context
stringclasses
269 values
id_string
stringlengths
15
16
answers
sequencelengths
5
5
label
int64
0
4
question
stringlengths
34
417
In 1968 the United States Congress passed the Fair Housing Act, intended to counter discrimination based on race, color, religion, sex, or national origin in the sale and leasing of housing. In Havens Realty Corp. v. Coleman (1982), the United States Supreme Court attempted to define for the Fair Housing Act those persons who fulfill the "standing" requirement, which holds that only those parties having a personal stake in the outcome of a controversy are warranted to bring suit. Specifically, the Court was asked to decide whether a "tester" (an individual who, without an intent to rent or purchase a dwelling, poses as a renter or purchaser for the purpose of investigating rental/sales practices) has standing. The Court was also asked whether an organization has standing to sue on its own behalf. Havens Realty Corp. v. Coleman originated in a class action suit filed in a local court in 1979. The plaintiffs were two testers—a black woman named Sylvia Coleman and a white man named R. Kent Willis—and HOME, a nonprofit fair housing organization. The plaintiffs alleged that Havens Realty had engaged in discriminatory practices such as showing each tester apartments only in buildings occupied primarily by that person's racial group and telling the plaintiffs conflicting stories regarding the availability of individual apartments. The court dismissed the plaintiffs' claims, holding that they lacked the required standing under the act. According to the court, only a person who actually intended to rent would meet the act's requirements. The case eventually came before the United States Supreme Court, which held that Coleman and Willis, as testers, did have standing to sue. In deciding the case, the Court looked to the appropriate sections of the Fair Housing Act. Section 804(d) states that it is unlawful "to represent to any person because of race, color, religion, national origin, or sex that any dwelling is not available ... when such dwelling is in fact so available." The Court reasoned that the act "conferred on all persons a legal right to truthful information about available housing." The testers had therefore suffered the exact injury made unlawful by the statute and thus it is irrelevant whether the tester intended to either rent or buy the dwelling. The Court also had to resolve whether HOME had a right to sue as an organization. The Court held that, like the individual plaintiffs, HOME had to show a direct or threatened injury caused by the defendant. HOME averred that it had been frustrated by the defendant's discriminatory practices in its effort to assist equal access to housing, and had been forced to devote significant resources to identifying and counteracting the said discriminatory practices. The Court agreed that the injury alleged by HOME was concrete and decided that the organization did have standing in this case.
india3_2-RC_4_24
[ "A piece of legislation is described and then the effect of the legislation on certain social practices is analyzed.", "A certain legal case with relevance to a piece of legislation is broadly introduced and then the history and resolution of the case is presented in greater detail.", "A legal problem related to a piece of legislation is posed and then several ways of solving that problem are examined in some detail.", "An illegal practice is described and legal safeguards against that practice are outlined and advocated.", "Several stages in the history of a legal issue are narrated and then several social and legal implications of that issue are suggested." ]
1
Which one of the following best describes the organization of the passage?
