney sales will increase the number of kidneys that are transplanted each year and thus save the lives of people who would otherwise die. We base this belief on two views that seem to us very plausible: first, that financial incentives will induce some people to give up a kidney for transplantation who would otherwise not have done so; and second, that the existence of financial incentives will not decrease significantly the current level of live kidney donations. The first view seems to us to follow from the basic idea that people are more likely to do something if they are going to get paid for it. The second view seems to us to follow from the fact that a very large majority of live kidney donations occur between family members and the idea that the motivation of a sister who donates a kidney to a brother, or a parent who donates a kidney to a child, will not be altered by the existence of financial incentives. Although we think these views are plausible, we acknowledge that there is no clear evidence that they are true. If subsequent research were to establish that the legalization of kidney sales would lead to a decrease in the number of kidneys that are transplanted each year, some of the arguments we make would be substantially weakened. 3 Third, we are arguing for allowing payment to living kidney donors, but many of the kidneys available for transplantation come from cadavers. [End Page 19] We believe that payment for cadaveric organs also ought to be legalized, but we will not discuss that issue here. If we successfully make the case for allowing payment to living donors, the case for payment for cadaveric kidneys should follow easily. The Prima Facie Case for Kidney Sales With these preliminary points in mind, we will proceed to the initial argument for permitting payment for kidneys. 4 This argument is based on two claims: the "good donor claim" and the "sale of tissue claim." The good donor claim contends that it is and ought to be legal for a living person to donate one of his or her kidneys to someone else who needs a kidney in order to survive. These donations typically consist of someone giving a kidney to a sibling, spouse, or child, but there are also cases of individuals donating to strangers. Such donations account for about half of all kidney transplants. 5 Our society, moreover, does not simply allow such live kidney donations. Rather, we actively praise and encourage them. 6 We typically take them to be morally unproblematic cases of saving a human life. The sale of tissue claim contends that it is and ought to be legal for living persons to sell parts of their bodies. We can sell such tissues as hair, sperm, and eggs, but the body parts we focus on here are blood products. A kidney is more like blood products than other tissues because both are physical necessities: people need them in order to survive. Our proposed kidney sales are more like the sale of blood products in that both involve the market only in acquisition and not in allocation: the current system pays people for plasma while continuing to distribute blood products without regard to patients' economic status, just as we propose for kidneys. We do not typically praise people who sell their plasma as we do people who donate a kidney to save the life of a sibling. At the same time, most people do not brand commercial blood banks as moral abominations. We generally take them to be an acceptable means of acquiring a resource that is needed to save lives. 7 It is doubtful, for instance, that there would be widespread support for the abolition of payment for plasma if the result were a reduction in supply so severe that thousands of people died every year for lack of blood products. If both the good donor claim and the sale of tissue claim are true, we have at least an initial argument, or prima facie grounds, for holding that payment for kidneys ought to be legal. The good donor claim implies that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer one of his or [End Page 20] her kidneys to someone else, while the sale of tissue claim implies that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer part of his or her body to someone else for money. It thus seems initially plausible to hold that the two claims together imply that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer one of his or her kidneys to someone else for money. Of course, there seems to be an obvious difference between donating a kidney and selling one: motive. Those who donate typically are motivated by benevolence or altruism, while those who sell typically are motivated by monetary self-interest. 8 The sale of tissue claim suggests, however, that this difference on its own is irrelevant to the question of whether kidney sales ought to be legal, because the sale of tissue claim establishes that it ought to be legal to transfer a body part in order to make money. If donating a kidney ought to be legal (the good donor claim), and if the only difference between donating a kidney and selling one is the motive of monetary self-interest, and if the motive of monetary self-interest does not on its own warrant legal prohibition (the sale of tissue claim), then the morally relevant part of the analogy between donating and selling should still obtain and we still have grounds for holding that selling kidneys ought to be legal. There is also an obvious difference between selling a kidney and selling plasma: the invasiveness of the procedure. Phlebotomy for sale of plasma is simple and quick, with no lasting side effects, while parting with a kidney involves major surgery and living with only one kidney thereafter. It is very unlikely, however, that there will be any long-term ill effects from the surgery itself or from life with a single kidney. 9 Indeed, the laws allowing live kidney donations presuppose that the risk to donors is very small and thus morally acceptable. The good donor claim implies, then, that the invasiveness of the procedure of transferring a kidney is not in and of itself a sufficient reason to legally prohibit live kidney transfer. If the only difference between selling plasma and selling a kidney is the risk of the procedure, and if that risk does not constitute grounds for prohibiting live kidney transfers, then the morally relevant part of the analogy between selling plasma and selling a kidney still should obtain and we still have grounds for holding that kidney sales ought to be legal. The point of the preceding two paragraphs is this: if we oppose the sale of kidneys because we think it is too dangerous, then we also should oppose live kidney donations. But we do not oppose live kidney donations because we realize that the risks are acceptably low and worth taking [End Page 21] in order to save lives. So, it is inconsistent to oppose selling kidneys because of the possible dangers while at the same time endorsing the good donor claim. Similarly, if we oppose kidney sales because we think people should not sell body parts, then we should also oppose commercial blood banks. But most people do not oppose blood banks because they realize that the banks play an important role in saving lives. So, it is inconsistent to oppose selling kidneys because it involves payment while at the same time endorsing the sale of tissue claim. 10 The considerable emotional resistance to permitting kidney sales may be based on a combination of distaste for payment and worry about risk. But if neither of these concerns on its own constitutes defensible grounds for opposing payment, then it seems unlikely that the two of them together will do so. This initial argument does not imply that we should legalize the sale of hearts and livers. The initial argument holds only that, if it is medically safe for living people to donate an organ, then people should also be allowed to sell that organ. But it is not medically safe for a living person to donate his or her heart or liver. Our reliance on the good donor claim does, however, commit us to the idea that if it is morally correct to allow someone to donate an organ or part of an organ, then it is morally correct to allow someone to sell that organ or organ part. If, therefore, it is morally correct to allow people to donate liver lobes and parts of lungs, then, according to our initial argument, it ought to be legal for a person to sell a liver lobe or part of a lung as well. Our proposal does not address the purchase of kidneys, which is a separate question. Many of the arguments against legalizing the purchase of kidneys do not apply to the sale of kidneys. For example, one argument against permitting the buying of kidneys is that it will lead to fewer kidneys for transplantation overall. Another argument is that while allowing individuals to purchase kidneys might not reduce the overall number of kidneys available for transplantation, it will reduce the number of donated kidneys and harm the poor who will not be able to afford to buy a kidney. Both arguments rest on empirical claims that are often stated as fact, yet have no supporting evidence. Even if the empirical claims were accurate, moreover, their moral importance could be disputed. Perhaps there are powerful moral reasons to legalize the buying of organs even if doing so leads to fewer organs overall or reduces the chances of a poor person's receiving a kidney transplant. Then again, perhaps a negative effect on the overall supply of kidneys or on the transplantation prospects [End Page 22] for the poor will turn out to be a conclusive reason not to legalize the buying of kidneys. The important point is that our proposal will not be affected either way. As already noted in our preliminary points, our proposal can be reasonably expected both to increase the overall number of kidneys for transplantation and to increase the chances that a poor person who needs a kidney will receive one. Therefore, in arguing for the legalization of kidney sales, we put aside the separate question of whether buying kidneys ought to be legal as well.
11,563
<h4>We legalize sales, not purchases – their turns don’t apply</h4><p><strong>Gill 2</strong> Michael Gill, Ph.D., Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, College of Charleston AND Robert Sade, M.D.,Professor in the Department of Surgery and Director of the Institute of Human Values in Health Care, Medical University of South Carolina. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12.1 (2002) 17-45</p><p>Paying for Kidneys: The Case against Prohibition http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/kennedy_institute_ of_ethics_journal<u>/v012/12.1gill.html</p><p></u>First, we are arguing for the claim that<u> it ought to be legal for a person to be paid for one of his or her kidneys. We <mark>are not arguing that it ought to be legal </mark>for a potential recipient <mark>to buy a kidney in an open market. We propose that </mark>the <mark>buyers </mark>of kidneys <mark>be the agencies in charge of </mark>kidney <mark>procurement </mark>or transplantation; </u>that is, we propose that such agencies should be allowed to use financial incentives to acquire kidneys. <u>We assume that <mark>allocation of kidneys will be based on medical criteria</mark>, as in the existing allocation system for cadaveric organs. Kidneys will <mark>not </mark>be traded in <mark>an unregulated market</mark>.</u> 2 <u>A similar system is currently in place for blood products: a person can receive money for providing blood products</u>, but one's chances of receiving blood are distinct from one's financial status. We further note that transplant recipients or their agents—e.g., insurance companies, Medicaid—pay for organs now, compensating the organ procurement organization that organizes the organ retrieval, the surgeon who removes the organ, the hospital where the organ is procured, and so forth. The only component of the organ procurement process not currently paid is the most critical component, the possessor of the kidney, who is sine qua non for organ availability. Second, we believe <u>the legalization of kidney sales will increase the number of kidneys that are transplanted each year and thus save the lives of people who would otherwise die.</u> We base this belief on two views that seem to us very plausible: first, that financial incentives will induce some people to give up a kidney for transplantation who would otherwise not have done so; and second, that the existence of financial incentives will not decrease significantly the current level of live kidney donations. The first view seems to us to follow from the basic idea that people are more likely to do something if they are going to get paid for it. The second view seems to us to follow from the fact that a very large majority of live kidney donations occur between family members and the idea that the motivation of a sister who donates a kidney to a brother, or a parent who donates a kidney to a child, will not be altered by the existence of financial incentives. Although we think these views are plausible, we acknowledge that there is no clear evidence that they are true. If subsequent research were to establish that the legalization of kidney sales would lead to a decrease in the number of kidneys that are transplanted each year, some of the arguments we make would be substantially weakened. 3 Third, we are arguing for allowing payment to living kidney donors, but many of the kidneys available for transplantation come from cadavers. [End Page 19] We believe that payment for cadaveric organs also ought to be legalized, but we will not discuss that issue here. If we successfully make the case for allowing payment to living donors, the case for payment for cadaveric kidneys should follow easily. The Prima Facie Case for Kidney Sales With these preliminary points in mind, we will proceed to the initial argument for permitting payment for kidneys. 4 This argument is based on two claims: the "good donor claim" and the "sale of tissue claim." The good donor claim contends that it is and ought to be legal for a living person to donate one of his or her kidneys to someone else who needs a kidney in order to survive. These donations typically consist of someone giving a kidney to a sibling, spouse, or child, but there are also cases of individuals donating to strangers. Such donations account for about half of all kidney transplants. 5 Our society, moreover, does not simply allow such live kidney donations. Rather, we actively praise and encourage them. 6 We typically take them to be morally unproblematic cases of saving a human life. The sale of tissue claim contends that it is and ought to be legal for living persons to sell parts of their bodies. We can sell such tissues as hair, sperm, and eggs, but the body parts we focus on here are blood products. A kidney is more like blood products than other tissues because both are physical necessities: people need them in order to survive. <u>Our proposed kidney sales are more like the sale of blood products in that both involve the market only in acquisition and not in allocation: the current system pays people for plasma while continuing to distribute blood products without regard to patients' economic status, just as we propose for kidneys</u>. We do not typically praise people who sell their plasma as we do people who donate a kidney to save the life of a sibling. At the same time, most people do not brand commercial blood banks as moral abominations. We generally take them to be an acceptable means of acquiring a resource that is needed to save lives. 7 It is doubtful, for instance, that there would be widespread support for the abolition of payment for plasma if the result were a reduction in supply so severe that thousands of people died every year for lack of blood products. If both the good donor claim and the sale of tissue claim are true, we have at least an initial argument, or prima facie grounds, for holding that payment for kidneys ought to be legal. The good donor claim implies that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer one of his or [End Page 20] her kidneys to someone else, while the sale of tissue claim implies that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer part of his or her body to someone else for money. It thus seems initially plausible to hold that the two claims together imply that it ought to be legal for a living person to decide to transfer one of his or her kidneys to someone else for money. Of course, there seems to be an obvious difference between donating a kidney and selling one: motive. Those who donate typically are motivated by benevolence or altruism, while those who sell typically are motivated by monetary self-interest. 8 The sale of tissue claim suggests, however, that this difference on its own is irrelevant to the question of whether kidney sales ought to be legal, because the sale of tissue claim establishes that it ought to be legal to transfer a body part in order to make money. If donating a kidney ought to be legal (the good donor claim), and if the only difference between donating a kidney and selling one is the motive of monetary self-interest, and if the motive of monetary self-interest does not on its own warrant legal prohibition (the sale of tissue claim), then the morally relevant part of the analogy between donating and selling should still obtain and we still have grounds for holding that selling kidneys ought to be legal. There is also an obvious difference between selling a kidney and selling plasma: the invasiveness of the procedure. Phlebotomy for sale of plasma is simple and quick, with no lasting side effects, while parting with a kidney involves major surgery and living with only one kidney thereafter. It is very unlikely, however, that there will be any long-term ill effects from the surgery itself or from life with a single kidney. 9 Indeed, the laws allowing live kidney donations presuppose that the risk to donors is very small and thus morally acceptable. The good donor claim implies, then, that the invasiveness of the procedure of transferring a kidney is not in and of itself a sufficient reason to legally prohibit live kidney transfer. If the only difference between selling plasma and selling a kidney is the risk of the procedure, and if that risk does not constitute grounds for prohibiting live kidney transfers, then the morally relevant part of the analogy between selling plasma and selling a kidney still should obtain and we still have grounds for holding that kidney sales ought to be legal. The point of the preceding two paragraphs is this: if we oppose the sale of kidneys because we think it is too dangerous, then we also should oppose live kidney donations. But we do not oppose live kidney donations because we realize that the risks are acceptably low and worth taking [End Page 21] in order to save lives. So, it is inconsistent to oppose selling kidneys because of the possible dangers while at the same time endorsing the good donor claim. Similarly, if we oppose kidney sales because we think people should not sell body parts, then we should also oppose commercial blood banks. But most people do not oppose blood banks because they realize that the banks play an important role in saving lives. So, it is inconsistent to oppose selling kidneys because it involves payment while at the same time endorsing the sale of tissue claim. 10 The considerable emotional resistance to permitting kidney sales may be based on a combination of distaste for payment and worry about risk. But if neither of these concerns on its own constitutes defensible grounds for opposing payment, then it seems unlikely that the two of them together will do so. This initial argument does not imply that we should legalize the sale of hearts and livers. The initial argument holds only that, if it is medically safe for living people to donate an organ, then people should also be allowed to sell that organ. But it is not medically safe for a living person to donate his or her heart or liver. Our reliance on the good donor claim does, however, commit us to the idea that if it is morally correct to allow someone to donate an organ or part of an organ, then it is morally correct to allow someone to sell that organ or organ part. If, therefore, it is morally correct to allow people to donate liver lobes and parts of lungs, then, according to our initial argument, it ought to be legal for a person to sell a liver lobe or part of a lung as well. <u>Our proposal does not address <mark>the purchase of kidneys, </mark>which <mark>is a separate question. Many </mark>of the <mark>arguments against legalizing the purchase </mark>of kidneys <mark>do not apply to the sale </mark>of kidneys<mark>.</u> <u></mark>For example<mark>, one argument against permitting </mark>the <mark>buying </mark>of <mark>kidneys is that it</u></mark> will lead to fewer kidneys for transplantation overall. Another argument is that while allowing individuals to purchase kidneys might not reduce the overall number of kidneys available for transplantation, it <u><mark>will reduce the number of donated kidneys and harm the poor who will not be able to afford </mark>to buy <mark>a kidney.</u> <u>Both arguments rest on empirical claims that </mark>are often stated as fact, yet<mark> have no supporting evidence. </mark>Even if the empirical claims were accurate</u>, moreover, their moral importance could be disputed. Perhaps there are powerful moral reasons to legalize the buying of organs even if doing so leads to fewer organs overall or reduces the chances of a poor person's receiving a kidney transplant. Then again, perhaps a negative effect on the overall supply of kidneys or on the transplantation prospects [End Page 22] for the poor will turn out to be a conclusive reason not to legalize the buying of kidneys. <u>The important point is that <mark>our proposal will </mark>not be affected either way.</u> As already noted in our preliminary points, <u>our proposal can be reasonably expected both to<mark> increase the overall number of kidneys for transplantation and </mark>to <mark>increase the chances that a poor person who needs a kidney will receive one</mark>. Therefore, in arguing for the legalization of kidney sales, we put aside the separate question of whether buying kidneys ought to be legal as well. </p></u>
null
null
Contention 3 The Plan solves
430,594
8
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,209
Claimed inevitability is the worst act of closure – alternative discourse is key and empirically solves
null
Kraig 02 – Robert Alexander is Wisconsin state political director for Service Employees International Union (SEIU). He is also an instructor in the Communication Department at the University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Rhetoric & Public Affairs 5.1 1-30
Given the claimed inevitability of realism's description one might think that nations need not look to expert guidance realist/idealist dichotomy dichotomy is used to discredit leaders who dare to consider transcending or transforming established patterns It is assumed that strategic doctrine can be rationally and objectively established The science This objective order can only be revealed by rational and dispassionate investigators who are well-schooled in the constraints and possibilities of power politics realism presumes that human social nature, even if ethically deplorable, cannot be significantly improved , is fate Tremendous human suffering can be rationalized away as the inevitable product of the impersonal international system of power relations. World leaders are actively encouraged to put aside moral pangs of doubt and play the game of international politics according to the established rules of political engagement. . Since ideals cannot be valid in a social scientific sense, they cannot be objectively true The greatest barrier to engaging the realists in serious dialogue about their premises is that they deny that these questions can be seriously debated imparted through the back door. It is very hard to argue with prescription under the guise of description. matter of first principles denies all others alleged to be an immutable reality that we must accept to avoid disastrous consequences amateurs. no standing in debate those who question the existence or universality of this controlling scene are beyond debate determinism of political realism, even though it is grounded in human social nature, is antihumanist democratic thought of the last 200 years is grounded on the idea that humanity is self-determining. Society as social contract is a joint project which, over time, is subject to dialectical improvement beyond the power of humans to mediate ] face a powerful rhetorical arsenal that will be used to deflect any serious dialogue on the fundamental ethical and strategic assumptions of realism symbolic ammunition What is needed is a full-blooded antirealist rhetoric. It must be said, in the strongest possible terms, that realism engenders an attitude of cynicism and fatalism in those who would otherwise engage the great moral and political questions of our age. History is replete with ideals that, matured into new social realities. In the not-so-distant past, republican governance on a mass scale and socially active government were empirical impossibilities. However halting and imperfect these historical innovations may be, they suggest the power of ideals and the possibility of human social transformation. On the other hand, fatalism fulfills itself. The surest way to make a situation impossible is to imagine it so.
Given claimed inevitability of realism one might think nations need not look to expert guidance realist dichotomy is used to discredit leaders who consider transcending established patterns Tremendous suffering can be rationalized away as the product of the impersonal system of power leaders are encouraged to put aside moral pangs of doubt and play the game of politics realists deny these questions can be debated determinism of realism is antihumanist democratic thought of the last 200 years is grounded on the idea that humanity i self-determining. Society as social contract which is subject to dialectical improvement What is needed is a full-blooded antirealist rhetoric. that realism engenders cynicism and fatalism in those who would engage moral questions History is replete with ideals that matured into social realities. In the not-so-distant past, republican governance and socially active government were impossibilities. they suggest possibility of human social transformation surest way to make a situation impossible is to imagine it so.
Given the claimed inevitability of realism's description of international politics, one might think that nations need not look to expert guidance because power interests will inevitably determine governmental policy. But the realists, while embracing determinism, simultaneously argue that human nature is repeatedly violated. One traditional claim has been that America, because of its unique history, has been ever in danger of ignoring the dictates of the foreign policy scene. This argument is offered by Henry Kissinger in his avowedly Morgenthauian work Nuclear Weapons and Foreign Policy. 21 Realists also argue that there are idealists in all human societies who refuse to see the reality of power. As Richard W. Cottam, a trenchant critic of orthodox realism, explained the argument: "Every era has its incorrigible idealists who persist in seeing evil man as good. When they somehow gain power and seek to put their ideas into effect, Machiavellians who understand man's true nature appear and are more than willing and more than capable of exploiting this eternal naivete." 22 Cottam was referring to one of the central ideological constructs of international relations theory—the realist/idealist dichotomy. First explicated in detail by Morgenthau in his Scientific Man vs. Power Politics, 23 this dichotomy is used to discredit leaders who dare to consider transcending or transforming established patterns of global competition. This construct is enriched by the narratives of failed idealists—most prominently Tsar Alexander the First, Woodrow Wilson, Neville Chamberlain, and Jimmy Carter—men who, despite and in fact because of their good intentions, caused untold human suffering. After World War II, realists built their conception of leadership on a negative caricature of Woodrow Wilson. 24 As George Kennan, one of the primary architects of Cold War policy, warned in 1945: "If we insist at this moment in our history in wandering about with our heads in the clouds of Wilsonean idealism . . . we run the risk of losing even that bare minimum of security which would be assured to us by the maintenance of humane, stable, and cooperative forms of society on the immediate European shores of the Atlantic." 25 Wilson's supposed idealism was said by the emerging realist scholars to have led to the unstable international political structure that caused World War II [End Page 6] and now threatened the postwar balance of forces. Despite convincing refutations by the leading historians of Wilson's presidency, most recently John Milton Cooper Jr. in his definitive study of the League of Nations controversy, realists continue to caricature Wilson as a fuzzy-headed idealist. 26 Idealists, in realist writings, all share a fatal flaw: an inability to comprehend the realities of power. They live in a world of unreality, responding to nonexistent scenes. As Riker put it, "Unquestionably, there are guilt-ridden and shame-conscious men who do not desire to win, who in fact desire to lose. These are irrational ones in politics." 27 It is here that the realist expert comes in. It is assumed that strategic doctrine can be rationally and objectively established. According to Kissinger, a theorist who later became a leading practitioner, "it is the task of strategic doctrine to translate power into policy." The science of international relations claims the capacity to chart the foreign policy scene and then establish the ends and means of national policy. This objective order can only be revealed by rational and dispassionate investigators who are well-schooled in the constraints and possibilities of power politics. Realism's scenic character makes it a radically empirical science. As Morgenthau put it, the political realist "believes in the possibility of distinguishing in politics between truth and opinion—between what is true objectively and rationally supported by evidence and illuminated by reason, and what is only subjective judgement." Avowedly modernist in orientation, realism claims to be rooted not in a theory of how international relations ought to work, but in a privileged reading of a necessary and predetermined foreign policy environment. 28 In its orthodox form political realism assumes that international politics are and must be dominated by the will to power. Moral aspirations in the international arena are merely protective coloration and propaganda or the illusions that move hopeless idealists. What is most revealing about this assessment of human nature is not its negativity but its fatalism. There is little if any place for human moral evolution or perfectibility. Like environmental determinism—most notably the social darwinism of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries—political realism presumes that human social nature, even if ethically deplorable, cannot be significantly improved upon. From the stationary perspective of social scientific realism in its pure form, the fatal environment of human social interaction can be navigated but not conquered. Description, in other words, is fate. All who dare to challenge the order—Carter's transgression—will do much more damage than good. The idealist makes a bad situation much worse by imagining a better world in the face of immutable realities. As one popular saying among foreign policy practitioners goes: "Without vision, men die. With it, more men die." 70 (continued) The implications of this social philosophy are stark. Tremendous human suffering can be rationalized away as the inevitable product of the impersonal international system of power relations. World leaders are actively encouraged by the realists to put aside moral pangs of doubt and play the game of international politics according to the established rules of political engagement. This deliberate limitation of interest excuses leaders from making hard moral choices. While a moralist Protestant like Jimmy Carter sees history as a progressive moral struggle to realize abstract ideals in the world, the realist believes that it is dangerous to struggle against the inexorable. The moral ambiguities of political and social ethics that have dogged philosophy and statesmanship time out of mind are simply written out of the equation. Since ideals cannot be valid in a social scientific sense, they cannot be objectively true. The greatest barrier to engaging the realists in serious dialogue about their premises is that they deny that these questions can be seriously debated. First, realists teach a moral philosophy that denies itself. There is exceedingly narrow ground, particularly in the technical vocabulary of the social sciences, for discussing the moral potential of humanity or the limitations of human action. Yet, as we have seen in the tragedy of Jimmy Carter, a philosophical perspective on these very questions is imparted through the back door. It is very hard to argue with prescription under the guise of description. The purveyors of this philosophical outlook will not admit this to themselves, let alone to potential interlocutors. [End Page 21] Second, and most importantly, alternative perspectives are not admitted as possibilities—realism is a perspective that as a matter of first principles denies all others. There is, as we have seen in the Carter narrative, alleged to be an immutable reality that we must accept to avoid disastrous consequences. Those who do not see this underlying order of things are idealists or amateurs. Such people have no standing in debate because they do not see the intractable scene that dominates human action. Dialogue is permissible within the parameters of the presumed order, but those who question the existence or universality of this controlling scene are beyond debate. Third, the environmental determinism of political realism, even though it is grounded in human social nature, is antihumanist. Much of the democratic thought of the last 200 years is grounded on the idea that humanity is in some sense socially self-determining. Society as social contract is a joint project which, over time, is subject to dialectical improvement. Foreign policy realism, as we have seen, presupposes that there is an order to human relations that is beyond the power of humans to mediate. 71 When you add to this the moral imperative to be faithful to the order (the moral of the Carter narrative), then democratic forms lose a great deal of their value. Indeed, there has been a great deal of hand wringing in international relations literature about how the masses are inexorably drawn to idealists like Carter and Wilson. Morgenthau states this much more frankly than most of his intellectual descendants: [the] thinking required for the successful conduct of foreign policy can be diametrically opposed to the rhetoric and action by which the masses and their representatives are likely to be moved. . . . The statesman must think in terms of the national interest, conceived as power among other powers. The popular mind, unaware of the fine distinctions of the statesman's thinking, reasons more often than not in the simple moralistic and legalistic terms of absolute good and absolute evil. 72 Some realists, based on this empirical observation, openly propose that a realist foreign policy be cloaked in a moral facade so that it will be publicly palatable. Kissinger's mistake, they say, was that he was too honest. Morgenthau concludes that "the simple philosophy and techniques of the moral crusade are useful and even indispensable for the domestic task of marshaling public opinion behind a given policy; they are but blunt weapons in the struggle of nations for dominance over the minds of men." If one believes that social scientists have unique access to an inexorable social reality which is beyond the control of humanity—and which it is social suicide to ignore—it is easy to see how democratic notions of consent and self-determination can give way to the reign of manipulative propaganda. 73 There is another lesson that can be drawn from the savaging of Carter in international relations scholarship for those who seek to broaden the terms of American foreign policy thought and practice. Those who would challenge the realist orthodoxy [End Page 22] face a powerful rhetorical arsenal that will be used to deflect any serious dialogue on the fundamental ethical and strategic assumptions of realism. Careful and balanced academic critiques, although indispensable, are unlikely to be a match for such formidable symbolic ammunition. Post-realism, if it is to make any advance against the realist battlements, must marshal equally powerful symbolic resources. What is needed, in addition to academic critiques aimed at other scholars, is a full-blooded antirealist rhetoric. It must be said, in the strongest possible terms, that realism engenders an attitude of cynicism and fatalism in those who would otherwise engage the great moral and political questions of our age. 74 History is replete with ideals that, after much time and effort, matured into new social realities. In the not-so-distant past, republican governance on a mass scale and socially active government were empirical impossibilities. However halting and imperfect these historical innovations may be, they suggest the power of ideals and the possibility of human social transformation. On the other hand, fatalism fulfills itself. The surest way to make a situation impossible is to imagine it so. This is a tragic irony we should strive to avoid, no matter how aesthetically fitting it may be.
11,554
<h4>Claimed inevitability is the worst act of closure – alternative discourse is key and empirically solves </h4><p>Kraig 02 – Robert Alexander is Wisconsin state political director for Service Employees International Union (SEIU). He is also an instructor in the Communication Department at the University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Rhetoric & Public Affairs 5.1 1<u>-30</p><p><mark>Given</mark> the <mark>claimed inevitability of realism</mark>'s description</u> of international politics, <u><mark>one might think </mark>that <mark>nations need not look to expert guidance</mark> </u>because power interests will inevitably determine governmental policy. But the realists, while embracing determinism, simultaneously argue that human nature is repeatedly violated. One traditional claim has been that America, because of its unique history, has been ever in danger of ignoring the dictates of the foreign policy scene. This argument is offered by Henry Kissinger in his avowedly Morgenthauian work Nuclear Weapons and Foreign Policy. 21 Realists also argue that there are idealists in all human societies who refuse to see the reality of power. As Richard W. Cottam, a trenchant critic of orthodox realism, explained the argument: "Every era has its incorrigible idealists who persist in seeing evil man as good. When they somehow gain power and seek to put their ideas into effect, Machiavellians who understand man's true nature appear and are more than willing and more than capable of exploiting this eternal naivete." 22 Cottam was referring to one of the central ideological constructs of international relations theory—the<u> <mark>realist</mark>/idealist dichotomy</u>. First explicated in detail by Morgenthau in his Scientific Man vs. Power Politics, 23 this <u><mark>dichotomy is used to discredit leaders who</mark> dare to <mark>consider transcending</mark> or transforming <mark>established patterns</u></mark> of global competition. This construct is enriched by the narratives of failed idealists—most prominently Tsar Alexander the First, Woodrow Wilson, Neville Chamberlain, and Jimmy Carter—men who, despite and in fact because of their good intentions, caused untold human suffering. After World War II, realists built their conception of leadership on a negative caricature of Woodrow Wilson. 24 As George Kennan, one of the primary architects of Cold War policy, warned in 1945: "If we insist at this moment in our history in wandering about with our heads in the clouds of Wilsonean idealism . . . we run the risk of losing even that bare minimum of security which would be assured to us by the maintenance of humane, stable, and cooperative forms of society on the immediate European shores of the Atlantic." 25 Wilson's supposed idealism was said by the emerging realist scholars to have led to the unstable international political structure that caused World War II [End Page 6] and now threatened the postwar balance of forces. Despite convincing refutations by the leading historians of Wilson's presidency, most recently John Milton Cooper Jr. in his definitive study of the League of Nations controversy, realists continue to caricature Wilson as a fuzzy-headed idealist. 26 Idealists, in realist writings, all share a fatal flaw: an inability to comprehend the realities of power. They live in a world of unreality, responding to nonexistent scenes. As Riker put it, "Unquestionably, there are guilt-ridden and shame-conscious men who do not desire to win, who in fact desire to lose. These are irrational ones in politics." 27 It is here that the realist expert comes in.<u> It is assumed that strategic doctrine can be <strong>rationally and objectively established</u></strong>. According to Kissinger, a theorist who later became a leading practitioner, "it is the task of strategic doctrine to translate power into policy." <u><strong>The science</u> </strong>of international relations claims the capacity to chart the foreign policy scene and then establish the ends and means of national policy<strong>. <u>This objective order can only be revealed by rational and dispassionate investigators who are well-schooled in the constraints and possibilities of power politics</u>.</strong> Realism's scenic character makes it a radically empirical science. As Morgenthau put it, the political realist "believes in the possibility of distinguishing in politics between truth and opinion—between what is true objectively and rationally supported by evidence and illuminated by reason, and what is only subjective judgement." Avowedly modernist in orientation, realism claims to be rooted not in a theory of how international relations ought to work, but in a privileged reading of a necessary and predetermined foreign policy environment. 28 In its orthodox form political realism assumes that international politics are and must be dominated by the will to power. Moral aspirations in the international arena are merely protective coloration and propaganda or the illusions that move hopeless idealists. What is most revealing about this assessment of human nature is not its negativity but its fatalism. There is little if any place for human moral evolution or perfectibility. Like environmental determinism—most notably the social darwinism of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries—political <u>realism presumes that human social nature, even if ethically deplorable, cannot be significantly improved </u>upon. From the stationary perspective of social scientific realism in its pure form, the fatal environment of human social interaction can be navigated but not conquered. Description, in other words<u><strong>, is fate</u></strong>. All who dare to challenge the order—Carter's transgression—will do much more damage than good. The idealist makes a bad situation much worse by imagining a better world in the face of immutable realities. As one popular saying among foreign policy practitioners goes: "Without vision, men die. With it, more men die." 70 (continued) The implications of this social philosophy are stark. <u><strong><mark>Tremendous</mark> human <mark>suffering can be rationalized away as the</mark> inevitable <mark>product of the impersonal</mark> international <mark>system of power</mark> relations. </strong>World <mark>leaders are</mark> actively <mark>encouraged</u></mark> by the realists <u><mark>to put aside moral pangs of doubt and <strong>play the game</strong> of</mark> international <mark>politics</mark> according to the established rules of political engagement. </u>This deliberate limitation of interest excuses leaders from making hard moral choices. While a moralist Protestant like Jimmy Carter sees history as a progressive moral struggle to realize abstract ideals in the world, the realist believes that it is dangerous to struggle against the inexorable. The moral ambiguities of political and social ethics that have dogged philosophy and statesmanship time out of mind are simply written out of the equation<u>. Since ideals cannot be valid in a social scientific sense, they cannot be objectively true</u>.<u> The greatest barrier to engaging the <mark>realists </mark>in serious dialogue about their premises is that they <strong><mark>deny</mark> that <mark>these questions can be</mark> seriously <mark>debated</u></strong></mark>. First, realists teach a moral philosophy that denies itself. There is exceedingly narrow ground, particularly in the technical vocabulary of the social sciences, for discussing the moral potential of humanity or the limitations of human action. Yet, as we have seen in the tragedy of Jimmy Carter, a philosophical perspective on these very questions is <u><strong>imparted through the back door.</u> <u>It is very hard to argue with prescription under the guise of description.</u></strong> The purveyors of this philosophical outlook will not admit this to themselves, let alone to potential interlocutors. [End Page 21] Second, and most importantly, alternative perspectives are not admitted as possibilities—realism is a perspective that as a <u><strong>matter of first principles denies all others</u></strong>. There is, as we have seen in the Carter narrative, <u><strong>alleged to be an immutable reality that we must accept to avoid disastrous consequences</u></strong>. Those who do not see this underlying order of things are idealists or <u><strong>amateurs.</u></strong> Such people have <u><strong>no standing in debate</u></strong> because they do not see the intractable scene that dominates human action. Dialogue is permissible within the parameters of the presumed order, but <u><strong>those who question the existence or universality of this controlling scene are beyond debate</u>.</strong> Third, the environmental<u> <mark>determinism of</mark> political <mark>realism</mark>, even though it is grounded in human social nature, <mark>is antihumanist</u></mark>. Much of the <u><mark>democratic thought of the last 200 years is grounded on the idea that humanity i</mark>s</u> in some sense socially <u><mark>self-determining. Society as social contract</mark> is a joint project <mark>which</mark>, over time, <mark>is subject to dialectical improvement</u></mark>. Foreign policy realism, as we have seen, presupposes that there is an order to human relations that is <u><strong>beyond the power of humans to mediate</u>.</strong> 71 When you add to this the moral imperative to be faithful to the order (the moral of the Carter narrative), then democratic forms lose a great deal of their value. Indeed, there has been a great deal of hand wringing in international relations literature about how the masses are inexorably drawn to idealists like Carter and Wilson. Morgenthau states this much more frankly than most of his intellectual descendants: [the] thinking required for the successful conduct of foreign policy can be diametrically opposed to the rhetoric and action by which the masses and their representatives are likely to be moved. . . . The statesman must think in terms of the national interest, conceived as power among other powers. The popular mind, unaware of the fine distinctions of the statesman's thinking, reasons more often than not in the simple moralistic and legalistic terms of absolute good and absolute evil. 72 Some realists, based on this empirical observation, openly propose that a realist foreign policy be cloaked in a moral facade so that it will be publicly palatable. Kissinger's mistake, they say, was that he was too honest. Morgenthau concludes that "the simple philosophy and techniques of the moral crusade are useful and even indispensable for the domestic task of marshaling public opinion behind a given policy; they are but blunt weapons in the struggle of nations for dominance over the minds of men." If one believes that social scientists have unique access to an inexorable social reality which is beyond the control of humanity—and which it is social suicide to ignore—it is easy to see how democratic notions of consent and self-determination can give way to the reign of manipulative propaganda. 73 There is another lesson that can be drawn from the savaging of Carter in international relations scholarship for those who seek to broaden the terms of American foreign policy thought and practice. Those who would challenge the realist orthodoxy [End Page 22<u><strong>] face a powerful rhetorical arsenal that will be used to deflect any serious dialogue on the fundamental ethical and strategic assumptions of realism</u>.</strong> Careful and balanced academic critiques, although indispensable, are unlikely to be a match for such formidable <u><strong>symbolic ammunition</u></strong>. Post-realism, if it is to make any advance against the realist battlements, must marshal equally powerful symbolic resources. <u><mark>What is needed</u></mark>, in addition to academic critiques aimed at other scholars, <u><strong><mark>is a full-blooded antirealist rhetoric</strong>.</mark> It must be said, in the <strong>strongest possible terms,</strong> <mark>that realism engenders</mark> an attitude of <mark>cynicism and fatalism in those who</mark> <mark>would</mark> otherwise <mark>engage</mark> the great <mark>moral</mark> and political <mark>questions</mark> of our age.</u> 74 <u><mark>History is replete with ideals that</mark>,</u> after much time and effort, <u><mark>matured into</mark> new <mark>social realities. In the not-so-distant past, republican governance</mark> on a mass scale <mark>and socially active government were</mark> empirical <mark>impossibilities.</u> <u></mark>However halting and imperfect these historical innovations may be, <mark>they suggest</mark> the power of ideals and the <mark>possibility of human social transformation</mark>. On the other hand, fatalism fulfills itself. <strong>The <mark>surest way to make a situation impossible is to imagine it so</strong>. </u><strong></mark>This is a tragic irony we should strive to avoid, no matter how aesthetically fitting it may be.</p></strong>
Block
AT: Empirics
AT: Inevitable
877
18
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,210
Another clarification is needed. This strategy does not call for reforming capitalism, for changing capitalism into something else. It calls for replacing capitalism, totally, with a new civilization. This is an important distinction, because capitalism has proved impervious to reforms, as a system. We can sometimes in some places win certain concessions from it (usually only temporary ones) and win some (usually short-lived) improvements in our lives as its victims, but we cannot reform it piecemeal, as a system.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>  <u><strong>Another clarification is needed.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>This strategy does not call for reforming capitalism, for changing capitalism into something else.</mark> <mark>It calls for replacing capitalism</mark>, totally</u></strong>, with a new civilization. This is an important distinction, because <u><strong><mark>capitalism has proved impervious to reforms</mark>, as a system. We can sometimes in some places win certain concessions from it (usually only temporary ones) and win some (usually short-lived) improvements in our lives as its victims, but <mark>we cannot reform it piecemeal, as a system</strong></mark>.</h4></u>
null
null
Cap
430,611
1
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,211
The ban on organ sales for transplant has created a large and growing shortage
Williams 14
Williams 14 Kristy L. Williams, University of Houston Law Center, Health Law & Policy Institute; University of Texas Medical Branch, Institute of Medical Humanities.; Marisa Finley, Baylor Scott & White Health Center for Health Care Policy; J. James Rohack, Baylor Scott & White Health March 31, 2014 American Journal of Law and Medicine, Forthcoming Just Say No to NOTA: Why the Prohibition of Compensation for Human Transplant Organs in NOTA Should Be Repealed and a Regulated Market for Cadaver
Organ transplantation saves thousands of lives every year. However, many individuals die waiting for transplants due to an insufficiency of organs Currently, more than 122,000 individuals are waitlisted for organs in the U S Due to financial and other barriers to becoming waitlisted, the actual number requiring organs is likely higher This gap between available organs and the need for organs continues to widen The supply of organs is limited as only a small number of individuals die in circumstances medically eligible for organ donation, The current organ donation system in the United States relies on the altruism of donors. The (NOTA) prohibits the receipt of any form of valuable consideration in exchange for organs to be used for transplantation other methods have been employed in attempts to increase donations Despite the implementation of these strategies, a severe organ shortage remains
many individuals die waiting for transplants due to an insufficiency of organ more than 122,000 individuals are waitlisted Due to financial and other barriers to becoming waitlisted, the actual number is higher The current organ donation system in the United States relies on the altruism of donors. NOTA) prohibits the receipt of any form of valuable consideration in exchange for organs other methods have been employed in attempts to increase donations a severe organ shortage remains.
Organs Instituted http://ssrn.com/abstract=2418514 Organ transplantation saves thousands of lives every year. However, many individuals die waiting for transplants due to an insufficiency of organs.1 Currently, more than 122,000 individuals are waitlisted for organs in the United States.2 Due to financial and other barriers to becoming waitlisted, the actual number of Americans requiring organs is likely higher.3 This gap between available organs and the need for organs continues to widen.4 The supply of organs is limited as only a small number of individuals die in circumstances medically eligible for organ donation, and less than sixty-eight percent of eligible individuals donate.5 As a result of those long waitlists and limited supply there is a substantial need to increase organ donations. This paper will focus on increasing consent rates for cadaveric organ donation in the Unites States by repealing current law prohibiting cadaveric donors and their estates from being financially compensated.6 The current organ donation system in the United States relies on the altruism of donors. The National Organ Transplantation Act (NOTA) prohibits the receipt of any form of valuable consideration in exchange for organs to be used for transplantation.7 State statutes also prohibit the sale of certain organs and tissue for transplantation; however, state laws vary widely as to what body parts are covered.8 As paying for organs is prohibited, other methods have been employed in attempts to increase donations.9 Despite the implementation of these strategies, a severe organ shortage remains.
1,611
<h4>The ban on organ sales for transplant has created a large and growing shortage</h4><p><strong>Williams 14</strong> Kristy L. Williams, University of Houston Law Center, Health Law & Policy Institute; University of Texas Medical Branch, Institute of Medical Humanities.; Marisa Finley, Baylor Scott & White Health Center for Health Care Policy; J. James Rohack, Baylor Scott & White Health March 31, 2014 American Journal of Law and Medicine, Forthcoming Just Say No to NOTA: Why the Prohibition of Compensation for Human Transplant Organs in NOTA Should Be Repealed and a Regulated Market for Cadaver </p><p>Organs Instituted http://ssrn.com/abstract=2418514</p><p><u>Organ transplantation saves thousands of lives every year. However, <mark>many individuals die waiting for transplants due to an insufficiency of organ</mark>s</u>.1 <u>Currently, <mark>more than 122,000 individuals are waitlisted</mark> for organs in the U</u>nited <u>S</u>tates.2 <u><mark>Due to financial and other barriers to becoming waitlisted, the actual number</mark> </u>of Americans <u>requiring organs <mark>is</mark> likely <mark>higher</u></mark>.3 <u>This gap between available organs and the need for organs continues to widen</u>.4 <u>The supply of organs is limited as only a small number of individuals die in circumstances medically eligible for organ donation, </u>and less than sixty-eight percent of eligible individuals donate.5 As a result of those long waitlists and limited supply there is a substantial need to increase organ donations. This paper will focus on increasing consent rates for cadaveric organ donation in the Unites States by repealing current law prohibiting cadaveric donors and their estates from being financially compensated.6 <u><mark>The current organ donation system in the United States relies on the altruism of donors.</mark> The</u> National Organ Transplantation Act <u>(<mark>NOTA) prohibits the receipt of any form of valuable consideration in exchange for organs</mark> to be used for transplantation</u>.7 State statutes also prohibit the sale of certain organs and tissue for transplantation; however, state laws vary widely as to what body parts are covered.8 As paying for organs is prohibited, <u><mark>other methods have been employed in attempts to increase donations</u></mark>.9 <u>Despite the implementation of these strategies, <mark>a severe organ shortage remains</u>.</p></mark>
null
null
Contention 1 – Organ sales will save lives
430,245
16
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,212
CP PICs out of “physician assisted” part of plan---solves the case while avoiding our net-benefits.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>CP PICs out of “physician assisted” part of plan---solves the case while avoiding our net-benefits.</h4>
null
Off
CP
430,612
1
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,213
Review of literature concludes that sales will increase supply
Beard et al 13
Beard et al 13 T. Randolph "Randy" Beard, Professor of Economics at Auburn University.; Rigmar Osterkamp, Fellow at the School for Political Studies at University of Munich.; And David L. Kaserman, Torchmark Professor of Economics at Auburn University.2013 The Global Organ Shortage: Economic Causes, Human Consequences, Policy Responses
On balance, a fair-minded reading of the evidence suggests that compensation for donors, if done correctly and sensibly, would increase, probably substantially, the number of organs available for transplant. In the cases of both deceased donors (and their families) and living donors, available evidence confirms the observation that people respond to incentives
On balance a fair reading of the evidence suggests that compensation for donors would increase substantially the number of organs available for transplant both deceased donors (and their families) and living donors respond to incentives
On balance, a fair-minded reading of the evidence suggests that compensation for donors, if done correctly and sensibly, would increase, probably substantially, the number of organs available for transplant. In the cases of both deceased donors (and their families) and living donors, available evidence confirms the observation that people respond to incentives.
363
<h4>Review of literature concludes that sales will increase supply</h4><p><strong>Beard et al 13</strong> T. Randolph "Randy" Beard, Professor of Economics at Auburn University.; Rigmar Osterkamp, Fellow at the School for Political Studies at University of Munich.; And David L. Kaserman, Torchmark Professor of Economics at Auburn University.2013 The Global Organ Shortage: Economic Causes, Human Consequences, Policy Responses</p><p><u><mark>On balance</mark>, <mark>a fair</mark>-minded <mark>reading of</mark> <mark>the evidence suggests that compensation for donors</mark>, if done correctly and sensibly, <mark>would increase</mark>, probably <mark>substantially</mark>, <mark>the number of organs available for transplant</mark>. In the cases of <mark>both deceased donors (and their families) and living donors</mark>, available evidence confirms the observation that people <mark>respond to incentives</u><strong></mark>.</p></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 The Plan solves
430,350
6
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,214
Heres a bunch of counterexamples
Wright 5
Wright 5 Logan doctoral candidate in Chinese politics and U.S.-China relations at George Washington University in Washington, DC. http://survivedsars.typepad.com/survivedsars/2005/11/offensive_reali_1.html 11-18-05
Mearsheimer, the godfather of offensive realist theory provided a rejection of the idea of China's peaceful rise This article could have been written in 1985, 1995, or 2005. Mearsheimer was well-known for predicting the collapse of NATO and breakup of Europe Why would China have so few nuclear weapons? Why would Russia agree to sell China significant quantities of military hardware, if they were concerned about great power competition? Why would China's military modernization efforts be focused intensely on the Taiwan question, rather than larger issues of great-power competition Why would China attempt to join international institutions, Why would China have negotiated border settlements with India, Russia, and Kazakhstan on terms that were generally unfavorable to China How long do we have to wait, Dr. Mearsheimer, before your predictions begin to make sense? how do you explain the collapse of the Soviet Union again
offensive realist theory was well-known for predicting collapse of NATO and breakup of Europe Why would China have few nuclear weapons? Why would Russia sell China military hardware, Why would military modernization be focused on Taiwan rather than larger issues Why would China join international institutions Why would China negotiate settlements with India on terms that were unfavorable to China How long do we have to wait, Dr. Mearsheimer, before predictions make sense how do you explain collapse of the Soviet Union
It would take something like this to bring me out of my blogging slumber, which resulted from a trip to England and a general feeling that I'm behind on other work, so that I should stay away from blogging for a while. John Mearsheimer, the godfather of offensive realist theory, has provided a completely deductive, completely theoretical rejection of the idea of China's peaceful rise into the international system. When I read this article, I didn't even know where to start, and how to concisely summarize my criticism. I'm sure I'll fail to be brief, but I'll start this way: This article could have been written in 1985, 1995, or 2005. Mearsheimer was well-known for predicting the collapse of NATO at the end of the Cold War (he still claims he's right, given US-European tension) and the breakup of European integration into hypernationalist or ethnic conflict (again, Mearsheimer claims violence in the former Yugoslavia in the early 1990s provides support for his argument). There is a significant debate over whether theories should attempt to explain, predict, or contribute to understanding of international phenomena, but offensive realism is definitely in the "predictive" category, if only because its prescriptions are so unidirectional. In contrast to defensive realists like Robert Jervis, offensive realists argue that security, ultimately, is scarce, and states, in order to preserve their own security, must actually maximize their power. Note: not maintain, but maximize. This is what is so frustrating about this article. Mearsheimer lays out the case for great power competition between the United States and China. China - whether it remains authoritarian or becomes democratic - is likely to try to dominate Asia the way the US dominates the Western hemisphere. Specifically, China will seek to maximise the power gap between itself and its neighbours, especially Japan and Russia. China will want to make sure that it is so powerful that no state in Asia has the wherewithal to threaten it. It is unlikely that China will pursue military superiority so that it can go on a rampage and conquer other Asian countries, although that is always possible. Instead, it is more likely that it will want to dictate the boundaries of acceptable behaviour to neighbouring countries, much the way the US makes it clear to other states in the Americas that it is the boss. Gaining regional hegemony, I might add, is probably the only way that China will get Taiwan back. An increasingly powerful China is also likely to try to push the US out of Asia, much the way the US pushed the European great powers out of the Western hemisphere. We should expect China to come up with its own version of the Monroe Doctrine, as Japan did in the 1930s. These policy goals make good strategic sense for China. Beijing should want a militarily weak Japan and Russia as its neighbours, just as the US prefers a militarily weak Canada and Mexico on its borders. Note what Mearsheimer said. "China will seek to maximise the power gap between itself and its neighbours, especially Japan and Russia." Maximize? Really? Keep in mind, this is the essential prediction of this theory, which is parsimonious, to Mearsheimer's credit. In light of this, I have a number of questions for Dr. Mearsheimer. If your theory is correct... Why would China have so few nuclear weapons? Why would Russia agree to sell China significant quantities of military hardware, if they were concerned about great power competition? Why would China's military modernization efforts be focused intensely on the Taiwan question, rather than larger issues of great-power competition (a blue-water navy, more ICBMs, etc.)? Why would China attempt to join international institutions, if they are concerned that these institutions are part of the global economic and political order dominated by the United States? Why would Chinese officials openly claim that they are not interested in pushing the United States out of Asia, as the US presence provides a level of security essential for China's economic growth? Why would China have negotiated border settlements with India, Russia, and Kazakhstan on terms that were generally unfavorable to China, given their past historical positions? Why would China attempt to work within existing international institutions, and campaign actively to join them, rather than attempting to create their own? Why would a democratic China still be interested in a military solution to the Taiwan issue? Why would Taiwan be opposed to reunification in such a scenario? Keep in mind, in offensive realism, the character of the state involved is not relevant to the analysis. How long do we have to wait, Dr. Mearsheimer, before your predictions begin to make sense? How would this article have been different in 1985 or 1995, rather than 2005? Are we all just engaging in the Popperian "inductivist illusion" by having the audacity to look at empirical evidence, rather than living in our deductive theoretical cocoons? Or is the theory simply a cut too thin, designed to maximize parsimony at the expense of explaining independent observations? And by the way, how do you explain the collapse of the Soviet Union again?
5,289
<h4>Heres a bunch of counterexamples</h4><p><strong>Wright 5</strong> Logan doctoral candidate in Chinese politics and U.S.-China relations at George Washington University in Washington, DC. http://survivedsars.typepad.com/survivedsars/2005/11/offensive_reali_1.html 11-18-05</p><p>It would take something like this to bring me out of my blogging slumber, which resulted from a trip to England and a general feeling that I'm behind on other work, so that I should stay away from blogging for a while. John <u>Mearsheimer, the godfather of <mark>offensive realist theory</u></mark>, has <u>provided a </u>completely deductive, completely theoretical <u>rejection of the idea of China's peaceful rise </u>into the international system. When I read this article, I didn't even know where to start, and how to concisely summarize my criticism. I'm sure I'll fail to be brief, but I'll start this way: <u>This article could have been written in 1985, 1995, or 2005. Mearsheimer <mark>was well-known for predicting </mark>the <mark>collapse of NATO </u></mark>at the end of the Cold War (he still claims he's right, given US-European tension) <u><mark>and</u> </mark>the <u><mark>breakup of Europe</u></mark>an integration into hypernationalist or ethnic conflict (again, Mearsheimer claims violence in the former Yugoslavia in the early 1990s provides support for his argument). There is a significant debate over whether theories should attempt to explain, predict, or contribute to understanding of international phenomena, but offensive realism is definitely in the "predictive" category, if only because its prescriptions are so unidirectional. In contrast to defensive realists like Robert Jervis, offensive realists argue that security, ultimately, is scarce, and states, in order to preserve their own security, must actually maximize their power. Note: not maintain, but maximize. This is what is so frustrating about this article. Mearsheimer lays out the case for great power competition between the United States and China. China - whether it remains authoritarian or becomes democratic - is likely to try to dominate Asia the way the US dominates the Western hemisphere. Specifically, China will seek to maximise the power gap between itself and its neighbours, especially Japan and Russia. China will want to make sure that it is so powerful that no state in Asia has the wherewithal to threaten it. It is unlikely that China will pursue military superiority so that it can go on a rampage and conquer other Asian countries, although that is always possible. Instead, it is more likely that it will want to dictate the boundaries of acceptable behaviour to neighbouring countries, much the way the US makes it clear to other states in the Americas that it is the boss. Gaining regional hegemony, I might add, is probably the only way that China will get Taiwan back. An increasingly powerful China is also likely to try to push the US out of Asia, much the way the US pushed the European great powers out of the Western hemisphere. We should expect China to come up with its own version of the Monroe Doctrine, as Japan did in the 1930s. These policy goals make good strategic sense for China. Beijing should want a militarily weak Japan and Russia as its neighbours, just as the US prefers a militarily weak Canada and Mexico on its borders. Note what Mearsheimer said. "China will seek to maximise the power gap between itself and its neighbours, especially Japan and Russia." Maximize? Really? Keep in mind, this is the essential prediction of this theory, which is parsimonious, to Mearsheimer's credit. In light of this, I have a number of questions for Dr. Mearsheimer. If your theory is correct... <u><mark>Why would China have </mark>so <mark>few nuclear weapons? Why would Russia</mark> agree to <mark>sell China </mark>significant quantities of <mark>military hardware, </mark>if they were concerned </p><p>about great power competition? <mark>Why would</mark> China's <mark>military modernization</mark> efforts <mark>be focused</mark> intensely <mark>on</mark> the <mark>Taiwan</mark> question, <mark>rather than</mark> <mark>larger issues</mark> of great-power competition </u>(a blue-water navy, more ICBMs, etc.)? <u><mark>Why would China </mark>attempt to <mark>join international institutions</mark>, </u>if they are concerned that these institutions are part of the global economic and political order dominated by the United States? Why would Chinese officials openly claim that they are not interested in pushing the United States out of Asia, as the US presence provides a level of security essential for China's economic growth? <u><mark>Why would China </mark>have <mark>negotiate</mark>d border <mark>settlements with India</mark>, Russia, and Kazakhstan <mark>on terms that were </mark>generally <mark>unfavorable to China</u></mark>, given their past historical positions? Why would China attempt to work within existing international institutions, and campaign actively to join them, rather than attempting to create their own? Why would a democratic China still be interested in a military solution to the Taiwan issue? Why would Taiwan be opposed to reunification in such a scenario? Keep in mind, in offensive realism, the character of the state involved is not relevant to the analysis.<u> <mark>How long do we have to wait, Dr. Mearsheimer,</mark> <mark>before</mark> your <mark>predictions</mark> begin to <mark>make sense</mark>? </u>How would this article have been different in 1985 or 1995, rather than 2005? Are we all just engaging in the Popperian "inductivist illusion" by having the audacity to look at empirical evidence, rather than living in our deductive theoretical cocoons? Or is the theory simply a cut too thin, designed to maximize parsimony at the expense of explaining independent observations? And by the way,<u> <mark>how do you explain </mark>the <mark>collapse of the Soviet Union </mark>again</u>?</p>
Block
AT: Empirics
AT: Inevitable
430,552
6
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,215
The United States should legalize non-physician assisted suicide and cyanide pills for all persons who qualify as terminally ill.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The United States should legalize non-physician assisted suicide and cyanide pills for all persons who qualify as terminally ill. </h4>
null
null
CP
430,613
1
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,216
Varied efforts to increase voluntary donations fail – individually and in combination
Beard 8
Beard 8 T.RANDOLPH BEARD, JOHN D. JACKSON , AND DAVID L. KASERMAN, profs of economics, Auburn University Winter 2008 Regulation The Failure of US 'Organ Procurement Policy
the transplant industry has examined and adopted a series of policy options ostensibly designed to improve the system’s performance. All of these, however, continue to maintain the basic zero-price property of the altruistic system. As a result, the likelihood that any of them, even in combination, will resolve the organ shortage is remote At least seven such actions have been implemented INCREASED EDUCATIONAL EXPENDITURES incorporating organ donor cards on states’ driver licenses. federal legislation requiring all hospitals to request organ donation additional legislation to refer potential organ donors the Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative,” ■ KIDNEY EXCHANGES Finally, i legislation authorizing reimbursement of any direct costs incurred by onors We must conclude that none of the policies should be expected to resolve the transplant organ shortage. . Rather, every time another one of these marginalist policies is devised, it delays the only real reform that is capable of fully resolving the organ shortage
a series of policy options ostensibly designed to improve the system’s performance. however, continue to maintain the basic zero-price property of the altruistic system. the likelihood any of them will resolve the organ shortage is remote At least seven such actions have been implemented EDUCATIONAL EXPENDITURES incorporating organ donor cards on driver licenses requiring all hospitals to request organ donation the Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative Finally legislation authorizing reimbursement of any direct costs incurred by donors We must conclude that none of the policies should be expected to resolve the transplant organ shortage every time another one of these marginalist policies is devised, it delays the only real reform that is capable of fully resolving the organ shortage
http://object.cato.org/sites/cato.org/files/serials/files/regulation/2007/12/v30n4-3.pdf Aware of the increasingly dire consequences of continued reliance on the existing approach to cadaveric organ procurement and alarmed at the figures shown above, the transplant industry has examined and adopted a series of policy options ostensibly designed to improve the system’s performance. All of these, however, continue to maintain the basic zero-price property of the altruistic system. As a result, the likelihood that any of them, even in combination, will resolve the organ shortage is remote. At least seven such actions have been implemented over the last two decades or so: ■ INCREASED EDUCATIONAL EXPENDITURES In the absence of financial incentives, moral suasion becomes the principal avenue through which additional supply may be motivated. Consequently, the organ procurement organizations (opos) created under the 1984 Act have launched substantial promotional campaigns. The campaigns have been designed to both educate the general public about the desperate need for donated organs and educate physicians and critical care hospital staff regarding the identification of potential deceased donors. Over the years, a substantial sum has been spent on these types of educational activities. Recent empirical evidence, however, suggests that further spending on these programs is unlikely to increase supply by a significant amount. ■ ORGAN DONOR CARDS A related activity has been the process of incorporating organ donor cards on states’ driver licenses. The cards can be easily completed and witnessed at the time the licenses are issued or renewed. They serve as a pre-mortem statement of the bearer’s wish to have his or her organs removed for transplantation purposes at the time of death. Their principal use, in practice, is to facilitate the opos’ efforts to convince surviving family members to consent to such removal by revealing the decedant’s wishes. The 1968 Uniform Anatomical Gift Act gave all states the authority to issue donor cards and incorporate them in drivers’ licenses. Moreover, a few states have recently begun to rely entirely on donor cards to infer consent without requiring the surviving family’s permission when such cards are present. Survey evidence indicates that less than 40 percent of U.S. citizens have signed their donor cards. ■ REQUIRED REQUEST Some survey evidence published in the late 1980s and early 1990s found that in a number of cases families of potential deceased donors were not being asked to donate the organs. As a result, donation was apparently failing to occur in some of those instances simply because the request was not being presented. In response to this evidence, federal legislation was passed in 1987 requiring all hospitals receiving any federal funding (which, of course, is virtually all hospitals) to request organ donation in all deaths that occur under circumstances that would allow the deceased’s organs to be used in transplantation. It appears that this legal obligation is now being met in most, if not all, cases. Yet, the organ shortage has persisted and the waiting list has continued to grow. ■ REQUIRED REFERRAL While required-request legislation can compel hospitals to approach the families of recently deceased potential organ donors with an appeal for donation, it cannot ensure that the request will be made in a sincere, compassionate manner likely to elicit an agreement. Following implementation of the required-request law, there were a number of anecdotes in which the compulsory organ donation requests were presented in an insincere or even offensive manner that was clearly intended to elicit a negative response. The letter of the law was being met but not the spirit. As a result, additional legislation was passed that requires hospitals to refer potential organ donors to the regional opo so that trained procurement personnel can approach the surviving family with the donation request. This policy response has resulted in no perceptible progress in resolving the shortage. ■ COLLABORATION A fairly recent response to the organ shortage has been the so-called “Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative,” which was championed by then-secretary of health and human services Tommy Thompson. The program was initiated shortly after Thompson took office in 2001 and is currently continuing. The program’s basic motivation is provided by the observation of a considerable degree of variation in performance across the existing opos. Specifically, the number of deceased organ donors per thousand hospital deaths has been found to vary by a factor of almost five across the organizations. The presumption, then, is that the relatively successful opos employ superior procurement techniques and/or knowledge that, if shared with the relatively unsuccessful organizations, would significantly improve their performance. Thus, diffusion of “best practice” techniques is seen as a promising method through which cadaveric donation rates may be greatly improved. A thorough and objective evaluation of the Thompson initiative has not, to our knowledge, been conducted. Figure 1, in conjunction with a recent econometric study of observed variations in opo efficiency, suggests that such an evaluation would yield both good news and bad news. The good news is that the program appears to have had a positive (and potentially significant) impact on the number of donations. In particular, it appears that, after 2002, the growth rate of the waiting list has slowed somewhat. Whether this effect will permanently lower the growth rate of the waiting list or simply cause a temporary intercept shift remains to be seen. The bad news, however, is unequivocal— the initiative is not going to resolve the organ shortage. Even if, contrary to reasonable expectations, all opo relative inefficiencies were miraculously eliminated (i.e., if al organizations’ performance were brought up to the most efficient unit), the increase in donor collection rates would still be insufficient to eliminate the shortage. ■ KIDNEY EXCHANGES Another approach that has received some attention recently involves the exchange of kidneys between families who have willing but incompatible living donors. Suppose, for example, a person in one family needs a kidney transplant and a sibling has offered to donate the needed organ. Further suppose that the two siblings are not compatible — perhaps their blood types differ. If this family can locate a second, similarly situated family, then it may be possible that the donor in the first family will match the recipient in the second, and vice versa. A relatively small number of such exchanges have recently occurred and a unos-based computerized system of matching such interfamily donors has been proposed to facilitate a larger number of these living donor transactions. Two observations regarding kidney exchanges are worth noting. First, such exchanges obviously constitute a crude type of market in living donor kidneys that is based upon barter rather than currency. Like all such barter markets, this exchange will be considerably less efficient than currency-based trade. Puzzlingly, some of the staunchest critics of using financial incentives for cadaveric donors have openly supported expanded use of living donor exchanges. Apparently, it is not market exchange per se that offends them but, rather, the use of money to facilitate efficient market exchange. This combination of positions merely highlights the critics’ lack of knowledge regarding the operation of market processes. It is quite apparent that living donor kidney exchanges are not going to resolve the organ shortage. Opportunities for such barter-based exchanges are simply too limited. ■ REIMBURSEMENT OF DONOR COSTS Finally, in another effort to encourage an increase in the number of living (primarily kidney) donors, several states have passed legislation authorizing reimbursement of any direct (explicit) costs incurred by such donors (e.g., travel expenses, lost wages, and so on). Economically, this policy action raises the price paid to living kidney donors from a negative amount to zero. As such, it should be expected to increase the quantity of organs supplied from this source. Because the explicit, out-of-pocket expenses associated with live kidney donation are unlikely to be large relative to the longer-term implicit costs of potential health risks, however, such reimbursement should not be expected to bring forth a flood of new donors. Moreover, recent empirical evidence suggests that an increase in the number of living donors may have a negative impact on the number of deceased donors because of some degree of supply-side substitutability. Again, this policy is not a solution to the organ shortage. We must conclude that none of the above-listed policies should be expected to resolve the transplant organ shortage. We say this not because we oppose any of these policies; indeed, each appears sensible in its own right and some have unquestionably succeeded in raising the number of organ donors by some (perhaps nontrivial) amount. Rather, our concern is that every time another one of these marginalist policies is devised, it delays the only real reform that is capable of fully resolving the organ shortage.
9,339
<h4>Varied efforts to increase voluntary donations fail – individually and in combination </h4><p><strong>Beard 8</strong> T.RANDOLPH BEARD, JOHN D. JACKSON , AND DAVID L. KASERMAN, profs of economics, Auburn University Winter 2008 Regulation The Failure of US 'Organ Procurement Policy</p><p>http://object.cato.org/sites/cato.org/files/serials/files/regulation/2007/12/v30n4-3.pdf</p><p>Aware of the increasingly dire consequences of continued reliance on the existing approach to cadaveric organ procurement and alarmed at the figures shown above, <u>the transplant industry has examined and adopted <mark>a series of policy options ostensibly designed to improve the system’s performance.</mark> All of these, <mark>however, continue to maintain the basic zero-price property of the altruistic system.</mark> As a result, <mark>the likelihood</mark> that <mark>any of them</mark>, even in combination, <mark>will resolve the organ shortage is remote</u></mark>. <u><mark>At least seven such actions have been implemented</u></mark> over the last two decades or so: ■ <u>INCREASED <mark>EDUCATIONAL EXPENDITURES</u></mark> In the absence of financial incentives, moral suasion becomes the principal avenue through which additional supply may be motivated. Consequently, the organ procurement organizations (opos) created under the 1984 Act have launched substantial promotional campaigns. The campaigns have been designed to both educate the general public about the desperate need for donated organs and educate physicians and critical care hospital staff regarding the identification of potential deceased donors. Over the years, a substantial sum has been spent on these types of educational activities. Recent empirical evidence, however, suggests that further spending on these programs is unlikely to increase supply by a significant amount. ■ ORGAN DONOR CARDS A related activity has been the process of <u><mark>incorporating organ donor cards on</mark> states’ <mark>driver licenses</mark>.</u> The cards can be easily completed and witnessed at the time the licenses are issued or renewed. They serve as a pre-mortem statement of the bearer’s wish to have his or her organs removed for transplantation purposes at the time of death. Their principal use, in practice, is to facilitate the opos’ efforts to convince surviving family members to consent to such removal by revealing the decedant’s wishes. The 1968 Uniform Anatomical Gift Act gave all states the authority to issue donor cards and incorporate them in drivers’ licenses. Moreover, a few states have recently begun to rely entirely on donor cards to infer consent without requiring the surviving family’s permission when such cards are present. Survey evidence indicates that less than 40 percent of U.S. citizens have signed their donor cards.<u> </u>■ REQUIRED REQUEST Some survey evidence published in the late 1980s and early 1990s found that in a number of cases families of potential deceased donors were not being asked to donate the organs. As a result, donation was apparently failing to occur in some of those instances simply because the request was not being presented. In response to this evidence, <u>federal legislation</u> was passed in 1987 <u><mark>requiring all hospitals</u></mark> receiving any federal funding (which, of course, is virtually all hospitals) <u><mark>to request organ donation</u></mark> in all deaths that occur under circumstances that would allow the deceased’s organs to be used in transplantation. It appears that this legal obligation is now being met in most, if not all, cases. Yet, the organ shortage has persisted and the waiting list has continued to grow. ■ REQUIRED REFERRAL While required-request legislation can compel hospitals to approach the families of recently deceased potential organ donors with an appeal for donation, it cannot ensure that the request will be made in a sincere, compassionate manner likely to elicit an agreement. Following implementation of the required-request law, there were a number of anecdotes in which the compulsory organ donation requests were presented in an insincere or even offensive manner that was clearly intended to elicit a negative response. The letter of the law was being met but not the spirit. As a result, <u>additional legislation</u> was passed that requires hospitals<u> to refer potential organ donors </u>to the regional opo so that trained procurement personnel can approach the surviving family with the donation request. This policy response has resulted in no perceptible progress in resolving the shortage. ■ COLLABORATION A fairly recent response to the organ shortage has been <u><mark>the</mark> </u>so-called “<u><mark>Organ Donation Breakthrough Collaborative</mark>,” </u>which was championed by then-secretary of health and human services Tommy Thompson. The program was initiated shortly after Thompson took office in 2001 and is currently continuing. The program’s basic motivation is provided by the observation of a considerable degree of variation in performance across the existing opos. Specifically, the number of deceased organ donors per thousand hospital deaths has been found to vary by a factor of almost five across the organizations. The presumption, then, is that the relatively successful opos employ superior procurement techniques and/or knowledge that, if shared with the relatively unsuccessful organizations, would significantly improve their performance. Thus, diffusion of “best practice” techniques is seen as a promising method through which cadaveric donation rates may be greatly improved. A thorough and objective evaluation of the Thompson initiative has not, to our knowledge, been conducted. Figure 1, in conjunction with a recent econometric study of observed variations in opo efficiency, suggests that such an evaluation would yield both good news and bad news. The good news is that the program appears to have had a positive (and potentially significant) impact on the number of donations. In particular, it appears that, after 2002, the growth rate of the waiting list has slowed somewhat. Whether this effect will permanently lower the growth rate of the waiting list or simply cause a temporary intercept shift remains to be seen. The bad news, however, is unequivocal— the initiative is not going to resolve the organ shortage. Even if, contrary to reasonable expectations, all opo relative inefficiencies were miraculously eliminated (i.e., if al organizations’ performance were brought up to the most efficient unit), the increase in donor collection rates would still be insufficient to eliminate the shortage. <u>■ KIDNEY EXCHANGES</u> Another approach that has received some attention recently involves the exchange of kidneys between families who have willing but incompatible living donors. Suppose, for example, a person in one family needs a kidney transplant and a sibling has offered to donate the needed organ. Further suppose that the two siblings are not compatible — perhaps their blood types differ. If this family can locate a second, similarly situated family, then it may be possible that the donor in the first family will match the recipient in the second, and vice versa. A relatively small number of such exchanges have recently occurred and a unos-based computerized system of matching such interfamily donors has been proposed to facilitate a larger number of these living donor transactions. Two observations regarding kidney exchanges are worth noting. First, such exchanges obviously constitute a crude type of market in living donor kidneys that is based upon barter rather than currency. Like all such barter markets, this exchange will be considerably less efficient than currency-based trade. Puzzlingly, some of the staunchest critics of using financial incentives for cadaveric donors have openly supported expanded use of living donor exchanges. Apparently, it is not market exchange per se that offends them but, rather, the use of money to facilitate efficient market exchange. This combination of positions merely highlights the critics’ lack of knowledge regarding the operation of market processes. It is quite apparent that living donor kidney exchanges are not going to resolve the organ shortage. Opportunities for such barter-based exchanges are simply too limited. ■ REIMBURSEMENT OF DONOR COSTS <u><mark>Finally</mark>, i</u>n another effort to encourage an increase in the number of living (primarily kidney) donors, several states have passed <u><mark>legislation authorizing reimbursement of any direct</mark> </u>(explicit) <u><mark>costs incurred by</u></mark> such <mark>d<u>onors</mark> </u>(e.g., travel expenses, lost wages, and so on). Economically, this policy action raises the price paid to living kidney donors from a negative amount to zero. As such, it should be expected to increase the quantity of organs supplied from this source. Because the explicit, out-of-pocket expenses associated with live kidney donation are unlikely to be large relative to the longer-term implicit costs of potential health risks, however, such reimbursement should not be expected to bring forth a flood of new donors. Moreover, recent empirical evidence suggests that an increase in the number of living donors may have a negative impact on the number of deceased donors because of some degree of supply-side substitutability. Again, this policy is not a solution to the organ shortage. <u><mark>We must conclude that none of the</u></mark> above-listed <u><mark>policies should be expected to resolve the transplant organ shortage</mark>.</u> We say this not because we oppose any of these policies; indeed, each appears sensible in its own right and some have unquestionably succeeded in raising the number of organ donors by some (perhaps nontrivial) amount<u>. Rather,</u> our concern is that <u><mark>every time another one of these marginalist policies is devised, it delays the only real reform that is capable of fully resolving the organ shortage</u></mark>.</p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Organ sales will save lives
430,246
21
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,217
Empirically, sales would not be primarily from the poor. All income groups would participate.
Halpern 10
Halpern 10 Scott D. Halpern, MD, PhD, MBioethics, Amelie Raz, Rachel Kohn, BA, Michael Rey, BA, David A. Asch, MD, MBA, and Peter Reese, MD, MSCE, University of Pennsylvania School of Medicine and Philadelphia Veterans Affairs Medical Center, Ann Intern Med. 2010 Mar 16; 152(6): 358–365. Regulated Payments for Living Kidney Donation: An Empirical Assessment of the Ethical Concerns
Higher payments increased the probabilities of donating but did so evenly across the 6 income strata, such that no evidence of an interaction between payment and income was found Even when we restricted analyses to the lowest income stratum and the highest income stratum no significant interaction emerged (OR, 0.99 [CI, 0.97 to 1.02]) (Figure 3). Among participants in the lowest income stratum, conditionally adjusted donation rates were 29.8% (CI, 19.5% to 42.7%) for $0, 44.1% (CI, 33.1% to 55.7%) for $10 000, and 47.9% (CI, 36.4% to 59.6%) for $100 000. Among participants in the highest income stratum, the rates were 15.2% (CI, 9.0% to 24.5%), 27.5% (CI, 18.8% to 38.2%), and 31.3% (CI, 21.7% to 42.9%), respectively. These results suggest that payment is not an unjust inducement for living kidney donation.
Higher payments increased the probabilities of donating but did so evenly across the 6 income strata, no evidence of an interaction between payment and income was found Even when we restricted analyses to the lowest income stratum and the highest no significant interaction emerged
http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2865248/?report=classic%5Dab Unjust Inducement Higher payments increased the probabilities of donating but did so evenly across the 6 income strata, such that no evidence of an interaction between payment and income was found (OR, 1.01 [CI, 0.99 to 1.03]) (Figure 3). Even when we restricted analyses to the 57 participants in the lowest income stratum (annual household income ≤$20 000) and the 66 participants in the highest income stratum (annual household income >$100 000), no significant interaction emerged (OR, 0.99 [CI, 0.97 to 1.02]) (Figure 3). Among participants in the lowest income stratum, conditionally adjusted donation rates were 29.8% (CI, 19.5% to 42.7%) for $0, 44.1% (CI, 33.1% to 55.7%) for $10 000, and 47.9% (CI, 36.4% to 59.6%) for $100 000. Among participants in the highest income stratum, the rates were 15.2% (CI, 9.0% to 24.5%), 27.5% (CI, 18.8% to 38.2%), and 31.3% (CI, 21.7% to 42.9%), respectively. These results suggest that payment is not an unjust inducement for living kidney donation.
1,068
<h4><strong>Empirically, sales would not be primarily from the poor. All income groups would participate.</h4><p>Halpern 10</strong> Scott D. Halpern, MD, PhD, MBioethics, Amelie Raz, Rachel Kohn, BA, Michael Rey, BA, David A. Asch, MD, MBA, and Peter Reese, MD, MSCE, University of Pennsylvania School of Medicine and Philadelphia Veterans Affairs Medical Center, Ann Intern Med. 2010 Mar 16; 152(6): 358–365. Regulated Payments for Living Kidney Donation: An Empirical Assessment of the Ethical Concerns</p><p>http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2865248/?report=classic%5Dab</p><p>Unjust Inducement</p><p><u><mark>Higher payments increased the probabilities of donating but did so <strong>evenly</strong> across the 6 income strata,</mark> such that <mark>no evidence of an interaction between payment and income was found</mark> </u>(OR, 1.01 [CI, 0.99 to 1.03]) (Figure 3). <u><mark>Even when we restricted analyses to the</u></mark> 57 participants in the <u><mark>lowest income stratum</u></mark> (annual household income ≤$20 000) <u><mark>and the</u></mark> 66 participants in the <u><mark>highest</mark> income stratum</u> (annual household income >$100 000), <u><mark>no significant interaction emerged<strong></mark> (OR, 0.99 [CI, 0.97 to 1.02]) (Figure 3). Among participants in the lowest income stratum, conditionally adjusted donation rates were 29.8% (CI, 19.5% to 42.7%) for $0, 44.1% (CI, 33.1% to 55.7%) for $10 000, and 47.9% (CI, 36.4% to 59.6%) for $100 000. Among participants in the highest income stratum, the rates were 15.2% (CI, 9.0% to 24.5%), 27.5% (CI, 18.8% to 38.2%), and 31.3% (CI, 21.7% to 42.9%), respectively. These results suggest that payment is not an unjust inducement for living kidney donation.</p></u></strong>
null
null
Contention 3 The Plan solves
430,596
4
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,218
Use of the physician subjects the patient to medical scrutiny-the aff cannot be an act of autonomy.
Salem 99
Salem 99 Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full
no doubt emphasis on inner individuals prevails in contemporary arguments for physician-assisted suicide Influences from the outside are seen as pernicious in subverting the main goal: the “pure” or “true” choice reached from within self-centered ethics rests on a nonrelational conception of personhood there is a paradox underlying physician-assisted suicide It is conceived of as an intimate, existential act and indeed a response to modern medicine, but at the same time it is a request for the complicity of physicians and society What seems unusual in the debate about aid in dying is the request for public endorsement and legitimization of the act of suicide Whereas in suicide the individual “drops out” of the social order, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the individual “drops into” a system that recognizes and must even authorize this particular choice displacing suicide from the private arena to bring it under medicine's stewardship means surrendering suicide to the (medical) “establishment decision to die by suicide is treated precisely as if it were a set of clinical problems to be solved medically the “private self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event it cannot be seen as an act that solely expresses the ideal of individual autonomy as long as it entails assistance it implies a mutual decision and even more importantly assisted suicide presupposes that medicine has passed judgment on the act of suicide physician-assisted suicide entails an increase of medical power over death and social morality
emphasis on inner individuals prevails in contemporary arguments for p a s Influences from the outside are seen as pernicious in subverting the pure choice self-centered ethics rests on a nonrelational conception of personhood there is a paradox underlying physician-assisted suicide it is a request for the complicity of physicians (and society Whereas in suicide the individual “drops out” of the social order, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the individual “drops into” a system that recognizes and must even authorize this particular choice displacing suicide from the private arena to bring it under medicine's stewardship means surrendering suicide to the (medical) “establishment the “private self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event it cannot be seen as an act that solely expresses the ideal of individual autonomy as long as it entails assistance even more importantly assisted suicide presupposes that medicine has passed judgment on the act of suicide physician-assisted suicide entails an increase of medical power over death and social morality
There is no doubt that the emphasis on inner individuals prevails in contemporary arguments for physician-assisted suicide. Influences from the outside, whether subtle or blatant, are seen as pernicious in subverting the main goal: the “pure” or “true” choice reached from within that at bottom takes account of the interests of the decisionmaker. This self-centered ethics rests on a nonrelational conception of personhood. The second—and closely related—pillar of this discourse is the insistence that individuals be radically free to exercise their singularities and idiosyncrasies. In pluralistic societies, it is asserted, “there is far from any agreement, or near-agreement, about how one can establish as canonical a particular normative view of life.”13 Because personal styles, experiences, and beliefs are radically irreducible, it is impossible to suppose a priori that individual choices will coincide; each must find his or her own way of facing dying and death.14 Yet there is a paradox underlying physician-assisted suicide. It is conceived of as an intimate, existential act and indeed a response to modern medicine, but at the same time it is a request for the complicity of physicians (and society). In contemporary Western societies the decision to take death into one's own hands has been construed as an act that is not simply personal, private, and solitary, but contrary to social norms and expectations. From a societal perspective, the individual who commits or attempts suicide is in this sense an outsider. What seems unusual in the debate about aid in dying is the request for public endorsement and legitimization of the act of suicide. Whereas in suicide the individual “drops out” of the social order, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the individual “drops into” a system that recognizes and must even authorize this particular (ostensibly private) choice. In other words, displacing suicide from the private arena to bring it under medicine's stewardship means surrendering suicide to the (medical) “establishment.” The decision to die by suicide is treated precisely as if it were a set of clinical problems to be solved medically— the “private,” “intimate,” “self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event. Precisely because assisted suicide requires the connivance of others (direct from doctors, indirect from society), it cannot be seen as an act that solely expresses the ideal of individual autonomy. On the contrary, as long as it entails assistance it implies a mutual decision. Additionally, and even more importantly, more than a mutual decision, assisted suicide presupposes that medicine has passed judgment on the act of suicide. In sum, physician-assisted suicide both introduces tensions in the principle of personal autonomy and entails an increase of medical power over death and social morality.
2,892
<h4>Use of the physician subjects the patient to medical scrutiny-the aff cannot be an act of autonomy.</h4><p><strong>Salem 99</strong> Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full</p><p>There is <u>no doubt</u> that the <u><mark>emphasis on inner individuals prevails in contemporary arguments for p</mark>hysician-<mark>a</mark>ssisted <mark>s</mark>uicide</u>. <u><mark>Influences from the outside</u></mark>, whether subtle or blatant, <u><mark>are seen as pernicious in subverting the</mark> main goal: the “<mark>pure</mark>” or “true” <mark>choice</mark> reached from within</u> that at bottom takes account of the interests of the decisionmaker. This <u><mark>self-centered ethics rests on a nonrelational conception of personhood</u></mark>.</p><p>The second—and closely related—pillar of this discourse is the insistence that individuals be radically free to exercise their singularities and idiosyncrasies. In pluralistic societies, it is asserted, “there is far from any agreement, or near-agreement, about how one can establish as canonical a particular normative view of life.”13 Because personal styles, experiences, and beliefs are radically irreducible, it is impossible to suppose a priori that individual choices will coincide; each must find his or her own way of facing dying and death.14</p><p>Yet <u><mark>there is a paradox underlying physician-assisted suicide</u></mark>. <u>It is conceived of as an intimate, existential act and indeed a response to modern medicine, but at the same time <mark>it is a request for the complicity of physicians</u> (<u>and society</u></mark>). In contemporary Western societies the decision to take death into one's own hands has been construed as an act that is not simply personal, private, and solitary, but contrary to social norms and expectations. From a societal perspective, the individual who commits or attempts suicide is in this sense an outsider.</p><p><u>What seems unusual in the debate about aid in dying is the request for public endorsement and legitimization of the act of suicide</u>. <u><mark>Whereas in suicide the individual “drops out” of the social order, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the individual “drops into” a system that recognizes and must even authorize this particular</u></mark> (ostensibly private) <u><mark>choice</u></mark>. In other words, <u><mark>displacing suicide from the private arena to bring it under medicine's stewardship means surrendering suicide to the (medical) “establishment</u></mark>.”</p><p>The <u>decision to die by suicide is treated precisely as if it were a set of clinical problems to be solved medically</u>— <u><mark>the “private</u></mark>,” “intimate,” “<u><mark>self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event</u></mark>.</p><p>Precisely because assisted suicide requires the connivance of others (direct from doctors, indirect from society), <u><mark>it cannot be seen as an act that solely expresses the ideal of individual autonomy</u></mark>. On the contrary, <u><mark>as long as it entails assistance</mark> it implies a mutual decision</u>. Additionally, <u>and <mark>even more importantly</u></mark>, more than a mutual decision, <u><mark>assisted suicide presupposes that medicine has passed judgment on the act of suicide</u></mark>. In sum, <u><mark>physician-assisted suicide</u></mark> both introduces tensions in the principle of personal autonomy and <u><mark>entails an increase of medical power over death and social morality</u><strong></mark>.</p></strong>
null
Off
CP
430,345
3
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,219
Zero solvency for their vague “future catastrophes” impact---prediction markets are worthless for policy responses to them
HLR 9
HLR 9 – Harvard Law Review, February 2009, “Note: Prediction Markets and Law: A Skeptical Account,” 122 Harv. L. Rev. 1217
disaster might strike risks are not likely to be mitigated efficiently without national governments Some scholars have advanced prediction markets as a way to develop this information But remoteness of risk and magnitude of loss correlate inversely with a prediction market's accuracy the low probability of such disasters as in the case of bioterrorism and abrupt global warming is among the things that baffle efforts at responding rationally to them nations may be operating in the domain of uncertainty rather than risk they are able to identify the worst outcomes without being able to specify the likelihood that they will occur Information Markets Poorly Predict Catastrophic Events for two reasons prediction markets exhibit a favorite-longshot bias the favorite-longshot bias could be endemic to information markets If] bettors undervalue near certainties and overvalue low probabilities prediction markets might not be accurate with respect to highly improbable events predicting a very unlikely event presents a insurmountable design problem the contract has to have a payout trigger The occurrence or nonoccurrence of the event is essential for disciplining the market When it comes to catastrophe, the triggering event (a disaster) is at best speculative, and it is the very thing that the market is designed to help avoid when an investor purchases a contract, he may actually reduce the likelihood of the event that would allow him to cash in risks, if properly mitigated, will never materialize in a way that makes payout possible Investment in catastrophe markets would be so high-risk that individuals may not bet at more than novelty levels, like participation in a lottery With the chance of winning so slight, participants may not have a sufficient incentive to educate themselves and purchase according to the confidence of their prediction Salience, fear, and the availability heuristic are biases that are strong in the context of disaster Markets may help reduce bias, but some biases are too strong for the market to overcome
disaster might strike scholars have advanced p m s But remoteness of risk and magnitude of loss correlate inversely with a prediction market's accuracy the low probability of such disasters bioterror and warming baffle efforts at responding rationally to them Information Markets Poorly Predict Catastrophic Events predicting a very unlikely event presents a insurmountable design problem some biases are too strong for the market to overcome
3. Information Pertains to Unlikely, But Catastrophic Harms. - At any moment, disaster might strike. These risks are not likely to be mitigated efficiently without large-scale collective action, n75 probably at the level of national governments. Without coercive cost-spreading through regulation and taxation, we are sitting ducks to environmental disasters, hurricanes, and stock market crashes. Increasingly, scholars are recognizing government's responsibility to fix these market failures, n76 but to do so it needs good information about these catastrophes - risks that are inherently difficult to measure and anticipate. The more remote a risk, and the greater its potential loss, the more urgent the need for regulation becomes. Some scholars have advanced prediction markets as a way to develop this information. n77 But remoteness of risk and magnitude of loss both correlate inversely with a prediction market's accuracy. n78 [*1233] (a) The Informational Problem of Catastrophe. - Responding efficiently to potential catastrophes presents formidable analytical and institutional challenges. n79 Cost-benefit analysis of catastrophe is "a function of both the probability that one or another of [the risks] will materialize if we do nothing and the awfulness of the consequences if that happens." n80 The result - the risk times the harm - is the benefit gained by taking a measure that prevents the risk, and so would be the maximum rational amount to spend on its prevention. This number is the product of a very small number (the likelihood) and a very large number (the harm), and so is very sensitive to error. n81 The most vexing part of the equation is the smaller number: the probability. According to Judge Posner, "the low probability of such disasters - frequently the unknown probability, as in the case of bioterrorism and abrupt global warming - is among the things that baffle efforts at responding rationally to them." n82 Some disasters are unimaginable, but even those that can be imagined cannot be confidently predicted; as Professor Sunstein argues, "in the case of terrorism and climate change, nations may be operating in the domain of uncertainty rather than risk, in the sense that they are able to identify the worst outcomes without being able to specify the likelihood that they will occur." n83 The reasons for this uncertainty are diverse and controversial. Professor Sunstein cites social-scientific and psychological phenomena such as availability, probability neglect, and outrage for both under-and over-estimation of low-probability risks. n84 More controversially, Judge Posner blames scientific illiteracy, science worship, science fiction, doomsters, optimists, limited horizons, false positives, temperament, economics of innovation, global decentralization, and the tragedy of the commons. n85 But most of Judge Posner's reasons, and all of Professor Sunstein's, have something in common: they involve irrationality in thinking about worst-case scenarios. Not surprisingly, both scholars include in their prescription the need to improve the rational assessment of very small probabilities. Might prediction markets help develop good factual predicates for assessing risk? (b) Limits of a Market Solution: Information Markets Poorly Predict Catastrophic Events. - Information markets are bad at predicting very low-probability events for two reasons; one pertains to a systematic [*1234] bias exhibited in prediction markets, and the other relates to market design. First, prediction markets exhibit a favorite-longshot bias. n86 This phenomenon may explain why a prediction market predicted an 8% chance that Arnold Schwarzenegger will become president by 2022 - a number Professor Abramowicz finds implausibly high, "given that the Constitution would need to be amended for this to take place and that he would then need to win the Republican nomination and the general election." n87 According to Professor Sunstein, the favorite-longshot bias could be endemic to information markets: "[If] bettors undervalue near certainties and overvalue low probabilities ... , prediction markets might not be accurate with respect to highly improbable events." n88 Second, predicting a very unlikely event presents a potentially insurmountable design problem. For a contract to have an underlying value that accurately reflects the likelihood of an event, the contract has to have a payout trigger. Defining this event is easy in the case of contests like elections and horse races, where there is a concrete moment at which the predictions will come to fruition. n89 The occurrence or nonoccurrence of the event is essential for disciplining the market since those with good information who made accurate predictions must be rewarded and those who made foolish bets must be punished. n90 When it comes to catastrophe, the triggering event (a disaster) is at best speculative, and anyway it is the very thing that the market is designed to help avoid. Mitigation of catastrophe can come in two forms: prevention and reduction of harm. For events that can be prevented - things that are sufficiently within human control - the market may be self-defeating. When a participant purchases a share that is redeemable for cash in the event of a particular catastrophe, he signals his belief that the [*1235] event will occur. Indeed, the value of the prediction market to lawmakers would be this information. Presumably, if investors manifested enough belief in a risk to make costly prevention efficient, then the government would take preventative action. But just as these measures will prevent the harm, so they will prevent investors from benefiting from their (presumably good) information about the risk, since the catastrophe will now not occur. In short, when an investor purchases a contract, he may actually reduce the likelihood of the event that would allow him to cash in. n91 Of course, some disasters cannot be prevented but can only be mitigated. For these, the self-defeating problem goes away. Suppose a market predicted that a major asteroid would hit the Earth before 2020. Based on this information, the government built an asteroid shield in 2012. Holders of the asteroid-hits-earth contract could still experience a payout if a major asteroid struck and was successfully deflected by the shield in 2015. But most risks, if properly mitigated, will never materialize in a way that makes payout possible. Whether a catastrophe can be prevented or mitigated, it is (by definition) very unlikely to happen. For investors, payday is at best a remote possibility. Investment in catastrophe markets would be so high-risk that individuals may not bet at more than novelty levels, like participation in a lottery. With the chance of winning so slight, participants may not have a sufficient incentive to educate themselves and purchase according to the confidence of their prediction. Then again, the low probability of house fires does not prevent homeowners from mitigating their risk. In the same way that insurance companies reduce risk through aggregation, disaster firms could reduce the risk of investing in one disaster by offering diversified securities to customers. This disaster mutual fund idea is the inverse of Judge Posner's prescription for catastrophic uncertainty. He suggests that one "infer the risk of a bioterrorist attack from the premiums charged for insurance against such attacks." n92 The failure of this model in practice, however, illustrates the difficulty of getting useful information about catastrophe from a market, even if the market offered sufficiently aggregated and diversified securities to make investment rational: In the wake of 9/11, insurance companies terminated coverage of losses due to terrorism (for which previously they had charged only nominal premiums), and though they were forced to restore coverage by the Terrorism Risk Insurance Act of 2002, the act ... heavily subsidizes this insurance and makes it difficult to determine the industry's implicit estimate of the probability and magnitude of future terrorist attacks. n93 [*1236] Salience, fear, and the availability heuristic are biases that are strong in the context of disaster. To Americans, having just experienced an attack, the possibility of disaster seemed imminent and so the demand for insurance went up. At the same time, insurance companies' fear of a huge payout, made salient by the 9/11 attacks, caused their willingness to sell at all to plummet. Markets may help reduce bias, but some biases are too strong for the market to overcome.
