|
\documentclass[a4paper,UKenglish]{lipics} |
|
|
|
|
|
\usepackage{microtype} |
|
|
|
\usepackage{stmaryrd} |
|
\usepackage{bussproofs} |
|
\usepackage{xspace} |
|
\usepackage{mdframed} |
|
\usepackage{fancybox} |
|
\usepackage{nicefrac} |
|
\usepackage{xypic} |
|
\xyoption{tips} |
|
\SelectTips{cm}{} \usepackage{multicol} |
|
\usepackage{booktabs} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\bibliographystyle{plain} |
|
|
|
\title{A Type Theory for Probabilistic and Bayesian Reasoning\footnote{This work was supported by ERC Advanced Grant QCLS: Quantum Computation, Logic and Security.}} |
|
|
|
|
|
\author[1]{Robin Adams} |
|
\author[1]{Bart Jacobs} |
|
\affil[1]{Institute for Computing and Information Sciences,\\ |
|
Radboud University, the Netherlands\\ |
|
\texttt{\{r.adams,bart\}@cs.ru.nl}} |
|
\authorrunning{R. Adams and B. Jacobs} |
|
|
|
\Copyright{Robin Adams and Bart Jacobs} |
|
|
|
\subjclass{F.4.1 [Mathematical Logic and Formal Languages]: Mathematical Logic --- Lambda calculus and related systems; G.3 [Probability and Statistics]: Probabilistic algorithms; F.3.1 [Logics and Meanings of Programs]: Specifying and Verifying and Reasoning about Programs}\keywords{Probability theory, type theory, effect module, Bayesian reasoning} |
|
|
|
\serieslogo{}\volumeinfo {Billy Editor and Bill Editors}{2}{Conference title on which this volume is based on}{1}{1}{1}\EventShortName{} |
|
\DOI{10.4230/LIPIcs.xxx.yyy.p} |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\COMETgrammar}{ |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rvar}{ |
|
\text{(var)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tvar}{ |
|
\TBvar |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTvar}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBvar |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBvar}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rvar} |
|
\AxiomC{$ x : A \in \Gamma$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash x : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rexch}{ |
|
\text{(exch)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Texch}{ |
|
\TBexch |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTexch}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBexch |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBexch}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rexch} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma, x : A, y : B, \Delta \vdash \mathcal{J}$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma, y : B, x : A, \Delta \vdash \mathcal{J}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rref}{ |
|
\text{(ref)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tref}{ |
|
\TBref |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTref}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBref |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBref}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rref} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash t = t : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rsym}{ |
|
\text{(sym)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tsym}{ |
|
\TBsym |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTsym}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBsym |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBsym}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rsym} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s = t : A$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash t = s : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rtrans}{ |
|
\text{(trans)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Ttrans}{ |
|
\TBtrans |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTtrans}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBtrans |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBtrans}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rtrans} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash r = s : A$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s = t : A$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash r = t : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rmagic}{ |
|
\text{(magic)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tmagic}{ |
|
\TBmagic |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTmagic}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBmagic |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBmagic}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rmagic} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : 0$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \magic{t} : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Retazero}{ |
|
\text{($\eta 0$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tetazero}{ |
|
\TBetazero |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTetazero}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBetazero |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBetazero}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Retazero} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s : 0$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \magic{s} = t : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Runit}{ |
|
\text{(unit)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tunit}{ |
|
\TBunit |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTunit}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBunit |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBunit}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Runit} |
|
\AxiomC{$$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash * : 1$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Retaone}{ |
|
\text{($\eta 1$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tetaone}{ |
|
\TBetaone |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTetaone}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBetaone |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBetaone}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Retaone} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : 1$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash t = * : 1$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rinl}{ |
|
\text{(inl)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tinl}{ |
|
\TBinl |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTinl}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBinl |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBinl}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rinl} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \inl{t} : A + B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rinleq}{ |
|
\text{(inl-eq)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tinleq}{ |
|
\TBinleq |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTinleq}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBinleq |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBinleq}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rinleq} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t = t' : A$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \inl{t} = \inl{t'} : A + B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rinr}{ |
|
\text{(inr)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tinr}{ |
|
\TBinr |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTinr}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBinr |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBinr}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rinr} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : B$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \inr{t} : A + B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rinreq}{ |
|
\text{(inr-eq)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tinreq}{ |
|
\TBinreq |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTinreq}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBinreq |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBinreq}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rinreq} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t = t' : B$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \inr{t} = \inr{t'} : A + B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rcase}{ |
|
\text{(case)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tcase}{ |
|
\TBcase |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTcase}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBcase |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBcase}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rcase} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash r : A + B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A \vdash s : C$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, y : B \vdash t : C$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{t} : C$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rcaseeq}{ |
|
\text{(case-eq)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tcaseeq}{ |
|
\TBcaseeq |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTcaseeq}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBcaseeq |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBcaseeq}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rcaseeq} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash r = r' : A + B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A \vdash s = s' : C$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, y : B \vdash t = t': C$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{t} = \pcase{r'}{x}{s'}{y}{t'} : C$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rbetaplustwo}{ |
|
\text{($\beta+_2$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tbetaplustwo}{ |
|
\TBbetaplustwo |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTbetaplustwo}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBbetaplustwo |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBbetaplustwo}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rbetaplustwo} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash r : B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A \vdash s : C$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, y : B \vdash t : C$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \pcase{\inr{r}}{x}{s}{y}{t} = t[y:=r] : C$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rbetaplusone}{ |
|
\text{($\beta+_1$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tbetaplusone}{ |
|
\TBbetaplusone |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTbetaplusone}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBbetaplusone |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBbetaplusone}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rbetaplusone} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash r : A$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A \vdash s : C$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, y : B \vdash t : C$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \pcase{\inl{r}}{x}{s}{y}{t} = s[x:=r] : C$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Retaplus}{ |
|
\text{($\eta+$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tetaplus}{ |
|
\TBetaplus |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTetaplus}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBetaplus |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBetaplus}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Retaplus} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A + B$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash t = \pcase{t}{x}{\inl{x}}{y}{\inr{y}} : A + B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rcasecase}{ |
|
\text{(case-case)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tcasecase}{ |
|
\TBcasecase |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTcasecase}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBcasecase |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBcasecase}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rcasecase} |
|
\AxiomC{ |
|
$\begin{array}{ccc} |
|
\Gamma \vdash r : A + B & \Delta, x : A \vdash s : C + D & \Delta, y : B \vdash s' : C + D\\ |
|
\multicolumn{3}{c}{\Theta, z : C \vdash t : E \qquad \Theta, w : D \vdash t' : E} |
|
\end{array}$ |
|
} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta, \Theta \vdash |
|
\begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
\case r \of \inl{x} \mapsto \pcase{s}{z}{t}{w}{t'} \mid \\ |
|
\qquad \inr{y} \mapsto \pcase{s'}{z}{t}{w}{t'} \\ |
|
= \case (\pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{s'}) \\ |
|
\qquad \of \inl{z} \mapsto t \mid \inr{w} \mapsto t' : E |
|
\end{array}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rcasepair}{ |
|
\text{(case-$\sotimes$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tcasepair}{ |
|
\TBcasepair |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTcasepair}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBcasepair |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBcasepair}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rcasepair} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash r : A + B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A \vdash s : C$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, y : A \vdash s' : C$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Theta \vdash t : D$} |
|
\QuaternaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta, \Theta \vdash |
|
\begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
(\pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{s'}) \sotimes t = \\ |
|
\pcase{r}{x}{s \sotimes t}{y}{s' \sotimes t} : D |
|
\end{array}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rletcase}{ |
|
\text{(let-case)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tletcase}{ |
|
\TBletcase |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTletcase}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBletcase |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBletcase}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rletcase} |
|
\AxiomC{ |
|
$\begin{array}{cc} |
|
\Gamma \vdash r : A + B & \Delta, z : A \vdash s : C \otimes D\\ |
|
\Delta, w : B \vdash s' : C \otimes D & \Theta, x : C, y : D \vdash t : E |
|
\end{array}$ |
|
} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta, \Theta \vdash |
|
\begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
\plet{x}{y}{\pcase{r}{z}{s}{w}{s'}}{t} = \\ |
|
\pcase{r}{z}{\plet{x}{y}{s}{t}}{w}{\plet{x}{y}{s'}{t}} : E |
|
\end{array}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rinlr}{ |
|
\text{(inlr)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tinlr}{ |
|
\TBinlr |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTinlr}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBinlr |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBinlr}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rinlr} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s : A + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : B + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s \downarrow = t \uparrow : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \inlr{s}{t} : A + B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rinlreq}{ |
|
\text{(inlr-eq)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tinlreq}{ |
|
\TBinlreq |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTinlreq}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBinlreq |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBinlreq}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rinlreq} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s = s' : A + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t = t' : B + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s \downarrow = t \uparrow : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \inlr{s}{t} = \inlr{s'}{t'} : A + B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rbetainlrone}{ |
|
\text{($\beta$inlr$_1$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tbetainlrone}{ |
|
\TBbetainlrone |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTbetainlrone}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBbetainlrone |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBbetainlrone}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rbetainlrone} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s : A + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : B + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s \downarrow = t \uparrow : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \rhd_1(\inlr{s}{t}) = s : A + 1$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rbetainlrtwo}{ |
|
\text{($\beta$inlr$_1$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tbetainlrtwo}{ |
|
\TBbetainlrtwo |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTbetainlrtwo}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBbetainlrtwo |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBbetainlrtwo}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rbetainlrtwo} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s : A + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : B + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s \downarrow = t \uparrow : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \rhd_2(\inlr{s}{t}) = t : B + 1$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Retainlr}{ |
|
\text{($\eta$inlr)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tetainlr}{ |
|
\TBetainlr |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTetainlr}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBetainlr |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBetainlr}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Retainlr} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A + B$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash t = \inlr{\rhd_1(t)}{\rhd_2(t)} : A + B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rleft}{ |
|
\text{(left)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tleft}{ |
|
\TBleft |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTleft}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBleft |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBleft}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rleft} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A + B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash \inlprop{t} = \top : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \lft{t} : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rlefteq}{ |
|
\text{(left-eq)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tlefteq}{ |
|
\TBlefteq |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTlefteq}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBlefteq |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBlefteq}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rlefteq} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t = t' : A + B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash \inlprop{t} = \top : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \lft{t} = \lft{t'} : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rbetaleft}{ |
|
\text{($\beta$left)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tbetaleft}{ |
|
\TBbetaleft |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTbetaleft}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBbetaleft |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBbetaleft}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rbetaleft} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A + B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash \inlprop{t} = \top : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \inl{\lft{t}} = t : A + B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Retaleft}{ |
|
\text{($\eta$left)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tetaleft}{ |
|
\TBetaleft |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTetaleft}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBetaleft |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBetaleft}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Retaleft} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \lft{\inl{t}} = t : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\RJMprime}{ |
|
\text{(JM)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TJMprime}{ |
|
\TBJMprime |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTJMprime}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBJMprime |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBJMprime}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\RJMprime} |
|
\AxiomC{ |
|
$\begin{array}{cc} |
|
\Gamma \vdash s : (A + A) + 1 & \Gamma \vdash t : (A + A) + 1\\ |
|
\Gamma \vdash s \goesto \rhd_1 = t \goesto \rhd_1 : A + 1 & \Gamma \vdash s \goesto \rhd_2 = t \goesto \rhd_2 : A + 1 |
|
\end{array}$ |
|
} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash s = t : (A + A) + 1$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rpair}{ |
|
\text{($\sotimes$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tpair}{ |
|
\TBpair |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTpair}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBpair |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBpair}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rpair} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s : A$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta \vdash t : B$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash s \sotimes t : A \otimes B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rpaireq}{ |
|
\text{(paireq)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tpaireq}{ |
|
\TBpaireq |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTpaireq}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBpaireq |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBpaireq}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rpaireq} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s = s' : A$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta \vdash t = t': B$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash s \sotimes t = s' \sotimes t' : A \otimes B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rlett}{ |
|
\text{(lett)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tlett}{ |
|
\TBlett |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTlett}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBlett |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBlett}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rlett} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s : A \otimes B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A, y : B \vdash t : C$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \plet{x}{y}{s}{t} : C$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rleteq}{ |
|
\text{(leteq)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tleteq}{ |
|
\TBleteq |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTleteq}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBleteq |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBleteq}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rleteq} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s = s' : A \otimes B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A, y : B \vdash t = t' : C$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash (\plet{x}{y}{s}{t}) = (\plet{x}{y}{s'}{t'}) : C$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rbeta}{ |
|
\text{($\beta \otimes$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tbeta}{ |
|
\TBbeta |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTbeta}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBbeta |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBbeta}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rbeta} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash r : A$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta \vdash s : B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Theta, x : A, y : B \vdash t : C$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta, \Theta \vdash (\plet{x}{y}{r \sotimes s}{t}) = t[x:=r,y:=s] : C$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Reta}{ |
|
\text{($\eta \otimes$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Teta}{ |
|
\TBeta |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTeta}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBeta |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBeta}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Reta} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A \otimes B$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash t = (\plet{x}{y}{t}{x \sotimes y}) : A \otimes B$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rletlet}{ |
|
\text{(let-let)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tletlet}{ |
|
\TBletlet |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTletlet}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBletlet |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBletlet}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rletlet} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash r : A \otimes B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A, y : B \vdash s : C \otimes D$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Theta, z : C, w : D \vdash t : E$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta, \Theta \vdash |
|
\begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
\plet{x}{y}{r}{(\plet{z}{w}{s}{t})} \\ |
|
= \plet{z}{w}{(\plet{x}{y}{r}{s})}{t} |
|
: E |
|
\end{array}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rletpair}{ |
|
\text{(let-$\sotimes$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tletpair}{ |
|
\TBletpair |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTletpair}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBletpair |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBletpair}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rletpair} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash r : A \otimes B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A, y : B \vdash s : C$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Theta \vdash t : D$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta, \Theta \vdash |
|
\plet{x}{y}{r}{(s \sotimes t)} = (\plet{x}{y}{r}{s}) \sotimes t : D$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\RleqI}{ |
|
\text{(order)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TleqI}{ |
|
\TBleqI |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTleqI}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBleqI |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBleqI}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\RleqI} |
|
\AxiomC{ |
|
$\begin{array}{cc} |
|
\Gamma \vdash s : A + 1 & \Gamma \vdash t : A + 1\\ |
|
\Gamma \vdash b : (A + A) + 1 & \Gamma \vdash \doo{x}{b}{\rhd_1(x)} = s : A + 1\\ |
|
\multicolumn{2}{c}{\Gamma \vdash \doo{x}{b}{\return \nabla(x)} = t : A + 1} |
|
\end{array}$ |
|
} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash s \leq t : A + 1$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rinstr}{ |
|
\text{(instr)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tinstr}{ |
|
\TBinstr |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTinstr}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBinstr |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBinstr}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rinstr} |
|
\AxiomC{$x : A \vdash t : \mathbf{n}$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s : A$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \instr_{\lambda x t}(s) : n \cdot A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rnablainstr}{ |
|
\text{($\nabla$-instr)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tnablainstr}{ |
|
\TBnablainstr |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTnablainstr}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBnablainstr |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBnablainstr}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rnablainstr} |
|
\AxiomC{$x : A \vdash t : \mathbf{n}$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s : A$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \nabla(\instr_{\lambda x t}(s)) = s : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rinstrtest}{ |
|
\text{(instr-test)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tinstrtest}{ |
|
\TBinstrtest |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTinstrtest}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBinstrtest |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBinstrtest}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rinstrtest} |
|
\AxiomC{$x : A \vdash t : \mathbf{n}$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s : A$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \case_{i=1}^n \instr_{\lambda x t}(s) \of \nin{i}{n}{\_} \mapsto i = t[x:=s] : \mathbf{n}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Retainstr}{ |
|
\text{($\eta$instr)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tetainstr}{ |
|
\TBetainstr |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTetainstr}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBetainstr |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBetainstr}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Retainstr} |
|
\AxiomC{$x : A \vdash r : n \cdot A$} |
|
\AxiomC{$x : A \vdash \nabla(r) = x : A$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s : A$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \instr_{\lambda x. \case_{i=1}^n r \of \nin{i}{n}{\_} \mapsto i}(s) = r[x:=s] : n \cdot A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rinstreq}{ |
|
\text{(instr-eq)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tinstreq}{ |
|
\TBinstreq |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTinstreq}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBinstreq |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBinstreq}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rinstreq} |
|
\AxiomC{$x : A \vdash t = t' : \mathbf{n}$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash s = s' : A$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \instr_{\lambda x t}(s) = \instr_{\lambda x t'}(s') : n \cdot A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rcomm}{ |
|
\text{(comm)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tcomm}{ |
|
\TBcomm |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTcomm}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBcomm |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBcomm}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rcomm} |
|
\AxiomC{$x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\AxiomC{$x : A \vdash q : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
\assert_{\lambda x p}(t) \goesto \assert_{\lambda x q} = \assert_{\lambda x q}(t) \goesto \assert_{\lambda x p} : A + 1 |
|
\end{array}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Roneovern}{ |
|
\text{($1 / n$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Toneovern}{ |
|
\TBoneovern |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TToneovern}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBoneovern |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBoneovern}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Roneovern} |
|
\AxiomC{$$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash 1 / n : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rntimesoneovern}{ |
|
\text{($n \cdot 1 / n$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tntimesoneovern}{ |
|
\TBntimesoneovern |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTntimesoneovern}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBntimesoneovern |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBntimesoneovern}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rntimesoneovern} |
|
\AxiomC{$$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash n \cdot 1 / n = \top : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rdivide}{ |
|
\text{(divide)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tdivide}{ |
|
\TBdivide |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTdivide}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBdivide |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBdivide}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rdivide} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash n \cdot t = \top : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash t = 1 / n : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rnorm}{ |
|
\text{(nrm)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tnorm}{ |
|
\TBnorm |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTnorm}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBnorm |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBnorm}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rnorm} |
|
\AxiomC{$\vdash t : A + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\vdash 1 / n \leq t : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \norm{t} : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rbetanorm}{ |
|
\text{($\beta$nrm)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tbetanorm}{ |
|
\TBbetanorm |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTbetanorm}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBbetanorm |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBbetanorm}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rbetanorm} |
|
\AxiomC{$\vdash t : A + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\vdash 1 / n \leq t \downarrow : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash t = \doo{\_}{t}{\return{\norm{t}}} : A + 1$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Retanorm}{ |
|
\text{($\eta$nrm)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tetanorm}{ |
|
\TBetanorm |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTetanorm}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBetanorm |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBetanorm}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Retanorm} |
|
\AxiomC{$\vdash t : A + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\vdash 1 / n \leq t \downarrow : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\vdash \rho : A$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\vdash t = \doo{\_}{t}{\return{\rho}} : A + 1$} |
|
\QuaternaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \rho = \norm{t} : A$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rrhdoneboundmn}{ |
|
\text{($\rhd_1-b_{mn}$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Trhdoneboundmn}{ |
|
\TBrhdoneboundmn |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTrhdoneboundmn}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBrhdoneboundmn |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBrhdoneboundmn}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rrhdoneboundmn} |
|
\AxiomC{$$} |
|
\RightLabel{$\left(1 \leq m < n\right)$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \doo{x}{b_{mn}}{\rhd_1(x)} = m \cdot 1 / n : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rrhdtwoboundmnprime}{ |
|
\text{($\rhd_2-b_{mn}$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Trhdtwoboundmnprime}{ |
|
\TBrhdtwoboundmnprime |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTrhdtwoboundmnprime}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBrhdtwoboundmnprime |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBrhdtwoboundmnprime}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rrhdtwoboundmnprime} |
|
\AxiomC{$$} |
|
\RightLabel{$\left(1 \leq m < n\right)$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \doo{x}{b_{mn}}{\return \nabla(x)} = 1 / n : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rboundmn}{ |
|
\text{($b_{mn}$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tboundmn}{ |
|
\TBboundmn |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTboundmn}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBboundmn |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBboundmn}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rboundmn} |
|
\AxiomC{$$} |
|
\RightLabel{$\left(1 \leq m < n\right)$} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash b_{mn} : \mathbf{3}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Roveeprime}{ |
|
\text{($\ovee$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Toveeprime}{ |
|
\TBoveeprime |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TToveeprime}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBoveeprime |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBoveeprime}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Roveeprime} |
|
\AxiomC{ |
|
$\begin{array}{cc} |
|
\Gamma \vdash s : A + 1 & \Gamma \vdash t : A + 1\\ |
|
\Gamma \vdash b : (A + A) + 1 & \Gamma \vdash \doo{x}{b}{\rhd_1(x)} = s : A + 1\\ |
|
\multicolumn{2}{c}{\Gamma \vdash \doo{x}{b}{\rhd_2(x)} = t : A + 1} |
|
\end{array}$ |
|
} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t : A + 1$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Roveedef}{ |
|
\text{($\ovee$-def)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Toveedef}{ |
|
\TBoveedef |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TToveedef}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBoveedef |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBoveedef}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Roveedef} |
|
\AxiomC{ |
|
$\begin{array}{cc} |
|
\Gamma \vdash s : A + 1 & \Gamma \vdash t : A + 1\\ |
|
\Gamma \vdash b : (A + A) + 1 & \Gamma \vdash \doo{x}{b}{\rhd_1(x)} = s : A + 1\\ |
|
\multicolumn{2}{c}{\Gamma \vdash \doo{x}{b}{\rhd_2(x)} = t : A + 1} |
|
\end{array}$ |
|
} |
|
\UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t = \doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}} : A + 1$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rletsub}{ |
|
\text{(letsub)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tletsub}{ |
|
\TBletsub |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTletsub}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBletsub |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBletsub}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rletsub} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash r : A \otimes B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A, y : B \vdash s : C$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Theta, z : C \vdash t : D$} |
|
\TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta, \Theta \vdash t[z:=\plet{x}{y}{r}{s}] = \plet{x}{y}{r}{t[z:=s]} : D$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rcasesub}{ |
|
\text{(case-sub)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tcasesub}{ |
|
\TBcasesub |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTcasesub}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBcasesub |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBcasesub}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rcasesub} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash r : A + B$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A \vdash s : C$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, y : B \vdash s' : C$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Theta, z : C \vdash t : D$} |
|
\QuaternaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta, \Theta \vdash \begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
t[z:=\pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{s'}] \\ |
|
= \pcase{r}{x}{t[z:=s]}{y}{t[z:=s']} : D |
|
\end{array}$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rassert}{ |
|
\text{(assert)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tassert}{ |
|
\TBassert |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTassert}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBassert |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBassert}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rassert} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A$} |
|
\AxiomC{$x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \assert_{\lambda x p}(t) : A + 1$} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Rgoesto}{ |
|
\text{($\goesto$)\xspace} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Tgoesto}{ |
|
\TBgoesto |
|
\DisplayProof |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TTgoesto}{ |
|
\begin{prooftree} |
|
\TBgoesto |
|
\end{prooftree} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\TBgoesto}{ |
|
\LeftLabel{\Rgoesto} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash t : A + 1$} |
|
\AxiomC{$\Delta, x : A \vdash f(x) : B + 1$} |
|
\BinaryInfC{$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash t \goesto f : B + 1$} |
|
} \newcommand{\Lweak}{ |
|
\begin{lm} |
|
\label{lm:weak} |
|
The following rule of deduction is admissible. \TTweak |
|
\end{lm} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Lsub}{ |
|
\begin{lm} |
|
\label{lm:sub} |
|
The following rule of deduction is admissible. \TTsub |
|
\end{lm} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Leqval}{ |
|
\begin{lm} |
|
\label{lm:eqval} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash s = t : A$ then $\Gamma \vdash s : A$ and $\Gamma \vdash t : A$. |
|
\end{lm} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Lineqval}{ |
|
\begin{lm} |
|
\label{lm:ineqval} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash s \leq t : A$ then $\Gamma \vdash s : A$ and $\Gamma \vdash t : A |
|
\end{lm} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Lfunc}{ |
|
\begin{lm} |
|