In 1968 the United States Congress passed the Fair Housing Act, intended to counter discrimination based on race, color, religion, sex, or national origin in the sale and leasing of housing. In Havens Realty Corp. v. Coleman (1982), the United States Supreme Court attempted to define for the Fair Housing Act those persons who fulfill the "standing" requirement, which holds that only those parties having a personal stake in the outcome of a controversy are warranted to bring suit. Specifically, the Court was asked to decide whether a "tester" (an individual who, without an intent to rent or purchase a dwelling, poses as a renter or purchaser for the purpose of investigating rental/sales practices) has standing. The Court was also asked whether an organization has standing to sue on its own behalf. Havens Realty Corp. v. Coleman originated in a class action suit filed in a local court in 1979. The plaintiffs were two testers—a black woman named Sylvia Coleman and a white man named R. Kent Willis—and HOME, a nonprofit fair housing organization. The plaintiffs alleged that Havens Realty had engaged in discriminatory practices such as showing each tester apartments only in buildings occupied primarily by that person's racial group and telling the plaintiffs conflicting stories regarding the availability of individual apartments. The court dismissed the plaintiffs' claims, holding that they lacked the required standing under the act. According to the court, only a person who actually intended to rent would meet the act's requirements. The case eventually came before the United States Supreme Court, which held that Coleman and Willis, as testers, did have standing to sue. In deciding the case, the Court looked to the appropriate sections of the Fair Housing Act. Section 804(d) states that it is unlawful "to represent to any person because of race, color, religion, national origin, or sex that any dwelling is not available ... when such dwelling is in fact so available." The Court reasoned that the act "conferred on all persons a legal right to truthful information about available housing." The testers had therefore suffered the exact injury made unlawful by the statute and thus it is irrelevant whether the tester intended to either rent or buy the dwelling. The Court also had to resolve whether HOME had a right to sue as an organization. The Court held that, like the individual plaintiffs, HOME had to show a direct or threatened injury caused by the defendant. HOME averred that it had been frustrated by the defendant's discriminatory practices in its effort to assist equal access to housing, and had been forced to devote significant resources to identifying and counteracting the said discriminatory practices. The Court agreed that the injury alleged by HOME was concrete and decided that the organization did have standing in this case.
india3_2-RC_4_25
[ "the hiring and training of security experts to protect HOME's offices", "the hiring of attorneys to fight off frivolous lawsuits filed against HOME by realty companies", "the hiring and training of testers to investigate the rental practices of realty companies", "the expansion of HOME's mission to combat a wider variety of civil rights abuses", "the compensation of HOME employees for hazards to their health and safety caused by housing management organizations" ]
2
Which one of the following is most likely to be an example of the use of resources claimed by HOME to have been necessitated by the defendant?
In 1968 the United States Congress passed the Fair Housing Act, intended to counter discrimination based on race, color, religion, sex, or national origin in the sale and leasing of housing. In Havens Realty Corp. v. Coleman (1982), the United States Supreme Court attempted to define for the Fair Housing Act those persons who fulfill the "standing" requirement, which holds that only those parties having a personal stake in the outcome of a controversy are warranted to bring suit. Specifically, the Court was asked to decide whether a "tester" (an individual who, without an intent to rent or purchase a dwelling, poses as a renter or purchaser for the purpose of investigating rental/sales practices) has standing. The Court was also asked whether an organization has standing to sue on its own behalf. Havens Realty Corp. v. Coleman originated in a class action suit filed in a local court in 1979. The plaintiffs were two testers—a black woman named Sylvia Coleman and a white man named R. Kent Willis—and HOME, a nonprofit fair housing organization. The plaintiffs alleged that Havens Realty had engaged in discriminatory practices such as showing each tester apartments only in buildings occupied primarily by that person's racial group and telling the plaintiffs conflicting stories regarding the availability of individual apartments. The court dismissed the plaintiffs' claims, holding that they lacked the required standing under the act. According to the court, only a person who actually intended to rent would meet the act's requirements. The case eventually came before the United States Supreme Court, which held that Coleman and Willis, as testers, did have standing to sue. In deciding the case, the Court looked to the appropriate sections of the Fair Housing Act. Section 804(d) states that it is unlawful "to represent to any person because of race, color, religion, national origin, or sex that any dwelling is not available ... when such dwelling is in fact so available." The Court reasoned that the act "conferred on all persons a legal right to truthful information about available housing." The testers had therefore suffered the exact injury made unlawful by the statute and thus it is irrelevant whether the tester intended to either rent or buy the dwelling. The Court also had to resolve whether HOME had a right to sue as an organization. The Court held that, like the individual plaintiffs, HOME had to show a direct or threatened injury caused by the defendant. HOME averred that it had been frustrated by the defendant's discriminatory practices in its effort to assist equal access to housing, and had been forced to devote significant resources to identifying and counteracting the said discriminatory practices. The Court agreed that the injury alleged by HOME was concrete and decided that the organization did have standing in this case.
india3_2-RC_4_26
[ "refusal to rent housing to an individual or organization", "noncompliance with local regulations regarding housing practices", "the denial of accurate information about available housing", "rejection on insufficient grounds of a legitimate lawsuit", "facilitating the establishment of housing occupied primarily by a single racial group" ]
2
The "injury made unlawful by the statute" (lines 43-C44) refers to which one of the following?