8,620
<h4>Zero solvency for their vague “future catastrophes” impact---prediction markets are worthless for policy responses to them </h4><p><strong>HLR 9</strong> – Harvard Law Review, February 2009, “Note: Prediction Markets and Law: A Skeptical Account,” 122 Harv. L. Rev. 1217</p><p>3. Information Pertains to Unlikely, But Catastrophic Harms. - At any moment, <u><mark>disaster might strike</u></mark>. These <u>risks are not likely to be mitigated efficiently without</u> large-scale collective action, n75 probably at the level of <u>national governments</u>. Without coercive cost-spreading through regulation and taxation, we are sitting ducks to environmental disasters, hurricanes, and stock market crashes. Increasingly, scholars are recognizing government's responsibility to fix these market failures, n76 but to do so it needs good information about these catastrophes - risks that are inherently difficult to measure and anticipate. The more remote a risk, and the greater its potential loss, the more urgent the need for regulation becomes. <u>Some <mark>scholars have advanced</mark> <mark>p</mark>rediction <mark>m</mark>arket<mark>s</mark> as a way to develop this information</u>. n77 <u><mark>But</u> <u>remoteness of risk and magnitude of loss</u></mark> both <u><mark>correlate inversely with a prediction market's accuracy</u></mark>. n78</p><p> [*1233] (a) The Informational Problem of Catastrophe. - Responding efficiently to potential catastrophes presents formidable analytical and institutional challenges. n79 Cost-benefit analysis of catastrophe is "a function of both the probability that one or another of [the risks] will materialize if we do nothing and the awfulness of the consequences if that happens." n80 The result - the risk times the harm - is the benefit gained by taking a measure that prevents the risk, and so would be the maximum rational amount to spend on its prevention. This number is the product of a very small number (the likelihood) and a very large number (the harm), and so is very sensitive to error. n81</p><p>The most vexing part of the equation is the smaller number: the probability. According to Judge Posner, "<u><mark>the low probability of such disasters</u></mark> - frequently the unknown probability, <u>as in the case of <mark>bioterror</mark>ism <mark>and</mark> abrupt global <mark>warming</u></mark> - <u>is among the things that</u> <u><mark>baffle efforts at responding rationally to them</u></mark>." n82 Some disasters are unimaginable, but even those that can be imagined cannot be confidently predicted; as Professor Sunstein argues, "in the case of terrorism and climate change, <u>nations may be operating in the domain of uncertainty rather than risk</u>, in the sense that <u>they are able to</u> <u>identify the worst outcomes without being able to specify the likelihood that they will occur</u>." n83</p><p>The reasons for this uncertainty are diverse and controversial. Professor Sunstein cites social-scientific and psychological phenomena such as availability, probability neglect, and outrage for both under-and over-estimation of low-probability risks. n84 More controversially, Judge Posner blames scientific illiteracy, science worship, science fiction, doomsters, optimists, limited horizons, false positives, temperament, economics of innovation, global decentralization, and the tragedy of the commons. n85 But most of Judge Posner's reasons, and all of Professor Sunstein's, have something in common: they involve irrationality in thinking about worst-case scenarios. Not surprisingly, both scholars include in their prescription the need to improve the rational assessment of very small probabilities. Might prediction markets help develop good factual predicates for assessing risk?</p><p>(b) Limits of a Market Solution: <u><mark>Information Markets Poorly Predict Catastrophic Events</u></mark>. - Information markets are bad at predicting very low-probability events <u>for two reasons</u>; one pertains to a systematic [*1234] bias exhibited in prediction markets, and the other relates to market design. First, <u>prediction markets exhibit a favorite-longshot bias</u>. n86 This phenomenon may explain why a prediction market predicted an 8% chance that Arnold Schwarzenegger will become president by 2022 - a number Professor Abramowicz finds implausibly high, "given that the Constitution would need to be amended for this to take place and that he would then need to win the Republican nomination and the general election." n87 According to Professor Sunstein, <u>the favorite-longshot bias could be endemic to information markets</u>: "[<u>If] bettors undervalue near certainties and overvalue low probabilities</u> ... , <u>prediction markets might not be accurate with respect to highly improbable events</u>." n88</p><p>Second, <u><mark>predicting a very unlikely event presents a</u></mark> potentially <u><mark>insurmountable design problem</u></mark>. For a contract to have an underlying value that accurately reflects the likelihood of an event, <u>the contract has to have a payout trigger</u>. Defining this event is easy in the case of contests like elections and horse races, where there is a concrete moment at which the predictions will come to fruition. n89 <u>The occurrence or nonoccurrence of the event is essential for disciplining the market</u> since those with good information who made accurate predictions must be rewarded and those who made foolish bets must be punished. n90 <u>When it comes to catastrophe, the triggering event (a disaster) is at best speculative, and</u> anyway <u>it is the very thing that the market is designed to help avoid</u>.</p><p>Mitigation of catastrophe can come in two forms: prevention and reduction of harm. For events that can be prevented - things that are sufficiently within human control - the market may be self-defeating. When a participant purchases a share that is redeemable for cash in the event of a particular catastrophe, he signals his belief that the [*1235] event will occur. Indeed, the value of the prediction market to lawmakers would be this information. Presumably, if investors manifested enough belief in a risk to make costly prevention efficient, then the government would take preventative action. But just as these measures will prevent the harm, so they will prevent investors from benefiting from their (presumably good) information about the risk, since the catastrophe will now not occur. In short, <u>when an investor purchases a contract, he may actually</u> <u>reduce the likelihood of the event that would allow him to cash in</u>. n91</p><p>Of course, some disasters cannot be prevented but can only be mitigated. For these, the self-defeating problem goes away. Suppose a market predicted that a major asteroid would hit the Earth before 2020. Based on this information, the government built an asteroid shield in 2012. Holders of the asteroid-hits-earth contract could still experience a payout if a major asteroid struck and was successfully deflected by the shield in 2015. But most <u>risks, if properly mitigated, will never materialize in a way that makes payout possible</u>.</p><p>Whether a catastrophe can be prevented or mitigated, it is (by definition) very unlikely to happen. For investors, payday is at best a remote possibility. <u>Investment in catastrophe markets would be so high-risk that</u> <u>individuals may not bet at more than novelty levels, like participation in a lottery</u>. <u>With the chance of winning so slight, participants may not have a sufficient incentive to educate themselves and purchase according to the confidence of their prediction</u>. Then again, the low probability of house fires does not prevent homeowners from mitigating their risk. In the same way that insurance companies reduce risk through aggregation, disaster firms could reduce the risk of investing in one disaster by offering diversified securities to customers.</p><p>This disaster mutual fund idea is the inverse of Judge Posner's prescription for catastrophic uncertainty. He suggests that one "infer the risk of a bioterrorist attack from the premiums charged for insurance against such attacks." n92 The failure of this model in practice, however, illustrates the difficulty of getting useful information about catastrophe from a market, even if the market offered sufficiently aggregated and diversified securities to make investment rational: </p><p>In the wake of 9/11, insurance companies terminated coverage of losses due to terrorism (for which previously they had charged only nominal premiums), and though they were forced to restore coverage by the Terrorism Risk Insurance Act of 2002, the act ... heavily subsidizes this insurance and makes it difficult to determine the industry's implicit estimate of the probability and magnitude of future terrorist attacks. n93</p><p> [*1236] <u>Salience, fear, and the availability heuristic are biases that are strong in the context of disaster</u>. To Americans, having just experienced an attack, the possibility of disaster seemed imminent and so the demand for insurance went up. At the same time, insurance companies' fear of a huge payout, made salient by the 9/11 attacks, caused their willingness to sell at all to plummet. <u>Markets may help reduce bias, but</u> <u><mark>some biases are too strong for the market to overcome</u></mark>.</p>
Block
AT: Empirics
AT: Inevitable
430,615
12
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,220
CP PICs out of “physician assisted” part of plan---solves the case while avoiding our net-benefits.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>CP PICs out of “physician assisted” part of plan---solves the case while avoiding our net-benefits.</h4>
null
null
CP
430,614
1
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,221
The shortage means many die
Beard 8
Beard 8 T.RANDOLPH BEARD, JOHN D. JACKSON , AND DAVID L. KASERMAN, profs of economics, Auburn University Winter 2008 Regulation The Failure of US 'Organ Procurement Policy
our failure to adapt our organ procurement policy suggests that more than 80,000 lives have now been sacrificed on the altar of our so-called “altruistic” system. In addition, the unnecessary pain and suffering of those who have been forced to wait while undergoing dialysis, unemployment, and declining health must also be reckoned along with the growing despair of family members who must witness all of this. Nonetheless, the pain, suffering, and death imposed on the innocents thus far pales in comparison to what lies ahead if more fundamental change is not forthcoming we are able to produce forecasts of the expected size of future waiting lists We run the forecasts out 10 years a cumulative total of 196,310 patients are conservatively expected to die by 2015 as a consequence of the ongoing shortage.
more than 80,000 lives have now been sacrificed on the altar of our so-called “altruistic” system. the pain, suffering, and death imposed on the innocents pales in comparison to what lies ahead if more fundamental change is not forthcoming we are able to produce forecasts of future waiting lists 196,310 patients are conservatively expected to die by 2015 as a consequence of the ongoing shortage
http://object.cato.org/sites/cato.org/files/serials/files/regulation/2007/12/v30n4-3.pdf WAITING LISTS YET TO COME The consequences of our failure to adapt our cadaveric organ procurement policy to the changed technological realities of the transplant industry have been unconscionable. Figure 2, above, suggests that more than 80,000 lives have now been sacrificed on the altar of our so-called “altruistic” system. In addition, the unnecessary pain and suffering of those who have been forced to wait while undergoing dialysis, unemployment, and declining health must also be reckoned along with the growing despair of family members who must witness all of this. Nonetheless, the pain, suffering, and death imposed on the innocents thus far pales in comparison to what lies ahead if more fundamental change is not forthcoming. In order to illustrate the severe consequences of a continuation of the altruistic system, we use the data presented in Figures 1 and 2 above to generate forecasts of future waiting lists and deaths. The forecasts represent our best guess of what the future holds if fundamental change continues to be postponed. The results should serve as a wake-up call for those who argue that we should continue tinkering with the existing procurement system while further postponing the implementation of financial incentives. The costs of such a “wait and see” approach are rapidly becoming intolerable. CHANGING VARIABLE To produce reasonable forecasts of future waiting lists and deaths, we must first confront an apparent anomaly in the reported data that could cast doubt on the accuracy of some of the more recent figures. Specifically, the reported number of deaths of patients on the waiting list (plus those too sick to receive a transplant) follows a consistently upward trend that is very close to a constant proportion of the size of the waiting list over most of the sample period. Beginning in 2002, however, the number of deaths levels off and even starts to decline, despite continued growth of the waiting list. It is not clear why there is an abrupt change in the observed trend in this variable. Our investigation of this issue yielded several plausible explanations but no definitive answer. For example, it may be the case that recent advances in medical care, such as the left ventricular assist device, have extended some patients’ lives and, thereby, reduced the number of deaths on the list. Alternatively, it may be the case that because of rising criticism of the current system, unos has taken steps to remove some of the relatively higher-risk patients from the list before they die. For example, the meld/peld program, which was introduced in February 2002, removed a number of liver patients (who have a comparatively high death rate) from the waiting list. Additionally, the increasing use of so-called “extended criteria” donor organs may have a similar effect, getting the most critically ill patients off the list prior to their deaths. Clearly, the implications of these alternative explanations for reliance on the data are not the same. For example, if patients are, in fact, simply living longer and the data accurately reflect that reality, then our analysis should incorporate the observations. But if the more recent figures are, instead, a manifestation of strategic actions taken by the reporting agency, then they should be excluded. Because we have been unable to identify a single, convincing explanation for the observed phenomenon, we elected to perform our analysis both ways — including and excluding the post-2002 observations on the number of deaths. ESTIMATES Given the two alternative sample periods, the methodology we employ to generate our forecasts is as follows: First, because the number of deaths appears to be causally driven by the number of patients on the waiting list, we begin by estimating a simple linear regression model of the former as a function of the latter. The results of that estimation are reported in Table 1 for the two sample periods described above. Next, we estimate a second linear model with the number of patients on the waiting list regressed against time, again using the two alternative sample periods. Those results are reported in Table 2. From the results, we are able to produce forecasts of the expected size of future waiting lists for each of our sample periods. We run the forecasts out 10 years from the end of our longer sample period, to 2015. Given the forecasted waiting list values, we are then able to use the regression results in Table 1 to generate our forecasts of the number of deaths over the same period. The two alternative sets of forecasts are shown graphically in Figures 3 and 4. Depending upon the sample period chosen, the results show the waiting list reaching 145,691 to 152,400 patients by 2015. Of the patients listed at that time, between 10,547 and 13,642 are expected to die that year. Even more tragically, over the entire period of both actual and predicted values, a cumulative total of 196,310 patients are conservatively expected to die by 2015 as a consequence of the ongoing shortage. Figure 5 illustrates the results. In that figure, we incorporate several historical reference points in order to put the numbers in perspective. No one directly involved in the transplant industry is likely to be surprised by our results. Thirty years of experience consistently point to a continuation of the current, long-standing trends. There is nothing on the horizon that should lead anyone to expect a sudden reversal. But our purpose is not to surprise the parties who are already knowledgeable about this increasingly severe problem. Rather, our intent is to awaken the sleeping policymakers whose continuing inaction will inevitably lead to these results. They can no longer continue to postpone meaningful reform of the U.S. organ transplant system in the futile hope that, somehow, things will improve. They will not.
5,967
<h4>The shortage means many die</h4><p><strong>Beard 8</strong> T.RANDOLPH BEARD, JOHN D. JACKSON , AND DAVID L. KASERMAN, profs of economics, Auburn University Winter 2008 Regulation The Failure of US 'Organ Procurement Policy</p><p>http://object.cato.org/sites/cato.org/files/serials/files/regulation/2007/12/v30n4-3.pdf</p><p>WAITING LISTS YET TO COME</p><p>The consequences of <u>our failure to adapt our</u> cadaveric <u>organ procurement policy</u> to the changed technological realities of the transplant industry have been unconscionable. Figure 2, above, <u>suggests that <mark>more than 80,000 lives have now been sacrificed on the altar of our so-called “altruistic” system.</mark> In addition, the unnecessary pain and suffering of those who have been forced to wait while undergoing dialysis, unemployment, and declining health must also be reckoned along with the growing despair of family members who must witness all of this. Nonetheless, <mark>the pain, suffering, and death imposed on the innocents</mark> thus far <mark>pales in comparison to what lies ahead if more fundamental change is not forthcoming</u></mark>. In order to illustrate the severe consequences of a continuation of the altruistic system, we use the data presented in Figures 1 and 2 above to generate forecasts of future waiting lists and deaths. The forecasts represent our best guess of what the future holds if fundamental change continues to be postponed. The results should serve as a wake-up call for those who argue that we should continue tinkering with the existing procurement system while further postponing the implementation of financial incentives. The costs of such a “wait and see” approach are rapidly becoming intolerable. CHANGING VARIABLE To produce reasonable forecasts of future waiting lists and deaths, we must first confront an apparent anomaly in the reported data that could cast doubt on the accuracy of some of the more recent figures. Specifically, the reported number of deaths of patients on the waiting list (plus those too sick to receive a transplant) follows a consistently upward trend that is very close to a constant proportion of the size of the waiting list over most of the sample period. Beginning in 2002, however, the number of deaths levels off and even starts to decline, despite continued growth of the waiting list. It is not clear why there is an abrupt change in the observed trend in this variable. Our investigation of this issue yielded several plausible explanations but no definitive answer. For example, it may be the case that recent advances in medical care, such as the left ventricular assist device, have extended some patients’ lives and, thereby, reduced the number of deaths on the list. Alternatively, it may be the case that because of rising criticism of the current system, unos has taken steps to remove some of the relatively higher-risk patients from the list before they die. For example, the meld/peld program, which was introduced in February 2002, removed a number of liver patients (who have a comparatively high death rate) from the waiting list. Additionally, the increasing use of so-called “extended criteria” donor organs may have a similar effect, getting the most critically ill patients off the list prior to their deaths. Clearly, the implications of these alternative explanations for reliance on the data are not the same. For example, if patients are, in fact, simply living longer and the data accurately reflect that reality, then our analysis should incorporate the observations. But if the more recent figures are, instead, a manifestation of strategic actions taken by the reporting agency, then they should be excluded. Because we have been unable to identify a single, convincing explanation for the observed phenomenon, we elected to perform our analysis both ways — including and excluding the post-2002 observations on the number of deaths. ESTIMATES Given the two alternative sample periods, the methodology we employ to generate our forecasts is as follows: First, because the number of deaths appears to be causally driven by the number of patients on the waiting list, we begin by estimating a simple linear regression model of the former as a function of the latter. The results of that estimation are reported in Table 1 for the two sample periods described above. Next, we estimate a second linear model with the number of patients on the waiting list regressed against time, again using the two alternative sample periods. Those results are reported in Table 2. From the results, <u><mark>we are able to produce forecasts of </mark>the expected size of <mark>future waiting lists</u></mark> for each of our sample periods. <u>We run the forecasts out 10 years</u> from the end of our longer sample period, to 2015. Given the forecasted waiting list values, we are then able to use the regression results in Table 1 to generate our forecasts of the number of deaths over the same period. The two alternative sets of forecasts are shown graphically in Figures 3 and 4. Depending upon the sample period chosen, the results show the waiting list reaching 145,691 to 152,400 patients by 2015. Of the patients listed at that time, between 10,547 and 13,642 are expected to die that year. Even more tragically, over the entire period of both actual and predicted values, <u>a cumulative total of<mark> 196,310 patients are conservatively expected to die by 2015 as a consequence of the ongoing shortage</mark>.</u> Figure 5 illustrates the results. In that figure, we incorporate several historical reference points in order to put the numbers in perspective. No one directly involved in the transplant industry is likely to be surprised by our results. Thirty years of experience consistently point to a continuation of the current, long-standing trends. There is nothing on the horizon that should lead anyone to expect a sudden reversal. But our purpose is not to surprise the parties who are already knowledgeable about this increasingly severe problem. Rather, our intent is to awaken the sleeping policymakers whose continuing inaction will inevitably lead to these results. They can no longer continue to postpone meaningful reform of the U.S. organ transplant system in the futile hope that, somehow, things will improve. They will not.</p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Organ sales will save lives
430,247
16
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,222
Medicalization controls their impacts – if they don’t solve it they don’t solve any part of the aff
Elden 2
Stuart Elden, politics at University of Warwick, 2/29/2002 “The War of Races and the Constitution of the State: Foucault's «Il faut défendre la société» and the Politics of Calculation,” Boundary,http://boundary2.dukejournals.org/content/29/1/125.full.pdf
null
Racism as biologizing, as tied to a state, takes shape where the procedures of intervention ‘‘at the level of the body, conduct, health, and everyday life, received justification from the mythical concern with protecting the purity of the blood Because certain groups in society are conceived of in medical terms, society is no longer in need of being defended from the outsider but from the insider: the abnormal in behavior, species, or race What is novel is not the mentality of power but the technology of power hen coupled with the mechanisms of mathematics and medicine in bio-power, this can be conceived of in entirely different ways. Bio-power is able to establish, between my life and the death of the other, a relation that is not warlike or confrontational but biological abnormal individuals can be eliminated the death of the other, of the bad, inferior race or the degenerate or abnormal, makes life purer This holds for indirect death—the exposure to death—as much as for direct killing The theme of the political enemy is extrapolated biologically war is no longer simply a way of securing one race by eliminating the other but of regenerating that race In Nazism Eugenics and medical/mathematical techniques are coupled with the fantasy of blood and the ideal of the purity of the race the old sovereign power of killing traversed the entire society
The reverse side is the power to allow death. State racism is a recoding of the old mechanisms of blood through the new procedures of regulation. Racism, as biologizing, as tied to a state, takes shape where the procedures of intervention ‘‘at the level of the body, conduct, health, and everyday life, received their color and their justification from the mythical concern with protecting the purity of the blood and ensuring the triumph of the race’’ (VS, 197; WK, 149).37 For example, the old anti-Semitism based on religion is reused under the new rubric of state racism. The integrity and purity of the race is threatened, and the state apparatuses are introduced against the race that has infiltrated and introduced noxious elements into the body. The Jews are characterized as the race present in the middle of all races (FDS, 76).38 The use of medical language is important. Because certain groups in society are conceived of in medical terms, society is no longer in need of being defended from the outsider but from the insider: the abnormal in behavior, species, or race. What is novel is not the mentality of power but the technology of power (FDS, 230). The recoding of old problems is made possible through new techniques.2 A break or cut (coupure) is fundamental to racism: a division or incision between those who must live and those who must die. The ‘‘biological continuum of the human species’’ is fragmented by the apparition of races, which are seen as distinguished, hierarchized, qualified as good or inferior, and so forth. The species is subdivided into subgroups that are thought of as races. In a sense, then, just as the continuum of geometry becomes divisible in Descartes,39 the human continuum is divided, that is, made calculable and orderable, two centuries later. As Anderson has persuasively argued, to suggest that racism has its roots in nationalism is a mistake. He suggests that ‘‘the dreams of racism actually have their origin in ideologies of class, rather than in those of nation: above all in claims to divinity among rulers and to ‘blue’ or ‘white’ blood and breeding among aristocracies.’’40 As Stoler has noted, for Foucault, it is the other way around: ‘‘A discourse of class derives from an earlier discourse of races.’’41 But it is a more subtle distinction than that. What Foucault suggests is that discourses of class have their roots in the war of races, but so, too, does modern racism; what is different is the biological spin put on the concepts.42 But as well as emphasizing the biological, modern racism puts this another way: to survive, to live, one must be prepared to massacre one’s enemies, a relation of war. As a relation of war, this is no different from the earlier war of races that Foucault has spent so much of the course explaining. But when coupled with the mechanisms of mathematics and medicine in bio-power, this can be conceived of in entirely different ways. Bio-power is able to establish, between my life and the death of the other, a relation that is not warlike or confrontational but biological: ‘‘The more inferior species tend to disappear, the more abnormal individuals can be eliminated, the less the species will be degenerated, the more I— not as an individual but as a species—will live, will be strong, will be vigorous, will be able to proliferate.’’ The death of the other does not just make me safer personally, but the death of the other, of the bad, inferior race or the degenerate or abnormal, makes life in general healthier and purer (FDS, 227–28). ‘‘The existence in question is no longer of sovereignty, juridical; but that of the population, biological. If genocide is truly the dream of modern powers, this is not because of a return today of the ancient right to kill; it is because power is situated and exercised at the level of life, the species, the race, and the large-scale phenomena of population’’ (VS, 180; WK, 136). ‘‘If the power of normalization wishes to exercise the ancient sovereign right of killing, it must pass through racism. And if, inversely, a sovereign power, that is to say a power with the right of life and death, wishes to function with the instruments, mechanisms, and technology of normalization, it must also pass through racism’’ (FDS, 228). This holds for indirect death—the exposure to death—as much as for direct killing. While not Darwinism, this biological sense of power is based on evolutionism and enables a thinking of colonial relations, the necessity of wars, criminality, phenomena of madness and mental illness, class divisions, and so forth. The link to colonialism is central: This form of modern state racism develops first with colonial genocide. The theme of the political enemy is extrapolated biologically. But what is important in the shift at the end of the nineteenth century is that war is no longer simply a way of securing one race by eliminating the other but of regenerating that race (FDS, 228–30). As Foucault puts it in La volonté de savoir: Wars are no longer waged in the name of a sovereign who must be defended; they are waged on behalf of the existence of all; entire populations are mobilized for the purpose of wholesale slaughter in the name of life necessity. Massacres have become vital [vitaux— understood in a dual sense, both as essential and biological]. It is as managers of life and survival, of bodies and the race, that so many regimes have been able to wage so many wars, causing so many men to be killed. (VS, 180; WK, 136) The shift Foucault thinks is interesting is what might be called a shift from sanguinity to sexuality: sanguinity, in that it had an instrumental role (the shedding of blood) and a symbolic role (purity of blood, differences of blood); sexuality, when mechanisms of power are directed to the body, to life. The theme of race is present in both, but in a different form (VS, 194; WK, 147). We have moved from ‘‘a symbolics of blood to an analytics of sexuality. Clearly, nothing was more on the side of the law, death, transgression, the symbolic, and sovereignty than blood; just as sexuality was on the side of the norm, knowledge, life, meaning, the disciplines and regulations’’ (VS, 195; WK, 148). In Nazism, the two are combined. Eugenics and medical/mathematical techniques are coupled with the fantasy of blood and the ideal of the purity of the race. Foucault notes that there was immediate control of procreation and genetics in the Nazi regime, and that regulation, security, and assurance were imposed over the disciplined, ordered society; but at the same time, the old sovereign power of killing traversed the entire society. This was not simply confined to the state, nor simply to the SA or the SS, but ultimately to everyone, as, through denunciation, everyone could have this power over their neighbor (FDS, 231).
6,840
<h4><strong>Medicalization controls their impacts – if they don’t solve it they don’t solve any part of the aff</h4><p></strong>Stuart <strong>Elden</strong>, politics at University of Warwick, 2/29/200<strong>2</strong> “The War of Races and the Constitution of the State: Foucault's «Il faut défendre la société» and the Politics of Calculation,” Boundary,http://boundary2.dukejournals.org/content/29/1/125.full.pdf </p><p><strong>The reverse side is the power to allow death. State racism is a recoding of the old mechanisms of blood through the new procedures of regulation. <mark>Racism</mark>, <mark>as biologizing, as tied to a state, takes shape where the procedures of intervention ‘‘at the level of the body, conduct, health, and everyday life,</mark> <mark>received</mark> their color and their <mark>justification from the mythical concern with protecting the purity of the blood</mark> and ensuring the triumph of the race’’ (VS, 197; WK, 149).37 For example, the old anti-Semitism based on religion is reused under the new rubric of state racism. The integrity and purity of the race is threatened, and the state apparatuses are introduced against the race that has infiltrated and introduced noxious elements into the body. The Jews are characterized as the race present in the middle of all races (FDS, 76).38 The use of medical language is important. <mark>Because certain groups in society are conceived of in medical terms, society is no longer in need of being defended from the outsider but from the insider: the abnormal in behavior, species, or race</mark>. <mark>What is novel is not the mentality of power but the technology of power</mark> (FDS, 230). The recoding of old problems is made possible through new techniques.2 A break or cut (coupure) is fundamental to racism: a division or incision between those who must live and those who must die. The ‘‘biological continuum of the human species’’ is fragmented by the apparition of races, which are seen as distinguished, hierarchized, qualified as good or inferior, and so forth. The species is subdivided into subgroups that are thought of as races. In a sense, then, just as the continuum of geometry becomes divisible in Descartes,39 the human continuum is divided, that is, made calculable and orderable, two centuries later. As Anderson has persuasively argued, to suggest that racism has its roots in nationalism is a mistake. He suggests that ‘‘the dreams of racism actually have their origin in ideologies of class, rather than in those of nation: above all in claims to divinity among rulers and to ‘blue’ or ‘white’ blood and breeding among aristocracies.’’40 As Stoler has noted, for Foucault, it is the other way around: ‘‘A discourse of class derives from an earlier discourse of races.’’41 But it is a more subtle distinction than that. What Foucault suggests is that discourses of class have their roots in the war of races, but so, too, does modern racism; what is different is the biological spin put on the concepts.42 But as well as emphasizing the biological, modern racism puts this another way: to survive, to live, one must be prepared to massacre one’s enemies, a relation of war. As a relation of war, this is no different from the earlier war of races that Foucault has spent so much of the course explaining. But w<mark>hen coupled with the mechanisms of mathematics and medicine in bio-power, this can be conceived of in entirely different ways. Bio-power is able to establish, between my life and the death of the other, a relation that is not warlike or confrontational but biological</mark>: ‘‘The more inferior species tend to disappear, the more <mark>abnormal individuals can be eliminated</mark>, the less the species will be degenerated, the more I— not as an individual but as a species—will live, will be strong, will be vigorous, will be able to proliferate.’’ The death of the other does not just make me safer personally, but <mark>the death of the other, of the bad, inferior race or the degenerate or abnormal, makes life</mark> in general healthier and <mark>purer</mark> (FDS, 227–28). ‘‘The existence in question is no longer of sovereignty, juridical; but that of the population, biological. If genocide is truly the dream of modern powers, this is not because of a return today of the ancient right to kill; it is because power is situated and exercised at the level of life, the species, the race, and the large-scale phenomena of population’’ (VS, 180; WK, 136). ‘‘If the power of normalization wishes to exercise the ancient sovereign right of killing, it must pass through racism. And if, inversely, a sovereign power, that is to say a power with the right of life and death, wishes to function with the instruments, mechanisms, and technology of normalization, it must also pass through racism’’ (FDS, 228). <mark>This holds for indirect death—the exposure to death—as much as for direct killing</mark>. While not Darwinism, this biological sense of power is based on evolutionism and enables a thinking of colonial relations, the necessity of wars, criminality, phenomena of madness and mental illness, class divisions, and so forth. The link to colonialism is central: This form of modern state racism develops first with colonial genocide. <mark>The theme of the political enemy is extrapolated biologically</mark>. But what is important in the shift at the end of the nineteenth century is that <mark>war is no longer simply a way of securing one race by eliminating the other but of regenerating that race</mark> (FDS, 228–30). As Foucault puts it in La volonté de savoir: Wars are no longer waged in the name of a sovereign who must be defended; they are waged on behalf of the existence of all; entire populations are mobilized for the purpose of wholesale slaughter in the name of life necessity. Massacres have become vital [vitaux— understood in a dual sense, both as essential and biological]. It is as managers of life and survival, of bodies and the race, that so many regimes have been able to wage so many wars, causing so many men to be killed. (VS, 180; WK, 136) The shift Foucault thinks is interesting is what might be called a shift from sanguinity to sexuality: sanguinity, in that it had an instrumental role (the shedding of blood) and a symbolic role (purity of blood, differences of blood); sexuality, when mechanisms of power are directed to the body, to life. The theme of race is present in both, but in a different form (VS, 194; WK, 147). We have moved from ‘‘a symbolics of blood to an analytics of sexuality. Clearly, nothing was more on the side of the law, death, transgression, the symbolic, and sovereignty than blood; just as sexuality was on the side of the norm, knowledge, life, meaning, the disciplines and regulations’’ (VS, 195; WK, 148). <mark>In Nazism</mark>, the two are combined. <mark>Eugenics and medical/mathematical techniques are coupled with the fantasy of blood and the ideal of the purity of the race</mark>. Foucault notes that there was immediate control of procreation and genetics in the Nazi regime, and that regulation, security, and assurance were imposed over the disciplined, ordered society; but at the same time, <mark>the old sovereign power of killing traversed the entire society</strong></mark>. This was not simply confined to the state, nor simply to the SA or the SS, but ultimately to everyone, as, through denunciation, everyone could have this power over their neighbor (FDS, 231).</p>
null
Off
CP
55,906
45
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,223
Coercion of the poor does not apply to central purchasing –egg donations prove
Sobota 4
Sobota 4 Margaret R. Sobota, J.D. Candidate (2005), Washington University School of Law. Washington University Law Quarterly Fall, 2004 82 Wash. U. L. Q. 1225 NOTE: THE PRICE OF LIFE: $ 50,000 FOR AN EGG, WHY NOT $ 1,500 FOR A KIDNEY? AN ARGUMENT TO ESTABLISH A MARKET FOR ORGAN PROCUREMENT SIMILAR TO THE CURRENT MARKET FOR HUMAN EGG PROCUREMENT lexis
, the economic coercion argument is based on the false premise that the prices donors will be paid for their organs will be high enough to override their doubts and ethical concerns In the proposed market system for organ procurement, the state will be paying the donors; thus preventing potential wealthy recipients from driving up the prices . With only moderate prices being paid , economic incentives would likely not outweigh a donor's moral objections , and thus no economic coercion would occur. Additionally, the current market system for egg donation suggests that economic coercion would not be a problem in a market for organ procurement. A majority of egg donors are not poor or minority women, and the amounts paid to them for their donations are usually not an "undue inducement to undergo the medical risks involved." These facts suggest that if a system of financial compensation for organ donation were established, comparable to the system already in place for egg donation, there would similarly be no economic coercion of donors.
the state will be paying the donors; thus preventing potential wealthy recipients from driving up the prices With moderate prices being paid economic incentives would likely not outweigh a donor's moral objections thus no economic coercion would occur dditionally the market for egg donation suggests that economic coercion would not be a problem in a market for organ procurement majority of egg donors are not poor or minority women
A. Arguments Opposing a Market for Organ Procurement The main argument against establishing a market for organ procurement is economic coercion. n141 Market opponents insist that poor, destitute people from around the world will be forced into selling their organs without making an in-formed decision. n142 There are several flaws with this argument. n143 First, the economic coercion argument is based on the false premise that the prices donors will be paid for their organs will be high enough to override their doubts and ethical concerns about becoming a donor. n144 In the proposed market system for organ procurement, either OPOs or the state will be paying the donors; thus preventing potential wealthy recipients from driving up the prices paid for organs. n145 With only moderate prices being paid to organ donors, economic incentives would likely not outweigh a donor's moral objections to donation, and thus no economic coercion would occur. n146 Additionally, the current market system for egg donation suggests that economic coercion would not be a problem in a market for organ procurement. n147 A majority of egg donors are not poor or minority women, and the amounts paid to them for their donations are usually not an "undue inducement to undergo the medical [*1246] risks involved." n148 These facts suggest that if a system of financial compensation for organ donation were established, comparable to the system already in place for egg donation, there would similarly be no economic coercion of donors.
1,526
<h4><strong>Coercion of the poor does not apply to central purchasing –egg donations prove</h4><p>Sobota 4</strong> Margaret R. Sobota, J.D. Candidate (2005), Washington University School of Law. Washington University Law Quarterly Fall, 2004 82 Wash. U. L. Q. 1225 NOTE: THE PRICE OF LIFE: $ 50,000 FOR AN EGG, WHY NOT $ 1,500 FOR A KIDNEY? AN ARGUMENT TO ESTABLISH A MARKET FOR ORGAN PROCUREMENT SIMILAR TO THE CURRENT MARKET FOR HUMAN EGG PROCUREMENT lexis</p><p>A. Arguments Opposing a Market for Organ Procurement</p><p>The main argument against establishing a market for organ procurement is economic coercion. n141 Market opponents insist that poor, destitute people from around the world will be forced into selling their organs without making an in-formed decision. n142 There are several flaws with this argument. n143 First<u>, the economic coercion argument is based on the false premise that the prices donors will be paid for their organs will be high enough to override their doubts and ethical concerns </u>about becoming a donor. n144 <u>In the proposed market system for organ procurement, </u>either OPOs or<u> <mark>the state will be paying the donors; thus preventing potential wealthy recipients from driving up the prices</mark> </u>paid for organs<u>.</u> n145 <u><mark>With </mark>only <mark>moderate prices being paid</mark> </u>to organ donors<u>, <mark>economic incentives would likely not outweigh a donor's moral objections</mark> </u>to donation<u>, and <mark>thus no economic coercion</mark> <mark>would occur</mark>.</u> n146 <u>A<mark>dditionally</mark>, <mark>the</mark> current <mark>market</mark> system <mark>for egg donation suggests that economic coercion would not be a problem in a market for organ procurement</mark>.</u> n147 <u><strong>A <mark>majority of egg donors are not poor or minority women</strong></mark>, and the amounts paid to them for their donations are usually not an "undue inducement to undergo the medical</u> [*1246] <u>risks involved." </u>n148<u> These facts suggest that if a system of financial compensation for organ donation were established, comparable to the system already in place for egg donation, there would similarly be no economic coercion of donors.</p></u>
null
null
Contention 3 The Plan solves
430,597
8
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,224
Governments won’t utilize prediction market data
Tunkelang 10
Daniel Tunkelang 10, Head of Search Quality at LinkedIn, 6/9/10, “Why Can’t We Just Use Prediction Markets?,” http://thenoisychannel.com/2010/06/09/why-cant-we-just-use-prediction-markets
Prediction markets were all the rage a few years ago There was a proposal to have the US government run a prediction market for terrorist attacks In principle, this framework allows any event with a quantifiable outcome to be predicted prediction markets have not had a broad impact on decision making despite all of the “anys Outside of political forecasting and sports gambling I’m not aware of any groups outside of academia that invest significantly in the use of prediction markets it’s safe to say prediction markets have had limited traction
P m s were all the rage years ago There was a proposal to have the gov run a market In principle, this allows any event to be predicted prediction markets have not had a broad impact on decision making, despite all the “anys Outside of political forecasting and sports gambling I’m not aware of any groups outside of academia that invest significantly in the use of prediction markets prediction markets have had limited traction
Prediction markets were all the rage a few years ago, two of the most notable being the Iowa Electronic Market forecasting electoral results and the now defunct Tradesports offering a similar platform for betting on sports events. There was even a proposal to have the US government run a prediction market for terrorist attacks. In a prediction market, any event with a quantifiable (e.g., binary) outcome can be converted into an asset. At any given time, the asset value corresponds to the market prediction of the probability of the outcome. Just as in any security market, participants determine the value through their buying and selling actions. In principle, this framework allows any event with a quantifiable outcome to be predicted by a marketplace. But, at least from my vantage point, prediction markets have not had a broad impact on decision making, despite all of the “anys” in the previous paragraph. Outside of political forecasting and sports gambling (and of course finance itself), I’m not aware of any groups outside of academia that invest significantly in the use of prediction markets. Sure, there’s the Hollywood Stock Exchange that applies the fantasy sports concept to the movie industry and even startup Empire Avenue that aspires to generalize this idea even further into an “online influence stock exchange”. Still, I think it’s safe to say that prediction markets have had limited traction to date.
1,431
<h4>Governments won’t <u>utilize</u> prediction market data </h4><p>Daniel <strong>Tunkelang 10</strong>, Head of Search Quality at LinkedIn, 6/9/10, “Why Can’t We Just Use Prediction Markets?,” http://thenoisychannel.com/2010/06/09/why-cant-we-just-use-prediction-markets</p><p><u><mark>P</mark>rediction <mark>m</mark>arket<mark>s were</u> <u>all the rage</mark> a few <mark>years ago</u></mark>, two of the most notable being the Iowa Electronic Market forecasting electoral results and the now defunct Tradesports offering a similar platform for betting on sports events. <u><mark>There was</u></mark> even <u><mark>a proposal to have the</mark> US <mark>gov</mark>ernment <mark>run a</mark> prediction <mark>market</mark> for terrorist attacks</u>. </p><p>In a prediction market, any event with a quantifiable (e.g., binary) outcome can be converted into an asset. At any given time, the asset value corresponds to the market prediction of the probability of the outcome. Just as in any security market, participants determine the value through their buying and selling actions. <u><mark>In principle, this</mark> framework <mark>allows any event</mark> with a quantifiable outcome <mark>to be predicted</u></mark> by a marketplace. </p><p>But, at least from my vantage point, <u><mark>prediction markets have</u> <u>not had a broad impact on decision making</u>, <u>despite all</mark> of <mark>the “anys</u></mark>” in the previous paragraph. <u><mark>Outside of political forecasting and sports gambling</u></mark> (and of course finance itself), <u><mark>I’m not aware of any groups outside of academia that invest significantly in the use of prediction markets</u></mark>. Sure, there’s the Hollywood Stock Exchange that applies the fantasy sports concept to the movie industry and even startup Empire Avenue that aspires to generalize this idea even further into an “online influence stock exchange”. Still, I think <u>it’s safe to say</u> that <u><mark>prediction markets have had limited traction</u></mark> to date.</p>
Block
AT: Empirics
AT: Inevitable
429,698
13
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,225
Organs from cadavers don’t solve
Fry-Revere 14
Fry-Revere 14 Sigrid Fry-Revere. Director of bioethics studies, CATO Institute 2014
The Kidney Sellers: A Journey of Discovery in Iran p 6 Today the number of kidneys provided from cadavers could never be enough, even if every organ from every potential qualified donor could be harvested. This is true because not every death results in useable organs. Organs can be diseased or injured, or the body can be dead too long before it reaches the hospital. no matter how the process for retrieving organs from the dead improves, there will never be enough kidneys to meet the ever-growing demand.
kidneys provided from cadavers could never be enough, even if every organ from every potential qualified donor could be harvested. because not every death results in useable organs. Organs can be diseased or injured, or the body can be dead too long before it reaches the hospital no matter how the process for retrieving organs improves there will never be enough
The Kidney Sellers: A Journey of Discovery in Iran p 6 At the time, what Congress did seemed reasonable, but over the following three decades, no matter how efficient the U.S. cadaver organ procurement sys- tem became, it could not satisfy the demand. Medical innovations keep people alive longer, and the ever-growing diabetes and hypertension epidemics contin- ually increased the number of people who could benefit from a kidney transplant. Today the number of kidneys provided from cadavers could never be enough, even if every organ from every potential qualified donor could be harvested. This is true because not every death results in useable organs. Organs can be diseased or injured, or the body can be dead too long before it reaches the hospital. Patients who die in the hospital after a car accident or similar trauma are the best potential organ donors because the appropriate medical equip- ment is at hand to switch gears from saving the patient to preserving organs for transplantation. Nevertheless, given what we know now, no matter how the process for retrieving organs from the dead improves, there will never be enough kidneys to meet the ever-growing demand.
1,179
<h4>Organs from cadavers don’t solve</h4><p><strong>Fry-Revere 14</strong> Sigrid Fry-Revere. Director of bioethics studies, CATO Institute 2014 </p><p><u>The Kidney Sellers: A Journey of Discovery in Iran p 6</p><p></u>At the time, what Congress did seemed reasonable, but over the following three decades, no matter how efficient the U.S. cadaver organ procurement sys- tem became, it could not satisfy the demand. Medical innovations keep people alive longer, and the ever-growing diabetes and hypertension epidemics contin- ually increased the number of people who could benefit from a kidney transplant. <u>Today the number of <mark>kidneys provided from cadavers could never be enough, even if every organ from every potential qualified donor could be harvested. </mark>This is true <mark>because not every death results in useable organs. Organs can be diseased or injured, or the body can be dead too long before it reaches the hospital</mark>.</u> Patients who die in the hospital after a car accident or similar trauma are the best potential organ donors because the appropriate medical equip- ment is at hand to switch gears from saving the patient to preserving organs<u> </u>for transplantation. Nevertheless, given what we know now,<u> <mark>no matter how the process for retrieving organs</mark> from the dead <mark>improves</mark>, <mark>there will never be enough</mark> kidneys to meet the ever-growing demand.</p></u>
null
null
Contention 1 – Organ sales will save lives
430,248
7
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,226
Suicide isn’t a medical problem---legalizing suicide but removing the physician and medical profession as a whole from the picture is key
Szasz 99
Thomas S. Szasz 99, psychiatrist, Fellow of the American Psychiatric Association, member of the American Psychoanalytic Association, professor of psychiatry at the State University of New York, and professor emeritus of psychiatry at the SUNY Upstate Medical University in Syracuse, “Suicide as a Moral Issue”, July 1999, published by The Foundation for Economic Education, The Freeman, 49: 41-42
*edited for gender "Suicide is an event that is a part of human nature every person must confront it for himself anew, and every age must come to its own terms with it." --Johann Wolfgang von Goethe (1749-1832) dying voluntarily is a choice intrinsic to human existence. It is our ultimate, fatal freedom. That is not how the right-thinking person today sees voluntary death: [s]he believes that no one in his right mind kills himself, that suicide is a mental health problem. Behind that belief lies a transparent evasion: relying on physicians to prevent suicide as well as to provide suicide -- and thus avoid the subject of suicide -- is an evasion of personal responsibility fatal to freedom. the time is ripe to rethink our attitude toward suicide and its relation to the medical profession, accept suicide comfortably, and speak about it calmly we must demedicalize and destigmatize voluntary death and accept it as a behavior that has always been and will always be a part of the human condition Wanting to die cannot be a bona fide medical treatment; and it can never justify deprivation of liberty. advances in medical technology have transformed how we die machines, transplanted organs, and immunosuppressive drugs have created choices not only about whether to live or die but also about when and how to die. procreating voluntarily is a personal decision dying voluntarily is also a personal decision The state and the medical profession no longer interfere with birth control. They ought to stop interfering with death control. As a society, we can choose to let people die on their own terms or force them to die on terms decreed by the dominant ethic suicide is logically anterior to physician-assisted suicide. Over time, social attitudes toward many behaviors have changed. Suicide began as a sin, became a crime, then became a mental illness, and now some people propose transferring it into the category called "treatment," provided the cure is under the control of doctors. Is killing oneself a voluntary act or the product of mental illness? Should physicians be permitted to use force to prevent suicide? Should they be authorized to prescribe a lethal dose of a drug for the purpose of suicide? Personal careers, professional identities, multi-billion dollar industries, legal doctrines, judicial procedures, and the life and liberty of every American hangs on how we answer these questions. Answering such questions requires no specialized knowledge of medicine or law. It requires only a willingness to open our eyes and look life -- and death -- in the eye. Evading that challenge is tantamount to denying that we are just as responsible for how we die as we are for how we live. The person who kills [her]self sees suicide as a solution For the person who kills [her]self suicide is an action Psychiatrists maintain that suicide is the result of a disease Set against this mind set, the view that, a priori, suicide has nothing to do with illness or medicine risks being dismissed akin to asserting that cancer has nothing to do with illness or medicine. The evidence that suicide is not a medical matter is all around us suicide is plainly not legal if it were, it would be illegal to use force to prevent suicide Instead, coercive suicide prevention is considered a life-saving treatment and helping a person kill [her]self is a felony. For a long time, suicide was the business of the Church and the priest. Now it is the business of the State and the doctor
Suicide is an event that is a part of human nature dying voluntarily is a choice intrinsic to human existence It is our ultimate fatal freedom relying on physicians to provide suicide is an evasion of personal responsibility fatal to freedom the time is ripe to rethink our attitude toward suicide and its relation to the medical profession we must demedicalize voluntary death procreating is a personal decision dying is also The state and the medical profession ought to stop interfering with death control Over time social attitudes change For the person who kills [her]self suicide is an action Psychiatrists maintain suicide is the result of a disease Set against this mind set, the view that suicide has nothing to do with medicine risks being dismissed The evidence that suicide is not a medical matter is all around us suicide is plainly not legal if it were, it would be illegal to use force to prevent suicide Instead coercive suicide prevention is considered life-saving and helping a person kill [her]self is a felony
*edited for gender "Suicide is an event that is a part of human nature. However much may have been said and done about it in the past, every person must confront it for himself anew, and every age must come to its own terms with it." --Johann Wolfgang von Goethe (1749-1832) Behind Goethe's simple statement lies a profound truth: dying voluntarily is a choice intrinsic to human existence. It is our ultimate, fatal freedom. That is not how the right-thinking person today sees voluntary death: [s]he believes that no one in his right mind kills himself, that suicide is a mental health problem. Behind that belief lies a transparent evasion: relying on physicians to prevent suicide as well as to provide suicide -- and thus avoid the subject of suicide -- is an evasion of personal responsibility fatal to freedom. Not long ago the right-thinking person believed that masturbation, oral sex, homosexuality, and other "unnatural acts" were medical problems whose solution was delegated to doctors. It took us a surprisingly long time to take these behaviors back from physicians, accept them comfortably, and speak about them calmly. Perhaps the time is ripe to rethink our attitude toward suicide and its relation to the medical profession, accept suicide comfortably, and speak about it calmly. To accomplish this, we must demedicalize and destigmatize voluntary death and accept it as a behavior that has always been and will always be a part of the human condition. Wanting to die or killing oneself is sometimes blameworthy, sometimes praiseworthy, and sometimes neither; it is not a disease; it cannot be a bona fide medical treatment; and it can never justify deprivation of liberty. Increasing life expectancy, advances in medical technology, and radical changes in the regulation of drug use and the economics of health care have transformed how we die. Formerly, most people died at home. Today, most people die in a hospital. Formerly, patients who could not breathe or whose kidneys or livers or hearts failed to function died. Now, they can be kept alive by machines, transplanted organs, and immunosuppressive drugs. These developments have created choices not only about whether to live or die but also about when and how to die. Birth and death are unique phenomena. Absent celibacy or infertility, practicing birth control -- that is, procreating voluntarily -- is a personal decision. Absent accidental or sudden death, practicing death control -- that is, dying voluntarily -- is also a personal decision. The state and the medical profession no longer interfere with birth control. They ought to stop interfering with death control. Practicing birth control and practicing death control as well as abstaining from these practices have far-reaching consequences, for both the individual and others. Birth control is important for the young, death control, for the old. The young are often entrapped by abstaining from birth control, the old, by abstaining from death control. As individuals, we can choose to die actively or passively, practicing death control or dying of disease or old age. As a society, we can choose to let people die on their own terms or force them to die on terms decreed by the dominant ethic. Camus maintained that suicide is the only "truly serious philosophical problem." It would be more accurate to say that suicide is our foremost moral and political problem, logically anterior to such closely related problems as the right to reject treatment or the right to physician-assisted suicide. Faced with a particular personal conduct, we can approve, facilitate, and reward it; disapprove, hinder, and penalize it; or accept, tolerate, and ignore it. Over time, social attitudes toward many behaviors have changed. Suicide began as a sin, became a crime, then became a mental illness, and now some people propose transferring it into the category called "treatment," provided the cure is under the control of doctors. Is killing oneself a voluntary act or the product of mental illness? Should physicians be permitted to use force to prevent suicide? Should they be authorized to prescribe a lethal dose of a drug for the purpose of suicide? Personal careers, professional identities, multi-billion dollar industries, legal doctrines, judicial procedures, and the life and liberty of every American hangs on how we answer these questions. Answering such questions requires no specialized knowledge of medicine or law. It requires only a willingness to open our eyes and look life -- and death -- in the eye. Evading that challenge is tantamount to denying that we are just as responsible for how we die as we are for how we live. The person who kills [her]self sees suicide as a solution. If the observer views it as problem, he precludes understanding the suicide just as surely as he would preclude understanding a Japanese speaker if [s]he assumed that he is hearing garbled English. For the person who kills [her]self or plans to kill [her]self, suicide is, eo ipso, an action. Psychiatrists, however, maintain that suicide is a happening, the result of a disease: as coronary arteriosclerosis causes myocardial infarction, so clinical depression causes suicide. Set against this mind set, the view that, a priori, suicide has nothing to do with illness or medicine, which is my view, risks being dismissed as an act of intellectual know-nothingness, akin to asserting that cancer has nothing to do with illness or medicine. The evidence that suicide is not a medical matter is all around us. We are proud that suicide is no longer a crime, yet it is plainly not legal; if it were, it would be illegal to use force to prevent suicide and it would be legal to help a person kill himself. Instead, coercive suicide prevention is considered a life-saving treatment and helping a person kill [her]self is (in most jurisdictions) a felony. Supporters and opponents of policies concerning troubling social issues -- such as slavery, pornography, abortion -- have always invoked a sacred authority or creed to justify the policies they favored. Formerly, God, the Bible, the Church; now, the Constitution, Law, Medicine. It is an unpersuasive tactic: too many deplorable social policies have been justified by appeals to Scriptural, Constitutional, and Medical sanctions. The question of who should control when and how we die is one of the most troubling issues we face today. The debate is in full swing. Once again, the participants invoke the authority of the Bible, the Constitution, and Medicine to cast the decisive ballot in favor of their particular program. It is a spineless gambit: persons who promote particular social policies do so because they believe that their policies are superior to the policies of their adversaries. Accordingly, they ought to defend their position on the grounds of their own moral vision, instead of trying to disarm opponents by appealing to a sanctified authority. For a long time, suicide was the business of the Church and the priest. Now it is the business of the State and the doctor. Eventually we will make it our own business, regardless of what the Bible or the Constitution or Medicine supposedly tells us about it.
7,212
<h4>Suicide isn’t a medical problem---legalizing suicide but removing the physician and medical profession <u>as a whole</u> from the picture is key</h4><p>Thomas S. <strong>Szasz 99</strong>, psychiatrist, Fellow of the American Psychiatric Association, member of the American Psychoanalytic Association, professor of psychiatry at the State University of New York, and professor emeritus of psychiatry at the SUNY Upstate Medical University in Syracuse, “Suicide as a Moral Issue”, July 1999, published by The Foundation for Economic Education, The Freeman, 49: 41-42</p><p><u>*edited for gender</p><p>"<mark>Suicide is an event that is a part of human nature</u></mark>. However much may have been said and done about it in the past, <u>every person must confront it for himself anew, and every age must come to its own terms with it." </p><p><strong>--Johann Wolfgang von Goethe (1749-1832) </p><p></u></strong>Behind Goethe's simple statement lies a profound truth: <u><mark>dying voluntarily is a choice intrinsic to human existence</mark>. <mark>It is our ultimate</mark>, <mark>fatal freedom</mark>. That is not how the right-thinking person today sees voluntary death: [s]he believes that no one in his right mind kills himself, that suicide is a mental health problem. Behind that belief lies a transparent evasion: <strong><mark>relying on physicians</strong></mark> to prevent suicide as well as <strong><mark>to provide suicide</strong></mark> -- and thus avoid the subject of suicide -- <strong><mark>is an evasion of personal responsibility fatal to freedom</mark>.</p><p></u></strong>Not long ago the right-thinking person believed that masturbation, oral sex, homosexuality, and other "unnatural acts" were medical problems whose solution was delegated to doctors. It took us a surprisingly long time to take these behaviors back from physicians, accept them comfortably, and speak about them calmly. Perhaps <u><strong><mark>the time is ripe to rethink our attitude toward suicide and its relation to the medical profession</mark>, accept suicide comfortably, and speak about it calmly</u></strong>. To accomplish this, <u><mark>we must <strong>demedicalize</strong></mark> and destigmatize <mark>voluntary death</mark> and accept it as a behavior that has always been and will always be a part of the human condition</u>. <u>Wanting to die</u> or killing oneself is sometimes blameworthy, sometimes praiseworthy, and sometimes neither; it is not a disease; it <u>cannot be a bona fide medical treatment; and it can never justify deprivation of liberty. </p><p></u>Increasing life expectancy, <u>advances in medical technology</u>, and radical changes in the regulation of drug use and the economics of health care <u>have transformed how we die</u>. Formerly, most people died at home. Today, most people die in a hospital. Formerly, patients who could not breathe or whose kidneys or livers or hearts failed to function died. Now, they can be kept alive by <u>machines, transplanted organs, and immunosuppressive drugs</u>. These developments <u><strong>have created choices not only about whether to live or die but also about when and how to die. </p><p></u></strong>Birth and death are unique phenomena. Absent celibacy or infertility, practicing birth control -- that is, <u><mark>procreating</mark> voluntarily</u> -- <u><mark>is a personal decision</u></mark>. Absent accidental or sudden death, practicing death control -- that is, <u><mark>dying</mark> voluntarily</u> -- <u><mark>is also</mark> a personal decision</u>. <u><mark>The state and the medical profession</mark> no longer interfere with birth control. <strong>They <mark>ought to stop interfering with death control</mark>. </p><p></u></strong>Practicing birth control and practicing death control as well as abstaining from these practices have far-reaching consequences, for both the individual and others. Birth control is important for the young, death control, for the old. The young are often entrapped by abstaining from birth control, the old, by abstaining from death control. </p><p>As individuals, we can choose to die actively or passively, practicing death control or dying of disease or old age. <u>As a society, we can choose to let people die on their own terms or force them to die on terms decreed by the dominant ethic</u>. Camus maintained that suicide is the only "truly serious philosophical problem." It would be more accurate to say that <u>suicide is</u> our foremost moral and political problem, <u>logically anterior to</u> such closely related problems as the right to reject treatment or the right to <u>physician-assisted suicide. </p><p></u>Faced with a particular personal conduct, we can approve, facilitate, and reward it; disapprove, hinder, and penalize it; or accept, tolerate, and ignore it. <u><mark>Over time</mark>, <mark>social attitudes</mark> toward many behaviors have <mark>change</mark>d. Suicide began as a sin, became a crime, then became a mental illness, and now some people propose transferring it into the category called "treatment," provided the cure is under the control of doctors. </p><p>Is killing oneself a voluntary act or the product of mental illness? Should physicians be permitted to use force to prevent suicide? Should they be authorized to prescribe a lethal dose of a drug for the purpose of suicide? Personal careers, professional identities, multi-billion dollar industries, legal doctrines, judicial procedures, and the life and liberty of every American hangs on how we answer these questions. Answering such questions requires no specialized knowledge of medicine or law. It requires only a willingness to open our eyes and look life -- and death -- in the eye. Evading that challenge is tantamount to denying that we are just as responsible for how we die as we are for how we live. </p><p>The person who kills [her]self sees suicide as a solution</u>. If the observer views it as problem, he precludes understanding the suicide just as surely as he would preclude understanding a Japanese speaker if [s]he assumed that he is hearing garbled English. <u><mark>For the person who kills [her]self</u></mark> or plans to kill [her]self, <u><mark>suicide is</u></mark>, eo ipso, <u><mark>an action</u></mark>. <u><mark>Psychiatrists</u></mark>, however, <u><mark>maintain</mark> that <mark>suicide is</mark> </u>a happening, <u><mark>the result of a disease</u></mark>: as coronary arteriosclerosis causes myocardial infarction, so clinical depression causes suicide. <u><mark>Set against this mind set, the view that</mark>, a priori, <mark>suicide has <strong>nothing to do with</strong></mark> illness or <strong><mark>medicine</u></strong></mark>, which is my view, <u><mark>risks being dismissed</u></mark> as an act of intellectual know-nothingness, <u>akin to asserting that cancer has nothing to do with illness or medicine. </p><p><strong><mark>The evidence that suicide is not a medical matter is all around us</u></strong></mark>. We are proud that <u><mark>suicide</u></mark> is no longer a crime, yet it <u><strong><mark>is plainly not legal</u></strong></mark>; <u><mark>if it were, it would be illegal to use force to prevent suicide</u></mark> and it would be legal to help a person kill himself. <u><mark>Instead</mark>, <mark>coercive suicide prevention is considered</mark> a <mark>life-saving</mark> treatment <mark>and helping a person kill [her]self is</u></mark> (in most jurisdictions) <u><mark>a felony</mark>. </p><p></u>Supporters and opponents of policies concerning troubling social issues -- such as slavery, pornography, abortion -- have always invoked a sacred authority or creed to justify the policies they favored. Formerly, God, the Bible, the Church; now, the Constitution, Law, Medicine. It is an unpersuasive tactic: too many deplorable social policies have been justified by appeals to Scriptural, Constitutional, and Medical sanctions. </p><p>The question of who should control when and how we die is one of the most troubling issues we face today. The debate is in full swing. Once again, the participants invoke the authority of the Bible, the Constitution, and Medicine to cast the decisive ballot in favor of their particular program. It is a spineless gambit: persons who promote particular social policies do so because they believe that their policies are superior to the policies of their adversaries. Accordingly, they ought to defend their position on the grounds of their own moral vision, instead of trying to disarm opponents by appealing to a sanctified authority. </p><p><u>For a long time, suicide was the business of the Church and the priest. Now it is the business of the State and the doctor</u>. Eventually we will make it our own business, regardless of what the Bible or the Constitution or Medicine supposedly tells us about it.</p>
null
null
CP
430,340
11
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,227
And their recentering of individual autonomy prevents an analysis of medicine as a system of power relations – links to the K and turns case even if they’re right about the act of PAS
Salem 99
Salem 99 Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full
There is a certain consensus that institutionalization of death has extended physicians’ role in regulating death In the wake of the “right to die” movement doctors share end-of-life decisions and choices with patients and families 70 percent of deaths in the hospital occur after a decision has been made to withhold treatment one of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dying medicalization of death, is so deeply embedded in our culture that it goes unnoticed The sway of medicine should not be understood as a Machiavellian strategy devised by doctors physicians themselves are under medicine's power and not always aware of their critical role in the cultural construction of death and dying the paradox dissolves, when we recognize it as a facet of how thoroughly public conscience is imbued with medical ideology Physician-assisted suicide is widely but incorrectly represented as a further step in the demedicalization of death begun by the patients’ rights and right to die movements. It ultimately extends the power of physicians in regulating death, now under the guise of “assisting” suicide
institutionalization of death has extended physicians’ role in regulating death doctors share end-of-life decisions and choices with patients and families one of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dyin medicalization of death, is so deeply embedded in our culture that it goes unnoticed The sway of medicine should not be understood as a Machiavellian strategy devised by doctors physicians themselves are under medicine's power and not always aware of their critical role in the cultural construction of death and dying Physician-assisted suicide is widely but incorrectly represented as a further step in the demedicalization of death begun by the patients’ rights movements It ultimately extends the power of physicians in regulating death, now under the guise of “assisting” suicide
There is a certain consensus that the institutionalization of death, its transference from the community to the hospital setting and its medicalization, has extended physicians’ role in regulating death. Today some 80 percent of deaths in the United States take place in health care facilities, while as recently as fifty years ago only a small minority of people died in hospitals or long-term care facilities. In the wake of the “right to die” movement, today in theory—and to some extent in actual practice—doctors share end-of-life decisions and choices with patients and families. In this sense, all contrive to consolidate “managed death” as the predominant way of dying in the United States. Indeed, the American Hospital Association reported that about 70 percent of deaths in the hospital occur after a decision has been made to withhold treatment.30 Despite the space ceded to patients’ autonomous choices, one of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dying. This intangible aspect of medicine's power, such a crucial facet of the medicalization of death, is so deeply embedded in our culture that it goes unnoticed. The sway of medicine should not be understood as a Machiavellian strategy devised by doctors to dominate various domains of contemporary life; physicians themselves are under medicine's power and not always aware of their critical role in the cultural construction of death and dying. There is a paradox in our attitude toward modern medicine: on the one hand, we criticize and wish to counterbalance medicine's power through the enhancement of the patient's autonomy, and on the other, we open up the doors for physicians in the domain of suicide. Yet from another perspective the paradox dissolves, when we recognize it as a facet of how thoroughly public conscience is imbued with medical ideology. Physician-assisted suicide is widely but incorrectly represented as a further step in the demedicalization of death begun by the patients’ rights and right to die movements. It ultimately extends the power of physicians in regulating death, now under the guise of “assisting” suicide.
2,230
<h4>And their recentering of individual autonomy prevents an analysis of medicine as a system of power relations – links to the K and turns case even if they’re right about the act of PAS</h4><p><strong>Salem 99</strong> Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full</p><p><u>There is a certain consensus that</u> the <u><mark>institutionalization of death</u></mark>, its transference from the community to the hospital setting and its medicalization, <u><mark>has extended physicians’ role in regulating death</u></mark>. Today some 80 percent of deaths in the United States take place in health care facilities, while as recently as fifty years ago only a small minority of people died in hospitals or long-term care facilities.</p><p><u>In the wake of the “right to die” movement</u>, today in theory—and to some extent in actual practice—<u><mark>doctors share end-of-life decisions and choices with patients and families</u></mark>. In this sense, all contrive to consolidate “managed death” as the predominant way of dying in the United States. Indeed, the American Hospital Association reported that about <u>70 percent of deaths in the hospital occur after a decision has been made to withhold treatment</u>.30</p><p>Despite the space ceded to patients’ autonomous choices, <u><mark>one of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dyin</mark>g</u>. This intangible aspect of medicine's power, such a crucial facet of the <u><mark>medicalization of death, is so deeply embedded in our culture that it goes unnoticed</u></mark>. <u><mark>The sway of medicine should not be understood as a Machiavellian strategy devised by doctors</u></mark> to dominate various domains of contemporary life; <u><mark>physicians themselves are under medicine's power and not always aware of their critical role in the cultural construction of death and dying</u></mark>.</p><p>There is a paradox in our attitude toward modern medicine: on the one hand, we criticize and wish to counterbalance medicine's power through the enhancement of the patient's autonomy, and on the other, we open up the doors for physicians in the domain of suicide. Yet from another perspective <u>the paradox dissolves, when we recognize it as a facet of how thoroughly public conscience is imbued with medical ideology</u>.</p><p><u><mark>Physician-assisted suicide is widely but incorrectly represented as a further step in the demedicalization of death begun by the patients’ rights</mark> and right to die <mark>movements</mark>. <mark>It ultimately extends the power of physicians in regulating death, now under the guise of “assisting” suicide</u></mark>.</p>
null
Off
CP
430,351
7
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,228
Structural violence is the largest proximate cause of war- creates priming that psychologically structures escalation
Scheper-Hughes and Bourgois ‘4
Scheper-Hughes and Bourgois ‘4
Absolutely central to our approach is a blurring of categories and distinctions between wartime and peacetime violence. Close attention to the “little” violences produced in the structures, habituses, and mentalites of everyday life shifts our attention to pathologies of class, race, and gender inequalities. The violence continuum also refers to the ease with which humans are capable of reducing the socially vulnerable into expendable nonpersons and assuming the license - even the duty - to kill, maim, or soul-murder. it is absolutely necessary to make just such existential leaps in purposefully linking violent acts in normal times to those of abnormal times. there is), an even greater risk lies in failing to sensitize ourselves, in misrecognizing protogenocidal practices and sentiments daily enacted as normative behavior by “ordinary” good-enough citizens. Peacetime crimes constitute the “small wars and invisible genocides” These are “invisible” genocides not because they are secreted away or hidden from view, but quite the opposite. , the things that are hardest to perceive are those which are right before our eyes and therefore taken for granted. Peacetime crimes suggests the possibility that war crimes are merely ordinary, everyday crimes of public consent applied systematically and dramatically in the extreme context of war The public consensus is based primarily on a new mobilization of an old fear of the mob, the mugger, the rapist, the Black man, the undeserving poor. How many public executions of mentally deficient prisoners in the United States are needed to make life feel more secure for the affluent? it is essential that we recognize the existence of a genocidal capacity among otherwise good-enough humans and that we need to exercise a defensive hypervigilance to the less dramatic, permitted, and even rewarded everyday acts of violence that render participation in genocidal acts and policies possible Under the violence continuum we include, therefore, all expressions of radical social exclusion, dehumanization, depersonal- ization, pseudospeciation, and reification which normalize atrocious behavior and violence toward others. A constant self-mobilization for alarm, a state of constant hyperarousal is, perhaps, a reasonable response to Benjamin’s view of late modern history as a chronic “state of emergency” Making that decisive move to recognize the continuum of violence allows us to see the capacity and the willingness - if not enthusiasm - of ordinary people, the practical technicians of the social consensus, to enforce genocidal-like crimes against categories of rubbish people. There is no primary impulse out of which mass violence and genocide are born, it is ingrained in the common sense of everyday social life. The mad, the differently abled, the mentally vulnerable have often fallen into this category of the unworthy living, as have the very old and infirm, the sick-poor, and, of course, the despised racial, religious, sexual, and ethnic groups of the moment. . Collective denial and misrecognition are prerequisites for mass violence and genocide. Everyday violence encompasses the implicit, legitimate, and routinized forms of violence inherent in particular social, economic, and political formations. that mass violence is part of a continuum, and that it is socially incremental and often experienced by perpetrators, collaborators, bystanders - and even by victims themselves - as expected, routine, even justified They harbor the “priming” that push social consensus toward devaluing certain forms of human life
central to our approach is a blurring of wartime and peacetime violence Close attention to the “little” violences produced in structures of everyday life shifts our attention to pathologies of class, race, and gender inequalities humans are capable of reducing the socially vulnerable into expendable nonpersons it is absolutely necessary to make existential leaps in purposefully linking violent acts in normal times to those of abnormal times. an even greater risk lies in in misrecognizing protogenocidal practices daily enacted by “ordinary” citizens These are “invisible” genocides because they are right before our eyes and war crimes are ordinary, everyday crimes of public consent applied systematically in the extreme context of war it is essential that we exercise a defensive hypervigilance to the everyday acts of violence that render participation in genocidal acts and policies possible Making that decisive move to recognize the continuum of violence allows us to see the capacity of ordinary people, to enforce genocidal like crimes There is no primary impulse out of which mass violence and genocide are born, it is ingrained in the common sense of everyday social life Collective denial and misrecognition are prerequisites for mass violence mass violence is socially incremental and often experienced as expected, routine They harbor the priming that push social consensus toward devaluing certain forms of human life
(Prof of Anthropology @ Cal-Berkely; Prof of Anthropology @ UPenn) (Nancy and Philippe, Introduction: Making Sense of Violence, in Violence in War and Peace, pg. 19-22) **Answers no root cause- because there is no root cause we must be attentative to structural inequality of all kinds because it primes people for broader violence- our impact is about the scale of violence and the disproportionate relationship between that scale and warfare, not that one form of social exclusion comes first This large and at first sight “messy” Part VII is central to this anthology’s thesis. It encompasses everything from the routinized, bureaucratized, and utterly banal violence of children dying of hunger and maternal despair in Northeast Brazil (Scheper-Hughes, Chapter 33) to elderly African Americans dying of heat stroke in Mayor Daly’s version of US apartheid in Chicago’s South Side (Klinenberg, Chapter 38) to the racialized class hatred expressed by British Victorians in their olfactory disgust of the “smelly” working classes (Orwell, Chapter 36). In these readings violence is located in the symbolic and social structures that overdetermine and allow the criminalized drug addictions, interpersonal bloodshed, and racially patterned incarcerations that characterize the US “inner city” to be normalized (Bourgois, Chapter 37 and Wacquant, Chapter 39). Violence also takes the form of class, racial, political self-hatred and adolescent self-destruction (Quesada, Chapter 35), as well as of useless (i.e. preventable), rawly embodied physical suffering, and death (Farmer, Chapter 34). Absolutely central to our approach is a blurring of categories and distinctions between wartime and peacetime violence. Close attention to the “little” violences produced in the structures, habituses, and mentalites of everyday life shifts our attention to pathologies of class, race, and gender inequalities. More important, it interrupts the voyeuristic tendencies of “violence studies” that risk publicly humiliating the powerless who are often forced into complicity with social and individual pathologies of power because suffering is often a solvent of human integrity and dignity. Thus, in this anthology we are positing a violence continuum comprised of a multitude of “small wars and invisible genocides” (see also Scheper- Hughes 1996; 1997; 2000b) conducted in the normative social spaces of public schools, clinics, emergency rooms, hospital wards, nursing homes, courtrooms, public registry offices, prisons, detention centers, and public morgues. The violence continuum also refers to the ease with which humans are capable of reducing the socially vulnerable into expendable nonpersons and assuming the license - even the duty - to kill, maim, or soul-murder. We realize that in referring to a violence and a genocide continuum we are flying in the face of a tradition of genocide studies that argues for the absolute uniqueness of the Jewish Holocaust and for vigilance with respect to restricted purist use of the term genocide itself (see Kuper 1985; Chaulk 1999; Fein 1990; Chorbajian 1999). But we hold an opposing and alternative view that, to the contrary, it is absolutely necessary to make just such existential leaps in purposefully linking violent acts in normal times to those of abnormal times. Hence the title of our volume: Violence in War and in Peace. If (as we concede) there is a moral risk in overextending the concept of “genocide” into spaces and corners of everyday life where we might not ordinarily think to find it (and there is), an even greater risk lies in failing to sensitize ourselves, in misrecognizing protogenocidal practices and sentiments daily enacted as normative behavior by “ordinary” good-enough citizens. Peacetime crimes, such as prison construction sold as economic development to impoverished communities in the mountains and deserts of California, or the evolution of the criminal industrial complex into the latest peculiar institution for managing race relations in the United States (Waquant, Chapter 39), constitute the “small wars and invisible genocides” to which we refer. This applies to African American and Latino youth mortality statistics in Oakland, California, Baltimore, Washington DC, and New York City. These are “invisible” genocides not because they are secreted away or hidden from view, but quite the opposite. As Wittgenstein observed, the things that are hardest to perceive are those which are right before our eyes and therefore taken for granted. In this regard, Bourdieu’s partial and unfinished theory of violence (see Chapters 32 and 42) as well as his concept of misrecognition is crucial to our task. By including the normative everyday forms of violence hidden in the minutiae of “normal” social practices - in the architecture of homes, in gender relations, in communal work, in the exchange of gifts, and so forth - Bourdieu forces us to reconsider the broader meanings and status of violence, especially the links between the violence of everyday life and explicit political terror and state repression, Similarly, Basaglia’s notion of “peacetime crimes” - crimini di pace - imagines a direct relationship between wartime and peacetime violence. Peacetime crimes suggests the possibility that war crimes are merely ordinary, everyday crimes of public consent applied systematically and dramatically in the extreme context of war. Consider the parallel uses of rape during peacetime and wartime, or the family resemblances between the legalized violence of US immigration and naturalization border raids on “illegal aliens” versus the US government- engineered genocide in 1938, known as the Cherokee “Trail of Tears.” Peacetime crimes suggests that everyday forms of state violence make a certain kind of domestic peace possible. Internal “stability” is purchased with the currency of peacetime crimes, many of which take the form of professionally applied “strangle-holds.” Everyday forms of state violence during peacetime make a certain kind of domestic “peace” possible. It is an easy-to-identify peacetime crime that is usually maintained as a public secret by the government and by a scared or apathetic populace. Most subtly, but no less politically or structurally, the phenomenal growth in the United States of a new military, postindustrial prison industrial complex has taken place in the absence of broad-based opposition, let alone collective acts of civil disobedience. The public consensus is based primarily on a new mobilization of an old fear of the mob, the mugger, the rapist, the Black man, the undeserving poor. How many public executions of mentally deficient prisoners in the United States are needed to make life feel more secure for the affluent? What can it possibly mean when incarceration becomes the “normative” socializing experience for ethnic minority youth in a society, i.e., over 33 percent of young African American men (Prison Watch 2002). In the end it is essential that we recognize the existence of a genocidal capacity among otherwise good-enough humans and that we need to exercise a defensive hypervigilance to the less dramatic, permitted, and even rewarded everyday acts of violence that render participation in genocidal acts and policies possible (under adverse political or economic conditions), perhaps more easily than we would like to recognize. Under the violence continuum we include, therefore, all expressions of radical social exclusion, dehumanization, depersonal- ization, pseudospeciation, and reification which normalize atrocious behavior and violence toward others. A constant self-mobilization for alarm, a state of constant hyperarousal is, perhaps, a reasonable response to Benjamin’s view of late modern history as a chronic “state of emergency” (Taussig, Chapter 31). We are trying to recover here the classic anagogic thinking that enabled Erving Goffman, Jules Henry, C. Wright Mills, and Franco Basaglia among other mid-twentieth-century radically critical thinkers, to perceive the symbolic and structural relations, i.e., between inmates and patients, between concentration camps, prisons, mental hospitals, nursing homes, and other “total institutions.” Making that decisive move to recognize the continuum of violence allows us to see the capacity and the willingness - if not enthusiasm - of ordinary people, the practical technicians of the social consensus, to enforce genocidal-like crimes against categories of rubbish people. There is no primary impulse out of which mass violence and genocide are born, it is ingrained in the common sense of everyday social life. The mad, the differently abled, the mentally vulnerable have often fallen into this category of the unworthy living, as have the very old and infirm, the sick-poor, and, of course, the despised racial, religious, sexual, and ethnic groups of the moment. Erik Erikson referred to “pseudo- speciation” as the human tendency to classify some individuals or social groups as less than fully human - a prerequisite to genocide and one that is carefully honed during the unremark- able peacetimes that precede the sudden, “seemingly unintelligible” outbreaks of mass violence. Collective denial and misrecognition are prerequisites for mass violence and genocide. But so are formal bureaucratic structures and professional roles. The practical technicians of everyday violence in the backlands of Northeast Brazil (Scheper-Hughes, Chapter 33), for example, include the clinic doctors who prescribe powerful tranquilizers to fretful and frightfully hungry babies, the Catholic priests who celebrate the death of “angel-babies,” and the municipal bureaucrats who dispense free baby coffins but no food to hungry families. Everyday violence encompasses the implicit, legitimate, and routinized forms of violence inherent in particular social, economic, and political formations. It is close to what Bourdieu (1977, 1996) means by “symbolic violence,” the violence that is often “nus-recognized” for something else, usually something good. Everyday violence is similar to what Taussig (1989) calls “terror as usual.” All these terms are meant to reveal a public secret - the hidden links between violence in war and violence in peace, and between war crimes and “peace-time crimes.” Bourdieu (1977) finds domination and violence in the least likely places - in courtship and marriage, in the exchange of gifts, in systems of classification, in style, art, and culinary taste- the various uses of culture. Violence, Bourdieu insists, is everywhere in social practice. It is misrecognized because its very everydayness and its familiarity render it invisible. Lacan identifies “rneconnaissance” as the prerequisite of the social. The exploitation of bachelor sons, robbing them of autonomy, independence, and progeny, within the structures of family farming in the European countryside that Bourdieu escaped is a case in point (Bourdieu, Chapter 42; see also Scheper-Hughes, 2000b; Favret-Saada, 1989). Following Gramsci, Foucault, Sartre, Arendt, and other modern theorists of power-vio- lence, Bourdieu treats direct aggression and physical violence as a crude, uneconomical mode of domination; it is less efficient and, according to Arendt (1969), it is certainly less legitimate. While power and symbolic domination are not to be equated with violence - and Arendt argues persuasively that violence is to be understood as a failure of power - violence, as we are presenting it here, is more than simply the expression of illegitimate physical force against a person or group of persons. Rather, we need to understand violence as encompassing all forms of “controlling processes” (Nader 1997b) that assault basic human freedoms and individual or collective survival. Our task is to recognize these gray zones of violence which are, by definition, not obvious. Once again, the point of bringing into the discourses on genocide everyday, normative experiences of reification, depersonalization, institutional confinement, and acceptable death is to help answer the question: What makes mass violence and genocide possible? In this volume we are suggesting that mass violence is part of a continuum, and that it is socially incremental and often experienced by perpetrators, collaborators, bystanders - and even by victims themselves - as expected, routine, even justified. The preparations for mass killing can be found in social sentiments and institutions from the family, to schools, churches, hospitals, and the military. They harbor the early “warning signs” (Charney 1991), the “priming” (as Hinton, ed., 2002 calls it), or the “genocidal continuum” (as we call it) that push social consensus toward devaluing certain forms of human life and lifeways from the refusal of social support and humane care to vulnerable “social parasites” (the nursing home elderly, “welfare queens,” undocumented immigrants, drug addicts) to the militarization of everyday life (super-maximum-security prisons, capital punishment; the technologies of heightened personal security, including the house gun and gated communities; and reversed feelings of victimization).
13,177
<h4><strong>Structural violence is the largest proximate cause of war- creates priming that psychologically structures escalation</h4><p>Scheper-Hughes and Bourgois ‘4</p><p></strong>(Prof of Anthropology @ Cal-Berkely; Prof of Anthropology @ UPenn) (Nancy and Philippe, Introduction: Making Sense of Violence, in Violence in War and Peace, pg. 19-22) **Answers no root cause- because there is no root cause we must be attentative to structural inequality of all kinds because it primes people for broader violence- our impact is about the scale of violence and the disproportionate relationship between that scale and warfare, not that one form of social exclusion comes first</p><p>This large and at first sight “messy” Part VII is central to this anthology’s thesis. It encompasses everything from the routinized, bureaucratized, and utterly banal violence of children dying of hunger and maternal despair in Northeast Brazil (Scheper-Hughes, Chapter 33) to elderly African Americans dying of heat stroke in Mayor Daly’s version of US apartheid in Chicago’s South Side (Klinenberg, Chapter 38) to the racialized class hatred expressed by British Victorians in their olfactory disgust of the “smelly” working classes (Orwell, Chapter 36). In these readings violence is located in the symbolic and social structures that overdetermine and allow the criminalized drug addictions, interpersonal bloodshed, and racially patterned incarcerations that characterize the US “inner city” to be normalized (Bourgois, Chapter 37 and Wacquant, Chapter 39). Violence also takes the form of class, racial, political self-hatred and adolescent self-destruction (Quesada, Chapter 35), as well as of useless (i.e. preventable), rawly embodied physical suffering, and death (Farmer, Chapter 34). <u>Absolutely <mark>central</mark> <mark>to our approach</mark> <mark>is a blurring of</mark> categories and distinctions between <mark>wartime and peacetime violence</mark>. <mark>Close attention to the “little” violences produced in</mark> the <mark>structures</mark>, habituses, and mentalites <mark>of everyday life shifts our attention to pathologies of class, race, and gender inequalities</mark>.</u> More important, it interrupts the voyeuristic tendencies of “violence studies” that risk publicly humiliating the powerless who are often forced into complicity with social and individual pathologies of power because suffering is often a solvent of human integrity and dignity. Thus, in this anthology we are positing a violence continuum comprised of a multitude of “small wars and invisible genocides” (see also Scheper- Hughes 1996; 1997; 2000b) conducted in the normative social spaces of public schools, clinics, emergency rooms, hospital wards, nursing homes, courtrooms, public registry offices, prisons, detention centers, and public morgues. <u>The violence continuum also refers to the ease with which <strong><mark>humans are capable of reducing the socially vulnerable into expendable nonpersons</strong></mark> and assuming the license - even the duty - to kill, maim, or soul-murder.</u> We realize that in referring to a violence and a genocide continuum we are flying in the face of a tradition of genocide studies that argues for the absolute uniqueness of the Jewish Holocaust and for vigilance with respect to restricted purist use of the term genocide itself (see Kuper 1985; Chaulk 1999; Fein 1990; Chorbajian 1999). But we hold an opposing and alternative view that, to the contrary, <u><mark>it is absolutely necessary to make</mark> just such <mark>existential leaps in purposefully linking violent acts in normal times to those of abnormal times.</u></mark> Hence the title of our volume: Violence in War and in Peace. If (as we concede) there is a moral risk in overextending the concept of “genocide” into spaces and corners of everyday life where we might not ordinarily think to find it (and <u>there is), <mark>an even greater</mark> <mark>risk</mark> <mark>lies in</mark> failing to sensitize ourselves, <mark>in misrecognizing protogenocidal practices</mark> and sentiments <mark>daily enacted</mark> as normative behavior <mark>by “ordinary”</mark> good-enough <mark>citizens</mark>. Peacetime crimes</u>, such as prison construction sold as economic development to impoverished communities in the mountains and deserts of California, or the evolution of the criminal industrial complex into the latest peculiar institution for managing race relations in the United States (Waquant, Chapter 39), <u>constitute the “small wars and invisible genocides”</u> to which we refer. This applies to African American and Latino youth mortality statistics in Oakland, California, Baltimore, Washington DC, and New York City. <u><mark>These are “invisible” genocides</mark> not <mark>because they are</mark> secreted away or hidden from view, but quite the opposite.</u> As Wittgenstein observed<u>, the things that are hardest to perceive are those which are <mark>right before our eyes and</mark> therefore taken for granted.</u> In this regard, Bourdieu’s partial and unfinished theory of violence (see Chapters 32 and 42) as well as his concept of misrecognition is crucial to our task. By including the normative everyday forms of violence hidden in the minutiae of “normal” social practices - in the architecture of homes, in gender relations, in communal work, in the exchange of gifts, and so forth - Bourdieu forces us to reconsider the broader meanings and status of violence, especially the links between the violence of everyday life and explicit political terror and state repression, Similarly, Basaglia’s notion of “peacetime crimes” - crimini di pace - imagines a direct relationship between wartime and peacetime violence. <u>Peacetime crimes suggests the possibility that <mark>war crimes are</mark> merely <mark>ordinary, everyday crimes of public consent applied systematically</mark> and dramatically <mark>in the extreme context of war</u></mark>. Consider the parallel uses of rape during peacetime and wartime, or the family resemblances between the legalized violence of US immigration and naturalization border raids on “illegal aliens” versus the US government- engineered genocide in 1938, known as the Cherokee “Trail of Tears.” Peacetime crimes suggests that everyday forms of state violence make a certain kind of domestic peace possible. Internal “stability” is purchased with the currency of peacetime crimes, many of which take the form of professionally applied “strangle-holds.” Everyday forms of state violence during peacetime make a certain kind of domestic “peace” possible. It is an easy-to-identify peacetime crime that is usually maintained as a public secret by the government and by a scared or apathetic populace. Most subtly, but no less politically or structurally, the phenomenal growth in the United States of a new military, postindustrial prison industrial complex has taken place in the absence of broad-based opposition, let alone collective acts of civil disobedience. <u>The public consensus is based primarily on a new mobilization of an old fear of the mob, the mugger, the rapist, the Black man, the undeserving poor. How many public executions of mentally deficient prisoners in the United States are needed to make life feel more secure for the affluent? </u>What can it possibly mean when incarceration becomes the “normative” socializing experience for ethnic minority youth in a society, i.e., over 33 percent of young African American men (Prison Watch 2002). In the end <u><mark>it is essential that we</mark> recognize the existence of a genocidal capacity among otherwise good-enough humans and that we need to <mark>exercise a defensive hypervigilance to the</mark> less dramatic, permitted, and even rewarded <mark>everyday acts of violence that render participation in genocidal acts</mark> <mark>and policies</mark> <mark>possible</u></mark> (under adverse political or economic conditions), perhaps more easily than we would like to recognize. <u>Under the violence continuum we include, therefore, all expressions of radical social exclusion, dehumanization, depersonal- ization, pseudospeciation, and reification which normalize atrocious behavior and violence toward others. A constant self-mobilization for alarm, a state of constant hyperarousal is, perhaps, a reasonable response to Benjamin’s view of late modern history as a chronic “state of emergency”</u> (Taussig, Chapter 31). We are trying to recover here the classic anagogic thinking that enabled Erving Goffman, Jules Henry, C. Wright Mills, and Franco Basaglia among other mid-twentieth-century radically critical thinkers, to perceive the symbolic and structural relations, i.e., between inmates and patients, between concentration camps, prisons, mental hospitals, nursing homes, and other “total institutions.” <u><mark>Making that decisive move to recognize the continuum of violence</mark> <mark>allows us to see the capacity</mark> and the willingness - if not enthusiasm - <mark>of ordinary people,</mark> the practical technicians of the social consensus, <mark>to enforce genocidal</mark>-<mark>like</mark> <mark>crimes</mark> against categories of rubbish people. <mark>There is no primary impulse out of which mass violence and genocide are born, it is ingrained in the common sense of everyday social life</mark>. The mad, the differently abled, the mentally vulnerable have often fallen into this category of the unworthy living, as have the very old and infirm, the sick-poor, and, of course, the despised racial, religious, sexual, and ethnic groups of the moment.</u> Erik Erikson referred to “pseudo- speciation” as the human tendency to classify some individuals or social groups as less than fully human - a prerequisite to genocide and one that is carefully honed during the unremark- able peacetimes that precede the sudden, “seemingly unintelligible” outbreaks of mass violence<u>. <mark>Collective denial and misrecognition are prerequisites for mass violence</mark> and genocide.</u> But so are formal bureaucratic structures and professional roles. The practical technicians of everyday violence in the backlands of Northeast Brazil (Scheper-Hughes, Chapter 33), for example, include the clinic doctors who prescribe powerful tranquilizers to fretful and frightfully hungry babies, the Catholic priests who celebrate the death of “angel-babies,” and the municipal bureaucrats who dispense free baby coffins but no food to hungry families. <u>Everyday violence encompasses the implicit, legitimate, and routinized forms of violence inherent in particular social, economic, and political formations.</u> It is close to what Bourdieu (1977, 1996) means by “symbolic violence,” the violence that is often “nus-recognized” for something else, usually something good. Everyday violence is similar to what Taussig (1989) calls “terror as usual.” All these terms are meant to reveal a public secret - the hidden links between violence in war and violence in peace, and between war crimes and “peace-time crimes.” Bourdieu (1977) finds domination and violence in the least likely places - in courtship and marriage, in the exchange of gifts, in systems of classification, in style, art, and culinary taste- the various uses of culture. Violence, Bourdieu insists, is everywhere in social practice. It is misrecognized because its very everydayness and its familiarity render it invisible. Lacan identifies “rneconnaissance” as the prerequisite of the social. The exploitation of bachelor sons, robbing them of autonomy, independence, and progeny, within the structures of family farming in the European countryside that Bourdieu escaped is a case in point (Bourdieu, Chapter 42; see also Scheper-Hughes, 2000b; Favret-Saada, 1989). Following Gramsci, Foucault, Sartre, Arendt, and other modern theorists of power-vio- lence, Bourdieu treats direct aggression and physical violence as a crude, uneconomical mode of domination; it is less efficient and, according to Arendt (1969), it is certainly less legitimate. While power and symbolic domination are not to be equated with violence - and Arendt argues persuasively that violence is to be understood as a failure of power - violence, as we are presenting it here, is more than simply the expression of illegitimate physical force against a person or group of persons. Rather, we need to understand violence as encompassing all forms of “controlling processes” (Nader 1997b) that assault basic human freedoms and individual or collective survival. Our task is to recognize these gray zones of violence which are, by definition, not obvious. Once again, the point of bringing into the discourses on genocide everyday, normative experiences of reification, depersonalization, institutional confinement, and acceptable death is to help answer the question: What makes mass violence and genocide possible? In this volume we are suggesting <u>that <mark>mass violence</mark> is part of a continuum, and that it <mark>is socially incremental and often experienced</mark> by perpetrators, collaborators, bystanders - and even by victims themselves - <mark>as expected, routine</mark>, even justified</u>. The preparations for mass killing can be found in social sentiments and institutions from the family, to schools, churches, hospitals, and the military. <u><mark>They harbor the</u></mark> early “warning signs” (Charney 1991), the <u>“<mark>priming</mark>”</u> (as Hinton, ed., 2002 calls it), or the “genocidal continuum” (as we call it) <u><mark>that push social consensus toward devaluing certain forms of human life</u></mark> and lifeways from the refusal of social support and humane care to vulnerable “social parasites” (the nursing home elderly, “welfare queens,” undocumented immigrants, drug addicts) to the militarization of everyday life (super-maximum-security prisons, capital punishment; the technologies of heightened personal security, including the house gun and gated communities; and reversed feelings of victimization).</p>
null
Contention 4 is risk calculus
Contention 3 The Plan solves
16,028
483
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,229
WTO non-compliance inev
Ikenson 13
Daniel J. Ikenson 13, director of Cato’s Herbert A. Stiefel Center for Trade Policy Studies, MA in economics from George Washington University, “Protectionist Antidumping Regime Is a Pox on America’s Glass House,” www.cato.org/publications/commentary/protectionist-antidumping-regime-pox-americas-glass-house
U.S. policies have been the subject of more W T O disputes 119 and have been found to violate WTO rules more frequently than any other government’s policies No government is more likely to be out of compliance with a final DSB ruling the U S remains out of compliance in cases involving U.S. subsidies to cotton farmers restrictions on Antigua’s gambling services, country of origin labeling requirements on meat products, the so-called Byrd Amendment, a variety of antidumping measures, and several other issues some of which were adjudicated more than a decade ago. , U.S. trade partners have either retaliated, or been authorized to retaliate yet non-compliance continues
U.S. policies have been the subject of more W T O disputes 119 and violate WTO rules more than any other government the U S remains out of compliance in subsidies to cotton farmers country of origin labeling requirements on meat products, the Byrd Amendment antidumping measures, and several other issues U.S. trade partners have retaliated, or been authorized to retaliate yet non-compliance continues
Other candidates come to mind when contemplating the world’s worst international trade scofflaw, but the United States makes a strong case for itself. A recent Commerce Department determination that foreign companies like Samsung, LG, and Electrolux engaged in “targeted dumping” by reducing prices on their washing machines for Black Friday sales confirms that the United States is actively seeking that ignominious distinction. U.S. policies have been the subject of more World Trade Organization disputes (119, followed by the EU with 73, then China with 30) and have been found to violate WTO rules more frequently than any other government’s policies. No government is more likely to be out of compliance with a final WTO Dispute Settlement Body (DSB) ruling — or for a longer period — than the U.S. government. To this day, the United States remains out of compliance in cases involving U.S. subsidies to cotton farmers, restrictions on Antigua’s provision of gambling services, country of origin labeling requirements on meat products, the so-called Byrd Amendment, a variety of antidumping measures, and several other issues, some of which were adjudicated more than a decade ago. In some of these cases, U.S. trade partners have either retaliated, or been authorized to retaliate, against U.S. exporters or asset holders, yet the non-compliance continues as though the United States considers itself above the rules.
1,425
<h4>WTO non-compliance inev </h4><p>Daniel J. <strong>Ikenson 13</strong>, director of Cato’s Herbert A. Stiefel Center for Trade Policy Studies, MA in economics from George Washington University, “Protectionist Antidumping Regime Is a Pox on America’s Glass House,” www.cato.org/publications/commentary/protectionist-antidumping-regime-pox-americas-glass-house</p><p>Other candidates come to mind when contemplating the world’s worst international trade scofflaw, but the United States makes a strong case for itself. A recent Commerce Department determination that foreign companies like Samsung, LG, and Electrolux engaged in “targeted dumping” by reducing prices on their washing machines for Black Friday sales confirms that the United States is actively seeking that ignominious distinction.</p><p><u><mark>U.S. policies have been the subject of more</u> <u>W</u></mark>orld <u><mark>T</u></mark>rade <u><mark>O</u></mark>rganization <u><mark>disputes</u></mark> (<u><strong><mark>119</u></strong></mark>, followed by the EU with 73, then China with 30) <u><mark>and</mark> have been found to <mark>violate WTO rules more</mark> frequently <mark>than any other government</mark>’s policies</u>. <u>No government is more likely to be out of compliance with a final</u> WTO Dispute Settlement Body (<u>DSB</u>) <u>ruling</u> — or for a longer period — than the U.S. government. To this day, <u><mark>the U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates <u><mark>remains out of compliance in</mark> cases involving U.S. <mark>subsidies to cotton farmers</u></mark>, <u>restrictions on Antigua’s </u>provision of<u> gambling services, <mark>country of origin labeling requirements on meat products, the </mark>so-called <mark>Byrd Amendment</mark>, a variety of <mark>antidumping measures, and <strong>several other issues</u></strong></mark>, <u>some of which were adjudicated more than a decade ago. </u>In some of these cases<u>, <mark>U.S. trade partners <strong>have</strong></mark> either <strong><mark>retaliated</strong>, or been authorized to</mark> <mark>retaliate</u></mark>, against U.S. exporters or asset holders, <u><mark>yet</u></mark> the <u><mark>non-compliance continues</u><strong></mark> as though the United States considers itself above the rules.</p></strong>
WTO
Meta
AT: Inevitable
97,365
55
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,230
The possibility of complex artificial organs that actually function is at best decades away.
Adhikari 14
Adhikari 14 Richard Adhikari has written about high-tech for leading industry publications since the 1990s
http://www.technewsworld.com/story/80198.html According to Jordan Miller at Rice "Parts of the body which require human cells to perform biomechanical functions, such as the liver or kidney, are still several decades away from reaching human patients," . "We are still in the feasibility stage -- not sure how to keep cells alive at high cell density and adequate size needed to match human organs." A 3D structure will require nearly 1 billion functioning cells to approximate the function of a liver or kidney, and "there are dozens of cell types in these organs," . "We are typically only looking at one or two cell types being put into a 3D printed structure."
Parts of the body which require human cells to perform biomechanical functions, such as the liver or kidney, are several decades away from reaching human patients We are still in the feasibility stage -- not sure how to keep cells alive at high cell density and adequate size needed to match human organs there are dozens of cell types in these organs We are typically only looking at one or two cell types being put into a 3D printed structure
03/26/14 Bioprinting, Part 1: The Promise and the Pitfalls http://www.technewsworld.com/story/80198.html [According to Jordan Miller, assistant professor of bioengineering at Rice University]. "Parts of the body which require human cells to perform biomechanical functions, such as the liver or kidney, are still several decades away from reaching human patients," Miller said. "We are still in the feasibility stage -- not sure how to keep cells alive at high cell density and adequate size needed to match human organs." A 3D structure will require nearly 1 billion functioning cells to approximate the function of a liver or kidney, and "there are dozens of cell types in these organs," Miller pointed out. "We are typically only looking at one or two cell types being put into a 3D printed structure." NOTE SOURCE WITH QUALS EDITED INTO BEGINNING OF CARD
861
<h4>The possibility of complex artificial organs that actually function is at best decades away.</h4><p><strong>Adhikari 14</strong> Richard Adhikari has written about high-tech for leading industry publications since the 1990s </p><p>03/26/14 Bioprinting, Part 1: The Promise and the Pitfalls <u>http://www.technewsworld.com/story/80198.html</p><p></u>[<u>According to Jordan Miller</u>, assistant professor of bioengineering <u>at Rice</u> University]. <u>"<mark>Parts of the body which require human cells to perform biomechanical functions, such as the liver or kidney, are </mark>still <mark>several decades away from reaching human patients</mark>," </u>Miller said<u>. "<mark>We are still in the feasibility stage -- not sure how to keep cells alive at high cell density and adequate size needed to match human organs</mark>." A 3D structure will require nearly 1 billion functioning cells to approximate the function of a liver or kidney, and "<mark>there are dozens of cell types in these organs</mark>," </u>Miller pointed out<u>. "<mark>We are typically only looking at one or two cell types being put into a 3D printed structure</mark>."</p><p></u>NOTE SOURCE WITH QUALS EDITED INTO BEGINNING OF CARD</p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Organ sales will save lives
430,249
7
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,231
Use of physicans turns the aff
Salem 99
Salem 99 Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full
no doubt emphasis on inner individuals prevails in contemporary arguments for physician-assisted suicide Influences from the outside are seen as pernicious in subverting the main goal: the “pure” or “true” choice reached from within self-centered ethics rests on a nonrelational conception of personhood there is a paradox underlying physician-assisted suicide It is conceived of as an intimate, existential act and indeed a response to modern medicine, but at the same time it is a request for the complicity of physicians and society What seems unusual in the debate about aid in dying is the request for public endorsement and legitimization of the act of suicide Whereas in suicide the individual “drops out” of the social order, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the individual “drops into” a system that recognizes and must even authorize this particular choice displacing suicide from the private arena to bring it under medicine's stewardship means surrendering suicide to the (medical) “establishment decision to die by suicide is treated precisely as if it were a set of clinical problems to be solved medically the “private self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event it cannot be seen as an act that solely expresses the ideal of individual autonomy as long as it entails assistance it implies a mutual decision and even more importantly assisted suicide presupposes that medicine has passed judgment on the act of suicide physician-assisted suicide entails an increase of medical power over death and social morality
emphasis on inner individuals prevails in contemporary arguments for p a s Influences from the outside are seen as pernicious in subverting the pure choice self-centered ethics rests on a nonrelational conception of personhood there is a paradox underlying physician-assisted suicide it is a request for the complicity of physicians (and society Whereas in suicide the individual “drops out” of the social order, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the individual “drops into” a system that recognizes and must even authorize this particular choice displacing suicide from the private arena to bring it under medicine's stewardship means surrendering suicide to the (medical) “establishment the “private self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event it cannot be seen as an act that solely expresses the ideal of individual autonomy as long as it entails assistance even more importantly assisted suicide presupposes that medicine has passed judgment on the act of suicide physician-assisted suicide entails an increase of medical power over death and social morality
There is no doubt that the emphasis on inner individuals prevails in contemporary arguments for physician-assisted suicide. Influences from the outside, whether subtle or blatant, are seen as pernicious in subverting the main goal: the “pure” or “true” choice reached from within that at bottom takes account of the interests of the decisionmaker. This self-centered ethics rests on a nonrelational conception of personhood. The second—and closely related—pillar of this discourse is the insistence that individuals be radically free to exercise their singularities and idiosyncrasies. In pluralistic societies, it is asserted, “there is far from any agreement, or near-agreement, about how one can establish as canonical a particular normative view of life.”13 Because personal styles, experiences, and beliefs are radically irreducible, it is impossible to suppose a priori that individual choices will coincide; each must find his or her own way of facing dying and death.14 Yet there is a paradox underlying physician-assisted suicide. It is conceived of as an intimate, existential act and indeed a response to modern medicine, but at the same time it is a request for the complicity of physicians (and society). In contemporary Western societies the decision to take death into one's own hands has been construed as an act that is not simply personal, private, and solitary, but contrary to social norms and expectations. From a societal perspective, the individual who commits or attempts suicide is in this sense an outsider. What seems unusual in the debate about aid in dying is the request for public endorsement and legitimization of the act of suicide. Whereas in suicide the individual “drops out” of the social order, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the individual “drops into” a system that recognizes and must even authorize this particular (ostensibly private) choice. In other words, displacing suicide from the private arena to bring it under medicine's stewardship means surrendering suicide to the (medical) “establishment.” The decision to die by suicide is treated precisely as if it were a set of clinical problems to be solved medically— the “private,” “intimate,” “self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event. Precisely because assisted suicide requires the connivance of others (direct from doctors, indirect from society), it cannot be seen as an act that solely expresses the ideal of individual autonomy. On the contrary, as long as it entails assistance it implies a mutual decision. Additionally, and even more importantly, more than a mutual decision, assisted suicide presupposes that medicine has passed judgment on the act of suicide. In sum, physician-assisted suicide both introduces tensions in the principle of personal autonomy and entails an increase of medical power over death and social morality.