\label{lm:func} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash r = s : A$ and $\Delta, x : A \vdash t : B$ then $\Gamma, \Delta \vdash t[x:=r] = t[x:=s] : B$. |
|
\end{lm} |
|
} |
|
\newcommand{\Sets}{\mathbf{Sets}} |
|
\newcommand{\Kl}{\mathcal{K}{\kern-.2ex}\ell} |
|
\newcommand{\Dst}{\mathcal{D}} |
|
\newcommand{\Giry}{\mathcal{G}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\Pred}{\mathbf{Pred}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\assert}{\mathsf{assert}} |
|
\newcommand{\case}{\mathsf{case}\ } |
|
\newcommand{\elsen}{\ \mathsf{else}\ } |
|
\newcommand{\idmap}[1][]{\ensuremath{\mathrm{id}_{#1}}} |
|
\newcommand{\id}{\idmap} |
|
\newcommand{\cond}[3]{\ifn {#1} \thenn {#2} \elsen {#3}} |
|
\newcommand{\ifn}{\mathsf{if}\ } |
|
\newcommand{\inln}{\mathsf{inl}} |
|
\newcommand{\inlprop}[1]{\mathsf{inl?} \left( {#1} \right)} |
|
\newcommand{\inlrn}{\mathsf{inlr}} |
|
\newcommand{\inl}[1]{\inln \left( {#1} \right)} |
|
\newcommand{\inn}{\ \mathsf{in}\ } |
|
\newcommand{\inrn}{\mathsf{inr}} |
|
\newcommand{\inrprop}[1]{\mathsf{inr?} \left( {#1} \right)} |
|
\newcommand{\inr}[1]{\inrn \left( {#1} \right)} |
|
\newcommand{\lett}{\mathsf{let}\ } |
|
\newcommand{\lftn}{\mathsf{left}} |
|
\newcommand{\lft}[1]{\lftn \left( {#1} \right)} |
|
\newcommand{\instr}{\mathsf{instr}} |
|
\newcommand{\measure}{\mathbf{TODO}} |
|
\newcommand{\meas}{\mathsf{measure}} |
|
\newcommand{\norm}[1]{\ensuremath{\mathsf{nrm} \left( {#1} \right)}} |
|
\newcommand{\of}{\ \mathsf{of}\ } |
|
\newcommand{\pcase}[5]{\case {#1} \of \inl{#2} \mapsto {#3}\mid \inr{#4} \mapsto {#5}} |
|
\newcommand{\rgtn}{\mathsf{right}} |
|
\newcommand{\rgt}[1]{\rgtn \left( {#1} \right)} |
|
\newcommand{\swapper}[1]{\ensuremath{\mathsf{swap} \left( {#1} \right)}} |
|
\newcommand{\thenn}{\ \mathsf{then}\ } |
|
\newcommand{\type}{\ \mathrm{type}} |
|
\newcommand{\nin}[3]{\mathsf{in}_{#1}^{#2} \left( {#3} \right)} |
|
\newcommand{\return}[1]{\mathsf{return}\ {#1}} |
|
\newcommand{\fail}{\mathsf{fail}} |
|
\newcommand{\doo}[3]{\mathsf{do}\ {#1} \leftarrow {#2} ; {#3}} |
|
\newcommand{\ind}[1]{\ensuremath{\mathsf{index} \left( {#1} \right)}} |
|
\newcommand{\intest}[2]{\mathsf{in}_{#1} ? \left( {#2} \right)} |
|
\newcommand{\condn}[2]{\mathsf{cond} \left( {#1} , {#2} \right)} |
|
\newcommand{\bang}{\mathord{!}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\inlr}[2]{\ensuremath{\text{\guillemotleft} {#1} , {#2} \text{\guillemotright}}} |
|
\newcommand{\eqdef}{\mathrel{\smash{\stackrel{\text{def}}{=}}}} |
|
\newcommand{\fromInit}{\,\mathop{\text{\rm \textexclamdown}}} |
|
\newcommand{\magic}[1]{\fromInit{#1}} |
|
\newcommand{\sotimes}{\mathrel{\raisebox{.05pc}{$\scriptstyle\otimes$}}} |
|
\newcommand{\plet}[4]{\lett {#1} \sotimes {#2} = {#3} \inn {#4}} |
|
\newcommand{\slet}[3]{\lett {#1} = {#2} \inn {#3}} |
|
\newcommand{\ifte}[3]{\ifn {#1} \thenn {#2} \elsen {#3}} |
|
\newcommand{\bigovee}{\mathop{\vphantom{\sum}\mathchoice {\vcenter{\hbox{\huge $\ovee$}}}{\vcenter{\hbox{\Large $\ovee$}}}{\ovee}{\ovee}}\displaylimits} |
|
\newcommand{\goesto}{\ensuremath{\gg\!\!=}} |
|
\newcommand{\andthen}{\mathrel{\&}} |
|
\renewcommand{\ker}[1]{{#1}\!\uparrow} |
|
\newcommand{\dom}[1]{{#1}\!\downarrow} |
|
\newcommand{\after}{\circ} |
|
\newcommand{\supp}{\mathop{\mathrm{supp}}} |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\brackets}[1]{\left[ \! \left[ {#1} \right] \! \right]} |
|
\newcommand{\Prob}[1]{\mathrm{Pr} \left( {#1} \right)} |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\COMET}{\mathbf{COMET}} |
|
|
|
\renewcommand{\arraystretch}{1.3} |
|
\setlength{\arraycolsep}{2pt} |
|
|
|
|
|
\theoremstyle{plain} |
|
\newtheorem{proposition}[theorem]{Proposition} |
|
|
|
\begin{document} |
|
|
|
\maketitle |
|
|
|
\begin{abstract} |
|
This paper introduces a novel type theory and logic for probabilistic |
|
reasoning. Its logic is quantitative, with fuzzy predicates. It |
|
includes normalisation and conditioning of states. This conditioning |
|
uses a key aspect that distinguishes our probabilistic type theory |
|
from quantum type theory, namely the bijective correspondence between |
|
predicates and side-effect free actions (called instrument, or assert, |
|
maps). The paper shows how suitable computation rules can be derived |
|
from this predicate-action correspondence, and uses these rules for |
|
calculating conditional probabilities in two well-known examples of |
|
Bayesian reasoning in (graphical) models. Our type theory may thus |
|
form the basis for a mechanisation of Bayesian inference. |
|
\end{abstract} |
|
|
|
|
|
\section{Introduction} |
|
|
|
A probabilistic program is understood (semantically) as a stochastic |
|
process. A key feature of probabilistic programs as studied in the |
|
1980s and 1990s is the presence of probabilistic choice, for instance |
|
in the form of a weighted sum $x +_{r} y$, where the number $r \in |
|
[0,1]$ determines the ratio of the contributions of $x$ and $y$ to the |
|
result. This can be expressed explicitly as a convex sum $r\cdot x + |
|
(1-r)\cdot y$. Some of the relevant sources |
|
are~\cite{Kozen81,Kozen85}, and~\cite{JonesP89}, |
|
and~\cite{MorganMS96}, and also~\cite{TixKP05} for the combination of |
|
probability and non-determinism. In the language of category theory, a |
|
probabilistic program is a map in the Kleisli category of the |
|
distribution monad $\Dst$ (in the discrete case) or of the Giry monad |
|
$\Giry$ (in the continuous case). |
|
|
|
In recent years, with the establishement of Bayesian machine learning |
|
as an important area of computer science, the meaning of probabilistic |
|
programming shifted towards conditional inference. The key feature is |
|
no longer probabilistic choice, but normalisation of distributions |
|
(states), see \textit{e.g.}~\cite{Borgstroem2011}. Interestingly, this |
|
can be done in basically the same underlying models, where a program |
|
still produces a distribution --- discrete or continuous --- over its |
|
output. |
|
|
|
This paper contributes to this latest line of work by formulating a |
|
novel type theory for probabilistic and Bayesian reasoning. We list |
|
the key features of our type theory. |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item It includes a logic, which is quantitative in nature. This means |
|
that its predicates are best understood as `fuzzy' predicates, |
|
taking values in the unit interval $[0,1]$ of probabilities, instead |
|
of in the two-element set $\{0,1\}$ of Booleans. |
|
|
|
\item As a result, the predicates of this logic do not form Boolean |
|
algebras, but effect modules (see \emph{e.g.}~\cite{Jacobs15d}). The |
|
double negation rule does hold, but the sum $\ovee$ is a partial |
|
operation. Moreover, there is a scalar multiplication $s\cdot p$, |
|
for a scalar $s$ and a predicate $p$, which produces a scaled |
|
version of the predicate $p$. |
|
|
|
\item This logic is a special case of a more general quantum type |
|
theory~\cite{Adams2014}. What we describe here is the probabilistic |
|
subcase of this quantum type theory, which is characterised by a |
|
bijective correspondence between predicates and side-effect free |
|
assert maps (see below for details). |
|
|
|
\item The type theory includes normalisation (and also probabilistic |
|
choice). Abstractly, normalisation means that each non-zero |
|
`substate' in the type theory can be turned into a proper state |
|
(like in~\cite{JacobsWW15a}). This involves, for instance, turning a |
|
\emph{sub}distribution $\sum_{i}r_{i}x_{i}$, where the probabilities |
|
$r_{i}\in [0,1]$ satisfy $0 < r \leq 1$ for $r \eqdef |
|
\sum_{i}r_{i}$, into a proper distribution |
|
$\sum_{i}\frac{r_i}{r}x_{i}$ --- where, by construction, |
|
$\sum_{i}\frac{r_i}{r} = 1$. |
|
|
|
\item The type theory also includes conditioning, via the combination |
|
of assert maps and normalisation (from the previous two points). |
|
Hence, we can calculate conditional probabilities inside the type |
|
theory, via appropriate (derived) computation rules. In contrast, in |
|
the language of~\cite{Borgstroem2011}, probabilistic (graphical) |
|
models can be formulated, but actual computations are done in the |
|
underlying mathematical models. Since these computation are done |
|
inside our calculus, our type theory can form the basis for |
|
mechanisation. |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
|
|
The type theory that we present is based on a new categorical |
|
foundation for quantum logic, called effectus theory, |
|
see~\cite{Jacobs15d,JacobsWW15a,Cho15a,ChoJWW15}\footnote{A general |
|
introduction to effectus theory~\cite{Cho} will soon be |
|
available.}. This theory involves a basic duality between states and |
|
effects (predicates), which is implicitly also present in our type |
|
theory. A subclass of `commutative' effectuses can be defined, forming |
|
models for probabilistic computation and logic. Our type theory |
|
corresponds to these commutative effectuses, and will thus be called |
|
$\COMET$, as abbreviation of COMmutative Effectus Theory. This |
|
$\COMET$ can be seen as an internal language for commutative |
|
effectuses. |
|
|
|
A key feature of quantum theory is that observations have a |
|
side-effect: measuring a system disturbs it at the quantum level. In |
|
order to perform such measurements, each quantum predicate comes with |
|
an associated `measurement' instrument operation which acts on the |
|
underlying space. Probabilistic theories also have such instruments |
|
\ldots but they are side-effect free! |
|
|
|
The idea that predicates come with an associated action is familiar in |
|
mathematics. For instance, in a Hilbert space $\mathscr{H}$, a closed |
|
subspace $P \subseteq \mathscr{H}$ (a predicate) can equivalently be |
|
described as a linear idempotent operator $p\colon \mathscr{H} |
|
\rightarrow \mathscr{H}$ (an action) that has $P$ has image. We sketch |
|
how these predicate-action correspondences also exist in the models |
|
that underly our type theory. |
|
|
|
First, in the category $\Sets$ of sets and functions, a predicate $p$ |
|
on a set $X$ can be identified with a subset of $X$, but also with a |
|
`characteristic' map $p\colon X \rightarrow 1+1$, where $1+1 = 2$ is |
|
the two-element set. We prefer the latter view. Such a predicate |
|
corresponds bijectively to a `side-effect free' instrument |
|
$\instr_{p} \colon X \rightarrow X+X$, namely to: |
|
$$\begin{array}{rcl} |
|
\instr_{p}(x) |
|
& = & |
|
\left\{\begin{array}{ll} |
|
\inl{x} \mbox{\quad} & \mbox{if } p(x) = 1 \\ |
|
\inr{x} & \mbox{if } p(x) = 0 \\ |
|
\end{array}\right. |
|
\end{array}$$ |
|
|
|
\noindent Here we write $X+X$ for the sum (coproduct), with left and |
|
right coprojections (also called injections) $\inl{\_}, \inr{\_} |
|
\colon X \rightarrow X+X$. Notice that this instrument merely makes a |
|
left-right distinction, as described by the predicate, but does not |
|
change the state $x$. It is called side-effect free because it |
|
satisfies $\nabla \after \instr_{p} = \idmap$, where $\nabla = |
|
[\idmap,\idmap] \colon X+X \rightarrow X$ is the codiagonal. It easy |
|
to see that each map $f\colon X \rightarrow X+X$ with $\nabla \after f |
|
= \idmap$ corresponds to a predicate $p\colon X \rightarrow 1+1$, |
|
namely to $p = (\bang+\bang) \after f$, where $\bang \colon X |
|
\rightarrow 1$ is the unique map to the final (singleton, unit) set |
|
$1$. |
|
|
|
Our next example describes the same predicate-action correspondence in |
|
a probabilistic setting. It assumes familiarity with the discrete |
|
distribution monad $\Dst$ --- see~\cite{Jacobs15d} for details, and |
|
also Subsection~\ref{section:dpc} --- and with its Kleisli category |
|
$\Kl(\Dst)$. A predicate map $p\colon X \rightarrow 1+1$ in |
|
$\Kl(\Dst)$ is (essentially) a fuzzy predicate $p\colon X \rightarrow |
|
[0,1]$, since $\Dst(1+1) = \Dst(2) \cong [0,1]$. There is also an |
|
associated instrument map $\instr_{p} \colon X \rightarrow X+X$ in |
|
$\Kl(\Dst)$, given by the function $\instr_{p} \colon X \rightarrow |
|
\Dst(X+X)$ that sends an element $x\in X$ to the distribution |
|
(formal convex combination): |
|
$$\begin{array}{rcl} |
|
\instr_{p}(x) |
|
& = & |
|
p(x)\cdot \inl{x} + (1-p(x))\cdot \inr{x}. |
|
\end{array}$$ |
|
|
|
\noindent This instrument makes a left-right distinction, with the |
|
weight of the distinction given by the fuzzy predicate $p$. Again we |
|
have $\nabla \after \instr_{p} = \idmap$, in the Kleisli category, |
|
since the instrument map does not change the state. It is easy to see |
|
that we get a bijective correspondence. |
|
|
|
These instrument maps $\instr_{p} \colon X \rightarrow X+X$ can in |
|
fact be simplified further into what we call assert maps. The |
|
(partial) map $\assert_{p} \colon X \rightarrow X+1$ can be defined as |
|
$\assert_{p} = (\idmap+\bang) \after \instr_{p}$. We say that such a |
|
map is side-effect free if there is an inequality $\assert_{p} \leq |
|
\inl{\_}$, for a suitable order on the homset of partial maps $X |
|
\rightarrow X+1$. Given assert maps for $p$, and for its |
|
orthosupplement (negation) $p^{\bot}$, we can define the associated |
|
instrument via a partial pairing operation as $\instr_{p} = |
|
\inlr{\assert_p}{\assert_{p^\bot}}$, see below for details. |
|
|
|
The key aspect of a probabilistic model, in contrast to a quantum model, |
|
is that there is a bijective correspondence between: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item predicates $X \rightarrow 1+1$ |
|
\item side-effect free instruments $X \rightarrow X+X$ --- or |
|
equivalently, side-effect free assert maps $X \rightarrow X+1$. |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
|
|
\noindent We shall define conditioning via normalisation after assert. |
|
More specifically, for a state $\omega\colon X$ and a predicate $p$ on |
|
$X$ we define the conditional state $\omega|_{p} = \condn{\omega}{p}$ |
|
as: |
|
$$\begin{array}{rcl} |
|
\condn{\omega}{p} |
|
& = & |
|
\norm{\assert_{p}(\omega)}, |
|
\end{array}$$ |
|
|
|
\noindent where $\norm{-}$ describes normalisation (of substates to |
|
states). This description occurs, in semantical form |
|
in~\cite{JacobsWW15a}. Here we formalise it at a type-theoretic level |
|
and derive suitable computation rules from it that allow us to do |
|
(exact) conditional inference. |
|
|
|
The paper is organised as follows. Section~\ref{section:overview} |
|
provides an overview of the type theory, with some key results, |
|
without giving all the details and |
|
proofs. Section~\ref{section:examples} takes two familiar examples of |
|
Bayesian reasoning and formalises them in our type theory $\COMET$. |
|
Subsequently, Section~\ref{section:metatheorems} explores the type |
|
theory in greater depth, and provides justification for the |
|
computation rules in the examples. Next, |
|
Section~\ref{section:semantics} sketches how our type theory can be |
|
interpreted in set-theoretic and probabilistic |
|
models. Appendix~\ref{section:rules} contains a formal presentation of |
|
the type theory $\COMET$. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\section{Syntax and Rules of Deduction} |
|
\label{section:overview} |
|
|
|
We present here the terms and types of $\COMET$. We shall describe the system |
|
at a high level here, giving the intuition behind each construction. The complete list of |
|
the rules of deduction of $\COMET$ is given in Appendix \ref{section:rules}, and the |
|
properties that we use are all proved in Section \ref{section:metatheorems}. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Syntax} |
|
|
|
Assume we are given a set of |
|
\emph{type constants} $\mathbf{C}$, representing the base data types needed for each example. (These may typically include for instance $\mathbf{bool}$, $\mathbf{nat}$ and $\mathbf{real}$.) |
|
Then the types of $\COMET$ are the following. |
|
$$ \begin{array}{lrcll} |
|
\text{Type} & A & ::= & \mathbf{C} \mid & \text{constant type} \\ |
|
& & & 0 \mid & \text{empty type} \\ |
|
& & & 1 \mid & \text{unit type} \\ |
|
& & & A + B \mid & \text{disjoint union} \\ |
|
& & & A \otimes B & \text{pairs} |
|
\end{array} $$ |
|
|
|
The \emph{terms} of $\COMET$ are given by the following grammar. |
|
|
|
$$ \begin{array}{lrcll} |
|
\text{Term} & t & ::= & x \mid & \text{variable} \\ |
|
& & & * \mid & \text{element of unit type} \\ |
|
& & & t \sotimes t \mid & \text{pair} \\ |
|
& & & \plet{x}{y}{t}{t} \mid & \text{decomposing a pair} \\ |
|
& & & \magic{t} \mid & \text{eliminate element of empty type} \\ |
|
& & & \inl{t} \mid \inr{t} \mid & \text{elements of a disjoint union} \\ |
|
& & & (\pcase{t}{x}{t}{x}{t}) \mid & \text{case distinction over union} \\ |
|
& & & \inlr{s}{t} \mid & \text{partial pairing} \\ |
|
& & & \lft{t} \mid & \text{extract element of union} \\ |
|
& & & \instr_{\lambda x t}{t} \mid & \text{instrument map} \\ |
|
& & & 1/n \mid & \text{constant scalar} (n \geq 2) \\ |
|
& & & \norm{t} \mid & \text{normalised substate} \\ |
|
& & & s \ovee t & \text{partial sum} |
|
\end{array}$$ |
|
|
|
The variables $x$ and $y$ are bound within $s$ in $\plet{x}{y}{s}{t}$. The variable $x$ is bound within $s$ and $y$ within $t$ in $\pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{t}$, and $x$ is bound within $t$ in $\instr_{\lambda x t}(s)$. |
|
We identify terms up to $\alpha$-conversion (change of bound variable). We write $t[x:=s]$ for the result of substituting $s$ for $x$ within $t$, renaming bound variables to avoid variable capture. |
|
We shall write $\_$ for a vacuous bound variable; for example, we write $\pcase{r}{\_}{s}{y}{t}$ for $\pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{t}$ when $y$ does not occur free in $s$. |
|
|
|
We shall also sometimes abbreviate our terms, for example writing $\instr_{\mathsf{inl}}(t)$ when we should strictly write $\instr_{\lambda x \inl{x}}(t)$. Each time, the meaning should be clear from context. |
|
|
|
The typing rules for these terms are given in Figure \ref{fig:typing}. (Note that some of these rules make use of defined |
|
expressions, which will be introduced in the sections below.) |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{mdframed} |
|
$$ \Tvar \; \Tunit \; \Tpair $$ |
|
\TTlett |
|
$$ \Tmagic \; \Tinl \; \Tinr $$ |
|
\TTcase |
|
\TTinlr |
|
$$ \Tleft \; \Tinstr $$ |
|
$$ \Toneovern \; \Tnorm $$ |
|
\TToveeprime |
|
\end{mdframed} |
|
\caption{Typing rules for $\COMET$} |
|
\label{fig:typing} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
The typing rule for the term $\magic{t}$ |
|
says that from an inhabitant $t:0$ we can produce an inhabitant |
|
$\magic{t}$ in any type $A$. Intuitively, this says `If the empty type is inhabited, |
|
then every type is inhabited', which is vacuously true. |
|
|
|
A term of type $A$ is intended to represent a \emph{total} computation, that always terminates and returns a value of type $A$. |
|
We can think of a term of type $A + 1$ as a \emph{partial} computation that may return a value $a$ of type $A$ |
|
(by outputting $\inl{a}$) or diverge (by outputting $\inr{*}$). The judgement $s \leq t$ should be understood as: |
|
the probability that $s$ returns $\inl{a}$ is $\leq$ the probability that $t$ returns $\inl{a}$, for all $a$. The rule for this |
|
ordering relation is given in Figure \ref{fig:ordering}. |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{mdframed} |
|
\TTleqI |
|
\end{mdframed} |
|
\caption{Rule for Ordering in $\COMET$} |
|
\label{fig:ordering} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
The term $\inlr{s}{t}$ is understood intuitively as follows. We are |
|
given two partial computations $s$ and $t$, and we have derived the |
|
judgement $\dom{s} = \ker{t}$, which tells us that exactly one of |
|
$s$ and $t$ converges on any given input. We may then form the |
|
computation $\inlr{s}{t}$ which, given an input $x$, returns either |
|
$s(x)$ or $t(x)$, whichever of the two converges. |
|
|
|
For the term $\lft{t}$: if we have a term $t : A + B$ and we have derived the judgement $\inlprop{t} = \top$, then we know |
|
that $t$ has the form $\inl{a}$ for some term $a : A$. We denote this unique term $a$ by $\lft{t}$. |
|
|
|
For the term $\instr_{\lambda x t}(s)$: think of the type $\mathbf{n}$ as the set $\{ 1, \ldots, n \}$. The elements of the type $A + \cdots + A$ consist of $n$ copies of each element $a$ of $A$, |
|
denoted $\nin{1}{n}{a}$, \ldots, $\nin{n}{n}{a}$. Then $\instr_{\lambda x t}(s)$ is the object $\nin{t[x:=s]}{n}{s}$. It maps $s$ into one of the $n$ copies of $A$, which one being |
|
determined by the test $t$. |
|
|
|
The term $1 / n$ represents the probability distribution on $\mathbf{2} = \{ \top, \bot \}$ which returns $\top$ with probability $1 / n$ and $\bot$ with probability $(n - 1) / n$. It can |
|
be thought of as a coin toss, with a weighted coin that returns heads with probability $1 / n$. |