The effects of the introduction of language upon human behavior are easily surmised. Language allowed rules for proper behavior to be communicated to children by precept and enforced among adults by gossip. Effective responses to different circumstances were usually guaranteed by traditional rules of behavior, and frictions were minimized because everyone knew what to expect of others in all ordinary situations. Such knowledge minimized quarrels, maximized effective cooperation, and allowed an increasingly complex division of labor among large numbers of individuals who spoke the same language. Language, however, also makes it easier to improve our behavioral responses when experience disappoints expectation. It helps us to move to and fro in imagined time, remembering useful things from the past and planning what to do in the future. Language is so powerful and pervasive in human lives that it seems right to say that our ancestors became fully human only when they began to use language and to act not on the basis of sensory stimuli alone but in accordance with plans and hopes and verbally formulated ideas about themselves and everything around them. Once the face-to-face verbal coordination of most everyday behavior had been achieved, major subsequent landmarks of human history depended principally on improvements in communication that allowed messages to travel farther and more accurately across time and distance than spoken words ordinarily do. Networks of messages, delivered in verbal form, supplemented by gesture, and sometimes solemnized by ritual, created and sustained local human communities. Eventually an increasing number of these primary communities came to be incorporated into larger communication networks centered in cities and sustaining what we call civilizations. As compared to primary communities, civilizations were tumultuous and unstable social structures, but they were also more powerful, exerting control over the natural environment and coordinating the actions of larger numbers of persons partly by obedience to commands, and partly by negotiated, more or less voluntary, exchanges of goods and services. Ever since the first civilizations arose, civilized social complexity has tended to spread, until in our own time almost all humankind is caught up in a single global system, furiously exchanging messages and upsetting traditional ways of life almost everywhere. The details of how small roving bands with only sporadic outside contacts evolved into today's unified world cannot be fully known. However, an imaginative historian can hope to discern major landmarks in the civilizing process by focusing on breakthroughs in communication that altered the range and flow of messages among human populations, thereby accelerating the propagation of novelties and meeting human needs and wants better than before.
india5_3-RC_1_1
[ "The pace of modern communication has upset traditional ways of life throughout the world.", "Our ancestors became fully human only when they began to use language to move to and fro in imagined time.", "The power of human communication will inevitably overcome traditional ways of life and create a single global system.", "The details of the history of language cannot be fully known, but the behavioral effects of the introduction of language are easily surmised.", "The development of human civilization was fundamentally dependent on language and communication." ]
4
Which one of the following most accurately expresses the main point of the passage?
The effects of the introduction of language upon human behavior are easily surmised. Language allowed rules for proper behavior to be communicated to children by precept and enforced among adults by gossip. Effective responses to different circumstances were usually guaranteed by traditional rules of behavior, and frictions were minimized because everyone knew what to expect of others in all ordinary situations. Such knowledge minimized quarrels, maximized effective cooperation, and allowed an increasingly complex division of labor among large numbers of individuals who spoke the same language. Language, however, also makes it easier to improve our behavioral responses when experience disappoints expectation. It helps us to move to and fro in imagined time, remembering useful things from the past and planning what to do in the future. Language is so powerful and pervasive in human lives that it seems right to say that our ancestors became fully human only when they began to use language and to act not on the basis of sensory stimuli alone but in accordance with plans and hopes and verbally formulated ideas about themselves and everything around them. Once the face-to-face verbal coordination of most everyday behavior had been achieved, major subsequent landmarks of human history depended principally on improvements in communication that allowed messages to travel farther and more accurately across time and distance than spoken words ordinarily do. Networks of messages, delivered in verbal form, supplemented by gesture, and sometimes solemnized by ritual, created and sustained local human communities. Eventually an increasing number of these primary communities came to be incorporated into larger communication networks centered in cities and sustaining what we call civilizations. As compared to primary communities, civilizations were tumultuous and unstable social structures, but they were also more powerful, exerting control over the natural environment and coordinating the actions of larger numbers of persons partly by obedience to commands, and partly by negotiated, more or less voluntary, exchanges of goods and services. Ever since the first civilizations arose, civilized social complexity has tended to spread, until in our own time almost all humankind is caught up in a single global system, furiously exchanging messages and upsetting traditional ways of life almost everywhere. The details of how small roving bands with only sporadic outside contacts evolved into today's unified world cannot be fully known. However, an imaginative historian can hope to discern major landmarks in the civilizing process by focusing on breakthroughs in communication that altered the range and flow of messages among human populations, thereby accelerating the propagation of novelties and meeting human needs and wants better than before.