2,892
<h4>Use of physicans turns the aff</h4><p><strong>Salem 99</strong> Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full</p><p>There is <u>no doubt</u> that the <u><mark>emphasis on inner individuals prevails in contemporary arguments for p</mark>hysician-<mark>a</mark>ssisted <mark>s</mark>uicide</u>. <u><mark>Influences from the outside</u></mark>, whether subtle or blatant, <u><mark>are seen as pernicious in subverting the</mark> main goal: the “<mark>pure</mark>” or “true” <mark>choice</mark> reached from within</u> that at bottom takes account of the interests of the decisionmaker. This <u><mark>self-centered ethics rests on a nonrelational conception of personhood</u></mark>.</p><p>The second—and closely related—pillar of this discourse is the insistence that individuals be radically free to exercise their singularities and idiosyncrasies. In pluralistic societies, it is asserted, “there is far from any agreement, or near-agreement, about how one can establish as canonical a particular normative view of life.”13 Because personal styles, experiences, and beliefs are radically irreducible, it is impossible to suppose a priori that individual choices will coincide; each must find his or her own way of facing dying and death.14</p><p>Yet <u><mark>there is a paradox underlying physician-assisted suicide</u></mark>. <u>It is conceived of as an intimate, existential act and indeed a response to modern medicine, but at the same time <mark>it is a request for the complicity of physicians</u> (<u>and society</u></mark>). In contemporary Western societies the decision to take death into one's own hands has been construed as an act that is not simply personal, private, and solitary, but contrary to social norms and expectations. From a societal perspective, the individual who commits or attempts suicide is in this sense an outsider.</p><p><u>What seems unusual in the debate about aid in dying is the request for public endorsement and legitimization of the act of suicide</u>. <u><mark>Whereas in suicide the individual “drops out” of the social order, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the individual “drops into” a system that recognizes and must even authorize this particular</u></mark> (ostensibly private) <u><mark>choice</u></mark>. In other words, <u><mark>displacing suicide from the private arena to bring it under medicine's stewardship means surrendering suicide to the (medical) “establishment</u></mark>.”</p><p>The <u>decision to die by suicide is treated precisely as if it were a set of clinical problems to be solved medically</u>— <u><mark>the “private</u></mark>,” “intimate,” “<u><mark>self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event</u></mark>.</p><p>Precisely because assisted suicide requires the connivance of others (direct from doctors, indirect from society), <u><mark>it cannot be seen as an act that solely expresses the ideal of individual autonomy</u></mark>. On the contrary, <u><mark>as long as it entails assistance</mark> it implies a mutual decision</u>. Additionally, <u>and <mark>even more importantly</u></mark>, more than a mutual decision, <u><mark>assisted suicide presupposes that medicine has passed judgment on the act of suicide</u></mark>. In sum, <u><mark>physician-assisted suicide</u></mark> both introduces tensions in the principle of personal autonomy and <u><mark>entails an increase of medical power over death and social morality</u></mark>.</p>
null
null
CP
430,345
3
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,232
PAS opens the door to physicians killing without the patients consent—Dutch studies prove.
Hendin et al 97
Hendin et al 97 Herbert Hendin, MD (AFSP), Chris Rutenfrans, PhD (Dept. of Justice, The Hague), Zbigniew Zylicz, MD (Hospice Rosenhuyvel), “Lessons From the Dutch”, Journal of the American Medical Association, June 4, 1997-Vol 277, No. 21. , http://www.life.org.nz/euthanasia/abouteuthanasia/history-euthanasia10/ //jchen
Death Without Consent The most alarming concern, to arise from the Dutch studies, has been the documentation of cases in which patients, who have not given their consent, have their lives ended by physicians. The 1990 study revealed that in 0.8% of the deaths, more than 1000 cases in the Netherlands each year, physicians admitted they had actively caused death without the explicit consent of the patient. while pointing to the decline, concede that differences in the way this particular information was obtained, make its significance uncertain. In both studies, however, about a quarter of physicians stated that they had "terminated the lives of patients without an explicit request" from the patient to do so and a third more of the physicians could conceive of doing so. The use of the word "explicit" is somewhat inaccurate since, in 48% of these cases, there was no request of any kind, (3[pp.1704]) and in the others, there were mainly references to patients’ earlier statements of not wanting to suffer (l[pp.5l]). International attention had centered on the 1350 cases, 1% of all Dutch deaths in 1990, in which physicians gave pain medication with the explicit intention of ending the patient's life As reported by the physicians, in the 1995 study, in more than 80% of these cases (1537 deaths), no request for death was made by the patient and involuntary (if the patient was competent) euthanasia, they will see this as a striking increase in the number of cases terminated without request and a refutation of the investigators’ claim that there has been perhaps a slight decrease in the number of such cases. totals all the deaths that resulted from euthanasia, assisted suicide, ending the life of a patient without consent, and giving opioids with the explicit intention of ending life, the estimated number of deaths, caused by active intervention by physicians, has increased from 4813 (3.7% of all deaths) in 1990 to 6368 (4.7% of all deaths) Based on data from the questionnaire study, this is an increase of 27% in cases in which physicians actively intervened to cause death (the interview study documents a 20% increase). The Dutch investigators minimize the significance of the number of deaths without consent by explaining that the patients were incompeten We are not told what percentage of those patients' who were given pain medication intended to end their lives without discussing it with them, were competent, but analysis of the data for opioid administration indicates that it is likely to be at least 20%. More than 4000 additional competent patients were given pain medication in amounts likely to end their lives by physicians who did not discuss the decision with them, but whose primary intention was not to end their lives Whether the intention was to end life, or whether death was simply likely, physicians usually gave as the reason for not discussing the decisions with the patients, that they had previously had some discussion of the subject with them (3[pp.1704]). Yet, it seems incomprehensible that a physician would terminate or put at risk the life of a competent patient on the basis of a previous discussion without checking what the patient currently felt. Dutch patient with disseminated breast cancer, who had said she did not want euthanasia, had her life ended because in the physician’s words, "It could have taken another week before she died. I just needed this bed"
The most alarming concern, to arise from the Dutch studies, has been the documentation of cases in which patients, who have not given their consent, have their lives ended by physicians. in 0.8% of the deaths, more than 1000 cases in the Netherlands each year, physicians admitted they had actively caused death without the consent of the patient. about a quarter of physicians stated that they had "terminated the lives of patients without an explicit request in 48% of these cases, there was no request of any kind in more than 80% of these cases (1537 deaths), no request for death was made by the patient Based on data from the questionnaire study, this is an increase of 27% in cases in which physicians actively intervened to cause death More than 4000 additional competent patients were given pain medication in amounts likely to end their lives by physicians who did not discuss the decision with them Dutch patient with disseminated breast cancer, who had said she did not want euthanasia, had her life ended because in the physician’s words, "It could have taken another week before she died. I just needed this bed
Moreover, almost 20% of the physicians’ most recent un-reported cases involved ending of a life without the patient's consent (4[pp.1708]). Such cases, both the 1990 and 1995 studies revealed, were virtually never reported (l[pp.65],4[pl7lO]). Death Without Consent The most alarming concern, to arise from the Dutch studies, has been the documentation of cases in which patients, who have not given their consent, have their lives ended by physicians. The 1990 study revealed that in 0.8% of the deaths, more than 1000 cases in the Netherlands each year, physicians admitted they had actively caused death without the explicit consent of the patient. The 1995 figure is 0.7% (fewer than 1000 cases), but the researchers, while pointing to the decline, concede that differences in the way this particular information was obtained, make its significance uncertain. In both studies, however, about a quarter of physicians stated that they had "terminated the lives of patients without an explicit request" from the patient to do so and a third more of the physicians could conceive of doing so. The use of the word "explicit" is somewhat inaccurate since, in 48% of these cases, there was no request of any kind, (3[pp.1704]) and in the others, there were mainly references to patients’ earlier statements of not wanting to suffer (l[pp.5l]). The 1990 study documented, and the 1995 study confirms, that cases classified, as "termination of the patient without explicit request", were a fraction of the nonvoluntary and involuntary euthanasia cases. International attention had centered on the 1350 cases, 1% of all Dutch deaths in 1990, in which physicians gave pain medication with the explicit intention of ending the patient's life (1[pp.73],12[pp.270]) The investigators minimized the number of patients put to death who had not requested it, by not including these 1350 patients, in that category. By 1995, there had been an increase in the number of deaths in which physicians gave pain medication, with the explicit intention of ending the patient's life, from 1350 cases (1% of all Dutch deaths) to 1896 (1.4% of all Dutch deaths)(3[p1700]). These are comparisons that the Dutch investigators do not make (see Table). As reported by the physicians, in the 1995 study, in more than 80% of these cases (1537 deaths), no request for death was made by the patient (3[pp.1704]). Since researchers around the world have treated these deaths as nonvoluntary and involuntary (if the patient was competent) euthanasia, they will see this as a striking increase in the number of cases terminated without request and a refutation of the investigators’ claim that there has been perhaps a slight decrease in the number of such cases. If one totals all the deaths that resulted from euthanasia, assisted suicide, ending the life of a patient without consent, and giving opioids with the explicit intention of ending life, the estimated number of deaths, caused by active intervention by physicians, has increased from 4813 (3.7% of all deaths) in 1990 to 6368 (4.7% of all deaths) in 1995 (Table). Based on data from the questionnaire study, this is an increase of 27% in cases in which physicians actively intervened to cause death (the interview study documents a 20% increase). The Dutch investigators minimize the significance of the number of deaths without consent by explaining that the patients were incompetent (3[pp.1702]). But in the 1995 study, 21% of the individuals classified as "patients whose lives were ended without explicit request" were competent: in the 1990 study, 37% were competent [l (pp.l704)] We are not told what percentage of those patients' who were given pain medication intended to end their lives without discussing it with them, were competent, but analysis of the data for opioid administration indicates that it is likely to be at least 20%. More than 4000 additional competent patients were given pain medication in amounts likely to end their lives by physicians who did not discuss the decision with them, but whose primary intention was not to end their lives (l[pp.75],3[pp.l700,l704]). Whether the intention was to end life, or whether death was simply likely, physicians usually gave as the reason for not discussing the decisions with the patients, that they had previously had some discussion of the subject with them (3[pp.1704]). Yet, it seems incomprehensible that a physician would terminate or put at risk the life of a competent patient on the basis of a previous discussion without checking what the patient currently felt. An illustration given by the attorney for the Dutch Voluntary Euthanasia Society of why it was often necessary for physicians to end the lives of competent patients without their consent, was the case of a nun whose physician ended her life a few days before she would have died because she was in excruciating pain but her religious convictions did not permit her to ask for death (8[pp.97]). In another case, a Dutch patient with disseminated breast cancer, who had said she did not want euthanasia, had her life ended because in the physician’s words, "It could have taken another week before she died. I just needed this bed" (13).
5,206
<h4><strong>PAS opens the door to physicians killing without the patients consent—Dutch studies prove.</h4><p>Hendin et al 97</p><p></strong>Herbert Hendin, MD (AFSP), Chris Rutenfrans, PhD (Dept. of Justice, The Hague), Zbigniew Zylicz, MD (Hospice Rosenhuyvel), “Lessons From the Dutch”, Journal of the American Medical Association, June 4, 1997-Vol 277, No. 21. , http://www.life.org.nz/euthanasia/abouteuthanasia/history-euthanasia10/ //jchen</p><p>Moreover, almost 20% of the physicians’ most recent un-reported cases involved ending of a life without the patient's consent (4[pp.1708]). Such cases, both the 1990 and 1995 studies revealed, were virtually never reported (l[pp.65],4[pl7lO]).</p><p><u>Death Without Consent</p><p><mark>The most alarming concern, to arise from the Dutch studies, has been the documentation of cases in which patients, who have not given their consent, have their lives ended by physicians.</mark> The 1990 study revealed that <mark>in 0.8% of the deaths, more than 1000 cases in the Netherlands each year, physicians admitted they had actively caused death without the </mark>explicit <mark>consent of the patient.</mark> </p><p></u>The 1995 figure is 0.7% (fewer than 1000 cases), but the researchers, <u>while pointing to the decline, concede that differences in the way this particular information was obtained, make its significance uncertain. In both studies, however, <mark>about a quarter of physicians stated that they had "terminated the lives of patients without an explicit request</mark>" from the patient to do so and a third more of the physicians could conceive of doing so. </p><p>The use of the word "explicit" is somewhat inaccurate since, <mark>in 48% of these cases, there was no request of any kind</mark>, (3[pp.1704]) and in the others, there were mainly references to patients’ earlier statements of not wanting to suffer (l[pp.5l]). </p><p></u>The 1990 study documented, and the 1995 study confirms, that cases classified, as "termination of the patient without explicit request", were a fraction of the nonvoluntary and involuntary euthanasia cases. <u>International attention had centered on the 1350 cases, 1% of all Dutch deaths in 1990, in which physicians gave pain medication with the explicit intention of ending the patient's life</u> (1[pp.73],12[pp.270]) The investigators minimized the number of patients put to death who had not requested it, by not including these 1350 patients, in that category. </p><p>By 1995, there had been an increase in the number of deaths in which physicians gave pain medication, with the explicit intention of ending the patient's life, from 1350 cases (1% of all Dutch deaths) to 1896 (1.4% of all Dutch deaths)(3[p1700]). These are comparisons that the Dutch investigators do not make (see Table). </p><p><u>As reported by the physicians, in the 1995 study, <mark>in more than 80% of these cases (1537 deaths), no request for death was made by the patient</u></mark> (3[pp.1704]). </p><p>Since researchers around the world have treated these deaths as nonvoluntary<u> and involuntary (if the patient was competent) euthanasia, they will see this as a striking increase in the number of cases terminated without request and a refutation of the investigators’ claim that there has been perhaps a slight decrease in the number of such cases. </p><p></u>If one <u>totals all the deaths that resulted from euthanasia, assisted suicide, ending the life of a patient without consent, and giving opioids with the explicit intention of ending life, the estimated number of deaths, caused by active intervention by physicians, has increased from 4813 (3.7% of all deaths) in 1990 to 6368 (4.7% of all deaths)</u> in 1995 (Table). <u><mark>Based on data from the questionnaire study, this is an increase of 27% in cases in which physicians actively intervened to cause death</mark> (the interview study documents a 20% increase). </p><p>The Dutch investigators minimize the significance of the number of deaths without consent by explaining that the patients were incompeten</u>t (3[pp.1702]). But in the 1995 study, 21% of the individuals classified as "patients whose lives were ended without explicit request" were competent: in the 1990 study, 37% were competent [l (pp.l704)] <u>We are not told what percentage of those patients' who were given pain medication intended to end their lives without discussing it with them, were competent, but analysis of the data for opioid administration indicates that it is likely to be at least 20%.</p><p><mark>More than 4000 additional competent patients were given pain medication in amounts likely to end their lives by physicians who did not discuss the decision with them</mark>, but whose primary intention was not to end their lives</u> (l[pp.75],3[pp.l700,l704]). </p><p><u>Whether the intention was to end life, or whether death was simply likely, physicians usually gave as the reason for not discussing the decisions with the patients, that they had previously had some discussion of the subject with them (3[pp.1704]). </p><p>Yet, it seems incomprehensible that a physician would terminate or put at risk the life of a competent patient on the basis of a previous discussion without checking what the patient currently felt. </p><p></u>An illustration given by the attorney for the Dutch Voluntary Euthanasia Society of why it was often necessary for physicians to end the lives of competent patients without their consent, was the case of a nun whose physician ended her life a few days before she would have died because she was in excruciating pain but her religious convictions did not permit her to ask for death (8[pp.97]). </p><p>In another case, a <u><mark>Dutch patient with disseminated breast cancer, who had said she did not want euthanasia, had her life ended because in the physician’s words, "It could have taken another week before she died. I just needed this bed</mark>"</u> (13).</p>
null
Case
CP
430,363
2
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,233
Great power war is obsolete – globalization, nuclear deterrence, and the cooperative liberal order ensure no conflict
Ikenberry and Deudney 9
Ikenberry and Deudney 9 (Daniel – Professor of Politics and International Affairs at Princeton University, and G. John – professor of political science at Johns Hopkins University, Jan/Feb, “The Myth of the Autocratic Revival,” Foreign Affairs, Vol. 88, Issue 1, p. 8)
the picture of an international system marked by conflict and competition is an exaggeration and ignores powerful countervailing factors and forces , the most striking features of the contemporary international landscape are globalization institutions and shared problems of interdependence. The overall structure is quite unlike that of the nineteenth century the contemporary liberal-centered international order provides constraints and opportunities that reduce the likelihood of severe conflict while creating strong imperatives for cooperative problem solving. great-power expansion has become obsolete. nuclear weapons have transformed great-power war into an exercise in national suicide. With all of the great powers possessing nuclear weapons and ample means to rapidly expand their deterrent forces The prospect of such great losses has instilled in the great powers a level of caution and restraint that effectively precludes major revisionist efforts the diffusion of small arms and the near universality of nationalism have severely limited the ability of great powers to conquer and occupy territory density of trade, investment, and production networks across international borders raises even more the costs of war. in the twenty-first century the status quo is much more difficult to overturn. Simple comparisons between China and the U S with regard to aggregate economic size and capability do not reflect the fact that the United States does not stand alone but rather is the head of a coalition of liberal capitalist states whose aggregate assets far exceed those of China revisionist states notably China and Russia are stakeholders in an ensemble of global institutions that make up the status quo, not least the UN Security Council (in which they have permanent seats and veto power Many other global institutions are configured in such a way that rising states can increase their voice only by buying into the institutions The pathway to modernity is not outside and against the status quo but rather inside the liberal international order. The viability of regimes hinges on their ability to sustain economic growth which is crucially dependent on international trade Not only have these states joined the world economy, but their people have increasingly joined the world community citizens of autocratic states are participating in transnational networks. the values of "us versus them" become difficult to generate and sustain. These social and diplomatic processes and developments suggest that there are strong tendencies toward normalization operating here China Europe, India, Japan, the United States Iran and Russia share a common interest in security . The declining utility of war and emerging environmental interdependencies undercut scenarios of international conflict and instability the conditions of the twenty-first century point to the renewed value of international integration and cooperation
the picture of an international system marked by conflict and competition is an exaggeration and ignores powerful countervailing factors the most striking features are globalization institutions and interdependence The overall structure provides constraints that reduce the likelihood of severe conflict while creating strong imperatives for cooperative problem solving. great-power expansion has become obsolete nuclear weapons have transformed great-power war into an exercise in national suicide. With all of the powers possessing nuclear weapons The prospect of losses has instilled level of restraint that effectively precludes major revisionist efforts trade, investment, and production across international borders raises the costs of war revisionist states, are stakeholders in an ensemble of global institutions that make up the status quo institution are configured in such a way that rising states can increase their voice only by buying into the institutions their people have increasingly joined the world community the values of us versus them" become difficult to generate China Europe, India, Japan Iran and Russia share a common interest in security The declining utility of and emerging environmental interdependencies undercut scenarios of international conflict and instability the conditions of the twenty-first century point to the renewed value of cooperation.
It is in combination with these factors that the regime divergence between autocracies and democracies will become increasingly dangerous. If all the states in the world were democracies, there would still be competition, but a world riven by a democratic-autocratic divergence promises to be even more conflictual. There are even signs of the emergence of an "autocrats international" in the Shanghai Cooperation Organization, made up of China, Russia, and the poorer and weaker Central Asian dictatorships. Overall, the autocratic revivalists paint the picture of an international system marked by rising levels of conflict and competition, a picture quite unlike the "end of history" vision of growing convergence and cooperation. This bleak outlook is based on an exaggeration of recent developments and ignores powerful countervailing factors and forces. Indeed, contrary to what trhe revivalists describe, the most striking features of the contemporary international landscape are the intensification of economic globalization, thickening institutions, and shared problems of interdependence. The overall structure of the international system today is quite unlike that of the nineteenth century. Compared to older orders, the contemporary liberal-centered international order provides a set of constraints and opportunities — of pushes and pulls — that reduce the likelihood of severe conflict while creating strong imperatives for cooperative problem solving. Those invoking the nineteenth century as a model for the twenty-first also fail to acknowledge the extent to which war as a path to conflict resolution and great-power expansion has become largely obsolete. Most important, nuclear weapons have transformed great-power war from a routine feature of international politics into an exercise in national suicide. With all of the great powers possessing nuclear weapons and ample means to rapidly expand their deterrent forces, warfare among these states has truly become an option of last resort. The prospect of such great losses has instilled in the great powers a level of caution and restraint that effectively precludes major revisionist efforts. Furthermore, the diffusion of small arms and the near universality of nationalism have severely limited the ability of great powers to conquer and occupy territory inhabited by resisting populations (as Algeria, Vietnam, Afghanistan, and now Iraq have demonstrated). Unlike during the days of empire building in the nineteenth century, states today cannot translate great asymmetries of power into effective territorial control; at most, they can hope for loose hegemonic relationships that require them to give something in return. Also unlike in the nineteenth century, today the density of trade, investment, and production networks across international borders raises even more the costs of war. A Chinese invasion of Taiwan, to take one of the most plausible cases of a future interstate war, would pose for the Chinese communist regime daunting economic costs, both domestic and international. Taken together, these changes in the economy of violence mean that the international system is far more primed for peace than the autocratic revivalists acknowledge. The autocratic revival thesis neglects other key features of the international system as well. In the nineteenth century, rising states faced an international environment in which they could reasonably expect to translate their growing clout into geopolitical changes that would benefit themselves. But in the twenty-first century, the status quo is much more difficult to overturn. Simple comparisons between China and the United States with regard to aggregate economic size and capability do not reflect the fact that the United States does not stand alone but rather is the head of a coalition of liberal capitalist states in Europe and East Asia whose aggregate assets far exceed those of China or even of a coalition of autocratic states. Moreover, potentially revisionist autocratic states, most notably China and Russia, are already substantial players and stakeholders in an ensemble of global institutions that make up the status quo, not least the UN Security Council (in which they have permanent seats and veto power). Many other global institutions, such as the International Monetary Fund and the World Bank, are configured in such a way that rising states can increase their voice only by buying into the institutions. The pathway to modernity for rising states is not outside and against the status quo but rather inside and through the flexible and accommodating institutions of the liberal international order. The fact that these autocracies are capitalist has profound implications for the nature of their international interests that point toward integration and accommodation in the future. The domestic viability of these regimes hinges on their ability to sustain high economic growth rates, which in turn is crucially dependent on international trade and investment; today's autocracies may be illiberal, but they remain fundamentally dependent on a liberal international capitalist system. It is not surprising that China made major domestic changes in order to join the WTO or that Russia is seeking to do so now. The dependence of autocratic capitalist states on foreign trade and investment means that they have a fundamental interest in maintaining an open, rulebased economic system. (Although these autocratic states do pursue bilateral trade and investment deals, particularly in energy and raw materials, this does not obviate their more basic dependence on and commitment to the WTO order.) In the case of China, because of its extensive dependence on industrial exports, the WTO may act as a vital bulwark against protectionist tendencies in importing states. Given their position in this system, which so serves their interests, the autocratic states are unlikely to become champions of an alternative global or regional economic order, let alone spoilers intent on seriously damaging the existing one. The prospects for revisionist behavior on the part of the capitalist autocracies are further reduced by the large and growing social networks across international borders. Not only have these states joined the world economy, but their people — particularly upwardly mobile and educated elites — have increasingly joined the world community. In large and growing numbers, citizens of autocratic capitalist states are participating in a sprawling array of transnational educational, business, and avocational networks. As individuals are socialized into the values and orientations of these networks, stark: "us versus them" cleavages become more difficult to generate and sustain. As the Harvard political scientist Alastair Iain Johnston has argued, China's ruling elite has also been socialized, as its foreign policy establishment has internalized the norms and practices of the international diplomatic community. China, far from cultivating causes for territorial dispute with its neighbors, has instead sought to resolve numerous historically inherited border conflicts, acting like a satisfied status quo state. These social and diplomatic processes and developments suggest that there are strong tendencies toward normalization operating here. Finally, there is an emerging set of global problems stemming from industrialism and economic globalization that will create common interests across states regardless of regime type. Autocratic China is as dependent on imported oil as are democratic Europe, India, Japan, and the United States, suggesting an alignment of interests against petroleum-exporting autocracies, such as Iran and Russia. These states share a common interest in price stability and supply security that could form the basis for a revitalization of the International Energy Agency, the consumer association created during the oil turmoil of the 1970s. The emergence of global warming and climate change as significant problems also suggests possibilities for alignments and cooperative ventures cutting across the autocratic-democratic divide. Like the United States, China is not only a major contributor to greenhouse gas accumulation but also likely to be a major victim of climate-induced desertification and coastal flooding. Its rapid industrialization and consequent pollution means that China, like other developed countries, will increasingly need to import technologies and innovative solutions for environmental management. Resource scarcity and environmental deterioration pose global threats that no state will be able to solve alone, thus placing a further premium on political integration and cooperative institution building. Analogies between the nineteenth century and the twenty-first are based on a severe mischaracterization of the actual conditions of the new era. The declining utility of war, the thickening of international transactions and institutions, and emerging resource and environmental interdependencies together undercut scenarios of international conflict and instability based on autocratic-democratic rivalry and autocratic revisionism. In fact, the conditions of the twenty-first century point to the renewed value of international integration and cooperation.
9,298
<h4><strong>Great power war is obsolete – globalization, nuclear deterrence, and the cooperative liberal order ensure no conflict </h4><p>Ikenberry and Deudney 9 </strong>(Daniel – Professor of Politics and International Affairs at Princeton University, and G. John – professor of political science at Johns Hopkins University, Jan/Feb, “The Myth of the Autocratic Revival,” Foreign Affairs, Vol. 88, Issue 1, p. 8)</p><p>It is in combination with these factors that the regime divergence between autocracies and democracies will become increasingly dangerous. If all the states in the world were democracies, there would still be competition, but a world riven by a democratic-autocratic divergence promises to be even more conflictual. There are even signs of the emergence of an "autocrats international" in the Shanghai Cooperation Organization, made up of China, Russia, and the poorer and weaker Central Asian dictatorships. Overall, the autocratic revivalists paint <u><mark>the picture of an international system marked by</u></mark> rising levels of <u><mark>conflict and competition</u></mark>, a picture quite unlike the "end of history" vision of growing convergence and cooperation. This bleak outlook <u><mark>is</u></mark> based on <u><strong><mark>an exaggeration</u></strong></mark> of recent developments <u><mark>and ignores powerful <strong>countervailing factors</mark> and forces</u></strong>. Indeed, contrary to what trhe revivalists describe<u>, <mark>the most striking features</mark> of the contemporary international landscape <mark>are</u></mark> the intensification of economic <u><strong><mark>globalization</u></strong></mark>, thickening <u><strong><mark>institutions</u></strong></mark>, <u><mark>and</u></mark> <u><strong>shared problems of <mark>interdependence</strong></mark>. <mark>The</u> <u>overall structure</u></mark> of the international system today <u>is quite unlike that of the nineteenth century</u>. Compared to older orders,<u> the contemporary liberal-centered international order <mark>provides</u></mark> a set of <u><mark>constraints</mark> and opportunities</u> — of pushes and pulls — <u><mark>that reduce the likelihood of severe conflict while creating strong imperatives for cooperative problem solving.</u></mark> Those invoking the nineteenth century as a model for the twenty-first also fail to acknowledge the extent to which war as a path to conflict resolution and <u><mark>great-power expansion has become</u></mark> largely <u><strong><mark>obsolete</strong></mark>.</u> Most important, <u><strong><mark>nuclear weapons</u></strong> <u>have transformed great-power war</mark> </u>from a routine feature of international politics <u><mark>into an exercise in <strong>national suicide.</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>With all of the</mark> great <mark>powers possessing nuclear weapons</mark> and ample means to rapidly expand their deterrent forces</u>, warfare among these states has truly become an option of last resort. <u><mark>The prospect of</mark> such great <mark>losses has instilled</mark> in the great powers a <mark>level <strong>of</mark> caution and <mark>restraint</strong> that <strong>effectively precludes major revisionist efforts</u></strong></mark>. Furthermore, <u>the diffusion of small arms and the near universality of nationalism have severely limited the ability of great powers to conquer and occupy territory</u> inhabited by resisting populations (as Algeria, Vietnam, Afghanistan, and now Iraq have demonstrated). Unlike during the days of empire building in the nineteenth century, states today cannot translate great asymmetries of power into effective territorial control; at most, they can hope for loose hegemonic relationships that require them to give something in return. Also unlike in the nineteenth century, today the<u> density of <mark>trade, investment, and production</mark> networks <mark>across international borders <strong>raises</mark> even more <mark>the costs of war</strong></mark>. </u>A Chinese invasion of Taiwan, to take one of the most plausible cases of a future interstate war, would pose for the Chinese communist regime daunting economic costs, both domestic and international. Taken together, these changes in the economy of violence mean that the international system is far more primed for peace than the autocratic revivalists acknowledge. The autocratic revival thesis neglects other key features of the international system as well. In the nineteenth century, rising states faced an international environment in which they could reasonably expect to translate their growing clout into geopolitical changes that would benefit themselves. But <u>in the twenty-first century</u>, <u>the status quo is much more difficult to overturn. Simple comparisons between China and the</u> <u><strong>U</u></strong>nited <u><strong>S</u></strong>tates <u>with regard to aggregate economic size and capability do not reflect the fact that the United States does not stand alone but rather is the head of a coalition of liberal capitalist states</u> in Europe and East Asia <u>whose aggregate assets far exceed those of China</u> or even of a coalition of autocratic states. Moreover, potentially <u><mark>revisionist</u></mark> autocratic <u><mark>states</u>,</mark> most <u>notably China and Russia</u>, <u><mark>are</u></mark> already substantial players and <u><strong><mark>stakeholders</strong> in</u></mark> <u><mark>an</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>ensemble of global institutions</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>that make up the status quo</mark>, not least the UN Security Council (in which they have permanent seats and veto power</u>). <u>Many other global <mark>institution</mark>s</u>, such as the International Monetary Fund and the World Bank, <u><mark>are configured in such a way that rising states can increase their voice <strong>only by buying into the institutions</u></strong></mark>. <u>The pathway to modernity</u> for rising states <u>is not outside and against the status quo but rather inside</u> and through the flexible and accommodating institutions of <u>the liberal international order.</u> The fact that these autocracies are capitalist has profound implications for the nature of their international interests that point toward integration and accommodation in the future. <u>The </u>domestic <u>viability of</u> these <u>regimes hinges on their ability to sustain</u> high <u>economic growth</u> rates, <u>which</u> in turn <u>is crucially dependent on international trade</u> and investment; today's autocracies may be illiberal, but they remain fundamentally dependent on a liberal international capitalist system. It is not surprising that China made major domestic changes in order to join the WTO or that Russia is seeking to do so now. The dependence of autocratic capitalist states on foreign trade and investment means that they have a fundamental interest in maintaining an open, rulebased economic system. (Although these autocratic states do pursue bilateral trade and investment deals, particularly in energy and raw materials, this does not obviate their more basic dependence on and commitment to the WTO order.) In the case of China, because of its extensive dependence on industrial exports, the WTO may act as a vital bulwark against protectionist tendencies in importing states. Given their position in this system, which so serves their interests, the autocratic states are unlikely to become champions of an alternative global or regional economic order, let alone spoilers intent on seriously damaging the existing one. The prospects for revisionist behavior on the part of the capitalist autocracies are further reduced by the large and growing social networks across international borders. <u>Not only have these states joined the world economy, but <mark>their people</u></mark> — particularly upwardly mobile and educated elites — <u><mark>have increasingly joined the world community</u></mark>. In large and growing numbers, <u>citizens of autocratic</u> capitalist <u>states are participating in</u> a sprawling array of <u>transnational </u>educational, business, and avocational <u>networks.</u> As individuals are socialized into <u><mark>the values</u></mark> and orientations <u><mark>of</u></mark> these networks, stark: <u>"<mark>us versus them"</u></mark> cleavages <u><mark>become</u></mark> more <u><strong><mark>difficult to generate</mark> and sustain</strong>.</u> As the Harvard political scientist Alastair Iain Johnston has argued, China's ruling elite has also been socialized, as its foreign policy establishment has internalized the norms and practices of the international diplomatic community. China, far from cultivating causes for territorial dispute with its neighbors, has instead sought to resolve numerous historically inherited border conflicts, acting like a satisfied status quo state. <u>These social and diplomatic processes and developments suggest that there are strong tendencies toward normalization operating here</u>. Finally, there is an emerging set of global problems stemming from industrialism and economic globalization that will create common interests across states regardless of regime type. Autocratic <u><strong><mark>China</u></strong></mark> is as dependent on imported oil as are democratic <u><strong><mark>Europe</strong>, <strong>India</strong>, <strong>Japan</strong></mark>,</u> and <u>the United States</u>, suggesting an alignment of interests against petroleum-exporting autocracies, such as <u><strong><mark>Iran</strong> and <strong>Russia</u></strong></mark>. These states <u><strong><mark>share a common interest</strong> in</u></mark> price stability and supply <u><mark>security</u></mark> that could form the basis for a revitalization of the International Energy Agency, the consumer association created during the oil turmoil of the 1970s. The emergence of global warming and climate change as significant problems also suggests possibilities for alignments and cooperative ventures cutting across the autocratic-democratic divide. Like the United States, China is not only a major contributor to greenhouse gas accumulation but also likely to be a major victim of climate-induced desertification and coastal flooding. Its rapid industrialization and consequent pollution means that China, like other developed countries, will increasingly need to import technologies and innovative solutions for environmental management. Resource scarcity and environmental deterioration pose global threats that no state will be able to solve alone, thus placing a further premium on political integration and cooperative institution building<u>.</u> Analogies between the nineteenth century and the twenty-first are based on a severe mischaracterization of the actual conditions of the new era. <u><strong><mark>The declining utility of</mark> war</u></strong>, the thickening of international transactions and institutions, <u><mark>and emerging</u></mark> resource and <u><mark>environmental interdependencies</u></mark> together <u><strong><mark>undercut scenarios of international conflict and instability</u></strong></mark> based on autocratic-democratic rivalry and autocratic revisionism. In fact, <u><mark>the conditions of the twenty-first century <strong>point to the renewed value</strong> of</mark> international integration and <mark>cooperation</u>.</p></mark>
null
Contention 4 is risk calculus
Contention 3 The Plan solves
18,192
80
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,234
The WTO is dead already – aff can’t solve
Donnan 8/1
Donnan 8/1, Shawn, Financial Times' World Trade Editor, “WTO plunged into crisis as doubts grow over its future,” August 1st, http://www.ft.com/intl/cms/s/0/bac249d0-198c-11e4-9745-00144feabdc0.html
Azevêdo the new head of the W T O announced The WTO is back Azevêdo was speaking too soon. the WTO has been plunged into an existential crisis, after India blocked the centrepiece of the Bali deal Azevêdo is now facing doubts about the future of his organisation There are bound to be efforts to revive negotiations However, the Bali agreement already amounted to a rescue operation and its failure bodes badly for the system. There is significant dysfunction India carried out a threat this week to block a procedural measure to the trade facilitation agreement The Doha round was launched in 2001 and has since repeatedly broken down Putting it back on track would mean tackling much knottier issues such as agricultural subsidies in a new climate of distrust Several members have threatened to enact the trade facilitation agreement as a “plurilateral” deal outside the WTO, a move that would further marginalise the Geneva-based organisation its future looks bleak if the Doha negotiations go back into the coma that has been their dominant state in recent years there are going to be more and more disputes that cannot be resolved [at the WTO
the WTO has been plunged into an existential crisis after India blocked the Bali deal the Bali amounted to a rescue operation its failure bodes badly for the system There is significant dysfunction Doha has repeatedly broken down Putting it back would mean tackling knottier issues such as ag subsidies in a climate of distrust its future looks bleak more and more disputes cannot be resolved [at the WTO
Roberto Azevêdo, the new head of the World Trade Organisation, struck a triumphal tone in Bali last December when he announced that the body’s 159 members had reached the first global agreement in its 18-year history. “The WTO is back!” the visibly sleep-deprived Brazilian told delegates, drawing cheers from all around. Mr Azevêdo, it turns out, was speaking too soon. Seven months later, the WTO has been plunged into an existential crisis, after India’s new government this week blocked the centrepiece of the Bali deal: a seemingly benign arrangement to reduce customs red tape around the world. As a result, Mr Azevêdo is now facing doubts about both the future of his organisation and, more broadly, the liberal vision of a multilateral trading system that has guided the postwar era in the global economy. The WTO, which took over in 1995 from the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade, has grown out of the agreements struck at Bretton Woods in the US in 1944, which sought to keep world leaders from repeating the protectionist mistakes of the 1930s. There are bound to be efforts to revive negotiations. The government in New Delhi has already sought to play down the implications of its stand. Announcing the failure to reach a compromise to members on Thursday, Mr Azevedo urged them to use the August break to ponder the future and return in September with ideas. However, the Bali agreement already amounted to a rescue operation and its failure bodes badly for the system. “There is an element of significant dysfunction that you can’t hide,” said one senior official on Friday. India had originally given its blessing to the deal. But that was before a new government, led by Narendra Modi, came to power two months ago. New Delhi has in recent weeks insisted it wants to renegotiate deadlines set in Bali in order to bring forward negotiations to update the WTO rules that apply to subsidies it gives to farmers as part of a massive government programme to provide cheap food to poor people. In an effort to get what it wanted, India carried out a threat this week to block a procedural measure to the trade facilitation agreement from making the July 31 deadline set in Bali for its implementation. The failure to meet the deadline means the WTO’s members are even less likely to meet another in December to come up with a plan to deliver the rest of the Doha round of negotiations for a global trade deal. The Doha round was launched in 2001 and has since repeatedly broken down as a result of the failure of rich countries, such as the US, and emerging economies, like China and India, to narrow their differences. Putting it back on track would mean tackling much knottier issues such as agricultural subsidies in a new climate of distrust, say diplomats. The irony is that India and other developing countries are likely to suffer most from any collapse of the Doha round, say trade analysts. The US, EU and other key players such as Japan all have big regional trade initiatives under way, and are likely to find moving on much easier than India or smaller and more vulnerable states. Several members have threatened to enact the trade facilitation agreement as a “plurilateral” deal outside the WTO, a move that would further marginalise the Geneva-based organisation. The text to do so has already been drafted and translated into three languages. Up to 60 countries have indicated they are keen to see it implemented. But that is a narrower issue than what happens next at the WTO. Negotiations such as those now under way between the EU and US or between the US and 11 other countries to create a Trans-Pacific Partnership are increasingly focused on more complex, non-tariff barriers to trade. In Brussels and Washington, negotiators are also starting to tackle how to guarantee the free flow of data across borders or ease the way for the global supply chains so vital to modern business. These are discussions that are years beyond what is on the agenda at the WTO. The WTO will not come crashing down tomorrow, says Kimberly Elliott, a trade analyst at the Center for Global Development think-tank in Washington. But its future looks bleak if the Doha negotiations go back into the coma that has been their dominant state in recent years. While many celebrate the WTO’s place as a venue for settling disputes, that function will be eroded if it is not updating its rules to reflect new issues. Without any progress in negotiations, “there are going to be more and more disputes that cannot be resolved [at the WTO],” said Ms Elliott.
4,566
<h4>The WTO is dead already – aff can’t solve</h4><p><strong>Donnan 8/1</strong>, Shawn, Financial Times' World Trade Editor, “WTO plunged into crisis as doubts grow over its future,” August 1st, http://www.ft.com/intl/cms/s/0/bac249d0-198c-11e4-9745-00144feabdc0.html</p><p>Roberto <u>Azevêdo</u>, <u>the new head of the W</u>orld <u>T</u>rade <u>O</u>rganisation, struck a triumphal tone in Bali last December when he <u>announced</u> that the body’s 159 members had reached the first global agreement in its 18-year history. “<u>The WTO is back</u>!” the visibly sleep-deprived Brazilian told delegates, drawing cheers from all around. Mr <u>Azevêdo</u>, it turns out, <u>was speaking too soon.</u> Seven months later, <u><strong><mark>the</mark> <mark>WTO has been plunged into an existential crisis</strong></mark>, <mark>after India</u></mark>’s new government this week <u><mark>blocked the</mark> centrepiece of the <mark>Bali deal</u></mark>: a seemingly benign arrangement to reduce customs red tape around the world. As a result, Mr <u>Azevêdo is now facing doubts about</u> both <u>the future of his organisation</u> and, more broadly, the liberal vision of a multilateral trading system that has guided the postwar era in the global economy. The WTO, which took over in 1995 from the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade, has grown out of the agreements struck at Bretton Woods in the US in 1944, which sought to keep world leaders from repeating the protectionist mistakes of the 1930s. <u>There are bound to be efforts to revive negotiations</u>. The government in New Delhi has already sought to play down the implications of its stand. Announcing the failure to reach a compromise to members on Thursday, Mr Azevedo urged them to use the August break to ponder the future and return in September with ideas. <u>However, <mark>the Bali</mark> agreement already <mark>amounted to a rescue operation</mark> and <mark>its</mark> <mark>failure bodes badly for the system</mark>. </u><strong>“<u></strong><mark>There is</u></mark> an element of <u><strong><mark>significant dysfunction</u></strong></mark> that you can’t hide,” said one senior official on Friday. India had originally given its blessing to the deal. But that was before a new government, led by Narendra Modi, came to power two months ago. New Delhi has in recent weeks insisted it wants to renegotiate deadlines set in Bali in order to bring forward negotiations to update the WTO rules that apply to subsidies it gives to farmers as part of a massive government programme to provide cheap food to poor people. In an effort to get what it wanted, <u>India carried out a threat this week to block a procedural measure to the trade facilitation agreement</u> from making the July 31 deadline set in Bali for its implementation. The failure to meet the deadline means the WTO’s members are even less likely to meet another in December to come up with a plan to deliver the rest of the Doha round of negotiations for a global trade deal. <u>The <mark>Doha</mark> round was launched in 2001 and <mark>has</mark> since <mark>repeatedly broken down</u></mark> as a result of the failure of rich countries, such as the US, and emerging economies, like China and India, to narrow their differences. <u><mark>Putting it back</mark> on track <mark>would mean tackling</mark> much <mark>knottier issues such as ag</mark>ricultural <mark>subsidies</mark> <mark>in a</mark> new <mark>climate of distrust</u><strong></mark>,</strong> say diplomats. The irony is that India and other developing countries are likely to suffer most from any collapse of the Doha round, say trade analysts. The US, EU and other key players such as Japan all have big regional trade initiatives under way, and are likely to find moving on much easier than India or smaller and more vulnerable states. <u>Several members have threatened to enact the trade facilitation agreement as a “plurilateral” deal outside the WTO, a move that would further marginalise the Geneva-based organisation</u>. The text to do so has already been drafted and translated into three languages. Up to 60 countries have indicated they are keen to see it implemented. But that is a narrower issue than what happens next at the WTO. Negotiations such as those now under way between the EU and US or between the US and 11 other countries to create a Trans-Pacific Partnership are increasingly focused on more complex, non-tariff barriers to trade. In Brussels and Washington, negotiators are also starting to tackle how to guarantee the free flow of data across borders or ease the way for the global supply chains so vital to modern business. These are discussions that are years beyond what is on the agenda at the WTO. The WTO will not come crashing down tomorrow, says Kimberly Elliott, a trade analyst at the Center for Global Development think-tank in Washington. But <u><strong><mark>its future looks bleak</strong></mark> if the Doha negotiations go back into the coma that has been their dominant state in recent years</u>. While many celebrate the WTO’s place as a venue for settling disputes, that function will be eroded if it is not updating its rules to reflect new issues. Without any progress in negotiations, “<u>there are going to be <mark>more and more disputes</mark> that <mark>cannot</mark> <mark>be resolved [at the WTO</u></mark>],” said Ms Elliott.</p>
WTO
Meta
AT: Inevitable
430,392
9
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,235
Crowd-out studies are based on Titmuss, who’s wrong
Economist 11
Economist 11 The Economist Feb 16th 2011 Blood, not money http://www.economist.com/blogs/blighty/2011/02/volunteering_and_profiteering
In a classic 1970 study called "The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy" Titmuss compared the voluntary British system with the American one in which payments were then widely made. Titmuss reckoned such a market was inefficient and wasteful, that it created shortages and surpluses, he was wrong, and such arguments have since been widely discredited
In a classic study Titmuss compared the voluntary system with the American one in which payments were made. Titmuss reckoned such created shortages and surpluses, he was wrong, and such arguments have since been widely discredited
Blood donors are also unpaid, in Britain and elsewhere. A debate over whether or not they should be compensated for their efforts has raged for at least four decades. In a classic 1970 study called "The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy" Richard Titmuss compared the voluntary British system favourably with the American one in which payments were then widely made. Titmuss reckoned such a market was inefficient and wasteful, that it created shortages and surpluses, and led eventually to a contaminated product. Although he was wrong, and such arguments have since been widely discredited, Americans mostly no longer receive payment for giving blood. Too many people in poor health lied about their medical histories in order to make a few bucks, endangering those who were to receive the blood. As the World Health Organisation notes, people who give blood voluntarily and for altruistic reasons have a lower prevalence of HIV, hepatitis viruses and other blood-borne infections than do those who seek monetary reward. Presumably that is because being rich is a great protection against disease.
1,117
<h4>Crowd-out studies are based on Titmuss, who’s wrong</h4><p><strong>Economist 11</strong> The Economist Feb 16th 2011 Blood, not money</p><p>http://www.economist.com/blogs/blighty/2011/02/volunteering_and_profiteering</p><p>Blood donors are also unpaid, in Britain and elsewhere. A debate over whether or not they should be compensated for their efforts has raged for at least four decades. <u><mark>In a classic </mark>1970 <mark>study </mark>called "The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy"</u> Richard <u><mark>Titmuss compared the voluntary </mark>British</u> <u><mark>system</u></mark> favourably <u><mark>with the American one in which payments were </mark>then widely <mark>made. Titmuss reckoned such </mark>a market was inefficient and wasteful, that it <mark>created shortages and surpluses,</u></mark> and led eventually to a contaminated product. Although <u><mark>he was wrong, and such arguments have since been widely discredited</u></mark>, Americans mostly no longer receive payment for giving blood. Too many people in poor health lied about their medical histories in order to make a few bucks, endangering those who were to receive the blood. As the World Health Organisation notes, people who give blood voluntarily and for altruistic reasons have a lower prevalence of HIV, hepatitis viruses and other blood-borne infections than do those who seek monetary reward. Presumably that is because being rich is a great protection against disease.</p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Organ sales will save lives
430,253
7
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,236
Interpretation- both “United States” and “legalize” have no inherent meaning in the plan text- the aff needs to specify beyond that- policy specifics are articulations of motives- refusing to engage the details guarantees cooption and turns solvency
Caulkins et al 2015
Caulkins et al 2015 (Jonathan P. Caulkins, Beau Kilmer, Mark A. R. Kleiman, Robert J. MacCoun, Gregory Midgette, Pat Oglesby, Rosalie Liccardo Pacula, and Peter H. Reuter, if you haven’t seen the quals for most of these people at this point in the year, I’m sure we could take a moment to look through literally any file on this section of the topic and tell you about at least Caulkins, Kleiman and Reuter, Options and Issues Regarding Marijuana Legalization, http://www.rand.org/content/dam/rand/pubs/perspectives/PE100/PE149/RAND_PE149.pdf)
Legalization is not simply a binary choice between making production legal and continuing prohibitions Legalization encompasses a wide range of possible regimes, distinguished along multiple dimensions Who would be allowed to supply Would marijuana be taxed How would marijuana be regulated These choices could have profound consequences for the outcomes of legalization Each of these strategies about whom the law would allow to produce and distribute marijuana is really itself a broad category of options encompassing considerable scope for fine-tuning a bad implementation of a good strategy might perform less well than a wise implementation of an inferior one picking a strategy is the beginning of a discussion and design process than an answer to the question of what should be done important consequences flow from selecting who may produce and supply marijuana it is very important to systematically consider the potential effects of each strategy the marketing and lobbying muscle of a for-profit industry is likely to influence the future trajectory of marijuana policy, whereas other options would allow legislatures and regulatory agencies to act with more regard for the public interest.
Legalization is not a binary choice Who would be allowed to supply Would marijuana be taxed How would marijuana be regulated These choices have profound consequences for the outcomes of legalization a bad implementation of a good strategy might perform less well than a wise implementation of an inferior one picking a strategy is the beginning of a gn process than an answer to the question of what should be done it is very important to systematically consider the potential effects of each strategy the marketing and lobbying muscle of a for-profit industry is likely to influence the future trajectory of marijuana
Legalization is not simply a binary choice between, on the one hand, making the production, sale, and possession of the drug legal and, on the other, continuing existing prohibitions. Legalization encompasses a wide range of possible regimes, distinguished along multiple dimensions. Here we highlight three key decisions: Who would be allowed to supply legal marijuana? Would legal marijuana be taxed and, if so, how? How would legal marijuana be regulated? These choices could have profound consequences for the outcomes of legalization in terms of health and social well-being, as well as for job creation and government revenue. Who Would Be Allowed to Supply Legal Marijuana? Although Colorado and Washington have adopted the for-profit commercial (or so-called alcohol) model and Alaska and Oregon are in the process of doing the same, that strategy is just one of a dozen options available to jurisdictions seeking to change their marijuana supply laws. The figure lists 12 supply alternatives to status quo prohibition, breaking them down into three groups: • the two options most commonly discussed in the United States – Retain prohibition but decrease sanctions. – Implement an alcohol-style commercial model. • eight options that find a middle ground between those commonly discussed – Allow adults to grow their own. – Allow distribution only within small co-ops or buyers’ clubs. – Permit locally controlled retail sales without legalizing commercial production (the Dutch coffee-shop model). – Have the government operate the supply chain (government monopoly). – Have a public authority operate the supply chain. – Permit only nonprofit organizations to sell. – Permit only for-benefit companies to sell. – Have very few closely monitored for-profit licensees. • two extreme options – Increase sanctions. – Repeal the state’s prohibition without creating any new, product-specific regulations. Twelve Supply Alternatives to Status Quo Prohibition RAND PE149-1 Extreme options Commonly discussed options Middle-ground options Allow adults to grow their own Retail sales only (Dutch model) Public authority (near monopoly) For-benet companies Prohibit and increase sanctions Standard commercial model Communal own-grow and distribution Government operates the supply chain Nonprofit organizations Very few monitored for-prot licensees Prohibit and decrease sanctions Repeal-only of state prohibition Legalization encompasses a wide range of possible regimes, distinguished along multiple dimensions.5 The key point made by identifying this range of approaches is that the debate in the United States has focused largely on just two options that are near the ends of the spectrum. Policymakers have largely ignored many available intermediate options. Indeed, commercial legalization is a high-stakes choice clouded by enormous uncertainty. Until 2012, no modern jurisdiction had implemented it—not even the Netherlands, which tolerates small retail sales, not wholesale production. Commercial legalization also conflates two distinct concepts: the size or scale of the organizations that are allowed to produce and who owns them, which determines what objectives shape those organizations’ behavior. Colorado and Washington State have decided not only to allow large, professionally operated suppliers that can realize economies of scale and promote a diverse range of products but also that those suppliers can be private companies whose goal is profit maximization. There is concern that profit-maximizing marijuana companies will target heavy users. Since 80 percent of marijuana consumption is by daily or near-daily users, roughly 80 percent of marijuana companies’ profits would come from marketing to such heavy users, about half of whom currently meet clinical criteria for having substance-use disorders (either with marijuana itself or with another substance, such as alcohol). Thus, like the alcohol industry, the private marijuana industry will likely seek to serve and develop a market of heavy users. Thus, it is important to note that jurisdictions considering large-scale marijuana production have other options to consider: (1) government monopoly, (2) public authorities, (3) nonprofit organizations, and (4) socially responsible businesses (e.g., B-Corps). Indeed, if a jurisdiction decides to create a new industry, they need to decide whether they want that industry to be exclusively focused on maximizing profits. All of the large-scale production options would create the potential for even a small state to raise tens of millions of dollars annually by taxing the consumption of its residents in one way or another. If realized, that would more than offset regulatory burdens that are likely to be in the low to mid single-digit millions of dollars in a small state. (Although nonprofits do not pay income taxes, their customers would pay sales and excise taxes, just as customers of for-profit businesses would. And although government stores do not pay taxes per se, their profits accrue to the state treasury.) But with any of these retail options, the twin elephants in the room—particularly for states located in densely populated regions—would be demand from out-of-state users and competition from suppliers in nearby states that legalize but impose lower taxes or lower regulatory burdens. For example, nearly 40 times as many current marijuana users live within 200 miles of Vermont’s borders as live in Vermont. So if Vermont legalized before any other states in the Northeast, marijuana tourism and illicit exports could be substantial and could, in theory, put Vermont’s annual tax revenues in the hundreds of millions. However, if the federal government intervened to stop such cross-border traffic or if another state in the Northeast decided to Debate in the United States has focused largely on just two options that are near the ends of the spectrum. Policymakers have largely ignored many available intermediate options.6 legalize marijuana and set lower tax rates, these potential revenues might not materialize. Indeed, because legal marijuana can flow across borders in either direction, Vermont’s prospects of deriving considerable tax revenue even from its own residents would become much less promising if one of its immediate neighbors were to legalize with low taxes. One implication of this is that, although, in theory, there may be benefit in allowing each state to pursue its own policies and so discover through experimentation which policies work best, in reality, cross-border flows of users and product mean that one state’s actions could affect levels of use and tax collections in other states.4 By comparison, options that do not involve creating large-scale producers are much less risky because they are less likely to incentivize consumption increases, particularly among the most-frequent users. The simplest step is full decriminalization, meaning reducing sanctions for simple possession to noncriminal charges akin to traffic tickets. Criminal offenses for marijuana in Vermont fell more than 80 percent after it decriminalized. When we inquired in September 2014, just three people in the entire state were behind bars solely for marijuana offenses; only eight were admitted during the entire fiscal year. The cost of enforcing marijuana prohibition is now on the order of $1 million per year in Vermont. Allowing individual users to grow their own product at home and give it away, as was recently authorized by the voters in Washington, D.C., creates an option for legal supply with few downside risks if the rules are written tightly to prevent exploitation by black-market producers; for example, the number of plants that any one person can grow is usually limited. Other jurisdictions, including Alaska, have allowed home production for some time, and the effects do not appear to be dramatic. That is, there is no clear evidence of large increases in use but also no evidence of reductions in black-market activity; illegal marijuana is so ubiquitous that relatively few users bother growing their own. The co-op model, as with Spanish cannabis clubs, allows modest numbers of people to pool their own-grow rights and share or sell at cost to other members of the club. Those economies of scale make co-ops a potential threat to the black market without creating the risks of commercialization. Further, some argue that cannabis clubs stay (just barely) within international treaty obligations because sales are priced only to recoup growing costs, not to make a profit. A state could follow the Dutch coffee-shop model and allow retail sales only. A fixed number of outlets could be licensed to retail marijuana while production and trafficking are still prohibited. This would allow access and taxation but avoid promotion by producers. Even if a state were to decide to allow large-scale production and distribution, it has distinct options. A state monopoly of the whole production and distribution chain would prevent diversion to the black market; it could set the price it thinks best serves the public interest and ensure no promotion. The state monopoly, however, risks provoking the federal government. For that and other reasons, a state might prefer to set up a public authority—a single authorized seller. The state would appoint members of the public Cross-border flows of users and product mean that one state’s actions could affect levels of use and tax collections in other states.7 authority and set policy to, for instance, control diversion, control interactions with consumers, restrict sales to particular types of products, avoid advertising and product innovation, and prevent a price collapse. Yet another option is to license only nonprofit enterprises. Because they are not profit maximizers, they are less likely than private enterprise to promote the drug. Requiring that each nonprofit have representatives of health-promotion and childwelfare groups in its leadership would ensure even better alignment with the public interest. Yet other models include restricting the market to for-benefit companies or to a very limited set of for-profit corporate licensees. Each of these strategies about whom the law would allow to produce and distribute marijuana is really itself a broad category of options encompassing considerable scope for fine-tuning. Moreover, a bad implementation of a good strategy might perform less well than a wise implementation of an inferior one. Therefore, picking a strategy is more the beginning of a discussion and design process than an answer to the question of what should be done. Nevertheless, important consequences flow from selecting who may produce and supply marijuana. So it is very important to systematically consider the potential effects of each strategy. In particular, the marketing and lobbying muscle of a for-profit industry is likely to influence the future trajectory of marijuana policy, whereas other options would allow legislatures and regulatory agencies to act with more regard for the public interest.
11,078
<h4>Interpretation- both “United States” and “legalize” have no inherent meaning in the plan text- the aff needs to specify beyond that- policy specifics are articulations of motives- refusing to engage the details guarantees cooption and turns solvency</h4><p><strong>Caulkins et al 2015</strong> <u>(Jonathan P. Caulkins, Beau Kilmer, Mark A. R. Kleiman, Robert J. MacCoun, Gregory Midgette, Pat Oglesby, Rosalie Liccardo Pacula, and Peter H. Reuter, if you haven’t seen the quals for most of these people at this point in the year, I’m sure we could take a moment to look through literally any file on this section of the topic and tell you about at least Caulkins, Kleiman and Reuter, Options and Issues Regarding Marijuana Legalization, http://www.rand.org/content/dam/rand/pubs/perspectives/PE100/PE149/RAND_PE149.pdf)</p><p><mark>Legalization is not</mark> simply <mark>a binary choice</mark> between</u>, on the one hand, <u>making</u> the <u>production</u>, sale, and possession of the drug <u>legal</u> <u>and</u>, on the other, <u>continuing</u> existing <u>prohibitions</u>. <u>Legalization</u> <u>encompasses a wide range of possible regimes, distinguished along multiple dimensions</u>. Here we highlight three key decisions: <u><mark>Who would be allowed to supply</u></mark> legal marijuana? <u><mark>Would</u></mark> legal <u><mark>marijuana</u> <u>be taxed</u></mark> and, if so, how? <u><mark>How</mark> <mark>would</u></mark> legal <u><mark>marijuana be regulated</u></mark>? <u><strong><mark>These choices </mark>could <mark>have profound consequences for the outcomes of legalization</u></strong></mark> in terms of health and social well-being, as well as for job creation and government revenue. Who Would Be Allowed to Supply Legal Marijuana? Although Colorado and Washington have adopted the for-profit commercial (or so-called alcohol) model and Alaska and Oregon are in the process of doing the same, that strategy is just one of a dozen options available to jurisdictions seeking to change their marijuana supply laws. The figure lists 12 supply alternatives to status quo prohibition, breaking them down into three groups: • the two options most commonly discussed in the United States – Retain prohibition but decrease sanctions. – Implement an alcohol-style commercial model. • eight options that find a middle ground between those commonly discussed – Allow adults to grow their own. – Allow distribution only within small co-ops or buyers’ clubs. – Permit locally controlled retail sales without legalizing commercial production (the Dutch coffee-shop model). – Have the government operate the supply chain (government monopoly). – Have a public authority operate the supply chain. – Permit only nonprofit organizations to sell. – Permit only for-benefit companies to sell. – Have very few closely monitored for-profit licensees. • two extreme options – Increase sanctions. – Repeal the state’s prohibition without creating any new, product-specific regulations. Twelve Supply Alternatives to Status Quo Prohibition RAND PE149-1 Extreme options Commonly discussed options Middle-ground options Allow adults to grow their own Retail sales only (Dutch model) Public authority (near monopoly) For-benet companies Prohibit and increase sanctions Standard commercial model Communal own-grow and distribution Government operates the supply chain Nonprofit organizations Very few monitored for-prot licensees Prohibit and decrease sanctions Repeal-only of state prohibition Legalization encompasses a wide range of possible regimes, distinguished along multiple dimensions.5 The key point made by identifying this range of approaches is that the debate in the United States has focused largely on just two options that are near the ends of the spectrum. Policymakers have largely ignored many available intermediate options. Indeed, commercial legalization is a high-stakes choice clouded by enormous uncertainty. Until 2012, no modern jurisdiction had implemented it—not even the Netherlands, which tolerates small retail sales, not wholesale production. Commercial legalization also conflates two distinct concepts: the size or scale of the organizations that are allowed to produce and who owns them, which determines what objectives shape those organizations’ behavior. Colorado and Washington State have decided not only to allow large, professionally operated suppliers that can realize economies of scale and promote a diverse range of products but also that those suppliers can be private companies whose goal is profit maximization. There is concern that profit-maximizing marijuana companies will target heavy users. Since 80 percent of marijuana consumption is by daily or near-daily users, roughly 80 percent of marijuana companies’ profits would come from marketing to such heavy users, about half of whom currently meet clinical criteria for having substance-use disorders (either with marijuana itself or with another substance, such as alcohol). Thus, like the alcohol industry, the private marijuana industry will likely seek to serve and develop a market of heavy users. Thus, it is important to note that jurisdictions considering large-scale marijuana production have other options to consider: (1) government monopoly, (2) public authorities, (3) nonprofit organizations, and (4) socially responsible businesses (e.g., B-Corps). Indeed, if a jurisdiction decides to create a new industry, they need to decide whether they want that industry to be exclusively focused on maximizing profits. All of the large-scale production options would create the potential for even a small state to raise tens of millions of dollars annually by taxing the consumption of its residents in one way or another. If realized, that would more than offset regulatory burdens that are likely to be in the low to mid single-digit millions of dollars in a small state. (Although nonprofits do not pay income taxes, their customers would pay sales and excise taxes, just as customers of for-profit businesses would. And although government stores do not pay taxes per se, their profits accrue to the state treasury.) But with any of these retail options, the twin elephants in the room—particularly for states located in densely populated regions—would be demand from out-of-state users and competition from suppliers in nearby states that legalize but impose lower taxes or lower regulatory burdens. For example, nearly 40 times as many current marijuana users live within 200 miles of Vermont’s borders as live in Vermont. So if Vermont legalized before any other states in the Northeast, marijuana tourism and illicit exports could be substantial and could, in theory, put Vermont’s annual tax revenues in the hundreds of millions. However, if the federal government intervened to stop such cross-border traffic or if another state in the Northeast decided to Debate in the United States has focused largely on just two options that are near the ends of the spectrum. Policymakers have largely ignored many available intermediate options.6 legalize marijuana and set lower tax rates, these potential revenues might not materialize. Indeed, because legal marijuana can flow across borders in either direction, Vermont’s prospects of deriving considerable tax revenue even from its own residents would become much less promising if one of its immediate neighbors were to legalize with low taxes. One implication of this is that, although, in theory, there may be benefit in allowing each state to pursue its own policies and so discover through experimentation which policies work best, in reality, cross-border flows of users and product mean that one state’s actions could affect levels of use and tax collections in other states.4 By comparison, options that do not involve creating large-scale producers are much less risky because they are less likely to incentivize consumption increases, particularly among the most-frequent users. The simplest step is full decriminalization, meaning reducing sanctions for simple possession to noncriminal charges akin to traffic tickets. Criminal offenses for marijuana in Vermont fell more than 80 percent after it decriminalized. When we inquired in September 2014, just three people in the entire state were behind bars solely for marijuana offenses; only eight were admitted during the entire fiscal year. The cost of enforcing marijuana prohibition is now on the order of $1 million per year in Vermont. Allowing individual users to grow their own product at home and give it away, as was recently authorized by the voters in Washington, D.C., creates an option for legal supply with few downside risks if the rules are written tightly to prevent exploitation by black-market producers; for example, the number of plants that any one person can grow is usually limited. Other jurisdictions, including Alaska, have allowed home production for some time, and the effects do not appear to be dramatic. That is, there is no clear evidence of large increases in use but also no evidence of reductions in black-market activity; illegal marijuana is so ubiquitous that relatively few users bother growing their own. The co-op model, as with Spanish cannabis clubs, allows modest numbers of people to pool their own-grow rights and share or sell at cost to other members of the club. Those economies of scale make co-ops a potential threat to the black market without creating the risks of commercialization. Further, some argue that cannabis clubs stay (just barely) within international treaty obligations because sales are priced only to recoup growing costs, not to make a profit. A state could follow the Dutch coffee-shop model and allow retail sales only. A fixed number of outlets could be licensed to retail marijuana while production and trafficking are still prohibited. This would allow access and taxation but avoid promotion by producers. Even if a state were to decide to allow large-scale production and distribution, it has distinct options. A state monopoly of the whole production and distribution chain would prevent diversion to the black market; it could set the price it thinks best serves the public interest and ensure no promotion. The state monopoly, however, risks provoking the federal government. For that and other reasons, a state might prefer to set up a public authority—a single authorized seller. The state would appoint members of the public Cross-border flows of users and product mean that one state’s actions could affect levels of use and tax collections in other states.7 authority and set policy to, for instance, control diversion, control interactions with consumers, restrict sales to particular types of products, avoid advertising and product innovation, and prevent a price collapse. Yet another option is to license only nonprofit enterprises. Because they are not profit maximizers, they are less likely than private enterprise to promote the drug. Requiring that each nonprofit have representatives of health-promotion and childwelfare groups in its leadership would ensure even better alignment with the public interest. Yet other models include restricting the market to for-benefit companies or to a very limited set of for-profit corporate licensees. <u>Each of these strategies about whom the law would allow to produce and distribute marijuana is really itself a broad category of options encompassing considerable scope for fine-tuning</u>. Moreover, <u><strong><mark>a bad implementation of a good strategy might perform less well than a wise implementation of an inferior one</u></strong></mark>. Therefore, <u><mark>picking a strategy is</u></mark> more <u><strong><mark>the beginning of a</mark> discussion and desi<mark>gn process</u></strong> <u>than an answer to the question of what should be done</u></mark>. Nevertheless, <u>important consequences flow from selecting who may produce and supply marijuana</u>. So <u><strong><mark>it is very important to systematically consider the potential effects of each strategy</u></strong></mark>. In particular, <u><mark>the marketing and lobbying muscle of a for-profit industry is likely to influence the future trajectory of marijuana</mark> policy, whereas other options would allow legislatures and regulatory agencies to act with more regard for the public interest.</p></u>
null
null
1NC
430,616
1
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,237
Obama can sustain a veto of sanctions now but it’s close- PC’s key- new sanctions cause war with Iran
CNN 1/9
CNN 1/9/2015 (New Congress, new nuclear showdown over Iran, http://www.cnn.com/2015/01/09/politics/iran-sanctions-fight-republican-congress/)
Iranian and American negotiators will be eying another showdown in Washington GOP lawmakers are poised to push a bill authorizing additional sanctions the majority doesn't guarantee that Republicans can muster the 67 votes they need and the fight is already underway for the votes that could fill the gap With fewer than two months until agreement deadline, and expecting the White House to start knocking on swing senators' doors supporters know the clock is ticking the ticking is more like a time bomb as a sanctions bill will torpedo negotiations and set the U.S. on a path to war with Iran Kirk expects a high-profile challenge from the White House four Democrats rejected the idea of moving forward amid negotiations after the White House made its push on Capitol Hill to keep the measure from a floor vote if Kirk, Menendez and their allies can pressure those four Democrats into signing on, they will need to pull three more Senate Democrats who didn't cosponsor the bill last year to secure the 15 needed to override a veto A coalition of dove organizations is already putting the gears in motion for what they expect to be the toughest battle yet on this issue
null
Iranian and American negotiators preparing to square off in Geneva next week over Iran's nuclear ambitions will also be eying another showdown brewing in Washington. One year after a Republican-led coalition in the Senate came up just short of a deal, GOP lawmakers are poised to wield their new power in the Senate to push a bill authorizing additional sanctions against Iran. But the new 54-member majority doesn't guarantee that Republicans can muster the 67 votes they need to override a presidential veto, and the fight is already underway for the votes that could fill the gap. With fewer than two months until diplomats' March 1 framework agreement deadline, and expecting the White House to start knocking on swing senators' doors, supporters know the clock is ticking to pass a sanctions bill they say will ratchet up pressure on Iran. But for opponents of additional sanctions, the ticking is more like a time bomb as a sanctions bill will torpedo negotiations and set the U.S. on a path to war with Iran, they claim. For Sen. Mark Kirk, the Republican half of the Kirk-Menendez sanctions bill he has pushed for the last three years, the sooner a sanctions bill hits the Senate floor, the better -- both politically and policy-wise. "If the Senate was allowed to vote tomorrow, I would be able to get two-thirds," Kirk said Sunday in a phone interview. "Now is the time to put pressure on Iran especially with oil prices so low. We are uniquely advantaged at this time to shut down this nuclear program." Sen. Lindsey Graham (R-South Carolina), another major proponent of the legislation, told CNN last month the Kirk-Menendez bill "will come up for a vote in January," a pledge he made the same day to Israeli Prime Minister Benjamin Netanyahu in a meeting in Jerusalem. Kirk said he backed that timing but insisted that it depends on Senate Majority Leader Mitch McConnell. A McConnell spokesman called the legislation "a priority," but said there isn't yet a schedule for a sanctions bill. Republicans have been clamoring for additional sanctions on Iran, but with control of Congress in their hands, Republican lawmakers will also have to own the consequences of sanctions legislation -- which the President, State Department and Iranian officials have warned could derail negotiations. "We have long believed that Congress should not consider any new sanctions while negotiations are underway, in order to give our negotiators the time and space they need to fully test the current diplomatic opportunity. New sanctions threaten the diplomatic process currently underway," a senior administration official told CNN. The Kirk-Menendez bill that died in the Senate last year would reimpose sanctions on Iran if Obama couldn't certify that Iran doesn't finance terror groups that have attacked Americans and would keep Iran from maintaining low-level nuclear enrichment in a final deal, just a few terms that are much stricter than the current framework for negotiations between Iran and the P5+1 world powers. Those congressional provisions are "poison pills," according to Dylan Williams, head of government affairs at J Street, a group that bills itself as pro-Israel. It lobbied heavily on the issue last year and is ramping up for another forceful push. "All of these things are poison pills, far from the clean sanctions, just-if-things-go-wrong idea," Williams said. "We know that many if not most of the people pushing for legislation don't want diplomacy to work." Kirk has already been working with Sen. Bob Menendez, of New Jersey, his Democratic partner on the bill, to rework some of its language -- changes that could potentially draw more Democratic support. The pair are still working on final language for the bill, which drew 59 cosponsors last year, though Kirk said he is working to stave off as many changes as possible -- "The more changes, the worse," he said. The Illinois Republican expects a high-profile challenge from the White House and its allies, but he will be getting his own backup from some Capitol Hill heavyweights: the American-Israel Public Affairs Committee, or AIPAC, which typically spends more than $2.5 million a year on lobbying, according to the Center for Responsive Politics. "I think they're pretty damned strong. This would be the No. 1 thing for them," Kirk said of AIPAC. Intense lobbying from AIPAC could help the sanctions supporters win back the four Democrats who joined 13 others in cosponsoring the sanctions bill last year, but later backtracked their support. Sens. Kirsten Gillibrand of New York, Joe Manchin of West Virginia, Richard Blumenthal of Connecticut and Chris Coons of Delaware rejected the idea of moving forward amid negotiations after the White House and allies made its push on Capitol Hill to keep the measure from a floor vote. "I did not sign it with the intention that it would ever be voted upon or used upon while we were negotiating," Manchin said on MSNBC after Obama talked about Iran in his State of the Union address. "I signed it because I wanted to make sure the president had a hammer if he needed it and showed them how determined we were to do it and use it if we had to." After talks failed to materialize into an agreement by the November 2014 deadline, some Democrats have started to lose patience with the stop-and-stall pace of negotiations with Iran and are facing pressure from groups like AIPAC to support a sanctions bill, though the White House insists the negotiations have yielded tangible results: rolling back Iran's nuclear program during negotiations. But even if Kirk, Menendez and their allies can pressure those four Democrats into signing on, they will need to pull three more Senate Democrats who didn't cosponsor the bill last year to secure the 15 Democrats needed to override a presidential veto. And they won't just be targeted by AIPAC. A coalition of dove organizations is already putting the gears in motion for what they expect to be the toughest battle yet on this issue, and while they're clear-eyed about the uphill climb they face, they dismiss the overconfident stride of pro-sanctions leaders. These groups will look to paint any new sanctions as a step onto the warpath with Iran and show wary Democrats that they have the grassroots backing to stave off attacks from groups like AIPAC. More than 400 faith leaders and activists traveled to D.C. in late November to lobby Congress against the sanctions in a day of action organized by the Friends Committee on National Legislation, a Quaker-founded organization, and the group plans to drive its 50,000 supporters to flood Congress with calls and letters in the weeks ahead. "The real trick that we have to do is really to make that opposition -- both in the public and that opposition on the Hill -- to really make it become public and to amplify those voices," said Kate Gould, the group's lead lobbyist on the issue. "Because right now you hear from, it's Lindsey Graham and (Marco) Rubio, who are very confident in their prognosis and have made it sound like it's inevitable that these sanctions will pass with a veto-proof majority."
7,128
<h4>Obama can sustain a veto of sanctions now but it’s close- PC’s key- new sanctions cause war with Iran</h4><p><strong>CNN 1/9</strong>/2015 (New Congress, new nuclear showdown over Iran, http://www.cnn.com/2015/01/09/politics/iran-sanctions-fight-republican-congress/)</p><p><u>Iranian and American negotiators</u> preparing to square off in Geneva next week over Iran's nuclear ambitions <u>will</u> also <u>be eying</u> <u>another showdown</u> brewing <u>in Washington</u>. One year after a Republican-led coalition in the Senate came up just short of a deal, <u>GOP lawmakers are poised to</u> wield their new power in the Senate to <u>push a bill authorizing additional sanctions </u>against Iran. But <u>the</u> new 54-member <u>majority doesn't guarantee that Republicans can muster the 67 votes they need</u> to override a presidential veto, <u>and the <strong>fight is already underway</strong> for the votes that could fill the gap</u>. <u>With fewer than two months until</u> diplomats' March 1 framework <u>agreement deadline, and expecting the <strong>White House to start knocking on swing senators' doors</u></strong>, <u>supporters know the clock is ticking</u> to pass a sanctions bill they say will ratchet up pressure on Iran. But for opponents of additional sanctions, <u><strong>the ticking is more like a time bomb as a sanctions bill will torpedo negotiations and set the U.S. on a path to war with Iran</u></strong>, they claim. For Sen. Mark Kirk, the Republican half of the Kirk-Menendez sanctions bill he has pushed for the last three years, the sooner a sanctions bill hits the Senate floor, the better -- both politically and policy-wise. "If the Senate was allowed to vote tomorrow, I would be able to get two-thirds," Kirk said Sunday in a phone interview. "Now is the time to put pressure on Iran especially with oil prices so low. We are uniquely advantaged at this time to shut down this nuclear program." Sen. Lindsey Graham (R-South Carolina), another major proponent of the legislation, told CNN last month the Kirk-Menendez bill "will come up for a vote in January," a pledge he made the same day to Israeli Prime Minister Benjamin Netanyahu in a meeting in Jerusalem. Kirk said he backed that timing but insisted that it depends on Senate Majority Leader Mitch McConnell. A McConnell spokesman called the legislation "a priority," but said there isn't yet a schedule for a sanctions bill. Republicans have been clamoring for additional sanctions on Iran, but with control of Congress in their hands, Republican lawmakers will also have to own the consequences of sanctions legislation -- which the President, State Department and Iranian officials have warned could derail negotiations. "We have long believed that Congress should not consider any new sanctions while negotiations are underway, in order to give our negotiators the time and space they need to fully test the current diplomatic opportunity. New sanctions threaten the diplomatic process currently underway," a senior administration official told CNN. The Kirk-Menendez bill that died in the Senate last year would reimpose sanctions on Iran if Obama couldn't certify that Iran doesn't finance terror groups that have attacked Americans and would keep Iran from maintaining low-level nuclear enrichment in a final deal, just a few terms that are much stricter than the current framework for negotiations between Iran and the P5+1 world powers. Those congressional provisions are "poison pills," according to Dylan Williams, head of government affairs at J Street, a group that bills itself as pro-Israel. It lobbied heavily on the issue last year and is ramping up for another forceful push. "All of these things are poison pills, far from the clean sanctions, just-if-things-go-wrong idea," Williams said. "We know that many if not most of the people pushing for legislation don't want diplomacy to work." Kirk has already been working with Sen. Bob Menendez, of New Jersey, his Democratic partner on the bill, to rework some of its language -- changes that could potentially draw more Democratic support. The pair are still working on final language for the bill, which drew 59 cosponsors last year, though <u>Kirk</u> said he is working to stave off as many changes as possible -- "The more changes, the worse," he said. The Illinois Republican <u>expects a <strong>high-profile challenge from the White House</u></strong> and its allies, but he will be getting his own backup from some Capitol Hill heavyweights: the American-Israel Public Affairs Committee, or AIPAC, which typically spends more than $2.5 million a year on lobbying, according to the Center for Responsive Politics. "I think they're pretty damned strong. This would be the No. 1 thing for them," Kirk said of AIPAC. Intense lobbying from AIPAC could help the sanctions supporters win back the <u>four Democrats</u> who joined 13 others in cosponsoring the sanctions bill last year, but later backtracked their support. Sens. Kirsten Gillibrand of New York, Joe Manchin of West Virginia, Richard Blumenthal of Connecticut and Chris Coons of Delaware <u>rejected the idea of moving forward amid negotiations <strong>after the White House</strong> </u>and allies<u> <strong>made its push</strong> on Capitol Hill to keep the measure from a floor vote</u>. "I did not sign it with the intention that it would ever be voted upon or used upon while we were negotiating," Manchin said on MSNBC after Obama talked about Iran in his State of the Union address. "I signed it because I wanted to make sure the president had a hammer if he needed it and showed them how determined we were to do it and use it if we had to." After talks failed to materialize into an agreement by the November 2014 deadline, some Democrats have started to lose patience with the stop-and-stall pace of negotiations with Iran and are facing pressure from groups like AIPAC to support a sanctions bill, though the White House insists the negotiations have yielded tangible results: rolling back Iran's nuclear program during negotiations. But even <u>if Kirk, Menendez and their allies can pressure those four Democrats into signing on, they will need to pull three more Senate Democrats who didn't cosponsor the bill last year to secure the 15</u> Democrats <u>needed to override a</u> presidential <u>veto</u>. And they won't just be targeted by AIPAC. <u>A coalition of dove organizations is already putting the gears in motion for what they expect to be the <strong>toughest battle yet on this issue</u></strong>, and while they're clear-eyed about the uphill climb they face, they dismiss the overconfident stride of pro-sanctions leaders. These groups will look to paint any new sanctions as a step onto the warpath with Iran and show wary Democrats that they have the <strong>grassroots backing to stave off attacks from groups like AIPAC. More than 400 faith leaders and activists traveled to D.C. in late November to lobby Congress against the sanctions in a day of action organized by the Friends Committee on National Legislation, a Quaker-founded organization, and the group plans to drive its 50,000 supporters to flood Congress with calls and letters in the weeks ahead. "The real trick that we have to do is really to make that opposition -- both in the public and that opposition on the Hill -- to really make it become public and to amplify those voices," said Kate Gould, the group's lead lobbyist on the issue. "Because right now you hear from, it's Lindsey Graham and (Marco) Rubio, who are very confident in their prognosis and have made it sound like it's inevitable that these sanctions will pass with a veto-proof majority."</p></strong>
null
null
DA
220,775
10
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,238
Legalization of PAS harms the most disadvantaged – elderly and disabled and crushes value to life and inevitably leads to a slippery slope
Lee 2013 )
Lee 2013 (Patrick Lee Ph.D., is the John N. and Jamie D. McAleer Professor of Bioethics and the director of the Institute of Bioethics at Franciscan University of Steubenville. The slippery slope of physician-assisted suicide http://www.legatusmagazine.org/the-slippery-slope-of-physician-assisted-suicide/ )
If a culture regards human life as inviolable, that fact protects all of us; if not, then the most vulnerable among us — especially the elderly and the disabled — are in danger. A culture that condones PAS views life as merely contingently valuable and so views the lives of many of the most vulnerable among us as mere burdens. rescinding the law against PAS would send the message that in many cases a person’s life is simply not worth living and, by implication, is merely a burden on his or her family. The sense of self-worth among the elderly, dying, and disabled would be profoundly harmed by legalizing physician-assisted suicide, and it would lead many to despair and request suicide out of undue deference to others. If the rationale for PAS is to respect autonomy, then why limit it to those who are terminally ill? Why privilege the autonomy of those who are terminally ill above those who are suffering chronically? Alternatively, if the rationale for PAS is that a person is in misery or has allegedly lost her dignity — if the law is based on the belief that for some people death is a benefit — then it will be impossible to deny this alleged benefit to other groups who lack decision-making capacity, for example, those who are unconscious, demented, or are children (as the Netherlands has been led to do with the open euthanasia of infants). Thus, PAS is a denial of the equal and inherent dignity of the elderly, the dying, and the disabled. Respect for human life and genuine compassion and care for all requires that PAS remain illegal.
if not the most vulnerable among us the elderly and the disabled — are in danger culture that condones PAS views life as merely contingently valuable and so views the lives of many of the most vulnerable among us as mere burdens. rescinding the law against PAS would send the message that a person’s life is simply not worth living and is merely a burden on his or her family. The sense of self-worth among the elderly, dying, and disabled would be profoundly harmed by legalizing p a s if the rationale for PAS is that a person is in misery if the law is based on the belief that for some people death is a benefit — then it will be impossible to deny this alleged benefit to other groups who lack decision-making capacity PAS is a denial of the equal and inherent dignity of the elderly, the dying, and the disabled
The protection of life is as an essential component of the public good. Especially important is how the culture as a whole — which is profoundly influenced by the law — regards human life. If a culture regards human life as inviolable, that fact protects all of us; if not, then the most vulnerable among us — especially the elderly and the disabled — are in danger. A culture that condones PAS views life as merely contingently valuable and so views the lives of many of the most vulnerable among us as mere burdens. Consider laws that prohibit physicians from amputating healthy limbs or performing female genital mutilation. Such laws exist precisely because we recognize that physicians should perform surgery only to provide a real medical (or cosmetic) benefit to the patient — or at least not significantly harm her. Rescinding such laws would send the message that these practices are not inherently harmful. In the same way, rescinding the law against PAS would send the message that in many cases a person’s life is simply not worth living and, by implication, is merely a burden on his or her family. The sense of self-worth among the elderly, dying, and disabled would be profoundly harmed by legalizing physician-assisted suicide, and it would lead many to despair and request suicide out of undue deference to others. A society cannot, then, be neutral with respect to the lives of these people: It will either protect their lives or it will help shape a culture that views them as better off dead. The logic of de-criminalizing PAS for the terminally ill who are suffering grievously would lead inexorably to allowing (and encouraging) other types of killing. If the rationale for PAS is to respect autonomy, then why limit it to those who are terminally ill? Why privilege the autonomy of those who are terminally ill above those who are suffering chronically? Alternatively, if the rationale for PAS is that a person is in misery or has allegedly lost her dignity — if the law is based on the belief that for some people death is a benefit — then it will be impossible to deny this alleged benefit to other groups who lack decision-making capacity, for example, those who are unconscious, demented, or are children (as the Netherlands has been led to do with the open euthanasia of infants). Thus, PAS is a denial of the equal and inherent dignity of the elderly, the dying, and the disabled. Respect for human life and genuine compassion and care for all requires that PAS remain illegal.
2,506
<h4>Legalization of PAS harms the most disadvantaged – elderly and disabled and crushes value to life and inevitably leads to a slippery slope</h4><p><strong>Lee 2013</strong> (Patrick Lee Ph.D., is the John N. and Jamie D. McAleer Professor of Bioethics and the director of the Institute of Bioethics at Franciscan University of Steubenville. The slippery slope of physician-assisted suicide http://www.legatusmagazine.org/the-slippery-slope-of-physician-assisted-suicide/ <u><strong>)</p><p></u></strong>The protection of life is as an essential component of the public good. Especially important is how the culture as a whole — which is profoundly influenced by the law — regards human life. <u><strong>If a culture regards human life as inviolable, that fact protects all of us; <mark>if not</mark>, then <mark>the most vulnerable among us</mark> — especially <mark>the elderly and the disabled — are in danger</mark>. A <mark>culture that condones PAS views life as merely contingently valuable and so views the lives of many of the most vulnerable among us as mere burdens.</u></strong></mark> Consider laws that prohibit physicians from amputating healthy limbs or performing female genital mutilation. Such laws exist precisely because we recognize that physicians should perform surgery only to provide a real medical (or cosmetic) benefit to the patient — or at least not significantly harm her. Rescinding such laws would send the message that these practices are not inherently harmful. In the same way, <u><strong><mark>rescinding the law against PAS would send the message that</mark> in many cases <mark>a person’s life is simply not worth living and</mark>, by implication, <mark>is merely a burden on his or her family. The sense of self-worth among the elderly, dying, and disabled would be profoundly harmed by legalizing p</mark>hysician-<mark>a</mark>ssisted <mark>s</mark>uicide, and it would lead many to despair and request suicide out of undue deference to others.</u></strong> A society cannot, then, be neutral with respect to the lives of these people: It will either protect their lives or it will help shape a culture that views them as better off dead. The logic of de-criminalizing PAS for the terminally ill who are suffering grievously would lead inexorably to allowing (and encouraging) other types of killing. <u><strong>If the rationale for PAS is to respect autonomy, then why limit it to those who are terminally ill? Why privilege the autonomy of those who are terminally ill above those who are suffering chronically? Alternatively, <mark>if the rationale for PAS is that a person is in misery</mark> or has allegedly lost her dignity — <mark>if the law is based on the belief that for some people death is a benefit — then it will be impossible to deny this alleged benefit to other groups who lack decision-making capacity</mark>, for example, those who are unconscious, demented, or are children (as the Netherlands has been led to do with the open euthanasia of infants). Thus, <mark>PAS is a denial of the equal and inherent dignity of the elderly, the dying, and the disabled</mark>. Respect for human life and genuine compassion and care for all requires that PAS remain illegal.</p></u></strong>
null
Case
CP
430,365
11
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,239
Prefer the affirmative’s impacts to highly specific long term disadvantages – cognitive bias means you will think their impact is better than it really is
Yudkowsky 06
Yudkowsky 06 [Eliezer, 8/31/2006. Singularity Institute for Artificial Intelligence Palo Alto, CA. “Cognitive biases potentially affecting judgment of global risks, Forthcoming in Global Catastrophic Risks, eds. Nick Bostrom and Milan Cirkovic, singinst.org/upload/cognitive-biases.pdf.
The conjunction fallacy similarly applies to futurological forecasts According to probability theory, adding additional detail onto a story must render the story less probable Yet human psychology seems to follow the rule that adding an additional detail can make the story more plausible. Overly detailed reassurances can create false perceptions of safety Vivid, specific scenarios can inflate our probability estimates of security, as well as misdirecting defensive investments into needlessly narrow or implausibly detailed risk scenarios More generally, people tend to overestimate conjunctive probabilities and underestimate disjunctive probabilities people tend to overestimate the probability that seven events of 90% probability will all occur people tend to underestimate the probability that at least one of seven events of 10% probability will occur
conjunction fallacy applies to futurological forecasts According to probability theory, adding additional detail must render the story less probable Yet human psychology seems to follow the rule that adding an additional detail can make the story more plausible specific scenarios can inflate our probability estimates as well as misdirecting investments into implausibly detailed risk scenarios people tend to overestimate conjunctive probabilities and underestimate disjunctive probabilities people overestimate the probability that seven events of 90% probability will all occur people underestimate the probability that one of seven events of 10% probability will occur
The conjunction fallacy similarly applies to futurological forecasts. Two independent sets of professional analysts at the Second International Congress on Forecasting were asked to rate, respectively, the probability of "A complete suspension of diplomatic relations between the USA and the Soviet Union, sometime in 1983" or "A Russian invasion of Poland, and a complete suspension of diplomatic relations between the USA and the Soviet Union, sometime in 1983". The second set of analysts responded with significantly higher probabilities. (Tversky and Kahneman 1983.) In Johnson et. al. (1993), MBA students at Wharton were scheduled to travel to Bangkok as part of their degree program. Several groups of students were asked how much they - 6 - were willing to pay for terrorism insurance. One group of subjects was asked how much they were willing to pay for terrorism insurance covering the flight from Thailand to the US. A second group of subjects was asked how much they were willing to pay for terrorism insurance covering the round-trip flight. A third group was asked how much they were willing to pay for terrorism insurance that covered the complete trip to Thailand. These three groups responded with average willingness to pay of $17.19, $13.90, and $7.44 respectively. According to probability theory, adding additional detail onto a story must render the story less probable. It is less probable that Linda is a feminist bank teller than that she is a bank teller, since all feminist bank tellers are necessarily bank tellers. Yet human psychology seems to follow the rule that adding an additional detail can make the story more plausible. People might pay more for international diplomacy intended to prevent nanotechnological warfare by China, than for an engineering project to defend against nanotechnological attack from any source. The second threat scenario is less vivid and alarming, but the defense is more useful because it is more vague. More valuable still would be strategies which make humanity harder to extinguish without being specific to nanotechnologic threats - such as colonizing space, or see Yudkowsky (this volume) on AI. Security expert Bruce Schneier observed (both before and after the 2005 hurricane in New Orleans) that the U.S. government was guarding specific domestic targets against "movie-plot scenarios" of terrorism, at the cost of taking away resources from emergency-response capabilities that could respond to any disaster. (Schneier 2005.) Overly detailed reassurances can also create false perceptions of safety: "X is not an existential risk and you don't need to worry about it, because A, B, C, D, and E"; where the failure of any one of propositions A, B, C, D, or E potentially extinguishes the human species. "We don't need to worry about nanotechnologic war, because a UN commission will initially develop the technology and prevent its proliferation until such time as an active shield is developed, capable of defending against all accidental and malicious outbreaks that contemporary nanotechnology is capable of producing, and this condition will persist indefinitely." Vivid, specific scenarios can inflate our probability estimates of security, as well as misdirecting defensive investments into needlessly narrow or implausibly detailed risk scenarios. More generally, people tend to overestimate conjunctive probabilities and underestimate disjunctive probabilities. (Tversky and Kahneman 1974.) That is, people tend to overestimate the probability that, e.g., seven events of 90% probability will all occur. Conversely, people tend to underestimate the probability that at least one of seven events of 10% probability will occur. Someone judging whether to, e.g., incorporate a new startup, must evaluate the probability that many individual events will all go right (there will be sufficient funding, competent employees, customers will want the product) while also considering the likelihood that at least one critical failure will occur (the bank refuses - 7 - a loan, the biggest project fails, the lead scientist dies). This may help explain why only 44% of entrepreneurial ventures3 survive after 4 years. (Knaup 2005.)
4,274
<h4>Prefer the affirmative’s impacts to highly specific long term disadvantages – cognitive bias means you will think their impact is better than it really is</h4><p><strong>Yudkowsky</strong> <strong>06</strong> [Eliezer, 8/31/2006. Singularity Institute for Artificial Intelligence Palo Alto, CA. “Cognitive biases potentially affecting judgment of global risks, Forthcoming in Global Catastrophic Risks, eds. Nick Bostrom and Milan Cirkovic, singinst.org/upload/cognitive-biases.pdf.</p><p><u>The <mark>conjunction fallacy</mark> similarly <mark>applies to futurological forecasts</u></mark>. Two independent sets of professional analysts at the Second International Congress on Forecasting were asked to rate, respectively, the probability of "A complete suspension of diplomatic relations between the USA and the Soviet Union, sometime in 1983" or "A Russian invasion of Poland, and a complete suspension of diplomatic relations between the USA and the Soviet Union, sometime in 1983". The second set of analysts responded with significantly higher probabilities. (Tversky and Kahneman 1983.)</p><p>In Johnson et. al. (1993), MBA students at Wharton were scheduled to travel to Bangkok as part of their degree program. Several groups of students were asked how much they - 6 - were willing to pay for terrorism insurance. One group of subjects was asked how much they were willing to pay for terrorism insurance covering the flight from Thailand to the US. A second group of subjects was asked how much they were willing to pay for terrorism insurance covering the round-trip flight. A third group was asked how much they were willing to pay for terrorism insurance that covered the complete trip to Thailand. These three groups responded with average willingness to pay of $17.19, $13.90, and $7.44 respectively. </p><p><u><mark>According to probability theory, adding additional detail</mark> onto a story <mark>must render the story less probable</u></mark>. It is less probable that Linda is a feminist bank teller than that she is a bank teller, since all feminist bank tellers are necessarily bank tellers. <u><mark>Yet human psychology seems to follow the rule that adding an additional detail can make the story more plausible</mark>.</u> </p><p>People might pay more for international diplomacy intended to prevent nanotechnological warfare by China, than for an engineering project to defend against nanotechnological attack from any source. The second threat scenario is less vivid and alarming, but the defense is more useful because it is more vague. More valuable still would be strategies which make humanity harder to extinguish without being specific to nanotechnologic threats - such as colonizing space, or see Yudkowsky (this volume) on AI. Security expert Bruce Schneier observed (both before and after the 2005 hurricane in New Orleans) that the U.S. government was guarding specific domestic targets against "movie-plot scenarios" of terrorism, at the cost of taking away resources from emergency-response capabilities that could respond to any disaster. (Schneier 2005.) </p><p><u>Overly detailed reassurances can</u> also <u>create false perceptions of safety</u>: "X is not an existential risk and you don't need to worry about it, because A, B, C, D, and E"; where the failure of any one of propositions A, B, C, D, or E potentially extinguishes the human species. "We don't need to worry about nanotechnologic war, because a UN commission will initially develop the technology and prevent its proliferation until such time as an active shield is developed, capable of defending against all accidental and malicious outbreaks that contemporary nanotechnology is capable of producing, and this condition will persist indefinitely." <u>Vivid, <mark>specific scenarios can inflate our probability estimates</mark> of security, <mark>as well as misdirecting</mark> defensive <mark>investments into</mark> needlessly narrow or <mark>implausibly detailed risk scenarios</u></mark>. </p><p><u>More generally, <mark>people tend to overestimate conjunctive probabilities and</mark> <mark>underestimate disjunctive probabilities</u></mark>. (Tversky and Kahneman 1974.) That is, <u><mark>people</mark> tend to <mark>overestimate the probability that</u></mark>, e.g., <u><mark>seven events of 90% probability will all occur</u></mark>. Conversely, <u><mark>people</mark> tend to <mark>underestimate the probability that</mark> at least <mark>one of seven events of 10% probability will occur</u></mark>. Someone judging whether to, e.g., incorporate a new startup, must evaluate the probability that many individual events will all go right (there will be sufficient funding, competent employees, customers will want the product) while also considering the likelihood that at least one critical failure will occur (the bank refuses - 7 - a loan, the biggest project fails, the lead scientist dies). This may help explain why only 44% of entrepreneurial ventures3 survive after 4 years. (Knaup 2005.) </p>
null
Contention 4 is risk calculus
Contention 3 The Plan solves
11,979
232
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,240
The DSM will inevitably fail and developing nations will never be able to effectively engage because of structural issues with the DSM
Odano and Abedin, 2008 http://gsir.iuj.ac.jp/publications/pdf/EDP08-1.pdf
Odano and Abedin, 2008 Sumimaru, Shiga University, and Ziaul, Shiga University, “Insufficiency in the Dispute Settlement Mechanism of the WTO: Consequences and Implications for the Multilateral Trading System” http://gsir.iuj.ac.jp/publications/pdf/EDP08-1.pdf
two out of six Ministerial Conferences of the WTO completely failed as the countries at the negotiation table could not reach any agreeable solution the success of a multilateral trade negotiation depends on the power of the DSU to provide remedies against unfair trade practices Examining the provisions of the DSU it has considerable insufficiencies Because of the insufficiencies it is very difficult for a country, especially for the small-developing ones, to get adequate relief against unfair trade practices The provisions of the DSU only allow retaliatory measures against a country using unfair trade practices If a small-developing country is affected by such unfair trade practices it is impossible for that small-developing country to “retaliate against the developed country, because in reality most of the developing countries are heavily dependent on few developed countries the countries with considerable financial strength, versatile tradable items and large trade share not only tend to use the dispute settlement mechanism more but win more disputes than the countries with low financial strength if a dispute is prolonged then it may favor the developed countries at the expense of the small-developing ones. These results provide logic for the finding that the developing countries participate in fewer trade disputes Without changes and actions the WTO will always face difficulty ensuring fare trade and successful multilateral trade negotiations.
two out of six Ministerial Conferences of the WTO completely failed as the countries could not reach any solution the success of a multilateral trade negotiation depends on the power of the DSU Examining the provisions it has considerable insufficiencies. Because of the insufficiencies it is very difficult for a country, to get adequate relief provisions only allow retaliatory measures it is impossible for that country to “retaliate the countries with considerable financial strength, tend to win more disputes if a dispute is prolonged then it may favor the developed countries at the expense of the small-developing ones. Without changes the WTO will face difficulty ensuring fare trade and successful multilateral trade negotiations.