|
|
|
For the term $\norm{t}$: the term $t : A + 1$ represents a distribution on $A + 1$. Let $s$ denote the probability that $t$ terminates (i.e. returns a term of the form $\inl{a}$), and let |
|
$\omega(a)$ denote the probability that $t$ returns $a$. Then $\norm{t}$ returns $a$ with probability $\omega(a) / s$. Thus, $\norm{t}$ is the distribution resulting from normalising |
|
the subdistribution given by $t$. |
|
|
|
The term $s \ovee t$ is the `sum' of $s$ and $t$ in the following sense. It is defined on a given input if and only if, for any $a$, the probability that $s$ and $t$ both return $\inl{a}$ is $\leq 1$. |
|
In this case, the probability that $s \ovee t$ returns $\inl{a}$ is the sum of these two probabilities. |
|
|
|
The computation rules that these terms obey are given in Figure \ref{fig:equations}. |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{mdframed} |
|
\begin{gather*} |
|
\plet{x}{y}{r \sotimes s}{t} = t[x:=r,y:=s] \tag*{\Rbeta} \\ |
|
\pcase{\inl{r}}{x}{s}{y}{t} = s[x:=r] \tag*{\Rbetaplusone} \\ |
|
\pcase{\inr{r}}{x}{s}{y}{t} = t[y:=r] \tag*{\Rbetaplustwo} \\ |
|
\rhd_1(\inlr{s}{t}) = s \tag*{\Rbetainlrone} \\ |
|
\rhd_2(\inlr{s}{t}) = t \tag*{\Rbetainlrtwo} \\ |
|
\inl{\lft{t}} = t \tag*{\Rbetaleft} \\ |
|
\lft{\inl{t}} = t \tag*{\Retaleft} \\ |
|
\ind{\instr_{\lambda x p}(t)} = p[x:=t] \tag*{\Rinstrtest} \\ |
|
\nabla(\instr_{\lambda x p}(t)) = t \tag*{\Rnablainstr} \\ |
|
\text{if } \nabla(t) = x \text{ then } \instr_{\lambda x \ind{t}}(s) = t[x:=s] \tag*{\Retainstr} \\ |
|
\text{if } t : 1 \text{ then } * = t \tag*{\Retaone} \\ |
|
\text{if } t : A \otimes B \text{ then } \plet{x}{y}{t}{x \sotimes y} = t \tag*{\Reta} \\ |
|
\text{if } t : A + B \text{ then } t\case t \of \inl{x} \mapsto \inl{x} \mid \inr{y} \mapsto \inr{y} = t \tag*{\Retaplus} \\ |
|
\text{if } t : A + B \text{ then } \inlr{\rhd_1(t)}{\rhd_2(t)} = t \tag*{\Retainlr} \\ |
|
\text{if } t \text{ is well-typed then } \doo{\_}{t}{\return{\norm{t}}} = t \tag*{\Rbetanorm} \\ |
|
\text{if } t = \doo{\_}{t}{\return{\rho}} \text{ and } 1 / n \leq t, \text{ then } \rho = \norm{t} |
|
\tag*{\Retanorm} \\ |
|
n \cdot 1 / n = \top |
|
\tag*{\Rntimesoneovern} \\ |
|
\text{if } n \cdot t = \top \text{ then } t = 1/n |
|
\tag*{\Rdivide} |
|
\end{gather*} |
|
\end{mdframed} |
|
\caption{Computation rules for $\COMET$} |
|
\label{fig:equations} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
Figures \ref{fig:typing} and \ref{fig:equations} should be understood |
|
simultaneously. So the term $\inlr{s}{t}$ is well-typed if and only |
|
if we can type $s : A + 1$ and $t : B + 1$ (using the rules in Figure |
|
\ref{fig:typing}), \emph{and} derive the equation $\dom{s} = \ker{t}$ |
|
using the rules in Figure~\ref{fig:equations}. |
|
|
|
The full set of rules of deduction for the system is given in Appendix \ref{section:rules}. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Linear Type Theory} |
|
|
|
Note the form of several of the typing rules in Figure \ref{fig:typing}, including\Rpair and\Rlett. These rules do not allow |
|
a variable to be duplicated; in particular, we cannot derive the judgement $x : A \vdash x \sotimes x : A \otimes A$. The \emph{contraction} rule does not hold in our type theory --- it is not the case in general that, if $\Gamma, x : A, y : B \vdash \mathcal{J}$, then $\Gamma, z : A \vdash \mathcal{J}[x:=z,y:=z]$. Our theory is thus similar to a \emph{linear} type theory (see for example \cite{Benton93aterm}). |
|
|
|
The reason is that these judgements do not behave well with respect to substitution. For example, take the computation $x : \mathbf{2} \vdash x \sotimes x : 2 \otimes 2$. |
|
If we apply this computation to the scalar $1 / 2$, we presumably wish the result to be $\top \sotimes \top$ with probability $1/2$, and $\bot \sotimes \bot$ with probability $1/2$. But |
|
this is not the semantics for the term $\vdash 1/2 \sotimes 1/2 : 2 \otimes 2$. This term assigns probability $1/4$ to all four possibilities $\top \sotimes \top$, $\top \sotimes \bot$, $\bot \sotimes \top$, |
|
$\top \sotimes \top$. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Defined Constructions} |
|
We can define the following types and computations from the primitive constructions given above. |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{States, Predicates and Scalars} |
|
|
|
A closed term $\vdash t : A$ will be called a \emph{state} of type $A$, and intuitively it represents a probability distribution over the elements of $A$. |
|
|
|
A \emph{predicate} on type $A$ is a proposition of the form $x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$. These shall be the formulas of the logic of $\COMET$ (see Section \ref{section:logic}). |
|
|
|
A \emph{scalar} is a term $s$ such that $\vdash s : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
The closed terms $t$ such that $\vdash t : \mathbf{2}$ are called \emph{scalars}, and represent the \emph{probabilities} or \emph{truth values} of our system. In our intended semantics for discrete and continuous probabilities, these |
|
denote elements of the real interval $[0,1]$. |
|
|
|
Given a state $\vdash t : A$ and a predicate $x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$, we can find the probability that $p$ is true when measured on $t$; this probability is simply the scalar $p[x:=t]$. |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Coproducts and Copowers} |
|
\label{section:copowers} |
|
|
|
Since we have the coproduct $A + B$ of two types, we can construct the disjoint union of $n$ types $A_1 + \cdots + A_n$ in the obvious way. We write $\nin{1}{n}{}$, \ldots, $\nin{n}{n}{}$ |
|
for its constructors; thus, if $a : A_i$ then $\nin{i}{n}{a} : A_1 + \cdots + A_n$. And given $t : A_1 + \cdots + A_n$, we can eliminate it as: |
|
\[ \case t \of \nin{1}{n}{x_1} \mapsto t_1 \mid \cdots \mid \nin{n}{n}{x_n} \mapsto t_n \enspace . \] |
|
We abbreviate this expression as $\case_{i=1}^n\ t \of \nin{i}{n}{x_i} \mapsto t_i$. |
|
|
|
For the special case where all the types are equal, we write $n \cdot A$ for the type $A + \cdots + A$, where there are $n$ copies of $A$. In category |
|
theory, this is known as the $n$th \emph{copower} of $A$. (We |
|
include the special cases $0 \cdot A \eqdef 0$ and $1 \cdot A \eqdef A$.) |
|
|
|
The \emph{codiagonal} $\nabla(t) : A$ for $t : n \cdot A$ is defined by |
|
\[ \nabla(t) = \case_{i=1}^n\ t \of \nin{i}{n}{x} \mapsto x \enspace . \] |
|
This computation extracts the value of type $A$ and discards the information about which of the $n$ copies it came from. |
|
|
|
We write $\mathbf{n}$ for $n \cdot 1$. Intuitively, this is a finite type with $n$ canonical elements. We denote these elements by $1$, $2$, \ldots, $n$: |
|
\[ i \eqdef \nin{i}{n}{*} : \mathbf{n} \qquad (1 \leq i \leq n) \enspace . \] |
|
For $t : n \cdot A$, we define |
|
\[ \ind{t} = \case_{i=1}^n t \of \nin{i}{n}{\_} \mapsto i : \mathbf{n} \enspace . \] |
|
Thus, if $t = \nin{i}{n}{a}$, then $\ind{t}$ extracts the index $i$ and throws away the value $a$. |
|
|
|
We have the $\lft{}$ construction, which extracts a term of type $A$ from a term of type $A + B$. |
|
We have a similar $\rgt{}$ construction, but there is no need to give primitive rules for this one, as it can be defined in terms of $\lft{}$: |
|
\[ \rgt{t} \eqdef \lft{\swapper{t}} \] |
|
where $\swapper{t} = \pcase{t}{x}{\inr{x}}{y}{\inl{y}}$. |
|
|
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Partial Functions} |
|
|
|
We may see a term $\Gamma \vdash t : A + 1$ as denoting a \emph{partial function} into $A$, which has some probability of terminating (returning a value of form $\inl{s}$) and some probability of diverging (returning $\inr{*}$). |
|
We shall introduce the following notation for dealing with partial functions. |
|
|
|
We define: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash t : A$ then $\Gamma \vdash \return{t} \eqdef \inl{t} : A + 1$. This program converges with probability 1. |
|
\item $\Gamma \vdash \fail \eqdef \inr{*} : A + 1$. This program diverges with probability 1. |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash s : A + 1$ and $\Delta, x : A \vdash t : B + 1$ then \\ |
|
$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \doo{x}{s}{t} \eqdef \pcase{s}{x}{t}{\_}{\fail}$. |
|
\item We introduce the following abbreviation. If $f$ is an expression (such as $\inln$, $\inrn$) such that $f(x)$ is a term, then we write $t \goesto f$ for $\doo{x}{t}{f(x)}$. |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
|
|
The term $\doo{x}{s}{t}$ should be read as the following computation: Run $s$. If $s$ returns a value, pass this as input $x$ to the computation $t$; otherwise, diverge. |
|
|
|
These constructions satisfy these computation rules (Lemma \ref{lm:do}): |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\doo{x}{\return{s}}{t} & = t[x:=s] \\ |
|
\doo{x}{\fail}{t} & = \fail \\ |
|
\doo{x}{r}{\return{x}} & = r \\ |
|
\doo{\_}{r}{\fail} & = \fail \\ |
|
\doo{x}{r}{(\doo{y}{s}{t})} & = \doo{y}{(\doo{x}{r}{s})}{t} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
|
|
This construction also allows us to define \emph{scalar multiplication}. Given a scalar $\vdash s : \mathbf{2}$ and a substate $\vdash t : A + 1$, the result of multiplying or scaling $t$ by $s$ is $\vdash \doo{\_}{s}{t} : A + 1$. |
|
|
|
\paragraph{Partial Projections} |
|
|
|
Recall that $n \cdot A$ has, as objects, $n$ copies of each object $a : A$, namely $\nin{1}{n}{a}$, \ldots, $\nin{n}{n}{a}$. |
|
Given $t : n \cdot A$, the \emph{partial projection} $\rhd_{i_1 i_2 \cdots i_k}^{n}(t) : A + 1$ is the partial computation that: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item given an element $\nin{i_r}{n}{a}$, returns $a$; |
|
\item given an element $\nin{j}{n}{a}$ for $j \neq i_1, \ldots, i_k$, diverges. |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
|
|
Formally, we define |
|
\[ \rhd_{i_1 i_2 \cdots i_k}^{n}(t) \eqdef \case_{i=1}^n t \of \nin{i}{n}{x} \mapsto \begin{cases} |
|
\return{x} & \text{if}\ i = i_1, \ldots, i_k \\ |
|
\fail & \text{otherwise} |
|
\end{cases} \] |
|
|
|
\paragraph{Partial Sum} |
|
\label{section:ordering} |
|
|
|
Let $\Gamma \vdash s,t : A + 1$. If these have disjoint domains (i.e. given any input $x$, the sum of the probability that $s$ and $t$ return $a$ is never greater than 1), then we may form the computation $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t$, |
|
the \emph{partial sum} of $s$ and $t$. The probability that this program converges with output $a$ is the sum of the probability that $s$ returns $a$, and the probability that $t$ returns $a$. The definition is given by the rule \Roveedef; see Section \ref{section:psum}. |
|
|
|
We write $n \cdot t$ for the sum $t \ovee \cdots \ovee t$ with $n$ summands. (We include the special cases $0 \cdot t = \fail$ and $1 \cdot t = t$.) |
|
|
|
With this operation, the partial functions |
|
in $A + 1$ form a \emph{partial commutative monoid} (PCM) (see Lemma \ref{lm:ordering}). |
|
|
|
\subsection{Logic} |
|
\label{section:logic} |
|
|
|
The type $\mathbf{2} = 1 + 1$ shall play a special role in this type theory. It is the type of \emph{propositions} or \emph{predicates}, and its objects shall be used as the formulas of our logic. |
|
|
|
We define $\top \eqdef \inl{*}$ and $\bot \eqdef \inr{*}$. |
|
We also define the \emph{orthosupplement} of a predicate $p$, which roughly corresponds to negation: |
|
\[ p^\bot \eqdef \pcase{p}{\_}{\bot}{\_}{\top} \] |
|
|
|
We immediately have that $p^{\bot \bot} = p$, $\top^\bot = \bot$ and $\bot^\bot = \top$. |
|
|
|
The ordering on $\mathbf{2}$ shall play the role of the \emph{derivability} relation in our logic: $p \leq q$ will indicate that $q$ is derivable from $p$, or that $p$ implies $q$. The rules for this logic |
|
are not the familiar rules of classical or intuitionistic logic. Rather, the predicates over any context form an \emph{effect algebra} (Proposition \ref{prop:logic}). |
|
|
|
In the case of two predicates $p$ and $q$, the partial sum can be thought of as the proposition `$p$ or $q$'. However, |
|
it differs from disjunction in classical or intuitionistic logic as it is a \emph{partial} operation: it is only defined if $p \leq q^\bot$ (Proposition \ref{prop:logic}.\ref{prop:ortho}). |
|
This condition can be thought of as expressing that $s$ and $t$ are \emph{disjoint}; that is, they are never both true. |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{$n$-tests} |
|
|
|
An \emph{$n$-test} in a context $\Gamma$ is an $n$-tuple of predicates $(p_1, \ldots, p_n)$ on $A$ such that |
|
\[ \Gamma \vdash p_1 \ovee \cdots \ovee p_n = \top : \mathbf{2} \enspace . \] |
|
|
|
Intutively, this can be thought of as a set of $n$ fuzzy predicates whose probabilities always sum to 1. We can think of this as a test that |
|
can be performed on the types of $\Gamma$ with $n$ possible outcomes; and, indeed, there is a one-to-one correspondence between |
|
the $n$-tests of $\Gamma$ and the terms of type $\mathbf{n}$ (Lemma \ref{lm:ntest}). |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Instrument Maps} |
|
|
|
Let $x : A \vdash t : \mathbf{n}$ and $\Gamma \vdash s : A$. |
|
The term $\instr_{\lambda x t}(s) : n \cdot A$ is interpreted as follows: we read the computation $x : A \vdash t : \mathbf{n}$ as a test on the type $A$, with $n$ possible outcomes. |
|
The computation $\instr_{\lambda x t}(s)$ runs $t$ on (the output of) $s$, and returns either $\nin{i}{n}{s}$, where $i$ is the outcome of the test. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Given an $n$-test $(p_1, \ldots, p_n)$ on $A$, we can write a program that tests which of $p_1$, \ldots, $p_n$ is true of its input, and performs one of $n$ different calculations |
|
as a result. We write this program as |
|
\[ \Gamma \vdash \mathsf{measure}\ p_1 \mapsto t_1 \mid \cdots \mid p_n \mapsto t_n \enspace . \] |
|
It will be defined in Definition \ref{df:measure}. |
|
|
|
If $x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$ and $\Gamma, x : A \vdash s,t : A$, we define |
|
\[ \Gamma \vdash (\cond{p}{s}{t}) = \meas\ p \mapsto s \mid p^\bot \mapsto t \enspace . \] |
|
In the case where $s$ and $t$ do not depend on $x$, |
|
we have the following fact (Lemma \ref{lm:measuretwo}.\ref{lm:measurecond}): |
|
\[ \cond{p}{s}{t} = \pcase{p}{\_}{s}{\_}{t} \] |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Assert Maps} |
|
|
|
If $x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$ is a predicate, we define |
|
\[ \Gamma \vdash \assert_{\lambda x p}(t) \eqdef \pcase{\instr_{\lambda x p}(t)}{x}{\return{x}}{\_}{\fail} : A + 1 \] |
|
The computation $\assert_p(t)$ is a partial computation with output type $A$. It tests whether $p$ is true of $t$; if so, it leaves $t$ unchanged; if not, it diverges. |
|
That is, if $p[x:=t]$ returns $\top$, the computation converges and returns $t$; if not, it diverges. |
|
|
|
These constructions satisfy the following computation rules (see Section \ref{section:assert} below for the proofs). |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\Rassertdown}{(assert$\downarrow$)\xspace} |
|
\newcommand{\Rassertscalar}{(assert-scalar)\xspace} |
|
\newcommand{\Rinstrplus}{(instr$+$)\xspace} |
|
\newcommand{\Rassertplus}{(assert$+$)\xspace} |
|
\newcommand{\Rinstrm}{(instr $m$)\xspace} |
|
\newcommand{\Rassertm}{(assert $m$)\xspace} |
|
\begin{description} |
|
\item[\Rassertdown] |
|
$\dom{(\assert_{\lambda x p}(t))} = p[x:=t]$ |
|
\item[\Rassertscalar] |
|
For a scalar $\vdash s : \mathbf{2}$: $\assert_{\lambda \_ s}(*) = \instr_{\lambda \_ s}(*) = s : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\item[\Rinstrplus] |
|
For $x : A + B \vdash t : \mathbf{n}$: |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\instr_{\lambda x t}(s) = |
|
\case s \of |
|
& \inl{y} \mapsto \case_{i=1}^n \instr_{\lambda a. t[x:=\inl{a}]}(y) \of \nin{i}{n}{z} \mapsto \nin{i}{n}{\inl{z}} \\ |
|
& \inr{y} \mapsto \case_{i=1}^n \instr_{\lambda b.t[x:=\inl{b}]}(y) \of \nin{i}{n}{z} \mapsto \nin{i}{n}{\inr{z}} \\ |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\item[\Rassertplus] |
|
For $x : A + B \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$: |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\assert_{\lambda x p}(t) = \case t \of |
|
& \inl{x} \mapsto \doo{z}{\assert_{\lambda a. p[x:=\inl{a}]}(x)}{\return{\inl{z}}} \mid \\ |
|
& \inr{y} \mapsto \doo{z}{\assert_{\lambda b.p[x:=\inr{b}]}(y)}{\return{\inr{z}}} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\item[\Rinstrm] |
|
For $x : \mathbf{m} \vdash t : \mathbf{n}$: |
|
\[ \instr_{\lambda x t}(s) = \case_{i=1}^m s \of i \mapsto \case_{j=1}^n t[x:=i] \of j \mapsto \nin{j}{n}{i} \] |
|
\item[\Rassertm] |
|
For $x : \mathbf{m} \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$: |
|
\[ \assert_{\lambda x p}(t) = \case_{i=1}^m t \of i \mapsto \cond{p[x:=i]}{\return{i}}{\fail} \] |
|
\end{description} |
|
|
|
In particular, we have $\assert_{\inln?}(t) = \rhd_1(t)$ and $\assert_{\inrn?}(t) = \rhd_2(t)$. |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Sequential Product} |
|
|
|
Given two predicates $x : A \vdash p,q : \mathbf{2}$, we can define their \emph{sequential product} |
|
\[ x : A \vdash p \andthen q \eqdef \doo{x}{\assert_p(x)}{q} : \mathbf{2} \enspace . \] |
|
The probability of this predicate being true at $x$ is the product of the probabilities of $p$ and $q$. |
|
This operation has many of the familiar properties of conjunction --- including commutativity --- but not all: in particular, we do not have $p \andthen p^\bot = \bot$ in all cases. (For example, $1/2 \andthen (1 / 2)^\bot = 1/4$.) |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Coproducts} |
|
|
|
We can define predicates which, given a term $t : A + B$, test which of $A$ and $B$ the term came from. We write these as $\inlprop{t}$ and $\inrprop{t}$. (Compare these with the operators |
|
$FstAnd$ and $SndAnd$ defined in \cite{Jacobs14}.) They are defined by |
|
|
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\inlprop{t} & \eqdef \pcase{t}{\_}{\top}{\_}{\bot} \\ |
|
\inrprop{t} & \eqdef \pcase{t}{\_}{\bot}{\_}{\top} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Kernels} |
|
|
|
The predicate $\inrprop{}$ is particularly important for partial maps. |
|
|
|
Let $\Gamma \vdash t : A + 1$. The \emph{kernel} of the map denoted by $t$ is |
|
\[ \ker{t} \eqdef \inrprop{t} \eqdef \pcase{t}{\_}{\bot}{\_}{\top} \] |
|
Intuitively, if we think of $t$ as a partial computation, then |
|
$\ker{t}$ is the proposition `$t$ does not terminate', or the function |
|
that gives the probability that $t$ will diverge on a given input. |
|
|
|
Its orthosupplement, $(\ker{t})^\bot = \inlprop{t}$, which we shall |
|
also write as $\dom{t}$, is also called the \emph{domain |
|
predicate} of $t$, and represents the proposition that $t$ |
|
terminates. We note that it is equal to $\doo{\_}{t}{\top}$. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Normalisation}\label{subsec:normalisation} |
|
|
|
We have a representation of all the rational numbers in our system: let $m / n$ be the term |
|
\[ \overbrace{1 / n \ovee \cdots \ovee 1 / n}^{m} \enspace . \] |
|
The usual arithmetic of rational numbers (between 0 and 1) can be carried out in our system (see Section \ref{sec:scalars}). In particular, for rational numbers $q$ and $r$, we have that if $q \leq r$ then the judgement $q \leq r$ is derivable; |
|
$q \ovee r$ is well-typed if and only if $q + r \leq 1$, in which case $q \ovee r$ is equal to $q + r$; and $q \andthen r = qr$. |
|
|
|
Now, let $\vdash t : A + 1$. Then $t$ represents a \emph{substate} of $A$. |
|
As long as the probability $\dom{t}$ is non-zero, we can |
|
\emph{normalise} this program over the probability of non-termination. The result is the state denoted by $\norm{t}$. Intuitively, the probability that $\norm{t}$ will output $a$ is the probability |
|
that $t$ will output $\inl{a}$, conditioned on the event that $t$ terminates. |
|
|
|
In order to type $\norm{t}$, we must first prove that $t$ has a |
|
non-zero probability of terminating by deriving an inequality of the |
|
form $1 / n \leq \dom{t}$ for some positive integer $n \geq 2$. |
|
|
|
If $\vdash t : A$ and $x : A \vdash p(x) : \mathbf{2}$, we write $\condn{t}{p}$ for |
|
\[ \condn{t}{p} \eqdef \norm{\assert_p(t)} \enspace . \] |
|
The term $t$ denotes a computation whose output is given by a probability distribution over $A$. Then $\condn{t}{p}$ gives the result of normalising that conditional probability distribution |
|
with respect to $p$. |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Marginalisation} |
|
|
|
The tensor product of type $A \otimes B$ comes with two \emph{projections}. Given $\Gamma \vdash t : A \otimes B$, define |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\Gamma \vdash \pi_1(t) \eqdef \plet{x}{\_}{t}{x} : A \\ |