india5_3-RC_1_2
[ "gossip", "ritual", "police power", "negotiated transactions", "division of labor" ]
3
According to the passage, one way in which urban civilizations coordinate the behavior of large numbers of people more powerfully than primary communities can is through
The effects of the introduction of language upon human behavior are easily surmised. Language allowed rules for proper behavior to be communicated to children by precept and enforced among adults by gossip. Effective responses to different circumstances were usually guaranteed by traditional rules of behavior, and frictions were minimized because everyone knew what to expect of others in all ordinary situations. Such knowledge minimized quarrels, maximized effective cooperation, and allowed an increasingly complex division of labor among large numbers of individuals who spoke the same language. Language, however, also makes it easier to improve our behavioral responses when experience disappoints expectation. It helps us to move to and fro in imagined time, remembering useful things from the past and planning what to do in the future. Language is so powerful and pervasive in human lives that it seems right to say that our ancestors became fully human only when they began to use language and to act not on the basis of sensory stimuli alone but in accordance with plans and hopes and verbally formulated ideas about themselves and everything around them. Once the face-to-face verbal coordination of most everyday behavior had been achieved, major subsequent landmarks of human history depended principally on improvements in communication that allowed messages to travel farther and more accurately across time and distance than spoken words ordinarily do. Networks of messages, delivered in verbal form, supplemented by gesture, and sometimes solemnized by ritual, created and sustained local human communities. Eventually an increasing number of these primary communities came to be incorporated into larger communication networks centered in cities and sustaining what we call civilizations. As compared to primary communities, civilizations were tumultuous and unstable social structures, but they were also more powerful, exerting control over the natural environment and coordinating the actions of larger numbers of persons partly by obedience to commands, and partly by negotiated, more or less voluntary, exchanges of goods and services. Ever since the first civilizations arose, civilized social complexity has tended to spread, until in our own time almost all humankind is caught up in a single global system, furiously exchanging messages and upsetting traditional ways of life almost everywhere. The details of how small roving bands with only sporadic outside contacts evolved into today's unified world cannot be fully known. However, an imaginative historian can hope to discern major landmarks in the civilizing process by focusing on breakthroughs in communication that altered the range and flow of messages among human populations, thereby accelerating the propagation of novelties and meeting human needs and wants better than before.