In many respects the WTO system is better than the old GATT system. It included all the GATT provisions plus improved by adding new Agreements covering key sectors and issues of international trade. Yet, two out of six Ministerial Conferences of the WTO completely failed as the countries at the negotiation table could not reach any agreeable solution.20 In addition, although the Doha Conference produced promising Doha Development Agenda (DDA), the commitments laid in the DDA have not yet been fulfilled. This paper assumes that the success of a multilateral trade negotiation depends on the power of the DSU to provide remedies against unfair trade practices,2 because if the remedial measures are not effective then it will induce violation of commitments. As a result, deadlocks in trade negotiations will fail the purpose of the Ministerial Conference. Examining the provisions of the DSU, this paper finds that it has considerable insufficiencies. Because of the insufficiencies it is practically very difficult for a country, especially for the small-developing ones, to get adequate relief against unfair trade practices. The provisions of the DSU only allow retaliatory measures against a country using unfair trade practices. If a small-developing country is affected by such unfair trade practices used by a developed country, then it is virtually impossible for that small-developing country to “retaliate” against the developed country, because in reality most of the developing countries are heavily dependent on few developed countries/regions, for example, to sell their exportable items. Our regression analyses show that the countries with considerable financial strength, versatile tradable items and large trade share not only tend to use the dispute settlement mechanism more but also win more disputes than the countries with low financial strength and small trade share. In addition, we also find that if a dispute is prolonged then it may favor the developed countries at the expense of the small-developing ones. These results provide logic for the empirical finding that the developing countries, especially the least-developed ones, participate in fewer trade disputes than the developed countries.21 Apparently the WTO does not have anything to do with the financial strength or the trade share of a country. However, the gap of financial power between the developed and the developing countries may be neutralized by providing the latter with intensified legal and technical assistance during the litigation process of a dispute. To encourage the developing countries to participate more in the dispute settlement process, the WTO should replace the provision of retaliation by introducing more meaningful measure, such as financial compensation instead of retaliation, in the system. 22 At the same time, the WTO should also take necessary steps to resolve the disputed matters within the time-frame stipulated in the DSU. Without these changes and actions the WTO will always face difficulty ensuring fare trade and successful multilateral trade negotiations.
3,093
<h4>The DSM will inevitably fail and developing nations will never be able to effectively engage because of structural issues with the DSM </h4><p><strong>Odano and Abedin, 2008</strong> Sumimaru, Shiga University, and Ziaul, Shiga University, “Insufficiency in the Dispute Settlement Mechanism of the WTO: Consequences and Implications for the Multilateral Trading System” <u><strong>http://gsir.iuj.ac.jp/publications/pdf/EDP08-1.pdf</p><p></u></strong>In many respects the WTO system is better than the old GATT system. It included all the GATT provisions plus improved by adding new Agreements covering key sectors and issues of international trade. Yet, <u><mark>two out of six Ministerial Conferences of the WTO <strong>completely failed</u></strong> <u>as the countries</mark> at the negotiation table <mark>could <strong>not reach</strong> any</mark> agreeable <mark>solution</u></mark>.20 In addition, although the Doha Conference produced promising Doha Development Agenda (DDA), the commitments laid in the DDA have not yet been fulfilled. This paper assumes that <u><mark>the success of a</mark> <mark>multilateral trade negotiation</u> <u>depends on the power of the DSU</mark> to provide remedies against unfair trade practices</u>,2 because if the remedial measures are not effective then it will induce violation of commitments. As a result, deadlocks in trade negotiations will fail the purpose of the Ministerial Conference. <u><mark>Examining the <strong>provisions</strong></mark> of the DSU</u>, this paper finds that <u><strong><mark>it has considerable insufficiencies</u></strong>. <u>Because of the insufficiencies it is</u> </mark>practically <u><strong><mark>very difficult</u></strong> <u>for a country,</mark> especially for the small-developing ones, <mark>to <strong>get adequate relief</strong></mark> against unfair trade practices</u>. <u>The <mark>provisions</mark> of the DSU <mark>only allow retaliatory measures</mark> against a country using unfair trade practices</u>. <u>If a small-developing country is affected by such unfair trade practices</u> used by a developed country, then <u><mark>it is</u></mark> virtually <u><strong><mark>impossible for that</mark> small-developing <mark>country to “retaliate</u></strong></mark>” <u>against the developed country, because in reality most of the developing countries are heavily dependent on few developed countries</u>/regions, for example, to sell their exportable items. Our regression analyses show that <u><mark>the countries with considerable financial strength,</mark> versatile tradable items and large trade share not only <mark>tend to</mark> use the dispute settlement mechanism more but </u>also <u><mark>win more disputes</mark> than the countries with low financial strength</u> and small trade share. In addition, we also find that <u><mark>if a dispute is <strong>prolonged</u></strong> <u>then it may favor the developed countries</u> <u><strong>at the expense of the small-developing ones.</u></strong></mark> <u>These results provide</u> <u>logic for the</u> empirical <u>finding that the developing countries</u>, especially the least-developed ones, <u>participate in fewer trade disputes</u> than the developed countries.21 Apparently the WTO does not have anything to do with the financial strength or the trade share of a country. However, the gap of financial power between the developed and the developing countries may be neutralized by providing the latter with intensified legal and technical assistance during the litigation process of a dispute. To encourage the developing countries to participate more in the dispute settlement process, the WTO should replace the provision of retaliation by introducing more meaningful measure, such as financial compensation instead of retaliation, in the system. 22 At the same time, the WTO should also take necessary steps to resolve the disputed matters within the time-frame stipulated in the DSU. <u><mark>Without</u></mark> these <u><strong><mark>changes</mark> and actions</u></strong> <u><mark>the WTO will</mark> <strong>always <mark>face difficulty ensuring fare trade and successful multilateral trade negotiations.</p></u></strong></mark>
WTO
Dispute Settlement Mechanism
AT: Inevitable
430,618
13
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,241
Specification is a voting issue- Caulkins proves that all marijuana literature is premised on the details of legalization rather than the binary yes/no- our interp is key to allow CPs and DAs based on different regulations and state/federal distinctions which are key to ground and depth of education
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Specification is a voting issue- Caulkins proves that all marijuana literature is premised on the details of legalization rather than the binary yes/no- our interp is key to allow CPs and DAs based on different regulations and state/federal distinctions which are key to ground and depth of education</h4>
null
null
1NC
430,617
1
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,242
Prostitutes are seen as threatening because they do not contribute to the future – their non-domesticized sexuality is labeled queer because it resists the perfect control of reproductive futurism.
Van Ness ’10
Van Ness ’10, Emma Van Ness, Ph.D candidate at UCLA, MA in Italian literature and film from Middlebury, (No) Queer Futurism: Prostitutes, Pink Poets, and Politics in Italy from 1913-1918, Carte Italiane 2(6), Peer Reviewed
Queer theory must present itself as an alternative to the tyranny of reproductive futurism a that queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children,” the side outside the consensus which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism. death drive.7 The contempt for woman and sentimentality present in the destructive, first phase of Futurism all point to the queerness of the artistic and literary movement that comes to be replaced with political engagement queerness also signifies resistance to bourgeois morality and traditional moral codes within the context of Futurism Queerness attains its ethical value precisely insofar as it accedes to that place, accepting its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure Prostitutes are for the sexual social network an inextricable yet alternative and hence “lower” or “marginal” sexuality, a threat that reinforces the illusion of the stability of marriage, the institution whose scope is the reproduction of children. Prostitutes, often depicted as sterile by theorists such as Lombroso, do not contribute to “the future.”9 They are queer, outside of the norm. queer theory resists this “logic of opposition” and rather than placing hope in some future that knows no form, proposes a refusal “of every substantialization of identity, which is always oppositionally defined, and by extension, history as a linear narrative in which meaning succeeds in revealing itself through time
Queer theory must present an alternative to the tyranny of reproductive futurism contempt for woman present in destructive Futurism point to the queerness of the movement that comes to be replaced with political engagement Prostitutes are for the sexual social network an inextricable yet alternative and hence marginal” sexuality, a threat that reinforces the illusion of the stability of marriage, the institution whose scope is the reproduction of children. Prostitutes depicted as sterile do not contribute to “the future They are queer queer theory resists this “logic of opposition” and rather than placing hope in some future that knows no form roposes a refusal “of every substantialization of identity and history as a linear narrative in which meaning succeeds in revealing itself through time
Recent studies in queer theory shed some light on the relationship between the periodization of Futurism and its relationship with homosexuality. Lee Edelman, in his work No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, discusses politics, “reproductive futurism,” and the symbol of the child. Queer theory must present itself as an alternative to the tyranny of reproductive futurism, with its scope as the founding of a better world for our children. He states: [At] the heart of my polemical engagement with the cultural text of politics and the politics of cultural texts lies a simple provocation: that queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children,” the side outside the consensus which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism. . . [so that] queerness. . . figures outside and beyond its political symptoms, the place of the social order’s death drive.7 The praise of war, the élan vital, and the contempt for woman and sentimentality present in the destructive, first phase of Italian Futurism all point to the queerness of the artistic and literary movement that comes to be replaced with political engagement following World War I. Yet queerness also signifies resistance to bourgeois morality and traditional moral codes within the context of Futurism, and Tavolato sought to combat precisely this with his literary production, especially in his praise of prostitution. As Edelman writes: “Queerness attains its ethical value precisely insofar as it accedes to that place, accepting its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure.”8 Tavolato’s attempt to épater le bourgeois reveals this innate hypocrisy within society. Prostitutes are for the sexual social network an inextricable yet alternative and hence “lower” or “marginal” sexuality, a threat that reinforces the illusion of the stability of marriage, the institution whose scope is the reproduction of children. Prostitutes, often depicted as sterile by theorists such as Lombroso, do not contribute to “the future.”9 They are queer, outside of the norm. Marinetti’s rhetorical rejection of homosexuality functions in the same way — it reinforces the virile and homo-social while maintaining the hetero-normative standards of the period. Marinetti makes use of the subversive quality of the queer for its ability to scandalize (hence the accusations of his being a “pink poet”) but limits his queerness to the symbolic, going to great lengths to differentiate himself from the queer on a real level. Edelman calls for a queer theory that resists this “logic of opposition” and rather than placing hope in some future that knows no form, proposes a refusal “of every substantialization of identity, which is always oppositionally defined, and by extension, history as a linear narrative (the poor man’s teleology) in which meaning succeeds in revealing itself — as itself — through time.”10 The future, as envisioned by Futurists during the first “heroic” phase of Futurism ending around 1915 upon Italy’s entry into the war, had little quantitative or real qualities, and was relegated rather to a utopic possibility. The second phase saw the entry into the real, into the political, with World War I as the catalyst for change within the movement. Between 1915, the year of the feud with Lacerba, and 1918, the year of the publication of L’isola dei baci, the rift between the queer Futurists and Marinetti widens. Marinetti’s programmatic rejection of his Decadent, Symbolist literary fathers, such as Oscar Wilde, d’Annunzio, Mallarmé, and Baudelaire by proclaiming them symptomatic of passatismo nietzschiano, as well as his entry into the political, are symptoms of the end of queer Futurism that takes place during this period.11 As Papini’s 1915 article, “Futurismo e Marinettismo,” makes clear, in defining himself as the Futurist, the prophetic Marinetti necessarily had to go about the operation of queering those ironic “Others” that had been a fundamental part of the movement at its inception.
4,119
<h4>Prostitutes are seen as threatening because they do not contribute to the future – their non-domesticized sexuality is labeled queer because it resists the perfect control of reproductive futurism.</h4><p><strong>Van Ness ’10</strong>, Emma Van Ness, Ph.D candidate at UCLA, MA in Italian literature and film from Middlebury, (No) Queer Futurism: Prostitutes, Pink Poets, and Politics in Italy from 1913-1918, Carte Italiane 2(6), Peer Reviewed</p><p>Recent studies in queer theory shed some light on the relationship between the periodization of Futurism and its relationship with homosexuality. Lee Edelman, in his work No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, discusses politics, “reproductive futurism,” and the symbol of the child. <u><mark>Queer theory must present </mark>itself as <mark>an alternative to the tyranny of reproductive futurism</u></mark>, with its scope as the founding of <u>a</u> better world for our children. He states:</p><p>[At] the heart of my polemical engagement with the cultural text of politics and the politics of cultural texts lies a simple provocation: <u>that queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children,” the side outside the consensus which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism.</u> . . [so that] queerness. . . figures outside and beyond its political symptoms, the place of the social order’s<u> death drive.7</p><p>The</u> praise of war, the élan vital, and the <u><mark>contempt for woman</mark> and sentimentality <mark>present in </mark>the <mark>destructive</mark>, first phase of </u>Italian<u> <mark>Futurism </mark>all <mark>point to the queerness of the </mark>artistic and literary <mark>movement that comes to be replaced with political engagement</u></mark> following World War I. Yet <u>queerness also signifies resistance to bourgeois morality and traditional moral codes within the context of Futurism</u>, and Tavolato sought to combat precisely this with his literary production, especially in his praise of prostitution. As Edelman writes: “<u>Queerness attains its ethical value precisely insofar as it accedes to that place, accepting its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure</u>.”8 Tavolato’s attempt to épater le bourgeois reveals this innate hypocrisy within society. <u><strong><mark>Prostitutes are for the sexual social network an inextricable yet alternative and hence</mark> “lower” or “<mark>marginal” sexuality, a threat that reinforces the illusion of the stability of marriage, the institution whose scope is the reproduction of children. Prostitutes</strong></mark>, often <strong><mark>depicted as sterile</mark> </strong>by theorists such as Lombroso, <strong><mark>do not contribute to “the future</strong></mark>.”9 <mark>They are queer</mark>, outside of the norm.</p><p></u>Marinetti’s rhetorical rejection of homosexuality functions in the same way — it reinforces the virile and homo-social while maintaining the hetero-normative standards of the period. Marinetti makes use of the subversive quality of the queer for its ability to scandalize (hence the accusations of his being a “pink poet”) but limits his queerness to the symbolic, going to great lengths to differentiate himself from the queer on a real level. Edelman calls for a<u> <mark>queer theory</mark> </u>that<u> <mark>resists this “logic of opposition” and rather than placing hope in some future that knows no form</mark>, p<mark>roposes a refusal “of every substantialization of identity</mark>, which is always oppositionally defined, <mark>and</mark> by extension, <mark>history as a linear narrative</u></mark> (the poor man’s teleology) <u><mark>in which meaning</mark> <mark>succeeds in revealing itself</u></mark> — as itself — <u><mark>through time</u></mark>.”10 The future, as envisioned by Futurists during the first “heroic” phase of Futurism ending around 1915 upon Italy’s entry into the war, had little quantitative or real qualities, and was relegated rather to a utopic possibility. The second phase saw the entry into the real, into the political, with World War I as the catalyst for change within the movement. Between 1915, the year of the feud with Lacerba, and 1918, the year of the publication of L’isola dei baci, the rift between the queer Futurists and Marinetti widens. Marinetti’s programmatic rejection of his Decadent, Symbolist literary fathers, such as Oscar Wilde, d’Annunzio, Mallarmé, and Baudelaire by proclaiming them symptomatic of passatismo nietzschiano, as well as his entry into the political, are symptoms of the end of queer Futurism that takes place during this period.11 As Papini’s 1915 article, “Futurismo e Marinettismo,” makes clear, in defining himself as the Futurist, the prophetic Marinetti necessarily had to go about the operation of queering those ironic “Others” that had been a fundamental part of the movement at its inception.</p>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,619
3
17,077
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
565,297
A
tournament
4
Binghamton Cepin-Sehgal
Baker, Webster Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,243
Crowd out of voluntary donations empirically denied
Boyer 12
Boyer 12 J. Randall Boyer, J.D. candidate, April 2012, J. Reuben Clark Law School, Brigham Young University. 2012 Brigham Young University Law Review 2012 B.Y.U.L. Rev. 313 COMMENT: Gifts of the Heart ... and Other Tissues: Legalizing the Sale of Human Organs and Tissues lexis
allowing the sale of organs would not preclude someone from donating . Currently, the sale of blood and ova is allowed under law, but many of the donations of these tissues take place without compensation In fact, giving the donor the right to sell could actually increase the value of an uncompensated donation
allowing the sale of organs would not preclude someone from donating , the sale of blood and ova is allowed under law, but many donations take place without compensation , giving the donor the right to sell could increase the value of an uncompensated donation
It should also be noted that allowing the sale of organs would not preclude someone from donating without compensation. n156 Currently, the sale of blood and ova is allowed under law, but many of the donations of these tissues take place without compensation. n157 In fact, giving the donor the right to sell could actually increase the value of an uncompensated donation by providing donors with more power to ensure the recipient receives the surplus value of the organ through contractually stipulated prices to prevent any inflation by middlemen.
550
<h4>Crowd out of voluntary donations empirically denied</h4><p><strong>Boyer 12</strong> J. Randall Boyer, J.D. candidate, April 2012, J. Reuben Clark Law School, Brigham Young University. 2012 Brigham Young University Law Review 2012 B.Y.U.L. Rev. 313 COMMENT: Gifts of the Heart ... and Other Tissues: Legalizing the Sale of Human Organs and Tissues lexis</p><p>It should also be noted that<u> <mark>allowing the sale of organs would not preclude someone from donating</mark> </u>without compensation<u>.</u> n156 <u>Currently<mark>, the sale of blood and ova is allowed under law, but many </mark>of the <mark>donations </mark>of these tissues <mark>take place without compensation</u></mark>. n157 <u>In fact<mark>, giving the donor the right to sell could </mark>actually <mark>increase the value of an uncompensated donation</mark> </u>by providing donors with more power to ensure the recipient receives the surplus value of the organ through contractually stipulated prices to prevent any inflation by middlemen.</p>
null
null
Contention 1 – Organ sales will save lives
430,620
4
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,244
Physician assisted suicide is a wedge issue – strong partisan gap.
Saad ’11
Saad, ’11 [Lydia, “Doctor-Assisted Suicide Is Moral Issue Dividing Americans Most”, 5-31-11, Gallup, http://www.gallup.com/poll/147842/doctor-assisted-suicide-moral-issue-dividing-americans.aspx, RSR]
Doctor-assisted suicide emerges as the most controversial cultural issue in Gallup's 2011 Values and Beliefs poll, with Americans divided 45% vs. 48% over whether it is morally acceptable or morally wrong The three most controversial issues -- doctor-assisted suicide, abortion, and out-of-wedlock births -- are the ones on which fewer than 15 points separate the percentage considering the issue morally acceptable from the percentage considering it morally wrong Partisans disagree widely on these issues with majorities of Democrats accepting of all three issues, compared with, at most, barely a third of Republicans
null
PRINCETON, NJ -- Doctor-assisted suicide emerges as the most controversial cultural issue in Gallup's 2011 Values and Beliefs poll, with Americans divided 45% vs. 48% over whether it is morally acceptable or morally wrong. Having a baby out of wedlock and abortion also closely divide Americans. However, stronger public consensus exists on 14 other issues tested. Americans are in broadest agreement about what behaviors are morally wrong. At least 8 in 10 U.S. adults interviewed in the May 5-8 survey say this about extramarital affairs, polygamy, cloning humans, and suicide. At least 6 in 10 say pornography and cloning animals are each morally wrong. Widest agreement about what is morally acceptable, ranging from 60% to 69%, is found for divorce, the death penalty, gambling, embryonic stem cell research, and premarital sex. Also, 55% or better say medical testing on animals, gay/lesbian relations, and the use of animal fur for clothing are each acceptable. The three most controversial issues -- doctor-assisted suicide, abortion, and out-of-wedlock births -- are the ones on which fewer than 15 points separate the percentage considering the issue morally acceptable from the percentage considering it morally wrong. Attitudes on each have been fairly stable in recent years. Partisans disagree widely on these issues, with majorities of Democrats accepting of all three issues, compared with, at most, barely a third of Republicans. Abortion is the most divisive of the three, with a 37-point Republican-Democratic gap.
1,533
<h4><strong>Physician assisted suicide is a wedge issue – strong partisan gap.</h4><p>Saad</strong>, <strong>’11</strong> [Lydia, “Doctor-Assisted Suicide Is Moral Issue Dividing Americans Most”, 5-31-11, Gallup, http://www.gallup.com/poll/147842/doctor-assisted-suicide-moral-issue-dividing-americans.aspx, RSR]</p><p>PRINCETON, NJ -- <u>Doctor-assisted suicide emerges as the <strong>most controversial cultural issue</strong> in Gallup's 2011 Values and Beliefs poll, with Americans divided 45% vs. 48% over whether it is morally acceptable or morally wrong</u>. Having a baby out of wedlock and abortion also closely divide Americans. However, stronger public consensus exists on 14 other issues tested. Americans are in broadest agreement about what behaviors are morally wrong. At least 8 in 10 U.S. adults interviewed in the May 5-8 survey say this about extramarital affairs, polygamy, cloning humans, and suicide. At least 6 in 10 say pornography and cloning animals are each morally wrong. Widest agreement about what is morally acceptable, ranging from 60% to 69%, is found for divorce, the death penalty, gambling, embryonic stem cell research, and premarital sex. Also, 55% or better say medical testing on animals, gay/lesbian relations, and the use of animal fur for clothing are each acceptable. <u>The three most controversial issues -- doctor-assisted suicide, abortion, and out-of-wedlock births -- are the ones on which fewer than 15 points separate the percentage considering the issue morally acceptable from the percentage considering it morally wrong</u>. Attitudes on each have been fairly stable in recent years. <u><strong>Partisans disagree widely on these issues</u></strong>, <u>with majorities of Democrats accepting of all three issues, compared with, at most, <strong>barely a third of Republicans</u></strong>. Abortion is the most divisive of the three, with a 37-point Republican-Democratic gap.</p>
null
null
DA
429,684
5
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,245
Right to die movements empirically justify larger use of ableist eugenics
Wright, 2K
Wright, 2K (Walter Wright - Associate Professor and Chair of Philosophy at Clark University, Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, Historical analogies, slippery slopes, and the question of euthanasia, EBSCO)
The gathering threads of the eugenics and “right-to- die” movements converged in Permitting the Destruction of Lives not Worth Living: Its Extent and Form by Binding Binding provides a careful legal analysis of a range of related cases, including assisting someone to com- mit suicide, not all lives are equal. Binding introduces the idea that “terminally ill or fatally wounded people” are in a new category. Binding’s arguments incorporate elements of the “right to die” movement as well as the eugenicist’s appeals to the preservation of social well-being ne could perhaps take these arguments as sensible, compas- sionate and progressive. They are surprisingly modern in tone can one abstract from the work’s historical effects? providing support for a limited practice of medical killing, Binding made such things discussible they provided intellectual cover for people who wished later to abuse the opportunity their work brought about a climate among German medical profes- sionals that permitted doctors to accept the idea of killing their patients. This climate could be claimed to have been a contributing cause for the vigorous advocacy by some German physicians of a policy of killing mentally retarded, physically handicapped, elderly people the German experience confirms the claim that even discuss- ing the idea that some lives might not be worth living helps to create the “unmitigated disaster Their influence in Germany effectively “pulled the peg” in the slope so that, when external social forces pushed the medi- cal cart, physicians were no longer able to arrest its slide
eugenics and “right-to- die” movements converge side. Binding provides a careful legal analysis of a range of related cases, including assisting someone to com- mit suicide not all lives are equal. Binding introduces the idea that “terminally ill or fatally wounded people” are in a new category one could perhaps take these arguments as sensible, compas- sionate and progressive. providing support for a limited practice of medical killing provided intellectual cover for people who wished later to abuse the opportunity their work brought about a climate that permitted doctors to accept the idea of killing their patients the German experience confirms the claim that even discuss- ing the idea that some lives might not be worth living helps to create the “unmitigated disaster Their influence in Germany pulled the peg” in the slope so that, when external social forces pushed the medi- cal cart, physicians were no longer able to arrest its slide.
The gathering threads of the eugenics and “right-to- die” movements converged in the influential 1920 publica- tion Die Freigabe der Vernichtung lebensunwerten Lebens: I hr Mass und Form (Permitting the Destruction of Lives not Worth Living: Its Extent and Form) by Karl Binding and Alfred Hoche.37 Binding was perhaps the most distinguished legal scholar of his time and Hoche was a physician and Professor at Freiburg. Their independent essays on the com- mon question appeared together. Most importantly, this little volume became a crucial avenue for disseminating the idea that some lives are not worth living. I will briefly review Binding's historically influential arguments leaving Hoche’s less germane discussion to the side. Binding provides a careful legal analysis of a range of related cases, including suicide, assisting someone to com- mit suicide, responding to a request from a terminally ill, hopeless, and suffering patient, killing a mentally ill person at the request of family members, and so on. He is very careful to make important distinctions, and he attempts to maintain clear boundaries around the specific cases of kill- ing he proposes to categorize as “not legally forbidden.” Thus, while he finds suicide “not legally forbidden,” assist- ing in a suicide is actually the killing of a third party and the consent of the victim does not remove legal liability from the assistant. However, not all lives are equal. Binding introduces the idea that “terminally ill or fatally wounded people” are in a new category. “Here there clearly appears the idea that such a life no longer merits strict legal protection.” These are, he thinks, “lives not worth living.” He distinguishes three cases. In the first group are “those irretrievably lost as a result of illness or injury, who, fully understanding their situation, possess and have somehow expressed their urgent wish for release.”M For Binding, killing such patients is “a duty of legal mercy.” Among other examples, he includes the fatally injured comrade on a battlefield or a mountain- eering expedition. The second group “consists of incur- able idiots."1’ These people have the will neither to live nor to die. In this case too Binding finds “no grounds— legally, socially, ethically, or religiously—for not permitting the killing of these people who are the fearsome counter image of true humanity, and who arouse horror in nearly everyone who meets them.”40 His restriction in this case is that the right of application should be limited to the family who have been caring for the handicapped patient, or to the guardian. The third group consists of mentally sound people who “through some event like a very severe, doubt- less fatal wound,” have become comatose. He docs not think that any blanket rule can cover this last group of cases, but then goes on to conclude with a general guideline: [OJnly those persons arc candidates for having their deaths permitted who are terminally ill and who, in addition to being beyond help, have either requested death or consented to dying, or else would have re- quested or consented, had they not fallen into uncon- sciousness at the critical time or if they had been able to achieve awareness of the situation.41 (Emphasis added.) All of this, Binding views within the constraint that “Every unforbidden killing of a third person must be expe- rienced as a release, at least by the victim; otherwise allow- ing it is self-evidently ruled out.”42 Having established his basic principle, Binding then goes on to propose a formal procedure with careful safeguards as a way to implement it without abuses.4* Binding’s arguments incorporate elements of the “right to die” movement as well as the eugenicist’s appeals to the preservation of social well-being. If one abstracts from this work’s historical results, ignores the occasionally crude cal- culations of social utility, and considers the rather careful protections that he includes against possible abuses, one could perhaps take these arguments as sensible, compas- sionate and progressive. They are surprisingly modern in tone, suggesting both Singer’s careful defense of permitting a limited practice of euthanasia, and recent guidelines in the Netherlands. But can one abstract from the work’s historical effects? This is the core of the slippery slope argument. Binding’s and Hoche’s views were extensively discussed by their con- temporaries and, although never officially accepted in the ^Xfeimar period, became widely influential among physicians. Participants in the T444 program used them explicitly to justify their actions.41 This connection is an instance of both a “precedent based” and a “causal” slippery slope. First, by providing support for a limited practice of medical killing, Binding and Hoche made such things discussible. In doing so, they provided intellectual cover for people who wished later to abuse the opportunity. Second, their work brought about a climate among German medical profes- sionals that permitted doctors to accept the idea of killing their patients. This climate could be claimed to have been a contributing cause for the vigorous advocacy by some German physicians of a policy of killing mentally retarded, physically handicapped, elderly people: the “useless eat- ers.” In that respect, Singer’s opponents might say, the German experience confirms the claim that even discuss- ing the idea that some lives might not be worth living helps to create the “unmitigated disaster.” Their argument also connects to the “peg” protecting our wagon from rolling down the hill. Their influence in Germany effectively “pulled the peg” in the slope (provided by the Hippocratic ethic), so that, when external social forces pushed the medi- cal cart, physicians were no longer able to arrest its slide.46
5,822
<h4>Right to die movements empirically justify larger use of ableist eugenics </h4><p><strong>Wright, 2K </strong>(Walter Wright - Associate Professor and Chair of Philosophy at Clark University, Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, Historical analogies, slippery slopes, and the question of euthanasia, EBSCO)</p><p><u>The gathering threads of the <mark>eugenics and “right-to- die” movements converge</mark>d<mark> </mark>in</u> the influential 1920 publica- tion Die Freigabe der Vernichtung lebensunwerten Lebens: I hr Mass und Form (<u>Permitting the Destruction of Lives not Worth Living: Its Extent and Form</u>) <u>by</u> Karl <u>Binding </u>and Alfred Hoche.37 Binding was perhaps the most distinguished legal scholar of his time and Hoche was a physician and Professor at Freiburg. Their independent essays on the com- mon question appeared together. Most importantly, this little volume became a crucial avenue for disseminating the idea that some lives are not worth living. I will briefly review Binding's historically influential arguments leaving Hoche’s less germane discussion to the <mark>side. <u>Binding provides a careful legal analysis of a range of related cases, including</u></mark> suicide, <u><mark>assisting someone to com- mit suicide</mark>, </u>responding to a request from a terminally ill, hopeless, and suffering patient, killing a mentally ill person at the request of family members, and so on. He is very careful to make important distinctions, and he attempts to maintain clear boundaries around the specific cases of kill- ing he proposes to categorize as “not legally forbidden.” Thus, while he finds suicide “not legally forbidden,” assist- ing in a suicide is actually the killing of a third party and the consent of the victim does not remove legal liability from the assistant. However, <u><mark>not all lives are equal. Binding introduces the idea that “terminally ill or fatally wounded people” are in a new category</mark>.</u> “Here there clearly appears the idea that such a life no longer merits strict legal protection.” These are, he thinks, “lives not worth living.” He distinguishes three cases. In the first group are “those irretrievably lost as a result of illness or injury, who, fully understanding their situation, possess and have somehow expressed their urgent wish for release.”M For Binding, killing such patients is “a duty of legal mercy.” Among other examples, he includes the fatally injured comrade on a battlefield or a mountain- eering expedition. The second group “consists of incur- able idiots."1’ These people have the will neither to live nor to die. In this case too Binding finds “no grounds— legally, socially, ethically, or religiously—for not permitting the killing of these people who are the fearsome counter image of true humanity, and who arouse horror in nearly everyone who meets them.”40 His restriction in this case is that the right of application should be limited to the family who have been caring for the handicapped patient, or to the guardian. The third group consists of mentally sound people who “through some event like a very severe, doubt- less fatal wound,” have become comatose. He docs not think that any blanket rule can cover this last group of cases, but then goes on to conclude with a general guideline: [OJnly those persons arc candidates for having their deaths permitted who are terminally ill and who, in addition to being beyond help, have either requested death or consented to dying, or else would have re- quested or consented, had they not fallen into uncon- sciousness at the critical time or if they had been able to achieve awareness of the situation.41 (Emphasis added.) All of this, Binding views within the constraint that “Every unforbidden killing of a third person must be expe- rienced as a release, at least by the victim; otherwise allow- ing it is self-evidently ruled out.”42 Having established his basic principle, Binding then goes on to propose a formal procedure with careful safeguards as a way to implement it without abuses.4* <u>Binding’s arguments incorporate elements of the “right to die” movement as well as the eugenicist’s appeals to the preservation of social well-being</u>. If one abstracts from this work’s historical results, ignores the occasionally crude cal- culations of social utility, and considers the rather careful protections that he includes against possible abuses, <mark>o<u>ne could perhaps take these arguments as sensible, compas- sionate and progressive.</mark> They are surprisingly modern in tone</u>, suggesting both Singer’s careful defense of permitting a limited practice of euthanasia, and recent guidelines in the Netherlands. But <u>can one abstract from the work’s historical effects? </u>This is the core of the slippery slope argument. Binding’s and Hoche’s views were extensively discussed by their con- temporaries and, although never officially accepted in the ^Xfeimar period, became widely influential among physicians. Participants in the T444 program used them explicitly to justify their actions.41 This connection is an instance of both a “precedent based” and a “causal” slippery slope. First, by <u><mark>providing support for a limited practice of medical killing</mark>, Binding</u> and Hoche <u>made such things discussible</u>. In doing so, <u>they <mark>provided intellectual cover for people who wished later to abuse the opportunity</u></mark>. Second, <u><mark>their work brought about a climate</mark> among German medical profes- sionals <mark>that permitted doctors to accept the idea of killing their patients</mark>. This climate could be claimed to have been a contributing cause for the vigorous advocacy by some German physicians of a policy of killing mentally retarded, physically handicapped, elderly people</u>: the “useless eat- ers.” In that respect, Singer’s opponents might say, <u><mark>the German experience confirms the claim that even discuss- ing the idea that some lives might not be worth living helps to create the “unmitigated disaster</u></mark>.” Their argument also connects to the “peg” protecting our wagon from rolling down the hill. <u><mark>Their influence in Germany</mark> effectively “<mark>pulled the peg” in the slope</u></mark> (provided by the Hippocratic ethic), <u><mark>so that, when external social forces pushed the medi- cal cart, <strong>physicians were no longer able to arrest its slide</u></strong>.<strong></mark>46</p></strong>
null
Case
CP
430,105
12
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,246
Low probability impacts should not be evaluated-- even if there’s some risk, policy decisions can’t be justified by vanishingly small probabilities
Rescher 03
Rescher 03 (Nicholas, Prof of Philosophy at the University of Pittsburgh, Sensible Decisions: Issues of Rational Decision in Personal Choice and Public Policy, p. 49-50)
small probabilities represent extremely remote prospect and can be written off we can forget about it as a worthy of concern. As a matter of practical policy We take the line that in our human dealings in real-life situations a sufficiently remote possibility can be viewed as being of probability zero Accordingly, such remote possibilities can simply be dismissed, and the outcomes with which they are associated can accordingly be set aside. And in “the real world” people do in fact seem to be prepared to treat certain probabilities as effectively zero, taking certain sufficiently improbable eventualities as no long representing real possibilities P]eople…refuse to worry about losses whose probability is below some threshold. Probabilities below the threshold are treated as though they were zero. No doubt, remote-possibility events having such a minute possibility can happen in some sense of the term, but this “can” functions somewhat figuratively—it is no longer seen as something that presents a realistic prospect
small probabilities can be written off. we can forget about it as a worthy of concern. As a matter of policy remote possibility can be viewed as being of probability zero remote possibilities can be dismissed, and outcomes set aside the real world” people treat certain probabilities as effectively zero, taking certain sufficiently improbable eventualities as no long representing real possibilities. Probabilities below the threshold are treated as though they were zero
On this issue there is a systemic disagreement between probabilists working on theory-oriented issues in mathematics or natural science and decision theorists who work on practical decision-oriented issues relating to human affairs. The former takes the line that small number are small numbers and must be taken into account as such—that is, the small quantities they actually are. The latter tend to take the view that small probabilities represent extremely remote prospect and can be written off. (De minimis non curat lex, as the old precept has it: in human affairs there is no need to bother with trifles.) When something is about as probable as a thousand fair dice when tossed a thousand times coming up all sixes, then, so it is held, we can pretty well forget about it as a worthy of concern. As a matter of practical policy, we operate with probabilities on the principle that when x ≤ E, then x = 0. We take the line that in our human dealings in real-life situations a sufficiently remote possibility can—for all sensible purposes—be viewed as being of probability zero. Accordingly, such remote possibilities can simply be dismissed, and the outcomes with which they are associated can accordingly be set aside. And in “the real world” people do in fact seem to be prepared to treat certain probabilities as effectively zero, taking certain sufficiently improbable eventualities as no long representing real possibilities. Here an extremely improbable event is seen as something we can simply write off as being outside the range of appropriate concern, something we can dismiss for all practical purposes. As one writer on insurance puts it: [P]eople…refuse to worry about losses whose probability is below some threshold. Probabilities below the threshold are treated as though they were zero. No doubt, remote-possibility events having such a minute possibility can happen in some sense of the term, but this “can” functions somewhat figuratively—it is no longer seen as something that presents a realistic prospect.
2,046
<h4>Low probability impacts should not be evaluated-- even if there’s some risk, policy decisions can’t be justified by vanishingly small probabilities</h4><p><strong>Rescher 03</strong> (Nicholas, Prof of Philosophy at the University of Pittsburgh, Sensible Decisions: Issues of Rational Decision in Personal Choice and Public Policy, p. 49-50)</p><p>On this issue there is a systemic disagreement between probabilists working on theory-oriented issues in mathematics or natural science and decision theorists who work on practical decision-oriented issues relating to human affairs. The former takes the line that small number are small numbers and must be taken into account as such—that is, the small quantities they actually are. The latter tend to take the view that <u><mark>small probabilities </mark>represent extremely remote prospect and <mark>can be written off</u>. </mark>(De minimis non curat lex, as the old precept has it: in human affairs there is no need to bother with trifles.) When something is about as probable as a thousand fair dice when tossed a thousand times coming up all sixes, then, so it is held, <u><mark>we can</u> </mark>pretty well <u><mark>forget about it as a worthy of concern. As a matter of </mark>practical <mark>policy</u></mark>, we operate with probabilities on the principle that when x ≤ E, then x = 0. <u>We take the line that in our human dealings in real-life situations a sufficiently <mark>remote possibility can</u></mark>—for all sensible purposes—<u><mark>be viewed as being of <strong>probability zero</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Accordingly, such <mark>remote possibilities can </mark>simply <mark>be dismissed, and </mark>the <mark>outcomes </mark>with which they are associated can accordingly be <mark>set aside</mark>.</strong> And in “<mark>the real world” people</mark> do in fact seem to be prepared to <mark>treat certain probabilities as effectively zero, taking certain sufficiently improbable eventualities as no long representing real possibilities</u>.</mark> Here an extremely improbable event is seen as something we can simply write off as being outside the range of appropriate concern, something we can dismiss for all practical purposes. As one writer on insurance puts it: [<u>P]eople…refuse to worry about losses whose probability is below some threshold. <mark>Probabilities below the threshold are treated as though they were zero</mark>. No doubt, remote-possibility events having such a minute possibility can happen in some sense of the term, but this “can” functions somewhat figuratively—it is no longer seen as something that presents a realistic prospect</u>.</p>
null
Contention 4 is risk calculus
Contention 3 The Plan solves
44,134
45
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,247
No asia war—their evidence is hype.
Bitzinger and Desker 9
Bitzinger and Desker 9 [Why East Asian War is Unlikely Richard A. Bitzinger and Barry Desker Richard A. Bitzinger is a Senior Fellow at the S. Rajaratnam School of International Studies. Barry Desker is Dean of the S. Rajaratnam School of International Studies and Director of the Institute of Defense and Strategic Studies, Nanyang Technological University, Singapore. Survival | vol. 50 no. 6 | December 2008–January 2009 | pp. 105–128 DOI 10.1080/00396330802601883]
Asia is more stable than one might expect. the break-up of states is unlikely. The North Korean nuclear issue is moving toward a conclusion with the likely denuclearisation of the peninsula. Tensions between China and Taiwan seem unlikely to erupt there are many multilateral organisations and international initiatives dedicated to enhancing peace and stability ASEAN has played a key role in conceiving and establishing broader regional institutions All this suggests war in Asia is unlikely.
Asia is more stable than one might expect the break-up of states is unlikely. The North Korean nuclear issue is moving toward a conclusion with the likely denuclearisation of the peninsula. Tensions between China and Taiwan seem unlikely to erupt there are many multilateral organisations and international initiatives dedicated to enhancing peace and stability ASEAN has played a key role in conceiving and establishing broader regional institutions All this suggests war in Asia is unlikely.
Yet despite all these potential crucibles of conflict, the Asia-Pacific, if not an area of serenity and calm, is certainly more stable than one might expect. To be sure, there are separatist movements and internal struggles, particularly with insurgencies, as in Thailand, the Philippines and Tibet. Since the resolution of the East Timor crisis, however, the region has been relatively free of open armed warfare. Separatism remains a challenge, but the break-up of states is unlikely. Terrorism is a nuisance, but its impact is contained. The North Korean nuclear issue, while not fully resolved, is at least moving toward a conclusion with the likely denuclearisation of the peninsula. Tensions between China and Taiwan, while always just beneath the surface, seem unlikely to erupt in open conflict any time soon, espe- cially given recent Kuomintang Party victories in Taiwan and efforts by Taiwan and China to re-open informal channels of consultation as well as institutional relationships between organisations responsible for cross-strait relations. And while in Asia there is no strong supranational political entity like the European Union, there are many multilateral organisations and international initiatives dedicated to enhancing peace and stability, includ- ing the Asia-Pacific Economic Cooperation (APEC) forum, the Proliferation Security Initiative and the Shanghai Co-operation Organisation. In Southeast Asia, countries are united in a common geopolitical and economic organi- sation – the Association of Southeast Asian Nations (ASEAN) – which is dedicated to peaceful economic, social and cultural development, and to the promotion of regional peace and stability. ASEAN has played a key role in conceiving and establishing broader regional institutions such as the East Asian Summit, ASEAN+3 (China, Japan and South Korea) and the ASEAN Regional Forum. All this suggests that war in Asia – while not inconceivable – is unlikely.
1,976
<h4>No asia war—their evidence is hype.</h4><p><u><strong>Bitzinger and Desker 9</u></strong> [Why East Asian War is Unlikely Richard A. Bitzinger and Barry Desker Richard A. Bitzinger is a Senior Fellow at the S. Rajaratnam School of International Studies. Barry Desker is Dean of the S. Rajaratnam School of International Studies and Director of the Institute of Defense and Strategic Studies, Nanyang Technological University, Singapore. Survival | vol<u><mark>. 50 no. 6 | December 2008–January 2009 | pp. 105–128 DOI 10.1080/00396330802601883]</p><p></u></mark>Yet despite all these potential crucibles of conflict, the <u><mark>Asia</u></mark>-Pacific, if not an area of serenity and calm, <u><mark>is</u></mark> certainly <u><mark>more stable than one might expect</mark>.</u> To be sure, there are separatist movements and internal struggles, particularly with insurgencies, as in Thailand, the Philippines and Tibet. Since the resolution of the East Timor crisis, however, the region has been relatively free of open armed warfare. Separatism remains a challenge, but <u><mark>the break-up of states is unlikely.</u></mark> Terrorism is a nuisance, but its impact is contained.<u><mark> The North Korean nuclear issue</u></mark>, while not fully resolved, <u><mark>is</u></mark> at least <u><mark>moving toward a conclusion with the likely denuclearisation of the peninsula. Tensions between China and Taiwan</u></mark>, while always just beneath the surface, <u><mark>seem unlikely to erupt</u></mark> in open conflict any time soon, espe- cially given recent Kuomintang Party victories in Taiwan and efforts by Taiwan and China to re-open informal channels of consultation as well as institutional relationships between organisations responsible for cross-strait relations. And while in Asia there is no strong supranational political entity like the European Union, <u><mark>there are many multilateral organisations and international initiatives dedicated to enhancing peace and stability</u></mark>, includ- ing the Asia-Pacific Economic Cooperation (APEC) forum, the Proliferation Security Initiative and the Shanghai Co-operation Organisation. In Southeast Asia, countries are united in a common geopolitical and economic organi- sation – the Association of Southeast Asian Nations (ASEAN) – which is dedicated to peaceful economic, social and cultural development, and to the promotion of regional peace and stability.<u> <mark>ASEAN has played a key role in conceiving and establishing broader regional institutions</u></mark> such as the East Asian Summit, ASEAN+3 (China, Japan and South Korea) and the ASEAN Regional Forum. <u><mark>All this suggests</u></mark> that <u><mark>war in Asia</u></mark> – while not inconceivable – <u><mark>is unlikely.</p></u></mark>
WTO
War
AT: Inevitable
129,553
67
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,248
Prostitutes are seen as threatening because they do not contribute to the future – their non-domesticized sexuality is labeled queer because it resists the perfect control of reproductive futurism.
Van Ness ’10
Van Ness ’10, Emma Van Ness, Ph.D candidate at UCLA, MA in Italian literature and film from Middlebury, (No) Queer Futurism: Prostitutes, Pink Poets, and Politics in Italy from 1913-1918, Carte Italiane 2(6), Peer Reviewed
Queer theory must present itself as an alternative to the tyranny of reproductive futurism a that queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children,” the side outside the consensus which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism. death drive.7 The contempt for woman and sentimentality present in the destructive, first phase of Futurism all point to the queerness of the artistic and literary movement that comes to be replaced with political engagement queerness also signifies resistance to bourgeois morality and traditional moral codes within the context of Futurism Queerness attains its ethical value precisely insofar as it accedes to that place, accepting its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure Prostitutes are for the sexual social network an inextricable yet alternative and hence “lower” or “marginal” sexuality, a threat that reinforces the illusion of the stability of marriage, the institution whose scope is the reproduction of children. Prostitutes, often depicted as sterile by theorists such as Lombroso, do not contribute to “the future.”9 They are queer, outside of the norm. queer theory resists this “logic of opposition” and rather than placing hope in some future that knows no form, proposes a refusal “of every substantialization of identity, which is always oppositionally defined, and by extension, history as a linear narrative in which meaning succeeds in revealing itself through time
Queer theory must present an alternative to the tyranny of reproductive futurism contempt for woman present in destructive Futurism point to the queerness of the movement that comes to be replaced with political engagement Prostitutes are for the sexual social network an inextricable yet alternative and hence marginal” sexuality, a threat that reinforces the illusion of the stability of marriage, the institution whose scope is the reproduction of children. Prostitutes depicted as sterile do not contribute to “the future They are queer queer theory resists this “logic of opposition” and rather than placing hope in some future that knows no form roposes a refusal “of every substantialization of identity and history as a linear narrative in which meaning succeeds in revealing itself through time
Recent studies in queer theory shed some light on the relationship between the periodization of Futurism and its relationship with homosexuality. Lee Edelman, in his work No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, discusses politics, “reproductive futurism,” and the symbol of the child. Queer theory must present itself as an alternative to the tyranny of reproductive futurism, with its scope as the founding of a better world for our children. He states: [At] the heart of my polemical engagement with the cultural text of politics and the politics of cultural texts lies a simple provocation: that queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children,” the side outside the consensus which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism. . . [so that] queerness. . . figures outside and beyond its political symptoms, the place of the social order’s death drive.7 The praise of war, the élan vital, and the contempt for woman and sentimentality present in the destructive, first phase of Italian Futurism all point to the queerness of the artistic and literary movement that comes to be replaced with political engagement following World War I. Yet queerness also signifies resistance to bourgeois morality and traditional moral codes within the context of Futurism, and Tavolato sought to combat precisely this with his literary production, especially in his praise of prostitution. As Edelman writes: “Queerness attains its ethical value precisely insofar as it accedes to that place, accepting its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure.”8 Tavolato’s attempt to épater le bourgeois reveals this innate hypocrisy within society. Prostitutes are for the sexual social network an inextricable yet alternative and hence “lower” or “marginal” sexuality, a threat that reinforces the illusion of the stability of marriage, the institution whose scope is the reproduction of children. Prostitutes, often depicted as sterile by theorists such as Lombroso, do not contribute to “the future.”9 They are queer, outside of the norm. Marinetti’s rhetorical rejection of homosexuality functions in the same way — it reinforces the virile and homo-social while maintaining the hetero-normative standards of the period. Marinetti makes use of the subversive quality of the queer for its ability to scandalize (hence the accusations of his being a “pink poet”) but limits his queerness to the symbolic, going to great lengths to differentiate himself from the queer on a real level. Edelman calls for a queer theory that resists this “logic of opposition” and rather than placing hope in some future that knows no form, proposes a refusal “of every substantialization of identity, which is always oppositionally defined, and by extension, history as a linear narrative (the poor man’s teleology) in which meaning succeeds in revealing itself — as itself — through time.”10 The future, as envisioned by Futurists during the first “heroic” phase of Futurism ending around 1915 upon Italy’s entry into the war, had little quantitative or real qualities, and was relegated rather to a utopic possibility. The second phase saw the entry into the real, into the political, with World War I as the catalyst for change within the movement. Between 1915, the year of the feud with Lacerba, and 1918, the year of the publication of L’isola dei baci, the rift between the queer Futurists and Marinetti widens. Marinetti’s programmatic rejection of his Decadent, Symbolist literary fathers, such as Oscar Wilde, d’Annunzio, Mallarmé, and Baudelaire by proclaiming them symptomatic of passatismo nietzschiano, as well as his entry into the political, are symptoms of the end of queer Futurism that takes place during this period.11 As Papini’s 1915 article, “Futurismo e Marinettismo,” makes clear, in defining himself as the Futurist, the prophetic Marinetti necessarily had to go about the operation of queering those ironic “Others” that had been a fundamental part of the movement at its inception.
4,119
<h4>Prostitutes are seen as threatening because they do not contribute to the future – their non-domesticized sexuality is labeled queer because it resists the perfect control of reproductive futurism.</h4><p><strong>Van Ness ’10</strong>, Emma Van Ness, Ph.D candidate at UCLA, MA in Italian literature and film from Middlebury, (No) Queer Futurism: Prostitutes, Pink Poets, and Politics in Italy from 1913-1918, Carte Italiane 2(6), Peer Reviewed</p><p>Recent studies in queer theory shed some light on the relationship between the periodization of Futurism and its relationship with homosexuality. Lee Edelman, in his work No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, discusses politics, “reproductive futurism,” and the symbol of the child. <u><mark>Queer theory must present </mark>itself as <mark>an alternative to the tyranny of reproductive futurism</u></mark>, with its scope as the founding of <u>a</u> better world for our children. He states:</p><p>[At] the heart of my polemical engagement with the cultural text of politics and the politics of cultural texts lies a simple provocation: <u>that queerness names the side of those not “fighting for the children,” the side outside the consensus which all politics confirms the absolute value of reproductive futurism.</u> . . [so that] queerness. . . figures outside and beyond its political symptoms, the place of the social order’s<u> death drive.7</p><p>The</u> praise of war, the élan vital, and the <u><mark>contempt for woman</mark> and sentimentality <mark>present in </mark>the <mark>destructive</mark>, first phase of </u>Italian<u> <mark>Futurism </mark>all <mark>point to the queerness of the </mark>artistic and literary <mark>movement that comes to be replaced with political engagement</u></mark> following World War I. Yet <u>queerness also signifies resistance to bourgeois morality and traditional moral codes within the context of Futurism</u>, and Tavolato sought to combat precisely this with his literary production, especially in his praise of prostitution. As Edelman writes: “<u>Queerness attains its ethical value precisely insofar as it accedes to that place, accepting its figural status as resistance to the viability of the social while insisting on the inextricability of such resistance from every social structure</u>.”8 Tavolato’s attempt to épater le bourgeois reveals this innate hypocrisy within society. <u><strong><mark>Prostitutes are for the sexual social network an inextricable yet alternative and hence</mark> “lower” or “<mark>marginal” sexuality, a threat that reinforces the illusion of the stability of marriage, the institution whose scope is the reproduction of children. Prostitutes</strong></mark>, often <strong><mark>depicted as sterile</mark> </strong>by theorists such as Lombroso, <strong><mark>do not contribute to “the future</strong></mark>.”9 <mark>They are queer</mark>, outside of the norm.</p><p></u>Marinetti’s rhetorical rejection of homosexuality functions in the same way — it reinforces the virile and homo-social while maintaining the hetero-normative standards of the period. Marinetti makes use of the subversive quality of the queer for its ability to scandalize (hence the accusations of his being a “pink poet”) but limits his queerness to the symbolic, going to great lengths to differentiate himself from the queer on a real level. Edelman calls for a<u> <mark>queer theory</mark> </u>that<u> <mark>resists this “logic of opposition” and rather than placing hope in some future that knows no form</mark>, p<mark>roposes a refusal “of every substantialization of identity</mark>, which is always oppositionally defined, <mark>and</mark> by extension, <mark>history as a linear narrative</u></mark> (the poor man’s teleology) <u><mark>in which meaning</mark> <mark>succeeds in revealing itself</u></mark> — as itself — <u><mark>through time</u></mark>.”10 The future, as envisioned by Futurists during the first “heroic” phase of Futurism ending around 1915 upon Italy’s entry into the war, had little quantitative or real qualities, and was relegated rather to a utopic possibility. The second phase saw the entry into the real, into the political, with World War I as the catalyst for change within the movement. Between 1915, the year of the feud with Lacerba, and 1918, the year of the publication of L’isola dei baci, the rift between the queer Futurists and Marinetti widens. Marinetti’s programmatic rejection of his Decadent, Symbolist literary fathers, such as Oscar Wilde, d’Annunzio, Mallarmé, and Baudelaire by proclaiming them symptomatic of passatismo nietzschiano, as well as his entry into the political, are symptoms of the end of queer Futurism that takes place during this period.11 As Papini’s 1915 article, “Futurismo e Marinettismo,” makes clear, in defining himself as the Futurist, the prophetic Marinetti necessarily had to go about the operation of queering those ironic “Others” that had been a fundamental part of the movement at its inception.</p>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,619
3
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,249
Indepedently, the movement part of the aff is extra-T and permits all sorts of non-topical actions that we could never be ready to debate – lets them choose their own topic areas – independent voting issue
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><u><strong>Indepedently, the movement part of the aff is extra-T and permits all sorts of non-topical actions that we could never be ready to debate – lets them choose their own topic areas – independent voting issue</h4></u></strong>
null
null
1NC
430,621
1
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,250
Rhetoric demonizing the prostitute abounds with appeals in the name of “the children.” Prohibition of prostitution attempts to maintain the purity of a patriarchal, domestic, and ultimately mythic social order.
Hubbard ’98
Hubbard ’98, Phil Hubbard, Prof. at University of Coventry, UK, “Sexuality, immorality and the city: Red-light districts and the marginalisation of female street prostitutes,” Gender, Place and Culture,
debates about the place of prostitution in the area focused on the figure of the street prostitute. The stereotyped notion of vulgar and conspicuous sex was prevalent in discourses opposing the presence of prostitution , according to one prostitute: It makes me furious when women are portrayed as walking, downtrodden victims foul-mouthed junkies, who are violent and who were abused as kids ('Barbara' cited in Scambler, 1997, p. 105). the female street worker was taken as a signifier of the sexual commodification of women's bodies. This notion of display, with street workers forced to adopt specified codes of dress to mark themselves 'for sale', is one that has featured heavily in the promise of 'unfettered sex' in exchange for money is a threat to the stability of a patriarchal society in which domesticised, vanilla hetero-sex is constructed as the norm. this predatory female sexual role is antithetical to patriarchal conventions which associate femininity with passivity, suggesting that the sight of women taking a more active sexual role is one that provokes considerable male anxiety. the sight of the exposed female body of the prostitute has been incorporated into circuits of masculine desire, and that this stereotyped body image is central to the establishment of heterosexual norms in society this sight is regulated and morally condemned because of the notion that it assaults standards of public decency. The conspicuous display of feminine sexuality through specific forms of comportment and dress is seen as transgressing social conventions, a fact recognised by many prostitutes who argue that they are subverting gendered expectations of appropriate behaviour for women [15]. This of course relates to much longer traditions of female bodily identities as immoral, with no possibility of a female flaneur, only the prostitute (Wilson, 1995). The Wolfenden Act, which preceded the 1959 Street Offense Act, makes this point clear, arguing that the control of the prostition is justified by 'the right of the normal decent citizen to go about the streets without affront to their sense of decency' (Scambler, 1997). What is significant is that this construction of the 'decent' citizen appears to be based around the notion of a femininely-defined personage, with males seeking to protect the 'innocent' female gaze the idea that prostitute women were morally polluting through their displays of 'dangerously underclad young prostitutes' claimed 'these girls must be taken off the streets of our suburbs for the sake of decent residents--and for their children 'young people growing up who need protection from the sights and sounds of vice'. Protesters reinforced this point claiming 'I know I'm living in a red-light district, and I don't have a problem with that but it's the impact on my children's way of life which concerns me' and another reporting that he didn't have a problem with it, but suppose my grandchildren had been with me' when prostitutes started soliciting in the mornings to avoid the pickets there was a moral outcry that this would bring prostitutes' into full view of children on their way to school' the idea that street prostitution was an assault against public decency was frequently restated, with resident women and childre depicted as the vulnerable 'victims' of street prostitution this idea that the visibility of street prostitutes was corrupting the local community, and, more especially, children appeared as a impetus to the Street Watch campaign.
The stereotyped notion of vulgar sex was prevalent in discourses opposing prostitution female street worker was taken as a signifier of sexual commodification of women's bodies the promise of 'unfettered sex' in exchange for money is a threat to the stability of a patriarchal society in which domesticised, hetero-sex is constructed as the norm this predatory female sexual role is antithetical to patriarchal conventions which associate femininity with passivity the sight of the exposed female body has been incorporated into masculine desire, and that this stereotyped body image is central to the establishment of heterosexual norms in society the idea that prostitute women were morally polluting claimed 'these girls must be taken off the streets for the sake of decent residents--and their children' 'young people growing up need protection from the sights of vice' the impact on my children's life concerns me' suppose my grandchildren had been with me' when prostitutes started soliciting in the mornings there was a moral outcry that this would bring prostitutes' into full view of children on their way to school' the idea prostitution was an assault against decency was frequently restated, with resident children depicted as the 'victims' of prostitution
Although street prostitution coexisted with window-working in Balsall Heath, the debates about the place of prostitution in the area focused on the figure of the street prostitute. The stereotyped notion of the street-walker as the embodiment of vulgar and conspicuous sex was prevalent in local discourses opposing the presence of prostitution, although, according to one prostitute: It makes me furious when women are portrayed as walking, downtrodden victims... Why are girls portrayed the way they are in the media? We are portrayed as women who stand on street corners, who wear microscopic mini-skirts, who are foul-mouthed junkies, who are violent and who were abused as kids ('Barbara' cited in Scambler, 1997, p. 105). Nonetheless, the media coverage was replete with voyeuristic images including some culled from national press files of other cities, of 'highly painted young girls, skirted up to the thigh' (The Sunday Telegraph, 6 November 1994), as the female street worker was taken as a signifier of the sexual commodification of women's bodies. This notion of display, with street workers forced to adopt specified codes of dress to mark themselves 'for sale', is one that has featured heavily in the development of the 'whore stigma' through conspicuous vulgarity--and the promise of 'unfettered sex' in exchange for money is seen as a threat to the stability of a patriarchal society in which domesticised, vanilla hetero-sex is constructed as the norm. Bondi 1998 further contends that this predatory female sexual role is antithetical to patriarchal conventions which associate femininity with passivity, suggesting that the sight of women taking a more active sexual role is one that provokes considerable male anxiety. Undoubtedly, the urge to exclude prostitutes from the street was magnified by the challenge that street prostitution was seen to posit to the collective identity of the local Muslim population, whose use of the term 'prostitute' as a pejorative term to describe any 'non-conforming' Muslim woman has been well-documented (Sabbah, 1984). Simultaneously though, Kirby 1996 suggests that the sight of the exposed female body of the prostitute has been incorporated into circuits of masculine desire, and that this stereotyped body image is central to the establishment of heterosexual norms in society, whether Muslim or otherwise. She also argues that this sight is regulated and morally condemned because of the notion that it assaults standards of public decency. The conspicuous display of feminine sexuality through specific forms of comportment and dress is seen as transgressing social conventions, a fact recognised by many prostitutes who argue that they are subverting gendered expectations of appropriate behaviour for women [15]. This of course relates to much longer traditions of female bodily identities as immoral, with no possibility of a female flaneur, only the prostitute (Wilson, 1995). The Wolfenden Act, which preceded the 1959 Street Offense Act, makes this point clear, arguing that the control of the prostition is justified by 'the right of the normal decent citizen to go about the streets without affront to their sense of decency' (Scambler, 1997). What is significant is that this construction of the 'decent' citizen appears to be based around the notion of a femininely-defined personage, with males seeking to protect the 'innocent' female gaze. Thus, while many campaigners claimed that theirs 'was not a moral crusade' and they had 'nothing against prostitutes' (Birmingham Post, 27 March 1993), the idea that prostitute women were morally polluting through their displays of 'dangerously underclad young prostitutes' on the street claimed 'these girls must be taken off the streets of our suburbs for the sake of decent residents--and for their children' (Birmingham Evening Mail, 13 February 1995). Another article spoke of 'young people growing up who need protection from the sights and sounds of vice'. Protesters reinforced this point, one claiming that 'I know I'm living in a red-light district, and I don't have a problem with that--after all, I lived in Amsterdam for 3 years, but it's the impact on my children's way of life which concerns me' (Express and Star, 13 1994), and another reporting that he became involved on the day he saw a prostitute with a 'near naked client... I didn't have a problem with it, but suppose my grandchildren had been with me' [6]. Furthermore, when prostitutes started soliciting in the mornings to avoid the pickets, there was a moral outcry that this would bring prostitutes' into full view of children on their way to school' (Birmingham Evening Mail, 16 May 1995). Consequently, the idea that street prostitution was an assault against public decency was frequently restated, with resident women and children, not the prostitutes themselves, depicted as the vulnerable 'victims' of the sight of street prostitution. It was this idea that the visibility of street prostitutes was corrupting the local community, and, more especially, virtuous women and children, that appeared as a fundamental impetus to the organisation of the predominantly male and masculine Street Watch campaign.
5,206
<h4>Rhetoric demonizing the prostitute abounds with appeals in the name of “the children.” Prohibition of prostitution attempts to maintain the purity of a patriarchal, domestic, and ultimately mythic social order.</h4><p><strong>Hubbard ’98</strong>, Phil Hubbard, Prof. at University of Coventry, UK, “Sexuality, immorality and the city: Red-light districts and the marginalisation of female street prostitutes,” Gender, Place and Culture<u>, </p><p></u>Although street prostitution coexisted with window-working in Balsall Heath, the <u>debates about the place of prostitution in the area focused on the figure of the street prostitute. <mark>The stereotyped notion of</mark> </u>the street-walker as the embodiment of <u><mark>vulgar </mark>and conspicuous <mark>sex was</mark> <mark>prevalent in</u></mark> local <u><mark>discourses opposing </mark>the presence of <mark>prostitution</u></mark>, although<u>, according to one prostitute:</p><p>It makes me furious when women are portrayed as walking, downtrodden victims</u>... Why are girls portrayed the way they are in the media? We are portrayed as women who stand on street corners, who wear microscopic mini-skirts, who are <u>foul-mouthed junkies, who are violent and who were abused as kids ('Barbara' cited in Scambler, 1997, p. 105).</p><p></u>Nonetheless, the media coverage was replete with voyeuristic images including some culled from national press files of other cities, of 'highly painted young girls, skirted up to the thigh' (The Sunday Telegraph, 6 November 1994), as <u>the <mark>female street worker was taken as a signifier of</mark> the <mark>sexual commodification of women's bodies</mark>. This notion of display, with street workers forced to adopt specified codes of dress to mark themselves 'for sale', is one that has featured heavily in</u> the development of the 'whore stigma' through conspicuous vulgarity--and <u><strong><mark>the promise of 'unfettered sex' in exchange for money is</strong></mark> </u>seen as<u> <strong><mark>a threat to the stability of a patriarchal society in which domesticised, </mark>vanilla <mark>hetero-sex is constructed as the norm</strong></mark>.</u> Bondi 1998 further contends that<u> <strong><mark>this predatory female sexual role is antithetical to patriarchal conventions which associate femininity with passivity</strong></mark>, suggesting that the sight of women taking a more active sexual role is one that provokes considerable male anxiety. </p><p></u>Undoubtedly, the urge to exclude prostitutes from the street was magnified by the challenge that street prostitution was seen to posit to the collective identity of the local Muslim population, whose use of the term 'prostitute' as a pejorative term to describe any 'non-conforming' Muslim woman has been well-documented (Sabbah, 1984). Simultaneously though, Kirby 1996 suggests that <u><mark>the sight of the exposed female body </mark>of the prostitute <mark>has been incorporated into </mark>circuits of <mark>masculine desire, and that this stereotyped body image is <strong>central to the establishment</strong> of heterosexual norms in society</u></mark>, whether Muslim or otherwise. She also argues that <u>this sight is regulated and morally condemned because of the notion that it assaults standards of public decency. The conspicuous display of feminine sexuality through specific forms of comportment and dress is seen as transgressing social conventions, a fact recognised by many prostitutes who argue that they are subverting gendered expectations of appropriate behaviour for women [15]. This of course relates to much longer traditions of female bodily identities as immoral, with no possibility of a female flaneur, only the prostitute (Wilson, 1995). The Wolfenden Act, which preceded the 1959 Street Offense Act, makes this point clear, arguing that the control of the prostition is justified by 'the right of the normal decent citizen to go about the streets without affront to their sense of decency' (Scambler, 1997).</p><p>What is significant is that this construction of the 'decent' citizen appears to be based around the notion of a femininely-defined personage, with males seeking to protect the 'innocent' female gaze</u>. Thus, while many campaigners claimed that theirs 'was not a moral crusade' and they had 'nothing against prostitutes' (Birmingham Post, 27 March 1993), <u><mark>the idea that prostitute women were morally polluting </mark>through their displays of 'dangerously underclad young prostitutes'</u> on the street <u><mark>claimed <strong>'these girls must be taken off the streets </mark>of our suburbs <mark>for the sake of decent residents--and </mark>for <mark>their children</u></strong>'</mark> (Birmingham Evening Mail, 13 February 1995). Another article spoke of <u><strong><mark>'young people growing up</mark> who <mark>need protection from the sights </mark>and sounds<mark> of vice'</strong></mark>. Protesters reinforced this point</u>, one <u>claiming</u> that <u>'I know I'm living in a red-light district, and I don't have a problem with that</u>--after all, I lived in Amsterdam for 3 years, <u><strong>but it's <mark>the impact on my children's </mark>way of <mark>life </mark>which <mark>concerns me'</u></strong></mark> (Express and Star, 13 1994), <u>and another reporting that he</u> became involved on the day he saw a prostitute with a 'near naked client... I <u>didn't have a problem with it, but</u> <u><strong><mark>suppose my grandchildren had been with me'</mark> </u></strong>[6]. Furthermore, <u><mark>when prostitutes started soliciting in the mornings</mark> to avoid the pickets</u>, <u><strong><mark>there was a moral outcry that this would bring prostitutes' into full view of children on their way to school'</u></strong></mark> (Birmingham Evening Mail, 16 May 1995). Consequently, <u><mark>the idea </mark>that street <mark>prostitution was an assault against </mark>public <mark>decency was frequently restated, with resident</mark> women and <mark>childre</u>n</mark>, not the prostitutes themselves, <u><mark>depicted as the </mark>vulnerable <mark>'victims' of</u></mark> the sight of <u>street <mark>prostitution</u></mark>. It was <u>this idea that the visibility of street prostitutes was corrupting the local community, and, more especially,</u> virtuous women and <u>children</u>, that <u>appeared as a </u>fundamental <u>impetus to the</u> organisation of the predominantly male and masculine <u>Street Watch campaign.</p></u>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,622
2
17,077
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
565,297
A
tournament
4
Binghamton Cepin-Sehgal
Baker, Webster Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,251
With organs, altruism is even less likely to be affected since the donations are primarily for friends and relatives
Gill 2
Gill 2 Michael Gill, Ph.D., Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, College of Charleston AND Robert Sade, M.D.,Professor in the Department of Surgery and Director of the Institute of Human Values in Health Care, Medical University of South Carolina. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12.1 (2002) 17-45
In the early 1970s, Titmuss and Singer argued that the existence of financial incentives for blood products would decrease the amount of blood products overall, and some people might believe that the same argument can be extended to financial incentives for kidneys, first the available evidence does not support the conclusion that payment for blood products has reduced blood supply in the U S secondly, because live kidney donations are usually between family members, there is a significant difference between blood and kidneys that makes it illegitimate to transfer Titmuss and Singer's conclusions to the kidney debate. We do, however, remain open to the possibility that future evidence may vitiate our belief that payment for kidneys will increase supplies. For discussion of Titmuss and Singer in relation to kidney sales, see Campbell (1992, pp. 41-42); Cherry (2000, pp. 340-41); and Harvey (1999, p. 119).
evidence does not support the conclusion that payment for blood has reduced blood supply in the U St secondly, because live kidney donations are usually between family members, there is a significant difference between blood and kidneys that makes it illegitimate to transfer Titmuss and Singer's conclusions to the kidney debate.
Paying for Kidneys: The Case against Prohibition http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/kennedy_institute_ of_ethics_journal/v012/12.1gill.html 3. In the early 1970s, Titmuss (1971) and Singer (1973) argued that the existence of financial incentives for blood products would decrease the amount of blood products overall, and some people might believe that the same argument can be extended to financial incentives for kidneys, leading to the conclusion that payment for kidneys will decrease the overall number of kidneys available for transplant. Singer and Titmuss's criticisms of payment for blood products are consequentialist—they argue that such payment is wrong because it would reduce the amount of blood for people who needed it. We believe, first of all, that their consequentialist arguments against payment for blood products have turned out to be inconclusive at best—that the available evidence does not support the conclusion that payment for blood products has reduced blood supply in the United States. And we believe, secondly, that because live kidney donations are usually between family members, there is a significant difference between blood and kidneys that makes it illegitimate to transfer Titmuss and Singer's conclusions to the kidney debate. We do, however, remain open to the possibility that future evidence may vitiate our belief that payment for kidneys will increase supplies. For discussion of Titmuss and Singer in relation to kidney sales, see Campbell (1992, pp. 41-42); Cherry (2000, pp. 340-41); and Harvey (1999, p. 119).
1,554
<h4>With organs, altruism is even less likely to be affected since the donations are primarily for friends and relatives</h4><p><strong>Gill 2</strong> Michael Gill, Ph.D., Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, College of Charleston AND Robert Sade, M.D.,Professor in the Department of Surgery and Director of the Institute of Human Values in Health Care, Medical University of South Carolina. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12.1 (2002) 17-45</p><p>Paying for Kidneys: The Case against Prohibition http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/kennedy_institute_ of_ethics_journal/v012/12.1gill.html</p><p>3. <u>In the early 1970s, Titmuss</u> (1971) <u>and Singer</u> (1973) <u>argued that the existence of financial incentives for blood products would decrease the amount of blood products overall, and some people might believe that the same argument can be extended to financial incentives for kidneys,</u> leading to the conclusion that payment for kidneys will decrease the overall number of kidneys available for transplant. Singer and Titmuss's criticisms of payment for blood products are consequentialist—they argue that such payment is wrong because it would reduce the amount of blood for people who needed it. We believe, <u>first </u>of all, that their consequentialist arguments against payment for blood products have turned out to be inconclusive at best—that <u>the available <mark>evidence does not support the conclusion that payment for blood </mark>products<mark> has reduced blood supply in the U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u>t</mark>ates. And we believe, <u><mark>secondly,</mark> </u>that<u> <mark>because live kidney donations are usually between family members, there is a significant difference between blood and kidneys that makes it illegitimate to transfer Titmuss and Singer's conclusions to the kidney debate.</mark> We do, however, remain open to the possibility that future evidence may vitiate our belief that payment for kidneys will increase supplies. For discussion of Titmuss and Singer in relation to kidney sales, see Campbell (1992, pp. 41-42); Cherry (2000, pp. 340-41); and Harvey (1999, p. 119). </p></u>
null
null
Contention 1 – Organ sales will save lives
430,252
7
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,252
New sanctions destroy the Iran deal- causes prolif and Israel strikes- extinction
Borger 12/31
Borger 12/31/2014 (Julian, the Guardian's diplomatic editor. He was previously a correspondent in the US, the Middle East, eastern Europe and the Balkans, A nuclear deal with Iran would mean a less volatile world, A nuclear deal with Iran would mean a less volatile world, http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/dec/31/nuclear-deal-iran-cuba-proliferation)
There will be no greater diplomatic prize in 2015 than a comprehensive nuclear deal with Iran. In its global significance, it would dwarf the US detente with Cuba This deal will be about nuclear proliferation in the most volatile region on Earth gaps remain substantial, but none of the parties involved can walk away A collapse of talks would lead to a slide back to the edge of conflict between Iran and Israel the latter has vowed to launch military strikes rather than allow the former to build a bomb. It could also trigger a wave of proliferation across the region and beyond as other countries hedge their bets. the parties to the talks have given themselves more time They have resumed meetings in Geneva, with an emphasis on sessions between the two most important countries, the US and Iran the White House can no longer rely on a Democratic majority leader to keep new sanctions legislation off the Senate floor legislation now under discussion could take the form of triggered sanctions That would provoke counter-measures from Iran’s parliament and a very volatile environment.
no greater diplomatic prize in 2015 than a comprehensive nuclear deal with Iran. is deal will b about nuclear proliferation in the most volatile region on Earth A collapse of talks would lead to a slide back to the edge of conflict between Iran and Israel; the latter has vowed to launch military strikes rather than allow the former to build a bomb. It could also trigger a wave of proliferation across the region and beyond as other countries hedge their bets anctions would also provoke counter-measures from Iran’s parliament and a very volatile environment
There will be no greater diplomatic prize in 2015 than a comprehensive nuclear deal with Iran. In its global significance, it would dwarf the US detente with Cuba, and not just because there are seven times more Iranians than Cubans. This deal will not be about cash machines in the Caribbean, but about nuclear proliferation in the most volatile region on Earth. An agreement was supposed to have been reached by 24 November, but Iran and the west were too far apart to make the final leap. After nine months of bargaining, the intricate, multidimensional negotiation boiled down to two main obstacles: Iran’s long-term capacity to enrich uranium, and the speed and scale of sanctions relief. Iran wants international recognition of its right not just to enrich, but to do so on an industrial scale. It wants to maintain its existing infrastructure of 10,000 centrifuges in operation and another 9,000 on standby, and it wants to be able to scale that capacity up many times. The US and its allies say Tehran has no need for so much enriched uranium. Its one existing reactor is Russian-built, as are its planned reactors, so all of them come with Russian-supplied fuel as part of the contract. The fear is that industrial enrichment capacity would allow Iran to make a bomb’s-worth of weapons-grade uranium very quickly, if it decided it needed one – faster than the international community could react. However, the west is currently not offering large-scale, immediate sanctions relief in return for such curbs on Iran’s activity. President Barack Obama can only temporarily suspend US congressional sanctions, and western states are prepared to reverse only some elements of UN security council sanctions. The best the west can offer upfront is a lifting of the EU oil embargo. These gaps remain substantial, but none of the parties involved can walk away from the table. A collapse of talks would lead to a slide back to the edge of conflict between Iran and Israel; the latter has vowed to launch military strikes rather than allow the former to build a bomb. It could also trigger a wave of proliferation across the region and beyond as other countries hedge their bets. So the parties to the talks have given themselves more time – until 1 March 2015 – to agree a framework deal for bridging them and until 1 July to work out all of the details. They have resumed meetings in Geneva, with an emphasis on sessions between the two most important countries, the US and Iran. The trouble is that, while the diplomats inside the chamber sense that they are still making progress in closing the gaps, the sceptics back home just see deceit and playing for time by the other side. This is particularly true of the US Congress. A new Republican-controlled Senate will convene on 6 January. From that date, the White House can no longer rely on a Democratic majority leader to keep new sanctions legislation off the Senate floor. The legislation now under discussion could take the form of triggered sanctions, which would come into effect if there was no deal by a target date. That would add urgency to the negotiations, undoubtedly a good thing, but it would also provoke counter-measures from Iran’s parliament, the Majlis, and a very volatile environment. It is possible that the Republican leadership in the Senate will choose other battles to fight with the president before trying to build a veto-proof majority on sanctions, but the pressure will build exponentially if there is no deal on the table on 1 March. It could be the most important diplomatic date of the year.
3,580
<h4>New sanctions destroy the Iran deal- causes prolif and Israel strikes- extinction</h4><p><strong>Borger 12/31</strong>/2014 (Julian, the Guardian's diplomatic editor. He was previously a correspondent in the US, the Middle East, eastern Europe and the Balkans, A nuclear deal with Iran would mean a less volatile world, A nuclear deal with Iran would mean a less volatile world, http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/dec/31/nuclear-deal-iran-cuba-proliferation)</p><p><u>There will be <mark>no greater diplomatic prize in 2015 than a comprehensive nuclear deal with Iran.</mark> In its global significance, it would dwarf the US detente with Cuba</u>, and not just because there are seven times more Iranians than Cubans. <u>Th<mark>is deal will</u></mark> not <u><mark>b</mark>e</u> about cash machines in the Caribbean, but <u><mark>about nuclear proliferation in the most volatile region on Earth</u></mark>. An agreement was supposed to have been reached by 24 November, but Iran and the west were too far apart to make the final leap. After nine months of bargaining, the intricate, multidimensional negotiation boiled down to two main obstacles: Iran’s long-term capacity to enrich uranium, and the speed and scale of sanctions relief. Iran wants international recognition of its right not just to enrich, but to do so on an industrial scale. It wants to maintain its existing infrastructure of 10,000 centrifuges in operation and another 9,000 on standby, and it wants to be able to scale that capacity up many times. The US and its allies say Tehran has no need for so much enriched uranium. Its one existing reactor is Russian-built, as are its planned reactors, so all of them come with Russian-supplied fuel as part of the contract. The fear is that industrial enrichment capacity would allow Iran to make a bomb’s-worth of weapons-grade uranium very quickly, if it decided it needed one – faster than the international community could react. However, the west is currently not offering large-scale, immediate sanctions relief in return for such curbs on Iran’s activity. President Barack Obama can only temporarily suspend US congressional sanctions, and western states are prepared to reverse only some elements of UN security council sanctions. The best the west can offer upfront is a lifting of the EU oil embargo. These <u>gaps remain substantial, but none of the parties involved can walk away</u> from the table. <u><strong><mark>A collapse of talks would lead to a slide back to the edge of conflict between Iran and Israel</u></strong>; <u>the latter has vowed to launch military strikes rather than allow the former to build a bomb. It could also trigger a <strong>wave of proliferation across the region and beyond</strong> as other countries hedge their bets</mark>. </u>So <u>the parties to the talks have given themselves more time</u> – until 1 March 2015 – to agree a framework deal for bridging them and until 1 July to work out all of the details. <u>They have resumed meetings in Geneva, with an emphasis on sessions between the two most important countries, the US and Iran</u>. The trouble is that, while the diplomats inside the chamber sense that they are still making progress in closing the gaps, the sceptics back home just see deceit and playing for time by the other side. This is particularly true of the US Congress. A new Republican-controlled Senate will convene on 6 January. From that date, <u>the White House can no longer rely on a Democratic majority leader to keep new sanctions legislation off the Senate floor</u>. The <u>legislation now under discussion could take the form of triggered s<mark>anctions</u></mark>, which would come into effect if there was no deal by a target date. <u>That</u> would add urgency to the negotiations, undoubtedly a good thing, but it <u><mark>would</u> also <u>provoke counter-measures from Iran’s parliament</u></mark>, the Majlis, <u><mark>and a very volatile environment</mark>. </u>It is possible that the Republican leadership in the Senate will choose other battles to fight with the president before trying to build a veto-proof majority on sanctions, but the pressure will build exponentially if there is no deal on the table on 1 March. It could be the most important diplomatic date of the year.</p>
null
null
DA
171,429
23
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,253
Ableism makes ongoing eugenics and extermination inevitable
Brown 11
Brown 11, Artist Initiative Grantee at Minnesota State Arts Board Senior Academic Adviser for the College of Education and Human Development at University of Minnesota Steering Committee at Education Abroad Network at University of Minnesota Volunteer Coordinator for Social Inclusion and Bullying Prevention at Marcy Open School see less Past 2012-2013 Buckman Fellow at Buckman Fellowship Travel and Study Grantee at Jerome Foundation Loft Mentor Series Award Winner for Poetry at The Loft Literary Center Institute on Community Integration Post-graduate Certificate Graduate Student at University of Minnesota University of Minnesota College of Education and Human Development/University Honors Program Liaison at University of Minnesota University Honors Program Academic Advisor at University of Minnesota University of Minnesota Learning Abroad Center/University Honors Program Liaison at University of Minnesota Foreign Lecturer--English Studies, Cultural Awareness, Humanities at Hokkaido University of Education Educational Technologies post-grad certificate program at University of British Columbia, Vancouver Adjunct Lecturer--Japanese Language at Wayne County Community College Adjunct Lecturer--English Composition at Wayne State University Foriegn Lecturer--English Studies, Creative Writing, English Literature at Sophia University--Tokyo, Japan ‘Screw normal’: Resisting the myth of normal by questioning media’s depiction of people with autism and their families, http://blog.lib.umn.edu/gara0030/iggds/Screw%20Normal_FINAL_Dosch%20Brown.pdf
The one societal need in our society that is often unacknowledged, silenced, and left unexamined is that humans have deep, visceral need to belong The media creates walls between its ideals and the people it views as Others when the media views people with autism as ‘abnormal mysteries’. We are being taught that differences occurring from autism are wrong, and too many families depicted in the media perpetuate this negative view of their own children. Michalko said the difference in his blindness must be grappled with inside his being in ―a space between nature and culture‖ and ―normal and abnormal it is within this confusing, unmarked space where he has had to build his own identity. By moving through the world with his ―body of blindness,‖ Michalko has projected himself into the ―social space society reacts to people who have disabilities who cannot live up to the mythical norms with ―help, ―pity, ―ridicule, ―unease,‖ and ―curiosity it results in an unequal power structure that creates treacherous terrain for all of us who have been Othered. mainstream Western society views all disabilities as abnormal, and it thus approaches people with disability as tragic people who live lives ―not worth living complexity, diversity, and range of differences of all human beings in this world are erased, denied, and ignored under a banner of ‗sameness‘ or ‗normalcy‘—and those who cannot or will not conform are silenced and lumped into the category of Other, and dealt with suspicion for not conforming to social construction of what is acceptable in appearance, behavior, and experience. Eugenics is still very much present in societal attitudes toward disability. Eugenics formalized ―the Normal, a cultural landscape outlined in order to support the hegemony of its inhabitants, a liberalist bourgeois class of white, able-bodied men By silencing those with perceived disabilities (or those with a particular perceived race, ethnicity, gender, or sexual orientation, etc.) and deeming them as lesser than ‘normal‘ humans—society is able to continue to deny that ‘being normal‘ is actually a socially constructed myth those who committed the war crimes by killing or sterilizing people they had deemed of inferior intelligence in the Nazis T-4 project were consistently given less severe convictions and higher acquittal rates revealing as a society we devalue the lost lives of those considered too different from the mythical norm, which we will demonstrate later is a devaluation of human life very much alive in media depiction of autism. Society rarely has ears for the voices or rooms reserved for those with differences who think otherwise The media maintains this gaping silence as well. Society, either expects those deemed ―abnormal‖ will ―get through their differences by adapting to the dominant rules, so as to be less noticed, or it expects them to ―get out‖ by removing themselves from view, by being silent and isolated
The one societal need in our society that is often unacknowledged, silenced, and left unexamined is that humans have, deep, visceral need to belong The media creates walls between its ideals and the people it views as Others it results in an unequal power structure that creates treacherous terrain for all of us who have been Othered complexity, diversity, and range of differences of all human beings in this world are erased, denied, and ignored under a banner of ‗sameness‘ or ‗normalcy‘—and those who cannot or will not conform are silenced and lumped into the category of Other Eugenics formalized ―the Normal, a cultural landscape outlined in order to support the hegemony of its inhabitants, a liberalist bourgeois class of white, able-bodied men By silencing those with perceived disabilities (or those with a particular perceived race, ethnicity, gender, or sexual orientation, and deeming them as lesser than ‘normal‘ humans—society is able to continue to deny that ‘being normal‘ is actually a socially constructed myth those who committed the war crimes by killing or sterilizing people ere consistently given less severe convictions and higher acquittal rates The media maintains this gaping silence as wel Society expects those deemed ―abnormal will get through their differences by adapting to the dominant rules by removing themselves from view, by being silent and isolated
The one societal need in our society that is often unacknowledged, silenced, and left unexamined is that humans have, as Michalko quoted Cornel West, the ―deep, visceral need to belong‖ (Michalko, 2002, p. 81) — all of us struggle with full acceptance of ourselves and our desire to be seen as acceptable or welcome in a society that loves to label people. The media creates walls between its ideals and the people it views as Others, such as when the media views people with autism as ‘abnormal mysteries’. We are being taught that differences occurring from autism are wrong, and sadly too many families depicted in the media perpetuate this negative view of their own children. When thinking of ‗normal‘ henceforth, let‘s consider what Michalko wrote about society and his blindness. He explained that, although society might have found ways technologically for him to participate (he is a professor), he is still seen as ‗strange‘ because he is blind. He said the difference in his blindness must be grappled with inside his being in ―a space between nature and culture‖ and ―normal and abnormal‖ (2002, p. 83), and it is within this confusing, unmarked space where he has had to build his own identity. By moving through the world with his ―body of blindness,‖ Michalko has projected himself into the ―social space,‖ just as my son must project his own self, by moving through the social space with his ‗mind of difference‘; thus, society reacts to people who have disabilities who cannot live up to the mythical norms with ―help, ―pity, ―ridicule, ―unease,‖ and ―curiosity‖ (2002, p. 88), and it results in an unequal power structure that creates treacherous terrain for all of us who have been Othered. Michalko (2002) noted that mainstream Western society views all disabilities as abnormal, and it thus approaches people with disability as tragic people who live lives ―not worth living‖; they are seen as the Other, as objects of pity, both ―vulnerable and fragile‖ (p.68). The complexity, diversity, and range of differences of all human beings in this world are erased, denied, and ignored under a banner of ‗sameness‘ or ‗normalcy‘—and those who cannot or will not conform are silenced and lumped into the category of Other, and dealt with suspicion for not conforming to social construction of what is acceptable in appearance, behavior, and experience. Eugenics, the academic Phil Smith (2008) has concluded, is still very much present in societal attitudes toward disability. Eugenics formalized ―the Normal, a cultural landscape outlined in order to support the hegemony of its inhabitants, a liberalist bourgeois class of white, able-bodied men‖ (P. Smith, p. 419). By silencing those with perceived disabilities (or those with a particular perceived race, ethnicity, gender, or sexual orientation, etc.) and deeming them as lesser than ‘normal‘ humans—society is able to continue to deny that ‘being normal‘ is actually a socially constructed myth (Michalko, 2002, p. 69). Phil Smith further pointed out that not so long ago those who committed the war crimes by killing or sterilizing people they had deemed of inferior intelligence in the Nazis T-4 project were consistently given less severe convictions and higher acquittal rates (P. Smith, 2008, p. 421)—revealing, indeed, that as a society we devalue the lost lives of those considered too different from the mythical norm, which we will demonstrate later is a devaluation of human life very much alive in media depiction of autism. Society rarely has ears for the voices or rooms reserved for those with differences who think otherwise, and it rarely realizes that indeed people with differences also have value and critical roles to play in society. The media maintains this gaping silence as well. Society, Michalko has argued, either expects those deemed ―abnormal‖ will ―get through their differences by adapting to the dominant rules, so as to be less noticed, or it expects them to ―get out‖ by removing themselves from view, by being silent and isolated (Michalko, 2002, p. 75); and some experts, doctors, educators, and therapists make a sizable income from attempting to enforce these societal expectations on families.
4,204
<h4><strong>Ableism makes <u>ongoing eugenics and extermination inevitable</u> </h4><p>Brown 11</strong>, Artist Initiative Grantee at Minnesota State Arts Board Senior Academic Adviser for the College of Education and Human Development at University of Minnesota Steering Committee at Education Abroad Network at University of Minnesota Volunteer Coordinator for Social Inclusion and Bullying Prevention at Marcy Open School see less Past 2012-2013 Buckman Fellow at Buckman Fellowship Travel and Study Grantee at Jerome Foundation Loft Mentor Series Award Winner for Poetry at The Loft Literary Center Institute on Community Integration Post-graduate Certificate Graduate Student at University of Minnesota University of Minnesota College of Education and Human Development/University Honors Program Liaison at University of Minnesota University Honors Program Academic Advisor at University of Minnesota University of Minnesota Learning Abroad Center/University Honors Program Liaison at University of Minnesota Foreign Lecturer--English Studies, Cultural Awareness, Humanities at Hokkaido University of Education Educational Technologies post-grad certificate program at University of British Columbia, Vancouver Adjunct Lecturer--Japanese Language at Wayne County Community College Adjunct Lecturer--English Composition at Wayne State University Foriegn Lecturer--English Studies, Creative Writing, English Literature at Sophia University--Tokyo, Japan ‘Screw normal’: Resisting the myth of normal by questioning media’s depiction of people with autism and their families, http://blog.lib.umn.edu/gara0030/iggds/Screw%20Normal_FINAL_Dosch%20Brown.pdf</p><p><u><strong><mark>The one societal need in our society that is often unacknowledged, silenced, and left unexamined is that humans have</u></strong>,</mark> as Michalko quoted Cornel West, the ―<u><strong><mark>deep, visceral need to belong</u></strong></mark>‖ (Michalko, 2002, p. 81) — all of us struggle with full acceptance of ourselves and our desire to be seen as acceptable or welcome in a society that loves to label people. <u><strong><mark>The media creates walls between its ideals and the people it views as Others</u></strong></mark>, such as <u><strong>when the media views people with autism as ‘abnormal mysteries’. We are being taught that differences occurring from autism are wrong, and</u></strong> sadly <u><strong>too many families depicted in the media perpetuate this negative view of their own children. </u></strong>When thinking of ‗normal‘ henceforth, let‘s consider what <u><strong>Michalko</u></strong> wrote about society and his blindness. He explained that, although society might have found ways technologically for him to participate (he is a professor), he is still seen as ‗strange‘ because he is blind. He <u><strong>said the difference in his blindness must be grappled with inside his being in ―a space between nature and culture‖ and ―normal and abnormal</u></strong>‖ (2002, p. 83), and <u><strong>it is within this confusing, unmarked space where he has had to build his own identity. By moving through the world with his ―body of blindness,‖ Michalko has projected himself into the ―social space</u></strong>,‖ just as my son must project his own self, by moving through the social space with his ‗mind of difference‘; thus, <u><strong>society reacts to people who have disabilities who cannot live up to the mythical norms with ―help, ―pity, ―ridicule, ―unease,‖ and ―curiosity</u></strong>‖ (2002, p. 88), and <u><strong><mark>it results in an unequal power structure that creates treacherous terrain for all of us who have been Othered</mark>. </u></strong>Michalko (2002) noted that <u><strong>mainstream Western society views all disabilities as abnormal, and it thus approaches people with disability as tragic people who live lives ―not worth living</u></strong>‖; they are seen as the Other, as objects of pity, both ―vulnerable and fragile‖ (p.68). The <u><strong><mark>complexity, diversity, and range of differences of all human beings in this world are erased, denied, and ignored under a banner of ‗sameness‘ or ‗normalcy‘—and those who cannot or will not conform are silenced and lumped into the category of Other</mark>, and dealt with suspicion for not conforming to social construction of what is acceptable in appearance, behavior, and experience. Eugenics</u></strong>, the academic Phil Smith (2008) has concluded, <u><strong>is still very much present in societal attitudes toward disability. <mark>Eugenics formalized ―the Normal, a cultural landscape outlined in order to support the hegemony of its inhabitants, a liberalist bourgeois class of white, able-bodied men</u></strong></mark>‖ (P. Smith, p. 419). <u><strong><mark>By silencing those with perceived disabilities (or those with a particular perceived race, ethnicity, gender, or sexual orientation,</mark> etc.) <mark>and deeming them as lesser than ‘normal‘ humans—society is able to continue to deny that ‘being normal‘ is actually a socially constructed myth</u></strong></mark> (Michalko, 2002, p. 69). Phil Smith further pointed out that not so long ago <u><strong><mark>those who committed the war crimes by killing or sterilizing people</mark> they had deemed of inferior intelligence in the Nazis T-4 project w<mark>ere consistently given less severe convictions and higher acquittal rates</u></strong></mark> (P. Smith, 2008, p. 421)—<u><strong>revealing</u></strong>, indeed, that <u><strong>as a society we devalue the lost lives of those considered too different from the mythical norm, which we will demonstrate later is a devaluation of human life very much alive in media depiction of autism. Society rarely has ears for the voices or rooms reserved for those with differences who think otherwise</u></strong>, and it rarely realizes that indeed people with differences also have value and critical roles to play in society.<u><strong> <mark>The media maintains this gaping silence as wel</mark>l. <mark>Society</mark>, </u></strong>Michalko has argued, <u><strong>either <mark>expects those deemed ―abnormal</mark>‖ <mark>will</mark> ―<mark>get through their differences by adapting to the dominant rules</mark>, so as to be less noticed, or it expects them to ―get out‖ <mark>by removing themselves from view, by being silent and isolated</u></strong></mark> (Michalko, 2002, p. 75); and some experts, doctors, educators, and therapists make a sizable income from attempting to enforce these societal expectations on families.</p>
null
Case
CP
159,864
25
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,254
Evaluating risk with a one percent doctrine makes life impossible – everything could theoretically cause extinction
Meskill 09
Meskill 09 (David, professor at Colorado School of Mines and PhD from Harvard, “The "One Percent Doctrine" and Environmental Faith,” Dec 9, http://davidmeskill.blogspot.com/2009/12/one-percent-doctrine-and-environmental.html)
Friedman's piece applies Cheney's "one percent doctrine" to the risk of environmental armageddon. But this doctrine is both intellectually incoherent and practically irrelevant. it cannot be applied consistently in a world with many potential disaster scenarios. In addition to the global-warming risk, there's also the asteroid-hitting-the-earth risk, the terrorists-with-nuclear-weapons risk the super-duper-pandemic risk, etc. Since each of these risks, on the "one percent doctrine," would deserve all of our attention, we cannot address all of them simultaneously. That is, even within the one-percent mentality, we'd have to begin prioritizing, making choices and trade-offs Why not also choose between them and other, things we value? Why treat the unlikely but cataclysmic event as somehow fundamentally different this is how we behave all the time. We get into our cars in order to buy a cup of coffee, even though there's some chance we will be killed on the way to the coffee shop. We are constantly risking death, if slightly, in order to pursue the things we value. Any creature that adopted the "precautionary principle" would neither be able to act, nor not act, since it would nowhere discover perfect safety it's striking how descriptions of the environmental risk always describe the situation as if it were five to midnight. It must be near midnight, since otherwise there would be no need to act. But it can never be five *past* midnight, since then acting would be pointless and we might as well party like it was 2099. Many religious movements have exhibited precisely this combination of traits: the looming apocalypse, with the time (just barely) to take action
Friedman's piece applies Cheney's "one percent doctrine" to the environmental armageddon this doctrine is both intellectually incoherent and practically irrelevant it cannot be applied consistently in a world with many potential scenarios warming asteroid terrorists nuclear-weapons pandemic each risk on the "one percent doctrine," would deserve all of our attention, we cannot address all of them simultaneously Why treat the unlikely but cataclysmic event as somehow fundamentally different We get into our cars to buy coffee, even though there's some chance we will be killed We are constantly risking death Any creature that adopted the "precautionary principle" would neither act, nor not act, since it would nowhere discover perfect safety Many movements exhibited precisely this combination of traits: the looming apocalypse, with the time (just barely) to take action
Tom Friedman's piece today in the Times on the environment (http://www.nytimes.com/2009/12/09/opinion/09friedman.html?_r=1) is one of the flimsiest pieces by a major columnist that I can remember ever reading. He applies Cheney's "one percent doctrine" (which is similar to the environmentalists' "precautionary principle") to the risk of environmental armageddon. But this doctrine is both intellectually incoherent and practically irrelevant. It is intellectually incoherent because it cannot be applied consistently in a world with many potential disaster scenarios. In addition to the global-warming risk, there's also the asteroid-hitting-the-earth risk, the terrorists-with-nuclear-weapons risk (Cheney's original scenario), the super-duper-pandemic risk, etc. Since each of these risks, on the "one percent doctrine," would deserve all of our attention, we cannot address all of them simultaneously. That is, even within the one-percent mentality, we'd have to begin prioritizing, making choices and trade-offs. But why then should we only make these trade-offs between responses to disaster scenarios? Why not also choose between them and other, much more cotidien, things we value? Why treat the unlikely but cataclysmic event as somehow fundamentally different, something that cannot be integrated into all the other calculations we make? And in fact, this is how we behave all the time. We get into our cars in order to buy a cup of coffee, even though there's some chance we will be killed on the way to the coffee shop. We are constantly risking death, if slightly, in order to pursue the things we value. Any creature that adopted the "precautionary principle" would sit at home - no, not even there, since there is some chance the building might collapse. That creature would neither be able to act, nor not act, since it would nowhere discover perfect safety. Friedman's approach reminds me somehow of Pascal's wager - quasi-religious faith masquerading as rational deliberation (as Hans Albert has pointed out, Pascal's wager itself doesn't add up: there may be a God, in fact, but it may turn out that He dislikes, and even damns, people who believe in him because they've calculated it's in their best interest to do so). As my friend James points out, it's striking how descriptions of the environmental risk always describe the situation as if it were five to midnight. It must be near midnight, since otherwise there would be no need to act. But it can never be five *past* midnight, since then acting would be pointless and we might as well party like it was 2099. Many religious movements - for example the early Jesus movement - have exhibited precisely this combination of traits: the looming apocalypse, with the time (just barely) to take action.