|
\Gamma \vdash \pi_2(t) \eqdef \plet{\_}{y}{t}{y} : B |
|
\end{align*} |
|
If $t$ is a state (i..e $\Gamma$ is the empty context), then $\pi_1(t)$ denotes the result of \emph{marginalising} $t$, as |
|
a probability distribution over $A \otimes B$, to a probability distribution over $A$. |
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Local Definition} |
|
|
|
In our examples, we shall make free use of \emph{local definition}. This is not a part of the syntax of $\COMET$ itself, |
|
but part of our metalanguage. We write $\lett x = s \inn t$ for $t[x:=s]$. We shall also locally define functions: we |
|
write $\lett f(x) = s \inn t$ for the result of replacing every subterm of the form $f(r)$ with $s[x:=r]$ in $t$. |
|
|
|
\section{Examples} |
|
\label{section:examples} |
|
|
|
This section describes two examples of (Bayesian) reasoning in our |
|
type theory $\COMET$. The first example is a typical exercise in |
|
Bayesian probability theory. Since such kind of reasoning is not very |
|
intuitive, a formal calculus is very useful. The second example |
|
involves a simple graphical model. |
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{example} |
|
(See also \cite{Yudkowsky2003,Borgstroem2011}) Consider the |
|
following situation. |
|
\begin{quote} |
|
1\% of a population have a disease. 80\% of subjects with the |
|
disease test positive, and 9.6\% without the disease also test |
|
positive. If a subject is positive, what are the odds they have |
|
the disease? |
|
\end{quote} |
|
|
|
\noindent This situation can be described as a very simple graphical |
|
model, with associated (conditional) probabilities. |
|
$$\vcenter{\xymatrix@R-1pc@C-2pc{ |
|
\ovalbox{HasDisease}\ar[d] |
|
\\ |
|
\ovalbox{PositiveResult} |
|
}} |
|
\qquad\qquad |
|
{\setlength\tabcolsep{0.3em}\begin{tabular}{|c|} |
|
\hline |
|
$\Prob{HD}$ \\ |
|
\hline\hline |
|
$0.01$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
\end{tabular}} |
|
\qquad |
|
{\setlength\tabcolsep{0.3em}\begin{tabular}{|c|c|} |
|
\hline |
|
$HD$ & $\Prob{PR}$ \\ |
|
\hline\hline |
|
$t$ & $0.8$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
$f$ & $0.096$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
\end{tabular}}$$ |
|
|
|
\newcommand{\subj}{\textsf{subject}} |
|
\newcommand{\pr}{\textsf{positive\_result}} |
|
|
|
\noindent In our type theory $\COMET$, we use the following description. |
|
$$\begin{array}{l} |
|
\slet{\subj}{0.01}{} \\ |
|
\qquad\slet{\pr(x)}{(\ifte{x}{0.8}{0.096})}{} \\ |
|
\condn{\subj}{\pr} |
|
\end{array}$$ |
|
|
|
\noindent We thus obtain a state $\subj : \mathbf{2}$, |
|
conditioned on the predicate $\pr$ on $\mathbf{2}$. We calculate the |
|
outcome in semi-formal style. The conditional state |
|
$\condn{\subj}{\pr}$ is defined via normalisation of assert, see |
|
Subsection~\ref{subsec:normalisation}. |
|
We first show what this assert |
|
term is, using the rule \Rassertm and \Rassertscalar: |
|
$$\begin{array}{rcl} |
|
\assert_{\pr}(x) |
|
& = & |
|
\ifn\ x \begin{array}[t]{ll} |
|
\thenn & \doo{\_}{\assert_{\pr(\top)}(x)}{\return{\top}} \\ |
|
\elsen & \doo{\_}{\assert_{\pr(\bot)}(x)}{\return{\bot}} |
|
\end{array} \\ |
|
& = & |
|
\ifn\ x \begin{array}[t]{ll} |
|
\thenn & \doo{\_}{\assert_{0.8}(x)}{\return{\top}} \\ |
|
\elsen & \doo{\_}{\assert_{0.096}(x)}{\return{\bot}} |
|
\end{array} \\ |
|
& = & \ifn x {\begin{array}[t]{rl} |
|
\thenn & \cond{0.8}{\return{\top}}{\fail} \\ |
|
\elsen & \cond{0.096}{\return{\bot}}{\fail} |
|
\end{array}} |
|
\end{array}$$ |
|
\noindent Conditioning requires that the domain of the substate |
|
$\assert_{\pr}(\subj)$ is non-zero. We compute this domain as: |
|
$$\begin{array}{rcll} |
|
\dom{\assert_{\pr}(\subj)} |
|
& = & |
|
\pr(\subj) & (\text{Rule \Rassertdown}) \\ |
|
& = & |
|
\cond{0.01}{0.8}{0.096} \\ |
|
& = & |
|
0.01 \andthen 0.8 \ovee 0.99 \andthen 0.096 \mbox{\qquad} & |
|
(\text{Lemma \ref{lm:measuretwo}.\ref{lm:measurecond}}) \\ |
|
& = & |
|
0.10304 & (\text{Lemma \ref{lm:rational}}) |
|
\end{array}$$ |
|
|
|
\noindent Hence we can choose (for example) $n = 10$, to get |
|
$\frac{1}{n} \leq 0.10304 = \dom{\assert_{\pr}(\subj)}$. |
|
|
|
We now proceed to calculate the result, answering the question in |
|
the beginning of this example. |
|
$$\begin{array}{rcll} |
|
\assert_{\pr}(\subj) |
|
& = & |
|
\ifn 0.01 {\begin{array}[t]{rl} |
|
\thenn & \cond{0.8}{\return{\top}}{\fail} \\ |
|
\elsen & \cond{0.096}{\return{\bot}}{\fail} |
|
\end{array}} \\ |
|
& = & |
|
\meas\ {\begin{array}[t]{lcl} |
|
0.01 \andthen 0.8 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\return{\top} \\ |
|
0.01 \andthen 0.8^\bot |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\fail \\ |
|
0.01^\bot \andthen 0.096 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\return{\bot} \\ |
|
0.01^\bot \andthen 0.096^\bot |
|
& \mapsto |
|
& \fail |
|
\end{array}} & (\text{Lemma \ref{lm:measure}.\ref{lm:measureand}}) |
|
\\ |
|
& = & |
|
\meas\ {\begin{array}[t]{lcl} |
|
0.008 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\return{\top} \\ |
|
0.09504 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\return{\bot} \\ |
|
0.89696 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\fail |
|
\end{array}} & (\text{Lemma \ref{lm:measure}.\ref{lm:measureor}}) |
|
\\ |
|
\condn{\subj}{\pr} |
|
& \eqdef & |
|
\norm{\assert_{\pr}(\subj)} \\ |
|
& = & |
|
\meas {\begin{array}[t]{lcl} |
|
0.0776 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\top \\ |
|
0.9224 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\bot |
|
\end{array}} & (\text{Corollary \ref{cor:normmeasure}}) \\ |
|
& = & |
|
0.0776. & (\text{Lemma \ref{lm:measuretwo}.\ref{lm:measuretwo'}}) |
|
\end{array}$$ |
|
|
|
\noindent Hence the probability of having the disease after a positive |
|
test result is 7.8\%. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{example}[Bayesian Network] |
|
The following is a standard example of a problem in Bayesian networks, |
|
created by~\cite[Chap.~14]{RusselN03}. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{quote} |
|
I’m at work, neighbor John calls to say my alarm is ringing. Sometimes |
|
it’s set off by minor earthquakes. Is there a burglar? |
|
\end{quote} |
|
|
|
We are given that the situation is as described by the following |
|
Bayesian network. |
|
$$\vcenter{\xymatrix@R-1pc@C-2pc{ |
|
\ovalbox{Burglary}\ar[dr] & & \ovalbox{Earthquake}\ar[dl] |
|
\\ |
|
& \ovalbox{Alarm}\ar[dl]\ar[dr] & |
|
\\ |
|
\ovalbox{JohnCalls} & & \ovalbox{MaryCalls} |
|
}} |
|
\qquad |
|
\begin{tabular}{c} |
|
{\setlength\tabcolsep{0.3em}\begin{tabular}{|c|} |
|
\hline |
|
$\Prob{B}$ \\ |
|
\hline\hline |
|
$\frac{1}{1000}$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
\end{tabular}} |
|
\\[2em] |
|
{\setlength\tabcolsep{0.3em}\begin{tabular}{|c|c|} |
|
\hline |
|
$A$ & $\Prob{J}$ \\ |
|
\hline\hline |
|
$t$ & $\frac{9}{10}$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
$f$ & $\frac{1}{20}$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
\end{tabular}} |
|
\end{tabular} |
|
\quad |
|
{\setlength\tabcolsep{0.3em}\begin{tabular}{|cc|c|} |
|
\hline |
|
$B$ & $E$ & $\Prob{A}$ \\ |
|
\hline\hline |
|
$t$ & $t$ & $\frac{95}{100}$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
$t$ & $f$ & $\frac{94}{100}$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
$f$ & $t$ & $\frac{29}{100}$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
$f$ & $f$ & $\frac{1}{1000}$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
\end{tabular}} |
|
\quad |
|
\begin{tabular}{c} |
|
{\setlength\tabcolsep{0.3em}\begin{tabular}{|c|} |
|
\hline |
|
$\Prob{E}$ \\ |
|
\hline\hline |
|
$\frac{1}{500}$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
\end{tabular}} |
|
\\[2em] |
|
{\setlength\tabcolsep{0.3em}\begin{tabular}{|c|c|} |
|
\hline |
|
$A$ & $\Prob{M}$ \\ |
|
\hline\hline |
|
$t$ & $\frac{7}{10}$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
$f$ & $\frac{1}{100}$ \\ |
|
\hline |
|
\end{tabular}} |
|
\end{tabular}$$ |
|
|
|
\noindent The probability of each event given its preconditions is as |
|
given in the tables --- for example, the probability that the alarm |
|
rings given that there is a burglar but no earthquake is 0.94. |
|
|
|
We model the above question in $\COMET$ as follows. |
|
$$\begin{array}{l} |
|
\slet{b}{0.01}{\slet{e}{0.002}{}} \\ |
|
\qquad\lett a(x,y) = (\ifn x {\begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
\thenn (\cond{y}{0.95}{0.94}) \\ |
|
\elsen (\cond{y}{0.29}{0.001})) \inn |
|
\end{array}} \\ |
|
\qquad\qquad \slet{j(z)}{(\cond{z}{0.9}{0.05})}{} \\ |
|
\qquad\qquad\qquad \slet{m(z)}{(\cond{z}{0.7}{0.01})}{} \\ |
|
\pi_{1}\big(\condn{b\sotimes e}{j \after a}\big) |
|
\end{array}$$ |
|
|
|
\noindent We first elaborate the predicate $j\after a$, given in |
|
context as $x\colon \mathbf{2}, y\colon \mathbf{2} \vdash j(a(x,y)) |
|
\colon \mathbf{2}$. It is: |
|
$$\begin{array}{rcl} |
|
j(a(x,y)) |
|
& = & |
|
\cond{a(x,y)}{0.90}{0.05} \\ |
|
& = & |
|
\ifn x {\begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
\thenn (\cond{y}{(\cond{0.95}{0.90}{0.05})}{(\cond{0.94}{0.90}{0.05})} \\ |
|
\elsen (\cond{y}{(\cond{0.29}{0.90}{0.05})}{(\cond{0.001}{0.90}{0.05})} |
|
\end{array}} |
|
\\ |
|
& = & |
|
\ifn x {\begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
\thenn (\cond{y}{0.95 \andthen 0.90 \ovee 0.95^{\bot} \andthen 0.05} |
|
{0.94 \andthen 0.90 \ovee 0.94^{\bot} \andthen 0.05}) \\ |
|
\elsen (\cond{y}{0.29\andthen 0.90 \ovee 0.29^{\bot} \andthen 0.05} |
|
{0.001 \andthen 0.90 \ovee 0.001^{\bot} \andthen 0.05} |
|
\end{array}} |
|
\\ |
|
& = & |
|
\ifn x \thenn (\cond{y}{0.8575}{0.849}) \elsen (\cond{y}{0.2965}{0.05085}) |
|
\end{array}$$ |
|
|
|
\noindent The associated assert map is: |
|
$$\begin{array}{rcl} |
|
\assert_{j \after a}(b,e) |
|
& = & |
|
\meas\ {\begin{array}[t]{lcl} |
|
0.001 \andthen 0.002 \andthen 0.8575 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\return{\top \sotimes \top} \\ |
|
0.001 \andthen 0.998 \andthen 0.849 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\return{\top \sotimes \bot} \\ |
|
0.999 \andthen 0.002 \andthen 0.2965 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\return{\bot \sotimes \top} \\ |
|
0.999 \andthen 0.998 \andthen 0.05085 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\return{\bot \sotimes \bot} \\ |
|
0.052138976^\bot |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\fail |
|
\end{array}} \\ |
|
& = & |
|
\meas\ {\begin{array}[t]{lcl} |
|
0.000001715 & \mapsto & |
|
\return{\top \sotimes \top} \\ |
|
0.000847302 & \mapsto & |
|
\return{\top \sotimes \bot} \\ |
|
0.000592407 & \mapsto & |
|
\return{\bot \sotimes \top} \\ |
|
0.050697552 & \mapsto & |
|
\return{\bot \sotimes \bot} \\ |
|
0.052138976^\bot & \mapsto & |
|
\fail |
|
\end{array}} |
|
\end{array}$$ |
|
|
|
\noindent Hence by Corollary~\ref{cor:normmeasure} we obtain the |
|
marginalised conditional: |
|
$$\begin{array}{rcl} |
|
\pi_{1}\big(\condn{b\sotimes e}{j \after a}\big) |
|
& = & |
|
\pi_{1}\big(\norm{\assert_{j \after a}(b,e)}\big) \\ |
|
& = & |
|
\pi_{1}\big(\meas\ {\begin{array}[t]{lcl} |
|
\nicefrac{0.000001715}{0.052138976} |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\top \sotimes \top \\ |
|
\nicefrac{0.000847302}{0.052138976} |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\top \sotimes \bot \\ |
|
\nicefrac{0.000592407}{0.052138976} |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\bot \sotimes \top \\ |
|
\nicefrac{0.050697552}{0.052138976} |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\bot \sotimes \bot\,\big) \\ |
|
\end{array}} \\ |
|
& = & |
|
\meas\ {\begin{array}[t]{lcl} |
|
0.000032893 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\pi_{1}(\top \sotimes \top) \\ |
|
0.016250837 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\pi_{1}(\top \sotimes \bot) \\ |
|
0.011362078 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\pi_{1}(\bot \sotimes \top) \\ |
|
0.972354194 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\pi_{1}(\bot \sotimes \bot) \\ |
|
\end{array}} |
|
\\ |
|
& = & |
|
\meas\ {\begin{array}[t]{lcl} |
|
0.000032893 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\top \\ |
|
0.016250837 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\top \\ |
|
0.011362076 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\bot \\ |
|
0.972354194 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\bot \\ |
|
\end{array}} |
|
\\ |
|
& = & |
|
\meas\ {\begin{array}[t]{lcl} |
|
0.01628373 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\top \\ |
|
0.98371627 |
|
& \mapsto & |
|
\bot \\ |
|
\end{array}} |
|
\\ |
|
& = & |
|
0.01628373 \end{array}$$ |
|
|
|
\noindent We conclude that there is a 1.6\% chance of a burglary when |
|
John calls. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\end{example} |
|
|
|
\section{Metatheorems} |
|
\label{section:metatheorems} |
|
|
|
We presented an overview of the system in Section \ref{section:overview}, and gave the intuitive meaning of the terms of $\COMET$. |
|
In this section, we proceed to a more formal development of the theory, and investigate what can be proved within the system. |
|
|
|
The type theory we have presented enjoys the following standard properties. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:meta} |
|
$ $ |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item \textbf{Weakening} |
|
\label{lm:weak} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash \mathcal{J}$ and $\Gamma \subseteq \Delta$ then $\Delta \vdash \mathcal{J}$. |
|
\item \textbf{Substitution} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash t : A$ and $\Delta, x : A \vdash \mathcal{J}$ then $\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \mathcal{J}[x:=t]$. |
|
\item \textbf{Equation Validity} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash s = t : A$ then $\Gamma \vdash s : A$ and $\Gamma \vdash t : A$. |
|
\item \textbf{Inequality Validity} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash s \leq t : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash s : A + 1$ and $\Gamma \vdash t : A + 1$. |
|
\item \textbf{Functionality} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash r = s : A$ and $\Delta, x : A \vdash t : B$ then $\Gamma, \Delta \vdash t[x:=r] = t[x:=s] : B$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
The proof in each case is by induction on derivations. Each case is straightforward. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
The following lemma shows that substituting within our binding operations works as desired. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:sub} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item \label{lm:letsub}If $\Gamma \vdash r : A \otimes B$; $\Delta, x : A, y : B \vdash s : C$; and $\Theta, z : C \vdash t : D$ |
|
then $\Gamma, \Delta, \Theta \vdash t[z:=\plet{x}{y}{r}{s}] = \plet{x}{y}{r}{t[z:=s]} : D$. |
|
\item \label{lm:casesub} If $\Gamma \vdash r : A + B$; $\Delta, x :A \vdash s : C$; $\Delta, y : B \vdash s' : C$; and $\Theta, z : C \vdash t : D$ then |
|
$$\Gamma, \Delta, \Theta \vdash \begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
t[z:=\pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{s'}] \\ |
|
= \pcase{r}{x}{t[z:=s]}{y}{t[z:=s']} : D |
|
\end{array} \enspace . $$ |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
For part 1, we us the following `trick' to simulate local definition (see \cite{Adams2014}): |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\lefteqn{t[z := \pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{s'}]} \\ |
|
& = \plet{z}{\_}{(\pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{s'}) \sotimes *}{t} & \Rbeta \\ |
|
& = \plet{z}{\_}{\pcase{r}{x}{s \sotimes *}{y}{s' \sotimes *}}{t} & \Rcasepair \\ |
|
& = \pcase{r}{x}{\plet{z}{\_}{s \sotimes *}{t}}{y}{\plet{z}{\_}{s' \sotimes *}{t}} & \Rletcase \\ |
|
& = \pcase{r}{x}{t[z:=s]}{y}{t[z:=s']} & \Rbeta |
|
\end{align*} |
|
Part 2 is proven similarly using\Rletpair and\Rletlet. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{corollary} |
|
\label{cor:vacsub} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash s : A \otimes B$ and $\Delta \vdash t : C$ then |
|
$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \plet{\_}{\_}{s}{t} = t : C$. |
|
\item \label{cor:vaccase} If $\Gamma \vdash s : A + B$ and $\Delta \vdash t : C$ then $\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \pcase{s}{\_}{t}{\_}{t} = t : C$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{corollary} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
These are both the special case where $z$ does not occur free in $t$. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Coproducts} |
|
|
|
We generalise the $\inlprop{}$ and $\inrprop{}$ constructions as follows. |
|
Define the predicate $\intest{i}{}$ on $n \cdot A$, which tests whether a term |
|
comes from the $i$th component, as follows. |
|
\[ \intest{i}{t} \eqdef \case_{j=1}^n t \of \nin{j}{n}{\_} \mapsto \begin{cases} |
|
\top & \text{if } i = j \\ |
|
\bot & \text{if } i \neq j |
|
\end{cases} \] |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{The Do Notation} |
|
|
|
Our construction $\doo{x}{s}{t}$ satisfies the following laws. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:do} |
|
Let $\Gamma \vdash r : A + 1$, $\Delta, x : A \vdash s : B + 1$, and $\Theta, y : B \vdash t : C$. Let |
|
also $\Gamma \vdash r' : A$. Then |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \doo{x}{\return{r'}}{s} & = t[x:=s] : B + 1 \\ |
|
\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \doo{x}{\fail}{s} & = \fail : B + 1 \\ |
|
\Gamma \vdash \doo{x}{r}{\return{x}} & = r : A + 1 \\ |
|
\Gamma \vdash \doo{\_}{r}{\fail} & = \fail : B + 1 \\ |
|
\Gamma, \Delta, \Theta \vdash \doo{x}{r}{(\doo{y}{s}{t})} & = \doo{y}{(\doo{x}{r}{s})}{t} : C |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
These all follow easily from the rules for coproducts\Rbetaplusone,\Rbetaplustwo,\Retaplus and\Rcasecase. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\subsection{Kernels} |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma}$ $ |
|
\label{lm:kernel} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash t : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash \dom{t} = (\doo{\_}{t}{\top}) : \mathbf{2}$ |
|
\item |
|
\label{lm:kernel2} |
|
Let $\Gamma \vdash t : A + 1$. Then |
|
$\Gamma \vdash \dom{t} = \bot : \mathbf{2}$ if and only if $\Gamma \vdash t = \fail : A + 1$. |
|
\item |
|
Let $\Gamma \vdash s : A + 1$ and $\Delta, x : A \vdash t : B + 1$. Then |
|
$\Gamma, \Delta \vdash \dom{(\doo{x}{s}{t})} = \doo{x}{s}{\dom{t}} : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof}$ $ |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item |
|
This holds just by expanding definitions. |
|
\item |
|
Obviously, $(\dom{\fail}) = \bot$. For the converse, if $\dom{t} = |
|
\bot$ then $\ker{t} = \top$ and so $t = \inr{\rgt{t}} = \inr{*}$ by\Retaone. |
|
\item |
|
$ \begin{aligned}[t] |
|
(\dom{\pcase{s}{x}{t}{\_}{\fail}}) & = \pcase{s}{x}{\dom{t}}{\_}{\dom{\fail}} \\ |
|
& = \pcase{s}{x}{\dom{t}}{\_}{\bot} |
|
\end{aligned} $ |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\subsection{Finite Types} |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:rhdfin} |
|
Let $\Gamma \vdash t : \mathbf{n}$ and $i \leq n$. |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash \rhd_i(t) = \top : \mathbf{2}$ then $\Gamma \vdash t = i : \mathbf{n}$. |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
Define $x : \mathbf{n} \vdash f(x) : 1 + \mathbf{n-1}$ by |
|
\[ f(x) \eqdef \case_{j=1}^n x \of \begin{cases} |
|
\inr{j} & \text{if } j < i \\ |
|
\inl{*} & \text{if } j = i \\ |
|
\inr{j-i} & \text{if } j > i |
|
\end{cases} \] |
|
Then $\Gamma \vdash \inlprop{f(t)} = \top : \mathbf{2}$, hence |
|
\[ f(t) = \inl{\lft{f(t)}} = \inl{*} \] |
|
We can define an inverse to $f$: given $x : 1 + \mathbf{n-1}$, define |
|
\[ f^{-1}(x) \eqdef \case x \of \inl{\_} \mapsto i \mid \inr{t} \mapsto \case_{j=1}^{n-1} t \of j \text{ if } j < i \mid j + 1 \text{ if } j \geq i \] |
|
Then $x : \mathbf{n} \vdash f^{-1}(f(x)) = x : 1 + \mathbf{n-1}$ and so $\Gamma \vdash t = f^{-1}(f(t)) = f^{-1}(\inl{*}) = i : \mathbf{n}$. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\subsection{Ordering on Partial Maps and the Partial Sum} |
|
\label{section:psum} |
|
Note that, from the rules\Roveeprime and\Roveedef, we have $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t : A + 1$ if and only if there exists $\Gamma \vdash b : (A + A) + 1$ such that |
|
\[ \Gamma \vdash b \goesto \rhd_1 = s : A + 1, \qquad \Gamma \vdash b \goesto \rhd_2 = t : A + 1 \enspace , \] |
|
in which case $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t = \doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}} : A + 1$. We say that such a term $b$ is a \emph{bound} for $s \ovee t$. By |