india5_3-RC_1_3
[ "contrary-to-fact situations", "time prior to historical records", "the time of legends and myths", "mental representations of the past and future", "occasions when experience disappoints expectation" ]
3
By "imagined time" (line 16) the author most likely means
The effects of the introduction of language upon human behavior are easily surmised. Language allowed rules for proper behavior to be communicated to children by precept and enforced among adults by gossip. Effective responses to different circumstances were usually guaranteed by traditional rules of behavior, and frictions were minimized because everyone knew what to expect of others in all ordinary situations. Such knowledge minimized quarrels, maximized effective cooperation, and allowed an increasingly complex division of labor among large numbers of individuals who spoke the same language. Language, however, also makes it easier to improve our behavioral responses when experience disappoints expectation. It helps us to move to and fro in imagined time, remembering useful things from the past and planning what to do in the future. Language is so powerful and pervasive in human lives that it seems right to say that our ancestors became fully human only when they began to use language and to act not on the basis of sensory stimuli alone but in accordance with plans and hopes and verbally formulated ideas about themselves and everything around them. Once the face-to-face verbal coordination of most everyday behavior had been achieved, major subsequent landmarks of human history depended principally on improvements in communication that allowed messages to travel farther and more accurately across time and distance than spoken words ordinarily do. Networks of messages, delivered in verbal form, supplemented by gesture, and sometimes solemnized by ritual, created and sustained local human communities. Eventually an increasing number of these primary communities came to be incorporated into larger communication networks centered in cities and sustaining what we call civilizations. As compared to primary communities, civilizations were tumultuous and unstable social structures, but they were also more powerful, exerting control over the natural environment and coordinating the actions of larger numbers of persons partly by obedience to commands, and partly by negotiated, more or less voluntary, exchanges of goods and services. Ever since the first civilizations arose, civilized social complexity has tended to spread, until in our own time almost all humankind is caught up in a single global system, furiously exchanging messages and upsetting traditional ways of life almost everywhere. The details of how small roving bands with only sporadic outside contacts evolved into today's unified world cannot be fully known. However, an imaginative historian can hope to discern major landmarks in the civilizing process by focusing on breakthroughs in communication that altered the range and flow of messages among human populations, thereby accelerating the propagation of novelties and meeting human needs and wants better than before.
india5_3-RC_1_4
[ "the development of ornamental calligraphy", "the development of the alphabet", "the invention of the printing press", "the development of the Internet", "the invention of radio" ]
0
All of the following meet the author's standard for identifying major landmarks of human history EXCEPT:
The effects of the introduction of language upon human behavior are easily surmised. Language allowed rules for proper behavior to be communicated to children by precept and enforced among adults by gossip. Effective responses to different circumstances were usually guaranteed by traditional rules of behavior, and frictions were minimized because everyone knew what to expect of others in all ordinary situations. Such knowledge minimized quarrels, maximized effective cooperation, and allowed an increasingly complex division of labor among large numbers of individuals who spoke the same language. Language, however, also makes it easier to improve our behavioral responses when experience disappoints expectation. It helps us to move to and fro in imagined time, remembering useful things from the past and planning what to do in the future. Language is so powerful and pervasive in human lives that it seems right to say that our ancestors became fully human only when they began to use language and to act not on the basis of sensory stimuli alone but in accordance with plans and hopes and verbally formulated ideas about themselves and everything around them. Once the face-to-face verbal coordination of most everyday behavior had been achieved, major subsequent landmarks of human history depended principally on improvements in communication that allowed messages to travel farther and more accurately across time and distance than spoken words ordinarily do. Networks of messages, delivered in verbal form, supplemented by gesture, and sometimes solemnized by ritual, created and sustained local human communities. Eventually an increasing number of these primary communities came to be incorporated into larger communication networks centered in cities and sustaining what we call civilizations. As compared to primary communities, civilizations were tumultuous and unstable social structures, but they were also more powerful, exerting control over the natural environment and coordinating the actions of larger numbers of persons partly by obedience to commands, and partly by negotiated, more or less voluntary, exchanges of goods and services. Ever since the first civilizations arose, civilized social complexity has tended to spread, until in our own time almost all humankind is caught up in a single global system, furiously exchanging messages and upsetting traditional ways of life almost everywhere. The details of how small roving bands with only sporadic outside contacts evolved into today's unified world cannot be fully known. However, an imaginative historian can hope to discern major landmarks in the civilizing process by focusing on breakthroughs in communication that altered the range and flow of messages among human populations, thereby accelerating the propagation of novelties and meeting human needs and wants better than before.