2,774
<h4>Evaluating risk with a one percent doctrine makes life impossible – everything could theoretically cause extinction</h4><p><strong>Meskill 09<u></strong> (David, professor at Colorado School of Mines and PhD from Harvard, “The "One Percent Doctrine" and Environmental Faith,” Dec 9, http://davidmeskill.blogspot.com/2009/12/one-percent-doctrine-and-environmental.html)</p><p></u>Tom <u><mark>Friedman's piece</u> </mark>today in the Times on the environment (http://www.nytimes.com/2009/12/09/opinion/09friedman.html?_r=1) is one of the flimsiest pieces by a major columnist that I can remember ever reading. He <u><mark>applies Cheney's "one percent doctrine"</u> </mark>(which is similar to the environmentalists' "precautionary principle") <u><mark>to the </mark>risk of <mark>environmental armageddon</mark>. <strong>But <mark>this doctrine is both intellectually incoherent and practically irrelevant</strong></mark>.</u> It is intellectually incoherent because <u><mark>it cannot be applied consistently in a world with many potential </mark>disaster <mark>scenarios</mark>. In addition to the global-<mark>warming </mark>risk, there's also the <mark>asteroid</mark>-hitting-the-earth risk, the <mark>terrorists</mark>-with-<mark>nuclear-weapons </mark>risk</u> (Cheney's original scenario), <u>the super-duper-<mark>pandemic </mark>risk, etc. Since <mark>each </mark>of these <mark>risk</mark>s, <strong><mark>on the "one percent doctrine," would deserve all of our attention</strong>, we cannot address all of them simultaneously</mark>. That is, even within the one-percent mentality, we'd have to begin prioritizing, making choices and trade-offs</u>. But why then should we only make these trade-offs between responses to disaster scenarios? <u>Why not also choose between them and other,</u> much more cotidien, <u>things we value? <mark>Why treat the unlikely but cataclysmic event as somehow fundamentally different</u></mark>, something that cannot be integrated into all the other calculations we make? And in fact, <u>this is how we behave all the time. <mark>We get into our cars </mark>in order <mark>to buy </mark>a cup of <mark>coffee, even though there's some chance we will be killed </mark>on the way to the coffee shop. <mark>We are constantly risking death</mark>, if slightly, in order to pursue the things we value. <mark>Any creature that adopted the "precautionary principle" would</u> </mark>sit at home - no, not even there, since there is some chance the building might collapse. That creature would <u><mark>neither </mark>be able to <mark>act, nor not act, <strong>since it would nowhere discover perfect safety</u></strong></mark>. Friedman's approach reminds me somehow of Pascal's wager - quasi-religious faith masquerading as rational deliberation (as Hans Albert has pointed out, Pascal's wager itself doesn't add up: there may be a God, in fact, but it may turn out that He dislikes, and even damns, people who believe in him because they've calculated it's in their best interest to do so). As my friend James points out, <u>it's striking how descriptions of the environmental risk always describe the situation as if it were five to midnight. It must be near midnight, since otherwise there would be no need to act. But it can never be five *past* midnight, since then acting would be pointless and we might as well party like it was 2099. <mark>Many </mark>religious <mark>movements</u> </mark>- for example the early Jesus movement - <u>have <mark>exhibited precisely this combination of traits: the looming apocalypse, with the time (just barely) to take action</u></mark>.<u> </p></u>
null
Contention 4 is risk calculus
Contention 3 The Plan solves
46,317
378
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,255
Increased trade has no effect on decreasing risk of conflict between nations
Gelpi and Greico 5
Gelpi and Greico 5[Chris, Joseph, Associate Professor and Professor of Political Science, Duke University, “Democracy, Interdependence, and the Sources of the Liberal Peace”, Journal of Peace Research]
As we have already emphasized, increasing levels of trade between an autocratic and democratic country are unlikely to constrain the former from initiating militarized disputes against the latter increased trade does little or nothing to alter that risk. Increases in trade dependence also have little effect on the likelihood that one autocracy will initiate a conflict with another. In this instance, the probability of dispute initiation remains constant at 0.33% regardless of the challenger’s level of trade dependence.
increasing levels of trade between an autocratic and democratic country are unlikely to constrain the former from initiating militarized disputes against the latter trade does little or nothing to alter that risk. Increases in trade dependence also have little effect on the likelihood that one autocracy will initiate a conflict with another the probability of dispute initiation remains constant regardless of the challenger’s level of trade dependence
As we have already emphasized, increasing levels of trade between an autocratic and democratic country are unlikely to constrain the former from initiating militarized disputes against the latter. As depicted in Figure 1, our analysis indicates that an increase in trade dependence by an autocratic challenger on a democratic target from zero to 5% of the former's GDP would increase the probability of the challenger’s dispute initiation from about 0.31% to 0.29%. Thus, the overall probability of dispute initiation by an autocratic country against a democracy is fairly high (given the rarity of disputes) at 23 nearly .3% per country per year. Moreover, increased trade does little or nothing to alter that risk. Increases in trade dependence also have little effect on the likelihood that one autocracy will initiate a conflict with another. In this instance, the probability of dispute initiation remains constant at 0.33% regardless of the challenger’s level of trade dependence.
986
<h4>Increased trade has no effect on decreasing risk of conflict between nations</h4><p><u><strong>Gelpi and Greico 5</u></strong>[Chris, Joseph, Associate<u> Professor and Professor of Political Science, Duke University, “Democracy, Interdependence, and the Sources of the Liberal Peace”, Journal of Peace Research]</p><p>As we have already emphasized, <mark>increasing levels of trade between an autocratic and democratic country are unlikely to constrain the former from initiating militarized disputes against the latter</u></mark>. As depicted in Figure 1, our analysis indicates that an increase in trade dependence by an autocratic challenger on a democratic target from zero to 5% of the former's GDP would increase the probability of the challenger’s dispute initiation from about 0.31% to 0.29%. Thus, the overall probability of dispute initiation by an autocratic country against a democracy is fairly high (given the rarity of disputes) at 23 nearly .3% per country per year. Moreover, <u>increased <mark>trade does little or nothing to alter that risk. Increases in trade dependence also have little effect on the likelihood that one autocracy will initiate a conflict with another</mark>. In this instance, <mark>the probability of dispute initiation remains constant</mark> at 0.33% <mark>regardless of the challenger’s level of trade dependence<strong></mark>. </p></u></strong>
WTO
Heg/Trade
AT: Inevitable
296,389
13
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,256
Rhetoric demonizing the prostitute abounds with appeals in the name of “the children.” Prohibition of prostitution attempts to maintain the purity of a patriarchal, domestic, and ultimately mythic social order.
Hubbard ’98
Hubbard ’98, Phil Hubbard, Prof. at University of Coventry, UK, “Sexuality, immorality and the city: Red-light districts and the marginalisation of female street prostitutes,” Gender, Place and Culture,
debates about the place of prostitution in the area focused on the figure of the street prostitute. The stereotyped notion of vulgar and conspicuous sex was prevalent in discourses opposing the presence of prostitution , according to one prostitute: It makes me furious when women are portrayed as walking, downtrodden victims foul-mouthed junkies, who are violent and who were abused as kids ('Barbara' cited in Scambler, 1997, p. 105). the female street worker was taken as a signifier of the sexual commodification of women's bodies. This notion of display, with street workers forced to adopt specified codes of dress to mark themselves 'for sale', is one that has featured heavily in the promise of 'unfettered sex' in exchange for money is a threat to the stability of a patriarchal society in which domesticised, vanilla hetero-sex is constructed as the norm. this predatory female sexual role is antithetical to patriarchal conventions which associate femininity with passivity, suggesting that the sight of women taking a more active sexual role is one that provokes considerable male anxiety. the sight of the exposed female body of the prostitute has been incorporated into circuits of masculine desire, and that this stereotyped body image is central to the establishment of heterosexual norms in society this sight is regulated and morally condemned because of the notion that it assaults standards of public decency. The conspicuous display of feminine sexuality through specific forms of comportment and dress is seen as transgressing social conventions, a fact recognised by many prostitutes who argue that they are subverting gendered expectations of appropriate behaviour for women [15]. This of course relates to much longer traditions of female bodily identities as immoral, with no possibility of a female flaneur, only the prostitute (Wilson, 1995). The Wolfenden Act, which preceded the 1959 Street Offense Act, makes this point clear, arguing that the control of the prostition is justified by 'the right of the normal decent citizen to go about the streets without affront to their sense of decency' (Scambler, 1997). What is significant is that this construction of the 'decent' citizen appears to be based around the notion of a femininely-defined personage, with males seeking to protect the 'innocent' female gaze the idea that prostitute women were morally polluting through their displays of 'dangerously underclad young prostitutes' claimed 'these girls must be taken off the streets of our suburbs for the sake of decent residents--and for their children 'young people growing up who need protection from the sights and sounds of vice'. Protesters reinforced this point claiming 'I know I'm living in a red-light district, and I don't have a problem with that but it's the impact on my children's way of life which concerns me' and another reporting that he didn't have a problem with it, but suppose my grandchildren had been with me' when prostitutes started soliciting in the mornings to avoid the pickets there was a moral outcry that this would bring prostitutes' into full view of children on their way to school' the idea that street prostitution was an assault against public decency was frequently restated, with resident women and childre depicted as the vulnerable 'victims' of street prostitution this idea that the visibility of street prostitutes was corrupting the local community, and, more especially, children appeared as a impetus to the Street Watch campaign.
The stereotyped notion of vulgar sex was prevalent in discourses opposing prostitution female street worker was taken as a signifier of sexual commodification of women's bodies the promise of 'unfettered sex' in exchange for money is a threat to the stability of a patriarchal society in which domesticised, hetero-sex is constructed as the norm this predatory female sexual role is antithetical to patriarchal conventions which associate femininity with passivity the sight of the exposed female body has been incorporated into masculine desire, and that this stereotyped body image is central to the establishment of heterosexual norms in society the idea that prostitute women were morally polluting claimed 'these girls must be taken off the streets for the sake of decent residents--and their children' 'young people growing up need protection from the sights of vice' the impact on my children's life concerns me' suppose my grandchildren had been with me' when prostitutes started soliciting in the mornings there was a moral outcry that this would bring prostitutes' into full view of children on their way to school' the idea prostitution was an assault against decency was frequently restated, with resident children depicted as the 'victims' of prostitution
Although street prostitution coexisted with window-working in Balsall Heath, the debates about the place of prostitution in the area focused on the figure of the street prostitute. The stereotyped notion of the street-walker as the embodiment of vulgar and conspicuous sex was prevalent in local discourses opposing the presence of prostitution, although, according to one prostitute: It makes me furious when women are portrayed as walking, downtrodden victims... Why are girls portrayed the way they are in the media? We are portrayed as women who stand on street corners, who wear microscopic mini-skirts, who are foul-mouthed junkies, who are violent and who were abused as kids ('Barbara' cited in Scambler, 1997, p. 105). Nonetheless, the media coverage was replete with voyeuristic images including some culled from national press files of other cities, of 'highly painted young girls, skirted up to the thigh' (The Sunday Telegraph, 6 November 1994), as the female street worker was taken as a signifier of the sexual commodification of women's bodies. This notion of display, with street workers forced to adopt specified codes of dress to mark themselves 'for sale', is one that has featured heavily in the development of the 'whore stigma' through conspicuous vulgarity--and the promise of 'unfettered sex' in exchange for money is seen as a threat to the stability of a patriarchal society in which domesticised, vanilla hetero-sex is constructed as the norm. Bondi 1998 further contends that this predatory female sexual role is antithetical to patriarchal conventions which associate femininity with passivity, suggesting that the sight of women taking a more active sexual role is one that provokes considerable male anxiety. Undoubtedly, the urge to exclude prostitutes from the street was magnified by the challenge that street prostitution was seen to posit to the collective identity of the local Muslim population, whose use of the term 'prostitute' as a pejorative term to describe any 'non-conforming' Muslim woman has been well-documented (Sabbah, 1984). Simultaneously though, Kirby 1996 suggests that the sight of the exposed female body of the prostitute has been incorporated into circuits of masculine desire, and that this stereotyped body image is central to the establishment of heterosexual norms in society, whether Muslim or otherwise. She also argues that this sight is regulated and morally condemned because of the notion that it assaults standards of public decency. The conspicuous display of feminine sexuality through specific forms of comportment and dress is seen as transgressing social conventions, a fact recognised by many prostitutes who argue that they are subverting gendered expectations of appropriate behaviour for women [15]. This of course relates to much longer traditions of female bodily identities as immoral, with no possibility of a female flaneur, only the prostitute (Wilson, 1995). The Wolfenden Act, which preceded the 1959 Street Offense Act, makes this point clear, arguing that the control of the prostition is justified by 'the right of the normal decent citizen to go about the streets without affront to their sense of decency' (Scambler, 1997). What is significant is that this construction of the 'decent' citizen appears to be based around the notion of a femininely-defined personage, with males seeking to protect the 'innocent' female gaze. Thus, while many campaigners claimed that theirs 'was not a moral crusade' and they had 'nothing against prostitutes' (Birmingham Post, 27 March 1993), the idea that prostitute women were morally polluting through their displays of 'dangerously underclad young prostitutes' on the street claimed 'these girls must be taken off the streets of our suburbs for the sake of decent residents--and for their children' (Birmingham Evening Mail, 13 February 1995). Another article spoke of 'young people growing up who need protection from the sights and sounds of vice'. Protesters reinforced this point, one claiming that 'I know I'm living in a red-light district, and I don't have a problem with that--after all, I lived in Amsterdam for 3 years, but it's the impact on my children's way of life which concerns me' (Express and Star, 13 1994), and another reporting that he became involved on the day he saw a prostitute with a 'near naked client... I didn't have a problem with it, but suppose my grandchildren had been with me' [6]. Furthermore, when prostitutes started soliciting in the mornings to avoid the pickets, there was a moral outcry that this would bring prostitutes' into full view of children on their way to school' (Birmingham Evening Mail, 16 May 1995). Consequently, the idea that street prostitution was an assault against public decency was frequently restated, with resident women and children, not the prostitutes themselves, depicted as the vulnerable 'victims' of the sight of street prostitution. It was this idea that the visibility of street prostitutes was corrupting the local community, and, more especially, virtuous women and children, that appeared as a fundamental impetus to the organisation of the predominantly male and masculine Street Watch campaign.
5,206
<h4>Rhetoric demonizing the prostitute abounds with appeals in the name of “the children.” Prohibition of prostitution attempts to maintain the purity of a patriarchal, domestic, and ultimately mythic social order.</h4><p><strong>Hubbard ’98</strong>, Phil Hubbard, Prof. at University of Coventry, UK, “Sexuality, immorality and the city: Red-light districts and the marginalisation of female street prostitutes,” Gender, Place and Culture<u>, </p><p></u>Although street prostitution coexisted with window-working in Balsall Heath, the <u>debates about the place of prostitution in the area focused on the figure of the street prostitute. <mark>The stereotyped notion of</mark> </u>the street-walker as the embodiment of <u><mark>vulgar </mark>and conspicuous <mark>sex was</mark> <mark>prevalent in</u></mark> local <u><mark>discourses opposing </mark>the presence of <mark>prostitution</u></mark>, although<u>, according to one prostitute:</p><p>It makes me furious when women are portrayed as walking, downtrodden victims</u>... Why are girls portrayed the way they are in the media? We are portrayed as women who stand on street corners, who wear microscopic mini-skirts, who are <u>foul-mouthed junkies, who are violent and who were abused as kids ('Barbara' cited in Scambler, 1997, p. 105).</p><p></u>Nonetheless, the media coverage was replete with voyeuristic images including some culled from national press files of other cities, of 'highly painted young girls, skirted up to the thigh' (The Sunday Telegraph, 6 November 1994), as <u>the <mark>female street worker was taken as a signifier of</mark> the <mark>sexual commodification of women's bodies</mark>. This notion of display, with street workers forced to adopt specified codes of dress to mark themselves 'for sale', is one that has featured heavily in</u> the development of the 'whore stigma' through conspicuous vulgarity--and <u><strong><mark>the promise of 'unfettered sex' in exchange for money is</strong></mark> </u>seen as<u> <strong><mark>a threat to the stability of a patriarchal society in which domesticised, </mark>vanilla <mark>hetero-sex is constructed as the norm</strong></mark>.</u> Bondi 1998 further contends that<u> <strong><mark>this predatory female sexual role is antithetical to patriarchal conventions which associate femininity with passivity</strong></mark>, suggesting that the sight of women taking a more active sexual role is one that provokes considerable male anxiety. </p><p></u>Undoubtedly, the urge to exclude prostitutes from the street was magnified by the challenge that street prostitution was seen to posit to the collective identity of the local Muslim population, whose use of the term 'prostitute' as a pejorative term to describe any 'non-conforming' Muslim woman has been well-documented (Sabbah, 1984). Simultaneously though, Kirby 1996 suggests that <u><mark>the sight of the exposed female body </mark>of the prostitute <mark>has been incorporated into </mark>circuits of <mark>masculine desire, and that this stereotyped body image is <strong>central to the establishment</strong> of heterosexual norms in society</u></mark>, whether Muslim or otherwise. She also argues that <u>this sight is regulated and morally condemned because of the notion that it assaults standards of public decency. The conspicuous display of feminine sexuality through specific forms of comportment and dress is seen as transgressing social conventions, a fact recognised by many prostitutes who argue that they are subverting gendered expectations of appropriate behaviour for women [15]. This of course relates to much longer traditions of female bodily identities as immoral, with no possibility of a female flaneur, only the prostitute (Wilson, 1995). The Wolfenden Act, which preceded the 1959 Street Offense Act, makes this point clear, arguing that the control of the prostition is justified by 'the right of the normal decent citizen to go about the streets without affront to their sense of decency' (Scambler, 1997).</p><p>What is significant is that this construction of the 'decent' citizen appears to be based around the notion of a femininely-defined personage, with males seeking to protect the 'innocent' female gaze</u>. Thus, while many campaigners claimed that theirs 'was not a moral crusade' and they had 'nothing against prostitutes' (Birmingham Post, 27 March 1993), <u><mark>the idea that prostitute women were morally polluting </mark>through their displays of 'dangerously underclad young prostitutes'</u> on the street <u><mark>claimed <strong>'these girls must be taken off the streets </mark>of our suburbs <mark>for the sake of decent residents--and </mark>for <mark>their children</u></strong>'</mark> (Birmingham Evening Mail, 13 February 1995). Another article spoke of <u><strong><mark>'young people growing up</mark> who <mark>need protection from the sights </mark>and sounds<mark> of vice'</strong></mark>. Protesters reinforced this point</u>, one <u>claiming</u> that <u>'I know I'm living in a red-light district, and I don't have a problem with that</u>--after all, I lived in Amsterdam for 3 years, <u><strong>but it's <mark>the impact on my children's </mark>way of <mark>life </mark>which <mark>concerns me'</u></strong></mark> (Express and Star, 13 1994), <u>and another reporting that he</u> became involved on the day he saw a prostitute with a 'near naked client... I <u>didn't have a problem with it, but</u> <u><strong><mark>suppose my grandchildren had been with me'</mark> </u></strong>[6]. Furthermore, <u><mark>when prostitutes started soliciting in the mornings</mark> to avoid the pickets</u>, <u><strong><mark>there was a moral outcry that this would bring prostitutes' into full view of children on their way to school'</u></strong></mark> (Birmingham Evening Mail, 16 May 1995). Consequently, <u><mark>the idea </mark>that street <mark>prostitution was an assault against </mark>public <mark>decency was frequently restated, with resident</mark> women and <mark>childre</u>n</mark>, not the prostitutes themselves, <u><mark>depicted as the </mark>vulnerable <mark>'victims' of</u></mark> the sight of <u>street <mark>prostitution</u></mark>. It was <u>this idea that the visibility of street prostitutes was corrupting the local community, and, more especially,</u> virtuous women and <u>children</u>, that <u>appeared as a </u>fundamental <u>impetus to the</u> organisation of the predominantly male and masculine <u>Street Watch campaign.</p></u>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,622
2
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,257
This effort to police the prostitute's sexuality is a task that can never be fully realized. The prostitute’s unfettered sexuality defines society itself because it represents a permanent danger to a politics of respectable sex – the immoral, queer excess against which morality is defined.
Hubbard ’98
Hubbard ’98, Phil Hubbard, Prof. at University of Coventry, UK, “Sexuality, immorality and the city: Red-light districts and the marginalisation of female street prostitutes,” Gender, Place and Culture,
female prostitutes have been marginalised as Other constructed as an Other identity through contradictory images of desire and disgust within processes defining dominant notions of respectable feminine sexuality mass media in Western societies has sought to perpetuate images that depict prostitutes as social pariahs, fallen women, or 'bad girls' and to use such images to distinguish this 'deviant' group from 'normal' purified populations the representation of sex workers has been based around persistent stereotypes of the prostitute as Other constitutes an important theme in writing on the regulation and containment of prostitution, albeit one that is fraught with contractions (prostitutes are, after all, a group that is eroticised and demonised simultaneously prostitutes, although socially marginalised, were of major symbolic importance their representation at the immoral 'margin' crucial for defining the moral 'centre': in essence, the boundaries between domesticised femininity and the unfettered sexuality of the street were constructed and maintained through the discursive identification of prostitutes as dirty and dangerous, a threat to bourgeois society. dominant male fears and fantasies were projected onto the figure of the street prostitute The prostitute was the quintessential figure of the urban scene... for men as well as women, the prostitute was the central spectacle in a set of urban encounters and fantasies. ). The link between sexual depravity and social disorder was further cemented in a literary tradition that depicted street prostitutes as part of a seedy Victorian underworld, affiliated with criminality, deviance, and sexual danger process of Othering prostitutes was reliant on a language of moral outrage and disgust (tempered with fascination and voyeurism), which was spatially transposed onto the landscape of the underworld, This collision between physical and moral impurity reinforced deep-seated anxieties and fears about prostitution, as the prostitute came to symbolise the division of society into high and low - the civilised and the grotesque through a series of metaphors of the body, morality and topography prostitution was the 'great social evil'
female prostitutes have been constructed as Other through contradictory images of desire and disgust Western societies depict prostitutes as 'deviant' group from 'normal' purified populations the prostitute Other constitutes an important theme in regulation and containment of prostitution prostitutes, were of major symbolic importance their representation at the immoral 'margin' crucial for defining the moral 'centre': the boundaries between domesticised femininity and the unfettered sexuality of the street were constructed through the discursive identification of prostitutes as dangerous, a threat to bourgeois society tradition depicted prostitutes as part of a seedy underworld, affiliated with deviance, and sexual danger process of Othering prostitutes was reliant on a moral outrage tempered with voyeurism), which was spatially transposed onto the landscape of the underworld the prostitute came to symbolise the division of society into high and low - the civilised and the grotesque through a series of metaphors of the body, morality and topography prostitution was the 'great social evil'
Such ideas are particularly useful for seeking to understand the way in which female prostitutes have, throughout history, been marginalised as Other. Pile 1996, for example, writes that the female prostitute has remained an emblematic figure at the intersection of sexual and gender relationships, constructed as an Other identity through contradictory images of desire and disgust within processes defining dominant notions of respectable feminine sexuality. Although it is important to note that the extent and intensity of this figuring has varied across time and space with some societies more tolerant of prostitution than others, the mass media in Western societies has generally sought to perpetuate images that depict prostitutes as social pariahs, fallen women, or 'bad girls' and to use such images to distinguish this 'deviant' group from 'normal' purified populations. Roberts, 1992. Exploring such ideas, Sibley 1995 has commented on the frequent representation of street prostitutes as defiling the purity of the city, and one merely needs to consider the way in which recent film and television drama from Taxi Driver to Mona Lisa, from The Bill to Band of Gold has consistently presented stereotyped images of prostitutes as part of a desperate, criminalised underworld, drug-dependent and reliant on the protection of pimps, to appreciate the importance of the media in shaping feelings of abjection towards prostitutes. Even sympathetic portrayals of prostitute women that subvert stereotypical expectations--for example, films such as Personal Services or Working Girls--may demand that these stereotypes are acknowledged, Perkins, 1989. The suggestion that the representation of sex workers has been based around persistent stereotypes of the prostitute as Other constitutes an important theme in writing on the regulation and containment of prostitution, albeit one that is fraught with contractions (prostitutes are, after all, a group that is eroticised and demonised simultaneously). Surprisingly little work has focused on the contemporary media stereotyping of prostitutes though see Murray & Robinson, 1996, with most commentators instead investigating the representation of sex work in the nineteenth century, exploring the way emerging moral-medical ideas were used to label prostitutes as a 'polluting' category at a time when women's role in urban society was undergoing dramatic transformation (Walkowitz, 1980; Mort, 1987). As Corbin 1990 has argued, prostitutes, although socially marginalised, were of major symbolic importance in Victorian society, with their representation at the immoral 'margin' crucial for defining the moral 'centre': in essence, the boundaries between domesticised femininity and the unfettered sexuality of the street were constructed and maintained through the discursive identification of prostitutes as dirty and dangerous, a threat to bourgeois society. Inevitably, a variety of urban flaneurs, epidemiologists, philologists and moral reformers contributed to this process, their obsessive scrutiny of the habits and habitats of 'fallen women' contributing to a variety of pseudo-scientific discourses in which dominant male fears and fantasies were projected onto the figure of the street prostitute: The prostitute was the quintessential figure of the urban scene... for men as well as women, the prostitute was the central spectacle in a set of urban encounters and fantasies. Repudiated and desired, degraded and threatening, the prostitute attracted the attention of a range of urban male explorers from the 1840s to the 1880s. (Walkowitz, 1992, p 233) The medicalisation of female prostitutes as an alleged source of sexually-transmitted diseases, for example, was based solely on the assumption that prostitutes had high numbers of sexual contacts rather than any detailed knowledge of transmission vectors, yet led directly to the imposition of the Contagious Diseases Act of 1864 (updated in 1866 and 1869), which was applied to prostitute women but not their clients in a largely indiscriminate manner (Ogborn, 1992; 1993). The link between sexual depravity and social disorder was further cemented in a literary tradition that depicted street prostitutes as part of a seedy Victorian underworld, affiliated with criminality, deviance, and sexual danger. Walkowitz 1992 has suggested that this tendency was evident not only in the sensationalist tabloid treatment of the Ripper murders, but also in 'high' literary explorations of living conditions in the Victorian city, with Stead's expose of child prostitution in the Pall Mall Gazette 1881 typical in its portrayal of prostitution as encapsulating all that was remiss in Victorian society--drunkenness, perversion, violence, and sexual slavery. Significantly, it has been noted that the nineteenth-century process of Othering prostitutes was reliant on a language of moral outrage and disgust (tempered with fascination and voyeurism), which was spatially transposed onto the landscape of the Victorian underworld, a twilight world of narrow streets, alleys and parks (Jackson, 1989). This collision between physical and moral impurity reinforced deep-seated anxieties and fears about prostitution, as the prostitute came to symbolise the division of society into high and low - the civilised and the grotesque through a series of metaphors of the body, morality and topography (Stallybrass & White, 1986). While prostitution was the 'great social evil' of the day, and a general metaphor for the disorder of the city, discourses of moral hygiene linked the 'erotomaniac and nymphomaniac' behaviour of prostitutes onto their surroundings, with Smart 1982 drawing attention to the correspondence between ideas of prostitutes as deviant and discourses concerning the filth and environmental squalor of slum areas (see also Matlock, 1994). Interventions in housing reform, planning and public health regulation were often rationalised in terms of moral hygiene, with the female prostitute posited as symptomatic of the degeneracy of working-class housing areas (Greed, 1994). It is this idea of space as being central to the process of Othering prostitutes to which I now turn.
6,204
<h4>This effort to police the prostitute's sexuality is a task that can never be fully realized. The prostitute’s unfettered sexuality <u>defines</u> society itself because it represents a permanent danger to a politics of respectable sex – the immoral, queer excess against which morality is defined.</h4><p><strong>Hubbard ’98</strong>, Phil Hubbard, Prof. at University of Coventry, UK, “Sexuality, immorality and the city: Red-light districts and the marginalisation of female street prostitutes,” Gender, Place and Culture, </p><p>Such ideas are particularly useful for seeking to understand the way in which <u><mark>female prostitutes have</u></mark>, throughout history, <u><mark>been</mark> marginalised as Other</u>. Pile 1996, for example, writes that the female prostitute has remained an emblematic figure at the intersection of sexual and gender relationships, <u><mark>constructed as </mark>an <mark>Other </mark>identity <mark>through contradictory images of desire and</mark> <mark>disgust </mark>within processes defining dominant notions of respectable feminine sexuality</u>. Although it is important to note that the extent and intensity of this figuring has varied across time and space with some societies more tolerant of prostitution than others, the <u>mass media in <mark>Western societies </mark>has </u>generally<u> sought to perpetuate images that <mark>depict prostitutes as </mark>social pariahs, fallen women, or 'bad girls' and to use such images to distinguish this <mark>'deviant' group from 'normal' purified populations</u></mark>. Roberts, 1992. Exploring such ideas, Sibley 1995 has commented on the frequent representation of street prostitutes as defiling the purity of the city, and one merely needs to consider the way in which recent film and television drama from Taxi Driver to Mona Lisa, from The Bill to Band of Gold has consistently presented stereotyped images of prostitutes as part of a desperate, criminalised underworld, drug-dependent and reliant on the protection of pimps, to appreciate the importance of the media in shaping feelings of abjection towards prostitutes. Even sympathetic portrayals of prostitute women that subvert stereotypical expectations--for example, films such as Personal Services or Working Girls--may demand that these stereotypes are acknowledged, Perkins, 1989.</p><p>The suggestion that<u> the representation of sex workers has been based around persistent stereotypes of <mark>the prostitute</mark> as <mark>Other</mark> <mark>constitutes an important theme</mark> <mark>in</mark> writing on the <mark>regulation and containment of prostitution</mark>, albeit one that is fraught with contractions (prostitutes are, after all, a group that is eroticised and demonised simultaneously</u>). Surprisingly little work has focused on the contemporary media stereotyping of prostitutes though see Murray & Robinson, 1996, with most commentators instead investigating the representation of sex work in the nineteenth century, exploring the way emerging moral-medical ideas were used to label prostitutes as a 'polluting' category at a time when women's role in urban society was undergoing dramatic transformation (Walkowitz, 1980; Mort, 1987). As Corbin 1990 has argued, <u><mark>prostitutes, </mark>although socially marginalised, <mark>were of <strong>major symbolic importance</strong> </u></mark>in Victorian society, with<u> <mark>their representation at the immoral 'margin' crucial for defining the moral 'centre':</mark> in essence, <strong><mark>the boundaries between domesticised femininity and the unfettered sexuality of the street were constructed </mark>and maintained <mark>through the discursive identification of prostitutes as </mark>dirty and <mark>dangerous, a threat to bourgeois society</strong></mark>.</u> Inevitably, a variety of urban flaneurs, epidemiologists, philologists and moral reformers contributed to this process, their obsessive scrutiny of the habits and habitats of 'fallen women' contributing to a variety of pseudo-scientific discourses in which <u>dominant male fears and fantasies were projected onto the figure of the street prostitute</u>:</p><p><u>The prostitute was the quintessential figure of the urban scene... for men as well as women, the prostitute was the central spectacle in a set of urban encounters and fantasies.</u> Repudiated and desired, degraded and threatening, the prostitute attracted the attention of a range of urban male explorers from the 1840s to the 1880s. (Walkowitz, 1992, p 233)</p><p>The medicalisation of female prostitutes as an alleged source of sexually-transmitted diseases, for example, was based solely on the assumption that prostitutes had high numbers of sexual contacts rather than any detailed knowledge of transmission vectors, yet led directly to the imposition of the Contagious Diseases Act of 1864 (updated in 1866 and 1869), which was applied to prostitute women but not their clients in a largely indiscriminate manner (Ogborn, 1992; 1993<u>). The link between sexual depravity and social disorder was further cemented in a literary <mark>tradition </mark>that <mark>depicted </mark>street <mark>prostitutes as part of a seedy </mark>Victorian <mark>underworld, affiliated with </mark>criminality, <mark>deviance, and sexual danger</u></mark>. Walkowitz 1992 has suggested that this tendency was evident not only in the sensationalist tabloid treatment of the Ripper murders, but also in 'high' literary explorations of living conditions in the Victorian city, with Stead's expose of child prostitution in the Pall Mall Gazette 1881 typical in its portrayal of prostitution as encapsulating all that was remiss in Victorian society--drunkenness, perversion, violence, and sexual slavery.</p><p>Significantly, it has been noted that the nineteenth-century<u> <mark>process of Othering prostitutes was reliant on a </mark>language of <mark>moral outrage </mark>and disgust (<mark>tempered with </mark>fascination and <mark>voyeurism), which was spatially transposed onto the landscape of the</u></mark> Victorian <u><mark>underworld</mark>,</u> a twilight world of narrow streets, alleys and parks (Jackson, 1989). <u>This collision between physical and moral impurity reinforced deep-seated anxieties and fears about prostitution, as <mark>the prostitute came to symbolise the division of society into high and low</u></mark> <u><mark>- the civilised and the grotesque through a series of metaphors of the body, morality and topography</u></mark> (Stallybrass & White, 1986). While <u><mark>prostitution was the 'great social evil' </u></mark>of the day, and a general metaphor for the disorder of the city, discourses of moral hygiene linked the 'erotomaniac and nymphomaniac' behaviour of prostitutes onto their surroundings, with Smart 1982 drawing attention to the correspondence between ideas of prostitutes as deviant and discourses concerning the filth and environmental squalor of slum areas (see also Matlock, 1994). Interventions in housing reform, planning and public health regulation were often rationalised in terms of moral hygiene, with the female prostitute posited as symptomatic of the degeneracy of working-class housing areas (Greed, 1994). It is this idea of space as being central to the process of Othering prostitutes to which I now turn.</p>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,623
2
17,077
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
565,297
A
tournament
4
Binghamton Cepin-Sehgal
Baker, Webster Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,258
Their attempt to make debate a site of activism is just the latest in a cycle of academic professionalization that stifles subversive action. Worse, it ignores theundercommon labor upon which their scholarship is built which makes affirming Life in Death impossible because ignoring that Life is precisely the condition of possibility for academics
Moten and Harney 04.
Moten and Harney 04. Fred Moten and Stefano Harney, The University and the Undercommons, SEVEN THESES Social Text 79, Vol. 22, No. 2, Summer 2004. Copyright © 2004 by Duke University Press
Surely there is some space here for a theory, a conference, a book, a school of thought? Surely the university also makes thought possible? Is it not therefore important to protect this , whatever its impurities, from professionalization in the university? But we would ask what is already not possible in this talk in the hallways, among the buildings, in rooms of the university about possibility? The maroons are the condition of possibility of production of knowledge in the university It is not merely a matter of the secret labor upon which such space is lifted, though of course such space is lifted from collective labor and by it. It is rather that to be a critical academic in the university is to be against the university, and to be against the university is always to recognize it and be recognized by it, and to institute the negligence of that internal outside, that unassimilated underground, a negligence of it that is precisely, we must insist, the basis of the professions It is not just the labor of the maroons but their prophetic organization that is negated by the idea of intellectual space in an organization called the university. This is why the negligence of the critical academic is always at the same time an assertion of bourgeois individualism It takes the form of a choice to put into question the knowledge object, let us say in this case the university, not so much without touching its foundation, as without touching one's own condition of possibility, without admitting the and being admitted to it a general negligence of condition is the only coherent position. Not so much an  or foundationalism, as both are used against each other to avoid contact with the . the maroons refuse to refuse professionalization, that is, to be against the university. The university will not recognize this indecision, and thus professionalization is shaped precisely by what it cannot acknowledge, its internal antagonism, its wayward labor, its surplus if professional education ever slips in its labor, ever reveals its condition of possibility to the professions it supports and reconstitutes, critical education is there to pick it up, and to tell it, never mind—it was just a bad dream, the ravings, the drawings of the mad. Because critical education is precisely there to tell professional education to rethink its relationship to its opposite—by which critical education means both itself and the unregulated, against which professional education is deployed. critical education arrives to support any faltering negligence, to be vigilant in its negligence, to be critically engaged in its negligence It is more than an ally of professional education, it is its attempted completion
null
But surely if one can write something on the surface of the university, if one can write for instance in the university about singularities—those events that refuse either the abstract or individual category of the bourgeois subject—one cannot say that there is no space in the university itself? Surely there is some space here for a theory, a conference, a book, a school of thought? Surely the university also makes thought possible? Is not the purpose of the university as Universitas, as liberal arts, to make the commons, make the public, make the nation of democratic citizenry? Is it not therefore important to protect this Universitas, whatever its impurities, from professionalization in the university? But we would ask what is already not possible in this talk in the hallways, among the buildings, in rooms of the university about possibility? How is the thought of the outside, as Gayatri Spivak means it, already not possible in this complaint? The maroons know something about possibility. They are the condition of possibility of production of knowledge in the university—the singularities against the writers of singularity, the writers who write, publish, travel, and speak. It is not merely a matter of the secret labor upon which such space is lifted, though of course such space is lifted from collective labor and by it. It is rather that to be a critical academic in the university is to be against the university, and to be against the university is always to recognize it and be recognized by it, and to institute the negligence of that internal outside, that unassimilated underground, a negligence of it that is precisely, we must insist, the basis of the professions. And this act of against always already excludes the unrecognized modes of politics, the beyond of politics already in motion, the discredited criminal para- organization, what Robin Kelley might refer to as the infrapolitical field (and its music). It is not just the labor of the maroons but their prophetic organization that is negated by the idea of intellectual space in an organization called the university. This is why the negligence of the critical academic is always at the same time an assertion of bourgeois individualism. Such negligence is the essence of professionalization where it turns out professionalization is not the opposite of negligence but its mode of politics in the United States. It takes the form of a choicethat excludes the [End Page 105] prophetic organization of the Undercommons—to be against, to put into question the knowledge object, let us say in this case the university, not so much without touching its foundation, as without touching one's own condition of possibility, without admitting the Undercommons and being admitted to it. From this, a general negligence of condition is the only coherent position. Not so much an antifoundationalism or foundationalism, as both are used against each other to avoid contact with the Undercommons. This always negligent act is what leads us to say there is no distinction between the university in the United States and professionalization. There is no point in trying to hold out the university against its professionalization. They are the same. Yetthe maroons refuse to refuse professionalization, that is, to be against the university. The university will not recognize this indecision, and thus professionalization is shaped precisely by what it cannot acknowledge, its internal antagonism, its wayward labor, its surplus. Against this wayward labor it sends the critical, sends its claim that what is left beyond the critical is waste. But in fact, critical education only attempts to perfect professional education. The professions constitute themselves in an opposition to the unregulated and the ignorant without acknowledging the unregulated, ignorant, unprofessional labor that goes on not opposite them but within them. But if professional education ever slips in its labor, ever reveals its condition of possibility to the professions it supports and reconstitutes, critical education is there to pick it up, and to tell it, never mind—it was just a bad dream, the ravings, the drawings of the mad. Because critical education is precisely there to tell professional education to rethink its relationship to its opposite—by which critical education means both itself and the unregulated, against which professional education is deployed. In other words,critical education arrives to support any faltering negligence, to be vigilant in its negligence, to be critically engaged in its negligence. It is more than an ally of professional education, it is its attempted completion. A professional education has become a critical education. But one should not applaud this fact. It should be taken for what it is, not progress in the professional schools, not cohabitation with the Universitas, but counterinsurgency, the refounding terrorism of law, coming for the discredited, coming for those who refuse to write off or write up the Undercommons.
5,035
<h4><strong>Their attempt to make debate a site of activism is just the latest in a cycle of academic professionalization that stifles subversive action. Worse, it ignores theundercommon labor upon which their scholarship is built which makes affirming Life in Death impossible because ignoring that Life is precisely the condition of possibility for academics</h4><p>Moten and Harney 04.</strong> Fred Moten and Stefano Harney, The University and the Undercommons, SEVEN THESES Social Text 79, Vol. 22, No. 2, Summer 2004. Copyright © 2004 by Duke University Press</p><p>But surely if one can write something on the surface of the university, if one can write for instance in the university about singularities—those events that refuse either the abstract or individual category of the bourgeois subject—one cannot say that there is no space in the university itself? <u>Surely there is some space here for a theory, a conference, a book, a school of thought? Surely the university also makes thought possible?</u> Is not the purpose of the university as Universitas, as liberal arts, to make the commons, make the public, make the nation of democratic citizenry? <u>Is it not therefore important to protect this </u>Universitas<u>, whatever its impurities, from professionalization in the university? But we would ask what is already not possible in this talk in the hallways, among the buildings, in rooms of the university about possibility?</u> How is the thought of the outside, as Gayatri Spivak means it, already not possible in this complaint? <u>The maroons</u> know something about possibility. They <u>are the condition of possibility of production of knowledge in the university</u>—the singularities against the writers of singularity, the writers who write, publish, travel, and speak. <u>It is not merely a matter of the secret labor upon which such space is lifted, though of course such space is lifted from collective labor and by it. It is rather that to be a critical academic in the university is to be against the university, and to be against the university is always to recognize it and be recognized by it, and to institute the negligence of that internal outside, that unassimilated underground, a negligence of it that is precisely, we must insist, the basis of the professions</u>. And this act of against always already excludes the unrecognized modes of politics, the beyond of politics already in motion, the discredited criminal para- organization, what Robin Kelley might refer to as the infrapolitical field (and its music). <u>It is not just the labor of the maroons but their prophetic organization that is negated by the idea of intellectual space in an organization called the university. This is why the negligence of the critical academic is always at the same time an assertion of bourgeois individualism</u>. Such negligence is the essence of professionalization where it turns out professionalization is not the opposite of negligence but its mode of politics in the United States. <u>It takes the form of a choice</u>that excludes the [End Page 105] prophetic organization of the Undercommons—to be against, <u>to put into question the knowledge object, let us say in this case the university, not so much without touching its foundation, as without touching one's own condition of possibility, without admitting the </u>Undercommons <u>and being admitted to it</u>. From this, <u>a general negligence of condition is the only coherent position. Not so much an </u>antifoundationalism<u> or foundationalism, as both are used against each other to avoid contact with the </u>Undercommons<u>.</u> This always negligent act is what leads us to say there is no distinction between the university in the United States and professionalization. There is no point in trying to hold out the university against its professionalization. They are the same. Yet<u>the maroons refuse to refuse professionalization, that is, to be against the university. The university will not recognize this indecision, and thus professionalization is shaped precisely by what it cannot acknowledge, its internal antagonism, its wayward labor, its surplus</u>. Against this wayward labor it sends the critical, sends its claim that what is left beyond the critical is waste. But in fact, critical education only attempts to perfect professional education. The professions constitute themselves in an opposition to the unregulated and the ignorant without acknowledging the unregulated, ignorant, unprofessional labor that goes on not opposite them but within them. But <u>if professional education ever slips in its labor, ever reveals its condition of possibility to the professions it supports and reconstitutes, critical education is there to pick it up, and to tell it, never mind—it was just a bad dream, the ravings, the drawings of the mad. Because critical education is precisely there to tell professional education to rethink its relationship to its opposite—by which critical education means both itself and the unregulated, against which professional education is deployed.</u> In other words,<u>critical education arrives to support any faltering negligence, to be vigilant in its negligence, to be critically engaged in its negligence</u>. <u>It is more than an ally of professional education, it is its attempted completion</u>. A professional education has become a critical education. But one should not applaud this fact. It should be taken for what it is, not progress in the professional schools, not cohabitation with the Universitas, but counterinsurgency, the refounding terrorism of law, coming for the discredited, coming for those who refuse to write off or write up the Undercommons.</p><p><strong> </p></strong>
null
null
1NC Version 2 – Undercommons
1,240,567
424
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,259
Even if some crowd out occurred, sales would still provide an adequate supply of organs
Study by Becker and Elias 14
Study by Becker and Elias 14 Gary S. Becker, Nobel Prize-winning professor of economics at the University of Chicago and a senior fellow at the Hoover Institution; and Julio J. Elias, economics professor at the Universidad del CEMA in Argentina. Updated Jan. 18, 2014 Wall Street Journal Cash for Kidneys: The Case for a Market for Organs http://online.wsj.com/news/articles/SB10001424052702304149404579322560004817176?mod=WSJ_hpp_MIDDLENexttoWhatsNewsFifth
Finding a way to increase the supply of organs would reduce wait times and deaths, and it would greatly ease the suffering that many sick individuals now endure while they hope for a transplant. The most effective change would be to provide compensation to people who give their organs—that is, we recommend establishing a market for organs. Paying donors for their organs would finally eliminate the supply-demand gap sufficient payment to kidney donors would increase the supply of kidneys by a large percentage, without greatly increasing the total cost of a kidney transplant. We have estimated how much individuals would need to be paid for kidneys to be willing to sell them for transplants. Our conclusion is that a very large number of both live and cadaveric kidney donations would be available by paying about $15,000 for each kidney. Iran permits the sale of kidneys by living donors. waiting times to get kidneys have been largely eliminated Since the number of kidneys available at a reasonable price would be far more than needed to close the gap between the demand and supply of kidneys, there would no longer be any significant waiting time to get a kidney transplant. The number of people on dialysis would decline dramatically, and deaths due to long waits for a transplant would essentially disappear. the claim that payments would be ineffective in eliminating the shortage of organs isn't consistent with what we know about the supply of other parts of the body for medical use. Paying for organs would save the cost of dialysis for people waiting for kidney transplants and other costs to individuals waiting for other organs. More important, it would prevent thousands of deaths and improve the quality of life among those who now must wait years before getting the organs they need.
The most effective change would be to provide compensation to people who give their organs Paying donors for their organs would finally eliminate the supply-demand gap. , sufficient payment to kidney donors would increase the supply of kidneys by a large percentage, without greatly increasing the total cost of a kidney transplant Our conclusion is that a very large number of both live and cadaveric kidney donations would be available by paying about $15,000 for each kidney Iran permits the sale of kidneys by living donors waiting times have been largely eliminated The number of people on dialysis would decline dramatically, and deaths due to long waits for a transplant would essentially disappear the claim that payments would be ineffective isn't consistent with what we know about the supply of other parts of the body for medical use Paying for organs would save the cost of dialysis for people waiting for kidney transplants and other costs to individuals waiting for other organs.
Finding a way to increase the supply of organs would reduce wait times and deaths, and it would greatly ease the suffering that many sick individuals now endure while they hope for a transplant. The most effective change, we believe, would be to provide compensation to people who give their organs—that is, we recommend establishing a market for organs. Organ transplants are one of the extraordinary developments of modern science. They began in 1954 with a kidney transplant performed at Brigham & Women's hospital in Boston. But the practice only took off in the 1970s with the development of immunosuppressive drugs that could prevent the rejection of transplanted organs. Since then, the number of kidney and other organ transplants has grown rapidly, but not nearly as rapidly as the growth in the number of people with defective organs who need transplants. The result has been longer and longer delays to receive organs. Many of those waiting for kidneys are on dialysis, and life expectancy while on dialysis isn't long. For example, people age 45 to 49 live, on average, eight additional years if they remain on dialysis, but they live an additional 23 years if they get a kidney transplant. That is why in 2012, almost 4,500 persons died while waiting for kidney transplants. Although some of those waiting would have died anyway, the great majority died because they were unable to replace their defective kidneys quickly enough. Enlarge Image The toll on those waiting for kidneys and on their families is enormous, from both greatly reduced life expectancy and the many hardships of being on dialysis. Most of those on dialysis cannot work, and the annual cost of dialysis averages about $80,000. The total cost over the average 4.5-year waiting period before receiving a kidney transplant is $350,000, which is much larger than the $150,000 cost of the transplant itself. Individuals can live a normal life with only one kidney, so about 34% of all kidneys used in transplants come from live donors. The majority of transplant kidneys come from parents, children, siblings and other relatives of those who need transplants. The rest come from individuals who want to help those in need of transplants. In recent years, kidney exchanges—in which pairs of living would-be donors and recipients who prove incompatible look for another pair or pairs of donors and recipients who would be compatible for transplants, cutting their wait time—have become more widespread. Although these exchanges have grown rapidly in the U.S. since 2005, they still account for only 9% of live donations and just 3% of all kidney donations, including after-death donations. The relatively minor role of exchanges in total donations isn't an accident, because exchanges are really a form of barter, and barter is always an inefficient way to arrange transactions. Exhortations and other efforts to encourage more organ donations have failed to significantly close the large gap between supply and demand. For example, some countries use an implied consent approach, in which organs from cadavers are assumed to be available for transplant unless, before death, individuals indicate that they don't want their organs to be used. (The U.S. continues to use informed consent, requiring people to make an active declaration of their wish to donate.) In our own highly preliminary study of a few countries—Argentina, Austria, Brazil, Chile and Denmark—that have made the shift to implied consent from informed consent or vice versa, we found that the switch didn't lead to consistent changes in the number of transplant surgeries. Other studies have found more positive effects from switching to implied consent, but none of the effects would be large enough to eliminate the sizable shortfall in the supply of organs in the U.S. That shortfall isn't just an American problem. It exists in most other countries as well, even when they use different methods to procure organs and have different cultures and traditions. Paying donors for their organs would finally eliminate the supply-demand gap. In particular, sufficient payment to kidney donors would increase the supply of kidneys by a large percentage, without greatly increasing the total cost of a kidney transplant. We have estimated how much individuals would need to be paid for kidneys to be willing to sell them for transplants. These estimates take account of the slight risk to donors from transplant surgery, the number of weeks of work lost during the surgery and recovery periods, and the small risk of reduction in the quality of life. Our conclusion is that a very large number of both live and cadaveric kidney donations would be available by paying about $15,000 for each kidney. That estimate isn't exact, and the true cost could be as high as $25,000 or as low as $5,000—but even the high estimate wouldn't increase the total cost of kidney transplants by a large percentage. Few countries have ever allowed the open purchase and sale of organs, but Iran permits the sale of kidneys by living donors. Scattered and incomplete evidence from Iran indicates that the price of kidneys there is about $4,000 and that waiting times to get kidneys have been largely eliminated. Since Iran's per capita income is one-quarter of that of the U.S., this evidence supports our $15,000 estimate. Other countries are also starting to think along these lines: Singapore and Australia have recently introduced limited payments to live donors that compensate mainly for time lost from work. Since the number of kidneys available at a reasonable price would be far more than needed to close the gap between the demand and supply of kidneys, there would no longer be any significant waiting time to get a kidney transplant. The number of people on dialysis would decline dramatically, and deaths due to long waits for a transplant would essentially disappear. Today, finding a compatible kidney isn't easy. There are four basic blood types, and tissue matching is complex and involves the combination of six proteins. Blood and tissue type determine the chance that a kidney will help a recipient in the long run. But the sale of organs would result in a large supply of most kidney types, and with large numbers of kidneys available, transplant surgeries could be arranged to suit the health of recipients (and donors) because surgeons would be confident that compatible kidneys would be available. The system that we're proposing would include payment to individuals who agree that their organs can be used after they die. This is important because transplants for heart and lungs and most liver transplants only use organs from the deceased. Under a new system, individuals would sell their organs "forward" (that is, for future use), with payment going to their heirs after their organs are harvested. Relatives sometimes refuse to have organs used even when a deceased family member has explicitly requested it, and they would be more inclined to honor such wishes if they received substantial compensation for their assent. The idea of paying organ donors has met with strong opposition from some (but not all) transplant surgeons and other doctors, as well as various academics, political leaders and others. Critics have claimed that paying for organs would be ineffective, that payment would be immoral because it involves the sale of body parts and that the main donors would be the desperate poor, who could come to regret their decision. In short, critics believe that monetary payments for organs would be repugnant. But the claim that payments would be ineffective in eliminating the shortage of organs isn't consistent with what we know about the supply of other parts of the body for medical use. For example, the U.S. allows market-determined payments to surrogate mothers—and surrogacy takes time, involves great discomfort and is somewhat risky. Yet in the U.S., the average payment to a surrogate mother is only about $20,000. Another illuminating example is the all-volunteer U.S. military. Critics once asserted that it wouldn't be possible to get enough capable volunteers by offering them only reasonable pay, especially in wartime. But the all-volunteer force has worked well in the U.S., even during wars, and the cost of these recruits hasn't been excessive. Whether paying donors is immoral because it involves the sale of organs is a much more subjective matter, but we question this assertion, given the very serious problems with the present system. Any claim about the supposed immorality of organ sales should be weighed against the morality of preventing thousands of deaths each year and improving the quality of life of those waiting for organs. How can paying for organs to increase their supply be more immoral than the injustice of the present system? Under the type of system we propose, safeguards could be created against impulsive behavior or exploitation. For example, to reduce the likelihood of rash donations, a period of three months or longer could be required before someone would be allowed to donate their kidneys or other organs. This would give donors a chance to re-evaluate their decisions, and they could change their minds at any time before the surgery. They could also receive guidance from counselors on the wisdom of these decisions. Though the poor would be more likely to sell their kidneys and other organs, they also suffer more than others from the current scarcity. Today, the rich often don't wait as long as others for organs since some of them go to countries such as India, where they can arrange for transplants in the underground medical sector, and others (such as the late Steve Jobs ) manage to jump the queue by having residence in several states or other means. The sale of organs would make them more available to the poor, and Medicaid could help pay for the added cost of transplant surgery. The altruistic giving of organs might decline with an open market, since the incentive to give organs to a relative, friend or anyone else would be weaker when organs are readily available to buy. On the other hand, the altruistic giving of money to those in need of organs could increase to help them pay for the cost of organ transplants. Paying for organs would lead to more transplants—and thereby, perhaps, to a large increase in the overall medical costs of transplantation. But it would save the cost of dialysis for people waiting for kidney transplants and other costs to individuals waiting for other organs. More important, it would prevent thousands of deaths and improve the quality of life among those who now must wait years before getting the organs they need.
10,692
<h4>Even if some crowd out occurred, sales would still provide an adequate supply of organs<u><strong> </h4><p></u>Study by Becker and Elias 14 </strong>Gary S. Becker, Nobel Prize-winning professor of economics at the University of Chicago and a senior fellow at the Hoover Institution; and Julio J. Elias, economics professor at the Universidad del CEMA in Argentina.<strong> </strong>Updated Jan. 18, 2014 Wall Street Journal Cash for Kidneys: The Case for a Market for Organs</p><p><u>http://online.wsj.com/news/articles/SB10001424052702304149404579322560004817176?mod=WSJ_hpp_MIDDLENexttoWhatsNewsFifth</p><p>Finding a way to increase the supply of organs would reduce wait times and deaths, and it would greatly ease the suffering that many sick individuals now endure while they hope for a transplant. <mark>The most effective change</u></mark>, we believe, <u><mark>would be to provide compensation to people who give their organs</mark>—that is, we recommend establishing a market for organs. </u>Organ transplants are one of the extraordinary developments of modern science. They began in 1954 with a kidney transplant performed at Brigham & Women's hospital in Boston. But the practice only took off in the 1970s with the development of immunosuppressive drugs that could prevent the rejection of transplanted organs. Since then, the number of kidney and other organ transplants has grown rapidly, but not nearly as rapidly as the growth in the number of people with defective organs who need transplants. The result has been longer and longer delays to receive organs. Many of those waiting for kidneys are on dialysis, and life expectancy while on dialysis isn't long. For example, people age 45 to 49 live, on average, eight additional years if they remain on dialysis, but they live an additional 23 years if they get a kidney transplant. That is why in 2012, almost 4,500 persons died while waiting for kidney transplants. Although some of those waiting would have died anyway, the great majority died because they were unable to replace their defective kidneys quickly enough. Enlarge Image The toll on those waiting for kidneys and on their families is enormous, from both greatly reduced life expectancy and the many hardships of being on dialysis. Most of those on dialysis cannot work, and the annual cost of dialysis averages about $80,000. The total cost over the average 4.5-year waiting period before receiving a kidney transplant is $350,000, which is much larger than the $150,000 cost of the transplant itself. Individuals can live a normal life with only one kidney, so about 34% of all kidneys used in transplants come from live donors. The majority of transplant kidneys come from parents, children, siblings and other relatives of those who need transplants. The rest come from individuals who want to help those in need of transplants. In recent years, kidney exchanges—in which pairs of living would-be donors and recipients who prove incompatible look for another pair or pairs of donors and recipients who would be compatible for transplants, cutting their wait time—have become more widespread. Although these exchanges have grown rapidly in the U.S. since 2005, they still account for only 9% of live donations and just 3% of all kidney donations, including after-death donations. The relatively minor role of exchanges in total donations isn't an accident, because exchanges are really a form of barter, and barter is always an inefficient way to arrange transactions. Exhortations and other efforts to encourage more organ donations have failed to significantly close the large gap between supply and demand. For example, some countries use an implied consent approach, in which organs from cadavers are assumed to be available for transplant unless, before death, individuals indicate that they don't want their organs to be used. (The U.S. continues to use informed consent, requiring people to make an active declaration of their wish to donate.) In our own highly preliminary study of a few countries—Argentina, Austria, Brazil, Chile and Denmark—that have made the shift to implied consent from informed consent or vice versa, we found that the switch didn't lead to consistent changes in the number of transplant surgeries. Other studies have found more positive effects from switching to implied consent, but none of the effects would be large enough to eliminate the sizable shortfall in the supply of organs in the U.S. That shortfall isn't just an American problem. It exists in most other countries as well, even when they use different methods to procure organs and have different cultures and traditions. <u><mark>Paying donors for their organs would finally eliminate the supply-demand gap</u>.</mark> In particular<mark>, <u>sufficient payment to kidney donors would increase the supply of kidneys by a large percentage, without greatly increasing the total cost of a kidney transplant</mark>. We have estimated how much individuals would need to be paid for kidneys to be willing to sell them for transplants. </u>These estimates take account of the slight risk to donors from transplant surgery, the number of weeks of work lost during the surgery and recovery periods, and the small risk of reduction in the quality of life. <u><mark>Our conclusion is that a very large number of both live and cadaveric kidney donations would be available by paying about $15,000 for each kidney</mark>.</u> That estimate isn't exact, and the true cost could be as high as $25,000 or as low as $5,000—but even the high estimate wouldn't increase the total cost of kidney transplants by a large percentage. Few countries have ever allowed the open purchase and sale of organs, but <u><mark>Iran permits the sale of kidneys by living donors</mark>.</u> Scattered and incomplete evidence from Iran indicates that the price of kidneys there is about $4,000 and that <u><mark>waiting times</mark> to get kidneys <mark>have been largely eliminated</u></mark>. Since Iran's per capita income is one-quarter of that of the U.S., this evidence supports our $15,000 estimate. Other countries are also starting to think along these lines: Singapore and Australia have recently introduced limited payments to live donors that compensate mainly for time lost from work. <u>Since the number of kidneys available at a reasonable price would be far more than needed to close the gap between the demand and supply of kidneys, there would no longer be any significant waiting time to get a kidney transplant. <mark>The number of people on dialysis would decline dramatically, and deaths due to long waits for a transplant would essentially disappear</mark>. </u>Today, finding a compatible kidney isn't easy. There are four basic blood types, and tissue matching is complex and involves the combination of six proteins. Blood and tissue type determine the chance that a kidney will help a recipient in the long run. But the sale of organs would result in a large supply of most kidney types, and with large numbers of kidneys available, transplant surgeries could be arranged to suit the health of recipients (and donors) because surgeons would be confident that compatible kidneys would be available. The system that we're proposing would include payment to individuals who agree that their organs can be used after they die. This is important because transplants for heart and lungs and most liver transplants only use organs from the deceased. Under a new system, individuals would sell their organs "forward" (that is, for future use), with payment going to their heirs after their organs are harvested. Relatives sometimes refuse to have organs used even when a deceased family member has explicitly requested it, and they would be more inclined to honor such wishes if they received substantial compensation for their assent. The idea of paying organ donors has met with strong opposition from some (but not all) transplant surgeons and other doctors, as well as various academics, political leaders and others. Critics have claimed that paying for organs would be ineffective, that payment would be immoral because it involves the sale of body parts and that the main donors would be the desperate poor, who could come to regret their decision. In short, critics believe that monetary payments for organs would be repugnant. But <u><mark>the claim that payments would be ineffective</mark> in eliminating the shortage of organs <mark>isn't consistent with what we know about the supply of other parts of the body for medical use</mark>.</u> For example, the U.S. allows market-determined payments to surrogate mothers—and surrogacy takes time, involves great discomfort and is somewhat risky. Yet in the U.S., the average payment to a surrogate mother is only about $20,000. Another illuminating example is the all-volunteer U.S. military. Critics once asserted that it wouldn't be possible to get enough capable volunteers by offering them only reasonable pay, especially in wartime. But the all-volunteer force has worked well in the U.S., even during wars, and the cost of these recruits hasn't been excessive. Whether paying donors is immoral because it involves the sale of organs is a much more subjective matter, but we question this assertion, given the very serious problems with the present system. Any claim about the supposed immorality of organ sales should be weighed against the morality of preventing thousands of deaths each year and improving the quality of life of those waiting for organs. How can paying for organs to increase their supply be more immoral than the injustice of the present system? Under the type of system we propose, safeguards could be created against impulsive behavior or exploitation. For example, to reduce the likelihood of rash donations, a period of three months or longer could be required before someone would be allowed to donate their kidneys or other organs. This would give donors a chance to re-evaluate their decisions, and they could change their minds at any time before the surgery. They could also receive guidance from counselors on the wisdom of these decisions. Though the poor would be more likely to sell their kidneys and other organs, they also suffer more than others from the current scarcity. Today, the rich often don't wait as long as others for organs since some of them go to countries such as India, where they can arrange for transplants in the underground medical sector, and others (such as the late Steve Jobs ) manage to jump the queue by having residence in several states or other means. The sale of organs would make them more available to the poor, and Medicaid could help pay for the added cost of transplant surgery. The altruistic giving of organs might decline with an open market, since the incentive to give organs to a relative, friend or anyone else would be weaker when organs are readily available to buy. On the other hand, the altruistic giving of money to those in need of organs could increase to help them pay for the cost of organ transplants. <u><mark>Paying for organs</mark> </u>would lead to more transplants—and thereby, perhaps, to a large increase in the overall medical costs of transplantation. But it <u><mark>would save the cost of dialysis for people waiting for kidney transplants and other costs to individuals waiting for other organs.</mark> More important, it would prevent thousands of deaths and improve the quality of life among those who now must wait years before getting the organs they need.</p></u>
null
null
Contention 1 – Organ sales will save lives
430,254
24
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,260
Suicide can’t be an affirmation of agency because it cancels the subject
Osborne 6
Osborne 6 Thomas Osborne, Department of Sociology, University of Bristol, “‘Fascinated dispossession’: suicide and the aesthetics of freedom,” Economy and Society Volume 34, Issue 2, 2005, 8/16/2006
the very image of suicide as a locus of free decision is something of a chimera a form of moral hubris or romanticism there is a kind of essentially contested ambiguity about the act of suicide suicide can never really amount to an act of pure agency , in so far as it does amount to such a thing it simultaneously cancels itself out The performance of the event is a failure for the subject for the simple - almost banal - reason that if the suicide attempt is successful there is no longer any subject present action here is only the mask of a fascinated dispossession However much suicide is an act of agency, that agency is conquered by death; and if it is not conquered by death it becomes an 'attempted suicide', a 'cry for help', hence not an act of constitutive agency at all but a failed act of will It is precisely the paradoxical nature of suicide as an act of pure will that accounts for the magnetism of the question of suicide and the impossibility of closure in relation to such questions Suicide can seem at once the most voluntaristic and defiant of actions and the most passive and fatalistic and the same suicide can seem to be simultaneously both same action can seem to be both a voluntaristic act of will and a negative capitulation
the very image of suicide as free decision is something of a chimera a form of moral romanticism suicide can never really amount to an act of pure agency in so far as it does it simultaneously cancels itself out The performance is a failure for the subject for the simple - almost banal - reason that if the suicide attempt is successful there is no longer any subject present action here is only the mask of a fascinated dispossession' agency is conquered by death; and if it is not conquered by death it becomes an 'attempted suicide' a failed act of will . It is precisely the paradoxical nature of suicide that accounts for the impossibility of closure in relation to such questions Suicide can seem at once the most voluntaristic and defiant of actions and the most passive and fatalistic and the same suicide can seem to be simultaneously both
But, the complexities of Foucault's own position aside, is the category of suicide actually capable of living up to the demands that are being made on it by the aesthetic conception? Can suicide really be deployed as a component of an aesthetic of freedom? What is at stake in such questions is really the status of the aesthetic view on existence itself. It could be argued, in fact, that the very image of suicide as a locus of free, aesthetic decision is something of a chimera, an instance of what could be described - when taken beyond the form of a regulative ideal - as a form of moral hubris or romanticism; even, indeed, an example of the phenomenon of willing what cannot be willed (Elster 1983; cf. Farber 1976). This is because there is a kind of essentially contested ambiguity about the act of suicide. As a tradition of thought associated with Maurice Blanchot has argued, suicide can never really amount to an act of pure agency, that is, an act for the subject. Or, at least, in so far as it does amount to such a thing it simultaneously cancels itself out; there is an essential ambiguity to it. The performance of the event is a failure for the subject for the simple - almost banal - reason that if the suicide attempt is successful there is no longer any subject present. As Blanchot has it in The Space of Literature, death cannot be conquered by suicide precisely because death is the unknown: 'It is the passage from the certainty of an act that has been planned ... to something which disorients every project, remains foreign to all decisions' (Blanchot 1982 [1955]: 104). The attempt is futile: 'Thus in voluntary death it is still extreme passivity that we perceive - the fact that action here is only the mask of a fascinated dispossession' (ibid.: 102). One thinks here of the question that Henry Miller wanted to ask of Mishima: 'how had death tasted? Was it truly the culmination of everything or did it still leave something to the imagination?' (Miller 1972: 38). The question is of course unanswerable. However much suicide is an act of agency, that agency is conquered by death; and if it is not conquered by death it becomes an 'attempted suicide', a 'cry for help', hence not an act of constitutive agency at all but a failed act of will (Stengel 1970). The willing of suicide as an act of will has self-defeating properties. There is, in any case, an integral ambiguity at the core of the very idea of suicide when addressed in terms of absolute agency and free autonomy. But no doubt this is precisely why a person's suicide so typically opens onto a sort of contested inquest zone as to the extent and limits of their autonomy at the time of their death. It is precisely the paradoxical nature of suicide as an act of pure will that accounts for both the magnetism of the question of suicide in relation to questions of ethics and deliberations over causality and the impossibility of closure in relation to such questions and deliberations. Suicide can seem at once the most voluntaristic and defiant of actions and the most passive and fatalistic and the same suicide can seem to be simultaneously both. Perhaps this is only a function of the figure of the 'indeterminacy of the past' given prominence by Ian Hacking after G. E. M. Anscombe (Hacking 1997). If all action is action under a description, then clearly there can be a plurality of descriptions or interpretations of any single action. But suicide seems, so to speak, to polarize the alternatives of description. The same action can seem at once to be both a voluntaristic act of will and a negative capitulation, Blanchot's extreme passivity at the heart of voluntary, active death.
3,687
<h4>Suicide can’t be an affirmation of agency because it cancels the subject</h4><p><strong>Osborne 6</strong> Thomas Osborne, Department of Sociology, University of Bristol, “‘Fascinated dispossession’: suicide and the aesthetics of freedom,” Economy and Society Volume 34, Issue 2, 2005, 8/16/2006</p><p>But, the complexities of Foucault's own position aside, is the category of suicide actually capable of living up to the demands that are being made on it by the aesthetic conception? Can suicide really be deployed as a component of an aesthetic of freedom? What is at stake in such questions is really the status of the aesthetic view on existence itself. It could be argued, in fact, that <u><mark>the very image of</mark> <mark>suicide as</mark> a locus of <mark>free</u></mark>, aesthetic <u><mark>decision is something of a chimera</u></mark>, an instance of what could be described - when taken beyond the form of a regulative ideal - as <u><mark>a form of moral</mark> hubris or <mark>romanticism</u></mark>; even, indeed, an example of the phenomenon of willing what cannot be willed (Elster 1983; cf. Farber 1976).</p><p>This is because <u>there is a kind of essentially contested ambiguity about the act of suicide</u>. As a tradition of thought associated with Maurice Blanchot has argued, <u><mark>suicide can never really amount to an act of pure agency</u></mark>, that is, an act for the subject. Or, at least<u>, <mark>in so far as it does</mark> amount to such a thing <mark>it simultaneously cancels itself out</u></mark>; there is an essential ambiguity to it. <u><mark>The performance</mark> of the event <mark>is a failure for the subject for the simple - almost banal - reason that if the suicide attempt is successful there is no longer any subject present</u></mark>. As Blanchot has it in The Space of Literature, death cannot be conquered by suicide precisely because death is the unknown: 'It is the passage from the certainty of an act that has been planned ... to something which disorients every project, remains foreign to all decisions' (Blanchot 1982 [1955]: 104). The attempt is futile: 'Thus in voluntary death it is still extreme passivity that we perceive - the fact that <u><mark>action here is only the mask of a fascinated dispossession</u>'</mark> (ibid.: 102).</p><p>One thinks here of the question that Henry Miller wanted to ask of Mishima: 'how had death tasted? Was it truly the culmination of everything or did it still leave something to the imagination?' (Miller 1972: 38). The question is of course unanswerable. <u>However much suicide is an act of agency, that <mark>agency is conquered by death; and if it is not conquered by death it becomes an 'attempted suicide'</mark>, a 'cry for help', hence not an act of constitutive agency at all but <mark>a failed act of will</u></mark> (Stengel 1970). The willing of suicide as an act of will has self-defeating properties.</p><p>There is, in any case, an integral ambiguity at the core of the very idea of suicide when addressed in terms of absolute agency and free autonomy. But no doubt this is precisely why a person's suicide so typically opens onto a sort of contested inquest zone as to the extent and limits of their autonomy at the time of their death<mark>. <u>It is precisely the paradoxical nature of suicide</mark> as an act of pure will <mark>that accounts for</u></mark> both <u>the magnetism of the question of suicide</u> in relation to questions of ethics and deliberations over causality <u>and <mark>the impossibility of closure in relation to such questions</u></mark> and deliberations. <u><mark>Suicide can seem at once the most voluntaristic and defiant of actions and the most passive and fatalistic and the same suicide can seem to be simultaneously both</u></mark>. Perhaps this is only a function of the figure of the 'indeterminacy of the past' given prominence by Ian Hacking after G. E. M. Anscombe (Hacking 1997). If all action is action under a description, then clearly there can be a plurality of descriptions or interpretations of any single action. But suicide seems, so to speak, to polarize the alternatives of description. The <u>same action can seem</u> at once <u>to be both a voluntaristic act of will and a negative capitulation</u>, Blanchot's extreme passivity at the heart of voluntary, active death.</p>
null
null
Case
430,369
3
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,261
We meet-Wilkinson says the plan is one way to legalize organ sales and Erin-Harris say it would maximize sales
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4><strong>We meet-Wilkinson says the plan is one way to legalize organ sales and Erin-Harris say it would maximize sales</h4></strong>
2AC
Contention 4 is risk calculus
2ac nearly all
430,624
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,262
Suicide can’t be an affirmation of agency because it cancels the subject
Osborne 6
Osborne 6 Thomas Osborne, Department of Sociology, University of Bristol, “‘Fascinated dispossession’: suicide and the aesthetics of freedom,” Economy and Society Volume 34, Issue 2, 2005, 8/16/2006
the very image of suicide as a locus of free decision is something of a chimera a form of moral hubris or romanticism there is a kind of essentially contested ambiguity about the act of suicide suicide can never really amount to an act of pure agency , in so far as it does amount to such a thing it simultaneously cancels itself out The performance of the event is a failure for the subject for the simple - almost banal - reason that if the suicide attempt is successful there is no longer any subject present action here is only the mask of a fascinated dispossession However much suicide is an act of agency, that agency is conquered by death; and if it is not conquered by death it becomes an 'attempted suicide', a 'cry for help', hence not an act of constitutive agency at all but a failed act of will It is precisely the paradoxical nature of suicide as an act of pure will that accounts for the magnetism of the question of suicide and the impossibility of closure in relation to such questions Suicide can seem at once the most voluntaristic and defiant of actions and the most passive and fatalistic and the same suicide can seem to be simultaneously both same action can seem to be both a voluntaristic act of will and a negative capitulation
the very image of suicide as free decision is something of a chimera a form of moral romanticism suicide can never really amount to an act of pure agency in so far as it does it simultaneously cancels itself out The performance is a failure for the subject for the simple - almost banal - reason that if the suicide attempt is successful there is no longer any subject present action here is only the mask of a fascinated dispossession' agency is conquered by death; and if it is not conquered by death it becomes an 'attempted suicide' a failed act of will . It is precisely the paradoxical nature of suicide that accounts for the impossibility of closure in relation to such questions Suicide can seem at once the most voluntaristic and defiant of actions and the most passive and fatalistic and the same suicide can seem to be simultaneously both
But, the complexities of Foucault's own position aside, is the category of suicide actually capable of living up to the demands that are being made on it by the aesthetic conception? Can suicide really be deployed as a component of an aesthetic of freedom? What is at stake in such questions is really the status of the aesthetic view on existence itself. It could be argued, in fact, that the very image of suicide as a locus of free, aesthetic decision is something of a chimera, an instance of what could be described - when taken beyond the form of a regulative ideal - as a form of moral hubris or romanticism; even, indeed, an example of the phenomenon of willing what cannot be willed (Elster 1983; cf. Farber 1976). This is because there is a kind of essentially contested ambiguity about the act of suicide. As a tradition of thought associated with Maurice Blanchot has argued, suicide can never really amount to an act of pure agency, that is, an act for the subject. Or, at least, in so far as it does amount to such a thing it simultaneously cancels itself out; there is an essential ambiguity to it. The performance of the event is a failure for the subject for the simple - almost banal - reason that if the suicide attempt is successful there is no longer any subject present. As Blanchot has it in The Space of Literature, death cannot be conquered by suicide precisely because death is the unknown: 'It is the passage from the certainty of an act that has been planned ... to something which disorients every project, remains foreign to all decisions' (Blanchot 1982 [1955]: 104). The attempt is futile: 'Thus in voluntary death it is still extreme passivity that we perceive - the fact that action here is only the mask of a fascinated dispossession' (ibid.: 102). One thinks here of the question that Henry Miller wanted to ask of Mishima: 'how had death tasted? Was it truly the culmination of everything or did it still leave something to the imagination?' (Miller 1972: 38). The question is of course unanswerable. However much suicide is an act of agency, that agency is conquered by death; and if it is not conquered by death it becomes an 'attempted suicide', a 'cry for help', hence not an act of constitutive agency at all but a failed act of will (Stengel 1970). The willing of suicide as an act of will has self-defeating properties. There is, in any case, an integral ambiguity at the core of the very idea of suicide when addressed in terms of absolute agency and free autonomy. But no doubt this is precisely why a person's suicide so typically opens onto a sort of contested inquest zone as to the extent and limits of their autonomy at the time of their death. It is precisely the paradoxical nature of suicide as an act of pure will that accounts for both the magnetism of the question of suicide in relation to questions of ethics and deliberations over causality and the impossibility of closure in relation to such questions and deliberations. Suicide can seem at once the most voluntaristic and defiant of actions and the most passive and fatalistic and the same suicide can seem to be simultaneously both. Perhaps this is only a function of the figure of the 'indeterminacy of the past' given prominence by Ian Hacking after G. E. M. Anscombe (Hacking 1997). If all action is action under a description, then clearly there can be a plurality of descriptions or interpretations of any single action. But suicide seems, so to speak, to polarize the alternatives of description. The same action can seem at once to be both a voluntaristic act of will and a negative capitulation, Blanchot's extreme passivity at the heart of voluntary, active death.
3,687
<h4>Suicide can’t be an affirmation of agency because it cancels the subject</h4><p><strong>Osborne 6</strong> Thomas Osborne, Department of Sociology, University of Bristol, “‘Fascinated dispossession’: suicide and the aesthetics of freedom,” Economy and Society Volume 34, Issue 2, 2005, 8/16/2006</p><p>But, the complexities of Foucault's own position aside, is the category of suicide actually capable of living up to the demands that are being made on it by the aesthetic conception? Can suicide really be deployed as a component of an aesthetic of freedom? What is at stake in such questions is really the status of the aesthetic view on existence itself. It could be argued, in fact, that <u><mark>the very image of</mark> <mark>suicide as</mark> a locus of <mark>free</u></mark>, aesthetic <u><mark>decision is something of a chimera</u></mark>, an instance of what could be described - when taken beyond the form of a regulative ideal - as <u><mark>a form of moral</mark> hubris or <mark>romanticism</u></mark>; even, indeed, an example of the phenomenon of willing what cannot be willed (Elster 1983; cf. Farber 1976).</p><p>This is because <u>there is a kind of essentially contested ambiguity about the act of suicide</u>. As a tradition of thought associated with Maurice Blanchot has argued, <u><mark>suicide can never really amount to an act of pure agency</u></mark>, that is, an act for the subject. Or, at least<u>, <mark>in so far as it does</mark> amount to such a thing <mark>it simultaneously cancels itself out</u></mark>; there is an essential ambiguity to it. <u><mark>The performance</mark> of the event <mark>is a failure for the subject for the simple - almost banal - reason that if the suicide attempt is successful there is no longer any subject present</u></mark>. As Blanchot has it in The Space of Literature, death cannot be conquered by suicide precisely because death is the unknown: 'It is the passage from the certainty of an act that has been planned ... to something which disorients every project, remains foreign to all decisions' (Blanchot 1982 [1955]: 104). The attempt is futile: 'Thus in voluntary death it is still extreme passivity that we perceive - the fact that <u><mark>action here is only the mask of a fascinated dispossession</u>'</mark> (ibid.: 102).</p><p>One thinks here of the question that Henry Miller wanted to ask of Mishima: 'how had death tasted? Was it truly the culmination of everything or did it still leave something to the imagination?' (Miller 1972: 38). The question is of course unanswerable. <u>However much suicide is an act of agency, that <mark>agency is conquered by death; and if it is not conquered by death it becomes an 'attempted suicide'</mark>, a 'cry for help', hence not an act of constitutive agency at all but <mark>a failed act of will</u></mark> (Stengel 1970). The willing of suicide as an act of will has self-defeating properties.</p><p>There is, in any case, an integral ambiguity at the core of the very idea of suicide when addressed in terms of absolute agency and free autonomy. But no doubt this is precisely why a person's suicide so typically opens onto a sort of contested inquest zone as to the extent and limits of their autonomy at the time of their death<mark>. <u>It is precisely the paradoxical nature of suicide</mark> as an act of pure will <mark>that accounts for</u></mark> both <u>the magnetism of the question of suicide</u> in relation to questions of ethics and deliberations over causality <u>and <mark>the impossibility of closure in relation to such questions</u></mark> and deliberations. <u><mark>Suicide can seem at once the most voluntaristic and defiant of actions and the most passive and fatalistic and the same suicide can seem to be simultaneously both</u></mark>. Perhaps this is only a function of the figure of the 'indeterminacy of the past' given prominence by Ian Hacking after G. E. M. Anscombe (Hacking 1997). If all action is action under a description, then clearly there can be a plurality of descriptions or interpretations of any single action. But suicide seems, so to speak, to polarize the alternatives of description. The <u>same action can seem</u> at once <u>to be both a voluntaristic act of will and a negative capitulation</u>, Blanchot's extreme passivity at the heart of voluntary, active death.</p>
null
Case
CP
430,369
3
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,263
Their threats are constructed by the military industrial complex
Lutz 9
Lutz (Research Professor at the Watson Institute for International Studies and Professor of Anthropology at Brown University) 9
The Asia-Pacific Journal, Vol. 12-3-09, March 16, 2009. elites have built bases as a visible sign of the nation’s standin politicians and the public have treated the number of their bases as indicators of the nation’s hyperpower overseas military bases can also be seen as symptoms of irrational or untethered fears, even paranoia, as they are built with the long-term goal of taming a world perceived to be out of control Empires frequently misperceive the world as rife with threats Militaries’ interest in organizational survival has also contributed to the amplification of this fear and imperial basing structures as the solution as they “sell themselves” to their populace by exaggerating threats, underestimating the costs of basing and war itself, as well as understating the obstacles facing preemption and belligerence
overseas bases can be seen as symptoms of untethered fears Militaries’ interest in organizational survival has contributed to the amplification of fear they “sell themselves” to their populace exaggerating threats underestimating costs of war
(Catherine, US Bases and Empire: Global Perspectives on the Asia Pacific, The Asia-Pacific Journal, Vol. 12-3-09, March 16, 2009. http://old.japanfocus.org/-Catherine_Lutz/3086) Alongside their military and economic functions, bases have symbolic and psychological dimensions.  They are highly visible expressions of a nation’s will to status and power.  Strategic elites have built bases as a visible sign of the nation’s standing, much as they have constructed monuments and battleships. So, too, contemporary US politicians and the public have treated the number of their bases as indicators of the nation’s hyperstatus and hyperpower.  More darkly, overseas military bases can also be seen as symptoms of irrational or untethered fears, even paranoia, as they are built with the long-term goal of taming a world perceived to be out of control.  Empires frequently misperceive the world as rife with threats and themselves as objects of violent hostility from others.  Militaries’ interest in organizational survival has also contributed to the amplification of this fear and imperial basing structures as the solution as they “sell themselves” to their populace by exaggerating threats, underestimating the costs of basing and war itself, as well as understating the obstacles facing preemption and belligerence (Van Evera 2001).
1,333
<h4><u><strong>Their threats are constructed by the military industrial complex</h4><p><mark>Lutz</u></strong></mark> (Research Professor at the Watson Institute for International Studies and Professor of Anthropology at Brown University) <u><strong><mark>9</p><p></u></strong></mark>(Catherine, US Bases and Empire: Global Perspectives on the Asia Pacific,<u><strong> The Asia-Pacific Journal, Vol. 12-3-09, March 16, 2009.</u></strong> http://old.japanfocus.org/-Catherine_Lutz/3086)</p><p>Alongside their military and economic functions, bases have symbolic and psychological dimensions.  They are highly visible expressions of a nation’s will to status and power.  Strategic<u> elites have built bases as a visible sign of the nation’s standin</u>g, much as they have constructed monuments and battleships. So, too, contemporary US <u>politicians and the public have treated the number of their bases as indicators of the nation’s</u> hyperstatus and <u>hyperpower</u>.  More darkly, <u><strong><mark>overseas</mark> military <mark>bases</mark> <mark>can</mark> also <mark>be seen as symptoms of</mark> irrational or <mark>untethered fears</mark>, even paranoia, as they are built with the long-term goal of taming a world perceived to be out of control</u></strong>.  <u>Empires frequently misperceive the world as rife with threats</u> and themselves as objects of violent hostility from others.  <u><mark>Militaries’ interest in <strong>organizational survival</strong> has</mark> also <mark>contributed to the amplification of </mark>this <mark>fear </mark>and imperial basing structures as the solution as <mark>they “sell themselves” to their populace </mark>by <mark>exaggerating threats</mark>, <mark>underestimating</mark> the <mark>costs of</mark> basing and <mark>war</mark> itself, as well as understating the obstacles facing preemption and belligerence</u> (Van Evera 2001).</p>
WTO
Heg/Trade
AT: Inevitable
430,625
1
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,264
Terrorism discourse is wrong and leads to war
Cortright 8
Cortright 8 [David, President of the Fourth Freedom Forum and research fellow for the Joan B. Kroc Institute for International Peace Studies, University of Notre Dame, 2008 (“Peace: A History of Movements and Ideas.” Pg. 125]
terrorism has replaced communism as the frame of dehumanization. to lump together all considered enemies. The victims of US bombing and attack in Iraq are branded terrorists, regardless of circumstances The so-called war on terror” is used to justify all measures – invasion, war, military occupation, torture, indefinite internment, warrantless wiretapping – whatever may be deemed necessary to defeat “evil” . Fighting terrorism offers a rationalization for what is otherwise unjustifiable
null
In recent years terrorism has replaced communism as the new frame of dehumanization. It has been used to lump together all those who are considered enemies. The victims of US bombing and attack in Iraq are branded terrorists, regardless of the specific circumstances involved. The so-called “global war on terror” is used to justify any and all measures – invasion, war, military occupation, torture, indefinite internment, warrantless wiretapping – whatever may be deemed necessary by government officials to defeat the “evil” enemy. Fighting terrorism offers a rationalization for what is otherwise unjustifiable, just as during the cold war the fight against communism provided the justification for the unthinkable.
719
<h4><u><strong>Terrorism discourse is wrong and leads to war</h4><p>Cortright 8</u></strong> [David, President of the Fourth Freedom Forum and research fellow for the Joan B. Kroc Institute for International Peace Studies, University of Notre Dame, 2008 (“Peace: A History of Movements and Ideas.” Pg. 125]</p><p>In recent years <u>terrorism has replaced communism as the </u>new<u> frame of dehumanization. </u>It has been used<u> to lump together all </u>those who are <u>considered enemies. The victims of US bombing and attack in Iraq are branded terrorists, regardless of</u> the specific<u> circumstances</u> involved. <u>The so-called </u>“global<u> war on terror” is used to justify </u>any and<u> all measures – invasion, war, military occupation, torture, indefinite internment, warrantless wiretapping – whatever may be deemed necessary </u>by government officials<u> to defeat </u>the<u> “evil” </u>enemy<u>. Fighting terrorism offers a rationalization for what is otherwise unjustifiable</u>, just as during the cold war the fight against communism provided the justification for the unthinkable.</p>
null
null
K
430,519
5
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,265
This effort to police the prostitute's sexuality is a task that can never be fully realized. The prostitute’s unfettered sexuality defines society itself because it represents a permanent danger to a politics of respectable sex – the immoral, queer excess against which morality is defined.
Hubbard ’98
Hubbard ’98, Phil Hubbard, Prof. at University of Coventry, UK, “Sexuality, immorality and the city: Red-light districts and the marginalisation of female street prostitutes,” Gender, Place and Culture,
female prostitutes have been marginalised as Other constructed as an Other identity through contradictory images of desire and disgust within processes defining dominant notions of respectable feminine sexuality mass media in Western societies has sought to perpetuate images that depict prostitutes as social pariahs, fallen women, or 'bad girls' and to use such images to distinguish this 'deviant' group from 'normal' purified populations the representation of sex workers has been based around persistent stereotypes of the prostitute as Other constitutes an important theme in writing on the regulation and containment of prostitution, albeit one that is fraught with contractions (prostitutes are, after all, a group that is eroticised and demonised simultaneously prostitutes, although socially marginalised, were of major symbolic importance their representation at the immoral 'margin' crucial for defining the moral 'centre': in essence, the boundaries between domesticised femininity and the unfettered sexuality of the street were constructed and maintained through the discursive identification of prostitutes as dirty and dangerous, a threat to bourgeois society. dominant male fears and fantasies were projected onto the figure of the street prostitute The prostitute was the quintessential figure of the urban scene... for men as well as women, the prostitute was the central spectacle in a set of urban encounters and fantasies. ). The link between sexual depravity and social disorder was further cemented in a literary tradition that depicted street prostitutes as part of a seedy Victorian underworld, affiliated with criminality, deviance, and sexual danger process of Othering prostitutes was reliant on a language of moral outrage and disgust (tempered with fascination and voyeurism), which was spatially transposed onto the landscape of the underworld, This collision between physical and moral impurity reinforced deep-seated anxieties and fears about prostitution, as the prostitute came to symbolise the division of society into high and low - the civilised and the grotesque through a series of metaphors of the body, morality and topography prostitution was the 'great social evil'
female prostitutes have been constructed as Other through contradictory images of desire and disgust Western societies depict prostitutes as 'deviant' group from 'normal' purified populations the prostitute Other constitutes an important theme in regulation and containment of prostitution prostitutes, were of major symbolic importance their representation at the immoral 'margin' crucial for defining the moral 'centre': the boundaries between domesticised femininity and the unfettered sexuality of the street were constructed through the discursive identification of prostitutes as dangerous, a threat to bourgeois society tradition depicted prostitutes as part of a seedy underworld, affiliated with deviance, and sexual danger process of Othering prostitutes was reliant on a moral outrage tempered with voyeurism), which was spatially transposed onto the landscape of the underworld the prostitute came to symbolise the division of society into high and low - the civilised and the grotesque through a series of metaphors of the body, morality and topography prostitution was the 'great social evil'
Such ideas are particularly useful for seeking to understand the way in which female prostitutes have, throughout history, been marginalised as Other. Pile 1996, for example, writes that the female prostitute has remained an emblematic figure at the intersection of sexual and gender relationships, constructed as an Other identity through contradictory images of desire and disgust within processes defining dominant notions of respectable feminine sexuality. Although it is important to note that the extent and intensity of this figuring has varied across time and space with some societies more tolerant of prostitution than others, the mass media in Western societies has generally sought to perpetuate images that depict prostitutes as social pariahs, fallen women, or 'bad girls' and to use such images to distinguish this 'deviant' group from 'normal' purified populations. Roberts, 1992. Exploring such ideas, Sibley 1995 has commented on the frequent representation of street prostitutes as defiling the purity of the city, and one merely needs to consider the way in which recent film and television drama from Taxi Driver to Mona Lisa, from The Bill to Band of Gold has consistently presented stereotyped images of prostitutes as part of a desperate, criminalised underworld, drug-dependent and reliant on the protection of pimps, to appreciate the importance of the media in shaping feelings of abjection towards prostitutes. Even sympathetic portrayals of prostitute women that subvert stereotypical expectations--for example, films such as Personal Services or Working Girls--may demand that these stereotypes are acknowledged, Perkins, 1989. The suggestion that the representation of sex workers has been based around persistent stereotypes of the prostitute as Other constitutes an important theme in writing on the regulation and containment of prostitution, albeit one that is fraught with contractions (prostitutes are, after all, a group that is eroticised and demonised simultaneously). Surprisingly little work has focused on the contemporary media stereotyping of prostitutes though see Murray & Robinson, 1996, with most commentators instead investigating the representation of sex work in the nineteenth century, exploring the way emerging moral-medical ideas were used to label prostitutes as a 'polluting' category at a time when women's role in urban society was undergoing dramatic transformation (Walkowitz, 1980; Mort, 1987). As Corbin 1990 has argued, prostitutes, although socially marginalised, were of major symbolic importance in Victorian society, with their representation at the immoral 'margin' crucial for defining the moral 'centre': in essence, the boundaries between domesticised femininity and the unfettered sexuality of the street were constructed and maintained through the discursive identification of prostitutes as dirty and dangerous, a threat to bourgeois society. Inevitably, a variety of urban flaneurs, epidemiologists, philologists and moral reformers contributed to this process, their obsessive scrutiny of the habits and habitats of 'fallen women' contributing to a variety of pseudo-scientific discourses in which dominant male fears and fantasies were projected onto the figure of the street prostitute: The prostitute was the quintessential figure of the urban scene... for men as well as women, the prostitute was the central spectacle in a set of urban encounters and fantasies. Repudiated and desired, degraded and threatening, the prostitute attracted the attention of a range of urban male explorers from the 1840s to the 1880s. (Walkowitz, 1992, p 233) The medicalisation of female prostitutes as an alleged source of sexually-transmitted diseases, for example, was based solely on the assumption that prostitutes had high numbers of sexual contacts rather than any detailed knowledge of transmission vectors, yet led directly to the imposition of the Contagious Diseases Act of 1864 (updated in 1866 and 1869), which was applied to prostitute women but not their clients in a largely indiscriminate manner (Ogborn, 1992; 1993). The link between sexual depravity and social disorder was further cemented in a literary tradition that depicted street prostitutes as part of a seedy Victorian underworld, affiliated with criminality, deviance, and sexual danger. Walkowitz 1992 has suggested that this tendency was evident not only in the sensationalist tabloid treatment of the Ripper murders, but also in 'high' literary explorations of living conditions in the Victorian city, with Stead's expose of child prostitution in the Pall Mall Gazette 1881 typical in its portrayal of prostitution as encapsulating all that was remiss in Victorian society--drunkenness, perversion, violence, and sexual slavery. Significantly, it has been noted that the nineteenth-century process of Othering prostitutes was reliant on a language of moral outrage and disgust (tempered with fascination and voyeurism), which was spatially transposed onto the landscape of the Victorian underworld, a twilight world of narrow streets, alleys and parks (Jackson, 1989). This collision between physical and moral impurity reinforced deep-seated anxieties and fears about prostitution, as the prostitute came to symbolise the division of society into high and low - the civilised and the grotesque through a series of metaphors of the body, morality and topography (Stallybrass & White, 1986). While prostitution was the 'great social evil' of the day, and a general metaphor for the disorder of the city, discourses of moral hygiene linked the 'erotomaniac and nymphomaniac' behaviour of prostitutes onto their surroundings, with Smart 1982 drawing attention to the correspondence between ideas of prostitutes as deviant and discourses concerning the filth and environmental squalor of slum areas (see also Matlock, 1994). Interventions in housing reform, planning and public health regulation were often rationalised in terms of moral hygiene, with the female prostitute posited as symptomatic of the degeneracy of working-class housing areas (Greed, 1994). It is this idea of space as being central to the process of Othering prostitutes to which I now turn.