|
the rule\RJMprime, this bound is unique if it exists. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
For predicates $\Gamma \vdash p, q : \mathbf{2}$, we have that $\Gamma \vdash b : \mathbf{3}$ is a bound for $p \ovee q$ if and only if $\rhd_1(b) = p$ and $\rhd_2(b) = q$. |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
This holds because $b \goesto \rhd_1 = \rhd_1(b)$ and $b \goesto \rhd_2 = \rhd_2(b)$, as can be seen just from expanding definitions. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
The set of \emph{partial} maps $A \rightarrow B + 1$ between any two types $A$ and $B$ form a \emph{partial commutative monoid} (PCM) with least element $\fail$, as shown by the following results. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma}$ $ |
|
\label{lm:ordering} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item \label{lm:zerolaw} If $\Gamma \vdash t : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash t \ovee \fail = t : A + 1$. |
|
\item (\textbf{Commutativity}) If $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash t \ovee s : A + 1$ and $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t = t \ovee s : A + 1$. |
|
\item (\textbf{Associativity}) $\Gamma \vdash (r \ovee s) \ovee t : A + 1$ if and only if $\Gamma \vdash r \ovee (s \ovee t) : A + 1$, in which case $\Gamma \vdash r \ovee (s \ovee t) = (r \ovee s) \ovee t : A + 1$. \label{lm:assoc} |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item The bound is $\doo{x}{t}{\return{\inl{x}}}$. |
|
\item |
|
Let $b$ be a bound for $s \ovee t$. Then $\doo{x}{b}{\return{\swapper{x}}}$ is a bound for $t \ovee s$ and we have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
t \ovee s & = \doo{y}{(\doo{x}{b}{\return{\swapper{x}}})}{\return{\nabla(y)}} \\ |
|
& = \doo{x}{b}{\doo{y}{\return{\swapper{x}}}{\return{\nabla(y)}}} \\ |
|
& = \doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(\swapper{x})}} = \doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}} \\ |
|
& = s \ovee t |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\item |
|
This is proved in Appendix \ref{section:associativity} |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:oveeleq} |
|
Let $\Gamma \vdash r : A + 1$ and $\Gamma \vdash s : A + 1$. Then $\Gamma \vdash r \leq s : A + 1$ if and only if there exists $t$ such that $\Gamma \vdash r \ovee t = s : A + 1$. |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
Suppose $r \leq s$. If $b$ is such that $\doo{x}{b}{\rhd_1(x)} = r$ and $\doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}} = s$ then take $t = \doo{x}{b}{\rhd_2(x)}$. |
|
|
|
Conversely, if $r \ovee t = s$, then inverting the derivation of $\Gamma \vdash r \ovee t : A + 1$ we have that there exists $b$ such that $r = |
|
\doo{x}{b}{\rhd_1(x)}$, $t = \doo{x}{b}{\rhd_2(x)}$ and $s = r \ovee t = \doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}}$. Therefore, $r \leq s$ by\RleqI. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{corollary} |
|
Let $\Gamma \vdash r : A + 1$ and $\Gamma \vdash s : A + 1$. Then $\Gamma \vdash r \leq s : A + 1$ if and only if there exists $b$ such that $\Gamma \vdash b : (A + A) + 1$, |
|
$\Gamma \vdash b \goesto \rhd_1 = s : A + 1$, and $\Gamma \vdash \doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}} = s : A + 1$. |
|
\end{corollary} |
|
|
|
This term $b$ is called a \emph{bound} for $s \leq t$. |
|
|
|
Using this characterisation of the ordering relation, we can read off several properties directly from Lemma \ref{lm:ordering}. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash s \leq s \ovee t : A + 1$ and $\Gamma \vdash t \leq s \ovee t : A + 1$. \label{lm:leqovee} |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash t : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash t \leq t : A + 1$. |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash t : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash \fail \leq t : A + 1$. |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash r \leq s : A + 1$ and $\Gamma \vdash s \leq t : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash r \leq t : A + 1$. |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash r \leq s : A + 1$ and $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash r \ovee t \leq s \ovee t : A + 1$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item |
|
From Lemma \ref{lm:oveeleq} and Commutativity. |
|
\item From Lemma \ref{lm:oveeleq} and Lemma \ref{lm:ordering}.\ref{lm:zerolaw}. |
|
\item From Lemma \ref{lm:oveeleq} and Lemma \ref{lm:ordering}.\ref{lm:zerolaw}. |
|
\item From Lemma \ref{lm:oveeleq} and Associativity. |
|
\item |
|
Let $r \ovee x = s$. Then $r \ovee x \ovee t = s \ovee t$ and so $r \ovee t \leq s \ovee t$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
On the predicates, we have the following structure, which shows that they form an \emph{effect algebra}. (In fact, they have more structure: |
|
they form an \emph{effect module} over the scalars, as we will prove in Proposition \ref{prop:effmod}.) |
|
|
|
\begin{proposition} |
|
\label{prop:logic} |
|
Let $\Gamma \vdash p,q,r : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$ then $\Gamma \vdash p \ovee p^\bot = \top : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash p \ovee q = \top : \mathbf{2}$ then $\Gamma \vdash q = p^\bot : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\item (\textbf{Zero-One Law}) If $\Gamma \vdash p \ovee \top : \mathbf{2}$ then $\Gamma \vdash p = \bot : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\item \label{prop:ortho} $\Gamma \vdash p \ovee q : \mathbf{2}$ if and only if $\Gamma \vdash p \leq q^\bot : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proposition} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item |
|
The term $\inl{p} : \mathbf{2} + 1$ is a bound for $p \ovee p^\bot$, and $\doo{x}{\inl{p}}{\return{\nabla(x)}} = \top$. |
|
\item |
|
Let $b$ be a bound for $p \ovee q$. We have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\top & = \doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}} = \doo{x}{b}{\top} & \text{using \Retaone} \\ |
|
& = \dom{b} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
Therefore, $b = \inl{\lft{b}}$ by\Rbetaleft, and so |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
p & = \rhd_1(\lft{b}), \qquad q = \rhd_2(\lft{b}) = \rhd_1(\lft{b})^\bot = p^\bot |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\item Let $b$ be a bound for $p \ovee \top$. Then $\rhd_2(b) = \top$ and so $b = 2 : \mathbf{3}$ by Lemma \ref{lm:rhdfin}. Therefore, $p = \rhd_1(b) = \bot$. |
|
\item |
|
Suppose $p \ovee q : \mathbf{2}$. Then $p \ovee q \ovee (p \ovee q)^\bot = \top$, hence $p \ovee (p \ovee q)^\bot = q^\bot$, and |
|
thus $p \leq q^\bot$. |
|
|
|
Conversely, if $p \leq q^\bot$, let $p \ovee x = q^\bot$. Then $\top = q \ovee q^\bot = p \ovee q \ovee x$, and so $p \ovee q : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{corollary} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item (\textbf{Cancellation}) If $\Gamma \vdash p \ovee q = p \ovee r : \mathbf{2}$ then $\Gamma \vdash q = r : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\item (\textbf{Positivity}) If $\Gamma \vdash p \ovee q = \bot : \mathbf{2}$ then $\Gamma \vdash p = \bot : \mathbf{2}$ and $\Gamma \vdash q = \bot : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$ then $\Gamma \vdash p \leq \top : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash p \leq q : \mathbf{2}$ then $\Gamma \vdash q^\bot \leq p^\bot : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{corollary} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item We have |
|
\begin{gather*} |
|
p \ovee q \ovee (p \ovee q)^\bot = p \ovee r \ovee (p \ovee q)^\bot = \top \\ |
|
\therefore q = r = (p \ovee (p \ovee q)^\bot)^\bot |
|
\end{gather*} |
|
\item |
|
If $p \ovee q = \bot$ then $p \ovee q \ovee \top : \mathbf{2}$, hence $p \ovee \top : \mathbf{2}$ by Associativity, and so $p = \bot$ by the Zero-One Law. |
|
\item |
|
We have $p \ovee p^\bot = \top$ and so $p \leq \top$. |
|
\item |
|
Let $p \ovee x = q$. Then $\top = q \ovee q^\bot = p \ovee x \ovee q^\bot$, and so $p^\bot = x \ovee q^\bot$. Thus, $q^\bot \leq p^\bot$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
Our next lemma shows how $\ovee$ and $\mathsf{case}$ interact. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:caseovee} |
|
Suppose $\Gamma \vdash r : A + B$ and $\Delta, x : A \vdash s \ovee t : C + 1$ and $\Delta, y : B \vdash s' \ovee t' : C + 1$. Then |
|
\[ \Gamma, \Delta \vdash \begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
\pcase{r}{x}{s \ovee t}{y}{s' \ovee t'} \\ |
|
= (\pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{s'}) \ovee (\pcase{r}{x}{t}{y}{t'}) : C + 1 |
|
\end{array} \] |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
Let $b(x)$ be a bound for $s \ovee t$ in $\Delta, x : A$, and $c(y)$ a bound for $s' \ovee t'$ in $\Delta, y : B$. Then |
|
\[ \pcase{r}{x}{b(x)}{y}{c(y)} : (B + B) + 1 \] |
|
is a bound for $(\pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{s'}) \ovee (\pcase{r}{x}{t}{y}{t'})$, and so |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\lefteqn{(\pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{s'}) \ovee (\pcase{r}{x}{t}{y}{t'})} \\ |
|
& = \doo{z}{\pcase{r}{x}{b(x)}{y}{c(y)}}{\return{\nabla(z)}} \\ |
|
& = \pcase{r}{x}{\doo{z}{b(x)}{\return{\nabla(z)}}}{y}{\doo{z}{c(y)}{\return{\nabla(z)}}} \\ |
|
& = \pcase{r}{x}{s \ovee t}{y}{s' \ovee t'} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{corollary} |
|
\label{cor:doovee} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash r : A + 1$ and $\Delta, x : A \vdash s \ovee t : B + 1$ then |
|
\[ \Gamma, \Delta \vdash \doo{x}{r}{s \ovee t} = (\doo{x}{r}{s}) \ovee (\doo{x}{r}{t}) : B + 1 \enspace . \] |
|
\end{corollary} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\doo{x}{r}{s \ovee t} = & \pcase{r}{x}{s \ovee t}{\_}{\fail \ovee \fail} \\ |
|
= & (\pcase{r}{x}{s}{\_}{\fail}) \ovee \\ |
|
& (\pcase{r}{x}{t}{\_}{\fail}) |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
The following lemma relates the structures on partial maps and predicates via the domain operator. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash \dom{(s \ovee t)} = \dom{s} \ovee \dom{t} : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
Let $b$ be a bound for $s \ovee t$. Then |
|
\[ \dom{(s \ovee t)} = \dom{(\doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}})} = \doo{x}{b}{\top} = \dom{b} \] |
|
We also have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\dom{s} & = \doo{x}{b}{\inlprop{x}}, \qquad \dom{t} = \doo{x}{b}{\inrprop{x}} \\ |
|
\therefore \dom{s} \ovee \dom{t} & = \doo{x}{b}{\inlprop{x} \ovee \inrprop{x}} & (\text{previous part}) \\ |
|
& = (\doo{x}{b}{\top}) = \dom{b} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
Using this, we can conclude several properties about partial maps immediately from the fact that they hold for predicates: |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item (\textbf{Restricted Cancellation Law}) If $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t = t : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash s = \fail : A + 1$. |
|
\item (\textbf{Positivity}) If $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t = \fail : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash s = \fail : A + 1$ and $\Gamma \vdash t = \fail : A + 1$. |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash s \leq t : A + 1$ and $\Gamma \vdash t \leq s : A + 1$ then $\Gamma \vdash s = t : A + 1$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item |
|
Suppose $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t = t : A + 1$. Then $\Gamma \vdash \dom{(s \ovee t)} = \dom{s} \ovee \dom{t} = \dom{t} : \mathbf{2}$, |
|
and so $\Gamma \vdash \dom{s} = \bot : \mathbf{2}$ and $\Gamma \vdash s = \fail : A + 1$ by Lemma \ref{lm:kernel}.\ref{lm:kernel2}. |
|
\item Suppose $\Gamma \vdash s \ovee t = \fail$. Then $\dom{(s \ovee |
|
t)} = \dom{s} \ovee \dom{t} = \bot$, and so $\dom{s} = \bot$ and |
|
$\dom{t} = \bot$. Therefore, $s = \fail$ and $t = \fail$ by Lemma |
|
\ref{lm:kernel}.\ref{lm:kernel2}. |
|
\item |
|
Let $s \ovee b = t$ and $t \ovee c = s$. Then $s \ovee b \ovee c = s$ and so $b \ovee c = \fail$ by the Restricted Cancellation Law, hence $b = c = \fail$ by Positivity. |
|
Thus, $s = s \ovee \fail = t$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
Finally, we can show that the partial projections on copowers behave as expected with respect to $\ovee$. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
For $t : n \cdot A$, |
|
\[ \rhd_{i_1, \ldots, i_k}(t) = \rhd_{i_1}(t) \ovee \cdots \ovee \rhd_{i_k}(t) \] |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
The proof is by induction on $k$. Take \[ b = \case_{i=1}^n t \of \nin{i}{n}{\_} \mapsto \begin{cases} 1 & \text{if } i = i_1, \ldots, i_k\\ |
|
2 & \text{if } i = i_{k+1} \\ |
|
3 & \text{otherwise} |
|
\end{cases}\] |
|
Then $\rhd_1(b) = \rhd_{i_1\cdots i_k}(t)$, $\rhd_2(b) = \rhd_{i_{k+1}}(t)$, and $\rhd_{12}(b) = \rhd_{i_1\cdots i_ki_{k+1}}(t)$. Therefore, |
|
\[ \rhd_{i_1i_2\cdots i_{k+1}}(t) = \rhd_{i_1\cdots i_k}(t) \ovee \rhd_{i_{k+1}}(t) = \rhd_{i_1}(t) \ovee \cdots \ovee \rhd_{i_{k+1}}(t) \] |
|
by the induction hypothesis. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subsubsection{Assert Maps} |
|
\label{section:assert} |
|
|
|
Recall that, for $x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$ and $\Gamma \vdash t : A$, we define $\Gamma \vdash \assert_{\lambda x p}(t) \eqdef \rhd_1(\instr_{\lambda x p}(t)) : A + 1$. |
|
|
|
This operation $\assert$ forms a bijection between: |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item |
|
the terms $p$ such that $x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$ (the predicates on $A$); and |
|
\item |
|
the terms $t$ such that $x : A \vdash t \leq \return{x} : A + 1$ |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
|
|
This is proven by the following result. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:assert} |
|
If $x : A \vdash p : 1 + 1$ and $\Gamma \vdash t : A$, then |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item |
|
$\Gamma \vdash \assert_{\lambda x p}(t) : A + 1$ |
|
\item |
|
$\Gamma \vdash \assert_{\lambda x p}(t) \leq \inl{t} : A + 1$. |
|
\item \textbf{\Rassertdown} |
|
\label{lm:assertdown} |
|
$\Gamma \vdash \dom{\assert_{\lambda x p}(t)} = [t/x] p : \mathbf{2}$ |
|
\item |
|
If $x : A \vdash t \leq \inl{x} : A + 1$ then $x : A \vdash t = \assert_{\lambda x (\dom{t})}(x) : A + 1$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item |
|
An easy application of the rules\Rinstr,\Rcase,\Rinl,\Rinr and\Runit. |
|
\item |
|
The term $\inl{\instr_{\lambda x p}(t)}$ is a bound for this inequality. |
|
\item |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\dom{\assert_{\lambda x p}(t)} & \eqdef \dom{\rhd_1(\instr_{\lambda x p}(t))} = \inlprop{\instr_{\lambda x p}(t)} \\ |
|
& = p[x:=t] & \text{by\Rinstrtest} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\item |
|
Let $b$ be a bound for the inequality $t \leq \inl{x}$, so $(b \goesto \rhd_1) = t$ and $\doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}} = \inl{x}$. |
|
Then |
|
\[ \dom{b} = \dom{(\doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}})} = \dom{\inl{x}} = \top . \] |
|
Hence we can define $c = \lft{b}$. We therefore have $\rhd_1(c) = t$ and $\nabla(c) = x$. |
|
Now, the rule\Retainstr gives us |
|
\begin{gather*} |
|
c = \instr_{\lambda x \inlprop{c}}(x) = \instr_{\dom{\lambda x t}}(x) \\ |
|
\therefore t = \rhd_1(c) = \assert_{\dom{\lambda x t}}(x) |
|
\end{gather*} |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
We now give rules for calculating $\instr_{\lambda x p}$ and $\assert_{\lambda x p}$ directed by the type. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma}[\Rassertscalar] |
|
If $\vdash s : \mathbf{2}$ then |
|
\[ \vdash \assert_{\lambda \_ s}(*) = \instr_{\lambda \_ s}(*) = s : \mathbf{2} \] |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
We have $\nabla(s) = *$ by\Retaone and $\dom{s} = s$ by\Retaplus. The |
|
result follows by\Retainstr. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma}[\Rinstrplus,\Rassertplus] |
|
If $x : A + B \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$ and $\Gamma \vdash t : A + B$ then |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\Gamma \vdash \instr_{\lambda x p}(t) = \case t \of |
|
& \inl{y} \mapsto (\inln + \inln)(\instr_{\lambda a. p[x:=\inl{a}]}(y)) \mid \\ |
|
& \inr{z} \mapsto (\inrn + \inrn)(\instr_{\lambda b. p[x:=\inr{b}]}(z)) \\ |
|
\Gamma \vdash \assert_{\lambda x p}(t) = \case t \of |
|
& \inl{y} \mapsto \doo{w}{\assert_{\lambda a. p[x:=\inl{a}]}(y)}{\return{\inl{w}}} \mid \\ |
|
& \inr{z} \mapsto \doo{w}{\assert_{\lambda b.p[x:=\inr{b}]}(z)}{\return{\inr{w}}} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
where $(\inln + \inln)(t) \eqdef \pcase{t}{x}{\inl{x}}{y}{\inl{y}}$, and $(\inrn + \inrn)(t)$ is defined similarly. |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
For $x : A + B$, let us write $f(x)$ for |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
f(x) \eqdef |
|
\case x \of |
|
& \inl{y} \mapsto (\inln + \inln)(\instr_{\lambda a.p[\inl{a}]}(y)) \mid \\ |
|
& \inr{z} \mapsto (\inrn + \inrn)(\instr_{\lambda b.p[\inr{b}]}(z)) |
|
\end{align*} |
|
We shall prove $f(x) = \instr_{\lambda x p}(x)$. |
|
|
|
We have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\nabla(f(x)) & = \case x \of \begin{array}[t]{l} \inl{y} \mapsto |
|
\inl{\nabla(\assert_{\lambda a.p[x:=\inl{a}]}(y))} \mid \\ |
|
\inr{z} \mapsto \inr{\nabla(\assert_{\lambda b.p[\inr{b}]}(z))} |
|
\end{array} \\ |
|
& = \pcase{x}{y}{\inl{y}}{z}{\inr{z}} \\ |
|
& = x & \text{by \Retaplus} \\ |
|
\dom{f(x)} & = \pcase{x}{y}{\dom{\instr_{\lambda a.p[x:=\inl{a}]}(y)}}{z}{\instr_{\lambda b.p[\inr{b}]}(z)} \\ |
|
& = \pcase{x}{y}{p[x:=\inl{y}]}{z}{p[x:=\inr{z}]} \\ |
|
& = p & \text{by Corollary \ref{cor:vacsub}.\ref{cor:vaccase}} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
Hence $f(x) = \instr_p(x)$ by\Retainstr. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{corollary}[\Rinstrm,\Rassertm] |
|
\label{cor:assertn} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item |
|
Given $x : \mathbf{m} \vdash t : \mathbf{n}$ and $\Gamma \vdash s : \mathbf{m}$, |
|
\[ \instr_{\lambda x t}(s) = \case_{i=1}^m\ s \of i \mapsto \case_{j=1}^n\ t[x:=i] \of j \mapsto \nin{j}{n}{i} \enspace . \] |
|
\item |
|
Given $x : \mathbf{n} \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$ and $\Gamma \vdash t : \mathbf{n}$, |
|
\[ \assert_p(t) = \case_{i=1}^n t \of i \mapsto \cond{p[x:=i]}{\return{i}}{\fail} \enspace . \] |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{corollary} |
|
|
|
\subsection{Sequential Product} |
|
|
|
We do not have conjunction or disjunction in our language for predicates over the same type, as this would involve duplicating variables. However, we do have |
|
the following \emph{sequential product}. |
|
(This was called the `and-then' test operator in Section 9 in \cite{Jacobs14}.) |
|
|
|
Let $x : A \vdash p,q : \mathbf{2}$. We define the \emph{sequential product} $p \andthen q$ by |
|
\[ x : A \vdash p \andthen q \eqdef \doo{x}{\assert_{\lambda x p}(x)}{q} : \mathbf{2} \enspace . \] |
|
|
|
\begin{proposition}$ $ |
|
\label{prop:testops} |
|
\label{prop:effmod} |
|
Let $x : A \vdash p,q : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item $\instr_{p \andthen q}(x) = \pcase{\instr_p(x)}{x}{\instr_q(x)}{y}{\inr{y}}$ |
|
\item $\assert_{p \andthen q}(x) = \doo{x}{\assert_p(x)}{\assert_q(x)} \eqdef \assert_p(x) \goesto \assert_q$ \label{prop:assertand} |
|
\item \label{prop:odotcomm} (\textbf{Commutativity}) |
|
$p \andthen q = q \andthen p$. |
|
\item $(p \ovee q) \andthen r = p \andthen r \ovee q \andthen r$ and $p \andthen (q \ovee r) = p \andthen q \ovee p \andthen r$. |
|
\item $p \andthen \bot = \bot \andthen q = \bot$ |
|
\item $p \andthen \top = p$ and $\top \andthen q = q$ |
|
\item $p \andthen (q \andthen r) = (p \andthen q) \andthen r$ |
|
\item Let $x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$. If $x$ does not occur in $q$, then $p \andthen q = \pcase{p}{\_}{q}{\_}{\bot}$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proposition} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item |
|
We have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
& \inlprop{\pcase{\instr_p(x)}{x}{\instr_q(x)}{y}{\inr{y}}} \\ |
|
& = \pcase{\instr_p(x)}{x}{q}{y}{\bot} \\ |
|
& = \doo{x}{\assert_p(x)}{q} = p \andthen q |
|
\end{align*} |
|
and |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
& \nabla(\pcase{\instr_p(x)}{x}{\instr_q(x)}{y}{\inr{y}}) \\ |
|
& = \pcase{\instr_p(x)}{x}{x}{y}{y} \\ |