india5_3-RC_1_5
[ "making possible the planning and organization of human endeavors", "enabling societies to exert control over the natural environment", "fostering the development of literature and the arts", "both supporting and upsetting traditional ways of life", "helping humans better achieve their needs and wants" ]
2
Each of the following is mentioned in the passage as something that the use of language does EXCEPT:
The effects of the introduction of language upon human behavior are easily surmised. Language allowed rules for proper behavior to be communicated to children by precept and enforced among adults by gossip. Effective responses to different circumstances were usually guaranteed by traditional rules of behavior, and frictions were minimized because everyone knew what to expect of others in all ordinary situations. Such knowledge minimized quarrels, maximized effective cooperation, and allowed an increasingly complex division of labor among large numbers of individuals who spoke the same language. Language, however, also makes it easier to improve our behavioral responses when experience disappoints expectation. It helps us to move to and fro in imagined time, remembering useful things from the past and planning what to do in the future. Language is so powerful and pervasive in human lives that it seems right to say that our ancestors became fully human only when they began to use language and to act not on the basis of sensory stimuli alone but in accordance with plans and hopes and verbally formulated ideas about themselves and everything around them. Once the face-to-face verbal coordination of most everyday behavior had been achieved, major subsequent landmarks of human history depended principally on improvements in communication that allowed messages to travel farther and more accurately across time and distance than spoken words ordinarily do. Networks of messages, delivered in verbal form, supplemented by gesture, and sometimes solemnized by ritual, created and sustained local human communities. Eventually an increasing number of these primary communities came to be incorporated into larger communication networks centered in cities and sustaining what we call civilizations. As compared to primary communities, civilizations were tumultuous and unstable social structures, but they were also more powerful, exerting control over the natural environment and coordinating the actions of larger numbers of persons partly by obedience to commands, and partly by negotiated, more or less voluntary, exchanges of goods and services. Ever since the first civilizations arose, civilized social complexity has tended to spread, until in our own time almost all humankind is caught up in a single global system, furiously exchanging messages and upsetting traditional ways of life almost everywhere. The details of how small roving bands with only sporadic outside contacts evolved into today's unified world cannot be fully known. However, an imaginative historian can hope to discern major landmarks in the civilizing process by focusing on breakthroughs in communication that altered the range and flow of messages among human populations, thereby accelerating the propagation of novelties and meeting human needs and wants better than before.
india5_3-RC_1_6
[ "the coordination of people's everyday behavior", "a single global language", "control over nature", "urbanization", "social complexity" ]
1
The passage suggests that all of the following are elements of civilization EXCEPT:
The effects of the introduction of language upon human behavior are easily surmised. Language allowed rules for proper behavior to be communicated to children by precept and enforced among adults by gossip. Effective responses to different circumstances were usually guaranteed by traditional rules of behavior, and frictions were minimized because everyone knew what to expect of others in all ordinary situations. Such knowledge minimized quarrels, maximized effective cooperation, and allowed an increasingly complex division of labor among large numbers of individuals who spoke the same language. Language, however, also makes it easier to improve our behavioral responses when experience disappoints expectation. It helps us to move to and fro in imagined time, remembering useful things from the past and planning what to do in the future. Language is so powerful and pervasive in human lives that it seems right to say that our ancestors became fully human only when they began to use language and to act not on the basis of sensory stimuli alone but in accordance with plans and hopes and verbally formulated ideas about themselves and everything around them. Once the face-to-face verbal coordination of most everyday behavior had been achieved, major subsequent landmarks of human history depended principally on improvements in communication that allowed messages to travel farther and more accurately across time and distance than spoken words ordinarily do. Networks of messages, delivered in verbal form, supplemented by gesture, and sometimes solemnized by ritual, created and sustained local human communities. Eventually an increasing number of these primary communities came to be incorporated into larger communication networks centered in cities and sustaining what we call civilizations. As compared to primary communities, civilizations were tumultuous and unstable social structures, but they were also more powerful, exerting control over the natural environment and coordinating the actions of larger numbers of persons partly by obedience to commands, and partly by negotiated, more or less voluntary, exchanges of goods and services. Ever since the first civilizations arose, civilized social complexity has tended to spread, until in our own time almost all humankind is caught up in a single global system, furiously exchanging messages and upsetting traditional ways of life almost everywhere. The details of how small roving bands with only sporadic outside contacts evolved into today's unified world cannot be fully known. However, an imaginative historian can hope to discern major landmarks in the civilizing process by focusing on breakthroughs in communication that altered the range and flow of messages among human populations, thereby accelerating the propagation of novelties and meeting human needs and wants better than before.