6,204
<h4>This effort to police the prostitute's sexuality is a task that can never be fully realized. The prostitute’s unfettered sexuality <u>defines</u> society itself because it represents a permanent danger to a politics of respectable sex – the immoral, queer excess against which morality is defined.</h4><p><strong>Hubbard ’98</strong>, Phil Hubbard, Prof. at University of Coventry, UK, “Sexuality, immorality and the city: Red-light districts and the marginalisation of female street prostitutes,” Gender, Place and Culture, </p><p>Such ideas are particularly useful for seeking to understand the way in which <u><mark>female prostitutes have</u></mark>, throughout history, <u><mark>been</mark> marginalised as Other</u>. Pile 1996, for example, writes that the female prostitute has remained an emblematic figure at the intersection of sexual and gender relationships, <u><mark>constructed as </mark>an <mark>Other </mark>identity <mark>through contradictory images of desire and</mark> <mark>disgust </mark>within processes defining dominant notions of respectable feminine sexuality</u>. Although it is important to note that the extent and intensity of this figuring has varied across time and space with some societies more tolerant of prostitution than others, the <u>mass media in <mark>Western societies </mark>has </u>generally<u> sought to perpetuate images that <mark>depict prostitutes as </mark>social pariahs, fallen women, or 'bad girls' and to use such images to distinguish this <mark>'deviant' group from 'normal' purified populations</u></mark>. Roberts, 1992. Exploring such ideas, Sibley 1995 has commented on the frequent representation of street prostitutes as defiling the purity of the city, and one merely needs to consider the way in which recent film and television drama from Taxi Driver to Mona Lisa, from The Bill to Band of Gold has consistently presented stereotyped images of prostitutes as part of a desperate, criminalised underworld, drug-dependent and reliant on the protection of pimps, to appreciate the importance of the media in shaping feelings of abjection towards prostitutes. Even sympathetic portrayals of prostitute women that subvert stereotypical expectations--for example, films such as Personal Services or Working Girls--may demand that these stereotypes are acknowledged, Perkins, 1989.</p><p>The suggestion that<u> the representation of sex workers has been based around persistent stereotypes of <mark>the prostitute</mark> as <mark>Other</mark> <mark>constitutes an important theme</mark> <mark>in</mark> writing on the <mark>regulation and containment of prostitution</mark>, albeit one that is fraught with contractions (prostitutes are, after all, a group that is eroticised and demonised simultaneously</u>). Surprisingly little work has focused on the contemporary media stereotyping of prostitutes though see Murray & Robinson, 1996, with most commentators instead investigating the representation of sex work in the nineteenth century, exploring the way emerging moral-medical ideas were used to label prostitutes as a 'polluting' category at a time when women's role in urban society was undergoing dramatic transformation (Walkowitz, 1980; Mort, 1987). As Corbin 1990 has argued, <u><mark>prostitutes, </mark>although socially marginalised, <mark>were of <strong>major symbolic importance</strong> </u></mark>in Victorian society, with<u> <mark>their representation at the immoral 'margin' crucial for defining the moral 'centre':</mark> in essence, <strong><mark>the boundaries between domesticised femininity and the unfettered sexuality of the street were constructed </mark>and maintained <mark>through the discursive identification of prostitutes as </mark>dirty and <mark>dangerous, a threat to bourgeois society</strong></mark>.</u> Inevitably, a variety of urban flaneurs, epidemiologists, philologists and moral reformers contributed to this process, their obsessive scrutiny of the habits and habitats of 'fallen women' contributing to a variety of pseudo-scientific discourses in which <u>dominant male fears and fantasies were projected onto the figure of the street prostitute</u>:</p><p><u>The prostitute was the quintessential figure of the urban scene... for men as well as women, the prostitute was the central spectacle in a set of urban encounters and fantasies.</u> Repudiated and desired, degraded and threatening, the prostitute attracted the attention of a range of urban male explorers from the 1840s to the 1880s. (Walkowitz, 1992, p 233)</p><p>The medicalisation of female prostitutes as an alleged source of sexually-transmitted diseases, for example, was based solely on the assumption that prostitutes had high numbers of sexual contacts rather than any detailed knowledge of transmission vectors, yet led directly to the imposition of the Contagious Diseases Act of 1864 (updated in 1866 and 1869), which was applied to prostitute women but not their clients in a largely indiscriminate manner (Ogborn, 1992; 1993<u>). The link between sexual depravity and social disorder was further cemented in a literary <mark>tradition </mark>that <mark>depicted </mark>street <mark>prostitutes as part of a seedy </mark>Victorian <mark>underworld, affiliated with </mark>criminality, <mark>deviance, and sexual danger</u></mark>. Walkowitz 1992 has suggested that this tendency was evident not only in the sensationalist tabloid treatment of the Ripper murders, but also in 'high' literary explorations of living conditions in the Victorian city, with Stead's expose of child prostitution in the Pall Mall Gazette 1881 typical in its portrayal of prostitution as encapsulating all that was remiss in Victorian society--drunkenness, perversion, violence, and sexual slavery.</p><p>Significantly, it has been noted that the nineteenth-century<u> <mark>process of Othering prostitutes was reliant on a </mark>language of <mark>moral outrage </mark>and disgust (<mark>tempered with </mark>fascination and <mark>voyeurism), which was spatially transposed onto the landscape of the</u></mark> Victorian <u><mark>underworld</mark>,</u> a twilight world of narrow streets, alleys and parks (Jackson, 1989). <u>This collision between physical and moral impurity reinforced deep-seated anxieties and fears about prostitution, as <mark>the prostitute came to symbolise the division of society into high and low</u></mark> <u><mark>- the civilised and the grotesque through a series of metaphors of the body, morality and topography</u></mark> (Stallybrass & White, 1986). While <u><mark>prostitution was the 'great social evil' </u></mark>of the day, and a general metaphor for the disorder of the city, discourses of moral hygiene linked the 'erotomaniac and nymphomaniac' behaviour of prostitutes onto their surroundings, with Smart 1982 drawing attention to the correspondence between ideas of prostitutes as deviant and discourses concerning the filth and environmental squalor of slum areas (see also Matlock, 1994). Interventions in housing reform, planning and public health regulation were often rationalised in terms of moral hygiene, with the female prostitute posited as symptomatic of the degeneracy of working-class housing areas (Greed, 1994). It is this idea of space as being central to the process of Othering prostitutes to which I now turn.</p>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,623
2
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,266
But the state has no business policing prostitutes’ sexual autonomy in the first place – true jouissance, or enjoyment, can only exist outside the violent utility-maximization apparatus of patriarchal legalism
Huang ‘11
Huang ‘11, Hans Tao-Ming Huang, assistant prof in English at National Central University, Taiwan, also affiliated with the Centre for the Study of Sexualities, “Queer Politics and Sexual Modernity in Taiwan,” p. 194-196
At stake here is how Lacan historicises how the good functions within utilitarian society, further using the notion of jouissance — namely the satisfaction of the drive that works to dissolve the fortress of the ego — to question the common good Lacan calls into question the utilitarian imperative that enjoins the modern individual to create the greatest good for the greatest number of people the problematic of the concept ‘good finds a new articulation in the modern era as utilitarianism re-articulates the good that had been linked to pleasure through the register of the useful, showing how ‘the good’ functions within the economy of ‘the goods there exists something excessive in the thing itself, something useless, that is, its jouissance use as the ‘good’ now becomes the useful, it is something that ‘the subject may have at his disposal’, and this, in turn, gives rise to a question of control To exercise the control of one’s good entails a certain disorder, that reveals its true nature, i.e., to exercise control over one’s goods is to have the right to deprive others of them What is meant by defending one’s goods is one and the same thing as forbidding oneself from enjoying them. ‘One is deprived of from being wholly real’ means that in so far as one is made a subject and is subject to the Good Pleasure principle, one becomes useful to the prescribed order of utilised things the good the bodily jouissance and the only asset that one is endowed with by virtue of being a living organism, has come to be deprived of the greatest happiness for the greatest number, under the utilitarian injunction to pursue the Common Good Good necessarily produces through its encompassing logic a jouissance use, a negativity inherent in the social This malignant jouissance is what the Good, embodied through the form of ‘general will’, bars, as Lee Edelman notes in the following: law take the form of excluding from its boundaries, and therefore from its protection, everything that is not integrated into its various registers’. For the general will to be general, that is, it must negate a certain specificity, which reflects, of course, first and foremost, the specific construction of the ‘general wi1l’.’ Zhen Zhen’s insistence on her own good as posing an ethical challenge to the feminist Good Insofar as ‘wife-in-monogamy’ is taken as the gold standard in the symbolic exchange of woman-as-goods and insofar as the notion of ‘sexual autonomy’ comes to promise the greatest conjugal happiness for the greatest number under the general will of gender equality, jouissance names the very social negativity that the extramarital comes to stand for in their attempt to soothe the gendered pain inflicted by sexual harassment and the putative violence of pornography and prostitution, state feminists have sought recourse to the very patriarchal power that subordinated them in the first place In wounded attachments’ to state power, state feminists foster ressentiment as they reproduce and wield power in the name of gender equality and through the liberal category of ‘sexual autonomy’, to the regulatory exclusion of queers and prostitutes [N]o jouissance is given to me or could be given to me other than that of my own body. That is not clear immediately, but is suspected, and people institute around this jouissance, which is good, which is thus my only asset, the protective fence of a so-called universal law called the rights of man: no one can stop me from using my body as ¡ see fit. The result of the limit ... is that jouissance dries up for everybody.73 This law, intended originally to confer on the individual the exclusive right to the enjoyment of his or her own body, works in effect to forbid others to enjoy their own body. one’s sexual autonomy is maintained at the expense of barring one’s jouissance call for the creation of ‘erotic satisfactions’, other than the perverse kind offered in the sex industry that she finds repulsive, must now be understood as veiling the sad fact that the jouissance of the ‘wife-in-monogamy’ dries up within the space of the conjugal bed.
jouissance the satisfaction of the drive that works to dissolve the fortress of the ego question the common good utilitarianism re-articulates the good wing how ‘the good’ functions within the economy of ‘the goods there exists something excessive that jouissance use the good’ becomes the useful, it is something that ‘the subject may have at his disposal’ To exercise the control of one’s good entails disorder to exercise control over one’s goods is to have the right to deprive others of them bodily jouissance and the only asset that one is endowed with by virtue of being a living organism, has come to be deprived of the greatest happiness for the greatest number . Insofar as ‘wife-in-monogamy’ is taken as the gold standard in the symbolic exchange of woman-as-goods and sexual autonomy’ comes to promise the greatest conjugal happiness jouissance names the social negativity that the extramarital comes to stand for in the attempt to soothe pain inflicted by the putative violence of prostitution state feminists have sought recourse to the very patriarchal power that subordinated them in the first place ate feminists foster ressentiment as they reproduce and wield power in the name of gender equality N]o jouissance is given to me or could be given to me other than that of my own body This law, works in effect to forbid others to enjoy their own body call for the creation of ‘erotic satisfactions’, other than the sex industry must be understood as veiling the fact that the jouissance of the ‘wife-in-monogamy’ dries up within the space of the conjugal bed.
The third quote from Lacan brings into sharp relief the egoism and self-interestedness in the desire to do good, in the name of pursuing the social good. At stake here is how Lacan historicises how the good functions within utilitarian society, further using the notion of jouissance — namely the satisfaction of the drive that works to dissolve the fortress of the ego — to question the common good. In his seminar 7 on the ethics of psychoanalysis, Lacan calls into question the utilitarian imperative that enjoins the modern individual to create the greatest good for the greatest number of people. Crucially, Lacan underscores how the problematic of the concept ‘good’, examined since Aristotle, finds a new articulation in the modern era as utilitarianism re-articulates the good that had been linked to pleasure through the register of the useful, showing how ‘the good’ functions within the economy of ‘the goods’ (where the plural also carries an ethical connotation).° Yet, Lacan notes, whatever the value of that piece of man-made thing, there exists something excessive in the thing itself, something useless, that is, its jouissance use. Thus for Lacan, as the ‘good’ now becomes the useful, it is something that ‘the subject may have at his disposal’, and this, in turn, gives rise to a question of control on the part of the subject. Lacan writes: To exercise the control of one’s good, as everyone knows, entails a certain disorder, that reveals its true nature, i.e., to exercise control over one’s goods is to have the right to deprive others of them ... [T]o the extent that nothing is deprived of nothing — which does not prevent the good one is deprived of from being wholly real. The important thing is to recognise that the depriving agent is an imaginary function. it is the little other, one’s fellow man, he who is given in the relationship that is half rooted in naturalness of the mirror stage, hut such as he appears to us there where things are articulated at the level of the symbolic ... What is meant by defending one’s goods is one and the same thing as forbidding oneself from enjoying them.67 ‘One is deprived of from being wholly real’ means that in so far as one is made a subject and is subject to the Good Pleasure principle, one becomes useful to the prescribed order of utilised things. Crucially for Lacan, the good (with a small ‘g’), the bodily jouissance and the only asset that one is endowed with by virtue of being a living organism, has come to be deprived of the greatest happiness for the greatest number, under the utilitarian injunction to pursue the Common Good. Yet at the same time, the Good necessarily produces through its encompassing logic a jouissance use, a negativity inherent in the social. This malignant jouissance is what the Good, embodied through the form of ‘general will’, bars, as Lee Edelman notes in the following: [The] focus on the negativity of the social, on its inherent antisociality, does not deny that such commonalities as community may posit can result, according to Jacques Lacan, in ‘a certain law of equality ... formulated in the notion of the general will’. But while the imposition of such a law may establish, for Lacan, ‘the common denominator of the respect for certain rights’, it also ... can ‘take the form of excluding from its boundaries, and therefore from its protection, everything that is not integrated into its various registers’. For the general will to be general, that is, it must negate a certain specificity, which reflects, of course, first and foremost, the specific construction of the ‘general wi1l’.’ Through the prism of Lacanian ethics, we can reformulate Zhen Zhen’s insistence on her own good as posing an ethical challenge to the feminist Good. Insofar as ‘wife-in-monogamy’ is taken as the gold standard in the symbolic exchange of woman-as-goods and insofar as the notion of ‘sexual autonomy’ comes to promise the greatest conjugal happiness for the greatest number under the general will of gender equality, jouissance names the very social negativity that the extramarital comes to stand for. Crucially, in their attempt to soothe the gendered pain inflicted by sexual harassment and the putative violence of pornography and prostitution, state feminists have sought recourse to the very patriarchal power that subordinated them in the first place. In their ‘wounded attachments’, to use the phase of Wendy Brown, to state power, state feminists foster ressentiment as they reproduce and wield power in the name of gender equality and through the liberal category of ‘sexual autonomy’, to the regulatory exclusion of queers and prostitutes. Given the mainstreaming of gender in recent years, sexual autonomy has indeed become the norm in post—martial law Taiwan, one that we become ‘passionately’ attached to in our very mode of subjection.7’ If indeed the right to erotic/sexual autonomy has been deconstructed as that which ‘we cannot not want’72 then I think Lacan’s remarks below reveal what is at stake: [N]o jouissance is given to me or could be given to me other than that of my own body. That is not clear immediately, but is suspected, and people institute around this jouissance, which is good, which is thus my only asset, the protective fence of a so-called universal law called the rights of man: no one can stop me from using my body as ¡ see fit. The result of the limit ... is that jouissance dries up for everybody.73 This law, intended originally to confer on the individual the exclusive right to the enjoyment of his or her own body, works in effect to forbid others to enjoy their own body. In other words, one’s sexual autonomy is maintained at the expense of barring one’s jouissance. In this regard, Hwang’s call for the creation of ‘erotic satisfactions’, other than the perverse kind offered in the sex industry that she finds repulsive, must now be understood as veiling the sad fact that the jouissance of the ‘wife-in-monogamy’ dries up within the space of the conjugal bed.
6,026
<h4>But the state has no business policing prostitutes’ sexual autonomy in the first place – true jouissance, or enjoyment, can only exist outside the violent utility-maximization apparatus of patriarchal legalism</h4><p><strong>Huang ‘11</strong>, Hans Tao-Ming Huang, assistant prof in English at National Central University, Taiwan, also affiliated with the Centre for the Study of Sexualities, “Queer Politics and Sexual Modernity in Taiwan,” p. 194-196</p><p>The third quote from Lacan brings into sharp relief the egoism and self-interestedness in the desire to do good, in the name of pursuing the social good. <u>At stake here is how Lacan historicises how the good functions within utilitarian society, further using the notion of <mark>jouissance</mark> — namely <mark>the satisfaction of the drive that works to dissolve the fortress of the ego</mark> — to <mark>question the common good</u></mark>. In his seminar 7 on the ethics of psychoanalysis, <u>Lacan calls into question the utilitarian imperative that enjoins the modern individual to create the greatest good for the greatest number of people</u>. Crucially, Lacan underscores how <u>the problematic of the concept ‘good</u>’, examined since Aristotle,<u> finds a new articulation in the modern era as <mark>utilitarianism re-articulates the good</mark> that had been linked to pleasure through the register of the useful, sho<mark>wing how ‘the good’ functions within the economy of ‘the goods</u></mark>’ (where the plural also carries an ethical connotation).° Yet, Lacan notes, whatever the value of that piece of man-made thing, <u><mark>there exists something excessive</mark> in the thing itself, something useless, <mark>that</mark> is, its <mark>jouissance</mark> <mark>use</u></mark>. Thus for Lacan, <u>as <mark>the</mark> ‘<mark>good’</mark> now <mark>becomes the useful, it is something that ‘the subject may have at his disposal’</mark>, and this, in turn, gives rise to a question of control</u> on the part of the subject. Lacan writes: <u><mark>To exercise the control of one’s good</u></mark>, as everyone knows, <u><mark>entails</mark> a certain <mark>disorder</mark>, that reveals its true nature, i.e., <mark>to exercise control over one’s goods is to have the right to deprive others of them</u></mark> ... </p><p>[T]o the extent that nothing is deprived of nothing — which does not prevent the good one is deprived of from being wholly real. The important thing is to recognise that the depriving agent is an imaginary function. it is the little other, one’s fellow man, he who is given in the relationship that is half rooted in naturalness of the mirror stage, hut such as he appears to us there where things are articulated at the level of the symbolic ... <u>What is meant by defending one’s goods is one and the same thing as forbidding oneself from enjoying them.</u>67</p><p><u>‘One is deprived of from being wholly real’ means that in so far as one is made a subject and is subject to the Good Pleasure principle, one becomes useful to the prescribed order of utilised things</u>. Crucially for Lacan, <u>the good</u> (with a small ‘g’), <u>the <mark>bodily</mark> <mark>jouissance and the only asset that one is endowed with by virtue of being a living organism, has come to be deprived of the greatest happiness for the greatest number</mark>, under the utilitarian injunction to pursue the Common Good</u>. Yet at the same time, the <u>Good necessarily produces through its encompassing logic a jouissance use, a negativity inherent in the social</u>. <u>This malignant jouissance is what the Good, embodied through the form of ‘general will’, bars, as Lee Edelman notes in the following:</p><p></u>[The] focus on the negativity of the social, on its inherent antisociality, does not deny that such commonalities as community may posit can result, according to Jacques Lacan, in ‘a certain law of equality ... formulated in the notion of the general will’. But while the imposition of such a <u>law</u> may establish, for Lacan, ‘the common denominator of the respect for certain rights’, it also ... can ‘<u>take the form of excluding from its boundaries, and therefore from its protection, everything that is not integrated into its various registers’. For the general will to be general, that is, it must negate a certain specificity, which reflects, of course, first and foremost, the specific construction of the ‘general wi1l’.’</p><p></u>Through the prism of Lacanian ethics, we can reformulate <u>Zhen Zhen’s insistence on her own good as posing an ethical challenge to the feminist Good</u><mark>. <u>Insofar as ‘wife-in-monogamy’ is taken as the gold standard in the symbolic exchange of woman-as-goods</mark> <mark>and</mark> insofar as the notion of ‘<mark>sexual autonomy’ comes to promise the greatest conjugal happiness</mark> for the greatest number under the general will of gender equality, <mark>jouissance names the </mark>very <mark>social negativity that the extramarital comes to stand for</u></mark>. Crucially, <u><mark>in the</mark>ir <mark>attempt to soothe</mark> the gendered <mark>pain inflicted by </mark>sexual harassment and<mark> the putative violence of</mark> pornography and <mark>prostitution</mark>, <mark>state feminists have sought recourse to the very patriarchal power that subordinated them in the first place</u></mark>. <u>In</u> their ‘<u>wounded attachments’</u>, to use the phase of Wendy Brown, <u>to state power, st<mark>ate feminists foster ressentiment as they reproduce and wield power in the name of gender equality</mark> and through the liberal category of ‘sexual autonomy’, to the regulatory exclusion of queers and prostitutes</u>. Given the mainstreaming of gender in recent years, sexual autonomy has indeed become the norm in post—martial law Taiwan, one that we become ‘passionately’ attached to in our very mode of subjection.7’ If indeed the right to erotic/sexual autonomy has been deconstructed as that which ‘we cannot not want’72 then I think Lacan’s remarks below reveal what is at stake:</p><p><u>[<mark>N]o jouissance is given to me or could be given to me other than that of my own body</mark>. That is not clear immediately, but is suspected, and people institute around this jouissance, which is good, which is thus my only asset, the protective fence of a so-called universal law called the rights of man: no one can stop me from using my body as ¡ see fit. The result of the limit ... is that jouissance dries up for everybody.73</p><p><mark>This law, </mark>intended originally to confer on the individual the exclusive right to the enjoyment of his or her own body, <mark>works in effect to forbid others to enjoy their own body</mark>.</u> In other words, <u>one’s sexual autonomy is maintained at the expense of barring one’s jouissance</u>. In this regard, Hwang’s <u><mark>call for the creation of ‘erotic satisfactions’, other than </mark>the perverse kind offered in <mark>the sex industry </mark>that she finds repulsive,<mark> must </mark>now <mark>be understood as veiling the </mark>sad <mark>fact that the jouissance of the ‘wife-in-monogamy’ dries up within the space of the conjugal bed.</p></u></mark>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,626
1
17,077
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
565,297
A
tournament
4
Binghamton Cepin-Sehgal
Baker, Webster Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,267
There can be no radical or critical pedagogy that is practiced within the power structures of the academy – turns case because academia is a site of social death
Occupied UC Berkeley 09
Occupied UC Berkeley 09 “The Necrosocial: Civic Life, Social Death, and the UC. http://anticapitalprojects.wordpress.com/2009/11/19/the-necrosocial/
When those values are violated by the very institutions which are created to protect them , we get indignant. We demand justice from them these institutions don’t care for those values, not at all, not for all those values are not even our own The values create popular images and ideals while they mean in practice the selling of  identities, the state’s monopoly on violence, the expansion of markets and capital accumulation, the rule of property, the rule of exclusions based on race, gender, class, and domination and humiliation in general Every institution has of course our best interest in mind, so much so that we’re willing to pay, to enter debt contracts, to strike a submissive pose in the classroom and eventually or simultaneously in the workplace to pay back those debts. Each bulging institutional value longing to become more than its sentiment through us is the management of our consent to social death. Social death is our banal acceptance of an institution’s meaning for our own lack of meaning. It’s the positions we thoughtlessly enact. It’s the particular nature of being owned
null
When those values are violated by the very institutions which are created to protect them, the veneer fades, the tired set collapses: and we call it injustice, we get indignant. We demand justice from them, for them to adhere to their values. What many have learned again and again is that these institutions don’t care for those values, not at all, not for all. And we are only beginning to understand that those values are not even our own. The values create popular images and ideals (healthcare, democracy, equality, happiness, individuality, pulling yourself up by your bootstraps, public education)while they mean in practice the selling of commodified identities, the state’s monopoly on violence, the expansion of markets and capital accumulation, the rule of property, the rule of exclusions based on race, gender, class, and domination and humiliation in general. They sell the practice through the image. We’re taught we’ll live the images once we accept the practice. In this crisis the Chancellors and Presidents, the Regents and the British Petroleums, the politicians and the managers, they all intend to be true to their values and capitalize on the university economically and socially—which is to say, nothing has changed, it is only an escalation, a provocation. Their most recent attempt to reorganize wealth and capital is called a crisis so that we are more willing to accept their new terms as well as what was always dead in the university, to see just how dead we are willing to play, how non-existent, how compliant, how desirous. Every institution has of course our best interest in mind, so much so that we’re willing to pay, to enter debt contracts, to strike a submissive pose in the classroom, in the lab, in the seminar, in the dorm, and eventually or simultaneously in the workplace to pay back those debts. Each bulging institutional value longing to become more than its sentiment through us, each of our empty gestures of feigned-anxiety to appear under pressure, or of cool-ambivalence to appear accustomed to horror, every moment of student life, is the management of our consent to social death. Social death is our banal acceptance of an institution’s meaning for our own lack of meaning. It’s the positions we thoughtlessly enact. It’s the particular nature of being owned. Social rupture is the initial divorce between the owners and the owned.
2,386
<h4><strong>There can be no radical or critical pedagogy that is practiced within the power structures of the academy – turns case because academia is a site of social death</h4><p>Occupied UC Berkeley 09</strong> “The Necrosocial: Civic Life, Social Death, and the UC. http://anticapitalprojects.wordpress.com/2009/11/19/the-necrosocial/</p><p><u>When those values are violated by the very institutions which are created to protect them</u>, the veneer fades, the tired set collapses: and we call it injustice<u>, we get indignant. We demand justice from them</u>, for them to adhere to their values. What many have learned again and again is that <u>these institutions don’t care for those values, not at all, not for all</u>. And we are only beginning to understand that <u>those values are not even our own</u>. <u>The values create popular images and ideals</u> (healthcare, democracy, equality, happiness, individuality, pulling yourself up by your bootstraps, public education)<u>while they mean in practice the selling of </u>commodified<u> identities, the state’s monopoly on violence, the expansion of markets and capital accumulation, the rule of property, the rule of exclusions based on race, gender, class, and domination and humiliation in general</u>. They sell the practice through the image. We’re taught we’ll live the images once we accept the practice. In this crisis the Chancellors and Presidents, the Regents and the British Petroleums, the politicians and the managers, they all intend to be true to their values and capitalize on the university economically and socially—which is to say, nothing has changed, it is only an escalation, a provocation. Their most recent attempt to reorganize wealth and capital is called a crisis so that we are more willing to accept their new terms as well as what was always dead in the university, to see just how dead we are willing to play, how non-existent, how compliant, how desirous. <u>Every institution has of course our best interest in mind, so much so that we’re willing to pay, to enter debt contracts, to strike a submissive pose in the classroom</u>, in the lab, in the seminar, in the dorm, <u>and eventually or simultaneously in the workplace to pay back those debts.</u> <u>Each bulging institutional value longing to become more than its sentiment through us</u>, each of our empty gestures of feigned-anxiety to appear under pressure, or of cool-ambivalence to appear accustomed to horror, every moment of student life, <u>is the management of our consent to social death. Social death is our banal acceptance of an institution’s meaning for our own lack of meaning. It’s the positions we thoughtlessly enact. It’s the particular nature of being owned</u>. Social rupture is the initial divorce between the owners and the owned.</p><p><strong> </p></strong>
null
null
1NC Version 2 – Undercommons
1,058
366
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,268
The US ban on sales has created an international illegal market
Hughes 9
Hughes 9 J. Andrew Hughes, J.D. candidate, Vanderbilt University Law School, May 2009.
U.S. organ procurement policy has consequences beyond a domestic organ shortage. A thriving global market in human organs has resulted from U.S. policy banning organ sales The illegality of the organ trade is insufficient to discourage many of those faced with the possibility of dying on an organ waiting list, and "transplant tourism" has become its own industry. U.S. doctors perform illegal transplants, too, often under hospitals' "don't ask, don't tell" policy regarding transplants involving foreigners who claim to be related The lack of a regulated organ marketplace in the U.S. has resulted in exploitation of the poor throughout the world. In short, U.S. policy and its ban on organ sales have produced some of the same immoral and unethical consequences the ban was designed to avoid
. A thriving global market in human organs has resulted from U.S. policy banning organ sales The illegality of the organ trade is insufficient to discourage many of those faced with the possibility of dying on an organ waiting list, and "transplant tourism" has become its own industry U.S. doctors perform illegal transplants, too, The lack of a regulated organ marketplace in the U.S. has resulted in exploitation of the poor throughout the world
Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law January, 2009 42 Vand. J. Transnat'l L. 351 Note: You Get What You Pay For?: Rethinking U.S. Organ Procurement Policy in Light of Foreign Models U.S. organ procurement policy has consequences beyond a domestic organ shortage. A thriving global black market in human organs has resulted from U.S. policy banning organ sales. n78 While nearly all developed nations have banned the sale and purchase of human organs, many countries do not strictly enforce these laws. n79 The illegality of the organ trade is insufficient to discourage many of those faced with the possibility of dying on an organ waiting list, and "transplant tourism" has become its own industry. n80 In Bombay in 2001, nearly US$ 10 million were exchanged for kidney transplants. n81 Patients use kidney brokers to locate sellers, who circumvent a ban on kidney sales by signing an affidavit swearing that they are not being paid. n82 Before the U.S. invaded Iraq in 2003, that country was known as "one of [the] world's best black marketplaces for human organs." n83 The lack of effective prosecution of these transactions extends beyond Asia and the Middle East to Europe, as recent cases in Estonia and Germany suggest. n84 U.S. doctors perform illegal transplants, too, often under hospitals' "don't ask, don't tell" policy regarding transplants involving foreigners who claim to be related. n85 U.S. hospitals set their own rules for who can be a live organ donor, and organ brokers can locate hospitals that do not question a purported familial relationship between "donors" and "donees." n86 The lack of a regulated organ marketplace in the U.S. has resulted in exploitation of the poor throughout the world. n87 Organ sellers often face debt, unemployment, and serious health problems; as such, they are easy targets for abuse. n88 Prisoners and the homeless are among those exploited. n89 Sellers of organs on the black market are often paid less than what they were initially promised, while their financial situations and health often grow worse after the transplants. n90 Data from the Indian black market trade in kidneys [*363] support the concern about sellers' lack of adequate information about the risks involved. In one study, 86% of the sellers there reported that their health had "deteriorated substantially" after their organ sales, and "four out of five sellers would not recommend that others follow their lead in selling organs." n91 In short, U.S. policy and its ban on organ sales have produced some of the same immoral and unethical consequences the ban was designed to avoid. n92
2,620
<h4>The US ban on sales has created an international illegal market</h4><p><strong>Hughes 9</strong> J. Andrew Hughes, J.D. candidate, Vanderbilt University Law School, May 2009.</p><p>Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law January, 2009 42 Vand. J. Transnat'l L. 351</p><p>Note: You Get What You Pay For?: Rethinking U.S. Organ Procurement Policy in Light of Foreign Models</p><p><u>U.S. organ procurement policy has consequences beyond a domestic organ shortage<mark>. A thriving global</u> </mark>black<mark> <u>market in human organs has resulted from U.S. policy banning organ sales</u></mark>. n78 While nearly all developed nations have banned the sale and purchase of human organs, many countries do not strictly enforce these laws. n79 <u><mark>The illegality of the organ trade is insufficient to discourage many of those faced with the possibility of dying on an organ waiting list, and "transplant tourism" has become its own industry</mark>.</u> n80 In Bombay in 2001, nearly US$ 10 million were exchanged for kidney transplants. n81 Patients use kidney brokers to locate sellers, who circumvent a ban on kidney sales by signing an affidavit swearing that they are not being paid. n82 Before the U.S. invaded Iraq in 2003, that country was known as "one of [the] world's best black marketplaces for human organs." n83 The lack of effective prosecution of these transactions extends beyond Asia and the Middle East to Europe, as recent cases in Estonia and Germany suggest. n84 <u><mark>U.S. doctors perform illegal transplants, too,</mark> often under hospitals' "don't ask, don't tell" policy regarding transplants involving foreigners who claim to be related</u>. n85 U.S. hospitals set their own rules for who can be a live organ donor, and organ brokers can locate hospitals that do not question a purported familial relationship between "donors" and "donees." n86 <u><mark>The lack of a regulated organ marketplace in the U.S. has resulted in exploitation of the poor throughout the world</mark>.</u> n87 Organ sellers often face debt, unemployment, and serious health problems; as such, they are easy targets for abuse. n88 Prisoners and the homeless are among those exploited. n89 Sellers of organs on the black market are often paid less than what they were initially promised, while their financial situations and health often grow worse after the transplants. n90 Data from the Indian black market trade in kidneys [*363] support the concern about sellers' lack of adequate information about the risks involved. In one study, 86% of the sellers there reported that their health had "deteriorated substantially" after their organ sales, and "four out of five sellers would not recommend that others follow their lead in selling organs." n91 <u>In short, U.S. policy and its ban on organ sales have produced some of the same immoral and unethical consequences the ban was designed to avoid</u>. n92</p>
null
null
Contention 2 is the Illegal market
430,256
14
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,269
No solve biopower, totalizing approaches to suicide bad
Osborne 6
Osborne 6 Thomas Osborne, Department of Sociology, University of Bristol, “‘Fascinated dispossession’: suicide and the aesthetics of freedom,” Economy and Society Volume 34, Issue 2, 2005, 8/16/2006
to associate suicide with resistance is to misunderstand the kind of action it embodies aesthetic model of suicide in its ideal-typical form embodies the idea of suicide as pure agency there can be no such thing, not only because of Blanchot's view that suicide is always mixed and double but also because suicide is hardly ever a matter for a single agent but entraps many others in its web and, on the other hand, because of the difficulty of escaping the realm of bio-politics, even from within the aesthetic view of suicide itself what sort of a space would suicide 'retreats' possibly occupy other than a bio-political one What count are not our theories but our practices and the experiences in which they are embedded invocation of the Stoic and other ideas of a beautiful death presupposes not some general view of suicide that would apply at all times but a precise - historical - understanding of the particular context of particular practices in connection with the ethics of one's life and the event of one's death Taken as a regulative ideal the idea of aesthetic suicide the existential suicide understood as an exercise of freedom has its uses taken more or less normatively as a moral panacea it risks exposing us to a kind of moral romanticism, a compromised utopia Suicide cannot unproblematically be the object of an uncompromised affirmation At the heart lurks not only agency but passivity Suicide cannot be the object of a finite moral or other kind of knowledge It is always ambiguous, always problematic it cannot be legislated away by a politics of affirmation or an aesthetic of freedom - perhaps it cannot be the object of a verdict but only of our continued and probably futile attempts at understanding case by case according to a concerned and open-minded empiricism
aesthetic model of suicide embodies pure agency there can be no such thing, not only because suicide is always mixed and double but also because suicide is hardly ever a matter for a single agent but entraps many others and because of the difficulty of escaping the realm of bio-politics even from within the aesthetic view what sort of a space would suicide 'retreats' possibly occupy other than a bio-political one What count are not our theories but the experiences in which they are embedded ideas of a beautiful death presuppose not some general view of suicide that would apply at all times but a particular context taken more or less normatively as a moral panacea it risks exposing us to a kind of moral romanticism, a compromised utopia Suicide cannot unproblematically be the object of an uncompromised affirmation Suicide cannot be the object of a finite moral or other kind of knowledge it cannot be legislated away by a politics of affirmation or an aesthetic of freedom - perhaps it cannot be the object of a verdict but only of our continued and probably futile attempts at understanding case by case
More than anything, to associate suicide with resistance is to misunderstand the kind of action it embodies. We do not actually need to take any particular moral stance to see that this is so. The aesthetic model of suicide, at least in its ideal-typical form, embodies the idea of suicide as pure agency. And yet there can be no such thing, not only because of Blanchot's view that suicide is always mixed and double, both agency and passivity, but also, on the one hand, because suicide is hardly ever a matter for a single agent but entraps many others - passively, one might say - in its web (one cannot evade the moral dimension so easily) and, on the other hand, because of the difficulty of escaping the realm of bio-politics, even from within the aesthetic view of suicide itself. This latter point is not meant as a critique of Foucault (cf. Foucault 1994b). His position came in the context of some speculative remarks only. But we would need to ask, for instance, what sort of a space would the suicide 'retreats' that he invokes possibly occupy other than one which would itself be a bio-political one? The answer would have to come by way of the positing of some sort of cultural 'experience' appropriate to such an institutional form, an experience to be created perhaps but one which at the moment does not pre-exist its speculative invocation - and no doubt Foucault's remarks were meant only to invoke the possibility of such an experience, not to presume its actuality. The lesson is no doubt an empirical even an empiricist one. What count are not our theories but our practices and the experiences in which they are embedded. No one knew this better than Foucault himself of course. His invocation of the Stoic and other ideas of a beautiful death presupposes not some general view of suicide that would apply at all times and at all periods but a precise - historical - understanding of the particular context of particular practices in connection with the ethics of one's life and the event of one's death (Foucault 2001). Taken as a regulative ideal, no doubt the idea of aesthetic suicide and its family relations - the suicide of free decision, the existential suicide understood as an exercise of freedom - has its uses, not least in combating the kind of moral dismissal of suicide that has been the norm throughout so much of history, as is so well described in the historical sections of The Savage God. But taken more or less normatively as a moral panacea it risks exposing us to a kind of moral romanticism, a compromised utopia. Indeed, More's Utopia is often credited with being one of the first works in the West to advocate suicide. But More's suicide retreats were in fact not crucibles of freedom but places of passive euthanasia. Suicide cannot unproblematically be the object of an uncompromised affirmation. At the heart even of the generalized vision of aesthetic suicide, then, lurks not only agency but also passivity, the web of dependence. Suicide cannot be the object of a finite moral or other kind of knowledge. It is always ambiguous, always problematic, and certainly always double; it cannot be legislated away by a politics of affirmation or an aesthetic of freedom - perhaps it cannot be the object of a verdict but only of our continued and probably futile attempts at understanding case by case according, perhaps, to a concerned and open-minded empiricism.
3,413
<h4>No solve biopower, totalizing approaches to suicide bad</h4><p><strong>Osborne 6</strong> Thomas Osborne, Department of Sociology, University of Bristol, “‘Fascinated dispossession’: suicide and the aesthetics of freedom,” Economy and Society Volume 34, Issue 2, 2005, 8/16/2006</p><p>More than anything, <u>to associate suicide with resistance is to misunderstand the kind of action it embodies</u>. We do not actually need to take any particular moral stance to see that this is so. The <u><mark>aesthetic model of suicide</u></mark>, at least <u>in its ideal-typical form</u>, <u><mark>embodies</mark> the idea of suicide as <mark>pure agency</u></mark>. And yet <u><mark>there can be no such thing, not only because</mark> of Blanchot's view that <mark>suicide is always mixed and double</u></mark>, both agency and passivity, <u><mark>but</u> <u>also</u></mark>, on the one hand, <u><mark>because</mark> <mark>suicide is hardly ever a matter for a single agent but entraps many others</u></mark> - passively, one might say - <u>in its web</u> (one cannot evade the moral dimension so easily) <u><mark>and</mark>, on the other hand, <mark>because of the difficulty of escaping the realm of bio-politics</mark>, <mark>even from within the aesthetic view</mark> of suicide itself</u>. This latter point is not meant as a critique of Foucault (cf. Foucault 1994b). His position came in the context of some speculative remarks only. But we would need to ask, for instance, <u><mark>what sort of a space would</u></mark> the <u><mark>suicide 'retreats'</mark> </u>that he invokes<u> <mark>possibly occupy other than</mark> </u>one which would itself be<u> <mark>a bio-political one</u></mark>? The answer would have to come by way of the positing of some sort of cultural 'experience' appropriate to such an institutional form, an experience to be created perhaps but one which at the moment does not pre-exist its speculative invocation - and no doubt Foucault's remarks were meant only to invoke the possibility of such an experience, not to presume its actuality.</p><p>The lesson is no doubt an empirical even an empiricist one. <u><mark>What count are not our theories but</mark> our practices and <mark>the experiences in which they are embedded</u></mark>. No one knew this better than Foucault himself of course. His <u>invocation of the Stoic and other <mark>ideas of a beautiful death presuppose</mark>s <mark>not some general view of suicide that would apply at all times</u></mark> and at all periods <u><mark>but a</mark> precise - historical - understanding of the <mark>particular context</mark> of particular practices</u> <u>in connection with the ethics of one's life and the event of one's death</u> (Foucault 2001). <u>Taken as a regulative ideal</u>, no doubt <u>the idea of aesthetic suicide</u> and its family relations - the suicide of free decision, <u>the existential suicide understood as an exercise of freedom</u> - <u>has its uses</u>, not least in combating the kind of moral dismissal of suicide that has been the norm throughout so much of history, as is so well described in the historical sections of The Savage God. But <u><mark>taken more or less normatively as a moral panacea it risks exposing us to a kind of moral romanticism, a compromised utopia</u></mark>. Indeed, More's Utopia is often credited with being one of the first works in the West to advocate suicide. But More's suicide retreats were in fact not crucibles of freedom but places of passive euthanasia. <u><mark>Suicide cannot unproblematically be the object of an uncompromised affirmation</u></mark>. <u>At the heart</u> even of the generalized vision of aesthetic suicide, then, <u>lurks not only agency but</u> also <u>passivity</u>, the web of dependence. <u><mark>Suicide cannot be the object of a finite moral or other kind of knowledge</u></mark>. <u>It is always ambiguous, always problematic</u>, and certainly always double; <u><mark>it cannot be legislated away by a politics of affirmation or an aesthetic of freedom - perhaps it cannot be the object of a verdict but only of our continued and probably futile attempts at understanding case by case</mark> according</u>, perhaps, <u>to a concerned and open-minded empiricism</u>.</p>
null
null
Case
430,356
3
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,270
Medicalization controls their impacts – broader cause of aff impacts is the assumption that only an external authority can validate the decision to live and die
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Medicalization controls their impacts – broader cause of aff impacts is the assumption that only an external authority can validate the decision to live and die </h4>
null
Case
2NC Link Debate
430,627
1
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,271
CI: Sales are the act of selling—anyone can sell an organ
Business Dictionary 14
Business Dictionary 2014
http://www.businessdictionary.com/definition/sales.html sales . The activity of selling products or services
. The activity of selling products or services
http://www.businessdictionary.com/definition/sales.html sales Definitions (2)Add to FlashcardsSave to FavoritesSee Examples 1. The activity or business of selling products or services. 2. An alternative term for sales revenue or sales volume. See also sale.
257
<h4>CI: Sales are the act of selling—anyone can sell an organ </h4><p><strong>Business Dictionary</strong> 20<strong>14 </p><p><u></strong>http://www.businessdictionary.com/definition/sales.html</p><p>sales</p><p></u>Definitions (2)Add to FlashcardsSave to FavoritesSee Examples</p><p>1<u><mark>. The activity</u></mark> or business <u><mark>of</mark> <mark>selling products or services</u></mark>.</p><p>2. An alternative term for sales revenue or sales volume. See also sale.</p>
2AC
Contention 4 is risk calculus
2ac nearly all
430,628
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,272
Heg and Forward deployment don’t solve conflict.
Fettweis, Political Science – Tulane, 10
Fettweis, Political Science – Tulane, 10 [Christopher J., fifth year doctoral student in the University of Maryland's Department of Government and Politics. His primary interests include US foreign and national security policies. His dissertation, currently titled The Geopolitics of Energy and the Obsolescence of Major War, focuses on the relationship between oil and conflict. Mr. Fettweis has a BA in History from the University of Notre Dame, Threat and Anxiety in US Foreign Policy, April 2010 Survival, 52:2, 59 - 82]
evidence suggests there is little reason to believe in the stabilising power of the US hegemon, and no relation between American activism and international stability. the verdict from the 90s world grew more peaceful while the U S cut its forces. No state seemed to believe its security was endangered No militaries were enhanced to address power vacuums; no security dilemmas drove insecurity or arms races; no regional balancing occurred once the stabilis-ing presence of the US military was diminished. the U S was no less safe.
evidence suggests there is little reason to believe in the stabilising power of the US hegemon, and between American activism and international stability the verdict from the 90s world grew while the U S cut its forces. No state seemed to believe its security was endangered No militaries were enhanced to address power vacuums; no security dilemmas drove insecurity or arms races; no regional balancing occurred once the stabilis-ing presence of the US military was diminished. the U S was no less safe.
One potential explanation for the growth of global peace can be dismissed fairly quickly: US actions do not seem to have contributed much. The limited evidence suggests that there is little reason to believe in the stabilising power of the US hegemon, and that there is no relation between the relative level of American activism and international stability. During the 1990s, the United States cut back on its defence spending fairly substantially. By 1998, the United States was spending $100 billion less on defence in real terms than it had in 1990, a 25% reduction.29 To internationalists, defence hawks and other believers in hegemonic stability, this irresponsible 'peace dividend' endangered both national and global security. 'No serious analyst of American military capabilities', argued neo-conservatives William Kristol and Robert Kagan in 1996, 'doubts that the defense budget has been cut much too far to meet America's responsibilities to itself and to world peace'.30 And yet the verdict from the 1990s is fairly plain: the world grew more peaceful while the United States cut its forces. No state seemed to believe that its security was endangered by a less-capable US military, or at least none took any action that would suggest such a belief. No militaries were enhanced to address power vacuums; no security dilemmas drove insecurity or arms races; no regional balancing occurred once the stabilis-ing presence of the US military was diminished. The rest of the world acted as if the threat of international war was not a pressing concern, despite the reduction in US military capabilities. Most of all, the United States was no less safe. The incidence and magnitude of global conflict declined while the United States cut its military spending under President Bill Clinton, and kept declining as the George W. Bush administration ramped the spending back up. Complex statistical analysis is unnecessary to reach the conclusion that world peace and US military expenditure are unrelated.
2,009
<h4>Heg and Forward deployment don’t solve conflict.</h4><p><u><strong>Fettweis, Political Science – Tulane, 10 </u></strong>[Christopher J., fifth year doctoral student in the University of Maryland's Department of Government and Politics. His primary interests include US foreign and national security policies. His dissertation, currently titled The Geopolitics of Energy and the Obsolescence of Major War, focuses on the relationship between oil and conflict. Mr. Fettweis has a BA in History from the University of Notre Dame, Threat and Anxiety in US Foreign Policy, April 2010 Survival, 52:2, 59 - 82]</p><p>One potential explanation for the growth of global peace can be dismissed fairly quickly: US actions do not seem to have contributed much. The limited <u><mark>evidence suggests</u></mark> that <u><mark>there is little reason to believe in the stabilising power of the US hegemon, and</u></mark> that there is <u><strong>no relation</strong><mark> between</u></mark> the relative level of <u><mark>American activism and international stability</mark>.</u> During the 1990s, the United States cut back on its defence spending fairly substantially. By 1998, the United States was spending $100 billion less on defence in real terms than it had in 1990, a 25% reduction.29 To internationalists, defence hawks and other believers in hegemonic stability, this irresponsible 'peace dividend' endangered both national and global security. 'No serious analyst of American military capabilities', argued neo-conservatives William Kristol and Robert Kagan in 1996, 'doubts that the defense budget has been cut much too far to meet America's responsibilities to itself and to world peace'.30 And yet <u><mark>the verdict from the</u></mark> 19<u><mark>90s</u></mark> is fairly plain: the <u><mark>world grew <strong></mark>more peaceful</strong><mark> while the U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates <u><mark>cut its forces. No state seemed to believe</u></mark> that <u><mark>its security was endangered</u></mark> by a less-capable US military, or at least none took any action that would suggest such a belief. <u><strong><mark>No militaries were enhanced to address power vacuums; no security dilemmas drove insecurity or arms races; no regional balancing occurred</strong> once the stabilis-ing presence of the US military was diminished.</u></mark> The rest of the world acted as if the threat of international war was not a pressing concern, despite the reduction in US military capabilities. Most of all, <u><mark>the U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates <u><mark>was no less safe.</u></mark> The incidence and magnitude of global conflict declined while the United States cut its military spending under President Bill Clinton, and kept declining as the George W. Bush administration ramped the spending back up. Complex statistical analysis is unnecessary to reach the conclusion that world peace and US military expenditure are unrelated.</p>
WTO
Heg/Trade
AT: Inevitable
67,081
49
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,273
The aff’’s binary between the US and Russia leads to endless war
Jæger 2k
Øyvind Jæger, @ Norweigian Institute of International Affairs and the Copenhagen Peace Research Institute, 2k [Peace and Conflict Studies 7.2, “Securitizing Russia: Discoursive Practice of the Baltic States,” http://shss.nova.edu/pcs/journalsPDF/V7N2.pdf#page=18]
Thus, the value "Russia" is also denoted by "instability", "Asia", "invasion", "chaos", unpredictability", "imperialism The opposite value of these markers ("stability "defence", "order would denote the Self and thus conjure up an identity this practice intensifies by shifting onto a security mode, treating the oppositions as if they were questions of political existence, sovereignty, and survival. Identity is (re)produced when the oppositions are employed in a discourse of danger, one approaches a conception of security in which the distinction between state and nation has disappeared in all-encompassing securitisation. Everyone is expected to defend everything with every possible means. . This is what David Campbell ) points out when he sees the practices of security as being about securing a precarious state identity. One way of going about it is to cast elements on the state inside resisting the privileged identity as the subversive errand boys of the prime external enemy. Wei 12 The American China threat mentality has become an effective tool that perpetuates American exceptionalist practice China threat mentality evolved from racial nativism McCarthyist extremism and American exceptionalism The climax was the Chinese Exclusion Act With growing interdependence and interweaving economies, America can no longer operate its relations with China by virtue of the American China threat mentality and the dichotomous view of the world , lack of historical perspective and a completely shallow understanding of the roots of Chinese culture will only misguide America and create more problems than solve this threat was a selfcreated and selffulfilling fallacy predicated on the paranoiac aspect of American politics, which will only perpetuate actual conflicts or even wars
"Russia" is denoted by "instability unpredictability", "imperialism . The opposite value of these markers ("stability ", "defence", "order would denote the Self and thus conjure up an identity this practice intensifies by shifting onto a security mode, treating the oppositions as if they were questions of survival. Identity is (re)produced when the oppositions are employed in a discourse of danger the distinction between state and nation has disappeared in all-encompassing securitisation. Everyone is expected to defend everything with every possible means This is what Campbell points out when he sees the practices of security as being about securing a precarious state identity The American China threat mentality has become a tool that perpetuates American exceptionalist practice With growing interdependence America can no longer operate its relations with China by virtue of the American China threat mentality lack of historical perspective and shallow understanding of Chinese culture will only misguide America and create more problems than solve this threat was a selfcreated and selffulfilling fallacy predicated on paranoiac politics, which will perpetuate actual wars
The Russian war on Chechnya is one event that was widely interpreted in the Baltic as a ominous sign of what Russia has in store for the Baltic states (see Rebas 1996: 27; Nekrasas 1996: 58; Tarand 1996: 24; cf. Haab 1997). The constitutional ban in all three states on any kind of association with post-Soviet political structures is indicative of a threat perception that confuses Soviet and post- Soviet, conflating Russia with the USSR and casting everything Russian as a threat through what Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe (1985) call a discursive "chain of equivalence". In this the value of one side in a binary opposition is reiterated in other denotations of the same binary opposition. Thus, the value "Russia" in a Russia/Europe-opposition is also denoted by "instability", "Asia", "invasion", "chaos", "incitement of ethnic minorities", "unpredictability", "imperialism", "slander campaign", "migration", and so forth. The opposite value of these markers ("stability", "Europe", "defence", "order", and so on) would then denote the Self and thus conjure up an identity. When identity is precarious, this discursive practice intensifies by shifting onto a security mode, treating the oppositions as if they were questions of political existence, sovereignty, and survival. Identity is (re)produced more effectively when the oppositions are employed in a discourse of in-security and danger, that is, made into questions of national security and thus securitised in the Wæverian sense. In the Baltic cases, especially the Lithuanian National Security Concept is knitting a chain of equivalence in a ferocious discourse of danger. Not only does it establish "[t]hat the defence of Lithuania is total and unconditional," and that "[s]hould there be no higher command, self-controlled combat actions of armed units and citizens shall be considered legal." (National Security Concept, Lithuania, Ch. 7, Sc. 1, 2) It also posits that [t]he power of civic resistance is constituted of the Nation’s Will and self-determination to fight for own freedom, of everyone citizen’s resolution to resist to [an] assailant or invader by all possible ways, despite citizen’s age and [or] profession, of taking part in Lithuania’s defence (National Security Concept, Lithuania, Ch. 7, Sc. 4). When this is added to the identifying of the objects of national security as "human and citizen rights, fundamental freedoms and personal security; state sovereignty; rights of the nation, prerequisites for a free development; the state independence; the constitutional order; state territory and its integrity, and; cultural heritage," and the subjects as "the state, the armed forces and other institutions thereof; the citizens and their associations, and; non governmental organisations,"(National Security Concept, Lithuania, Ch. 2, Sc. 1, 2) one approaches a conception of security in which the distinction between state and nation has disappeared in all-encompassing securitisation. Everyone is expected to defend everything with every possible means. And when the list of identified threats to national security that follows range from "overt (military) aggression", via "personal insecurity", to "ignoring of national values,"(National Security Concept, Lithuania, Ch. 10) the National Security Concept of Lithuania has become a totalising one taking everything to be a question of national security. The chain of equivalence is established when the very introduction of the National Security Concept is devoted to a denotation of Lithuania’s century-old sameness to "Europe" and resistance to "occupation and subjugation" (see quotation below), whereby Russia is depicted and installed as the first link in the discursive chain that follows. In much the same way the "enemy within" came about in Estonia and Latvia. As the independence-memory was ritualised and added to the sense of insecurity – already fed by confusion in state administration, legislation and government policy grappling not only with what to do but also how to do it given the inexperience of state institutions or their absence – unity behind the overarching objective of independence receded for partial politics and the construction of the enemy within. This is what David Campbell (1992) points out when he sees the practices of security as being about securing a precarious state identity. One way of going about it is to cast elements on the state inside resisting the privileged identity as the subversive errand boys of the prime external enemy. Chinese threat mentality is racist and causes serial policy failure and war Wei (Master’s at Dartmouth College) 12 (Li Juan, THE AMERICAN CHINA THREAT MENTALITY, Master’s Thesis in Liberal Studies, March 2012, pg. 77-79) The American China threat mentality has become an effective tool that perpetuates American exceptionalist practice in respect to U.S. relations with China and their dichotomous view of the world. It also helps shape the future trajectory of ChinaU.S. relations. The American China threat mentality basically evolved from three major trends including racial nativism in the late nineteen century, McCarthyist extremism in the Cold War and the new American exceptionalism in the postColdWar era. This evolution started in the late nineteenth century when racial nativism was in full swing, cultivating the fear of the Chinese immigrants. The climax of this nativist movement was the 1882 Chinese Exclusion Act. This fear and exclusion of the Chinese immediately morphed into the fear of Communism during the Cold War. McCarthyism definitely culminated in this paranoia of Communism or Chinese communism in particular. This extremist mindset and practice continued after the Cold War and was further reflected in the new American exceptionalism which supplied the American China threat mentality with the friendorfoe binary opposition and the exceptionalist norm that promoted the American political model and legitimized its transgressions of and exemptions from the rule of law. Moreover, as suggested by Galtung's oscillation model, Americans' misunderstanding of the stark realities of Chinese politics and economy from 1949 to 1958 also enhanced Americans' misperceptions of China and further contributed to this China threat mentality. Grounded on the friendorfoe rationale and exceptionalist norm, the American China threat mentality not only was reflected in American public opinion of China as well as U.S.China policy, but also found its way into the discourse of American mainstream media and scholarly works. The scrutiny of the media discourse and scholarly publications concerning the four pivotal incidents in the history of ChinaU.S. relations reveals that mass media reified the American China threat mentality by virtue of using those events as a way to revive Americans' Cold War memory, criticize the Chinese government and therefore accentuate the enemy image of the Chinese government and communism. In a bigger picture, the American China threat mentality followed a zigzag pattern similar to Galtung's oscillation model. This pattern featured alternating periods of the waxing and waning of the China threat mentality, corresponding to the fluctuation of American public opinion on China. To be specific, the waxing of this China threat mentality was parallel to the 9year distribution period and the waning to the 9year growth period. In a similar fashion, ChinaU.S. relations showed a curvy pattern as well. From the confrontation and containment in the 1950s to the moderate improvements in the bilateral ties between the two in the 1960s, ChinaU.S. relations fluctuated widely. From the nascent opening contacts and rapprochement in 1970s to the increasing military and economic cooperation in the 1980s, the fluctuation of ChinaU.S. relations continued. From the strategic engagement in the 1990s to the widespread concerns over China's future economic trajectory and military prowess in the 2000s, ChinaU.S. relations oscillated in the same manner. With a clear sight on the similar zigzag patterns of the American China threat mentality and ChinaU.S. relations, one can predict that ChinaU.S. relations will continue to fluctuate the conceivable future. With growing interdependence and interweaving economies, America can no longer operate its relations with China by virtue of the American China threat mentality and the dichotomous view of the world. It will be in the interest of our nations to seek common ground while reserving our differences. Moreover, lack of historical perspective and a completely shallow understanding of the roots of Chinese culture in Confucianism, Buddhism and Taoism will only misguide America and create more problems than solve. Additionally, the misperception of Americans in viewing all Communism as the same lacks the understanding that postCultural Revolution communism in China was a system that while flawed in some ways, worked for the Chinese people. Americans did not dare to admit that the communism at that time in China was actually saving a country of over 500 million people'97 from foreign oppression, domestic tyranny, constant warfare and starvation. It was Americans' imperative in post World War II to contain all of communism in the world which led to American policy seeking to ring China with a circle of strategic holdings. Another reason for America perceiving communism in the world and Chinese communism in particular as a threat was that communism was frequently linked to notables such as Stalin, and this threat of communism was a selfcreated and selffulfilling fallacy predicated on the paranoiac aspect of American politics, which will only perpetuate actual conflicts or even wars.
9,719
<h4><strong>The aff’’s binary between the US and Russia leads to endless war</h4><p></strong>Øyvind <strong>Jæger</strong>, @ Norweigian Institute of International Affairs and the Copenhagen Peace Research Institute, <u><strong>2k</u></strong> [Peace and Conflict Studies <u>7.2, “Securitizing Russia: Discoursive Practice of the Baltic States,” http://shss.nova.edu/pcs/journalsPDF/V7N2.pdf#page=18]</p><p></u>The Russian war on Chechnya is one event that was widely interpreted in the Baltic as a ominous sign of what Russia has in store for the Baltic states (see Rebas 1996: 27; Nekrasas 1996: 58; Tarand 1996: 24; cf. Haab 1997). The constitutional ban in all three states on any kind of association with post-Soviet political structures is indicative of a threat perception that confuses Soviet and post- Soviet, conflating Russia with the USSR and casting everything Russian as a threat through what Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe (1985) call a discursive "chain of equivalence". In this the value of one side in a binary opposition is reiterated in other denotations of the same binary opposition.<u> Thus, the value <mark>"Russia"</mark> </u>in a Russia/Europe-opposition <u><mark>is</mark> also <mark>denoted by "instability</mark>", "Asia", "invasion", "chaos", </u>"incitement of ethnic minorities", "<u><mark>unpredictability", "imperialism</u></mark>", "slander campaign", "migration", and so forth<mark>. <u>The opposite value of these markers ("stability</u></mark>", "Europe<mark>",<u> "defence", "order</u></mark>", and so on)<u><mark> would </u></mark>then<u><mark> denote the Self and thus conjure up an identity</u></mark>. When identity is precarious, <u><mark>this </u></mark>discursive<u><mark> practice intensifies by shifting onto a security mode, treating the oppositions as if they were questions of</mark> political existence, sovereignty, and <mark>survival. Identity is (re)produced</u></mark> more effectively <u><mark>when the oppositions are employed in a discourse of </u></mark>in-security and <u><mark>danger</mark>,</u> that is, made into questions of national security and thus securitised in the Wæverian sense. In the Baltic cases, especially the Lithuanian National Security Concept is knitting a chain of equivalence in a ferocious discourse of danger. Not only does it establish "[t]hat the defence of Lithuania is total and unconditional," and that "[s]hould there be no higher command, self-controlled combat actions of armed units and citizens shall be considered legal." (National Security Concept, Lithuania, Ch. 7, Sc. 1, 2) It also posits that [t]he power of civic resistance is constituted of the Nation’s Will and self-determination to fight for own freedom, of everyone citizen’s resolution to resist to [an] assailant or invader by all possible ways, despite citizen’s age and [or] profession, of taking part in Lithuania’s defence (National Security Concept, Lithuania, Ch. 7, Sc. 4). When this is added to the identifying of the objects of national security as "human and citizen rights, fundamental freedoms and personal security; state sovereignty; rights of the nation, prerequisites for a free development; the state independence; the constitutional order; state territory and its integrity, and; cultural heritage," and the subjects as "the state, the armed forces and other institutions thereof; the citizens and their associations, and; non governmental organisations,"(National Security Concept, Lithuania, Ch. 2, Sc. 1, 2) <u>one approaches a conception of security in which <mark>the distinction between state and nation has disappeared in all-encompassing securitisation. Everyone is expected to defend everything with <strong>every possible means</strong></mark>.</u> And when the list of identified threats to national security that follows range from "overt (military) aggression", via "personal insecurity", to "ignoring of national values,"(National Security Concept, Lithuania, Ch. 10) the National Security Concept of Lithuania has become a totalising one taking everything to be a question of national security. The chain of equivalence is established when the very introduction of the National Security Concept is devoted to a denotation of Lithuania’s century-old sameness to "Europe" and resistance to "occupation and subjugation" (see quotation below), whereby Russia is depicted and installed as the first link in the discursive chain that follows. In much the same way the "enemy within" came about in Estonia and Latvia. As the independence-memory was ritualised and added to the sense of insecurity – already fed by confusion in state administration, legislation and government policy grappling not only with what to do but also how to do it given the inexperience of state institutions or their absence – unity behind the overarching objective of independence receded for partial politics and the construction of the enemy within<u>. <mark>This is what</mark> David <mark>Campbell</u></mark> (1992<u>) <mark>points out when he sees the practices of security as being about securing a precarious state identity</mark>. One way of going about it is to cast elements on the state inside resisting the privileged identity as the subversive errand boys of the prime external enemy.</p><p></u>Chinese threat mentality is racist and causes serial policy failure and war</p><p><u><strong>Wei</u></strong> (Master’s at Dartmouth College) <u><strong>12</p><p></u></strong>(Li Juan, THE AMERICAN CHINA THREAT MENTALITY, Master’s Thesis in Liberal Studies, March 2012, pg. 77-79)</p><p><u><mark>The American China threat mentality has become a</mark>n effective <mark>tool that perpetuates American</mark> <mark>exceptionalist practice</u></mark> in respect to U.S. relations with China and their dichotomous view of the world. It also helps shape the future trajectory of ChinaU.S. relations.</p><p>The American <u>China threat mentality</u> basically <u>evolved from</u> three major trends including <u>racial nativism</u> in the late nineteen century, <u>McCarthyist extremism</u> in the Cold War <u>and</u> the new <u>American exceptionalism</u> in the postColdWar era. This evolution started in the late nineteenth century when racial nativism was in full swing, cultivating the fear of the Chinese immigrants. <u>The climax</u> of this nativist movement <u>was the</u> 1882 <u>Chinese Exclusion Act</u>. This fear and exclusion of the Chinese immediately morphed into the fear of Communism during the Cold War. McCarthyism definitely culminated in this paranoia of Communism or Chinese communism in particular. This extremist mindset and practice continued after the Cold War and was further reflected in the new American exceptionalism which supplied the American China threat mentality with the friendorfoe binary opposition and the exceptionalist norm that promoted the American political model and legitimized its transgressions of and exemptions from the rule of law. Moreover, as suggested by Galtung's oscillation model, Americans' misunderstanding of the stark realities of Chinese politics and economy from 1949 to 1958 also enhanced Americans' misperceptions of China and further contributed to this China threat mentality.</p><p>Grounded on the friendorfoe rationale and exceptionalist norm, the American China threat mentality not only was reflected in American public opinion of China as well as U.S.China policy, but also found its way into the discourse of American mainstream media and scholarly works. The scrutiny of the media discourse and scholarly publications concerning the four pivotal incidents in the history of ChinaU.S. relations reveals that mass media reified the American China threat mentality by virtue of using those events as a way to revive Americans' Cold War memory, criticize the Chinese government and therefore accentuate the enemy image of the Chinese government and communism.</p><p>In a bigger picture, the American China threat mentality followed a zigzag pattern similar to Galtung's oscillation model. This pattern featured alternating periods of the waxing and waning of the China threat mentality, corresponding to the fluctuation of American public opinion on China. To be specific, the waxing of this China threat mentality was parallel to the 9year distribution period and the waning to the 9year growth period.</p><p>In a similar fashion, ChinaU.S. relations showed a curvy pattern as well. From the confrontation and containment in the 1950s to the moderate improvements in the bilateral ties between the two in the 1960s, ChinaU.S. relations fluctuated widely. From the nascent opening contacts and rapprochement in 1970s to the increasing military and economic cooperation in the 1980s, the fluctuation of ChinaU.S. relations continued. From the strategic engagement in the 1990s to the widespread concerns over China's future economic trajectory and military prowess in the 2000s, ChinaU.S. relations oscillated in the same manner. With a clear sight on the similar zigzag patterns of the American China threat mentality and ChinaU.S. relations, one can predict that ChinaU.S. relations will continue to fluctuate the conceivable future.</p><p><u><mark>With growing interdependence</mark> and interweaving economies, <mark>America can no longer operate its relations with China by virtue of the American China threat mentality</mark> and the dichotomous view of the world</u>. It will be in the interest of our nations to seek common ground while reserving our differences. Moreover<u>, <mark>lack of historical perspective and</mark> a completely <mark>shallow understanding of</mark> the roots of <mark>Chinese culture</u></mark> in Confucianism, Buddhism and Taoism <u><mark>will only misguide America and create more problems than solve</u></mark>.</p><p>Additionally, the misperception of Americans in viewing all Communism as the same lacks the understanding that postCultural Revolution communism in China was a system that while flawed in some ways, worked for the Chinese people. Americans did not dare to admit that the communism at that time in China was actually saving a country of over 500 million people'97 from foreign oppression, domestic tyranny, constant warfare and starvation. It was Americans' imperative in post World War II to contain all of communism in the world which led to American policy seeking to ring China with a circle of strategic holdings. Another reason for America perceiving communism in the world and Chinese communism in particular as a threat was that communism was frequently linked to notables such as Stalin, and <u><mark>this threat</u></mark> of communism <u><mark>was</u> <u>a selfcreated and selffulfilling fallacy predicated on</mark> the <mark>paranoiac</mark> aspect of American <mark>politics, which will</mark> only <mark>perpetuate actual</mark> conflicts or even <mark>wars</u><strong></mark>.</p></strong>
null
null
K
4,059
86
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,274
This Othering of the prostitute in the name of the Children, the Family, the future, is the drive of reproductive futurism which sacrifices adult freedoms at the altar of the Child. This ensures the oppression and targeting of queer individuals and lifestyles which seem to threaten the reproduction of the social order.
Edelman ’04
Edelman ’04, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, p. 18-22
The Child, is the figure for this compulsory investment in the rnisrecognition of figure. It takes its place on the social stage like every adorable Annie gathering as viewed through the prism of the tears that it always calls forth, the figure of this Child seems to shimmer with the iridescent promise serving like the rainbow as the pledge of a covenant that shields us against the persistent threat of apocalypse the cult of the Child permits no shrines to the queerness of boys and girls, since queerness, for contemporary culture is understood as bringing children and childhood to an end. , the occasion of a gay man’s death gives the film the excuse to unleash once more the disciplinary image of the “innocent” Child performing its mandatory cultural labor of social reproduction We encounter this image as the lives, the speech, and the freedoms of adults face constant threat of legal curtailment out of deference to imaginary Children whose futures, as if they were permitted to have them except as they consist in the prospect of passing them on to Children of their own, are construed as endangered by the social disease as which queer sexualities register Thus, while lesbians and gay men work for political right refusing to acknowledge these comrades in reproductive futurism, counters their efforts by inviting us to kneel at the shrine of the sacred Child the Child who might witness lewd or inappropriately intimate behavior; the Child who might find information about dangerous “lifestyles” on the Internet the Child who might choose a pro vocative book from the shelves of the public library; the Child who might find an enjoyment that would nullify the figural value, itself imposed by adult desire, of the Child as unmarked by the adult’s adulterating implication in desire itself the Child for the satisfaction of adults, an Imaginary fullness that’s considered to want, for nothing a nation made for adult citizens has been replaced by one imagined for fetuses and children.” our enjoyment of liberty is eclipsed by the lengthening shadow of a Child whose freedom to develop undisturbed by encounters, or even by the threat of potential encounters, with an “otherness” of which its parents, its church, or the state do not approve, uncompromised by any possible access to what is painted as alien desire, terroristically holds us all in check and determines that political discourse conform to the logic of a narrative wherein history unfolds as the future envisioned for a Child who must never grow up. That Child, immured in an innocence seen as continuously under siege, condenses a fantasy of vulnerability to the queerness of queer sexualities precisely insofar as that Child enshrines, in its form as sublimation, the very value for which queerness regularly finds itself condemned The Child, marks the fetishistic fixation of heteronormativity: an erotically charged investment in the rigid same ness of identity that is central to the compulsory narrative of reproductive futurism the right maintains, the battle against queers is a life-and-death struggle for the future of a Child whose ruin is pursued by queers
the cult of the Child permits no shrines to queerness since queerness, is understood as bringing children and childhood to an end. the lives, and freedoms of adults face constant threat of legal curtailment out of deference to imaginary Children whose futures, as Children of their own, are construed as endangered by queer sexualities the political right, counters their efforts by inviting us to kneel at the shrine of the sacred Child the Child who might witness lewd or inappropriately intimate behavior; the Child who might find information about dangerous “lifestyles” on the Internet the Child ho might find an enjoyment that would nullify the figural value, itself imposed by adult desire, of the Child as unmarked a nation made for adult citizens has been replaced by one imagined for fetuses and children. That Child, immured in an innocence seen as under siege, condenses a fantasy of vulnerability to queerness precisely insofar as that Child enshrines the very value for which queerness regularly finds itself condemned The Child marks the fixation of heteronormativity: an erotically charged investment in the rigid same ness of identity that is central to the compulsory narrative of reproductive futurism the battle against queers is a life-and-death struggle for the future of a Child
The Child, in the historical epoch of our current epistemological regime, is the figure for this compulsory investment in the rnisrecognition of figure. It takes its place on the social stage like every adorable Annie gathering her limitless finds of pluck to “stick out /her chin/ And grin/ And say: ‘Tomorrow?/ Tomorrow/ I love ya/ Tomorrow/You’re always/ A day/ Away.” And lo and behold, as viewed through the prism of the tears that it always calls forth, the figure of this Child seems to shimmer with the iridescent promise of Noah’s rainbow, serving like the rainbow as the pledge of a covenant that shields us against the persistent threat of apocalypse now—or later. Recall, for example, the end of Jonathan Demme’s Philadelphia (1993), his filmic act of contrition for the homo- phobia some attributed to The Silence of the Lambs. After Andrew Beckett (a man for all seasons, as portrayed by the saintly Tom Ranks), last seen on his deathbed in an oxygen mask that seems to allude to, or trope on, Hannibal Lecter’s more memorable muzzle (see figures 1 and 2), has shuffled off this mortal coil to stand, as we are led to suppose, before a higher law, we find ourselves in, if not at, his wake surveying a room in his family home, now crowded with children and pregnant women whose reassuringly bulging bellies (see figure 3) displace the bulging basket (unseen) of the I-Iiv-posirive gay man (unseen) from whom, the filrnic text suggests, in a cinema (unlike the one in which we sir watching Philadelphia) not phobic about graphic representations of male-male sexual acts, Saint Thomas, a.k.a. Beckett, contracted the virus that cost him his life. When we witness, in the film’s final sequence, therefore, the videotaped representation of Andrew playing on the beach as a boy (see figure 4), the tears that these moving pictures solicit burn with an indignation directed not only against the intolerant world that sought to crush the honorable man this boy would later become, but also against the homosexual world in which boys like this eventually grow up to have crushes on other men. For the cult of the Child permits no shrines to the queerness of boys and girls, since queerness, for contemporary culture at large as for Philadelphia in particular, is understood as bringing children and childhood to an end. Thus, the occasion of a gay man’s death gives the film the excuse to unleash once more the disciplinary image of the “innocent” Child performing its mandatory cultural labor of social reproduction. We encounter this image on every side as the lives, the speech, and the freedoms of adults face constant threat of legal curtailment out of deference to imaginary Children whose futures, as if they were permitted to have them except as they consist in the prospect of passing them on to Children of their own, are construed as endangered by the social disease as which queer sexualities register. Nor should we forget how pervasively AIDS —for which to this day the most effective name associated with the congressional appropriation of funds is that of a child, Ryan White—reinforces an older connection, as old as the antigay reading imposed on the biblical narrative of Sodom’s destruction, between practices of gay sexuality and the undoing of futurity.’ This, of course, is the connection on which Anita Bryant played so cannily when she campaigned in Florida against gay civil rights under the banner of “Save Our Children,” and it remains the connection on which the national crusade against gay marriage rests its case. Thus, while lesbians and gay men by the thousands work for the right to marry, to serve in the military, to adopt and raise children of their own, the political right, refusing to acknowledge these comrades in reproductive futurism, counters their efforts by inviting us to kneel at the shrine of the sacred Child: the Child who might witness lewd or inappropriately intimate behavior; the Child who might find information about dangerous “lifestyles” on the Internet; the Child who might choose a pro vocative book from the shelves of the public library; the Child, in short, who might find an enjoyment that would nullify the figural value, itself imposed by adult desire, of the Child as unmarked by the adult’s adulterating implication in desire itself the Child, that is, made to image, for the satisfaction of adults, an Imaginary fullness that’s considered to want, and therefore to want for, nothing. As Lauren Berlant argues force fully at the outset of The Queen of Amenco Goes to Washington City, “a nation made for adult citizens has been replaced by one imagined for fetuses and children.”22 On every side, our enjoyment of liberty is eclipsed by the lengthening shadow of a Child whose freedom to develop undisturbed by encounters, or even by the threat of potential encounters, with an “otherness” of which its parents, its church, or the state do not approve, uncompromised by any possible access to what is painted as alien desire, terroristically holds us all in check and determines that political discourse conform to the logic of a narrative wherein history unfolds as the future envisioned for a Child who must never grow up. Not for nothing, after all, does the historical construction of the homosexual as distinctive social type overlap with the appearance of such literary creations as Tiny Tim, David Balfòur, and Peter Pan, who enact, in an imperative most evident today in the uncannily intimate connection between Harry Potter and Lord Voldemort, a Symbolic resistance to the unmarried men (Scrooge, Uncle Ebenezer, Captain Hook) who embody, as Voldemort’s name makes clear, a wish, a will, or a drive toward death that entails the destruction of the Child. That Child, immured in an innocence seen as continuously under siege, condenses a fantasy of vulnerability to the queerness of queer sexualities precisely insofar as that Child enshrines, in its form as sublimation, the very value for which queerness regularly finds itself condemned: an insistence on sameness that intends to restore an Imaginary past. The Child, that is, marks the fetishistic fixation of heteronormativity: an erotically charged investment in the rigid same ness of identity that is central to the compulsory narrative of reproductive futurism. And so, as the radical right maintains, the battle against queers is a life-and-death struggle for the future of a Child whose ruin is pursued by feminists, queers, and those who support the legal availability of abortion. Indeed, as the Army of God made clear in the bomb- making guide it produced from the assistance of its militantly “pm..1if members, its purpose w wholly congruent with the logic of reproductive futurism: to “disrupt and ultimately destroy Satan’s power to kill our children, God’s children.”23
6,821
<h4>This Othering of the prostitute in the name of the Children, the Family, the future, is the drive of reproductive futurism which sacrifices adult freedoms at the altar of the Child. This ensures the oppression and targeting of queer individuals and lifestyles which seem to threaten the reproduction of the social order.</h4><p><strong>Edelman ’04</strong>, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, p. 18-22</p><p><u>The Child,</u> in the historical epoch of our current epistemological regime, <u>is the figure for this compulsory investment in the rnisrecognition of figure. It takes its place on the social stage like every adorable Annie gathering</u> her limitless finds of pluck to “stick out /her chin/ And grin/ And say: ‘Tomorrow?/ Tomorrow/ I love ya/ Tomorrow/You’re always/ A day/ Away.” And lo and behold, <u>as viewed through the prism of the tears that it always calls forth, the figure of this Child seems to shimmer with the iridescent promise</u> of Noah’s rainbow, <u>serving like the rainbow as the pledge of a covenant that shields us against the persistent threat of apocalypse</u> now—or later. Recall, for example, the end of Jonathan Demme’s Philadelphia (1993), his filmic act of contrition for the homo- phobia some attributed to The Silence of the Lambs. After Andrew Beckett (a man for all seasons, as portrayed by the saintly Tom Ranks), last seen on his deathbed in an oxygen mask that seems to allude to, or trope on, Hannibal Lecter’s more memorable muzzle (see figures 1 and 2), has shuffled off this mortal coil to stand, as we are led to suppose, before a higher law, we find ourselves in, if not at, his wake surveying a room in his family home, now crowded with children and pregnant women whose reassuringly bulging bellies (see figure 3) displace the bulging basket (unseen) of the I-Iiv-posirive gay man (unseen) from whom, the filrnic text suggests, in a cinema (unlike the one in which we sir watching Philadelphia) not phobic about graphic representations of male-male sexual acts, Saint Thomas, a.k.a. Beckett, contracted the virus that cost him his life. When we witness, in the film’s final sequence, therefore, the videotaped representation of Andrew playing on the beach as a boy (see figure 4), the tears that these moving pictures solicit burn with an indignation directed not only against the intolerant world that sought to crush the honorable man this boy would later become, but also against the homosexual world in which boys like this eventually grow up to have crushes on other men. For <u><strong><mark>the cult of the Child permits no shrines to </mark>the <mark>queerness</mark> of boys and girls, <mark>since queerness,</mark> for contemporary culture</u></strong> at large as for Philadelphia in particular, <u><strong><mark>is understood as bringing children and childhood to an end.</mark> </u></strong>Thus<u>, the occasion of a gay man’s death gives the film the excuse to unleash once more the disciplinary image of the “innocent” Child performing its mandatory cultural labor of social reproduction</u>. <u><strong>We encounter this image</u></strong> on every side <u><strong>as <mark>the lives, </mark>the speech, <mark>and </mark>the <mark>freedoms of adults face constant threat of legal curtailment out of deference to imaginary Children whose futures, as</mark> if they were permitted to have them except as they consist in the prospect of passing them on to <mark>Children of their own, are construed as endangered by </mark>the social disease as which <mark>queer sexualities </mark>register</u></strong>. Nor should we forget how pervasively AIDS —for which to this day the most effective name associated with the congressional appropriation of funds is that of a child, Ryan White—reinforces an older connection, as old as the antigay reading imposed on the biblical narrative of Sodom’s destruction, between practices of gay sexuality and the undoing of futurity.’ This, of course, is the connection on which Anita Bryant played so cannily when she campaigned in Florida against gay civil rights under the banner of “Save Our Children,” and it remains the connection on which the national crusade against gay marriage rests its case.</p><p><u>Thus, while lesbians and gay men</u> by the thousands <u>work for</u> the right to marry, to serve in the military, to adopt and raise children of their own, <mark>the <u>political right</u>,</mark> <u>refusing to acknowledge these comrades in reproductive futurism, <mark>counters their efforts by inviting us to kneel at the shrine of the sacred Child</u></mark>: <u><mark>the Child who might witness lewd or inappropriately intimate behavior; the Child who might find information about dangerous “lifestyles” on the Internet</u></mark>; <u>the Child who might choose a pro vocative book from the shelves of the public library; <mark>the Child</u></mark>, in short, <u>w<mark>ho might find an enjoyment that would nullify the figural value, itself imposed by adult desire, of the Child as unmarked</mark> by the adult’s adulterating implication in desire itself the Child</u>, that is, made to image, <u>for the satisfaction of adults, an Imaginary fullness that’s considered to want,</u> and therefore to want <u>for</u>, <u>nothing</u>. As Lauren Berlant argues force fully at the outset of The Queen of Amenco Goes to Washington City, “<u><strong><mark>a nation made for adult citizens has been replaced by one imagined for fetuses and children</strong>.</mark>”</u>22 On every side, <u>our enjoyment of liberty is eclipsed by the lengthening shadow of a Child whose freedom to develop undisturbed by encounters, or even by the threat of potential encounters, with an “otherness” of which its parents, its church, or the state do not approve, uncompromised by any possible access to what is painted as alien desire, terroristically holds us all in check and determines that political discourse conform to the logic of a narrative wherein history unfolds as the future envisioned for a Child who must never grow up.</u> Not for nothing, after all, does the historical construction of the homosexual as distinctive social type overlap with the appearance of such literary creations as Tiny Tim, David Balfòur, and Peter Pan, who enact, in an imperative most evident today in the uncannily intimate connection between Harry Potter and Lord Voldemort, a Symbolic resistance to the unmarried men (Scrooge, Uncle Ebenezer, Captain Hook) who embody, as Voldemort’s name makes clear, a wish, a will, or a drive toward death that entails the destruction of the Child. <u><mark>That Child, immured in an innocence seen as </mark>continuously <mark>under siege, condenses a fantasy of vulnerability to </mark>the <mark>queerness </mark>of queer sexualities <mark>precisely insofar as that Child enshrines</mark>, in its form as sublimation, <mark>the very value for which queerness regularly finds itself condemned</u></mark>: an insistence on sameness that intends to restore an Imaginary past. <u><mark>The Child</mark>,</u> that is, <u><mark>marks the</mark> fetishistic <mark>fixation of heteronormativity: an erotically charged investment in the rigid same ness of identity that is central to the compulsory narrative of reproductive futurism</u></mark>. And so, as <u>the</u> radical <u>right maintains, <mark>the battle against queers is a life-and-death struggle for the future of a Child</mark> whose ruin is pursued by</u> feminists, <u>queers</u>, and those who support the legal availability of abortion. Indeed, as the Army of God made clear in the bomb- making guide it produced from the assistance of its militantly “pm..1if members, its purpose w wholly congruent with the logic of reproductive futurism: to “disrupt and ultimately destroy Satan’s power to kill our children, God’s children.”23</p>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
159,634
28
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,275
This Othering of the prostitute in the name of the Children, the Family, the future, is the drive of reproductive futurism which sacrifices adult freedoms at the altar of the Child. This ensures the oppression and targeting of queer individuals and lifestyles which seem to threaten the reproduction of the social order.
Edelman ’04
Edelman ’04, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, p. 18-22
The Child, is the figure for this compulsory investment in the rnisrecognition of figure. It takes its place on the social stage like every adorable Annie gathering as viewed through the prism of the tears that it always calls forth, the figure of this Child seems to shimmer with the iridescent promise serving like the rainbow as the pledge of a covenant that shields us against the persistent threat of apocalypse the cult of the Child permits no shrines to the queerness of boys and girls, since queerness, for contemporary culture is understood as bringing children and childhood to an end. , the occasion of a gay man’s death gives the film the excuse to unleash once more the disciplinary image of the “innocent” Child performing its mandatory cultural labor of social reproduction We encounter this image as the lives, the speech, and the freedoms of adults face constant threat of legal curtailment out of deference to imaginary Children whose futures, as if they were permitted to have them except as they consist in the prospect of passing them on to Children of their own, are construed as endangered by the social disease as which queer sexualities register Thus, while lesbians and gay men work for political right refusing to acknowledge these comrades in reproductive futurism, counters their efforts by inviting us to kneel at the shrine of the sacred Child the Child who might witness lewd or inappropriately intimate behavior; the Child who might find information about dangerous “lifestyles” on the Internet the Child who might choose a pro vocative book from the shelves of the public library; the Child who might find an enjoyment that would nullify the figural value, itself imposed by adult desire, of the Child as unmarked by the adult’s adulterating implication in desire itself the Child for the satisfaction of adults, an Imaginary fullness that’s considered to want, for nothing a nation made for adult citizens has been replaced by one imagined for fetuses and children.” our enjoyment of liberty is eclipsed by the lengthening shadow of a Child whose freedom to develop undisturbed by encounters, or even by the threat of potential encounters, with an “otherness” of which its parents, its church, or the state do not approve, uncompromised by any possible access to what is painted as alien desire, terroristically holds us all in check and determines that political discourse conform to the logic of a narrative wherein history unfolds as the future envisioned for a Child who must never grow up. That Child, immured in an innocence seen as continuously under siege, condenses a fantasy of vulnerability to the queerness of queer sexualities precisely insofar as that Child enshrines, in its form as sublimation, the very value for which queerness regularly finds itself condemned The Child, marks the fetishistic fixation of heteronormativity: an erotically charged investment in the rigid same ness of identity that is central to the compulsory narrative of reproductive futurism the right maintains, the battle against queers is a life-and-death struggle for the future of a Child whose ruin is pursued by queers
the cult of the Child permits no shrines to queerness since queerness, is understood as bringing children and childhood to an end. the lives, and freedoms of adults face constant threat of legal curtailment out of deference to imaginary Children whose futures, as Children of their own, are construed as endangered by queer sexualities the political right, counters their efforts by inviting us to kneel at the shrine of the sacred Child the Child who might witness lewd or inappropriately intimate behavior; the Child who might find information about dangerous “lifestyles” on the Internet the Child ho might find an enjoyment that would nullify the figural value, itself imposed by adult desire, of the Child as unmarked a nation made for adult citizens has been replaced by one imagined for fetuses and children. That Child, immured in an innocence seen as under siege, condenses a fantasy of vulnerability to queerness precisely insofar as that Child enshrines the very value for which queerness regularly finds itself condemned The Child marks the fixation of heteronormativity: an erotically charged investment in the rigid same ness of identity that is central to the compulsory narrative of reproductive futurism the battle against queers is a life-and-death struggle for the future of a Child
The Child, in the historical epoch of our current epistemological regime, is the figure for this compulsory investment in the rnisrecognition of figure. It takes its place on the social stage like every adorable Annie gathering her limitless finds of pluck to “stick out /her chin/ And grin/ And say: ‘Tomorrow?/ Tomorrow/ I love ya/ Tomorrow/You’re always/ A day/ Away.” And lo and behold, as viewed through the prism of the tears that it always calls forth, the figure of this Child seems to shimmer with the iridescent promise of Noah’s rainbow, serving like the rainbow as the pledge of a covenant that shields us against the persistent threat of apocalypse now—or later. Recall, for example, the end of Jonathan Demme’s Philadelphia (1993), his filmic act of contrition for the homo- phobia some attributed to The Silence of the Lambs. After Andrew Beckett (a man for all seasons, as portrayed by the saintly Tom Ranks), last seen on his deathbed in an oxygen mask that seems to allude to, or trope on, Hannibal Lecter’s more memorable muzzle (see figures 1 and 2), has shuffled off this mortal coil to stand, as we are led to suppose, before a higher law, we find ourselves in, if not at, his wake surveying a room in his family home, now crowded with children and pregnant women whose reassuringly bulging bellies (see figure 3) displace the bulging basket (unseen) of the I-Iiv-posirive gay man (unseen) from whom, the filrnic text suggests, in a cinema (unlike the one in which we sir watching Philadelphia) not phobic about graphic representations of male-male sexual acts, Saint Thomas, a.k.a. Beckett, contracted the virus that cost him his life. When we witness, in the film’s final sequence, therefore, the videotaped representation of Andrew playing on the beach as a boy (see figure 4), the tears that these moving pictures solicit burn with an indignation directed not only against the intolerant world that sought to crush the honorable man this boy would later become, but also against the homosexual world in which boys like this eventually grow up to have crushes on other men. For the cult of the Child permits no shrines to the queerness of boys and girls, since queerness, for contemporary culture at large as for Philadelphia in particular, is understood as bringing children and childhood to an end. Thus, the occasion of a gay man’s death gives the film the excuse to unleash once more the disciplinary image of the “innocent” Child performing its mandatory cultural labor of social reproduction. We encounter this image on every side as the lives, the speech, and the freedoms of adults face constant threat of legal curtailment out of deference to imaginary Children whose futures, as if they were permitted to have them except as they consist in the prospect of passing them on to Children of their own, are construed as endangered by the social disease as which queer sexualities register. Nor should we forget how pervasively AIDS —for which to this day the most effective name associated with the congressional appropriation of funds is that of a child, Ryan White—reinforces an older connection, as old as the antigay reading imposed on the biblical narrative of Sodom’s destruction, between practices of gay sexuality and the undoing of futurity.’ This, of course, is the connection on which Anita Bryant played so cannily when she campaigned in Florida against gay civil rights under the banner of “Save Our Children,” and it remains the connection on which the national crusade against gay marriage rests its case. Thus, while lesbians and gay men by the thousands work for the right to marry, to serve in the military, to adopt and raise children of their own, the political right, refusing to acknowledge these comrades in reproductive futurism, counters their efforts by inviting us to kneel at the shrine of the sacred Child: the Child who might witness lewd or inappropriately intimate behavior; the Child who might find information about dangerous “lifestyles” on the Internet; the Child who might choose a pro vocative book from the shelves of the public library; the Child, in short, who might find an enjoyment that would nullify the figural value, itself imposed by adult desire, of the Child as unmarked by the adult’s adulterating implication in desire itself the Child, that is, made to image, for the satisfaction of adults, an Imaginary fullness that’s considered to want, and therefore to want for, nothing. As Lauren Berlant argues force fully at the outset of The Queen of Amenco Goes to Washington City, “a nation made for adult citizens has been replaced by one imagined for fetuses and children.”22 On every side, our enjoyment of liberty is eclipsed by the lengthening shadow of a Child whose freedom to develop undisturbed by encounters, or even by the threat of potential encounters, with an “otherness” of which its parents, its church, or the state do not approve, uncompromised by any possible access to what is painted as alien desire, terroristically holds us all in check and determines that political discourse conform to the logic of a narrative wherein history unfolds as the future envisioned for a Child who must never grow up. Not for nothing, after all, does the historical construction of the homosexual as distinctive social type overlap with the appearance of such literary creations as Tiny Tim, David Balfòur, and Peter Pan, who enact, in an imperative most evident today in the uncannily intimate connection between Harry Potter and Lord Voldemort, a Symbolic resistance to the unmarried men (Scrooge, Uncle Ebenezer, Captain Hook) who embody, as Voldemort’s name makes clear, a wish, a will, or a drive toward death that entails the destruction of the Child. That Child, immured in an innocence seen as continuously under siege, condenses a fantasy of vulnerability to the queerness of queer sexualities precisely insofar as that Child enshrines, in its form as sublimation, the very value for which queerness regularly finds itself condemned: an insistence on sameness that intends to restore an Imaginary past. The Child, that is, marks the fetishistic fixation of heteronormativity: an erotically charged investment in the rigid same ness of identity that is central to the compulsory narrative of reproductive futurism. And so, as the radical right maintains, the battle against queers is a life-and-death struggle for the future of a Child whose ruin is pursued by feminists, queers, and those who support the legal availability of abortion. Indeed, as the Army of God made clear in the bomb- making guide it produced from the assistance of its militantly “pm..1if members, its purpose w wholly congruent with the logic of reproductive futurism: to “disrupt and ultimately destroy Satan’s power to kill our children, God’s children.”23
6,821
<h4>This Othering of the prostitute in the name of the Children, the Family, the future, is the drive of reproductive futurism which sacrifices adult freedoms at the altar of the Child. This ensures the oppression and targeting of queer individuals and lifestyles which seem to threaten the reproduction of the social order.</h4><p><strong>Edelman ’04</strong>, English prof at Tufts, Ph.D and M. Phil from Yale, No Future: Queer Theory and the Death Drive, p. 18-22</p><p><u>The Child,</u> in the historical epoch of our current epistemological regime, <u>is the figure for this compulsory investment in the rnisrecognition of figure. It takes its place on the social stage like every adorable Annie gathering</u> her limitless finds of pluck to “stick out /her chin/ And grin/ And say: ‘Tomorrow?/ Tomorrow/ I love ya/ Tomorrow/You’re always/ A day/ Away.” And lo and behold, <u>as viewed through the prism of the tears that it always calls forth, the figure of this Child seems to shimmer with the iridescent promise</u> of Noah’s rainbow, <u>serving like the rainbow as the pledge of a covenant that shields us against the persistent threat of apocalypse</u> now—or later. Recall, for example, the end of Jonathan Demme’s Philadelphia (1993), his filmic act of contrition for the homo- phobia some attributed to The Silence of the Lambs. After Andrew Beckett (a man for all seasons, as portrayed by the saintly Tom Ranks), last seen on his deathbed in an oxygen mask that seems to allude to, or trope on, Hannibal Lecter’s more memorable muzzle (see figures 1 and 2), has shuffled off this mortal coil to stand, as we are led to suppose, before a higher law, we find ourselves in, if not at, his wake surveying a room in his family home, now crowded with children and pregnant women whose reassuringly bulging bellies (see figure 3) displace the bulging basket (unseen) of the I-Iiv-posirive gay man (unseen) from whom, the filrnic text suggests, in a cinema (unlike the one in which we sir watching Philadelphia) not phobic about graphic representations of male-male sexual acts, Saint Thomas, a.k.a. Beckett, contracted the virus that cost him his life. When we witness, in the film’s final sequence, therefore, the videotaped representation of Andrew playing on the beach as a boy (see figure 4), the tears that these moving pictures solicit burn with an indignation directed not only against the intolerant world that sought to crush the honorable man this boy would later become, but also against the homosexual world in which boys like this eventually grow up to have crushes on other men. For <u><strong><mark>the cult of the Child permits no shrines to </mark>the <mark>queerness</mark> of boys and girls, <mark>since queerness,</mark> for contemporary culture</u></strong> at large as for Philadelphia in particular, <u><strong><mark>is understood as bringing children and childhood to an end.</mark> </u></strong>Thus<u>, the occasion of a gay man’s death gives the film the excuse to unleash once more the disciplinary image of the “innocent” Child performing its mandatory cultural labor of social reproduction</u>. <u><strong>We encounter this image</u></strong> on every side <u><strong>as <mark>the lives, </mark>the speech, <mark>and </mark>the <mark>freedoms of adults face constant threat of legal curtailment out of deference to imaginary Children whose futures, as</mark> if they were permitted to have them except as they consist in the prospect of passing them on to <mark>Children of their own, are construed as endangered by </mark>the social disease as which <mark>queer sexualities </mark>register</u></strong>. Nor should we forget how pervasively AIDS —for which to this day the most effective name associated with the congressional appropriation of funds is that of a child, Ryan White—reinforces an older connection, as old as the antigay reading imposed on the biblical narrative of Sodom’s destruction, between practices of gay sexuality and the undoing of futurity.’ This, of course, is the connection on which Anita Bryant played so cannily when she campaigned in Florida against gay civil rights under the banner of “Save Our Children,” and it remains the connection on which the national crusade against gay marriage rests its case.</p><p><u>Thus, while lesbians and gay men</u> by the thousands <u>work for</u> the right to marry, to serve in the military, to adopt and raise children of their own, <mark>the <u>political right</u>,</mark> <u>refusing to acknowledge these comrades in reproductive futurism, <mark>counters their efforts by inviting us to kneel at the shrine of the sacred Child</u></mark>: <u><mark>the Child who might witness lewd or inappropriately intimate behavior; the Child who might find information about dangerous “lifestyles” on the Internet</u></mark>; <u>the Child who might choose a pro vocative book from the shelves of the public library; <mark>the Child</u></mark>, in short, <u>w<mark>ho might find an enjoyment that would nullify the figural value, itself imposed by adult desire, of the Child as unmarked</mark> by the adult’s adulterating implication in desire itself the Child</u>, that is, made to image, <u>for the satisfaction of adults, an Imaginary fullness that’s considered to want,</u> and therefore to want <u>for</u>, <u>nothing</u>. As Lauren Berlant argues force fully at the outset of The Queen of Amenco Goes to Washington City, “<u><strong><mark>a nation made for adult citizens has been replaced by one imagined for fetuses and children</strong>.</mark>”</u>22 On every side, <u>our enjoyment of liberty is eclipsed by the lengthening shadow of a Child whose freedom to develop undisturbed by encounters, or even by the threat of potential encounters, with an “otherness” of which its parents, its church, or the state do not approve, uncompromised by any possible access to what is painted as alien desire, terroristically holds us all in check and determines that political discourse conform to the logic of a narrative wherein history unfolds as the future envisioned for a Child who must never grow up.</u> Not for nothing, after all, does the historical construction of the homosexual as distinctive social type overlap with the appearance of such literary creations as Tiny Tim, David Balfòur, and Peter Pan, who enact, in an imperative most evident today in the uncannily intimate connection between Harry Potter and Lord Voldemort, a Symbolic resistance to the unmarried men (Scrooge, Uncle Ebenezer, Captain Hook) who embody, as Voldemort’s name makes clear, a wish, a will, or a drive toward death that entails the destruction of the Child. <u><mark>That Child, immured in an innocence seen as </mark>continuously <mark>under siege, condenses a fantasy of vulnerability to </mark>the <mark>queerness </mark>of queer sexualities <mark>precisely insofar as that Child enshrines</mark>, in its form as sublimation, <mark>the very value for which queerness regularly finds itself condemned</u></mark>: an insistence on sameness that intends to restore an Imaginary past. <u><mark>The Child</mark>,</u> that is, <u><mark>marks the</mark> fetishistic <mark>fixation of heteronormativity: an erotically charged investment in the rigid same ness of identity that is central to the compulsory narrative of reproductive futurism</u></mark>. And so, as <u>the</u> radical <u>right maintains, <mark>the battle against queers is a life-and-death struggle for the future of a Child</mark> whose ruin is pursued by</u> feminists, <u>queers</u>, and those who support the legal availability of abortion. Indeed, as the Army of God made clear in the bomb- making guide it produced from the assistance of its militantly “pm..1if members, its purpose w wholly congruent with the logic of reproductive futurism: to “disrupt and ultimately destroy Satan’s power to kill our children, God’s children.”23</p>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
159,634
28
17,077
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
565,297
A
tournament
4
Binghamton Cepin-Sehgal
Baker, Webster Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,276
Our alternative is to steal from the university by refusing its demand for ongoing critique – this knowledge should exist in and for the undercommons
Moten and Harney 04.  ruptural
Moten and Harney 04. Fred Moten and Stefano Harney, The University and the Undercommons, SEVEN THESES Social Text 79, Vol. 22, No. 2, Summer 2004. Copyright © 2004 by Duke University Press“To the university I’ll steal, and there I’ll steal,” to borrow from Pistol at the end of Henry V, as he would surely borrow from us. This is the only possible relationship to the American university today.This may be true of universities everywhere. It may have to be true of the university in general. But certainly, this much is true in the United States: it cannot be denied that the university is a place of refuge, and it cannot be accepted that the university is a place of enlightenment. In the face of these conditions one can only sneak into the university and steal what one can. To abuse its hospitality, to spite its mission, to join its refugee colony, its gypsy encampment, to be in but not of—this is the path of the subversive intellectual in the modern university. Worry about the university. This is the injunction today in the United States, one with a long history. Call for its restoration like Harold Bloom or Stanley Fish or Gerald Graff. Call for its reform like Derek Bok or Bill Readings or Cary Nelson.Call out to it as it calls to you. But for the subversive intellectual, all of this goes on upstairs, in polite company, among the rational men. After all, the subversive intellectual came under false pretenses, with bad documents, out of love. Her labor is as necessary as it is unwelcome. The university needs what she bears but cannot bear what she brings. And on top of all that, she disappears.She disappears into the underground, the downlow lowdown maroon community of the university, into the Undercommons of Enlightenment, where the work gets done, where the work gets subverted, where the revolution is still black, still strong. What is that work and what is its social capacity for both reproducing the university and producing fugitivity? If one were to say teaching, onewould be performing the work of the university. Teaching is merely a profession and an operation of what Jacques Derrida calls the onto-/auto-encyclopedic circle of the Universitas. But it is useful to invoke this operation to glimpse the hole in the fence where labor enters, to glimpse its hiring hall, its night quarters. The university needs teaching labor, despite itself, or as itself, self-identical with and thereby erased by it. It is not teaching then that holds this social capacity, but something that produces the not visible other side of teaching, a thinking through the skin of teaching toward a collective orientation to the knowledge object as future project, and a commitment to what we want to call the prophetic organization. But it is teaching that brings us in. Before there are grants, research, conferences, books, and journals there is the experience of being taught and of teaching. Before the research post with no teaching, before the graduate students to mark the exams, before the string of sabbaticals, before the permanent reduction in teaching load, the appointment to run the Center, the consignment of pedagogy to a discipline called education, before the course designed to be a new book, teaching happened. The moment of teaching for food is therefore often mistakenly taken to be a stage, as if eventually, one should not teach for food. If the stage persists, there is a social pathology in the university. But if the teaching is successfully passed on, the stage is surpassed, and teaching is consigned to those who are known to remain in the stage, the sociopathologicallabor of the university. Kant interestingly calls such a stage “self-incurred minority.” He tries to contrast it with having the “determination and courage to use one’s intelligence without being guided by another.” “Have the courage to use your own intelligence.” But what would it mean if teaching or rather what we might call “the beyond of teaching” is precisely what one is asked to get beyond, to stop taking sustenance? And what of those minorities who refuse, the tribe of moles who will not come back from beyond2 (that which is beyond “the beyond of teaching”), as if they will not be subjects, as if they want to think as objects, as minority? Certainly, the perfect subjects of communication, those successfully beyond teaching, will see them as waste. But their collective labor will always call into question who truly is taking the orders of the Enlightenment. The waste lives for those moments 102 Moten/Harneybeyond2 teaching when you give away the unexpected beautiful phrase— unexpected, no one has asked, beautiful, it will never come back. Is being the biopower of the Enlightenment truly better than this? Perhaps the biopower of the Enlightenment know this, or perhaps it is just reacting to the objecthood of this labor as it must. But even as it depends on these moles, these refugees, they will call them uncollegial, impractical, naive, unprofessional. And one may be given one last chance to be pragmatic—why steal when one can have it all, they will ask. But if one hides from this interpellation, neither agrees nor disagrees but goes with hands full into the underground of the university, into the Undercommons—this will be regarded as theft, as a criminal act. And it is at the same time, the only possible act. In that Undercommons of the university one can see that it is not a matter of teaching versus research or even the beyond of teaching versus the individualization of research. To enter this space is to inhabit the ruptural and enraptured disclosure of the commons that fugitive enlightenment enacts, the criminal, matricidal, queer, in the cistern, on the stroll of the stolen life, the life stolen by enlightenment and stolen back, where the commons give refuge, where the refuge gives commons. What the beyond2 of teaching is really about is not finishing oneself, not passing, not completing; it’s about allowing subjectivity to be unlawfully overcome by others, a radical passion and passivity such that one becomes unfit for subjection, because one does not possess the kind of agency that can hold the regulatory forces of subjecthood, and one cannot initiate the auto-interpellative torque that biopower subjection requires and rewards. It is not so much the teaching as it is the prophecy in the organization of the act of teaching.