|
& = \nabla(\instr_p(x)) = x |
|
\end{align*} |
|
so the result follows by\Retainstr. |
|
\item This follows immediately from the previous part. |
|
\item This follows from the previous part and the rule\Rcomm (Appendix \ref{section:instruments}). |
|
\item |
|
$p \andthen (q \ovee r) = (p \andthen q) \ovee (p \andthen r)$ by Corollary \ref{cor:doovee}. The other case follows by Commutativity. |
|
\item |
|
$\bot \andthen p = \bot$ by Lemma \ref{lm:do}. |
|
\item |
|
$\top \andthen q = q$ by Lemma \ref{lm:do}. |
|
\item $ |
|
\begin{aligned}[t] |
|
(p \andthen q) \andthen r |
|
& \eqdef \doo{x}{\assert_{p \andthen q}(x)}{r} \\ |
|
& = \doo{x}{(\assert_p(x) \goesto \assert_q)}{r} & \text{by part \ref{prop:assertand}} \\ |
|
& = \doo{x}{\assert_p(x)}{\doo{x}{\assert_q(x)}{r}} & \text{by Lemma \ref{lm:do}} \\ |
|
& \eqdef p \andthen (q \andthen r) |
|
\end{aligned} $ |
|
\item |
|
$p \andthen q = \doo{\_}{\assert_p(x)}{q} = \pcase{\assert_p(x)}{\_}{q}{\_}{\bot} = \pcase{\dom{(\assert_p(x))}}{\_}{q}{\_}{\bot} = \cond{p}{q}{\bot}$. |
|
\item |
|
Let $b : \mathbf{3}$ be given by |
|
\[ b \eqdef \cond{p}{\cond{q}{1}{3}}{\cond{r}{2}{3}} \] |
|
Then |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
b \goesto \rhd_1 & = \cond{p}{\cond{q}{\top}{\bot}}{\cond{r}{\bot}{\bot}} \\ |
|
& = \cond{p}{q}{\bot} = p \andthen q \\ |
|
b \goesto \rhd_2 & = \cond{p}{\bot}{r} & \text{similarly} \\ |
|
& = \cond{p^\bot}{r}{\bot} = p^\bot \andthen r |
|
\end{align*} |
|
Thus, $b$ is a bound for $p \andthen q \ovee p^\bot \andthen r$. We also have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}} & \eqdef \cond{p}{\cond{q}{\top}{\bot}}{\cond{r}{\top}{\bot}} \\ |
|
& = \cond{p}{q}{r} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
and the result is proved. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
These results show that the scalars form an \emph{effect monoid}, and the predicates on any type form an \emph{effect module} over that effect monoid (see \cite{Jacobs14} Lemma 13 and Proposition 14). |
|
|
|
\subsection{n-tests} |
|
\label{section:ntest} |
|
|
|
Recall that an \emph{$n$-test} on a type $A$ is an $n$-tuple $(p_1, \ldots, p_n)$ such that |
|
\[ x : A \vdash p_1 \ovee \cdots \ovee p_n = \top : \mathbf{2} \] |
|
|
|
The following lemma shows that there is a one-to-one correspondance between the $n$-tests on $A$, and |
|
the maps $A \rightarrow \mathbf{n}$. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:ntest} |
|
For every $n$-test $(p_1, \ldots, p_n)$ on $A$, there exists a term $x : A \vdash t(x) : \mathbf{n}$, |
|
unique up to equality, such that |
|
\[ x : A \vdash p_i(x) = \rhd_i(t(x)) : \mathbf{2} \] |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
The proof is by induction on $n$. The case $n = 1$ is trivial. |
|
|
|
Suppose the result is true for $n$. Take an $n+1$-test $(p_1, \ldots, p_{n+1})$. Then \\ |
|
$(p_1, p_2, \ldots, p_n \ovee p_{n+1})$ is an $n$-test. By the induction hypothesis, there exists $t : \mathbf{n}$ such that |
|
\[ \rhd_i(t) = p_i \; (i < n), \qquad \rhd_n(t) = p_n \ovee p_{n+1} \enspace . \] |
|
Let $b : \mathbf{3}$ be the bound for $p_n \ovee p_{n+1}$, so |
|
\[ \rhd_1(b) = p_n, \qquad \rhd_2(b) = p_{n+1}, \qquad \rhd_{12}(b) = p_n \ovee p_{n+1} \enspace . \] |
|
Reading $t$ and $b$ as partial functions in $\mathbf{n-1} + 1$ and $\mathbf{2} + 1$, we have that |
|
$\ker{t} = \dom{b} = p_n \ovee p_{n+1}$. |
|
Hence $\inlr{b}{t} : \mathbf{2} + \mathbf{n - 1}$ exists. Reading it as a term of type $\mathbf{n+1}$, we have that |
|
\[ \rhd_1(\inlr{b}{t}) = p_n, \quad \rhd_2(\inlr{b}{t}) = p_{n+1}, \quad \rhd_{i + 2}(\inlr{b}{t}) = p_i \; (i < n) \enspace . \] |
|
From this it is easy to construct the term of type $\mathbf{n + 1}$ required. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
We write $\instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(s)$ for $\instr_t(s)$, where $t$ is the term such that $\rhd_i(t) = p_i$ for each $i$. |
|
We therefore have |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:instrn} |
|
$\instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x)$ is the unique term such that $\intest{i}{\instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x)} = p_i$ for all $i$ |
|
and |
|
$\nabla(\instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x)) = x$. |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
Let $t : \mathbf{n}$ be the term such that $\rhd_i(t) = p_i$ for all $i$. |
|
By the rules for instruments, $\instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x)$ is the unique term such that |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
(\case_{i=1}^n \instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x) \of \nin{i}{n}(\_) \mapsto i) & = t \\ |
|
\nabla(\instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x)) & = x |
|
\end{align*} |
|
It is therefore sufficient to prove that, given terms $\Gamma \vdash s, t : \mathbf{n}$, |
|
\[ \Gamma \vdash s = t : \mathbf{n} \Leftrightarrow \forall i. \Gamma \vdash \rhd_i(s) = \rhd_i(t) : \mathbf{2} \] |
|
This fact is proven by induction on $n$, with the case $n = 2$ holding by the rules\Rbetainlrone,\Rbetainlrtwo and\Retainlr. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:assertpi} |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\instr_{p_i}(x) & = \case_{j=1}^n \instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x) \of \nin{j}{n}{x} \mapsto |
|
\begin{cases} |
|
\inl{x} & \text{if } i = j \\ |
|
\inr{x} & \text{if } i \neq j |
|
\end{cases} \\ |
|
\assert_{p_i}(x) & = \case_{j=1}^n \instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x) \of \nin{j}{n}{x} \mapsto \begin{cases} |
|
\return x & \text{if } i = j \\ |
|
\fail & \text{if } i \neq j |
|
\end{cases} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
The first formula holds because $\inlprop{}$ maps the right-hand side to $\intest{i}{\instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x)} = p_i$, |
|
and $\nabla$ mapst the right-hand side to $x$. |
|
The second formula follows immediately from the first. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\item If $(p,q)$ is a 2-test, then $q = p^\bot$, and $\mathsf{instr}_{(p,q)}(t) = \mathsf{instr}_{p}(t)$. |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
If $(p,q)$ is a 2-test then $p \ovee q = \top$ and so $q = p^\bot$ by Proposition \ref{prop:logic}.\ref{prop:ortho}. Then |
|
$\mathsf{instr}_{(p,q)}(t) = \mathsf{instr}_p(t)$ by\Retainstr, since $\inlprop{\mathsf{instr}_{(p,q)}(x)} = \langle p ? \rangle \top \ovee \langle q ? \rangle \bot = p$ |
|
and $\nabla(\mathsf{instr}_{(p,q)}(x)) = x$. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
We can now define the program that divides into $n$ branches depending on the outcome of an $n$-test: |
|
|
|
\begin{definition} |
|
\label{df:measure} |
|
Given $x : A \vdash p_1(x) \ovee \cdots \ovee p_n(x) = \top : \mathbf{2}$, define |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
x : A & \vdash \meas\ p_1(x) \mapsto t_1(x) \mid \cdots \mid p_n(x) \mapsto t_n(x) \\ |
|
& \eqdef \case \mathsf{instr}_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x) \of \inn_1(x) \mapsto t_1(x) \mid \cdots \mid \inn_n(x) \mapsto t_n(x) |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\end{definition} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:measure} |
|
The $\meas$ construction satisfies the following laws. |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item \label{lm:measuretop} $(\meas\ \top \mapsto t) = t$ |
|
\item \label{lm:measurebot} $(\meas\ p_1 \mapsto t_1 \mid \cdots \mid p_n \mapsto t_n \mid \bot \mapsto t_{n+1}) = (\meas\ p_1 \mapsto t_1 \mid \cdots \mid p_n \mapsto t_n)$ |
|
\item \label{lm:measureand} $(\meas_i\ p_i \mapsto \meas_j\ q_{ij} \mapsto t_{ij}) = (\meas_{i,j}\ p_i \andthen q_{ij} \mapsto t_{ij})$ |
|
\item \label{lm:measureperm} For any permutation $\pi$ of $\{1, \ldots, n\}$, $\meas_i\ p_i \mapsto t_i = \meas_i\ p_{\pi(i)} \mapsto t_{\pi(i)}$. |
|
\item \label{lm:measureor} If $t_n = t_{n+1}$ then \\ $\meas_{i=1}^n p_i \mapsto t_i = \meas\ p_1 \mapsto t_1 \mid \cdots \mid p_{n-1} \mapsto t_{n-1} \mid p_n \ovee p_{n+1} \mapsto t_n$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item |
|
$ \begin{aligned}[t] |
|
\meas \top \mapsto t(x) & \eqdef \case \instr_{(\top)}(x) \of \nin{1}{1}{x} \mapsto t(x) \\ |
|
& = t(\instr_{(\top)}(x)) |
|
\end{aligned}$. |
|
|
|
So it suffices to prove $\instr_{(\top)}(s) = s$. |
|
This holds by the uniqueness of Lemma \ref{lm:instrn}, since we have $\intest{1}{x} = \top$ and $\nabla(x) = x$. |
|
\item |
|
It suffices to prove $\instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n, \bot)}(x) = \case_{i=1}^n \instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x) \of \nin{i}{n}{x} \mapsto \nin{i}{n+1}{x}$. |
|
Let $R$ denote the right-hand side. Then |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\intest{i}{R} & = \intest{i}{\instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x)} = p_i \\ |
|
\nabla(R) & = \case_{i=1}^n \instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x) \of \nin{i}{n}{x} \mapsto x \\ |
|
& = \nabla(\instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x)) = x |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\item |
|
Let us write $\nin{i,j}{}{}$ ($1 \leq i \leq m$, $1 \leq j \leq n_i$) for the constructors of $(n_1 + \cdots + n_m) \cdot A$, |
|
and $\intest{i,j}{}$ for the corresponding predicates. |
|
|
|
It suffices to prove that |
|
\[ \instr_{(p_i \andthen q_{ij})_{i,j}}(x) = \case_{i=1}^m\ \instr_{\vec{p}}(x) \of \nin{i}{m}{x} \mapsto |
|
\case_{j=1}^{n_1}\ \instr_{\vec{q_i}}(x) \of \nin{j}{n_i}{x} \mapsto \nin{i,j}{}{x} \enspace . \] |
|
Let $R$ denote the right-hand side. We have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\intest{i,j}{R} & = \case_{i'=1}^m\ \instr_{\vec{p}}(x) \of \nin{i'}{m}{x} \mapsto \begin{cases} |
|
\intest{j}{\instr_{\vec{q_i}}(x)} & \text{if } i = i' \\ |
|
\bot & \text{if } i \neq \i' |
|
\end{cases} \\ |
|
& = \case_{i'=1}^m\ \instr_{\vec{p}}(x) \of \nin{i'}{m}{x} \mapsto \begin{cases} |
|
q_{ij} & \text{if } i = i' \\ |
|
\bot & \text{if } i \neq i' |
|
\end{cases} \\ |
|
& = \doo{x}{\left( \case_{i'=1}^m\ \instr_{\vec{p}}(x) \of \nin{i'}{m}{x} \mapsto \begin{cases} |
|
\return x & \text{if } i = i' \\ |
|
\fail & \text{if } i \neq i' |
|
\end{cases} \right)}{q_{ij}} \\ |
|
& = \doo{x}{\assert_{p_i}(x)}{q_{ij}} \\ |
|
& \qquad \qquad \text{(by Lemma \ref{lm:assertpi})} \\ |
|
& = p_i \andthen q_{ij} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
and |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\nabla(R) & = \case_{i=1}^m\ \instr_{\vec{p}}(x) \of \nin{i}{m}{x} \mapsto \nabla(\instr_{\vec{q_i}}(x)) \\ |
|
& = \case_{i=1}^m\ \instr_{\vec{p}}(x) \of \nin{i}{m}{x} \mapsto x = \nabla(\instr_{\vec{p}}(x)) = x |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\item |
|
It is sufficient to prove that |
|
\[ \instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_n)}(x) = \case_{i=1}^n \instr_{(p_{\pi(1)}, \ldots, p_{\pi(n)})}(x) \of \nin{i}{n}{x} \mapsto \nin{\pi^{-1}(i)}{n}{x} |
|
\enspace . \] |
|
Let $R$ denote the right-hand side. We have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\intest{i}{R} & = \intest{\pi^{-1}(i)}{\instr_{(p_{\pi(1)}, \ldots, p_{\pi(n)})}(x)} = p_i \\ |
|
\nabla(R) & = \nabla(\instr_{(p_{\pi(1)}, \ldots, p_{\pi(n)})}(x)) = x |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\item |
|
It suffices to prove $\instr_{(p_1, \ldots, p_{n-1}, p_n \ovee p_{n+1})} = \case_{i=1}^{n+1} \instr_{\vec{p}}(x) \of \nin{i}{n}{x} \mapsto \begin{cases} |
|
\nin{i}{n}{x} & \text{if } i < n \\ \nin{i}{n}{x} & \text{if } i \geq n \end{cases}$. Let $R$ denote the right-hand side. We have, for $i < n$: |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\intest{i}{R} & = \intest{i}{\instr_{\vec{p}}(x)} = p_i |
|
\intest{n}{R} & = \rhd_{n,n+1}(\ind{\instr_{\vec{p}}(x)}) \\ |
|
& = \intest{n}{\instr_{\vec{p}}(x)} \ovee \intest{n+1}{\instr_{\vec{p}}(x)} = p_n \ovee p_{n+1} |
|
\nabla(R) & = x \enspace . |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Let $x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$ and $\Gamma, x : A \vdash s,t : B$. We define |
|
\[ \cond{p}{s}{t} \eqdef \meas\ p \mapsto s \mid p^\bot \mapsto t : B \enspace . \] |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:measuretwo} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item If $x : A \vdash p_1 \ovee \cdots \ovee p_n = \top : \mathbf{2}$ and $x : A \vdash q_1, \ldots, q_n : \mathbf{2}$, then |
|
\[ (\mathsf{measure}\ p_1 \mapsto q_1 \mid \cdots \mid p_n \mapsto q_n) = p_1 \andthen q_1 \ovee \cdots \ovee p_n \andthen q_n \enspace . \] |
|
\item Let $x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$ and $\Gamma \vdash q,r : B$ where $x \notin \Gamma$. Then $\cond{p}{q}{r} = \pcase{p}{\_}{q}{\_}{r} : B$. \label{lm:measurecond} |
|
\item\label{lm:measuretwo'} Let $x : A \vdash p : \mathbf{2}$. Then $x : A \vdash \cond{p}{\top}{\bot} = p : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item |
|
Immediate from Lemma \ref{lm:instrn}. |
|
\item We have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\meas\ p \mapsto q \mid p^\bot \mapsto r & \eqdef \case \instr_{\lambda x p}(x) \of \inl{\_} \mapsto q \mid \inr{\_} \mapsto r \\ |
|
& = \case \inlprop{\instr_{\lambda x p}(x)} \of \inl{\_} \mapsto q \mid \inr{\_} \mapsto r \\ |
|
& = \case p \of \inl{\_} \mapsto q \mid \inr{\_} \mapsto r |
|
\end{align*} |
|
\item $\cond{p}{\top}{\bot} = \pcase{p}{\_}{\top}{\_}{\bot} = p$ by\Retaplus. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\subsection{Scalars} |
|
\label{sec:scalars} |
|
|
|
From the rules given in Figure \ref{fig:equations}, the usual algebra of the rational interval from 0 to 1 follows. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
If $p / q = m / n$ as rational numbers, then $\vdash p \cdot (1 / q) = m \cdot (1 / n) : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
We first prove that $\vdash a \cdot (1 / a b) = 1 / b : \mathbf{2}$ for all $a$, $b$. This holds because $ab \cdot (1 / ab) = \top$ by\Rntimesoneovern, |
|
hence $a \cdot (1 / ab) = 1/b$ by\Rdivide. |
|
|
|
Hence we have $p \cdot (1 / q) = pn \cdot (1 / nq) = qm \cdot (1 / n q) = m \cdot (1 /n)$. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
Recall that within $\COMET$, we are writing $m / n$ for the term $m \cdot (1 / n)$. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
\label{lm:rational} |
|
Let $q$ and $r$ be rational numbers in $[0,1]$. |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item If $q \leq r$ in the usual ordering, then $\vdash q \leq r : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\item $\vdash q \ovee r : \mathbf{2}$ iff $q + r \leq 1$, in which case $\Gamma \vdash q \ovee r = q + r : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\item $\vdash q \andthen r = qr : \mathbf{2}$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
By the previous lemma, we may assume $q$ and $r$ have the same denominator. Let $q = a / n$ and $r = b / n$. |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item We have $a \leq b$, hence $\vdash a \cdot (1 / n) \leq b \cdot (1 / n) : \mathbf{2}$ by Lemma \ref{lm:ordering}.\ref{lm:leqovee}. |
|
\item If $q + r \leq 1$ then $\vdash a \cdot (1 / n) \ovee b \cdot (1 / n) = (a + b) \cdot (1 / n) : \mathbf{2}$ by Associativity. |
|
|
|
For the converse, suppose $\vdash q \ovee r : \mathbf{2}$, so $\vdash (a + b) \cdot (1 / n) : \mathbf{2}$, and suppose for a contradiction $q + r > 1$. Then we have |
|
\[ \vdash \top \ovee (a + b - n) \cdot (1 / n) : \mathbf{2} \] |
|
and so $\vdash (1 / n) = 0 : \mathbf{2}$ by the Zero-One Law, hence $\vdash \top = n \cdot (1 / n) = n \cdot 0 = \bot : \mathbf{2}$. This contradicts Corollary \ref{cor:consistency}. |
|
\item We first prove $(1 / a) \andthen (1 / b) = 1 / ab : \mathbf{2}$. This holds because $ab \cdot (1 / a) \andthen (1 / b) = (a \cdot (1 / a)) \andthen (b \cdot (1 / b)) = \top \andthen \top = \top$. |
|
|
|
Now we have, $(m / n) \andthen (p / q) = mp \cdot ((1 / n) \andthen (1 /q)) = mp \cdot (1 / nq)$ as required. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\subsection{Normalisation} |
|
|
|
The following lemma gives us a rule that allows us to calculate the normalised form of a substate in many cases, including the examples in Section \ref{section:examples}. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
Let $\vdash t : A + 1$, $\vdash p_1 \ovee \cdots \ovee p_n = \top : \mathbf{2}$, and $\vdash q : \mathbf{2}$. Let $\vdash s_1, \ldots, s_n : A$. Suppose $\vdash 1 / m \leq q : \mathbf{2}$. If |
|
\[ \vdash t = \meas\ p_1 \andthen q \mapsto \return{s_1} \mid \cdots \mid p_n \andthen q \mapsto \return{s_n} \mid q^\bot \mapsto \fail : A + 1 \] |
|
then |
|
\[ \vdash \norm{t} = \meas\ p_1 \mapsto s_1 \mid \cdots \mid p_n \mapsto s_n : A \] |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
Let $\rho \eqdef \meas_{i=1}^n p_i \mapsto s_i$. |
|
By the rule\Retanorm, it is sufficient to prove that $t = \doo{\_}{t}{\return{\rho}}$. |
|
We have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\doo{\_}{t}{\return{\rho}} |
|
& = \meas\ p_1 \andthen q \mapsto \return{\rho} \mid \cdots \mid p_n \andthen q \mapsto \return{\rho} \mid q^\bot \mapsto \fail \\ |
|
& = \meas\ (p_1 \ovee \cdots \ovee p_n) \andthen q \mapsto \return{\rho} \mid q^\bot \mapsto \fail \\ |
|
& = \meas\ q \mapsto \return{\rho} \mid q^\bot \mapsto \fail \\ |
|
& = \meas\ q \mapsto \meas_{i=1}^n p_i \mapsto \return{s_i} \mid q^\bot \mapsto \fail \\ |
|
& = \meas_{i=1}^n\ q \andthen p_i \mapsto \return{s_i} \mid q^\bot \mapsto \fail \\ |
|
& = t |
|
\end{align*} |
|
(We used the commutativity of $\andthen$ in the last step.) |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{corollary} |
|
\label{cor:normmeasure} |
|
Let $\alpha_1$, \ldots, $\alpha_n$, $\beta$ be rational numbers that sum to 1, with $\beta \neq 1$. If |
|
\[ \vdash t = \meas\ \alpha_1 \mapsto \return{s_1} \mid \cdots \mid \alpha_n \mapsto \return{s_n} \mid \beta \mapsto \fail : A + 1 \] |
|
then |
|
\[ \vdash \norm{t} = \meas\ \alpha_1 / (\alpha_1 + \cdots + \alpha_n) \mapsto s_1 \mid \cdots \mid \alpha_n / (\alpha_1 + \cdots + \alpha_n) \mapsto s_n : A \] |
|
\end{corollary} |
|
|
|
\section{Semantics} |
|
\label{section:semantics} |
|
|
|
The terms of $\COMET$ are intended to represent probabilistic programs. |
|
We show how to give semantics to our system in three different ways: using discrete and continuous probability distributions, and |
|
simple set-theoretic semantics for deterministic computation. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Discrete Probabilistic Computation} |
|
\label{section:dpc} |
|
|
|
We give an interpretation that assigns, to each term, a discrete probability distribution over its output type. |
|
|
|
\begin{definition} |
|
Let $A$ be a set. |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item |
|
The \emph{support} of a function $\phi : A \rightarrow [0,1]$ is $\supp \phi = \{ a \in A : \phi(a) \neq 0 \}$. |
|
\item |
|
A \emph{(discrete) probability distribution} over $A$ is a function $\phi : A \rightarrow \phi$ with finite support |
|
such that $\sum_{a \in A} \phi(a) = 1$. |
|
\item |
|
Let $\mathcal{D} A$ be the set of all probability distributions on $A$. |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
\end{definition} |
|
|
|
We shall interpret every type $A$ as a set |
|
$\brackets{A}$. Assume we are given a set $\brackets{\mathbf{C}}$ for each type constant $\mathbf{C}$. |
|
Define a set $\brackets{A}$ for each type $A$ thus: |
|
\[ \brackets{0} = \emptyset \qquad \brackets{1} = \{ * \} \qquad \brackets{A + B} = \brackets{A} \uplus \brackets{B} \qquad \brackets{A \sotimes B} = \brackets{A} \times \brackets{B} \] |
|
where $A \uplus B = \{ a_1 : a \in A \} \cup \{ b_2 : b \in B \}$. We extend this to contexts by defining $\brackets{x_1 : A_1, \ldots, x_n : A_n} = \brackets{A_1} \times \cdots \times \brackets{A_n}$. |
|
|
|
Now, to every term $x_1 : A_1, \ldots, x_n : A_n \vdash t : B$, we assign a function |
|
$\brackets{t} : \brackets{A_1} \times \cdots \times \brackets{A_n} \rightarrow \mathcal{D} \brackets{B}$. |
|
The value $\brackets{t}(a_1, \ldots, a_n)(b) \in [0,1]$ will be written as $P(t(a_1, \ldots, a_n) = b)$, and should be thought of as the probability |
|
that $b$ will be the output if $a_1$, \ldots, $a_n$ are the inputs. |
|
|
|
\begin{figure} |
|
\begin{mdframed} |
|
\begin{multicols}{2} |
|
$$\begin{aligned} |
|
P(x_i(\vec{a}) = b) & = \begin{cases} |
|
1 \text{ if } b = a_i \\ |
|
0 \text{ if } b \neq a_i |
|
\end{cases} \\ \midrule |
|
P(*(\vec{a}) = *) & = 1 \\ \midrule |
|
\multicolumn{2}{l}{$P((s \sotimes t)(\vec{g}, \vec{d}) = (a,b))$} \\ |
|
& = P(s(\vec{g}) = a) P(t(\vec{d}) = b) \\ \midrule |
|
P((\magic{t})(\vec{g}) = a) & = 0 \\ \midrule |
|