india5_3-RC_1_7
[ "local groups dependent on direct verbal communication", "any groups of individuals speaking the same language", "voluntary associations for the exchange of goods and services", "the cities at the core of particular urban civilizations", "the first urban civilizations to develop" ]
0
By the term "primary communities" (line 36) the author probably means
Passage A Though daguerreotypy and photography are obviously more closely related than daguerreotypy and painting, and though we do speak of them together, it is not mere pedantry to insist that the daguerreotype is not a photograph. The daguerreotype, like any art form, demands its own critical vocabulary, its own way of being seen and appreciated. For one thing, it had many inherent restrictions that would not have affected the painter or photographer. The daguerreotypist had to arrange a composition that would retain its authority when reduced to about 3 inches (7.62 cm) square, the most common plate size, and had to understand the nature of light and shadow on this highly polished silver plate at various distances from a lens. The length of the exposure in the daguerreotype necessitated the sitter's being quite still for some minutes, though this was eventually reduced to many seconds. Metal clamps were invented to hold the sitter's pose, and children were often tied in place; a stiff unnatural pose is one of the most common defects found in daguerreotypes, the blurred child another. The daguerreotypist had to rely on lighting, posing, composition, and a personal rapport with the sitter in order to overcome these potential problems. Still, those who witnessed the beauty of the form lamented its passing. Passage B In March 1839, Samuel Morse wrote that Daguerre's own daguerreotypes were "Rembrandt perfected." He understood what Daguerre had wrought, which was a beautiful leap, not of science, but of technology; here, for the first time, was art immaculately born of chemistry. The beauty of the daguerreotype was a compound of awe and delight. Other writers expressed their astonishment in terms that were quite uniform: "enchanting," "exquisitely perfect," "a piece of fairy work." Such fancy rhetoric is the expression of the unique thrill of seeing a brilliant and novel art form for the first time. And yet a great deal of this original pleasure remains for us today. Here in my hand is a daguerreotype. It is not famous, and it cannot be reproduced. The plate, as if it were a jewel, is enclosed in a case stamped with scrollwork. The image inside is the size of one's palm. Unlike any but the smallest paintings, it is an intimate art, meant only for one person at a time. Unfolding the case, one has on the left a rectangle of purple velvet, bordered with embossed gold leaves. The right-hand panel, seen straight on, is baffling: here is a small mirror in which one sees only part of one's face, superimposed onto three ghostlike shapes, graynegative faces with blank eyes atop the shape of some sort of clothing. But turn the mirror slightly and three full characters blaze out at you—a woman, man, and child. They are not merely an amalgam of mercury and silver on a copper surface, but a trace of life frozen forever in the sharpest detail of light and shadow.
india5_3-RC_2_8
[ "Roughly how much did it cost to produce a daguerreotype?", "What prevented the widespread use of daguerreotypes for purposes other than portraiture?", "Roughly how large was the typical daguerreotype?", "When did photography on paper supersede daguerreotypy?", "What were some words used by viewers upon experiencing daguerreotypes for the first time?" ]
2
Each passage provides information sufficient to answer which one of the following questions?