null
null
null
0
<h4><strong>Our alternative is to steal from the university by refusing its demand for ongoing critique – this knowledge should exist in and for the undercommons</h4><p>Moten and Harney 04.</strong> Fred Moten and Stefano Harney, The University and the Undercommons, SEVEN THESES Social Text 79, Vol. 22, No. 2, Summer 2004. Copyright © 2004 by Duke University Press“<u>To the university I’ll steal, and there I’ll steal</u>,” to borrow from Pistol at the end of Henry V, as he would surely borrow from us. <u>This is the only possible relationship to the American university today.</u>This may be true of universities everywhere. It may have to be true of the university in general. But certainly, this much is true in the United States: <u>it cannot be denied that the university is a place of refuge, and it cannot be accepted that the university is a place of enlightenment</u>. In the face of these conditions <u>one can only sneak into the university and steal what one can</u>. <u>To abuse its hospitality, to spite its mission, to join its refugee colony, its gypsy encampment, to be in but not of—this is the path of the subversive intellectual in the modern university</u>. Worry about the university. This is the injunction today in the United States, one with a long history. Call for its restoration like Harold Bloom or Stanley Fish or Gerald Graff. Call for its reform like Derek Bok or Bill Readings or Cary Nelson.<u>Call out to it as it calls to you</u>. <u>But for the subversive intellectual, all of this goes on upstairs, in polite company, among the rational men</u>. After all, <u>the subversive intellectual came under false pretenses, with bad documents, out of love</u>. <u>Her labor is as necessary as it is unwelcome</u>. The university needs what she bears but cannot bear what she brings. And on top of all that, she disappears.<u>She disappears into the underground, the </u>downlow<u> lowdown maroon community of the university, into the </u>Undercommons<u> of Enlightenment, where the work gets done, where the work gets subverted, where the revolution is still black, still strong</u>. What is that work and what is its social capacity for both reproducing the university and producing fugitivity? If one were to say <u>teaching</u>, one<u>would be performing the work of the university</u>. <u>Teaching is merely a profession and an operation of what Jacques Derrida calls the<strong> </strong>onto-/auto-encyclopedic circle of the </u>Universitas. But <u>it is useful to invoke this operation to glimpse the hole in the fence where labor enters, to glimpse its hiring hall, its night quarters</u>. <u>The university needs teaching labor, despite itself, or as itself, self-identical with and thereby erased by it</u>. It is not teaching then that holds this social capacity, but something that produces the not visible other side of teaching, a thinking through the skin of teaching toward a collective orientation to the knowledge object as future project, and a commitment to what we want to call the prophetic organization. But <u>it is teaching that brings us in</u>. Before there are grants, research, conferences, books, and journals there is the experience of being taught and of teaching. Before the research post with no teaching, before the graduate students to mark the exams, before the string of sabbaticals, before the permanent reduction in teaching load, the appointment to run the Center, the consignment of pedagogy to a discipline called education, before the course designed to be a new book, teaching happened. <u>The moment of teaching for food is therefore often mistakenly taken to be a stage, as if eventually, one should not teach for food</u>. If the stage persists, there is a social pathology in the university. But <u>if the teaching is successfully passed on, the stage is surpassed, and teaching is consigned to those who are known to remain in the stage, the </u>sociopathological<u>labor of the university</u>. Kant interestingly calls such a stage “self-incurred minority.” He tries to contrast it with having the “determination and courage to use one’s intelligence without being guided by another.” “Have the courage to use your own intelligence.” <u>But what would it mean if</u> teaching or rather what we might call “<u>the beyond of teaching” is precisely what one is asked to get beyond, to stop taking sustenance</u>? <u>And what of those minorities who refuse, the tribe of moles who will not come back from beyond2 (that which is beyond “the beyond of teaching”), as if they will not be subjects, as if they want to think as objects, as minority</u>? Certainly, <u>the perfect subjects of communication, those successfully beyond teaching, will see them as waste</u>. But <u>their collective labor will always call into question who<strong> </strong>truly is taking the orders of the Enlightenment</u>. The waste lives for those moments 102 Moten/Harneybeyond2 teaching when you give away the unexpected beautiful phrase— unexpected, no one has asked, beautiful, it will never come back. Is being the biopower of the Enlightenment truly better than this? Perhaps <u>the </u>biopower<u> of the Enlightenment know this, or perhaps it is just reacting to the </u>objecthood<u> of this labor as it must</u>. But <u>even as it depends on these moles, these refugees, they will call them </u>uncollegial<u>, impractical, naive, unprofessional</u>. And one may be given one last chance to be pragmatic—why steal when one can have it all, they will ask. But <u>if one hides from this interpellation, neither agrees nor disagrees but goes with hands full into the underground of the university, into the </u>Undercommons<u>—this will be regarded as theft, as a criminal act</u>. And <u>it is at the same time, the only possible act</u>. <u>In that </u>Undercommons<u> of the university one can see that it is not a matter of teaching versus research or even the beyond of teaching versus the individualization of research. To enter this space is to inhabit the<strong> </u>ruptural<u></strong> and enraptured disclosure of the commons that fugitive enlightenment enacts, the criminal, matricidal, queer, in the cistern, on the stroll of the stolen life, the life stolen by enlightenment and stolen back, where the commons give refuge, where the refuge gives commons</u>. What the beyond2 of teaching is really about is not finishing oneself, not passing, not completing; <u>it’s about allowing subjectivity to be unlawfully overcome by others, a radical passion and passivity such that one becomes unfit for subjection, because one does not possess the kind of agency that can hold the regulatory forces of </u>subjecthood<u>, and one cannot initiate the auto-</u>interpellative<u> torque that </u>biopower<u> subjection requires and rewards. It is not so much the teaching as it is the prophecy in the organization of the act of teaching</u>.</p><p> </p>
null
null
1NC Version 2 – Undercommons
430,629
1
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,277
People sell organs out of economic desperation, but the illicit market leaves them worse off
Jaycox 12
Jaycox 12 Michael P. Jaycox, teaching fellow and Ph.D. candidate in theological ethics at Boston College, Developing World Bioethics Volume 12 Number 3 2012 pp 135–147 COERCION, AUTONOMY, AND THE PREFERENTIAL OPTION FOR THE POOR IN THE ETHICS OF ORGAN TRANSPLANTATION
Pakistani surgeon and bioethicist Farhat Moazam offers the results of a recent study He found that almost all of these organ vendors were in significant debt to wealthy landlords at the time they sold their kidneys; Although the vendors were promised by third-party brokers an average price of 160,000 rupees per kidney, the amount actually received by the vendors was an average of 103,000 rupees. As a result, a majority of them were ‘either still in debt or had accumulated new debts’ a majority of the vendors experienced long-term physical and psychological malady as a result of their nephrectomies, and a majority also expressed regret or shame for their decision because they were not freed from their debts and/or felt they had committed a morally wrong act. Moazam summarizes his findings with the conclusion that the sale of kidneys functions to reinforce the poverty of those who sell them:
almost all of these organ vendors were in significant debt to wealthy landlords at the time they sold their kidneys Although the vendors were promised by third-party brokers an average price of 160,000 rupees per kidney, the amount actually received by the vendors was an average of 103,000 rupees. As a result, a majority (17) of them were ‘either still in debt or had accumulated new debts’ a majority of the vendors experienced long-term physical and psychological malady and expressed regret the sale of kidneys functions to reinforce the poverty of those who sell them
http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1471-8847.2012.00327.x/pdf Pakistani surgeon and bioethicist Farhat Moazam offers the results of a recent study in which he interviewed thirty-two farm laborers in Pakistan, each of whom had sold a kidney within the past three years. 14 He found that almost all of these organ vendors were in significant debt to wealthy landlords at the time they sold their kidneys; the average debt of each was 130,000 rupees at the time of sale. Although the vendors were promised by third-party brokers an average price of 160,000 rupees per kidney, the amount actually received by the vendors was an average of 103,000 rupees. As a result, a majority (17) of them were ‘either still in debt or had accumulated new debts’ at the time of their interviews. 15 Moreover, a majority of the vendors experienced long-term physical and psychological malady as a result of their nephrectomies, and a majority also expressed regret or shame for their decision because they were not freed from their debts and/or felt they had committed a morally wrong act. When asked why they had made the decision, ‘the most common [Urdu] words they used were majboori (a word that arises from the root jabr, which means a state that is beyond one’s control) and ghurbat (extreme poverty).’16,Moazam summarizes his findings with the conclusion that the sale of kidneys functions to reinforce the poverty of those who sell them: In the words of the vendors, they sell a kidney...in order to fulfill what they see as obligations toward immediate and extended families in which they are inextricably embedded, and within systems of social and economic inequalities which they can neither control nor escape. They sell kidneys in hopes of paying off loans taken to cover their families’ medical expenses or to meet the responsibilities for arranging marriages and burying their dead. These are recurring expenses, and for most the debts rapidly accumulate again, even if they have been partially or completely paid back with the money from selling a kidney. 17 4 F. Moazam, R.M. Zaman & A.M. Jafarey. Conversations with Kidney Vendors in Pakistan: An Ethnographic Study.Hastings Cent Rep 2009; 39: 29–44. Due to recent legislation (18 March 2010), the sale of human organs is now illegal in Pakistan, although the social effects of this new legislation remain to be studied; see T.M. Pope. Legal Briefing: Organ Donation and Allocation. J Clin Ethics 2010; 21: 243–263: 254.
2,479
<h4>People sell organs out of economic desperation, but the illicit market leaves them worse off</h4><p><strong>Jaycox 12</strong> Michael P. Jaycox, teaching fellow and Ph.D. candidate in theological ethics at Boston College,</p><p>Developing World Bioethics Volume 12 Number 3 2012 pp 135–147 COERCION, AUTONOMY, AND THE PREFERENTIAL OPTION FOR THE POOR IN THE ETHICS OF ORGAN TRANSPLANTATION</p><p>http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1471-8847.2012.00327.x/pdf</p><p><u>Pakistani surgeon and bioethicist Farhat Moazam offers the results of a recent study </u>in which he interviewed thirty-two farm laborers in Pakistan, each of whom had sold a kidney within the past three years. 14 <u>He found that <mark>almost all of these organ vendors were in significant debt to wealthy landlords at the time they sold their kidneys</mark>;</u> the average debt of each was 130,000 rupees at the time of sale. <u><mark>Although the vendors were promised by third-party brokers an average price of 160,000 rupees per kidney, the amount actually received by the vendors was an average of 103,000 rupees. As a result, a majority </u>(17) <u>of them were ‘either still in debt or had accumulated new debts’</mark> </u>at the time of their interviews. 15 Moreover, <u><mark>a majority of the vendors experienced long-term physical and psychological malady</mark> as a result of their nephrectomies, <mark>and</mark> a majority also <mark>expressed regret</mark> or shame for their decision because they were not freed from their debts and/or felt they had committed a morally wrong act.</u> When asked why they had made the decision, ‘the most common [Urdu] words they used were majboori (a word that arises from the root jabr, which means a state that is beyond one’s control) and<u> </u>ghurbat (extreme poverty).’16,<u><strong>Moazam summarizes his findings with the conclusion that<mark> the sale of kidneys functions to reinforce the poverty of those who sell them</mark>:</strong> </u>In the words of the vendors, they sell a kidney...in order to fulfill what they see as obligations toward immediate and extended families in which they are inextricably embedded, and within systems of social and economic inequalities which they can neither control nor escape. They sell kidneys in hopes of paying off loans taken to cover their families’ medical expenses or to meet the responsibilities for arranging marriages and burying their dead. These are recurring expenses, and for most the debts rapidly accumulate again, even if they have been partially or completely paid back with the money from selling a kidney. 17 4 F. Moazam, R.M. Zaman & A.M. Jafarey. Conversations with Kidney Vendors in Pakistan: An Ethnographic Study.Hastings Cent Rep 2009; 39: 29–44. Due to recent legislation (18 March 2010), the sale of human organs is now illegal in Pakistan, although the social effects of this new legislation remain to be studied; see T.M. Pope. Legal Briefing: Organ Donation and Allocation. J Clin Ethics 2010; 21: 243–263: 254.</p>
null
null
Contention 2 is the Illegal market
430,255
14
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,278
Link magnifier to any K of PAS – biopower doesn’t stop at the management of life, it also creates the conditions of suicide
Stoneman 5
Stoneman 5 Scott, “Suicide and Biopower: Foucault, Derrida, and Deconstruction,” Fall, http://www.scribd.com/doc/230752001/774-Long-Paper-Stoneman-Foucault-Derrida-and-Suicide#scribd
Where I find the treatment of suicide too lean is in dissociating of the effects of biopower from suicidality ucault is invested in the symbolic preservation of suicide, in deliberately belying those modes of suicidality which are the regulated result of biopower Foucault is never concerned about the possibility that it is an event in the lives of the broke, broken and berated bound by those operations of biopower which constitute a subject whose life is inscribed not worth living Were he to treat the two forces (suicidal and biopolitical) contiguously, he would be forced to account for situations in which power is less troubled by than responsible for suicidal ideation
Where I find the treatment of suicide too lean is in dissociating of the effects of biopower from suicidality Foucault is never concerned about the possibility that it is an event in the lives of the broke, broken and berated bound by those operations of biopower which constitute a subject whose life is inscribed not worth living Were he to treat the two forces contiguously, he would be forced to account for situations in which power is less troubled by than responsible for suicidal ideation
Where precisely in Foucault I find the treatment of suicide too lean is in his (no doubt strategic) dissociating of the effects of biopower from suicidality, or the contemplation and/or completion of suicide. Like Maurice Blanchot, Foucault is invested in the symbolic preservation of suicide, in deliberately belying those modes of suicidality which are the regulated result of biopower. Where he is concerned with suicide Foucault is never concerned about suicide, about the possibility that it is an event in the lives of the broke, broken and berated bound by those operations of biopower which constitute a subject whose life is inscribed not worth living, whose subjectivity consists precisely in exclusion and execration. Were he to treat the two forces (suicidal and biopolitical) contiguously, he would be forced to account for situations in which power is less troubled by than responsible for suicidal ideation and commitment—which he does not precisely do. I will argue later that Blanchot, while he shares much of Foucault’s heartened attitude towards suicide, in fact provides the dialectical thinking about the subject that the discourse on what I have elected to call autodestruction in Foucault ostensibly lacks. What Blanchot’s capacious consideration of the question makes most apparent, though, is the extent to which Foucault’s calculated deferral of a dialectical consideration of suicide is precisely that, a calculation. But we must then ask, what is the object of this rhetorical and political calculation, and what are its rhetorical and political consequences?
1,587
<h4>Link magnifier to any K of PAS – biopower doesn’t stop at the management of life, it also creates the conditions of suicide</h4><p><strong>Stoneman 5</strong> Scott, “Suicide and Biopower: Foucault, Derrida, and Deconstruction,” Fall, http://www.scribd.com/doc/230752001/774-Long-Paper-Stoneman-Foucault-Derrida-and-Suicide#scribd</p><p><u><mark>Where</u></mark> precisely in Foucault <u><mark>I find the treatment of suicide too lean is in</mark> </u>his (no doubt strategic) <u><mark>dissociating of the effects of biopower from suicidality</u></mark>, or the contemplation and/or completion of suicide. Like Maurice Blanchot, Fo<u>ucault is invested in the symbolic preservation of suicide, in deliberately belying those modes of suicidality which are the regulated result of biopower</u>. Where he is concerned with suicide <u><mark>Foucault is never concerned about</u></mark> suicide, about <u><mark>the possibility that it is an event in the lives of the broke, broken and berated bound by those operations of biopower which constitute a subject whose life is inscribed not worth living</u></mark>, whose subjectivity consists precisely in exclusion and execration. <u><mark>Were he to treat the two forces</mark> (suicidal and biopolitical) <mark>contiguously, he would be forced to account for situations in which power is less troubled by than responsible for suicidal ideation</u></mark> and commitment—which he does not precisely do. I will argue later that Blanchot, while he shares much of Foucault’s heartened attitude towards suicide, in fact provides the dialectical thinking about the subject that the discourse on what I have elected to call autodestruction in Foucault ostensibly lacks. What Blanchot’s capacious consideration of the question makes most apparent, though, is the extent to which Foucault’s calculated deferral of a dialectical consideration of suicide is precisely that, a calculation. But we must then ask, what is the object of this rhetorical and political calculation, and what are its rhetorical and political consequences? </p>
null
null
Case
430,354
8
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,279
Sales do not have to be free market – can have a third party
Knox 8
Knox 8 Richard Knox NPR May 21, 2008 Should We Legalize the Market for Human Organs?
Satel at A E I says: we need to be able to compensate people who are willing to give a kidney ... We are not talking about a classic commercial free-for-all, We're talking about a third-party payer predictble limits Almost all analysts who favor compensation for organ donation envision a state-sponsored and tightly regulated monopsony structure so financial incentives would be used solely to obtain organs
Satel at A E I says we need to compensate people who are willing to give a kidney We're talking about a third-party payer Almost all analysts who compensation for organ donation envision a state-sponsored monopsony
http://www.npr.org/2008/05/21/90632108/should-we-legalize-the-market-for-human-organs Sally Satel, a psychiatrist and resident scholar at the American Enterprise Institute who received a kidney from a friend in 2006, says: "Despite decades and decades of public education about the virtues of organ donation, the waiting list just gets longer, and the time to transplantation just gets longer. ... It's past time to face the fact that altruism is just not enough. Many people need more of an incentive to give. And that's why we need to be able to compensate people who are willing to give a kidney to a stranger, to save a life. ... We are not talking about a classic commercial free-for-all, or a free market, or an eBay system. We're talking about a third-party payer. For example, today you could decide to give a kidney. You'd be called a Good Samaritan donor. ... The only difference in a model that I'm thinking about is where you go and give your organ, and your retirement account is wired $40,000, end of story." They overlimit—the resolution only says nearly all sales—they force nearly everyone to buy it Also kill predictble limits—preventing governmental purchasing limits out core areas of the aff—it’s central to organ lit Beard et al 13 T. Randolph "Randy" Beard, Professor of Economics at Auburn University.; Rigmar Osterkamp, Fellow at the School for Political Studies at University of Munich.; And David L. Kaserman, Torchmark Professor of Economics at Auburn University.2013 The Global Organ Shortage: Economic Causes, Human Consequences, Policy Responses 11.Almost all analysts who favor compensation for organ donation envision a state-sponsored and tightly regulated monopsony structure so financial incentives would be used solely to obtain organs, while organ distribution among potential recipients would continue to be based on medical and ethical criteria and would be subject to public oversight. Substantially and functional limits checks Reasonability – the aff has to have a reasonable way to know if they’re topical
2,056
<h4>Sales do not have to be free market – can have a third party</h4><p><strong>Knox 8</strong> Richard Knox NPR May 21, 2008 Should We Legalize the Market for Human Organs?</p><p>http://www.npr.org/2008/05/21/90632108/should-we-legalize-the-market-for-human-organs</p><p>Sally <u><mark>Satel</u></mark>, a psychiatrist and resident scholar<u> <mark>at</mark> </u>the <u><mark>A</u></mark>merican<u> <mark>E</u></mark>nterprise<u> <mark>I</u></mark>nstitute who received a kidney from a friend in 2006, <u><mark>says</mark>:</u> "Despite decades and decades of public education about the virtues of organ donation, the waiting list just gets longer, and the time to transplantation just gets longer. ... It's past time to face the fact that altruism is just not enough. Many people need more of an incentive to give. And that's why<u> <mark>we need to</mark> be able to <mark>compensate people who are willing to give a kidney</mark> </u>to a stranger, to save a life. <u>... We are not talking about a classic commercial free-for-all, </u>or a free market, or an eBay system.<u> <mark>We're talking about a third-party payer</u><strong></mark>. For example, today you could decide to give a kidney. You'd be called a Good Samaritan donor. ... The only difference in a model that I'm thinking about is where you go and give your organ, and your retirement account is wired $40,000, end of story."</p><p>They overlimit—the resolution only says nearly all sales—they force nearly everyone to buy it</p><p>Also kill <u>predictble limits</u>—preventing governmental purchasing limits out core areas of the aff—it’s central to organ lit </p><p>Beard et al 13</strong> T. Randolph "Randy" Beard, Professor of Economics at Auburn University.; Rigmar Osterkamp, Fellow at the School for Political Studies at University of Munich.; And David L. Kaserman, Torchmark Professor of Economics at Auburn University.2013 The Global Organ Shortage: Economic Causes, Human Consequences, Policy Responses</p><p>11.<u><mark>Almost all analysts who</mark> favor <mark>compensation for organ donation envision a state-sponsored</mark> and tightly regulated <mark>monopsony</mark> structure so financial incentives would be used solely to obtain organs</u><strong>, while organ distribution among potential recipients would continue to be based on medical and ethical criteria and would be subject to public oversight.</p><p></strong>Substantially and functional limits checks </p><p>Reasonability – the aff has to have a reasonable way to know if they’re topical</p>
2AC
Contention 4 is risk calculus
2ac nearly all
430,631
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,280
Brooks, Wohlforth, and Ikenberry’s analysis doesn’t even consider the will of non-Americans. Their scholarship is just a tool of imperialism.
Roger 13 Comment on “Pull Back or Lean Forward?” The Monkey Cage; January 4, 2013; http://themonkeycage.org/blog/2013/01/03/pull-back-or-lean-forward/
Roger 13 Comment on “Pull Back or Lean Forward?” The Monkey Cage; January 4, 2013; http://themonkeycage.org/blog/2013/01/03/pull-back-or-lean-forward/
brooks et al. write as if the rest of the world doesn’t actually exist or matter except as a stage for US marauding. their article a terrible case of american bubble thought it doesn’t even cross their minds to ask what other people around the world actually think of ‘leaning forward they write as self-centered imperialists who assume the god given right to do what they want this is why American IR is laughed at around the world it just serves US primacy and thus is hardly a science of anything
brooks et al. write as if the rest of the world doesn’t exist their article a case of american bubble thought it doesn’t cross their minds what people around the world think of ‘leaning forward’ they write as self-centered imperialists it just serves US primacy and is hardly science
brooks et al. write as if the rest of the world doesn’t actually exist or matter except as a stage for US marauding. their article a terrible case of american centric bubble thought. seriously, it doesn’t even cross their minds to ask what other people around the world actually think of ‘leaning forward’. have they not learned a single thing from postcolonial theory? they write as self-centered imperialists, who assume the god given right to do what they want. this is why American IR is kind of laughed at around the world. it just serves US primacy and thus is hardly a science of anything…
596
<h4><strong>Brooks, Wohlforth, and Ikenberry’s analysis doesn’t even consider the will of non-Americans. Their scholarship is just a tool of imperialism.</h4><p>Roger 13 Comment on “Pull Back or Lean Forward?” The Monkey Cage; January 4, 2013; http://themonkeycage.org/blog/2013/01/03/pull-back-or-lean-forward/</p><p><u></strong><mark>brooks et al. write as if the rest of the world doesn’t</mark> actually <mark>exist</mark> or matter except as a stage for US marauding. <mark>their article a</mark> terrible <mark>case of american</u></mark> centric <u><strong><mark>bubble thought</u></strong></mark>. seriously, <u><strong><mark>it doesn’t</mark> even <mark>cross their minds</mark> to ask <mark>what</mark> other <mark>people around the world</mark> actually <mark>think of ‘leaning</mark> <mark>forward</u></strong>’</mark>. have they not learned a single thing from postcolonial theory? <u><strong><mark>they write as self-centered imperialists</u></strong></mark>, <u>who assume the god given right to do what they want</u>. <u><strong>this is why American IR is</u></strong> kind of <u><strong>laughed at around the world</u></strong>. <u><mark>it just serves US primacy and</mark> thus <mark>is hardly</mark> a <mark>science</mark> of anything</u><strong>…</p></strong>
WTO
Heg/Trade
AT: Inevitable
430,632
1
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,281
Comprehensive arg – they medicalize suicide on three registers – the act, the practice, and the social ethos of death
Salem 99
Salem 99 Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full
Medicalizing suicide encompasses three different facets the medicalization of an act, of a practice, and above all of the social ethos of death as long as the physician is in charge of assisting the patient either by his or her physical presence or by supplying the medical means to perform the act physician-assisted suicide entails the medicalization of the act of suicide Even without the doctor's physical presence in the last scene, as long as physician-assisted suicide presupposes medical assistance it cannot be conceived as immersed in the realm of self-determination Unless doctors are reduced strictly to being instruments to fulfill their patients’ desires, physician-assisted suicide enacts what must be seen as a mutual decision if legalized, physician-assisted suicide as a legitimate practice would become the prerogative of physicians monopoly leads to the more general question of why aid in dying should be provided only by a medical practitioner The most obvious answer is that physicians—and only physicians—have the necessary technical skills to ensure a “rapid” and “painless” death But Assisted suicide does not even require medical skill…. If freeing up patients truly is the goal, then assisted suicide's advocates disserve patients when they do not advocate ending the physician's exclusive power to prescribe medication advocates of patients’ rights end up empowering doctors more than patients either medicine is moving beyond its proper role, or the scope of medical competence has already been extended beyond appropriate boundaries idealization and the willingness to delegate to physicians the exclusive right to assist suicide bespeaks the social and symbolic power already conferred on medicine and medical professionals in our societies it is not the need for technical expertise that impels us to physician-assisted suicide Rather our culture takes for granted that assisted suicide should fall under the control and supervision of medicine physician-assisted suicide necessarily involves medicalizing the moral questions surrounding suicide it is a medical evaluation of the fairness and legitimacy of a person's desire or choice to end his or her life even the most radical advocates of physician-assisted suicide recognize the need to establish protocols and guidelines to prevent abuses protect the vulnerable establishing medical guidelines also introduces tensions into the value of autonomy in several ways requisites for physician-assisted suicide are still being debated There is, however, agreement about the moral attributes that the patien must evince the decision must be “informed,” “rational voluntary is requirement assumes that dispositions emanating from the patient herself or himself may threaten “pure choice Medical authority, that is, is assumed to have the proper ability to unveil the “real truth” behind the request to die The insult to autonomy is not exerted through repression, as was the criminalization of suicide it is exercised through normalization” of suicide, the subordination to medical scrutiny of this event and the person making the request The “patient” is subjected to observation, examination, and inquiry to confirm the “rationality” and “voluntariness” of his or her request. Thus medicalizing (assisted) suicide jeopardizes autonomy not only when the patient's request is denied Requiring that the patient submit to medical surveillance is, in itself, an outrage to autonomy It could reasonably be argued that guidelines for physician-assisted suicide do not injure the patient's self-determination since the request emanates from a patient who supposedly knows the rules of the game in advance the argument would continue, if one does not wish to submit to those rules, “do it yourself” remains a way out. But this seems to admit that ultimately assisted suicide has to do with something beyond strict self-determination physician-assisted suicide ends up reinforcing a power external to the self. It reinforces medical power at the expense of the individual in a very sensitive realm: one's decision to die
Medicalizing suicide encompasses three facets the medicalization of an act, of a practice, and above all of the social ethos of death as long as the physician is in charge physician-assisted suicide entails the medicalization of the act of suicide as physician-assisted suicide presupposes medical assistance it cannot be conceived as immersed in the realm of self-determination Assisted suicide does not even require medical skill…. If freeing up patients truly is the goal, then assisted suicide's advocates disserve patients when they do not advocate ending the physician's exclusive power to prescribe medication advocates of patients’ rights end up empowering doctors more than patients idealization and the willingness to delegate to physicians the exclusive right to assist suicide bespeaks the social and symbolic power already conferred on medicine and medical professionals in our societies. even the most radical advocates of physician-assisted suicide recognize the need to establish protocols and guidelines to prevent abuses Medical authority, that is, is assumed to have the proper ability to unveil the “real truth” behind the request to die The insult to autonomy is not exerted through repression it is exercised through normalization” of suicide, the subordination to medical scrutiny of this event and the person making the request medicalizing (assisted) suicide jeopardizes autonomy not only when the patient's request is denied physician-assisted suicide ends up reinforcing a power external to the self. It reinforces medical power at the expense of the individual in a very sensitive realm: one's decision to die
Medicalizing suicide encompasses three different (though interrelated) facets: the medicalization of an act, of a practice, and above all of the social ethos of death and suicide. Medicalizing the act of suicide In the typical physician-assisted suicide scenario, the patient is responsible both for requesting aid in dying and for performing the final deed, and she or he construes the act basically as suicide. Yet as long as the physician is in charge of assisting the patient—either by his or her physical presence or by supplying the medical means to perform the act—physician-assisted suicide entails the medicalization of the act of suicide. Ideally, for the physician to assist a patient's suicide the physician must be physically present—as attested in Timothy Quill's regrets for “abandoning” Diane, leaving her to take the prescribed lethal medication alone.15 Thus what is intriguing in physician-assisted suicide is not that ventilators, tubes, CPR, and so on are supplanted by “lethal drugs,” but that even in this context the physician and medicine are overwhelmingly present in the setting of death. Even without the doctor's physical presence in the last scene, as long as physician-assisted suicide presupposes medical assistance it cannot be conceived as immersed in the realm of self-determination. Unless doctors are reduced strictly to being instruments to fulfill their patients’ desires, physician-assisted suicide enacts what must be seen as a mutual decision. But what kind of questions are at stake in this joint decision? Proponents of assisted suicide suggest that patient and physician discuss the patient's medical condition and explore alternatives for alleviating pain and suffering. If it comes to it, the physician should provide a prescription for a lethal drug that leads to a “rapid” and “painless” death.16 That is, the decision to die by suicide is treated precisely as if it were a set of clinical problems to be solved medically—the “private,” “intimate,” “self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event. Medicalizing suicide as professional practice Medicalizing suicide also points to the fact that if legalized, physician-assisted suicide as a legitimate practice would become the prerogative of physicians. Indeed, Jack Kevorkian has seen the exclusive right as the foundation for a new medical subspeciality of “obitiatry.”17 This monopoly leads to the more general question of why aid in dying should be provided only by a medical practitioner. Why, that is, should assistance in suicide be understood as requiring medical authority rather than, for instance, a community of family or friends? The most obvious answer is that physicians—and only physicians—have the necessary technical skills to ensure a “rapid” and “painless” death. But as some critics have noted, “Assisted suicide does not even require medical skill…. If freeing up patients truly is the goal, then assisted suicide's advocates disserve patients when they do not advocate ending the physician's exclusive power to prescribe medication. Ironically, the advocates of patients’ rights end up empowering doctors more than they do patients.”18 Yet even those who maintain that technical knowledge is imperative do not confine their justification of physician-assisted suicide to this reason. Placing suicide under the stewardship of medicine is further defended as a way of “enhancing public accountability of the practice” and “protecting against abuse.”19 From the patient's perspective, the request for aid in dying may mean a “desire for companionship in pursuing a difficult course of action, a wish for confirmation of a decision about which the patient is unsure or simply a cry for help” (pp. 88–89, note 42). Moreover, since suicide is still stigmatized, “seeking a physician's assistance may be a way of trying to remove that stigma.”20 But inasmuch as cultural preconceptions and loneliness (whatever its source) are far from being exclusively medical issues, we must ask why we expect doctors to respond to them. Two possible answers come to mind: either medicine is moving beyond its proper role, or the scope of medical competence has already been extended beyond appropriate boundaries. It seems reasonable to conclude that ceding monopoly of assistance in suicide to doctors is anchored in an inflation of the physician's role, as well as in the extreme idealization of physicians’ character and the relationships they establish with patients. The bond physicians establish with patients is supposedly effective, collaborative, and committed.21 Both this idealization and the willingness to delegate to physicians the exclusive right to assist suicide bespeaks the social and symbolic power already conferred on medicine and medical professionals in our societies. In other words, it is not (or not only) the need for technical expertise that impels us to physician-assisted suicide. Rather, our culture, so impregnated by medicalization, takes for granted that assisted suicide should fall under the control and supervision of medicine. Medicalizing the morality of suicide As a legitimate domain of professional practice, then, physician-assisted suicide necessarily involves medicalizing the moral questions surrounding suicide. Physician-assisted suicide presupposes, and ultimately is, a medical judgment about death or suicide; it is a medical evaluation of the fairness and legitimacy of a person's (not simply a patient's) desire or choice to end his or her life. With some few exceptions, even the most radical advocates of physician-assisted suicide recognize the need to establish protocols and guidelines to prevent abuses, protect the vulnerable, guarantee public accountability, and even to assure the autonomous character of the patient's choice. Surely these aims are respectable and the setting up of criteria just and reasonable. Yet establishing medical guidelines also introduces tensions into the value of autonomy in several ways. The requisites for physician-assisted suicide (must the patient be terminally ill? which medical specialists are best qualified as consultants?) are still being debated. There is, however, agreement about the moral attributes that the patient and his or her request must evince: the decision to die must be “informed,” “rational,” “stable,” and “fully free” or “voluntary.”22 And there is broad agreement that to ensure that these conditions are fulfilled the patient must submit to screening by a team of doctors (the treating physician, a consulting physician, and a psychiatrist) who would evaluate the request for aid in dying. This requirement assumes that besides undue external influences, some impulses or dispositions emanating from the patient herself or himself—such as depression or guilt—may threaten “pure choice.” “Voluntariness” in this sense must be safeguarded from undue influence stemming not only from outside, but also from within. Ultimately, this is to assume that the inner world may be obscure to the individual, that she or he may be half blind to her or his own choice, desire, or personal truth. The presumption that the inner world is or may be opaque to the individual suggests a second underlying presupposition: someone other than the person requesting aid in dying has greater expertise in judging the appropriateness of that request. Medical authority, that is, is assumed to have the proper ability to unveil the “real truth” behind the request to die. The patient's treating physician, along with psychiatric and/or palliative care consultants, is charged to distinguish authentic from distorted choices; that is, to discern whether the request is pertinent or pathological (and if so, whether it is “curable” by medical means). Both these premises obviously collide with the principles of autonomy and self-determination. Both displace the final decision concerning suicide from the patient to the physician's judgment that the request is appropriate and free from “undue influence.” The insult to autonomy is not exerted through repression, as was the criminalization of suicide. Rather, it is exercised through what Foucault would call the “normalization” of suicide, the subordination to medical scrutiny of this event and the person making the request.23 The “patient” is subjected to observation, examination, and inquiry to confirm the “rationality” and “voluntariness” of his or her request. Thus medicalizing (assisted) suicide jeopardizes autonomy not only when the patient's request is denied for one reason or another. Requiring that the patient submit to medical surveillance is, in itself, an outrage to autonomy as this value is classically defined.24 To illustrate how complex is the apparatus through which suicide is normalized, consider guidelines suggested by Frank Miller, Howard Brody, and Timothy Quill, for example. To ensure public accountability for physician-assisted suicide, to guarantee that the procedure is used only as a “last resort,” and to assure that the patient's decision is genuinely voluntary, the authors suggest palliative care consultants and regional palliative care committees as the core of a whole supervising system.25 Thus the primary physician would be prohibited from providing lethal drugs without prior consultation with a palliative care expert who, based on “examination of medical records and interviews with the treating physician, the patient and the interested members of the patient's family” (p. 121), would assess the authenticity of the request to die. Patients and their physicians would have the right to appeal the consultant's denial of requests for assisted suicide to regional palliative care committees. The bureaucratization of suicide built into such proposals entails serious constraints on patients’ self-determination. Subjecting individuals who request aid in dying to this kind of scrutiny further affronts their dignity in putting all such requests under suspicion. In the name of protecting individuals from irreversible self-harm all are in principle treated as moral patients rather than moral agents and are presumed to be mentally incompetent. The capacity to make autonomous decisions, which is presumed in all other cases unless demonstrated otherwise, is stood on its head in physician-assisted suicide. Patients must prove their decisionmaking capacity from the outset. One of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dying. Subjecting the individual to medical norms in this way also introduces a tension for one of the central questions of liberal philosophers. If, as the liberal argument claims, the morality or immorality of decisions at the end of life rests on the competent patient's wishes rather than on a distinction between killing and allowing to die,26 protocols that may ultimately deny a patient's request for assistance in dying assert, in effect, that moral authority resides outside the patient's choice. And if medicine may, morally, reject patients’ autonomous requests for aid, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the value of patient autonomy becomes more rhetorical than real. Admittedly, even liberal theorists emphasize that there are limits to autonomy, and that like other important rights, the right to physician-assisted suicide is not absolute and can properly be restricted under certain circumstances. Indeed, Ronald Dworkin and others argue precisely that because autonomy must be protected and preserved physician-assisted suicide must be regulated. Under certain conditions the state has the power to override individual rights to protect patients from undue pressures, even internal ones. The tension remains, however. In the context of assisted suicide, how is it possible to reconcile the assertion that paternalistic influences are unacceptable with the concept that in some situations the state (or the medical establishment) may deny assistance in suicide in the name of “what it reasonably judges to be the best interest of the potential suicide”?27 Alexander Capron has argued that decisions on behalf of others should rest on a best interest standard of what the “‘average reasonable person’ would do under the given circumstances.”28 Doesn't this permit the tyranny of the majority over the individual? Doesn't this menace the right, so praised by liberal theorists, to exercise our singularities in a radical way? As Yale Kamisar has asked, “[I]f self-determination and autonomy is the major force driving the right to assisted suicide, why should a competent person's firm conclusion that life has become unendurable for her have to be ‘objectively reasonable’? Why should not a competent person's own evaluation of her situation suffice?”29 To phrase this in terms of the argument I make here, is it ever possible to reconcile medicalizing suicide with autonomy? It could reasonably be argued that guidelines for physician-assisted suicide do not injure the patient's self-determination since the request emanates from a patient who supposedly knows the rules of the game in advance. And, the argument would continue, if one does not wish to submit to those rules, “do it yourself” remains a way out. But this seems to admit that ultimately assisted suicide has to do with something beyond strict self-determination, that autonomy is not the primary moral foundation, or at least that if autonomy is to be exercised it demands constant external oversight. In sum, although advocated in the name of self-sovereignty, physician-assisted suicide ends up reinforcing a power external to the self. It reinforces medical power at the expense of the individual in a very sensitive realm: one's decision to die. There are implications for society in this as well.
13,869
<h4>Comprehensive arg – they medicalize suicide on three registers – the act, the practice, and the social ethos of death</h4><p><strong>Salem 99</strong> Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full</p><p><u><mark>Medicalizing suicide encompasses three</mark> different</u> (though interrelated) <u><mark>facets</u></mark>: <u><mark>the medicalization of an act, of a practice, and above all of the social ethos of death</u></mark> and suicide.</p><p>Medicalizing the act of suicide</p><p>In the typical physician-assisted suicide scenario, the patient is responsible both for requesting aid in dying and for performing the final deed, and she or he construes the act basically as suicide. Yet <u><mark>as long as the physician is in charge</mark> of assisting the patient</u>—<u>either by his or her physical presence or by supplying the medical means to perform the act</u>—<u><mark>physician-assisted suicide entails the medicalization of the act of suicide</u></mark>.</p><p>Ideally, for the physician to assist a patient's suicide the physician must be physically present—as attested in Timothy Quill's regrets for “abandoning” Diane, leaving her to take the prescribed lethal medication alone.15 Thus what is intriguing in physician-assisted suicide is not that ventilators, tubes, CPR, and so on are supplanted by “lethal drugs,” but that even in this context the physician and medicine are overwhelmingly present in the setting of death.</p><p><u>Even without the doctor's physical presence in the last scene, as long <mark>as physician-assisted suicide presupposes medical assistance it cannot be conceived as immersed in the realm of self-determination</u></mark>. <u>Unless doctors are reduced strictly to being instruments to fulfill their patients’ desires, physician-assisted suicide enacts what must be seen as a mutual decision</u>. But what kind of questions are at stake in this joint decision? Proponents of assisted suicide suggest that patient and physician discuss the patient's medical condition and explore alternatives for alleviating pain and suffering. If it comes to it, the physician should provide a prescription for a lethal drug that leads to a “rapid” and “painless” death.16 That is, the decision to die by suicide is treated precisely as if it were a set of clinical problems to be solved medically—the “private,” “intimate,” “self-determining” decision to commit suicide is translated into a clinical event.</p><p>Medicalizing suicide as professional practice</p><p>Medicalizing suicide also points to the fact that <u>if legalized, physician-assisted suicide as a legitimate practice would become the prerogative of physicians</u>. Indeed, Jack Kevorkian has seen the exclusive right as the foundation for a new medical subspeciality of “obitiatry.”17</p><p>This <u>monopoly leads to the more general question of why aid in dying should be provided only by a medical practitioner</u>. Why, that is, should assistance in suicide be understood as requiring medical authority rather than, for instance, a community of family or friends? <u>The most obvious answer is that physicians—and only physicians—have the necessary technical skills to ensure a “rapid” and “painless” death</u>. <u>But</u> as some critics have noted, “<u><mark>Assisted suicide does not even require medical skill…. If freeing up patients truly is the goal, then assisted suicide's advocates disserve patients when they do not advocate ending the physician's exclusive power to prescribe medication</u></mark>. Ironically, the <u><mark>advocates of patients’ rights end up empowering doctors more</u> <u>than</u></mark> they do <u><mark>patients</u></mark>.”18</p><p>Yet even those who maintain that technical knowledge is imperative do not confine their justification of physician-assisted suicide to this reason. Placing suicide under the stewardship of medicine is further defended as a way of “enhancing public accountability of the practice” and “protecting against abuse.”19 From the patient's perspective, the request for aid in dying may mean a “desire for companionship in pursuing a difficult course of action, a wish for confirmation of a decision about which the patient is unsure or simply a cry for help” (pp. 88–89, note 42). Moreover, since suicide is still stigmatized, “seeking a physician's assistance may be a way of trying to remove that stigma.”20 But inasmuch as cultural preconceptions and loneliness (whatever its source) are far from being exclusively medical issues, we must ask why we expect doctors to respond to them. Two possible answers come to mind: <u>either medicine is moving beyond its proper role, or the scope of medical competence has already been extended beyond appropriate boundaries</u>.</p><p>It seems reasonable to conclude that ceding monopoly of assistance in suicide to doctors is anchored in an inflation of the physician's role, as well as in the extreme idealization of physicians’ character and the relationships they establish with patients. The bond physicians establish with patients is supposedly effective, collaborative, and committed.21 Both this <u><mark>idealization and the willingness to delegate to physicians the exclusive right to assist suicide bespeaks the social and symbolic power already conferred on medicine and medical professionals in our societies</u>.</mark> In other words, <u>it is not</u> (or not only) <u>the need for technical expertise that impels us to physician-assisted suicide</u>. <u>Rather</u>, <u>our culture</u>, so impregnated by medicalization, <u>takes for granted that assisted suicide should fall under the control and supervision of medicine</u>.</p><p>Medicalizing the morality of suicide</p><p>As a legitimate domain of professional practice, then, <u>physician-assisted suicide necessarily involves medicalizing the moral questions surrounding suicide</u>. Physician-assisted suicide presupposes, and ultimately is, a medical judgment about death or suicide; <u>it is a medical evaluation of the fairness and legitimacy of a person's </u>(not simply a patient's) <u>desire or choice to end his or her life</u>.</p><p>With some few exceptions, <u><mark>even the most radical advocates of physician-assisted suicide recognize the need to establish protocols and guidelines to prevent abuses</u></mark>, <u>protect the vulnerable</u>, guarantee public accountability, and even to assure the autonomous character of the patient's choice. Surely these aims are respectable and the setting up of criteria just and reasonable. Yet <u>establishing medical guidelines also introduces tensions into the value of autonomy in several ways</u>.</p><p>The <u>requisites for physician-assisted suicide</u> (must the patient be terminally ill? which medical specialists are best qualified as consultants?) <u>are still being debated</u>. <u>There is, however, agreement about the moral attributes that the patien</u>t and his or her request <u>must evince</u>: <u>the decision</u> to die <u>must be “informed,” “rational</u>,” “stable,” and “fully free” or “<u>voluntary</u>.”22 And there is broad agreement that to ensure that these conditions are fulfilled the patient must submit to screening by a team of doctors (the treating physician, a consulting physician, and a psychiatrist) who would evaluate the request for aid in dying.</p><p>Th<u>is requirement assumes that </u>besides undue external influences, some impulses or <u>dispositions emanating from the patient herself or himself</u>—such as depression or guilt—<u>may threaten “pure choice</u>.” “Voluntariness” in this sense must be safeguarded from undue influence stemming not only from outside, but also from within. Ultimately, this is to assume that the inner world may be obscure to the individual, that she or he may be half blind to her or his own choice, desire, or personal truth.</p><p>The presumption that the inner world is or may be opaque to the individual suggests a second underlying presupposition: someone other than the person requesting aid in dying has greater expertise in judging the appropriateness of that request. <u><mark>Medical authority, that is, is assumed to have the proper ability to unveil the “real truth” behind the request to die</u></mark>. The patient's treating physician, along with psychiatric and/or palliative care consultants, is charged to distinguish authentic from distorted choices; that is, to discern whether the request is pertinent or pathological (and if so, whether it is “curable” by medical means).</p><p>Both these premises obviously collide with the principles of autonomy and self-determination. Both displace the final decision concerning suicide from the patient to the physician's judgment that the request is appropriate and free from “undue influence.”</p><p><u><mark>The insult to autonomy is not exerted through repression</mark>, as was the criminalization of suicide</u>. Rather, <u><mark>it is exercised through</u></mark> what Foucault would call the “<u><mark>normalization” of suicide, the subordination to medical scrutiny of this event and the person making the request</u></mark>.23 <u>The “patient” is subjected to observation, examination, and inquiry to confirm the “rationality” and “voluntariness” of his or her request. Thus <mark>medicalizing</u> <u>(assisted) suicide jeopardizes autonomy not only when the patient's request is denied</u></mark> for one reason or another. <u>Requiring that the patient submit to medical surveillance is, in itself, an outrage to autonomy</u> as this value is classically defined.24</p><p>To illustrate how complex is the apparatus through which suicide is normalized, consider guidelines suggested by Frank Miller, Howard Brody, and Timothy Quill, for example. To ensure public accountability for physician-assisted suicide, to guarantee that the procedure is used only as a “last resort,” and to assure that the patient's decision is genuinely voluntary, the authors suggest palliative care consultants and regional palliative care committees as the core of a whole supervising system.25 Thus the primary physician would be prohibited from providing lethal drugs without prior consultation with a palliative care expert who, based on “examination of medical records and interviews with the treating physician, the patient and the interested members of the patient's family” (p. 121), would assess the authenticity of the request to die. Patients and their physicians would have the right to appeal the consultant's denial of requests for assisted suicide to regional palliative care committees. The bureaucratization of suicide built into such proposals entails serious constraints on patients’ self-determination.</p><p>Subjecting individuals who request aid in dying to this kind of scrutiny further affronts their dignity in putting all such requests under suspicion. In the name of protecting individuals from irreversible self-harm all are in principle treated as moral patients rather than moral agents and are presumed to be mentally incompetent. The capacity to make autonomous decisions, which is presumed in all other cases unless demonstrated otherwise, is stood on its head in physician-assisted suicide. Patients must prove their decisionmaking capacity from the outset.</p><p>One of the most dramatic aspects of medicine's extended power over contemporary sensibilities has been precisely medicine's ability to mold our conceptions about dying.</p><p>Subjecting the individual to medical norms in this way also introduces a tension for one of the central questions of liberal philosophers. If, as the liberal argument claims, the morality or immorality of decisions at the end of life rests on the competent patient's wishes rather than on a distinction between killing and allowing to die,26 protocols that may ultimately deny a patient's request for assistance in dying assert, in effect, that moral authority resides outside the patient's choice. And if medicine may, morally, reject patients’ autonomous requests for aid, in the context of physician-assisted suicide the value of patient autonomy becomes more rhetorical than real.</p><p>Admittedly, even liberal theorists emphasize that there are limits to autonomy, and that like other important rights, the right to physician-assisted suicide is not absolute and can properly be restricted under certain circumstances. Indeed, Ronald Dworkin and others argue precisely that because autonomy must be protected and preserved physician-assisted suicide must be regulated. Under certain conditions the state has the power to override individual rights to protect patients from undue pressures, even internal ones.</p><p>The tension remains, however. In the context of assisted suicide, how is it possible to reconcile the assertion that paternalistic influences are unacceptable with the concept that in some situations the state (or the medical establishment) may deny assistance in suicide in the name of “what it reasonably judges to be the best interest of the potential suicide”?27 Alexander Capron has argued that decisions on behalf of others should rest on a best interest standard of what the “‘average reasonable person’ would do under the given circumstances.”28 Doesn't this permit the tyranny of the majority over the individual? Doesn't this menace the right, so praised by liberal theorists, to exercise our singularities in a radical way? As Yale Kamisar has asked, “[I]f self-determination and autonomy is the major force driving the right to assisted suicide, why should a competent person's firm conclusion that life has become unendurable for her have to be ‘objectively reasonable’? Why should not a competent person's own evaluation of her situation suffice?”29 To phrase this in terms of the argument I make here, is it ever possible to reconcile medicalizing suicide with autonomy?</p><p><u>It could reasonably be argued that guidelines for physician-assisted suicide do not injure the patient's self-determination since the request emanates from a patient who supposedly knows the rules of the game in advance</u>. And, <u>the argument would continue, if one does not wish to submit to those rules, “do it yourself” remains a way out. But this seems to admit that ultimately assisted suicide has to do with something beyond strict self-determination</u>, that autonomy is not the primary moral foundation, or at least that if autonomy is to be exercised it demands constant external oversight.</p><p>In sum, although advocated in the name of self-sovereignty, <u><mark>physician-assisted suicide ends up reinforcing a power external to the self. It reinforces medical power at the expense of the individual in a very sensitive realm: one's decision to die</u></mark>.</p><p>There are implications for society in this as well.</p>
null
Case
2NC Link Debate
429,689
14
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,282
Our alternative is to demilitarize the public sphere, bottom up rejection of security politics allows us to move beyond an unsustainable system that leads to inevitable threat escalation
null
Lal, 2007
national security is an antonym for human security the state should not be the referent object of security: “states are unreliable as primary referents because while some are in the business of security some are not; even those which are producers of security represent the means and not the ends; and states are too diverse in their character to serve as the basis for a comprehensive theory of security.” the national security state is merely an elite tool, which causes human insecurity at home and abroad. The state treats security as a problem that comes from the outside, rather than as a problem that can arise from domestic issues. The end result of state-centric security is that humans are alienated from discussions about their own security and welfare. “economic collapse, political oppression, scarcity, overpopulation, ethnic rivalry, the destruction of nature, terrorism, crime and disease provide more serious threats to the well-being of individuals and the interest of nations.” Thus, to millions of people, it is not the existence of the Other across the border that poses a security problem, but their own state that is a threat to security. put theory into practice Critical theory does not offer simple one-shot solutions to the problems created by the neo-realist state and elitist conception of security. To give simple answers would be a performative contradiction, especially after criticizing realism for being intellectually rigid for believing in objective truth. there are no alternatives; just alternative modes of understanding. However, using the poststructuralist analysis that discourse is power, we can move towards deconstructing the power of the state and elites to securitize using their own tool: discourse. we are colonized through discursive practices and subjected to the reality that the state wants us to see. However, definitions belong to the definer, and it is high time that we questioned and defined our own reality. citizen action is critical to questioning and deconstructing the national security state and taking away its power to define our security a grassroots statecraft that is defined as “challenging foreign policy of government through contending discursive and speech acts.” calls for pitting the values of civil society against the state establishment and challenging the American statecraft’s freedom to cast issues and events in a security or militarized framework. The U S has not always been a national security state and neither does it have to maintain that hegemonic and oppressive status in order to exist. It is critical to remember that fundamental changes in our institutions and structures of power do not occur from the top; they originate from the bottom. History is case in point. Citizen action was critical to ending the Red Scare and the Vietnam War grassroots citizen action performatively makes individuals the referent subject of security as people would call for the demilitarization and desecuritization of issues that are contrary and irrelevant to human security. There is hope for the future and practical application of critical theory in international relations. “it was the existence of the Other across the border that gave national security its power and authority; it is the disappearance of the border that has vanquished that power.” Britain, France and Germany set aside their historical enmities and became part of a European community, which has formed a new collective identity and security across borders. Cold War rivals that almost annihilated the world are now friends in the “war against terror.” The apartheid regime in South Africa did collapse eventually. India and Pakistan have been moving towards a more peaceful future While nation-states that were previously hostile to each other have united to be hostile towards other states, it is not overly idealist to suggest that with each new friendship and alliance, there is one less foe and one less Other. The world is not stable and stagnant, existing in an anarchic, nasty and brutish framework in which states have to endlessly bargain for their self-interest, as realists would like us to believe. On the contrary, international relations and the boundaries constructed by the state are subject to change and ever-transitioning, which presents a compelling case for critical theory as a more realistic framework through which we can view international relations. our ultimate search for security does not lie in securing the state from the threat of the enemy across the border, but in removing the state as the referent object of security and moving towards human emancipation. questioning and changing structures that oppress us Emancipation and security become two sides of the same coin as humans must be freed from their oppressive structures and overthrow physical and human constraints that prevent them from reaching their true potential. However, emancipation is not the end-all solution but a project that can never be fully realized. This may lead some to question the practicality of the concept that we can see in the horizon, but the closer we get to it, the further away it seems. Yet, when we look back, we see how far we have come. human emancipation serves practical purpose as an immanent critique, which can be utilized as a philosophical anchorage for tactical goal setting.
discourse is power, we can deconstruct the power of elites using their own tool: discourse. we are through discursive practices subjected to the reality the state wants us to see. it is time we defined our own reality citizen action is critical grassroots statecraft challenging policy through contending discursive acts calls for pitting values of society against the state The U S has not always been a national security state and neither does it have to maintain hegemonic and oppressive status to exist changes do not occur from the top; they originate from the bottom. . Citizen action was critical to ending the Red Scare and Vietnam grassroots action makes individuals the referent of security as people call for demilitarization of issues contrary to human security Britain, France and Germany set aside historical enmities and became a community Cold War rivals are now friends The apartheid regime did collapse India and Pakistan have been moving towards peace with each new friendship , there is one less foe and one less Other The world is not stable in a , nasty brutish framework which presents a compelling case for critical theory as a realistic framework
(Prerna P., Master of Arts in International Relations @ San Francisco State University, Senior Graduate Thesis, Critical Security Studies, “Deconstructing the National Security State: Towards a New Framework of Analysis,” http://prernalal.com/wp-content/uploads/2008/10/css-deconstructing-the-nat-sec-state.pdf) Throughout this paper, we have seen cases of how national security is an antonym for human security. With this essential realization, Booth (2005, 33) gives three reasons for why the state should not be the referent object of security: “states are unreliable as primary referents because while some are in the business of security some are not; even those which are producers of security represent the means and not the ends; and states are too diverse in their character to serve as the basis for a comprehensive theory of security.” Additionally, the cases of South Africa and Afghanistan prove how the national security state is merely an elite tool, which causes human insecurity at home and abroad. The state treats security as a problem that comes from the outside, rather than as a problem that can arise from domestic issues. The end result of state-centric security is that humans are alienated from discussions about their own security and welfare. The most compelling reason is provided by Hayward Akler (2005, 191) in Critical Security Studies and World Politics, in which he states that “economic collapse, political oppression, scarcity, overpopulation, ethnic rivalry, the destruction of nature, terrorism, crime and disease provide more serious threats to the well-being of individuals and the interest of nations.” Thus, to millions of people, it is not the existence of the Other across the border that poses a security problem, but their own state that is a threat to security. The question that arises next is how to put critical theory into practice and deconstruct the national security state. Critical theory does not offer simple one-shot solutions to the problems created by the neo-realist state and elitist conception of security. To give simple answers would be a performative contradiction, especially after criticizing realism for being intellectually rigid for believing in objective truth. In other words, there are no alternatives; just alternative modes of understanding. However, using the poststructuralist Foucaultian analysis that discourse is power, we can move towards deconstructing the power of the state and elites to securitize using their own tool: discourse. The elites who control the meaning of security and define it in terms that are appropriate to their interests hold tremendous power in the national security state. As Foucault astutely observed, “the exercise of power is always deeply entwined with the production of knowledge and discourse” (Dalby 1998, 4). For too long, language has been used against us to create our reality, thereby obfuscating our lens of the world, depriving us from an objective search for truth and knowledge. The history of colonized people shows how the construction of language defined and justified their oppressed status. In a way, we are colonized through discursive practices and subjected to the reality that the state wants us to see. However, definitions belong to the definer, and it is high time that we questioned and defined our own reality. Thus, citizen action is critical to questioning and deconstructing the national security state and taking away its power to define our security. In On Security, Pearl Alice Marsh (1995, 126) advances the idea of a grassroots statecraft that is defined as “challenging foreign policy of government through contending discursive and speech acts.” This calls for pitting the values of civil society against the state establishment and challenging the American statecraft’s freedom to cast issues and events in a security or militarized framework. The United States has not always been a national security state and neither does it have to maintain that hegemonic and oppressive status in order to exist. It is critical to remember that fundamental changes in our institutions and structures of power do not occur from the top; they originate from the bottom. History is case in point. Citizen action was critical to ending the Red Scare and the Vietnam War, as the American people realized the ludicrousness of framing Vietnam as a security issue, which led to the fall of the Second New Deal, the deaths of thousands of American soldiers and a financial cost that we are still shouldering. In the end, what they need to be secured from and how, is a question best left up to individual Americans and subsequently, civil society. Thus, grassroots citizen action performatively makes individuals the referent subject of security as people would call for the demilitarization and desecuritization of issues that are contrary and irrelevant to human security. There is hope for the future and practical application of critical theory in international relations. As Robert Lipschutz (2000, 61) concludes in After Authority: War, Peace, and Global Politics in the 21st Century, “it was the existence of the Other across the border that gave national security its power and authority; it is the disappearance of the border that has vanquished that power.” Britain, France and Germany set aside their historical enmities and became part of a European community, which has formed a new collective identity and security across borders. Cold War rivals that almost annihilated the world are now friends in the “war against terror.” The apartheid regime in South Africa did collapse eventually. In the past two years, India and Pakistan have been moving towards a more peaceful future that also includes fighting the “war against terror” together. While nation-states that were previously hostile to each other have united to be hostile towards other states, it is not overly idealist to suggest that with each new friendship and alliance, there is one less foe and one less Other. The world is not stable and stagnant, existing in an anarchic, nasty and brutish framework in which states have to endlessly bargain for their self-interest, as realists would like us to believe. On the contrary, international relations and the boundaries constructed by the state are subject to change and ever-transitioning, which presents a compelling case for critical theory as a more realistic framework through which we can view international relations. Therefore, our ultimate search for security does not lie in securing the state from the threat of the enemy across the border, but in removing the state as the referent object of security and moving towards human emancipation. Human emancipation is often cited as the ultimate goal of the CSS project. Kenneth Booth (2005, 181) defines human emancipation as “the theory and practice of inventing humanity, with a view of freeing people, as individuals and collectivities, from contingent and structural oppressions...the concept of emancipation shapes strategies and tactics of resistance, offers a theory of progress for society, and gives a politics of hope for common humanity.” For Booth then, human emancipation is a concern with questioning and changing structures and institutions that oppress us and prevent us from reaching our true potential, a seemingly Marxist and poststructuralist concern. Emancipation and security become two sides of the same coin for Booth (2005, 191), as humans must be freed from their oppressive structures and overthrow physical and human constraints that prevent them from reaching their true potential. However, emancipation is not the end-all solution but a project that can never be fully realized. This may lead some to question the practicality of the concept. Here, I will draw an analogy from Karl Marx, whose idea of human emancipation was communism, a goal that we can see in the horizon, but the closer we get to it, the further away it seems. Yet, when we look back, we see how far we have come. Therefore, human emancipation serves practical purpose as an immanent critique, which can be utilized as a philosophical anchorage for tactical goal setting.
8,181
<h4><strong>Our alternative is to demilitarize the public sphere, bottom up rejection of security politics allows us to move beyond</strong> an unsustainable system that leads to inevitable threat escalation</h4><p><u>Lal, 2007</p><p></u>(Prerna P., Master of Arts in International Relations @ San Francisco State University, Senior Graduate Thesis, Critical Security Studies, “Deconstructing the National Security State: Towards a New Framework of Analysis,” http://prernalal.com/wp-content/uploads/2008/10/css-deconstructing-the-nat-sec-state.pdf)</p><p>Throughout this paper, we have seen cases of how <u><strong>national security is an antonym for human security</u></strong>. With this essential realization, Booth (2005, 33) gives three reasons for why <u><strong>the state should not be the referent object of security: “states are unreliable as primary referents because while some are in the business of security some are not; even those which are producers of security represent the means and not the ends; and states are too diverse in their character to serve as the basis for a comprehensive theory of security.”</u></strong> Additionally, the cases of South Africa and Afghanistan prove how <u><strong>the national security state is merely an elite tool, which causes human insecurity at home and abroad. The state treats security as a problem that comes from the outside, rather than as a problem that can arise from domestic issues. The end result of state-centric security is that humans are alienated from discussions about their own security and welfare. </u></strong>The most compelling reason is provided by Hayward Akler (2005, 191) in Critical Security Studies and World Politics, in which he states that <u><strong>“economic collapse, political oppression, scarcity, overpopulation, ethnic rivalry, the destruction of nature, terrorism, crime and disease provide more serious threats to the well-being of individuals and the interest of nations.” Thus, to millions of people, it is not the existence of the Other across the border that poses a security problem, but their own state that is a threat to security.</u></strong> The question that arises next is how to <u><strong>put</u></strong> critical <u><strong>theory into practice</u></strong> and deconstruct the national security state. <u><strong>Critical theory does not offer simple one-shot solutions to the problems created by the neo-realist state and elitist conception of security. To give simple answers would be a performative contradiction, especially after criticizing realism for being intellectually rigid for believing in objective truth.</u></strong> In other words, <u><strong>there are no alternatives; just alternative modes of understanding. However, using the poststructuralist</u></strong> Foucaultian <u><strong>analysis that <mark>discourse is power, we can </mark>move towards <mark>deconstruct</mark>ing<mark> the power of </mark>the state and <mark>elites</mark> to securitize <mark>using their own tool: discourse.</u></strong></mark> The elites who control the meaning of security and define it in terms that are appropriate to their interests hold tremendous power in the national security state. As Foucault astutely observed, “the exercise of power is always deeply entwined with the production of knowledge and discourse” (Dalby 1998, 4). For too long, language has been used against us to create our reality, thereby obfuscating our lens of the world, depriving us from an objective search for truth and knowledge. The history of colonized people shows how the construction of language defined and justified their oppressed status. In a way, <u><strong><mark>we are </mark>colonized <mark>through discursive practices </mark>and <mark>subjected to the reality </mark>that <mark>the state wants us to see.</mark> However, definitions belong to the definer, and <mark>it is </mark>high <mark>time</mark> that <mark>we</mark> questioned and <mark>defined our own reality</mark>.</u></strong> Thus, <u><strong><mark>citizen action is critical</mark> to questioning and deconstructing the national security state and taking away its power to define our security</u></strong>. In On Security, Pearl Alice Marsh (1995, 126) advances the idea of <u><strong>a <mark>grassroots statecraft</mark> that is defined as “<mark>challenging</mark> foreign <mark>policy </mark>of government <mark>through contending discursive</mark> and speech <mark>acts</mark>.”</u></strong> This <u><strong><mark>calls for pitting</mark> the <mark>values of </mark>civil <mark>society against the state </mark>establishment and challenging the American statecraft’s freedom to cast issues and events in a security or militarized framework. <mark>The U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><strong><mark>has not always been a national security state and neither does it have to maintain</mark> that <mark>hegemonic and oppressive status</mark> in order <mark>to exist</mark>. It is critical to remember that fundamental <mark>changes </mark>in our institutions and structures of power <mark>do not occur from the top; they originate from the bottom.</mark> History is case in point<mark>. Citizen action was critical to ending the Red Scare and </mark>the <mark>Vietnam </mark>War</u></strong>, as the American people realized the ludicrousness of framing Vietnam as a security issue, which led to the fall of the Second New Deal, the deaths of thousands of American soldiers and a financial cost that we are still shouldering. In the end, what they need to be secured from and how, is a question best left up to individual Americans and subsequently, civil society. Thus, <u><strong><mark>grassroots </mark>citizen <mark>action </mark>performatively <mark>makes individuals the referent </mark>subject <mark>of security as people </mark>would <mark>call for</mark> the <mark>demilitarization</mark> and desecuritization <mark>of issues </mark>that are <mark>contrary</mark> and irrelevant <mark>to</mark> <mark>human security</mark>. There is hope for the future and practical application of critical theory in international relations. </u></strong>As Robert Lipschutz (2000, 61) concludes in After Authority: War, Peace, and Global Politics in the 21st Century, <u><strong>“it was the existence of the Other across the border that gave national security its power and authority; it is the disappearance of the border that has vanquished that power.” <mark>Britain, France and Germany set aside </mark>their <mark>historical enmities and became </mark>part of <mark>a </mark>European <mark>community</mark>, which has formed a new collective identity and security across borders. <mark>Cold War rivals </mark>that almost annihilated the world <mark>are now friends </mark>in the “war against terror.” <mark>The apartheid regime</mark> in South Africa <mark>did collapse</mark> eventually.</u></strong> In the past two years, <u><strong><mark>India and Pakistan have been moving towards </mark>a more <mark>peace</mark>ful future</u></strong> that also includes fighting the “war against terror” together. <u><strong>While nation-states that were previously hostile to each other have united to be hostile towards other states, it is not overly idealist to suggest that <mark>with each new friendship </mark>and alliance<mark>, there is one less foe and one less Other</mark>. <mark>The world is not stable </mark>and stagnant, existing <mark>in a</mark>n anarchic<mark>, nasty </mark>and <mark>brutish framework</mark> in which states have to endlessly bargain for their self-interest, as realists would like us to believe. On the contrary, international relations and the boundaries constructed by the state are subject to change and ever-transitioning, <mark>which presents a compelling case for critical theory as a </mark>more <mark>realistic framework </mark>through which we can view international relations.</u></strong> Therefore, <u><strong>our ultimate search for security does not lie in securing the state from the threat of the enemy across the border, but in removing the state as the referent object of security and moving towards human emancipation.</u></strong> Human emancipation is often cited as the ultimate goal of the CSS project. Kenneth Booth (2005, 181) defines human emancipation as “the theory and practice of inventing humanity, with a view of freeing people, as individuals and collectivities, from contingent and structural oppressions...the concept of emancipation shapes strategies and tactics of resistance, offers a theory of progress for society, and gives a politics of hope for common humanity.” For Booth then, human emancipation is a concern with <u><strong>questioning and changing structures</u></strong> and institutions <u><strong>that oppress us</u></strong> and prevent us from reaching our true potential, a seemingly Marxist and poststructuralist concern. <u><strong>Emancipation and security become two sides of the same coin</u></strong> for Booth (2005, 191), <u><strong>as humans must be freed from their oppressive structures and overthrow physical and human constraints that prevent them from reaching their true potential. However, emancipation is not the end-all solution but a project that can never be fully realized. This may lead some to question the practicality of the concept</u></strong>. Here, I will draw an analogy from Karl Marx, whose idea of human emancipation was communism, a goal <u><strong>that we can see in the horizon, but the closer we get to it, the further away it seems. Yet, when we look back, we see how far we have come.</u></strong> Therefore, <u><strong>human emancipation serves practical purpose as an immanent critique, which can be utilized as a philosophical anchorage for tactical goal setting.</u></strong> </p>
null
null
K
430,587
4
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,283
This culminates in massive violence against sex workers
Aronson 6
Aronson 6 (J.D., Rutgers School of Law) (Gregg, SEEKING A CONSOLIDATED FEMINIST VOICE FOR PROSTITUTION IN THE US, Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy, 3 Rutgers J.L. & Pub. Pol'y 357, LN)
Prostitutes are also victims of various forms of physical abuse prostitutes rarely report violence for fear of legal repercussions Those who do report abuse are systematically ignored by the police ne survey showed that sixty-five percent of prostitutes have been seriously injured by a customer.106 Another survey reported that two-thirds to three-fourths of street prostitutes are raped or beaten an average of four to fifteen times a year. women are murdered at equally alarming rates serial murderers kill more than one thousand female prostitutes each year the mortality rate among prostitutes is forty times the national average criminal law is most frequently enforced against street prostitutes, the poorest and greatest minority of women who deal in sex work. Since these women are the most visible prostitutes,120 they account for roughly ninety percent of all prostitution arrests.
Prostitutes are victims of physical abuse prostitutes rarely report such violence for fear of legal repercussions Those who do report are systematically ignored one survey showed that two-thirds to three-fourths of street prostitutes are raped or beaten an average of four to fifteen times a year women are murdered at equally alarming rates the mortality rate among prostitutes is forty times the national average criminal law is most frequently enforced against the poorest of women who deal in sex work
Prostitutes are also victims of various forms of physical abuse.103 This is especially problematic since prostitutes rarely report such violence to law enforcement for fear of legal repercussions against them.104 Those who do report abuse are systematically ignored by the police,105 leading most prostitutes to the conclusion that these violent crimes are not worth reporting. Many abusive men are fully aware of the legal dilemma that prostitutes face, and often take advantage of their legal vulnerability. Though statistics vary depending on the sample population, one survey showed that sixty-five percent of prostitutes have been seriously injured by a customer.106 Another survey reported that two-thirds to three-fourths of street prostitutes are raped or beaten an average of four to fifteen times a year.107 These women are murdered at equally alarming rates. Studies show that serial murderers kill more than one thousand female prostitutes each year.108 In fact, the mortality rate among prostitutes is forty times the national average.109 These figures are not surprising however, when one considers the options available for a prostitute to seek help. Not only are prostitutes frequently ignored by law enforcement, but they are often explicitly excluded from domestic violence shelters.110 Many shelters have written policies of barring women who engage in “illegal activities of any kind.”111 Rescue service shelters are among the few groups that do offer shelter and services to prostitutes.112 However, these groups are small, few in number, and poorly funded.113 B. COSTS AND RESOURCES The cost of maintaining a criminalized system of prostitution in the U.S., in terms of money spent and resources used, is staggering. One study conducted in 1985 estimated that each of America’s largest cities spends twelve million dollars a year fighting prostitution.114 Another study conducted on Los Angeles, estimated a cost of one hundred million dollars annually to that city alone.115 Many cities spend more money on the criminal enforcement of prostitution than on education, public welfare, and health services combined.116 In 1996, 99,000 people were arrested in the U.S. on prostitution related charges.117 A 1980's report found that the run-of-the-mill prosecution of a prostitute costs nearly two thousand dollars.118 The cost of prostitution to the U.S. government in terms of lost tax dollars is not a figure that can be accurately calculated, yet many agree that it is astronomical.119 Not only does the U.S. spend an exorbitant amount of money fighting prostitution, but it does so inefficiently. The criminal law is most frequently enforced against street prostitutes, the poorest and greatest minority of women who deal in sex work. Since these women are the most visible prostitutes,120 they account for roughly ninety percent of all prostitution arrests.121 However, street prostitutes comprise only ten to twenty percent of all prostitutes in the U.S..122 Another somewhat hidden cost of criminalized prostitution in the US is the over-dedication of police forces and the overcrowding of prisons. In 1985, police in the sixteen largest US cities made as many arrests for prostitution as for all violent crimes combined.123 A study performed that year indicated that police officers working in pairs expended an average of twenty-one hours per prostitution arrest,124 a gross over-commitment of limited police resources.125 Not surprisingly, this practice leads to a drastic overcrowding of prisons with female prostitutes.126 In over thirty-five US states, nearly half of the female inmates were arrested on prostitution related charges.127
3,668
<h4>This culminates in massive violence against sex workers</h4><p><strong>Aronson 6</strong> (J.D., Rutgers School of Law) (Gregg, SEEKING A CONSOLIDATED FEMINIST VOICE FOR PROSTITUTION IN THE US, Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy, 3 Rutgers J.L. & Pub. Pol'y 357, LN)</p><p><u><mark>Prostitutes are</mark> also <mark>victims of</mark> various forms of <mark>physical abuse</u></mark>.103 This is especially problematic since <u><mark>prostitutes rarely report</u> such <u>violence</u></mark> to law enforcement <u><mark>for fear of legal repercussions</u></mark> against them.104 <u><mark>Those who do report</mark> abuse <mark>are systematically ignored</mark> by the police</u>,105 leading most prostitutes to the conclusion that these violent crimes are not worth reporting. Many abusive men are fully aware of the legal dilemma that prostitutes face, and often take advantage of their legal vulnerability.</p><p>Though statistics vary depending on the sample population, <mark>o<u>ne survey showed that</mark> sixty-five percent of prostitutes have been seriously injured by a customer.106 Another survey reported that <mark>two-thirds to three-fourths of street prostitutes are raped or beaten an average of four to fifteen times a year</mark>.</u>107 These <u><mark>women are murdered at equally alarming rates</u></mark>. Studies show that <u>serial murderers kill more than one thousand female prostitutes each year</u>.108 In fact, <u><mark>the mortality rate among prostitutes is forty times the national average</u></mark>.109 These figures are not surprising however, when one considers the options available for a prostitute to seek help. Not only are prostitutes frequently ignored by law enforcement, but they are often explicitly excluded from domestic violence shelters.110 Many shelters have written policies of barring women who engage in “illegal activities of any kind.”111 Rescue service shelters are among the few groups that do offer shelter and services to prostitutes.112 However, these groups are small, few in number, and poorly funded.113</p><p>B. COSTS AND RESOURCES</p><p>The cost of maintaining a criminalized system of prostitution in the U.S., in terms of money spent and resources used, is staggering. One study conducted in 1985 estimated that each of America’s largest cities spends twelve million dollars a year fighting prostitution.114 Another study conducted on Los Angeles, estimated a cost of one hundred million dollars annually to that city alone.115 Many cities spend more money on the criminal enforcement of prostitution than on education, public welfare, and health services combined.116 In 1996, 99,000 people were arrested in the U.S. on prostitution related charges.117 A 1980's report found that the run-of-the-mill prosecution of a prostitute costs nearly two thousand dollars.118 The cost of prostitution to the U.S. government in terms of lost tax dollars is not a figure that can be accurately calculated, yet many agree that it is astronomical.119</p><p>Not only does the U.S. spend an exorbitant amount of money fighting prostitution, but it does so inefficiently. The <u><mark>criminal law is most frequently enforced against</mark> street prostitutes, <mark>the poorest </mark>and greatest minority <mark>of women who deal in sex work</mark>. Since these women are the most visible prostitutes,120 they account for roughly ninety percent of all prostitution arrests.</u>121 However, street prostitutes comprise only ten to twenty percent of all prostitutes in the U.S..122 Another somewhat hidden cost of criminalized prostitution in the US is the over-dedication of police forces and the overcrowding of prisons. In 1985, police in the sixteen largest US cities made as many arrests for prostitution as for all violent crimes combined.123 A study performed that year indicated that police officers working in pairs expended an average of twenty-one hours per prostitution arrest,124 a gross over-commitment of limited police resources.125 Not surprisingly, this practice leads to a drastic overcrowding of prisons with female prostitutes.126 In over thirty-five US states, nearly half of the female inmates were arrested on prostitution related charges.127</p>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,634
18
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,284
The fifty United States and relevant territories should legalize marihuana in opposition to racial oppression and the use of incarceration to maintain a racial caste system.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The fifty United States and relevant territories should legalize marihuana in opposition to racial oppression and the use of incarceration to maintain a racial caste system.</h4>
null
null
Counteradvocacy
430,633
1
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,285
This culminates in massive violence against sex workers
Aronson 6
Aronson 6 (J.D., Rutgers School of Law) (Gregg, SEEKING A CONSOLIDATED FEMINIST VOICE FOR PROSTITUTION IN THE US, Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy, 3 Rutgers J.L. & Pub. Pol'y 357, LN)
Prostitutes are also victims of various forms of physical abuse prostitutes rarely report violence for fear of legal repercussions Those who do report abuse are systematically ignored by the police ne survey showed that sixty-five percent of prostitutes have been seriously injured by a customer.106 Another survey reported that two-thirds to three-fourths of street prostitutes are raped or beaten an average of four to fifteen times a year. women are murdered at equally alarming rates serial murderers kill more than one thousand female prostitutes each year the mortality rate among prostitutes is forty times the national average criminal law is most frequently enforced against street prostitutes, the poorest and greatest minority of women who deal in sex work. Since these women are the most visible prostitutes,120 they account for roughly ninety percent of all prostitution arrests.
Prostitutes are victims of physical abuse prostitutes rarely report such violence for fear of legal repercussions Those who do report are systematically ignored one survey showed that two-thirds to three-fourths of street prostitutes are raped or beaten an average of four to fifteen times a year women are murdered at equally alarming rates the mortality rate among prostitutes is forty times the national average criminal law is most frequently enforced against the poorest of women who deal in sex work
Prostitutes are also victims of various forms of physical abuse.103 This is especially problematic since prostitutes rarely report such violence to law enforcement for fear of legal repercussions against them.104 Those who do report abuse are systematically ignored by the police,105 leading most prostitutes to the conclusion that these violent crimes are not worth reporting. Many abusive men are fully aware of the legal dilemma that prostitutes face, and often take advantage of their legal vulnerability. Though statistics vary depending on the sample population, one survey showed that sixty-five percent of prostitutes have been seriously injured by a customer.106 Another survey reported that two-thirds to three-fourths of street prostitutes are raped or beaten an average of four to fifteen times a year.107 These women are murdered at equally alarming rates. Studies show that serial murderers kill more than one thousand female prostitutes each year.108 In fact, the mortality rate among prostitutes is forty times the national average.109 These figures are not surprising however, when one considers the options available for a prostitute to seek help. Not only are prostitutes frequently ignored by law enforcement, but they are often explicitly excluded from domestic violence shelters.110 Many shelters have written policies of barring women who engage in “illegal activities of any kind.”111 Rescue service shelters are among the few groups that do offer shelter and services to prostitutes.112 However, these groups are small, few in number, and poorly funded.113 B. COSTS AND RESOURCES The cost of maintaining a criminalized system of prostitution in the U.S., in terms of money spent and resources used, is staggering. One study conducted in 1985 estimated that each of America’s largest cities spends twelve million dollars a year fighting prostitution.114 Another study conducted on Los Angeles, estimated a cost of one hundred million dollars annually to that city alone.115 Many cities spend more money on the criminal enforcement of prostitution than on education, public welfare, and health services combined.116 In 1996, 99,000 people were arrested in the U.S. on prostitution related charges.117 A 1980's report found that the run-of-the-mill prosecution of a prostitute costs nearly two thousand dollars.118 The cost of prostitution to the U.S. government in terms of lost tax dollars is not a figure that can be accurately calculated, yet many agree that it is astronomical.119 Not only does the U.S. spend an exorbitant amount of money fighting prostitution, but it does so inefficiently. The criminal law is most frequently enforced against street prostitutes, the poorest and greatest minority of women who deal in sex work. Since these women are the most visible prostitutes,120 they account for roughly ninety percent of all prostitution arrests.121 However, street prostitutes comprise only ten to twenty percent of all prostitutes in the U.S..122 Another somewhat hidden cost of criminalized prostitution in the US is the over-dedication of police forces and the overcrowding of prisons. In 1985, police in the sixteen largest US cities made as many arrests for prostitution as for all violent crimes combined.123 A study performed that year indicated that police officers working in pairs expended an average of twenty-one hours per prostitution arrest,124 a gross over-commitment of limited police resources.125 Not surprisingly, this practice leads to a drastic overcrowding of prisons with female prostitutes.126 In over thirty-five US states, nearly half of the female inmates were arrested on prostitution related charges.127
3,668
<h4>This culminates in massive violence against sex workers</h4><p><strong>Aronson 6</strong> (J.D., Rutgers School of Law) (Gregg, SEEKING A CONSOLIDATED FEMINIST VOICE FOR PROSTITUTION IN THE US, Rutgers Journal of Law & Public Policy, 3 Rutgers J.L. & Pub. Pol'y 357, LN)</p><p><u><mark>Prostitutes are</mark> also <mark>victims of</mark> various forms of <mark>physical abuse</u></mark>.103 This is especially problematic since <u><mark>prostitutes rarely report</u> such <u>violence</u></mark> to law enforcement <u><mark>for fear of legal repercussions</u></mark> against them.104 <u><mark>Those who do report</mark> abuse <mark>are systematically ignored</mark> by the police</u>,105 leading most prostitutes to the conclusion that these violent crimes are not worth reporting. Many abusive men are fully aware of the legal dilemma that prostitutes face, and often take advantage of their legal vulnerability.</p><p>Though statistics vary depending on the sample population, <mark>o<u>ne survey showed that</mark> sixty-five percent of prostitutes have been seriously injured by a customer.106 Another survey reported that <mark>two-thirds to three-fourths of street prostitutes are raped or beaten an average of four to fifteen times a year</mark>.</u>107 These <u><mark>women are murdered at equally alarming rates</u></mark>. Studies show that <u>serial murderers kill more than one thousand female prostitutes each year</u>.108 In fact, <u><mark>the mortality rate among prostitutes is forty times the national average</u></mark>.109 These figures are not surprising however, when one considers the options available for a prostitute to seek help. Not only are prostitutes frequently ignored by law enforcement, but they are often explicitly excluded from domestic violence shelters.110 Many shelters have written policies of barring women who engage in “illegal activities of any kind.”111 Rescue service shelters are among the few groups that do offer shelter and services to prostitutes.112 However, these groups are small, few in number, and poorly funded.113</p><p>B. COSTS AND RESOURCES</p><p>The cost of maintaining a criminalized system of prostitution in the U.S., in terms of money spent and resources used, is staggering. One study conducted in 1985 estimated that each of America’s largest cities spends twelve million dollars a year fighting prostitution.114 Another study conducted on Los Angeles, estimated a cost of one hundred million dollars annually to that city alone.115 Many cities spend more money on the criminal enforcement of prostitution than on education, public welfare, and health services combined.116 In 1996, 99,000 people were arrested in the U.S. on prostitution related charges.117 A 1980's report found that the run-of-the-mill prosecution of a prostitute costs nearly two thousand dollars.118 The cost of prostitution to the U.S. government in terms of lost tax dollars is not a figure that can be accurately calculated, yet many agree that it is astronomical.119</p><p>Not only does the U.S. spend an exorbitant amount of money fighting prostitution, but it does so inefficiently. The <u><mark>criminal law is most frequently enforced against</mark> street prostitutes, <mark>the poorest </mark>and greatest minority <mark>of women who deal in sex work</mark>. Since these women are the most visible prostitutes,120 they account for roughly ninety percent of all prostitution arrests.</u>121 However, street prostitutes comprise only ten to twenty percent of all prostitutes in the U.S..122 Another somewhat hidden cost of criminalized prostitution in the US is the over-dedication of police forces and the overcrowding of prisons. In 1985, police in the sixteen largest US cities made as many arrests for prostitution as for all violent crimes combined.123 A study performed that year indicated that police officers working in pairs expended an average of twenty-one hours per prostitution arrest,124 a gross over-commitment of limited police resources.125 Not surprisingly, this practice leads to a drastic overcrowding of prisons with female prostitutes.126 In over thirty-five US states, nearly half of the female inmates were arrested on prostitution related charges.127</p>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,634
18
17,077
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
565,297
A
tournament
4
Binghamton Cepin-Sehgal
Baker, Webster Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,286
For many, the coercion is more violent
Bowden 13
Bowden 13 Jackie Bowden, 2013 J.D. graduate from St. Thomas University School of Law. Intercultural Human Rights Law Review 2013 8 Intercultural Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 451 ARTICLE: FEELING EMPTY? ORGAN TRAFFICKING & TRADE: THE BLACK MARKET FOR HUMAN ORGANS lexis
Organ trafficking has been depriving innocent people of their fundamental right to life for decades Imagine living in a poor country As you walk peacefully you are grabbed and thrown into the back of an unmarked truck. a surgeon slices through your flesh to remove your kidney no anesthesia is administered and no medication is given to prevent infection Your body is then dumped on a side street, and you are extremely lucky if you live , there are reported accounts suggesting that abduction of organs is a harsh reality of organ trafficking. Furthermore, there is evidence of governmental involvement, which contributes to and exacerbates the problem.
Organ trafficking has been depriving innocent people of their fundamental right to life for decades Imagine living in a poor country you are grabbed and thrown into the back of an unmarked truck a surgeon slices through your flesh to remove your kidney no anesthesia is administered and no medication is given to prevent infection Your body is then dumped on a side street, and you are extremely lucky if you live there are reported accounts suggesting that abduction of organs is a harsh reality
[*452] Introduction Organ trafficking has been depriving innocent people of their fundamental right to life for decades. n1 Imagine living in a poor country, where you wake up in the morning and set out to find work and food for the day. As you walk peacefully to your home at the end of the day, you are grabbed and thrown into the back of an unmarked truck. n2 You wake up, screaming from excruciating pain, as a surgeon slices through your flesh to remove your kidney. Due to the costs associated with such a procedure, no anesthesia is administered and no medication is given to prevent infection. n3 In the event that the surgery does not go as planned, no forms of emergency assistance are available. Your body is then dumped on a side street, and you are extremely lucky if you live. Should you report the incident to government officials? What if the government is actually involved in this inhumane activity? n4 [*453] There are conflicting views on whether people are actually kidnapped for their organs. n5 In fact, many believe these stories are just myths. n6 However, there are reported accounts suggesting that abduction of organs is a harsh reality of organ trafficking. n7 Reports indicate organ trafficking is so prevalent that there is a surplus of organs available for transplantation. n8 Furthermore, there is evidence of governmental involvement, which contributes to and exacerbates the problem. n9 Fortunately, most countries have enacted laws to prevent and prohibit organ trafficking from occurring. n10
1,530
<h4>For many, the coercion is more violent</h4><p><strong>Bowden 13</strong> Jackie Bowden, 2013 J.D. graduate from St. Thomas University School of Law. Intercultural Human Rights Law Review 2013 8 Intercultural Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 451 ARTICLE: FEELING EMPTY? ORGAN TRAFFICKING & TRADE: THE BLACK MARKET FOR HUMAN ORGANS lexis</p><p> [*452] Introduction</p><p><u><mark>Organ trafficking has been depriving innocent people of their fundamental right to life for decades</u></mark>. n1 <u><mark>Imagine living in a poor country</u></mark>, where you wake up in the morning and set out to find work and food for the day. <u>As you walk peacefully</u> to your home at the end of the day, <u><mark>you are grabbed and</mark> <mark>thrown into the back of an unmarked truck</mark>. </u>n2 You wake up, screaming from excruciating pain, as <u><mark>a surgeon slices through your flesh to remove your kidney</u></mark>. Due to the costs associated with such a procedure, <u><mark>no anesthesia is administered and no medication is given to prevent infection</u></mark>. n3 In the event that the surgery does not go as planned, no forms of emergency assistance are available. <u><mark>Your body is then dumped on a side street, and you are extremely lucky if you live</u></mark>. Should you report the incident to government officials? What if the government is actually involved in this inhumane activity? n4 [*453] There are conflicting views on whether people are actually kidnapped for their organs. n5 In fact, many believe these stories are just myths. n6 However<u>, <mark>there are reported accounts suggesting that abduction of organs is a harsh reality</mark> of organ trafficking.</u> n7 Reports indicate organ trafficking is so prevalent that there is a surplus of organs available for transplantation. n8 <u>Furthermore, there is evidence of governmental involvement, which contributes to and exacerbates the problem. </u>n9 Fortunately, most countries have enacted laws to prevent and prohibit organ trafficking from occurring. n10</p><p><strong> </p></strong>
null
null
Contention 2 is the Illegal market
430,258
14
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,287
Their authors misread Foucault – he didn’t actually think suicide is itself resistance, just that it illustrates a point about biopower – the aff doesn’t do anything. BUT their allegoricization of suicide as resistance trivializes the overwhelming misery and pain that produces suicide.
Stoneman 5
Stoneman 5 Scott, “Suicide and Biopower: Foucault, Derrida, and Deconstruction,” Fall, http://www.scribd.com/doc/230752001/774-Long-Paper-Stoneman-Foucault-Derrida-and-Suicide#scribd
what are the implications for framing suicide as a kind of resistance Foucault’s concern with suicide is allegoric a peculiarly methodological tool used to explain a certain theory by reducing it to a specific, emblematic scenario He is invested in what discursively is yielded up by preserving the singularity of suicide as an event that exceeds the regulative purview of biopower it is imperative that the consequential shortcomings of treating this matter “allegorically” (the likely deliberate disavowal of the bleakness and misery of real suicides be resolved if a meaningful and engaged consideration of suicide is to be formed there are situations in which suicide not only authorizes, but demands precisely the kind of coercive surveillance and brute interruption characteristic of the operations of biopower Foucault’s theory of the suicidal astonishment needs some nuance
what are the implications for framing suicide as a kind of resistance concern with suicide is allegoric a peculiarly methodological tool used to explain a certain theory by reducing it to a specific emblematic scenario it is imperative that the consequential shortcomings of treating this matter “allegorically the likely deliberate disavowal of the bleakness and misery of real suicides) be resolved if a meaningful and engaged consideration of suicide is to be formed there are situations in which suicide not only authorizes, but demands precisely the kind of coercive surveillance and brute interruption characteristic of the operations of biopower, theory of the suicidal astonishment needs some nuance
This equivocal passage from Foucault explodes the possibilities for theorizing suicide. But what, I wonder, are Foucault’s specific motivations for entering this particular dialectic —what productive “distortions” or epistemic agitations do his observations provide to the discourse on selbstmord, or “self-murder”? What use does Foucault make of caching these two critical sentences in Volume 1 of The History of Sexuality within a broader formulation of bio-power (a thing which, as we will see, is at once productive of and threatened by suicidality)? More precisely to the point: what are the implications for framing suicide as a kind of resistance vis-à-vis a technology of power that, in Foucault’s account, grows out of the seventeenth century? I contend that Foucault’s concern with suicide is allegoric. This is not to trivialize or understate the complexity of his diffuse consideration of the subject. What I mean here by allegoric is the sense that Walter Benjamin gives the term: a peculiarly methodological tool or turn used to explain a certain theory by reducing it to a specific, emblematic scenario. Foucault is interested in the intersticiality and peripherality which suicide embodies: a thing which operates “at the borders and in the interstices of power that was exercised over life” (HS 139). He is invested, moreover, in what discursively is yielded up by preserving the singularity of suicide as an event that, precisely because of its singularity, exceeds the regulative purview of biopower. But it is imperative that the consequential shortcomings of treating this matter “allegorically” (the likely deliberate disavowal of the bleakness and misery of real suicides) be resolved if a meaningful and engaged consideration of suicide is to be formed. This move, it seems, can only be accomplished by means of a complicity with “sociological analysis” in considering the question of how and under what pretenses to intervene in suicide. Indeed, if we accept Michael J. Cholbi’s provocative and convincing claim that there are situations in which suicide not only authorizes, but demands precisely the kind of coercive surveillance and brute interruption characteristic of the operations of biopower, we are forced also to acknowledge that Foucault’s theory of the suicidal astonishment needs some nuance. Additionally, in order to consider the broader question of the relationship between sovereignty and suicide I will look to an interview conducted by Elisabeth Roudinesco with Jacques Derrida, in which Derrida provides the possibility of thinking the death penalty as an event of disciplinary suicidalization. Derrida’s brief theorization—one might even call it an intimation—of the ways in which execution is made autodestruction, of the manner in which being condemned to death is discursively reformed into an event of taking one’s own life, is one which idiomatically exceeds the critical capacity of available theories and taxonomies of suicide, and will provide the primary means through which to consider a Derridean re-reading of biopolitics.