P(\inl{t}(\vec{g}) = a_1) & = P(t(\vec{g}) = a) \\ |
|
P(\inl{t}(\vec{g}) = b_2) & = 0 \\ \midrule |
|
P(\inr{t}(\vec{g}) = a_1) & = 0 \\ |
|
P(\inr{t}(\vec{g}) = b_2) & = P(t(\vec{g}) = b) \\ \midrule |
|
P(\inlr{s}{t}(\vec{g}) = a_1) & = P(s(\vec{g}) = a_1) \\ |
|
P(\inlr{s}{t}(\vec{g}) = b_2) & = P(t(\vec{g}) = b_1) |
|
\end{aligned}$$ |
|
|
|
$\begin{aligned} |
|
\multicolumn{2}{l}{$P(\lft{t}(\vec{g}) = a) = P(t(\vec{g}) = a_1)$} \\ \midrule |
|
\multicolumn{2}{l}{$P(\instr_{\lambda x t}(s)(\vec{g}) = a_i)$} \\ & = P(s(\vec{g}) = a) P(t(a) = i) \\ \midrule |
|
\multicolumn{2}{l}{$P(1 / n(\vec{g}) = \top) = 1 / n$} \\ |
|
\multicolumn{2}{l}{$P(1 / n(\vec{g}) = \bot) = (n - 1) / n$} \\ \midrule |
|
\multicolumn{2}{l}{$P(\norm{t}(\vec{g}) = a)$} \\ & \ = P(t(\vec{g}) = a_1) / (1 - P(t(\vec{g}) = *_2)) \\ \midrule |
|
\multicolumn{2}{l}{$P((s \ovee t)(\vec{g}) = a_1)$} \\ & \ = P(s(\vec{g}) = a_1) + P(t(\vec{g}) = a_1) \\ |
|
\multicolumn{2}{l}{$P((s \ovee t)(\vec{g}) = *_2)$} \\ & \ = P(s(\vec{g}) = *_2) + P(t(\vec{g}) = *_2) - 1 |
|
\end{aligned}$ |
|
\end{multicols} |
|
$\begin{aligned} |
|
& P((\plet{x}{y}{s}{t})(\vec{g},\vec{d}) = c) = \sum_a \sum_b P(s(\vec{g}) = (a,b)) P(t(\vec{d},a,b) = c) \\ \midrule |
|
& P(\pcase{r}{x}{s}{y}{t}(\vec{g},\vec{d}) = c) \\ |
|
& = \sum_a P(r(\vec{g}) = a_1) P(s(\vec{d}, a) = c) + |
|
\sum_b P(r(\vec{g}) = b_2) P(t(\vec{d}, b) = c) |
|
\end{aligned}$ |
|
\end{mdframed} |
|
\end{figure} |
|
|
|
The sums involved here are all well-defined because, for all $t$ and $\vec{g}$, the function $P(t(\vec{g}) = -)$ has finite support. |
|
|
|
\begin{lemma} |
|
Let $\Gamma \vdash s : A$ and $\Delta, x : A \vdash t : B$, so that $\Gamma, \Delta \vdash t[x:=s] : B$. Then |
|
\[ P(t[x:=s](\vec{g}, \vec{d}) = b) = \sum_{a \in \brackets{A}} P(s(\vec{g}) = a) P(t(\vec{d},a) = b) \] |
|
\end{lemma} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
The proof is by induction on $t$. We do here the case where $t \equiv x$: |
|
\[ P(x[x:=s](\vec{g}) = b) = P(s(\vec{g}) = b) \] |
|
and |
|
\[ \sum_a P(s(\vec{g}) = a) P(x(a) = b) = P(s(\vec{g}) = b) \] |
|
since $P(x(a) = b)$ is 0 if $a \neq b$ and 1 if $a = b$. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{theorem}[Soundness] |
|
\begin{enumerate} |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash t : A$ is derivable, then for all $\vec{g} \in \brackets{\Gamma}$, we have $P(t(\vec{g}) = -)$ is a |
|
probability distribution on $\brackets{A}$. |
|
\item If $\Gamma \vdash s = t : A$, then $P(s(\vec{g}) = a) = P(t(\vec{g}) = a)$. |
|
\end{enumerate} |
|
\end{theorem} |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
The proof is by induction on derivations. We do here the case of the rule\Rinstrtest: |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
& P((\case_i\ \instr_{\lambda x t}(s) \of \nin{i}{n}{\_} \mapsto i)(\vec{g}) = i) \\ |
|
& = \sum_{j = 1}^n \sum_{a \in \brackets{A}} P(\instr_{\lambda x t}(s)(\vec{g}) = a_j) P(\nin{i}{n}{*}() = *_j) \\ |
|
& = \sum_{a \in \brackets{A}} P(\instr_{\lambda x t}(s)(\vec{g}) = a_i) \\ |
|
& = \sum_{a \in \brackets{A}} P(s(\vec{g}) = a) P(t(a) = i) \\ |
|
& = P(t[x:=s](\vec{g}) = i) |
|
\end{align*} |
|
by the lemma. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\begin{corollary} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash s \leq t : A + 1$ then $P(s(\vec{g}) = a) \leq P(t(\vec{g}) = a)$ for all $\vec{g}$, $a$. |
|
\end{corollary} |
|
|
|
As a corollary, we know that $\COMET$ is non-degenerate: |
|
|
|
\begin{corollary} |
|
\label{cor:consistency} |
|
Not every judgement is derivable; in particular, the judgement $\vdash \top = \bot : \mathbf{2}$ is not derivable. |
|
\end{corollary} |
|
|
|
With these definitions, we can calculate the semantics of each of our defined constructions. For example, |
|
the semantics of $\mathsf{assert}$ are given by |
|
\[ P(\assert_{\lambda x p}(t)(\vec{g}) = a_1) = P(t(\vec{g}) = a)P(p(a) = \top) \] |
|
\[ P(\assert_{\lambda x p}(t)(\vec{g}) = *_2) = \sum_a P(t(\vec{g}) = a) P(p(a) = \bot) \] |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Alternative Semantics} |
|
|
|
It is also possible to give semantics to $\COMET$ using continuous probabilities. We assign a measurable space $\brackets{A}$ to every type $A$. Each term then gives a measurable function $\brackets{A_1} \times \cdots \times \brackets{A_n} \rightarrow \mathcal{G} \brackets{B}$, where $\mathcal{G} X$ is the space of all probability distributions over the measurable space $X$. ($\mathcal{G}$ here is the \emph{Giry monad} \cite{Jacobs13a}.) |
|
|
|
If we remove the constants $1 / n$ from the system, we can give \emph{deterministic} semantics to the subsystem, in which we assign a set to every type, and a function $\brackets{A_1} \times \cdots \times \brackets{A_n} \rightarrow \brackets{B}$. |
|
|
|
More generally, we can give an interpretation of $\COMET$ in any \emph{commutative monoidal effectus with normalisation} |
|
in which there exists a scalar $s$ such that $n \cdot s = 1$ for all positive integers $n$ \cite{Cho}. The discrete and continuous semantics we have described are two instances of this interpretation. |
|
|
|
\section{Conclusion} |
|
|
|
The system $\COMET$ allows for the specification of probabilistic programs and reasoning about their properties, both within the same syntax. |
|
|
|
There are several avenues for further work and research. |
|
\begin{itemize} |
|
\item The type theory that we describe can be interpreted both in |
|
discrete and in continuous probabilistic models, that is, both in |
|
the Kleisli category $\Kl(\Dst)$ of the distribution monad $\Dst$ |
|
and in the Kleisli category $\Kl(\Giry)$ of the Giry monad $\Giry$. |
|
On a finite type each distribution is discrete. The discrete semantics were exploited in |
|
the current paper in the examples in Section~\ref{section:examples}. |
|
In a follow-up version we intend to elaborate also continuous |
|
examples. |
|
|
|
\item The normalisation and conditioning that we use in this paper can |
|
in principle also be used in a quantum context, using the |
|
appropriate (non-side-effect free) assert maps that one has |
|
there. This will give a form of Bayesian quantum theory, as also |
|
explored in~\cite{LeiferS13}. |
|
|
|
\item A further ambitious follow-up project is to develop tool support |
|
for $\COMET$, so that the computations that we carry out here by |
|
hand can be automated. This will provide a formal language for |
|
Bayesian inference. |
|
\end{itemize} |
|
|
|
\subparagraph*{Acknowledgements} |
|
|
|
Thanks to Kenta Cho for discussion and suggestions during the writing of this paper, and very detailed proofreading. Thanks to Bas Westerbaan for discussions about effectus theory. |
|
|
|
\bibliography{probable} |
|
|
|
\appendix |
|
|
|
\section{Formal Presentation of $\COMET$} |
|
\label{section:rules} |
|
|
|
The full set of rules of deduction for $\COMET$ are given below. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Structural Rules} |
|
\label{section:structural} |
|
$$ \Texch \qquad \Tvar $$ |
|
|
|
The exchange rule says that the order of the variables in the context does not matter. This holds |
|
for all types of judgements J on the right hand side of the turnstile. The weakening rule is admissible (see Lemma \ref{lm:meta}.\ref{lm:weak}), and says |
|
that one may add (unused) assumptions to the context. |
|
|
|
However, we do \emph{not} have the contraction rule in our type theory. In particular, the judgement $x : A \vdash x \otimes x : A \otimes A$ is \emph{not} derivable. |
|
Thus, in our probabilistic settings, information may be discarded, but cannot be duplicated. |
|
|
|
$$ \Tref \; \Tsym \; \Ttrans $$ |
|
|
|
These rules simply ensure that the judgement equality is an equivalence relation. |
|
|
|
\subsection{The Singleton Type} |
|
|
|
$$ \Tunit \quad \Tetaone $$ |
|
|
|
These ensure that the type $1$ is a type with only one object up to equality. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Tensor Product} |
|
|
|
$$ \Tpair \; \Tlett $$ |
|
$$ \Tpaireq $$ |
|
$$ \Tleteq $$ |
|
|
|
Notice that in rule\Rpair the contexts $\Gamma$ and |
|
$\Delta$ of the two terms $s$, $t$ are put together in the |
|
conclusion. Thus, the tensor $s \sotimes t$ on terms is a form of |
|
parallel composition. This is a so-called \emph{introduction rule} for the |
|
tensor type, since it tells us how to produce terms in a tensor type |
|
$A\otimes B$ on the right hand side of the turnstile $\vdash$. The |
|
rule\Rlett is an \emph{elimination rule} since it tells us how to use terms |
|
of tensor type. |
|
|
|
$$ \Tbeta $$ |
|
$$ \Teta $$ |
|
|
|
Rule\Rbeta tells how a let |
|
term should decompose a term $r \sotimes s$, namely by simultaneously |
|
substituting $r$ for $x$ and $s$ for $y$ in as described in the term |
|
$t[x:=r,y:=s]$. Rule\Reta is its dual, and says that decomposing an object then |
|
immediately recomposing it does nothing. |
|
|
|
$$ \Tletlet $$ |
|
$$ \Tletpair $$ |
|
|
|
\noindent Our final set of rules are so-called commuting conversion |
|
rules described above. They regulate the proper interaction between |
|
the term constructs let, case and $\sotimes$. It looks like several interactions are missing here (a $\lett$ on the right |
|
of a tensor, a $\lett$ inside a $\case$, etc.), but in fact, the rules for all the other cases can be derived from these four, as we show in |
|
Lemma \ref{lm:sub}.\ref{lm:letsub}. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Empty Type} |
|
|
|
$$ \Tmagic \quad \Tetazero $$ |
|
|
|
The rule\Rmagic |
|
says that from an inhabitant $M:0$ we can produce an inhabitant |
|
$\magic{M}$ in any type $A$. Intuitively, this says `If the empty type is inhabited, then every type is inhabited', which is vacuously true. |
|
And\Retazero says that vacuously, if the empty type $0$ is inhabited, then all terms of any type are equal. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Binary Coproducts} |
|
\label{section:coproducts} |
|
$$ \Tinl \quad \Tinr $$ |
|
$$ \Tinleq \quad \Tinreq $$ |
|
$$\Tcase $$ |
|
$$\Tcaseeq $$ |
|
|
|
For the coproduct type $A+B$ we have two introduction rules\Rinl |
|
and\Rinr which produce terms $\inl{s}, \inr{t} : A+B$, coming from |
|
$s:A$ and $t:B$. These operations $\inl{-}$ and $\inr{-}$ are often |
|
called \emph{coprojections} or \emph{injections}. |
|
|
|
The associated elimination |
|
rule\Rcase produces a term that uses a term $r:A+B$ by distinguishing |
|
whether or not $r$ is of the form $\inl{-}$ or $\inr{-}$. In the first |
|
case the outcome of $r$ is used in term $s$, and in the second case in |
|
term $t$. |
|
|
|
$$ \Tbetaplusone $$ |
|
$$ \Tbetaplustwo $$ |
|
$$ \Tetaplus $$ |
|
|
|
There are two $\beta$-conversions\Rbetaplusone and\Rbetaplustwo |
|
for the coproduct type, describing how a $\mathsf{case}$ term should handle a |
|
term of form $\inl{r}$ or $\inr{r}$. Again this this |
|
done via the expected substitution, using the appropriate variable |
|
($x$ or $y$). |
|
|
|
In rule\Retaplus, if the decomposition of $t$ into $\inl{-}$ and $\inr{-}$ |
|
is then immediately reconstituted, then the input is unchanged. |
|
$$ \Tcasecase $$ |
|
$$ \Tcasepair $$ |
|
$$ \Tletcase $$ |
|
These rules for commuting conversions show how the eliminators for $\otimes$ and $+$ interact. Again, |
|
the other cases can be derived from the primitive rules given here (Lemma \ref{lm:sub}). |
|
|
|
\subsection{Partial Pairing} |
|
\label{section:effectus} |
|
|
|
We now come to the constructions that are new to our type theory. These possess a feature that is unique to this type theory: |
|
we allow typing judgements (of the form $t : A$) to depend on equality judgements (of the form $s = t : A$). |
|
|
|
$$ \Tinlr $$ |
|
$$ \Tinlreq $$ |
|
|
|
The term $\inlr{s}{t}$ can be understood in this way. Consider a term $\Gamma \vdash t : A + 1$ as a partial computation: |
|
it may output a value of type $A$, or it may diverge (if it reduces to $\inr{*}$.) If the judgement $s \downarrow = t \uparrow$ holds, |
|
then we know that exactly one of the computations $s$ and $t$ will terminate on any input. The term $\inlr{s}{t}$ intuitively denotes the following computation: |
|
given an input, decide which of $s$ or $t$ will terminate. If $s$ will terminate, run $s$; otherwise, run $t$. |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
We have the following $\beta$- and $\eta$-rules for the $\inlrn$ construction: |
|
|
|
$$ \Tbetainlrone $$ |
|
$$ \Tbetainlrtwo $$ |
|
$$ \Tetainlr $$ |
|
|
|
\subsection{The $\lft{}$ Construction} |
|
|
|
$$ \Tleft $$ |
|
$$ \Tlefteq $$ |
|
|
|
The term $\lft{t}$ should be understood as follows: if we have a term $t : A + B$ and a `proof' that $t = \inl{s}$ for some term $s : A$, then |
|
$\lft{t}$ is that term $s$. The computation rules for this construction are: |
|
|
|
$$ \Tbetaleft \Tetaleft $$ |
|
|
|
\subsection{Joint Monicity Condition} |
|
\label{section:JM} |
|
|
|
We need the following rule for technical reasons. It corresponds to the condition that the two maps $\rhd_!$ and $\rhd_2$ from $A + A$ to $A$ are jointly monic |
|
in the partial form of the effectus (see \cite{Jacobs14} Assumption 1 or \cite{Cho} Lemma 49.4). |
|
|
|
\TTJMprime |
|
|
|
It is used in the proof of the associativity of $\ovee$ (Lemma \ref{lm:ordering}.\ref{lm:assoc}). |
|
|
|
\subsection{Instruments} |
|
\label{section:instruments} |
|
|
|
The \emph{instrument} map $\instr_{\lambda x t}(s)$ should be understood as follows: it denotes the value $\nin{i}{n}{s}$ if $t[x:=s]$ returns the value $i : \mathbf{n}$. |
|
|
|
If we were allowed to simply duplicate data, we could have defined $\measure{x}{p}{t}$ to be $\pcase{[t/x]p}{\_}{\inl{t}}{\_}{\inr{t}}$. This cannot be done in our system, as it would involve duplicating the variables in $t$. |
|
|
|
The computation rules for this construction are as follows. |
|
|
|
$$ \Tinstr \quad \Tnablainstr $$ |
|
$$ \Tinstrtest $$ |
|
$$ \Tetainstr $$ |
|
$$ \Tinstreq $$ |
|
|
|
We also introduce the following rule, which ensures that the sequential product $\andthen$ is commutative. |
|
|
|
\TTcomm |
|
|
|
\subsection{Scalar Constants} |
|
|
|
For any natural number $n \geq 2$, we have the following rules. |
|
|
|
$$ \Toneovern \; \Tntimesoneovern $$ |
|
$$ \Tdivide \; \Tboundmn $$ |
|
$$ \Trhdoneboundmn $$ |
|
$$ \Trhdtwoboundmnprime $$ |
|
|
|
These ensure that $1 / n$ is the unique scalar whose sum with itself $n$ times is $\top$. |
|
The term $b_{mn}$ is required to ensure that the term $1 / n \ovee \cdots \ovee 1 / n$ is well-typed. |
|
|
|
\subsection{Normalisation} |
|
|
|
Finally, we have these rules for normalisation. |
|
|
|
$$ \Tnorm \; \Tbetanorm $$ |
|
$$ \Tetanorm $$ |
|
|
|
These ensure that, if $t$ is a non-zero state in $A + 1$, then $\rho$ is the unique state in $A$ such that |
|
$t = \doo{\_}{t}{\return{\rho}}$. |
|
|
|
\section{Proof of Associativity} |
|
\label{section:associativity} |
|
|
|
\begin{theorem} |
|
If $\Gamma \vdash (r \ovee s) \ovee t : A + 1$, then $\Gamma \vdash r \ovee (s \ovee t) : A + 1$ and $\Gamma \vdash r \ovee (s \ovee t) = (r \ovee s) \ovee t : A + 1$. |
|
\end{theorem} |
|
|
|
(Note: this proof follows the proofs that $\ovee$ is associative in an effectus, found in \cite{Jacobs14} Proposition 12 or \cite{Cho} Proposition 13.) |
|
|
|
\begin{proof} |
|
Let $b$ be a bound for $r \ovee s$ and $c$ a bound for $(r \ovee s) \ovee t$, so that |
|
\begin{align} |
|
b \goesto \rhd_1 & = r \label{eq:axiom1} \\ |
|
b \goesto \rhd_2 & = s \label{eq:axiom2} \\ |
|
\doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}} & = r \ovee s \label{eq:axiom3} \\ |
|
c \goesto \rhd_1 & = r \ovee s \label{eq:axiom4} \\ |
|
c \goesto \rhd_2 & = t \label{eq:axiom5} \\ |
|
\doo{x}{c}{\return{\nabla(x)}} & = (r \ovee s) \ovee t \label{eq:axiom6} |
|
\end{align} |
|
|
|
Define $d : (A + 1) + 1$ by |
|
\[ d = \case c \of \inl{\inl{\_}} \mapsto \fail \mid \inl{\inr{x}} \mapsto \return{\inl{x}} \mid \inr{\_} \mapsto \return{\inr{*}} \] |
|
We wish to form the term $\inlr{b}{d}$. To do this, we must prove |
|
$\dom{b} = \ker{d}$. We do this by proving both are equal to $\dom{(r |
|
\ovee s)}$. |
|
|
|
We have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\dom{(r \ovee s)} & = \dom{(\doo{x}{b}{\return{\nabla(x)}})} = \doo{x}{b}{\dom{(\return{\nabla(x)})}} = \doo{x}{b}{\top} = \dom{b} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
and |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
\dom{(r \ovee s)} & = \dom{(\doo{x}{c}{\rhd_1(x)})} = \doo{x}{c}{\dom{(\rhd_1(x))}} = \doo{x}{c}{\inlprop{x}} \\ |
|
\ker{d} & = \case c \of \inl{\inl{\_}} \mapsto \top \mid \inl{\inr{\_}} \mapsto \bot \mid \inr{\_} \mapsto \bot \\ |
|
& = \doo{x}{c}{\inlprop{y}} \\ |
|
\therefore \dom{b} & = \ker{d} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
So, let $e = \inlr{b}{d} : (A + A) + (A + 1)$. We claim |
|
\begin{align} |
|
\label{eq:transitivity} |
|
c = \case e \of & \inl{\inl{a}} \mapsto \return{\inl{a}} \mid \inl{\inr{a}} \mapsto \return{\inl{a}} \mid \\ |
|
& \inr{\inl{a}} \mapsto \return{\inr{a}} \mid \inr{\inr{\_}} \mapsto \fail \nonumber |
|
\end{align} |
|
|
|
We prove the claim using\RJMprime. Writing $R$ for the right-hand side of (\ref{eq:transitivity}), we have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
(RHD \goesto \rhd_1) |
|
& = \doo{x}{\rhd_1(e)}{\return \nabla(x)} = \doo{x}{b}{\return \nabla(x)} = r \ovee s & \text{by (\ref{eq:axiom3})} \\ |
|
(c \goesto \rhd_1) & = r \ovee s & \text{by (\ref{eq:axiom4})} \\ |
|
(R \goesto \rhd_2) |
|
& = (\doo{x}{\rhd_2(e)}{x}) = (\doo{x}{d}{x}) = (c \goesto \rhd_2) |
|
\end{align*} |
|
and so (\ref{eq:transitivity}) follows by\RJMprime. |
|
|
|
Now that the claim (\ref{eq:transitivity}) is proved, we return to the main proof. Define $e' : (A + A) + 1$ by |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
e' = \case e \of & \inl{\inl{\_}} \mapsto \fail \mid \inl{\inr{a}} \mapsto \return{\inl{a}} \mid \\ |
|
& \inr{\inl{a}} \mapsto \return{\inr{a}} \mid \inr{\inr{\_}} \mapsto \fail |
|
\end{align*} |
|
We claim $e'$ is a bound for $s \ovee t$. We have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
(e' \goesto \rhd_1) |
|
& = \case e \of \inl{\inl{\_}} \mapsto \fail \mid \inl{\inr{a}} \mapsto \return{a} \mid \inr{\_} \mapsto \fail \\ |
|
& = (\rhd_1(e) \goesto \rhd_2) = (b \goesto \rhd_2) = s & \text{by (\ref{eq:axiom2})} \\ |
|
(e' \goesto \rhd_2) & = \case e \of \inl{\_} \mapsto \fail \mid \inr{\inl{a}} \mapsto \return{a} \mid \inr{\inr{\_}} \mapsto \fail \\ |
|
& = (\rhd_2(e) \goesto \rhd_1) = (d \goesto \rhd_1) \\ |
|
& = \case c \of \inl{\inl{\_}} \mapsto \fail \mid \inl{\inr{x}} \mapsto \return{x} \mid \inr{\_} \mapsto \fail \\ |
|
& = (c \goesto \rhd_2) = t & \text{by (\ref{eq:axiom5})} |
|
\end{align*} |
|
and so |
|
\begin{align} |
|
s \ovee t = & \doo{x}{e'}{\return{\nabla(x)}} \label{eq:soveet} \\ |
|
= & \case e \of \inl{\inl{\_}} \mapsto \fail \mid \inl{\inr{a}} \mapsto \return{a} \mid \nonumber \\ |
|
& \inr{\inl{a}} \mapsto \return{a} \mid \inr{\inr{\_}} \mapsto \fail \nonumber \\ |
|
\end{align} |
|
Now, define $e'' : (A + A) + 1$ by |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
e'' = \case e \of & \inl{\inl{a}} \mapsto \return{\inl{a}} \mid \inl{\inr{a}} \mapsto \return{\inr{a}} \\ |
|
& \inr{\inl{a}} \mapsto \return{\inr{a}} \mid \inr{\inr{\_}} \mapsto \fail |
|
\end{align*} |
|
We will prove that $e''$ is a bound for $r \ovee (s \ovee t)$. We have |
|
\begin{align*} |
|
(e'' \goesto \rhd_1) |
|
& = \case e \of \begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
\inl{\inl{a}} \mapsto \return{a} \\ |
|
\mid \inl{\inr{\_}} \mapsto \fail \\ |
|
\mid \inr{\inl{\_}} \mapsto \fail \\ |
|
\mid \inr{\inr{\_}} \mapsto \fail |
|
\end{array} \\ |
|
& = (\rhd_1(e) \goesto \rhd_1) = (b \goesto \rhd_1) = r & \text{by (\ref{eq:axiom1})} \\ |
|
(e'' \goesto \rhd_2) & = \case e \of \begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
\inl{\inl{\_}} \mapsto \fail \\ |
|
\mid \inl{\inr{a}} \mapsto \return{a} \\ |
|
\mid \inr{\inl{a}} \mapsto \return{a} \\ |
|
\mid \inr{\inr{\_}} \mapsto \fail |
|
\end{array} \\ |
|
& = s \ovee t & \text{by (\ref{eq:soveet})} \\ |
|
\doo{x}{e''}{\return{\nabla(x)}} & = \case e \of \begin{array}[t]{l} |
|
\inn_1(a) \mapsto \return{a} \\ |
|
\inn_2(a) \mapsto \return{a} \\ |
|
\inn_3(a) \mapsto \return{a} \\ |
|
\inn_4(\_) \mapsto \fail |
|
\end{array} \\ |
|
& = \mathsf{do}\ x \leftarrow \case e \of \begin{array}[t]{l} \inn_1(a) \mapsto \return{\inl{a}} \\ |
|
\inn_2(a) \mapsto \return{\inl{a}} \\ |
|
\inn_3(a) \mapsto \return{\inr{a}} \\ |
|
\inn_4(a) \mapsto \fail; \return{\nabla(x)} |
|
\end{array} \\ |
|
& = \doo{x}{c}{\return{\nabla(x)}} & \text{by (\ref{eq:transitivity})} \\ |
|
& = (r \ovee s) \ovee t |
|
\end{align*} |
|
Thus, $r \ovee (s \ovee t) = \doo{x}{e''}{\return{\nabla(x)}} = (r \ovee s) \ovee t$. |
|
\end{proof} |
|
|
|
\end{document} |
|
|