3,081
<h4>Their authors misread Foucault – he didn’t actually think suicide is itself resistance, just that it illustrates a point about biopower – the aff doesn’t do anything. BUT their allegoricization of suicide as resistance trivializes the overwhelming misery and pain that produces suicide. </h4><p><strong>Stoneman 5</strong> Scott, “Suicide and Biopower: Foucault, Derrida, and Deconstruction,” Fall, http://www.scribd.com/doc/230752001/774-Long-Paper-Stoneman-Foucault-Derrida-and-Suicide#scribd</p><p>This equivocal passage from Foucault explodes the possibilities for theorizing suicide. But what, I wonder, are Foucault’s specific motivations for entering this particular dialectic —what productive “distortions” or epistemic agitations do his observations provide to the discourse on selbstmord, or “self-murder”? What use does Foucault make of caching these two critical sentences in Volume 1 of The History of Sexuality within a broader formulation of bio-power (a thing which, as we will see, is at once productive of and threatened by suicidality)? More precisely to the point: <u><mark>what are the implications for framing suicide as a kind of resistance</u></mark> vis-à-vis a technology of power that, in Foucault’s account, grows out of the seventeenth century? I contend that <u>Foucault’s <mark>concern with suicide is allegoric</u></mark>. This is not to trivialize or understate the complexity of his diffuse consideration of the subject. What I mean here by allegoric is the sense that Walter Benjamin gives the term: <u><mark>a peculiarly methodological tool</u></mark> or turn <u><mark>used to explain a certain theory by reducing it to a specific</mark>, <mark>emblematic scenario</u></mark>. Foucault is interested in the intersticiality and peripherality which suicide embodies: a thing which operates “at the borders and in the interstices of power that was exercised over life” (HS 139). <u>He is invested</u>, moreover, <u>in what discursively is yielded up by preserving the singularity of suicide as an event that</u>, precisely because of its singularity, <u>exceeds the regulative purview of biopower</u>. But <u><mark>it is imperative that</mark> <mark>the consequential shortcomings of treating this matter “allegorically</mark>”</u> <u>(<mark>the likely deliberate disavowal of the bleakness and misery of real suicides</u>) <u>be resolved if a meaningful and engaged consideration of suicide is to be formed</u></mark>. This move, it seems, can only be accomplished by means of a complicity with “sociological analysis” in considering the question of how and under what pretenses to intervene in suicide. Indeed, if we accept Michael J. Cholbi’s provocative and convincing claim that <u><mark>there are situations in which suicide not only authorizes, but demands precisely the kind of coercive surveillance and brute interruption characteristic of the operations of biopower</u>,</mark> we are forced also to acknowledge that <u>Foucault’s <mark>theory of the suicidal astonishment needs some nuance</u><strong></mark>. Additionally, in order to consider the broader question of the relationship between sovereignty and suicide I will look to an interview conducted by Elisabeth Roudinesco with Jacques Derrida, in which Derrida provides the possibility of thinking the death penalty as an event of disciplinary suicidalization. Derrida’s brief theorization—one might even call it an intimation—of the ways in which execution is made autodestruction, of the manner in which being condemned to death is discursively reformed into an event of taking one’s own life, is one which idiomatically exceeds the critical capacity of available theories and taxonomies of suicide, and will provide the primary means through which to consider a Derridean re-reading of biopolitics.</p></strong>
null
null
Case
430,354
8
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,288
And it returns power to the doctor
Salem 99
Salem 99 Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full
Let us assume that from the point of view of patients assisted suicide does demedicalize their dying it liberates them from pain and the hands of medicine and its paraphernalia This liberation is achieved through torturous ways, however it is precisely physicians who are in charge of freeing patients from medicine Second, this emancipation presupposes and is achieved at the cost of the individual's submission to medical norms and scrutiny people will have physician-assisted suicide not only because they want it, but because physicians agree they can have it physician-assisted suicide radicalizes the right of the medical profession to make life and death decisions for now even (assisted) suicide must surrender to its hands Second, physician-assisted suicide translates one more sphere of personal and intimate meaning into a medical event this trade-off should not obscure the price being paid. It urges us, further, to re-examine the claims of honoring personal autonomy and demedicalizing death and dying as the argumentative basis on which physician-assisted suicide rests
assume from the point of view of patients assisted suicide does demedicalize their dying liberation is achieved through torturous ways, however is precisely physicians who are in charge of freeing patients from medicine Second, this emancipation presupposes and is achieved at the cost of the individual's submission to medical norms and scrutiny people will have physician-assisted suicide not only because they want it, but because physicians agree they can have it physician-assisted suicide translates one more sphere of personal and intimate meaning into a medical event trade-off should not obscure the price being paid It urges us to re-examine the claims of honoring personal autonomy and demedicalizing death and dying as the argumentative basis on which physician-assisted suicide rests
Let us assume that from the point of view of particular patients who will eventually undergo assisted suicide the practice does demedicalize their dying: as long as it hastens death, it liberates them not only from pain and suffering but from the hands of medicine and its paraphernalia as well. This liberation is achieved through torturous ways, however: first, it is precisely physicians who are in charge of freeing patients from medicine. Second, this emancipation presupposes and is achieved at the cost of the individual's submission to medical norms and scrutiny. What the patients’ rights movement still struggles to recapture from medicine—control over the decision to die—is being returned to medicine through physician-assisted suicide. Eventually, people will have physician-assisted suicide not only because they want it, but because physicians agree they can have it. At the societal level too physician-assisted suicide in fact extends the medicalization of death. First, physician-assisted suicide radicalizes the right of the medical profession to make life and death decisions, for now even (assisted) suicide must surrender to its hands. Second, physician-assisted suicide translates one more sphere of personal and intimate meaning into a medical event. Moreover, placing assisted suicide under physicians’ control and supervision ends up transforming moral categories (such as “rationality” and “voluntariness”) into medical ones. Perhaps submitting to medical scrutiny individually and to the increasing medicalization of death and dying societally are lesser evils than the agony some people endure at the end of life. Nevertheless, this trade-off should not obscure the price being paid. It urges us, further, to re-examine the claims of honoring personal autonomy and demedicalizing death and dying as the argumentative basis on which physician-assisted suicide rests.
1,894
<h4>And it returns power to the doctor</h4><p><strong>Salem 99</strong> Tania Salem, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: Promoting Autonomy—Or Medicalizing Suicide?” Hastings Center Report, 29: 30–36. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.2307/3528193/full</p><p><u>Let us <mark>assume</mark> that <mark>from the point of view of</mark> </u>particular <u><mark>patients</u></mark> who will eventually undergo <u><mark>assisted suicide</u></mark> the practice <u><mark>does demedicalize their dying</u></mark>: as long as it hastens death, <u>it liberates them </u>not only <u>from pain</u> <u>and</u> suffering but from <u>the hands of medicine and its paraphernalia</u> as well. <u>This <mark>liberation is achieved through torturous ways, however</u></mark>: first, <u>it <mark>is precisely physicians who are in charge of freeing patients from medicine</u></mark>. <u><mark>Second, this emancipation presupposes and is achieved at the cost of the individual's submission to medical norms and scrutiny</u></mark>. What the patients’ rights movement still struggles to recapture from medicine—control over the decision to die—is being returned to medicine through physician-assisted suicide. Eventually, <u><mark>people will have physician-assisted suicide not only because they want it, but because physicians agree they can have it</u></mark>.</p><p>At the societal level too physician-assisted suicide in fact extends the medicalization of death. First, <u>physician-assisted suicide radicalizes the right of the medical profession to make life and death decisions</u>, <u>for now even (assisted) suicide must surrender to its hands</u>. <u>Second, <mark>physician-assisted suicide translates one more sphere of personal and intimate meaning into a medical event</u></mark>. Moreover, placing assisted suicide under physicians’ control and supervision ends up transforming moral categories (such as “rationality” and “voluntariness”) into medical ones.</p><p>Perhaps submitting to medical scrutiny individually and to the increasing medicalization of death and dying societally are lesser evils than the agony some people endure at the end of life. Nevertheless, <u>this <mark>trade-off should not obscure the price being paid</mark>. <mark>It urges us</mark>, further, <mark>to re-examine the claims of honoring personal autonomy and demedicalizing death and dying as the argumentative basis on which physician-assisted suicide rests</u><strong></mark>.</p></strong>
null
Case
2NC Link Debate
430,635
4
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,289
Structural violence is the largest proximate cause of war- creates priming that psychologically structures escalation.
Scheper-Hughes and Bourgois ‘4
Scheper-Hughes and Bourgois ‘4
null
null
(Prof of Anthropology @ Cal-Berkely; Prof of Anthropology @ UPenn) (Nancy and Philippe, Introduction: Making Sense of Violence, in Violence in War and Peace, pg. 19-22) **Answers no root cause- because there is no root cause we must be attentative to structural inequality of all kinds because it primes people for broader violence- our impact is about the scale of violence and the disproportionate relationship between that scale and warfare, not that one form of social exclusion comes first
494
<h4><strong>Structural violence is the largest proximate cause of war- creates priming that psychologically structures escalation. </h4><p>Scheper-Hughes and Bourgois ‘4</p><p></strong>(Prof of Anthropology @ Cal-Berkely; Prof of Anthropology @ UPenn) (Nancy and Philippe, Introduction: Making Sense of Violence, in Violence in War and Peace, pg. 19-22) **Answers no root cause- because there is no root cause we must be attentative to structural inequality of all kinds because it primes people for broader violence- our impact is about the scale of violence and the disproportionate relationship between that scale and warfare, not that one form of social exclusion comes first</p>
2AC
Case
Framing
430,637
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,290
Stats prove heg causes war
Monteiro 12
Monteiro 12 [Nuno, Asst. prof of political science at Yale, teaches IR theory and security studies, winter, “Unrest Assured: Why Unipolarity is Not Peaceful”, http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/ISEC_a_00064]
Unipolarity is the most conflict prone system In unipolarity , the probability war involving a great power would break out was four times higher. Unipolarity (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2010).
null
How well, then, does the argument that unipolar systems are peaceful account for the first two decades of unipolarity since the end of the Cold War? Table 1 presents a list of great powers divided into three periods: 1816 to 1945, [CHART OMITTED – PLACED AT BOTTOM OF PARAGRAPH] multipolarity; 1946 to 1989, bipolarity; and since 1990, unipolarity.46 Table 2 presents summary data about the incidence of war during each of these periods. Unipolarity is the most conflict prone of all the systems, according to at least two important criteria: the percentage of years that great powers spend at war and the incidence of war involving great powers. In multipolarity, 18 percent of great power years were spent at war. In bipolarity, the ratio is 16 percent. In unipolarity, however, a remarkable 59 percent of great power years until now were spent at war. This is by far the highest percentage in all three systems. Furthermore, during periods of multipolarity and bipolarity, the probability that war involving a great power would break out in any given year was, respectively, 4.2 percent and 3.4 percent. Under unipolarity, it is 18.2 percent—or more than four times higher.47 These figures provide no evidence that unipolarity is peaceful.48 Table 1. Great Powers since 1816 95254953000 Multipolarity Bipolarity Unipolarity 3952875419100025146004127500 1181100-381000 DatesYears Dates Years Dates Years 95254953000 Austro-Hungarian 1816–1918 103 Empire France 1816–1940 125 Prussia/Germany 1816–1918 / 124 1925–45 Italy 1860–1943 84 Japan 1895–1945 51 United Kingdom 1816–1945 130 Russia / 1816–1917 / 126 1946–89 44 Soviet Union 1922–45 United States 1898–1945 48 1946–89 44 1990–2011 22 Total 791 88 22 95257620000 SOURCES: Data are from the Correlates of War, ver. 4.0, dataset, modified by the author as follows: only the Soviet Union and the United States are counted as great powers from 1946 to 1989, and only the United States is counted as a great power since 1990. See Reid Sarkees and Frank Wayma, Resort to War: A Data Guide to Inter-state, Extra-state, Intrastate, and Non-state Wars, 1816–2007 (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2010). 95252857500 952511430000 952518097500Table 2. Interstate Wars Involving Great Powers since 1816 952517208500MultipolarityBipolarityUnipolarity Great power years 791 88 22 Great power years at war 143 14 13 Percentage of great power years at war 18% 16% 59% Wars involving great powers 33 3 4 -3810018161000Incidence of war per great power year 4.2% 3.4% 18.2% SOURCES: Data are from the Correlates of War, ver. 4.0, dataset. See Reid Sarkees and Frank Wayma, Resort to War: A Data Guide to Inter-state, Extra-state, Intra-state, and Non-state -3810018097500 Wars, 1816–2007 (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2010). In sum, the argument that unipolarity makes for peace is heavily weighted toward interactions among the most powerful states in the system. This should come as no surprise given that Wohlforth makes a structural argument: peace flows from the unipolar structure of international politics, not from any particular characteristic of the unipole. 49 Structural analyses of the international system are usually centered on interactions between great powers. 50 As Waltz writes, “The theory, like the story, of international politics is written in terms of the great powers of an era.” 51 In the sections that follow, however I show that in the case of unipolarity, an investigation of its peacefulness must consider potential causes of conflict beyond interactions between the most important states in the system.
4,171
<h4><strong>Stats prove heg causes war</h4><p><u>Monteiro 12</u></strong> [Nuno, Asst. prof of political science at Yale, teaches IR theory and security studies, winter, “Unrest Assured: Why Unipolarity is Not Peaceful”, http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/ISEC_a_00064]</p><p>How well, then, does the argument that unipolar systems are peaceful account for the first two decades of unipolarity since the end of the Cold War? Table 1 presents a list of great powers divided into three periods: 1816 to 1945, [CHART OMITTED – PLACED AT BOTTOM OF PARAGRAPH] multipolarity; 1946 to 1989, bipolarity; and since 1990, unipolarity.46 Table 2 presents summary data about the incidence of war during each of these periods. <u><strong>Unipolarity is the most conflict prone </u></strong>of all the<u><strong> system</u></strong>s, according to at least two important criteria: the percentage of years that great powers spend at war and the incidence of war involving great powers. In multipolarity, 18 percent of great power years were spent at war. In bipolarity, the ratio is 16 percent. <u>In unipolarity</u>, however, a remarkable 59 percent of great power years until now were spent at war. This is by far the highest percentage in all three systems. Furthermore, during periods of multipolarity and bipolarity<u>, the probability </u>that<u> war involving a great power would break out</u> in any given year <u>was</u>, respectively, 4.2 percent and 3.4 percent. Under unipolarity, it is 18.2 percent—or more than <u><strong>four times higher.</u></strong>47 These figures provide no evidence that unipolarity is peaceful.48</p><p>Table 1. Great Powers since 1816</p><p>95254953000</p><p>Multipolarity Bipolarity <u>Unipolarity</p><p></u>3952875419100025146004127500</p><p>1181100-381000 DatesYears Dates Years Dates Years</p><p>95254953000</p><p>Austro-Hungarian 1816–1918 103</p><p> Empire</p><p>France 1816–1940 125</p><p>Prussia/Germany 1816–1918 / 124</p><p> 1925–45</p><p>Italy 1860–1943 84</p><p>Japan 1895–1945 51</p><p>United Kingdom 1816–1945 130</p><p>Russia / 1816–1917 / 126 1946–89 44</p><p> Soviet Union 1922–45</p><p>United States 1898–1945 48 1946–89 44 1990–2011 22</p><p>Total 791 88 22</p><p>95257620000</p><p>SOURCES: Data are from the Correlates of War, ver. 4.0, dataset, modified by the author as</p><p> follows: only the Soviet Union and the United States are counted as great powers from</p><p> 1946 to 1989, and only the United States is counted as a great power since 1990. See Reid</p><p> Sarkees and Frank Wayma, Resort to War: A Data Guide to Inter-state, Extra-state, Intrastate,</p><p> and Non-state Wars, 1816–2007 (Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2010).</p><p>95252857500</p><p>952511430000</p><p>952518097500Table 2. Interstate Wars Involving Great Powers since 1816</p><p>952517208500MultipolarityBipolarityUnipolarity</p><p>Great power years 791 88 22</p><p>Great power years at war 143 14 13</p><p>Percentage of great power years at war 18% 16% 59%</p><p>Wars involving great powers 33 3 4</p><p>-3810018161000Incidence of war per great power year 4.2% 3.4% 18.2%</p><p>SOURCES: Data are from the Correlates of War, ver. 4.0, dataset. See Reid Sarkees and Frank</p><p> Wayma, Resort to War: A Data Guide to Inter-state, Extra-state, Intra-state, and Non-state</p><p>-3810018097500 Wars, 1816–2007 <u>(Washington, D.C.: CQ Press, 2010).</p><p></u>In sum, the argument that unipolarity makes for peace is heavily weighted toward interactions among the most powerful states in the system. This should come as no surprise given that Wohlforth makes a structural argument: peace flows from the unipolar structure of international politics, not from any particular characteristic of the unipole. 49 Structural analyses of the international system are usually centered on interactions between great powers. 50 As Waltz writes, “The theory, like the story, of international politics is written in terms of the great powers of an era.” 51 In the sections that follow, however I show that in the case of unipolarity, an investigation of its peacefulness must consider potential causes of conflict beyond interactions between the most important states in the system.</p>
WTO
Heg/Trade
AT: Inevitable
16,080
81
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,291
The United States should amend the Interstate Horseracing Act to prohibit all online gambling on horseracing and make all online gambling in the United States illegal. The United States should pay annual compensation to Antigua and Barbuda for its online gambling including but not limited to the amount specified by the World Trade Organization.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The United States should amend the Interstate Horseracing Act to prohibit all online gambling on horseracing and make all online gambling in the United States illegal. The United States should pay annual compensation to Antigua and Barbuda for its online gambling including but not limited to the amount specified by the World Trade Organization. </h4>
null
null
CP
430,636
1
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,292
Anti-queer violence is a manifestation of futurism’s impetus to violence. The construction of a more perfect future demands a scapegoat upon which to impose society’s ills. Stigmatization demands extermination of the queer to ensure society’s successful reproduction.
Stavrakakis 99
Stavrakakis 99 (Yannis, Lacan and the Political, Visiting Professor, Department of Government, University of Essex, pages 99-100).
universalist fantasy took the form of a series of utopian constructions of a reconciled future society. The fragmentation of our cultural milieu entails the collapse of such grandiose fantasies talk about utopia is usually characterised by a certain ambiguity It is particularly the political experience of these last decades that led to the dislocation of utopian sensibilities and brought to the fore a novel appreciation of human finitude, together with a growing suspicion of all grandiose political projects and the meta-narratives traditionally associated with them by pessimism or even resignation. This is a result of the crisis in the dominant modality of our political imagination (meaning utopianism in its various forms) and of our inability to resolve this crisis in a productive way.3 In this chapter, I will try to show that Lacanian theory provides new angles through which we can reflect on our historical experience of utopia and reorient our political imagination beyond its suffocating strait-jacket. Let’s start our exploration with the most elementary of questions: what is the meaning of the current crisis of utopia? And is this crisis a development to be regretted or cherished? all utopias strive to negate the negative...in human existence; it is the negative in that existence which makes the idea of utopia necessary Utopia then is one of the possible responses to the ever-present negativity, to the real antagonism which is constitutive of human experience Utopias are images of future human communities in which these antagonisms and the dislocations fuelling them will be forever resolved, leading to a reconciled and harmonious world This final resolution is the essence of the utopian promise. every utopian fantasy construction needs a ‘scapegoat’ in order to constitute itself Every utopian fantasy produces its reverse and calls for its elimination. the beatific side of fantasy is coupled in utopian constructions with a horrific side, a paranoid need for a stigmatised scapegoat. The naivety of utopian structures is revealed when the realisation of this fantasy is attempted stigmatisation is followed by extermination This is not an accident It is inscribed in the structure of utopian constructions if utopia is based on the expulsion and repression of violence this is only because it owes its own creation to violence; it is sustained and fed by violence This repressed moment of violence resurfaces in the difference inscribed in the name utopia itself it resurfaces in the production of the figure of an enemy
universalist fantasy took the form of a series of utopian constructions of a reconciled future society. fragmentation of cultural milieu entails the collapse of such grandiose fantasies Utopias are images of future human communities in which antagonisms will be forever resolved, leading to a harmonious world every utopian fantasy construction needs a ‘scapegoat’ in order to constitute itself Every utopian fantasy produces its reverse and calls for its elimination. stigmatisation is followed by extermination. This is not an accident. It is inscribed in the structure of utopian constructions , if utopia is based on the expulsion and repression of violence this is only because it owes its own creation to violence; it is sustained and fed by violence This repressed moment of violence resurfaces in the production of the figure of an enemy.
Our age is clearly an age of social fragmentation, political disenchantment and open cynicism characterised by the decline of the political mutations of modern universalism—a universalism that, by replacing God with Reason, reoccupied the ground of a pre-modern aspiration to fully represent and master the essence and the totality of the real. On the political level this universalist fantasy took the form of a series of utopian constructions of a reconciled future society. The fragmentation of our present social terrain and cultural milieu entails the collapse of such grandiose fantasies.1 Today, talk about utopia is usually characterised by a certain ambiguity. For some, of course, utopian constructions are still seen as positive results of human creativity in the socio- political sphere: ‘utopia is the expression of a desire for a better way of being’ (Levitas, 1990:8). Other, more suspicious views, such as the one expressed in Marie Berneri’s book Journey through Utopia, warn—taking into account experiences like the Second World War—of the dangers entailed in trusting the idea of a perfect, ordered and regimented world. For some, instead of being ‘how can we realise our utopias?’, the crucial question has become ‘how can we prevent their final realisation?.... [How can] we return to a non-utopian society, less perfect and more free’ (Berdiaev in Berneri, 1971:309).2 It is particularly the political experience of these last decades that led to the dislocation of utopian sensibilities and brought to the fore a novel appreciation of human finitude, together with a growing suspicion of all grandiose political projects and the meta-narratives traditionally associated with them (Whitebook, 1995:75). All these developments, that is to say the crisis of the utopian imaginary, seem however to leave politics without its prime motivating force: the politics of today is a politics of aporia. In our current political terrain, hope seems to be replaced by pessimism or even resignation. This is a result of the crisis in the dominant modality of our political imagination (meaning utopianism in its various forms) and of our inability to resolve this crisis in a productive way.3 In this chapter, I will try to show that Lacanian theory provides new angles through which we can reflect on our historical experience of utopia and reorient our political imagination beyond its suffocating strait-jacket. Let’s start our exploration with the most elementary of questions: what is the meaning of the current crisis of utopia? And is this crisis a development to be regretted or cherished? In order to answer these questions it is crucial to enumerate the conditions of possibility and the basic characteristics of utopian thinking. First of all it seems that the need for utopian meaning arises in periods of increased uncertainty, social instability and conflict, when the element of the political subverts the fantasmatic stability of our political reality. Utopias are generated by the surfacing of grave antagonisms and dislocations in the social field. As Tillich has put it ‘all utopias strive to negate the negative...in human existence; it is the negative in that existence which makes the idea of utopia necessary’ (Tillich in Levitas, 1990:103). Utopia then is one of the possible responses to the ever-present negativity, to the real antagonism which is constitutive of human experience. Furthermore, from the time of More’s Utopia (1516) it is conceived as an answer to the negativity inherent in concrete political antagonism. What is, however, the exact nature of this response? Utopias are images of future human communities in which these antagonisms and the dislocations fuelling them (the element of the political) will be forever resolved, leading to a reconciled and harmonious world—it is not a coincidence that, among others, Fourier names his utopian community ‘Harmony’ and that the name of the Owenite utopian community in the New World was ‘New Harmony’. As Marin has put it, utopia sets in view an imaginary resolution to social contradiction; it is a simulacrum of synthesis which dissimulates social antagonism by projecting it onto a screen representing a harmonious and immobile equilibrium (Marin, 1984:61). This final resolution is the essence of the utopian promise. What I will try to do in this chapter is, first of all, to demonstrate the deeply problematic nature of utopian politics. Simply put, my argument will be that every utopian fantasy construction needs a ‘scapegoat’ in order to constitute itself—the Nazi utopian fantasy and the production of the ‘Jew’ is a good example, especially as pointed out in Žižek’s analysis.4 Every utopian fantasy produces its reverse and calls for its elimination. Put another way, the beatific side of fantasy is coupled in utopian constructions with a horrific side, a paranoid need for a stigmatised scapegoat. The naivety—and also the danger—of utopian structures is revealed when the realisation of this fantasy is attempted. It is then that we are brought close to the frightening kernel of the real: stigmatisation is followed by extermination. This is not an accident. It is inscribed in the structure of utopian constructions; it seems to be the way all fantasy constructions work. If in almost all utopian visions, violence and antagonism are eliminated, if utopia is based on the expulsion and repression of violence (this is its beatific side) this is only because it owes its own creation to violence; it is sustained and fed by violence (this is its horrific side). This repressed moment of violence resurfaces, as Marin points out, in the difference inscribed in the name utopia itself (Marin, 1984:110). What we shall argue is that it also resurfaces in the production of the figure of an enemy. To use a phrase enunciated by the utopianist Fourier, what is ‘driven out through the door comes back through the window’ (is not this a ‘precursor’ of Lacan’s dictum that ‘what is foreclosed in the symbolic reappears in the real’?—VII:131).5 The work of Norman Cohn and other historians permits the articulation of a genealogy of this manichean, equivalential way of understanding the world, from the great witch-hunt up to modern anti-Semitism, and Lacanian theory can provide valuable insights into any attempt to understand the logic behind this utopian operation—here the approach to fantasy developed in Chapter 2 will further demonstrate its potential in analysing our political experience. In fact, from the time of his unpublished seminar on The Formations of the Unconscious, Lacan identified the utopian dream of a perfectly functioning society as a highly problematic area (seminar of 18 June 1958).
6,719
<h4>Anti-queer violence is a manifestation of futurism’s impetus to violence. The construction of a more perfect future demands a scapegoat upon which to impose society’s ills. Stigmatization demands extermination of the queer to ensure society’s successful reproduction.</h4><p><strong>Stavrakakis 99</strong> (Yannis, Lacan and the Political, Visiting Professor, Department of Government, University of Essex, pages 99-100). </p><p>Our age is clearly an age of social fragmentation, political disenchantment and open cynicism characterised by the decline of the political mutations of modern universalism—a universalism that, by replacing God with Reason, reoccupied the ground of a pre-modern aspiration to fully represent and master the essence and the totality of the real. On the political level this<u> <mark>universalist fantasy took the form of a series of utopian constructions of a reconciled future society.</mark> The <mark>fragmentation of</mark> our </u>present social terrain and <u><mark>cultural milieu entails the collapse of such grandiose fantasies</u></mark>.1 Today, <u>talk about utopia is usually characterised by a certain ambiguity</u>. For some, of course, utopian constructions are still seen as positive results of human creativity in the socio- political sphere: ‘utopia is the expression of a desire for a better way of being’ (Levitas, 1990:8). Other, more suspicious views, such as the one expressed in Marie Berneri’s book Journey through Utopia, warn—taking into account experiences like the Second World War—of the dangers entailed in trusting the idea of a perfect, ordered and regimented world. For some, instead of being ‘how can we realise our utopias?’, the crucial question has become ‘how can we prevent their final realisation?.... [How can] we return to a non-utopian society, less perfect and more free’ (Berdiaev in Berneri, 1971:309).2 <u>It is particularly the political experience of these last decades that led to the dislocation of utopian sensibilities and brought to the fore a novel appreciation of human finitude, together with a growing suspicion of all grandiose political projects and the meta-narratives traditionally associated with them</u> (Whitebook, 1995:75). All these developments, that is to say the crisis of the utopian imaginary, seem however to leave politics without its prime motivating force: the politics of today is a politics of aporia. In our current political terrain, hope seems to be replaced <u>by pessimism or even resignation. This is a result of the crisis in the dominant modality of our political imagination (meaning utopianism in its various forms) and of our inability to resolve this crisis in a productive way.3 In this chapter, I will try to show that Lacanian theory provides new angles through which we can reflect on our historical experience of utopia and reorient our political imagination beyond its suffocating strait-jacket. Let’s start our exploration with the most elementary of questions: what is the meaning of the current crisis of utopia? And is this crisis a development to be regretted or cherished?</p><p></u>In order to answer these questions it is crucial to enumerate the conditions of possibility and the basic characteristics of utopian thinking. First of all it seems that the need for utopian meaning arises in periods of increased uncertainty, social instability and conflict, when the element of the political subverts the fantasmatic stability of our political reality. Utopias are generated by the surfacing of grave antagonisms and dislocations in the social field. As Tillich has put it ‘<u>all utopias strive to negate the negative...in human existence; it is the negative in that existence which makes the idea of utopia necessary</u>’ (Tillich in Levitas, 1990:103). <u>Utopia</u> <u>then is one of the possible responses to the ever-present negativity, to the real antagonism which is constitutive of human experience</u>. Furthermore, from the time of More’s Utopia (1516) it is conceived as an answer to the negativity inherent in concrete political antagonism. What is, however, the exact nature of this response? <u><mark>Utopias are images of future human communities in which </mark>these <mark>antagonisms </mark>and the dislocations fuelling them</u> (the element of the political) <u><mark>will be forever resolved, leading to a </mark>reconciled and <mark>harmonious world</u></mark>—it is not a coincidence that, among others, Fourier names his utopian community ‘Harmony’ and that the name of the Owenite utopian community in the New World was ‘New Harmony’. As Marin has put it, utopia sets in view an imaginary resolution to social contradiction; it is a simulacrum of synthesis which dissimulates social antagonism by projecting it onto a screen representing a harmonious and immobile equilibrium (Marin, 1984:61). <u>This final resolution is the essence of the utopian promise. </p><p></u>What I will try to do in this chapter is, first of all, to demonstrate the deeply problematic nature of utopian politics. Simply put, my argument will be that <u><strong><mark>every utopian fantasy construction needs a ‘scapegoat’ in order to constitute itself</u></strong></mark>—the Nazi utopian fantasy and the production of the ‘Jew’ is a good example, especially as pointed out in Žižek’s analysis.4 <u><mark>Every utopian fantasy produces its reverse and calls for its elimination.</mark> </u>Put another way, <u>the beatific side of fantasy is coupled in utopian constructions with a horrific side, a paranoid need for a stigmatised scapegoat. The naivety</u>—and also the danger—<u>of utopian structures is revealed when the realisation of this fantasy is attempted</u>. It is then that we are brought close to the frightening kernel of the real: <u><strong><mark>stigmatisation is followed by extermination</u></strong>. <u><strong>This is not an accident</u></strong>. <u><strong>It is inscribed in the structure of utopian constructions</u></strong></mark>; it seems to be the way all fantasy constructions work. If in almost all utopian visions, violence and antagonism are eliminated<mark>, <u>if utopia is based on the expulsion and repression of violence</u></mark> (this is its beatific side) <u><mark>this is only because it owes its own creation to violence; it is sustained and fed by violence</u></mark> (this is its horrific side). <u><mark>This repressed moment of violence resurfaces</u></mark>, as Marin points out, <u>in the difference inscribed in the name utopia itself</u> (Marin, 1984:110). What we shall argue is that <u>it</u> also <u>resurfaces <mark>in the production of the figure of an enemy</u>.</mark> To use a phrase enunciated by the utopianist Fourier, what is ‘driven out through the door comes back through the window’ (is not this a ‘precursor’ of Lacan’s dictum that ‘what is foreclosed in the symbolic reappears in the real’?—VII:131).5 The work of Norman Cohn and other historians permits the articulation of a genealogy of this manichean, equivalential way of understanding the world, from the great witch-hunt up to modern anti-Semitism, and Lacanian theory can provide valuable insights into any attempt to understand the logic behind this utopian operation—here the approach to fantasy developed in Chapter 2 will further demonstrate its potential in analysing our political experience. In fact, from the time of his unpublished seminar on The Formations of the Unconscious, Lacan identified the utopian dream of a perfectly functioning society as a highly problematic area (seminar of 18 June 1958).</p>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
85,390
139
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,293
The United States Supreme Court should apply a clear statement rule to enforcement of provisions of the Controlled Substances Act relating to marihuana, finding that it does not contain a clear statement intended to preempt state marihuana laws nor a clear statement authorizing commandeering of state resources for enforcement of federal marihuana laws. The United States Attorney General should offer each state government a contract stipulating that the Justice Department will exercise prosecutorial discretion in its enforcement of federal marihuana laws, specifically taking no enforcement action against entities clearly following the marihuana laws of that state. The United States federal government should prohibit the use of federal funds to penalize banks and credit unions for providing financial services to state-licensed marihuana businesses.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>The United States Supreme Court should apply a clear statement rule to enforcement of provisions of the Controlled Substances Act relating to marihuana, finding that it does not contain a clear statement intended to preempt state marihuana laws nor a clear statement authorizing commandeering of state resources for enforcement of federal marihuana laws. The United States Attorney General should offer each state government a contract stipulating that the Justice Department will exercise prosecutorial discretion in its enforcement of federal marihuana laws, specifically taking no enforcement action against entities clearly following the marihuana laws of that state. The United States federal government should prohibit the use of federal funds to penalize banks and credit unions for providing financial services to state-licensed marihuana businesses.</h4>
null
null
Counteradvocacy
430,638
1
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,294
Anti-queer violence is a manifestation of futurism’s impetus to violence. The construction of a more perfect future demands a scapegoat upon which to impose society’s ills. Stigmatization demands extermination of the queer to ensure society’s successful reproduction.
Stavrakakis 99
Stavrakakis 99 (Yannis, Lacan and the Political, Visiting Professor, Department of Government, University of Essex, pages 99-100).
universalist fantasy took the form of a series of utopian constructions of a reconciled future society. The fragmentation of our cultural milieu entails the collapse of such grandiose fantasies talk about utopia is usually characterised by a certain ambiguity It is particularly the political experience of these last decades that led to the dislocation of utopian sensibilities and brought to the fore a novel appreciation of human finitude, together with a growing suspicion of all grandiose political projects and the meta-narratives traditionally associated with them (Whitebook, 1995:75). All these developments, that is to say the crisis of the utopian imaginary, seem however to leave politics without its prime motivating force: the politics of today is a politics of aporia. In our current political terrain, hope seems to be replaced by pessimism or even resignation. This is a result of the crisis in the dominant modality of our political imagination (meaning utopianism in its various forms) and of our inability to resolve this crisis in a productive way.3 In this chapter, I will try to show that Lacanian theory provides new angles through which we can reflect on our historical experience of utopia and reorient our political imagination beyond its suffocating strait-jacket. Let’s start our exploration with the most elementary of questions: what is the meaning of the current crisis of utopia? And is this crisis a development to be regretted or cherished? all utopias strive to negate the negative...in human existence; it is the negative in that existence which makes the idea of utopia necessary Utopia then is one of the possible responses to the ever-present negativity, to the real antagonism which is constitutive of human experience Utopias are images of future human communities in which these antagonisms and the dislocations fuelling them will be forever resolved, leading to a reconciled and harmonious world This final resolution is the essence of the utopian promise. every utopian fantasy construction needs a ‘scapegoat’ in order to constitute itself Every utopian fantasy produces its reverse and calls for its elimination. the beatific side of fantasy is coupled in utopian constructions with a horrific side, a paranoid need for a stigmatised scapegoat. The naivety of utopian structures is revealed when the realisation of this fantasy is attempted stigmatisation is followed by extermination This is not an accident It is inscribed in the structure of utopian constructions if utopia is based on the expulsion and repression of violence this is only because it owes its own creation to violence; it is sustained and fed by violence This repressed moment of violence resurfaces in the difference inscribed in the name utopia itself it resurfaces in the production of the figure of an enemy
universalist fantasy took the form of a series of utopian constructions of a reconciled future society. fragmentation of cultural milieu entails the collapse of such grandiose fantasies Utopias are images of future human communities in which antagonisms will be forever resolved, leading to a harmonious world every utopian fantasy construction needs a ‘scapegoat’ in order to constitute itself Every utopian fantasy produces its reverse and calls for its elimination. stigmatisation is followed by extermination. This is not an accident. It is inscribed in the structure of utopian constructions , if utopia is based on the expulsion and repression of violence this is only because it owes its own creation to violence; it is sustained and fed by violence This repressed moment of violence resurfaces in the production of the figure of an enemy.
Our age is clearly an age of social fragmentation, political disenchantment and open cynicism characterised by the decline of the political mutations of modern universalism—a universalism that, by replacing God with Reason, reoccupied the ground of a pre-modern aspiration to fully represent and master the essence and the totality of the real. On the political level this universalist fantasy took the form of a series of utopian constructions of a reconciled future society. The fragmentation of our present social terrain and cultural milieu entails the collapse of such grandiose fantasies.1 Today, talk about utopia is usually characterised by a certain ambiguity. For some, of course, utopian constructions are still seen as positive results of human creativity in the socio- political sphere: ‘utopia is the expression of a desire for a better way of being’ (Levitas, 1990:8). Other, more suspicious views, such as the one expressed in Marie Berneri’s book Journey through Utopia, warn—taking into account experiences like the Second World War—of the dangers entailed in trusting the idea of a perfect, ordered and regimented world. For some, instead of being ‘how can we realise our utopias?’, the crucial question has become ‘how can we prevent their final realisation?.... [How can] we return to a non-utopian society, less perfect and more free’ (Berdiaev in Berneri, 1971:309).2 It is particularly the political experience of these last decades that led to the dislocation of utopian sensibilities and brought to the fore a novel appreciation of human finitude, together with a growing suspicion of all grandiose political projects and the meta-narratives traditionally associated with them (Whitebook, 1995:75). All these developments, that is to say the crisis of the utopian imaginary, seem however to leave politics without its prime motivating force: the politics of today is a politics of aporia. In our current political terrain, hope seems to be replaced by pessimism or even resignation. This is a result of the crisis in the dominant modality of our political imagination (meaning utopianism in its various forms) and of our inability to resolve this crisis in a productive way.3 In this chapter, I will try to show that Lacanian theory provides new angles through which we can reflect on our historical experience of utopia and reorient our political imagination beyond its suffocating strait-jacket. Let’s start our exploration with the most elementary of questions: what is the meaning of the current crisis of utopia? And is this crisis a development to be regretted or cherished? In order to answer these questions it is crucial to enumerate the conditions of possibility and the basic characteristics of utopian thinking. First of all it seems that the need for utopian meaning arises in periods of increased uncertainty, social instability and conflict, when the element of the political subverts the fantasmatic stability of our political reality. Utopias are generated by the surfacing of grave antagonisms and dislocations in the social field. As Tillich has put it ‘all utopias strive to negate the negative...in human existence; it is the negative in that existence which makes the idea of utopia necessary’ (Tillich in Levitas, 1990:103). Utopia then is one of the possible responses to the ever-present negativity, to the real antagonism which is constitutive of human experience. Furthermore, from the time of More’s Utopia (1516) it is conceived as an answer to the negativity inherent in concrete political antagonism. What is, however, the exact nature of this response? Utopias are images of future human communities in which these antagonisms and the dislocations fuelling them (the element of the political) will be forever resolved, leading to a reconciled and harmonious world—it is not a coincidence that, among others, Fourier names his utopian community ‘Harmony’ and that the name of the Owenite utopian community in the New World was ‘New Harmony’. As Marin has put it, utopia sets in view an imaginary resolution to social contradiction; it is a simulacrum of synthesis which dissimulates social antagonism by projecting it onto a screen representing a harmonious and immobile equilibrium (Marin, 1984:61). This final resolution is the essence of the utopian promise. What I will try to do in this chapter is, first of all, to demonstrate the deeply problematic nature of utopian politics. Simply put, my argument will be that every utopian fantasy construction needs a ‘scapegoat’ in order to constitute itself—the Nazi utopian fantasy and the production of the ‘Jew’ is a good example, especially as pointed out in Žižek’s analysis.4 Every utopian fantasy produces its reverse and calls for its elimination. Put another way, the beatific side of fantasy is coupled in utopian constructions with a horrific side, a paranoid need for a stigmatised scapegoat. The naivety—and also the danger—of utopian structures is revealed when the realisation of this fantasy is attempted. It is then that we are brought close to the frightening kernel of the real: stigmatisation is followed by extermination. This is not an accident. It is inscribed in the structure of utopian constructions; it seems to be the way all fantasy constructions work. If in almost all utopian visions, violence and antagonism are eliminated, if utopia is based on the expulsion and repression of violence (this is its beatific side) this is only because it owes its own creation to violence; it is sustained and fed by violence (this is its horrific side). This repressed moment of violence resurfaces, as Marin points out, in the difference inscribed in the name utopia itself (Marin, 1984:110). What we shall argue is that it also resurfaces in the production of the figure of an enemy. To use a phrase enunciated by the utopianist Fourier, what is ‘driven out through the door comes back through the window’ (is not this a ‘precursor’ of Lacan’s dictum that ‘what is foreclosed in the symbolic reappears in the real’?—VII:131).5 The work of Norman Cohn and other historians permits the articulation of a genealogy of this manichean, equivalential way of understanding the world, from the great witch-hunt up to modern anti-Semitism, and Lacanian theory can provide valuable insights into any attempt to understand the logic behind this utopian operation—here the approach to fantasy developed in Chapter 2 will further demonstrate its potential in analysing our political experience. In fact, from the time of his unpublished seminar on The Formations of the Unconscious, Lacan identified the utopian dream of a perfectly functioning society as a highly problematic area (seminar of 18 June 1958).
6,719
<h4>Anti-queer violence is a manifestation of futurism’s impetus to violence. The construction of a more perfect future demands a scapegoat upon which to impose society’s ills. Stigmatization demands extermination of the queer to ensure society’s successful reproduction.</h4><p><strong>Stavrakakis 99</strong> (Yannis, Lacan and the Political, Visiting Professor, Department of Government, University of Essex, pages 99-100). </p><p>Our age is clearly an age of social fragmentation, political disenchantment and open cynicism characterised by the decline of the political mutations of modern universalism—a universalism that, by replacing God with Reason, reoccupied the ground of a pre-modern aspiration to fully represent and master the essence and the totality of the real. On the political level this<u> <mark>universalist fantasy took the form of a series of utopian constructions of a reconciled future society.</mark> The <mark>fragmentation of</mark> our </u>present social terrain and <u><mark>cultural milieu entails the collapse of such grandiose fantasies</u></mark>.1 Today, <u>talk about utopia is usually characterised by a certain ambiguity</u>. For some, of course, utopian constructions are still seen as positive results of human creativity in the socio- political sphere: ‘utopia is the expression of a desire for a better way of being’ (Levitas, 1990:8). Other, more suspicious views, such as the one expressed in Marie Berneri’s book Journey through Utopia, warn—taking into account experiences like the Second World War—of the dangers entailed in trusting the idea of a perfect, ordered and regimented world. For some, instead of being ‘how can we realise our utopias?’, the crucial question has become ‘how can we prevent their final realisation?.... [How can] we return to a non-utopian society, less perfect and more free’ (Berdiaev in Berneri, 1971:309).2 <u>It is particularly the political experience of these last decades that led to the dislocation of utopian sensibilities and brought to the fore a novel appreciation of human finitude, together with a growing suspicion of all grandiose political projects and the meta-narratives traditionally associated with them (Whitebook, 1995:75). All these developments, that is to say the crisis of the utopian imaginary, seem however to leave politics without its prime motivating force: the politics of today is a politics of aporia. In our current political terrain, hope seems to be replaced by pessimism or even resignation. This is a result of the crisis in the dominant modality of our political imagination (meaning utopianism in its various forms) and of our inability to resolve this crisis in a productive way.3 In this chapter, I will try to show that Lacanian theory provides new angles through which we can reflect on our historical experience of utopia and reorient our political imagination beyond its suffocating strait-jacket. Let’s start our exploration with the most elementary of questions: what is the meaning of the current crisis of utopia? And is this crisis a development to be regretted or cherished?</p><p></u>In order to answer these questions it is crucial to enumerate the conditions of possibility and the basic characteristics of utopian thinking. First of all it seems that the need for utopian meaning arises in periods of increased uncertainty, social instability and conflict, when the element of the political subverts the fantasmatic stability of our political reality. Utopias are generated by the surfacing of grave antagonisms and dislocations in the social field. As Tillich has put it ‘<u>all utopias strive to negate the negative...in human existence; it is the negative in that existence which makes the idea of utopia necessary</u>’ (Tillich in Levitas, 1990:103). <u>Utopia</u> <u>then is one of the possible responses to the ever-present negativity, to the real antagonism which is constitutive of human experience</u>. Furthermore, from the time of More’s Utopia (1516) it is conceived as an answer to the negativity inherent in concrete political antagonism. What is, however, the exact nature of this response? <u><mark>Utopias are images of future human communities in which </mark>these <mark>antagonisms </mark>and the dislocations fuelling them</u> (the element of the political) <u><mark>will be forever resolved, leading to a </mark>reconciled and <mark>harmonious world</u></mark>—it is not a coincidence that, among others, Fourier names his utopian community ‘Harmony’ and that the name of the Owenite utopian community in the New World was ‘New Harmony’. As Marin has put it, utopia sets in view an imaginary resolution to social contradiction; it is a simulacrum of synthesis which dissimulates social antagonism by projecting it onto a screen representing a harmonious and immobile equilibrium (Marin, 1984:61). <u>This final resolution is the essence of the utopian promise. </p><p></u>What I will try to do in this chapter is, first of all, to demonstrate the deeply problematic nature of utopian politics. Simply put, my argument will be that <u><strong><mark>every utopian fantasy construction needs a ‘scapegoat’ in order to constitute itself</u></strong></mark>—the Nazi utopian fantasy and the production of the ‘Jew’ is a good example, especially as pointed out in Žižek’s analysis.4 <u><mark>Every utopian fantasy produces its reverse and calls for its elimination.</mark> </u>Put another way, <u>the beatific side of fantasy is coupled in utopian constructions with a horrific side, a paranoid need for a stigmatised scapegoat. The naivety</u>—and also the danger—<u>of utopian structures is revealed when the realisation of this fantasy is attempted</u>. It is then that we are brought close to the frightening kernel of the real: <u><strong><mark>stigmatisation is followed by extermination</u></strong>. <u><strong>This is not an accident</u></strong>. <u><strong>It is inscribed in the structure of utopian constructions</u></strong></mark>; it seems to be the way all fantasy constructions work. If in almost all utopian visions, violence and antagonism are eliminated<mark>, <u>if utopia is based on the expulsion and repression of violence</u></mark> (this is its beatific side) <u><mark>this is only because it owes its own creation to violence; it is sustained and fed by violence</u></mark> (this is its horrific side). <u><mark>This repressed moment of violence resurfaces</u></mark>, as Marin points out, <u>in the difference inscribed in the name utopia itself</u> (Marin, 1984:110). What we shall argue is that <u>it</u> also <u>resurfaces <mark>in the production of the figure of an enemy</u>.</mark> To use a phrase enunciated by the utopianist Fourier, what is ‘driven out through the door comes back through the window’ (is not this a ‘precursor’ of Lacan’s dictum that ‘what is foreclosed in the symbolic reappears in the real’?—VII:131).5 The work of Norman Cohn and other historians permits the articulation of a genealogy of this manichean, equivalential way of understanding the world, from the great witch-hunt up to modern anti-Semitism, and Lacanian theory can provide valuable insights into any attempt to understand the logic behind this utopian operation—here the approach to fantasy developed in Chapter 2 will further demonstrate its potential in analysing our political experience. In fact, from the time of his unpublished seminar on The Formations of the Unconscious, Lacan identified the utopian dream of a perfectly functioning society as a highly problematic area (seminar of 18 June 1958).</p>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
85,390
139
17,077
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
565,297
A
tournament
4
Binghamton Cepin-Sehgal
Baker, Webster Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,295
The illicit market exploits in a way like slavery
Delmonico 3
Delmonico 3 Francis L. Delmonico, Director of the Renal Transplantation Unit at Massachusetts
the exploitation of organ sellers veers dangerously close to human slavery The pressures put by organ brokers upon the desperation of the world’s dislocated, refugee, and poorest populations to provide the scarce commodities reveals the limits of argu- ments based solely on individual autonomy. the pressure of organ brokers upon the poor makes their decision to sell an organ anything but a free and autonomous choice. The most disturbing issue of organ sales is the formation of an economic underclass of organ donors throughout the world to serve the wealthy. they are indifferent to the social and individual pathologies that markets in kidneys and other body parts produce, such as the documented evidence of postsurgery medical complications, chronic pain, psychological problems, unemployment, decreased earning power, social ostracism, and social stigma faced by kidney sellers in many parts of the world
exploitation of organ sellers veers dangerously close to human slavery pressures put by organ brokers provide the scarce commodities reveals the limits of argu- ments based solely on individual autonomy. makes their decision to sell an organ anything but a free and autonomous choice formation of an economic underclass of organ donors throughout the world to serve the wealthy they are indifferent to the social and individual pathologies that markets in kidneys and other body parts produce medical complications, chronic pain, psychological problems, unemployment, decreased earning power, social ostracism, and social stigma faced by kidney sellers
General Hospital, the medical director at the New England Organ Bank, and Professor of Surgery at Harvard Medical School; and Nancy Scheper-Hughes.Director of Organs Watch and Professor of Medical Anthropology at the University of California at Berkeley Zygon, vol. 38, no. 3 (September 2003) WHY WE SHOULD NOT PAY FOR HUMAN ORGANS Ebsco Although class distinctions are an almost naturalized part of social life in all complex societies, in this particular instance the exploitation of organ sellers veers dangerously close to human slavery, as argued by Giovanni Berlinguer (Berlinguer and Garrafa 1996). The pressures put by organ brokers upon the desperation of the world’s dislocated, refugee, and poorest populations to provide the scarce commodities reveals the limits of argu- ments based solely on individual autonomy. Yes, even the poorest people of the world “make choices,” but they do not make these freely or under social or economic conditions of their own making. Further, the pressure of organ brokers upon the poor makes their decision to sell an organ anything but a free and autonomous choice. These secular arguments reach a conclusion similar to one derived from Christian morality—that the sale of human organs is unethical. The most disturbing issue of organ sales to both Christian and secular ethicists is the formation of an economic underclass of organ donors throughout the world to serve the wealthy. This is not to suggest that proponents of organ sales are in favor of exploiting the poor but, rather, that they are indifferent to the social and individual pathologies that markets in kidneys and other body parts produce, such as the documented evidence of postsurgery medical complications, chronic pain, psychological problems, unemployment, decreased earning power, social ostracism, and social stigma faced by kidney sellers in many parts of the world (see Zargooshi 2002; Jimenez and Scheper-Hughes 2002a; Ram 2002).
1,963
<h4><strong>The illicit market exploits in a way like slavery</h4><p>Delmonico 3 </strong>Francis L. Delmonico, Director of the Renal Transplantation Unit at Massachusetts</p><p>General Hospital, the medical director at the New England Organ Bank, and Professor of</p><p>Surgery at Harvard Medical School; and Nancy Scheper-Hughes.Director of Organs Watch and Professor of Medical Anthropology at the University of California at Berkeley Zygon, vol. 38, no. 3 (September 2003)</p><p>WHY WE SHOULD NOT PAY FOR HUMAN ORGANS Ebsco </p><p>Although class distinctions are an almost naturalized part of social life in all complex societies, in this particular instance <u>the <mark>exploitation of organ sellers veers dangerously close to human slavery</u></mark>, as argued by Giovanni Berlinguer (Berlinguer and Garrafa 1996). <u>The <mark>pressures put by organ brokers</mark> upon the desperation of the world’s dislocated, refugee, and poorest populations to <mark>provide the scarce commodities reveals the limits of argu- ments based solely on individual autonomy.</mark> </u>Yes, even the poorest people of the world “make choices,” but they do not make these freely or under social or economic conditions of their own making. Further, <u>the pressure of organ brokers upon the poor <mark>makes their decision to sell an organ anything but a free and autonomous choice</mark>. </u>These secular arguments reach a conclusion similar to one derived from Christian morality—that the sale of human organs is unethical. <u>The most disturbing issue of organ sales </u>to both Christian and secular ethicists <u>is the <mark>formation of an economic underclass of organ donors throughout the world to serve the wealthy</mark>.</u> This is not to suggest that proponents of organ sales are in favor of exploiting the poor but, rather, that <u><mark>they are indifferent to the social and individual pathologies that markets in kidneys and other body parts produce</mark>, such as the documented evidence of postsurgery <mark>medical complications, chronic pain, psychological problems, unemployment, decreased earning power, social ostracism, and social stigma faced by kidney sellers</mark> in many parts of the world</u><strong> (see Zargooshi 2002; Jimenez and Scheper-Hughes 2002a; Ram 2002). </p></strong>
null
null
Contention 2 is the Illegal market
430,260
15
17,075
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
565,295
A
Navy
1
George Mason Call-Mohney
Steiner
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Navy-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,296
Reject arguments that isolate individuals away from their social context - their emphasis on liberty is oblivious to the constrictions that make individuals come to the “free” choice of suicide.
Hansen 12.
Hansen 12. Sarah Hansen (Asst. Teaching Prof. of Phil. @ Drexel Univ.; Ph.D. Vanderbilt Univ., M.A. Vanderbilt Univ.). “Terri Schiavo and the language of biopolitics,” International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 5.1 (Spring 2012). Page 98-99 //dtac – brackets and ellipses in original
By emphasizing liberty, Annas distinguishes “good life” and mere life. The protections of the state should be distributed according to expressions of freedom and self-determination While Annas and Perry “err on the side of liberty threats to freedom, integrity, and dignity appear everywhere in evidence as the task of controlling and shaping life dominates, if not defines, the ends of politics. The regulatory functions of government do not reflect the flourishing of individual self-determination and the integrity of bodily borders. Rather, they illustrate the “ubiquity of dependence not only vertically, across a life span, but horizontally, across a population” as “an individual’s bodily boundaries overlap exactly and precisely with . . . political boundaries” Annas and Perry suggest that the value of freedom take hold prescriptively the atomistic account of individual rights that underlies the call to “err on the side of liberty” is problematic “[atomistic] arguments about a right to life and a right to die will inevitably be oblivious to the factors that help determine when and how we die” By emphasizing individuals over social groups or populations, Annas and Perry implicitly reinforce and obscure the broad and differential ways in which the “quality of life” is “in question,” and often in peril, beyond and before end-of-life decisions
By emphasizing liberty, Annas distinguishes good life” and mere life threats to freedom and dignity appear everywhere The regulatory functions of government do not reflect the flourishing of individual self-determination , they illustrate the “ubiquity of dependence the atomistic account of individual rights that underlies the call to “err on the side of liberty” is problematic atomistic] arguments about right to die will inevitably be oblivious to the factors that help determine when and how we die By emphasizing individuals over groups Annas reinforce and obscure the broad and differential ways in which the “quality of life” is peril, beyond and before end-of-life decisions
In opposition to Richard Land, Randall Terry, and various proponents of the “sanctity-of-life” ethic, those “infected with a ‘quality of life’ ethic” argued for the removal of Terri Schiavo’s feeding tube. The “quality-of-life” position resituates the value of life, shifting from intrinsic sanctity to the value of human freedom and dignity. Referencing and responding to President George W. Bush’s call to “err on the side of life” wherever there are “serious doubts,” George Annas articulates this line of argument: “Erring on the side of life” in this context often results in violating a person’s body and human dignity in a way few would want for themselves. In such situations, erring on the side of liberty—specifically the patient’s right to decide on treatment—is more consistent with American values and our constitutional traditions. (Annas 2006, 1714) By emphasizing liberty, Annas distinguishes rather than equates the “good life” and mere life. The protections of the state should be distributed according to expressions of freedom and self-determination, not, as the “sanctity-of-life” position would have it, according to the motion of organs and the endurance of bodily functions. On Annas’s track, the decisions of the Florida judiciary can be affirmed because, in Joshua Perry’s words, the courts were equipped “to best determine Mrs. Schiavo’s beliefs regarding the notion of life’s sanctity and whether she would have personally determined to receive life-sustaining treatments that held no promise for restoring her to health or even consciousness” (Perry 2006, 628). Beyond the question of whether her condition was “terminal” and irreversible, the entirety of the Florida adjudications focused on “delineating and exercising Terri Schiavo’s personal autonomy rights” (Perry 2006, 628). While Annas and Perry “err on the side of liberty,” it is not clear that this choice is consistent with contemporary American values. In the United States today, a life understood to be free and a body understood to have integrity are likely to be just as entangled in the regulatory government and sciences of life as Terri Schiavo’s. In biopolitical contexts, threats to freedom, integrity, and dignity appear everywhere in evidence as the task of controlling and shaping life dominates, if not defines, the ends of politics. The regulatory functions of government do not reflect the flourishing of individual self-determination and the integrity of bodily borders. Rather, they illustrate the “ubiquity of dependence not only vertically, across a life span, but horizontally, across a population” as “an individual’s bodily boundaries overlap exactly and precisely with . . . political boundaries” (Parmet 2006, 19; Miller 2007, 162). To be sure, Annas and Perry suggest that the value of freedom take hold prescriptively if not descriptively. However, the atomistic account of individual rights that underlies the call to “err on the side of liberty” is problematic. As Wendy Parmet has argued, “[atomistic] arguments about a right to life and a right to die will inevitably be oblivious to the factors that help determine when and how we die” (Parmet 2006, 26). By emphasizing individuals over social groups or populations, Annas and Perry implicitly reinforce and obscure the broad and differential ways in which the “quality of life” is “in question,” and often in peril, beyond and before end-of-life decisions.
3,430
<h4><strong>Reject arguments that isolate individuals away from their social context - their emphasis on liberty is oblivious to the constrictions that make individuals come to the “free” choice of suicide.</h4><p>Hansen 12.</p><p></strong>Sarah Hansen (Asst. Teaching Prof. of Phil. @ Drexel Univ.; Ph.D. Vanderbilt Univ., M.A. Vanderbilt Univ.). “Terri Schiavo and the language of biopolitics,” International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 5.1 (Spring 2012). Page 98-99 //dtac – <u><strong>brackets and ellipses in original</p><p></u></strong>In opposition to Richard Land, Randall Terry, and various proponents of the “sanctity-of-life” ethic, those “infected with a ‘quality of life’ ethic” argued for the removal of Terri Schiavo’s feeding tube. The “quality-of-life” position resituates the value of life, shifting from intrinsic sanctity to the value of human freedom and dignity. Referencing and responding to President George W. Bush’s call to “err on the side of life” wherever there are “serious doubts,” George Annas articulates this line of argument: “Erring on the side of life” in this context often results in violating a person’s body and human dignity in a way few would want for themselves. In such situations, erring on the side of liberty—specifically the patient’s right to decide on treatment—is more consistent with American values and our constitutional traditions. (Annas 2006, 1714) <u><strong><mark>By emphasizing liberty, Annas distinguishes</u></strong></mark> rather than equates the <u><strong>“<mark>good life” and mere life</mark>. The protections of the state should be distributed according to expressions of freedom and self-determination</u></strong>, not, as the “sanctity-of-life” position would have it, according to the motion of organs and the endurance of bodily functions. On Annas’s track, the decisions of the Florida judiciary can be affirmed because, in Joshua Perry’s words, the courts were equipped “to best determine Mrs. Schiavo’s beliefs regarding the notion of life’s sanctity and whether she would have personally determined to receive life-sustaining treatments that held no promise for restoring her to health or even consciousness” (Perry 2006, 628). Beyond the question of whether her condition was “terminal” and irreversible, the entirety of the Florida adjudications focused on “delineating and exercising Terri Schiavo’s personal autonomy rights” (Perry 2006, 628). <u>While Annas and Perry “err on the side of liberty</u>,” it is not clear that this choice is consistent with contemporary American values. In the United States today, a life understood to be free and a body understood to have integrity are likely to be just as entangled in the regulatory government and sciences of life as Terri Schiavo’s. In biopolitical contexts, <u><strong><mark>threats to freedom</mark>, integrity, <mark>and dignity appear everywhere</mark> in evidence as the task of controlling and shaping life dominates, if not defines, the ends of politics. </strong><mark>The regulatory functions of government do not reflect the flourishing of individual self-determination</mark> and the integrity of bodily borders. Rather<mark>, they illustrate the “ubiquity of dependence</mark> not only vertically, across a life span, but horizontally, across a population” as “an individual’s bodily boundaries overlap exactly and precisely with . . . political boundaries”</u> (Parmet 2006, 19; Miller 2007, 162). To be sure, <u>Annas and Perry suggest that the value of freedom take hold prescriptively</u> if not descriptively. However, <u><strong><mark>the atomistic account of individual</mark> <mark>rights that underlies the call to “err on the side of liberty” is problematic</u></strong></mark>. As Wendy Parmet has argued, <u><strong>“[<mark>atomistic] arguments about</mark> a right to life and a <mark>right to die will inevitably be</mark> <mark>oblivious to the factors that help determine when and how we die</mark>”</u></strong> (Parmet 2006, 26). <u><strong><mark>By emphasizing individuals over</mark> social <mark>groups</mark> or populations, <mark>Annas</mark> and Perry implicitly <mark>reinforce and obscure the broad and differential ways in which the “quality of life” is</mark> “in question,” and often in <mark>peril, beyond and before end-of-life decisions</u></mark>.</p></strong>
null
null
Case
430,639
3
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,297
Prefer the affirmative’s impacts to highly specific long term disadvantages – cognitive bias means you will think their impact is better than it really is Yudkowsky 06 [Eliezer, 8/31/2006. Singularity Institute for Artificial Intelligence Palo Alto, CA. “Cognitive biases potentially affecting judgment of global risks, Forthcoming in Global Catastrophic Risks, eds. Nick Bostrom and Milan Cirkovic, singinst.org/upload/cognitive-biases.pdf.
Yudkowsky 06
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Prefer the affirmative’s impacts to highly specific long term disadvantages – cognitive bias means you will think their impact is better than it really is</h4><p><strong>Yudkowsky</strong> <strong>06</strong> [Eliezer, 8/31/2006. Singularity Institute for Artificial Intelligence Palo Alto, CA. “Cognitive biases potentially affecting judgment of global risks, Forthcoming in Global Catastrophic Risks, eds. Nick Bostrom and Milan Cirkovic, singinst.org/upload/cognitive-biases.pdf.</p>
2AC
Case
Framing
430,640
1
17,071
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
565,299
A
Ndt
3
Gonzaga Newton-Spraker
Deming, Gramzinski, Susko
1AC - Organs (Shortages Illegal Markets) 1NC - T-Sales Property Rights DA TPA DA Tax Incentives CP 2NC - CP Case 1NR - Property Rights DA 2NR - DA Case
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-Ndt-Round3.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,298
Physicians suck at their jobs, and you can always just stop consuming in order to die.
Miller 98
Miller 98 Franklin G. Miller, PhD, Diane Meier, MD, Ann Intern Med. 1998;128(7):559-562., “Voluntary Death: A Comparison of Terminal Dehydration and Physician-Assisted Suicide”, http://annals.org/article.aspx?articleid=711286 //jchen
physician-assisted suicide should be considered in light of voluntary death. terminal dehydration. By voluntarily forgoing food and water, competent patients with terminal or incurable illness can escape intolerable, irremediable conditions without requiring transformation of the law and medical ethics. Terminal dehydration offers substantial advantages over physician-assisted suicide with respect to self-determination, access, professional integrity, and social implications That a legal option of physician-assisted suicide could become a “quick fix” for dying patients is a serious risk in view of the built-in incentives of managed care plans to limit treatment, coupled with the documented deficiencies of physicians in providing adequate pain relief and diagnosing and treating depression in terminally ill patients [4–5]. Terminal dehydration, accompanied by standard measures of palliative care, offers patients a way to escape agonizing, incurable conditions that they consider to be worse than death, without requiring transformation of the law and medical ethics.
null
The controversial issue of legalizing physician-assisted suicide should be considered in light of legally available alternative methods of voluntary death. The increasingly polarized debate over this issue has failed to give due attention to an alternative: terminal dehydration. By voluntarily forgoing food and water, competent patients with terminal or incurable illness can escape intolerable, irremediable conditions without requiring transformation of the law and medical ethics. Terminal dehydration offers substantial advantages over physician-assisted suicide with respect to self-determination, access, professional integrity, and social implications but also has distinctive drawbacks as a humane means of voluntary death. This article analyzes clinical, ethical, and policy issues related to terminal dehydration compared with physician-assisted suicide. The deeply divisive question of whether to legalize physician-assisted suicide has become a pressing matter of public policy at a time of radical change in the U.S. health care system. Managed care has expanded rapidly and now serves as the form of health care coverage for more than half of Americans with health insurance [1]. Although this organizational change seems to have reduced the growth of health care expenditures [2], approximately 40 million Americans (15% of the population) continue to lack health insurance [3]. That a legal option of physician-assisted suicide could become a “quick fix” for dying patients is a serious risk in view of the built-in incentives of managed care plans to limit treatment, coupled with the documented deficiencies of physicians in providing adequate pain relief and diagnosing and treating depression in terminally ill patients [4–5]. Given the potential for abuse if physician-assisted suicide were to be legalized in a climate of over-arching cost containment in health care, careful consideration of alternative ways for patients to retain some control over the timing and circumstances of death seems warranted. The debate over legalizing physician-assisted suicide has failed to give due attention to terminal dehydration as an alternative [6]. With terminal dehydration, competent patients who have terminal or incurable illness seek voluntary death by forgoing artificial nutrition and hydration or by ceasing to eat and drink. Terminal dehydration, accompanied by standard measures of palliative care, offers patients a way to escape agonizing, incurable conditions that they consider to be worse than death, without requiring transformation of the law and medical ethics.
2,594
<h4><strong>Physicians suck at their jobs, and you can always just stop consuming in order to die.</h4><p>Miller 98</p><p></strong>Franklin G. Miller, PhD, Diane Meier, MD, Ann Intern Med. 1998;128(7):559-562., “Voluntary Death: A Comparison of Terminal Dehydration and Physician-Assisted Suicide”, http://annals.org/article.aspx?articleid=711286 //jchen</p><p>The controversial issue of legalizing <u>physician-assisted suicide should be considered in light of </u>legally available alternative methods of <u>voluntary death. </u>The increasingly polarized debate over this issue has failed to give due attention to an alternative: <u>terminal dehydration. By voluntarily forgoing food and water, competent patients with terminal or incurable illness can escape intolerable, irremediable conditions without requiring transformation of the law and medical ethics. Terminal dehydration offers substantial advantages over physician-assisted suicide with respect to self-determination, access, professional integrity, and social implications</u> but also has distinctive drawbacks as a humane means of voluntary death. This article analyzes clinical, ethical, and policy issues related to terminal dehydration compared with physician-assisted suicide.</p><p>The deeply divisive question of whether to legalize physician-assisted suicide has become a pressing matter of public policy at a time of radical change in the U.S. health care system. Managed care has expanded rapidly and now serves as the form of health care coverage for more than half of Americans with health insurance [1]. Although this organizational change seems to have reduced the growth of health care expenditures [2], approximately 40 million Americans (15% of the population) continue to lack health insurance [3]. <u>That a legal option of physician-assisted suicide could become a “quick fix” for dying patients is a serious risk in view of the built-in incentives of managed care plans to limit treatment, coupled with the documented deficiencies of physicians in providing adequate pain relief and diagnosing and treating depression in terminally ill patients [4–5].</p><p></u>Given the potential for abuse if physician-assisted suicide were to be legalized in a climate of over-arching cost containment in health care, careful consideration of alternative ways for patients to retain some control over the timing and circumstances of death seems warranted. The debate over legalizing physician-assisted suicide has failed to give due attention to terminal dehydration as an alternative [6]. With terminal dehydration, competent patients who have terminal or incurable illness seek voluntary death by forgoing artificial nutrition and hydration or by ceasing to eat and drink. <u>Terminal dehydration, accompanied by standard measures of palliative care, offers patients a way to escape agonizing, incurable conditions that they consider to be worse than death, without requiring transformation of the law and medical ethics.</p></u>
null
Case
2NC Link Debate
430,642
2
17,073
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
565,303
N
Navy
5
Florida Cone-Marchini
Corrigan
1AC PAS Biopower 1NC Foucault K Physician PIC Ableism Turns 2NR Ableism
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,299
And that no one can really agree on what the data means let alone what the data IS.
Human Security Report ’10
Human Security Report ’10 ( Embargoed until 2 December 2010, 11:00am EST Human Security Report Project. Human Security Report 2009/2010: The Causes of Peace and the Shrinking Costs of War. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011.
there are profound disagreements between quantitative scholars about the factors that drive war and peace Despite immense data collections, prestigious journals, and sophisticated analyses … Many statistical results change from article to article and specification to specification a recent survey of key findings in the quantitative conflict research literature reported that the literature was rife with divergent findings. points out that various quantitative studies have found that does.  Dependence on primary commodities makes war more likely—and it does not. Increases in levels of democracy reduce the risk of war— and have no impact. Countries whose neighbours experience civil war face increased risks of war themselves—and they do not.  Economic growth decreases the risk of war—and it has no significant effect.  Mountainous terrain increases the risk of war—and it does not.
there are profound disagreements about the factors that drive war Despite immense data statistical results change from article to article a survey of conflict research lit reported the lit was rife with divergent findings studies have found
Although rarely discussed in quantitative research literature, there are profound disagreements between quantitative scholars about the factors that drive war and peace. As one review put it: “Despite immense data collections, prestigious journals, and sophisticated analyses … Many statistical results change from article to article and specification to specification. Accurate forecasts are nonexistent.” 63 This bleak assessment by three leading methodologists in the US was directed at quantitative studies of international conflicts 10 years ago, but it is equally applicable, and largely for the same reasons, to quantitative studies of civil wars today. This was made evident in a recent survey of key findings in the quantitative conflict research literature on civil war by Håvard Hegre and Nicolas Sambanis, which reported that the literature was rife with divergent findings. 64 Their research— —points out that various quantitative studies have found that:  Ethnic diversity has no impact on the risk of armed conflict—and it does.  Dependence on primary commodities makes war more likely—and it does not.  Increases in levels of democracy reduce the risk of war— and have no impact.  Inequality increases the risk of war—and has no effect.  Grievances increase the risk of war—and they do not.  Countries whose neighbours experience civil war face increased risks of war themselves—and they do not.  Economic growth decreases the risk of war—and it has no significant effect.  Mountainous terrain increases the risk of war—and it does not. Surprisingly, despite these and many other divergent findings, there have been very few attempts by researchers to resolve their differences.
1,702
<h4><strong>And that no one can really agree on what the data means let alone what the data IS.</h4><p>Human Security Report ’10 </strong>( Embargoed until 2 December 2010, 11:00am EST Human Security Report Project. Human Security Report 2009/2010: The Causes of Peace and the Shrinking Costs of War. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011. </p><p>Although rarely discussed in quantitative research literature, <u><mark>there are profound disagreements</mark> between quantitative scholars <mark>about the factors that drive</mark> <mark>war</mark> and peace</u>. As one review put it: “<u><mark>Despite</mark> <mark>immense data</mark> collections, prestigious journals, and sophisticated analyses … Many <mark>statistical results change from article to article</mark> and specification to specification</u>. Accurate forecasts are nonexistent.” 63 This bleak assessment by three leading methodologists in the US was directed at quantitative studies of international conflicts 10 years ago, but it is equally applicable, and largely for the same reasons, to quantitative studies of civil wars today. This was made evident in <u><mark>a</mark> recent <mark>survey</mark> <mark>of</mark> key findings in the quantitative <mark>conflict research lit</mark>erature</u> on civil war by Håvard Hegre and Nicolas Sambanis, which <u><mark>reported</mark> that <mark>the lit</mark>erature <mark>was</mark> <mark>rife</mark> <mark>with</mark> <mark>divergent</mark> <mark>findings</mark>.</u> 64 Their research— —<u>points out that various quantitative <mark>studies have found</mark> that</u>:  Ethnic diversity has no impact on the risk of armed conflict—and it <u>does.  Dependence on primary commodities makes war more likely—and it does not.</u> <u> Increases in levels of democracy reduce the risk of war— and have no impact.</u>  Inequality increases the risk of war—and has no effect.  Grievances increase the risk of war—and they do not.  <u>Countries whose neighbours experience civil war face increased risks of war themselves—and they do not.  Economic growth decreases the risk of war—and it has no significant effect.  Mountainous terrain increases the risk of war—and it does not.</u> Surprisingly, despite these and many other divergent findings, there have been very few attempts by researchers to resolve their differences.</p>
WTO
Heg/Trade
AT: Inevitable
224,797
2
17,069
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
565,304
N
Navy
8
Wake Forest Nasar-Raudenbush
Ridley
1AC OG (WTO Banks) 1NC Security K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round8.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,300
We call for a rejection of reproductive futurism and illustrate that rejection with the following plan:
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>We call for a rejection of reproductive futurism and illustrate that rejection with the following plan:</h4>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,641
1
17,076
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
565,296
A
tournament
1
NYU Itliong-Zhan
Glass, Thoma
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round1.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,301
Daniel and I affirm the prostitute.
null
null
null
null
null
null
<h4>Daniel and I affirm the prostitute.</h4>
1AC
null
Prostitution 1AC
430,643
1
17,077
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
565,297
A
tournament
4
Binghamton Cepin-Sehgal
Baker, Webster Dunn
null
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Aff-tournament-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,302
Solves trade---the issue is discrimination, not legality---CP’s universal ban causes WTO compliance
Rose 5
Nelson Rose 5, professor, recognized as one of the world's leading authorities on gambling law, Internet Gaming: U.S. Beats Antigua in WTO, www.gamblingandthelaw.com/index.php/columns/65-109wto
As for federal law, with just a little tweaking of the I H A the U.S. will be in complete compliance with its WTO treaty obligations The WTO held that the federal laws prohibiting interstate and international betting were necessary it said that the U.S. had established "a specific connection between the remote supply of gambling services" and dangers to the American public. It found the U.S. had presented evidence showing "a link in relation to money laundering, fraud, compulsive gambling and underage gambling." But the U.S. laws had to pass one more test. A nation can enact laws to protect its residents from the perceived evils of gambling, but it cannot discriminate against foreigners just to protect its local businesses. One federal law failed this test the Interstate Horseracing Act ("IHA") allow betting on horse races by phone or computer. But the law on its face is limited to states in the U.S. where it is legal to place and accept bets.¶ Since foreign operators were expressly excluded, the WTO found the U.S. had failed to show there was no discrimination. The WTO held the U.S. had not shown that it applied its prohibition on remote wagering on horseraces in a nondiscriminatory manner.¶ the solution is easy. Congress should amend the IHA to allow what is already being done: expressly allow Americans to bet on foreign races and allow foreign bettors to wager on American races. The U.S. could then safely prohibit all other forms of Internet gambling, foreign and domestic.
with a little tweaking of the I H A U.S. will be in complete compliance with WTO obligations WTO held federal laws prohibiting betting were necessary it said U.S. had established "a connection between the remote gambling " and dangers U.S. had presented a link to laundering and underage gambling."¶ but it cannot discriminate against foreigners the IHA allow betting on horse races limited to states in the U.S. Since foreign operators were excluded, the WTO found discrimination WTO held the U.S. had not applied its prohibition on remote wagering on horseraces in a nondiscriminatory manner the solution is easy. The U.S. could prohibit all Internet gambling, foreign and domestic
First, the WTO decided not to look at U.S. state laws, which outlaw all unlicenced commercial gambling.¶ As for federal law, with just a little tweaking of the Interstate Horseracing Act, the U.S. will be in complete compliance with its WTO treaty obligations.¶ The entire controversy can be traced back to a mistake the U.S. federal government keeps making: It does not take gambling seriously.¶ Nations that sign trade treaties like the ones creating the WTO agree that they will let in some types of goods and services of other signatories. One category was "Recreational, Cultural & Sporting Services," which included everything from circuses to news agencies. Some other countries expressly stated that they were not agreeing to open their doors to foreign gambling operations. But the U.S. agreed to let in every recreational service, "except sporting."¶ Sporting" services were undoubtedly excluded to keep out foreign sports teams. The U.S. argued that "sporting" includes gambling. It didn't work.¶ The funny thing is that the U.S. did want to keep out gambling. And all it had to do was say so.¶ The U.S. signed the WTO treaty in 1994. Maybe the federal government did not know about Internet gaming then, but it should have. It certainly did know that foreign operators were trying to gain patrons from the U.S.: The federal government was seizing a million pieces of foreign lottery mail at the borders each year.¶ But the U.S. could still keep out Internet gambling if it could show that this was "necessary to protect public morals or to maintain public order."¶ The first panel held the U.S. had failed to show this because the U.S. had refused to talk with Antigua about changing its laws against Internet gaming. On appeal the WTO ruled that whether or not the U.S. had met with Antigua was irrelevant to the legal of question of whether the anti-gambling laws were necessary.¶ The WTO held that the federal laws prohibiting interstate and international betting were necessary. Specifically, it said that the U.S. had established "a specific connection between the remote supply of gambling services" and dangers to the American public. It found the U.S. had presented evidence showing "a link in relation to money laundering, fraud, compulsive gambling and underage gambling."¶ This does not mean that any of this is true. Only that the federal government was able to show that it had reason to be concerned about foreign operators taking bets from at-home Americans. It focused on Internet gambling's "volume, speed and international reach," "virtual anonymity," "low barriers to entry," and "isolated and anonymous environment."¶ The WTO did reject the federal government=s concern for organized crime, finding the U.S. had not submitted concrete evidence to show that remote gambling, as opposed to other forms of gambling, was particularly vulnerable to mob involvement.¶ This WTO ruling was the first ever to discuss "public morals," but it follows established international law. The High Court of Europe has consistently ruled that the nations of the European Community cannot keep out trade from other members - except gambling. Even in the U.S., we have long had the concept of a state's Police Power, the state's right to do just about anything to protect the health, safety, welfare and morality of that state's citizens.¶ But the U.S. laws had to pass one more test. A nation can enact laws to protect its residents from the perceived evils of gambling, but it cannot discriminate against foreigners just to protect its local businesses. One federal law failed this test.¶ In December 2000, Congress amended the Interstate Horseracing Act ("IHA") to allow parimutuel betting on horse races by phone or computer. But the law on its face is limited to states in the U.S. where it is legal to place and accept bets.¶ Since foreign operators were expressly excluded, the WTO found the U.S. had failed to show there was no discrimination. The government lawyers did not help by making the silly argument that the IHA was only civil and that it did not repeal the criminal anti-gambling laws. Of course it did. That was why it was amended, so that off-tracking betting parlors would not be arrested for taking out-of-state bets.¶ Once again, the government did not bother to talk to anyone in the business. If it had, it would have learned that international betting on horseracing has been around for decades. Betting on the Kentucky Derby is very big in Canada and France, and I personally saw Hollywood Park taking bets on races in Hong Kong.¶ ¶ The WTO held the U.S. had not shown that it applied its prohibition on remote wagering on horseraces in a nondiscriminatory manner.¶ But the solution is easy. Congress should immediately amend the IHA to allow what is already being done: expressly allow Americans to bet on foreign races and allow foreign bettors to wager on American races. The U.S. could then safely prohibit all other forms of Internet gambling, foreign and domestic.
5,009
<h4>Solves trade---the issue is <u>discrimination</u>, not <u>legality</u>---CP’s <u>universal ban</u> causes WTO compliance</h4><p>Nelson <strong>Rose 5</strong>, professor, recognized as one of the world's leading authorities on gambling law, Internet Gaming: U.S. Beats Antigua in WTO, <u>www.gamblingandthelaw.com/index.php/columns/65-109wto</p><p></u>First, the WTO decided not to look at U.S. state laws, which outlaw all unlicenced commercial gambling.¶ <u>As for federal law, <strong><mark>with</mark> just <mark>a little tweaking of the I</u></strong></mark>nterstate <u><strong><mark>H</u></strong></mark>orseracing <u><strong><mark>A</u></strong></mark>ct, <u><strong>the <mark>U.S. will be in complete compliance with</mark> its <mark>WTO</mark> treaty <mark>obligations</u></strong></mark>.¶ The entire controversy can be traced back to a mistake the U.S. federal government keeps making: It does not take gambling seriously.¶ Nations that sign trade treaties like the ones creating the WTO agree that they will let in some types of goods and services of other signatories. One category was "Recreational, Cultural & Sporting Services," which included everything from circuses to news agencies. Some other countries expressly stated that they were not agreeing to open their doors to foreign gambling operations. But the U.S. agreed to let in every recreational service, "except sporting."¶ Sporting" services were undoubtedly excluded to keep out foreign sports teams. The U.S. argued that "sporting" includes gambling. It didn't work.¶ The funny thing is that the U.S. did want to keep out gambling. And all it had to do was say so.¶ The U.S. signed the WTO treaty in 1994. Maybe the federal government did not know about Internet gaming then, but it should have. It certainly did know that foreign operators were trying to gain patrons from the U.S.: The federal government was seizing a million pieces of foreign lottery mail at the borders each year.¶ But the U.S. could still keep out Internet gambling if it could show that this was "necessary to protect public morals or to maintain public order."¶ The first panel held the U.S. had failed to show this because the U.S. had refused to talk with Antigua about changing its laws against Internet gaming. On appeal the WTO ruled that whether or not the U.S. had met with Antigua was irrelevant to the legal of question of whether the anti-gambling laws were necessary.¶ <u>The <mark>WTO held</mark> that the <strong><mark>federal laws prohibiting </mark>interstate and international <mark>betting were necessary</u></strong></mark>. Specifically, <u><mark>it said</mark> that the <mark>U.S. had established "a </mark>specific <mark>connection between the remote </mark>supply of <mark>gambling </mark>services<mark>" and dangers</mark> to the American public. It found the <mark>U.S. had presented</mark> evidence showing "<mark>a link </mark>in relation <mark>to</mark> money <mark>laundering</mark>, fraud, compulsive gambling <mark>and underage gambling."</u>¶ </mark>This does not mean that any of this is true. Only that the federal government was able to show that it had reason to be concerned about foreign operators taking bets from at-home Americans. It focused on Internet gambling's "volume, speed and international reach," "virtual anonymity," "low barriers to entry," and "isolated and anonymous environment."¶ The WTO did reject the federal government=s concern for organized crime, finding the U.S. had not submitted concrete evidence to show that remote gambling, as opposed to other forms of gambling, was particularly vulnerable to mob involvement.¶ This WTO ruling was the first ever to discuss "public morals," but it follows established international law. The High Court of Europe has consistently ruled that the nations of the European Community cannot keep out trade from other members - except gambling. Even in the U.S., we have long had the concept of a state's Police Power, the state's right to do just about anything to protect the health, safety, welfare and morality of that state's citizens.¶ <u>But the U.S. laws had to pass one more test. A nation can enact laws to protect its residents from the perceived evils of gambling, <mark>but it <strong>cannot discriminate</strong> against foreigners</mark> just to protect its local businesses. One federal law failed this test</u>.¶ In December 2000, Congress amended <u><mark>the</mark> Interstate Horseracing Act ("<mark>IHA</mark>")</u> to <u><mark>allow</u></mark> parimutuel <u><mark>betting on horse races</mark> by phone or computer. But the law on its face is <mark>limited to states in the U.S.</mark> where it is legal to place and accept bets.¶</u> <u><mark>Since foreign operators were</mark> expressly <mark>excluded, the WTO</mark> <mark>found</mark> the U.S. had failed to show there was no <mark>discrimination</mark>.</u> The government lawyers did not help by making the silly argument that the IHA was only civil and that it did not repeal the criminal anti-gambling laws. Of course it did. That was why it was amended, so that off-tracking betting parlors would not be arrested for taking out-of-state bets.¶ Once again, the government did not bother to talk to anyone in the business. If it had, it would have learned that international betting on horseracing has been around for decades. Betting on the Kentucky Derby is very big in Canada and France, and I personally saw Hollywood Park taking bets on races in Hong Kong.¶ ¶ <u>The <mark>WTO held the U.S. had not</mark> shown that it <mark>applied its prohibition on remote wagering on horseraces in a nondiscriminatory manner</mark>.¶</u> But <u><strong><mark>the solution is easy.</u></strong> <u></mark>Congress should</u> immediately <u>amend the IHA to allow what is already being done: expressly allow Americans to bet on foreign races and allow foreign bettors to wager on American races. <mark>The U.S. could</mark> then <strong>safely <mark>prohibit all</mark> other forms of <mark>Internet gambling, foreign and domestic</strong></mark>.</p></u>
null
null
CP
430,517
23
17,072
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
565,302
N
Navy
4
Wake Forest Manchester-Stirrat
Bobbitt
1AC Gambling (Costa Rica Laundering WTO) 1NC Security K Ban CP Politics 2NR K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,303
CP solves- only 1% of marijuana cases are federal- we end virtually all enforcement
Schwartz 2013
Schwartz 2013 (David, Foley & Lardner-Bascom Professor of Law, University of Wisconsin Law School, High Federalism: Marijuana Legalization and the Limits of Federal Power to Regulate States, 35 Cardozo L. Rev. 567, December, lexis)
forcing Congress to internalize the fiscal costs of federal regulation is a significant check, and allowing it to externalize costs is a significant incentive to commandeer. marijuana legalization provides a salient example the shifting of fiscal costs onto the states through commandeering is potentially enormous there were approximately 120,000 federal law enforcement agents in the United States, compared to 765,000 at the state level only 1 percent of the roughly 800,000 marijuana cases generated every year are handled by federal authorities commandeering state officials to enforce the CSA could create a massive shift in law enforcement costs onto the states The idea that the courts might have the power to accomplish this large-scale commandeering through an aggressive CSA-preemption ruling should alarm anyone who believes in political safeguards of federalism Such a judicial application of preemption doctrine would bypass the significant political obstacles that would likely prevent Congress from taking such a step directly
only 1 percent of marijuana cases generated every year are handled by federal authorities commandeering state officials to enforce the CSA could create a massive shift in law enforcement costs a judicial application of preemption doctrine would bypass political obstacles that would prevent Congress from taking such a step directly
Still, to convince proponents of the political safeguards of federalism to overcome their resistance to a categorical anti-commandeering rule may take some work. Young and others have explained the rule as serving state autonomy interests by forcing Congress to internalize the costs - political and fiscal - of federal legislation. n236 The New York and Printz Courts both made much of the "democratic accountability" problem created by commandeering, which could be used by Congress to make an unpopular policy look like it emanated from the state. n237 This problem can be overblown, of course. Externalizing political costs - making the state the bad guy through commandeering - might be an issue in the case of an obscure, complex regulatory scheme like that involved in New York; but it would hardly have been an issue in Printz, where it would have been a simple matter for local police chiefs to inform the public that they were reluctantly enforcing a federal law that they strongly opposed, where the law had been well publicized, and where it would be easy for the public to understand the point. A much stronger rationale for anti-commandeering is its tendency to prevent Congress from externalizing the financial costs of the law: By forcing state governments to absorb the financial burden of implementing a federal regulatory program, Members of Congress can take credit for "solving" problems without having to ask their constituents to pay for the solutions with higher federal taxes. n238 Given the culture of resistance to taxes and government spending, forcing Congress to internalize the fiscal costs of federal regulation is a significant check, and allowing it to externalize costs is a significant incentive to commandeer. [*633] The marijuana legalization issue provides a salient example. The accountability issue is minimal: Any reasonably well-informed person in a marijuana legalization state knows that it is federal law that imposes the strict prohibition. But the shifting of fiscal costs onto the states through commandeering is potentially enormous. As of 2008, there were approximately 120,000 federal law enforcement agents in the United States, compared to 765,000 at the state level. n239 Professor Mikos reports that "only 1 percent of the roughly 800,000 marijuana cases generated every year are handled by federal authorities." n240 Thus, commandeering state officials to enforce the CSA could create a massive shift in law enforcement costs onto the states. The idea that the courts might have the power to accomplish this large-scale commandeering through an aggressive CSA-preemption ruling should alarm anyone who believes in political safeguards of federalism. Such a judicial application of preemption doctrine would bypass the significant political obstacles that would likely prevent Congress from taking such a step directly.
2,875
<h4>CP solves- only 1% of marijuana cases are federal- we end virtually all enforcement</h4><p><strong>Schwartz 2013</strong> (David, Foley & Lardner-Bascom Professor of Law, University of Wisconsin Law School, High Federalism: Marijuana Legalization and the Limits of Federal Power to Regulate States, 35 Cardozo L. Rev. 567, December, lexis)</p><p>Still, to convince proponents of the political safeguards of federalism to overcome their resistance to a categorical anti-commandeering rule may take some work. Young and others have explained the rule as serving state autonomy interests by forcing Congress to internalize the costs - political and fiscal - of federal legislation. n236 The New York and Printz Courts both made much of the "democratic accountability" problem created by commandeering, which could be used by Congress to make an unpopular policy look like it emanated from the state. n237 This problem can be overblown, of course. Externalizing political costs - making the state the bad guy through commandeering - might be an issue in the case of an obscure, complex regulatory scheme like that involved in New York; but it would hardly have been an issue in Printz, where it would have been a simple matter for local police chiefs to inform the public that they were reluctantly enforcing a federal law that they strongly opposed, where the law had been well publicized, and where it would be easy for the public to understand the point. A much stronger rationale for anti-commandeering is its tendency to prevent Congress from externalizing the financial costs of the law: By forcing state governments to absorb the financial burden of implementing a federal regulatory program, Members of Congress can take credit for "solving" problems without having to ask their constituents to pay for the solutions with higher federal taxes. n238 Given the culture of resistance to taxes and government spending, <u>forcing Congress to internalize the fiscal costs of federal regulation is a significant check, and allowing it to externalize costs is a significant incentive to commandeer. </u>[*633] The <u>marijuana legalization</u> issue <u>provides a salient example</u>. The accountability issue is minimal: Any reasonably well-informed person in a marijuana legalization state knows that it is federal law that imposes the strict prohibition. But <u>the shifting of fiscal costs onto the states through commandeering is potentially enormous</u>. As of 2008, <u>there were approximately 120,000 federal law enforcement agents in the United States, compared to 765,000 at the state level</u>. n239 Professor Mikos reports that "<u><strong><mark>only 1 percent of </mark>the roughly 800,000 <mark>marijuana cases generated every year are handled by federal authorities</u></strong></mark>." n240 Thus, <u><mark>commandeering state officials to enforce the CSA could create a massive shift in law enforcement costs </mark>onto the states</u>. <u>The idea that the courts might have the power to accomplish this large-scale commandeering through an aggressive CSA-preemption ruling should alarm anyone who believes in political safeguards of federalism</u>. <u>Such <mark>a judicial application of preemption doctrine would bypass </mark>the significant <mark>political obstacles that would </mark>likely <mark>prevent Congress from taking such a step directly</u></mark>.</p>
null
null
Counteradvocacy
430,416
19
17,078
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
565,306
N
tournament
5
NYU Dellamore-Kuzmenko
Glass, Weddington
1AC - mass mobilization against incarceration - marijuana 1NC - Reg-spec T States CP Academy K Treaties DA 2NC - K CP 1NR - T DA 2NR - T K
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-tournament-Round5.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2
742,304
Physicians suck at there jobs, and you can always just stop consuming in order to die.
Miller 98
Miller 98 Franklin G. Miller, PhD, Diane Meier, MD, Ann Intern Med. 1998;128(7):559-562., “Voluntary Death: A Comparison of Terminal Dehydration and Physician-Assisted Suicide”, http://annals.org/article.aspx?articleid=711286 //jchen
null
null
The controversial issue of legalizing physician-assisted suicide should be considered in light of legally available alternative methods of voluntary death. The increasingly polarized debate over this issue has failed to give due attention to an alternative: terminal dehydration. By voluntarily forgoing food and water, competent patients with terminal or incurable illness can escape intolerable, irremediable conditions without requiring transformation of the law and medical ethics. Terminal dehydration offers substantial advantages over physician-assisted suicide with respect to self-determination, access, professional integrity, and social implications but also has distinctive drawbacks as a humane means of voluntary death. This article analyzes clinical, ethical, and policy issues related to terminal dehydration compared with physician-assisted suicide. The deeply divisive question of whether to legalize physician-assisted suicide has become a pressing matter of public policy at a time of radical change in the U.S. health care system. Managed care has expanded rapidly and now serves as the form of health care coverage for more than half of Americans with health insurance [1]. Although this organizational change seems to have reduced the growth of health care expenditures [2], approximately 40 million Americans (15% of the population) continue to lack health insurance [3]. That a legal option of physician-assisted suicide could become a “quick fix” for dying patients is a serious risk in view of the built-in incentives of managed care plans to limit treatment, coupled with the documented deficiencies of physicians in providing adequate pain relief and diagnosing and treating depression in terminally ill patients [4–5]. Given the potential for abuse if physician-assisted suicide were to be legalized in a climate of over-arching cost containment in health care, careful consideration of alternative ways for patients to retain some control over the timing and circumstances of death seems warranted. The debate over legalizing physician-assisted suicide has failed to give due attention to terminal dehydration as an alternative [6]. With terminal dehydration, competent patients who have terminal or incurable illness seek voluntary death by forgoing artificial nutrition and hydration or by ceasing to eat and drink. Terminal dehydration, accompanied by standard measures of palliative care, offers patients a way to escape agonizing, incurable conditions that they consider to be worse than death, without requiring transformation of the law and medical ethics.
2,594
<h4><strong>Physicians suck at there jobs, and you can always just stop consuming in order to die.</h4><p>Miller 98</p><p></strong>Franklin G. Miller, PhD, Diane Meier, MD, Ann Intern Med. 1998;128(7):559-562., “Voluntary Death: A Comparison of Terminal Dehydration and Physician-Assisted Suicide”, http://annals.org/article.aspx?articleid=711286 //jchen</p><p>The controversial issue of legalizing <strong>physician-assisted suicide should be considered in light of </strong>legally available alternative methods of <strong>voluntary death. </strong>The increasingly polarized debate over this issue has failed to give due attention to an alternative: <strong>terminal dehydration. By voluntarily forgoing food and water, competent patients with terminal or incurable illness can escape intolerable, irremediable conditions without requiring transformation of the law and medical ethics. Terminal dehydration offers substantial advantages over physician-assisted suicide with respect to self-determination, access, professional integrity, and social implications</strong> but also has distinctive drawbacks as a humane means of voluntary death. This article analyzes clinical, ethical, and policy issues related to terminal dehydration compared with physician-assisted suicide.</p><p>The deeply divisive question of whether to legalize physician-assisted suicide has become a pressing matter of public policy at a time of radical change in the U.S. health care system. Managed care has expanded rapidly and now serves as the form of health care coverage for more than half of Americans with health insurance [1]. Although this organizational change seems to have reduced the growth of health care expenditures [2], approximately 40 million Americans (15% of the population) continue to lack health insurance [3]. <strong>That a legal option of physician-assisted suicide could become a “quick fix” for dying patients is a serious risk in view of the built-in incentives of managed care plans to limit treatment, coupled with the documented deficiencies of physicians in providing adequate pain relief and diagnosing and treating depression in terminally ill patients [4–5].</p><p></strong>Given the potential for abuse if physician-assisted suicide were to be legalized in a climate of over-arching cost containment in health care, careful consideration of alternative ways for patients to retain some control over the timing and circumstances of death seems warranted. The debate over legalizing physician-assisted suicide has failed to give due attention to terminal dehydration as an alternative [6]. With terminal dehydration, competent patients who have terminal or incurable illness seek voluntary death by forgoing artificial nutrition and hydration or by ceasing to eat and drink. <strong>Terminal dehydration, accompanied by standard measures of palliative care, offers patients a way to escape agonizing, incurable conditions that they consider to be worse than death, without requiring transformation of the law and medical ethics.</p></strong>
null
null
Case
430,642
2
17,074
./documents/ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
565,301
N
Navy
2
Gonzaga Skoog-Weinhardt
Allen
1AC - PAS (pain) 1NC - Cap Physicians PIC Politics 2NR - Politics
ndtceda14/Dartmouth/KrMa/Dartmouth-Kreus-Martin-Neg-Navy-Round2.docx
null
48,459
KrMa
Dartmouth KrMa
null
Da.....
Kr.....
Jo.....
Ma.....
18,764
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,004
ndtceda14
NDT/CEDA 2014-15
2,014
cx
college
2