Passage A Though daguerreotypy and photography are obviously more closely related than daguerreotypy and painting, and though we do speak of them together, it is not mere pedantry to insist that the daguerreotype is not a photograph. The daguerreotype, like any art form, demands its own critical vocabulary, its own way of being seen and appreciated. For one thing, it had many inherent restrictions that would not have affected the painter or photographer. The daguerreotypist had to arrange a composition that would retain its authority when reduced to about 3 inches (7.62 cm) square, the most common plate size, and had to understand the nature of light and shadow on this highly polished silver plate at various distances from a lens. The length of the exposure in the daguerreotype necessitated the sitter's being quite still for some minutes, though this was eventually reduced to many seconds. Metal clamps were invented to hold the sitter's pose, and children were often tied in place; a stiff unnatural pose is one of the most common defects found in daguerreotypes, the blurred child another. The daguerreotypist had to rely on lighting, posing, composition, and a personal rapport with the sitter in order to overcome these potential problems. Still, those who witnessed the beauty of the form lamented its passing. Passage B In March 1839, Samuel Morse wrote that Daguerre's own daguerreotypes were "Rembrandt perfected." He understood what Daguerre had wrought, which was a beautiful leap, not of science, but of technology; here, for the first time, was art immaculately born of chemistry. The beauty of the daguerreotype was a compound of awe and delight. Other writers expressed their astonishment in terms that were quite uniform: "enchanting," "exquisitely perfect," "a piece of fairy work." Such fancy rhetoric is the expression of the unique thrill of seeing a brilliant and novel art form for the first time. And yet a great deal of this original pleasure remains for us today. Here in my hand is a daguerreotype. It is not famous, and it cannot be reproduced. The plate, as if it were a jewel, is enclosed in a case stamped with scrollwork. The image inside is the size of one's palm. Unlike any but the smallest paintings, it is an intimate art, meant only for one person at a time. Unfolding the case, one has on the left a rectangle of purple velvet, bordered with embossed gold leaves. The right-hand panel, seen straight on, is baffling: here is a small mirror in which one sees only part of one's face, superimposed onto three ghostlike shapes, graynegative faces with blank eyes atop the shape of some sort of clothing. But turn the mirror slightly and three full characters blaze out at you—a woman, man, and child. They are not merely an amalgam of mercury and silver on a copper surface, but a trace of life frozen forever in the sharpest detail of light and shadow.
india5_3-RC_2_9
[ "the daguerreotype is not a photograph", "the daguerreotype is an exquisite art form", "the daguerreotype is the most precise form of pictorial art", "daguerreotypes are commonplace and usually imperfect", "daguerreotypes are complex, elaborate, and expensive" ]
4
Passage A, but not passage B, argues that
Passage A Though daguerreotypy and photography are obviously more closely related than daguerreotypy and painting, and though we do speak of them together, it is not mere pedantry to insist that the daguerreotype is not a photograph. The daguerreotype, like any art form, demands its own critical vocabulary, its own way of being seen and appreciated. For one thing, it had many inherent restrictions that would not have affected the painter or photographer. The daguerreotypist had to arrange a composition that would retain its authority when reduced to about 3 inches (7.62 cm) square, the most common plate size, and had to understand the nature of light and shadow on this highly polished silver plate at various distances from a lens. The length of the exposure in the daguerreotype necessitated the sitter's being quite still for some minutes, though this was eventually reduced to many seconds. Metal clamps were invented to hold the sitter's pose, and children were often tied in place; a stiff unnatural pose is one of the most common defects found in daguerreotypes, the blurred child another. The daguerreotypist had to rely on lighting, posing, composition, and a personal rapport with the sitter in order to overcome these potential problems. Still, those who witnessed the beauty of the form lamented its passing. Passage B In March 1839, Samuel Morse wrote that Daguerre's own daguerreotypes were "Rembrandt perfected." He understood what Daguerre had wrought, which was a beautiful leap, not of science, but of technology; here, for the first time, was art immaculately born of chemistry. The beauty of the daguerreotype was a compound of awe and delight. Other writers expressed their astonishment in terms that were quite uniform: "enchanting," "exquisitely perfect," "a piece of fairy work." Such fancy rhetoric is the expression of the unique thrill of seeing a brilliant and novel art form for the first time. And yet a great deal of this original pleasure remains for us today. Here in my hand is a daguerreotype. It is not famous, and it cannot be reproduced. The plate, as if it were a jewel, is enclosed in a case stamped with scrollwork. The image inside is the size of one's palm. Unlike any but the smallest paintings, it is an intimate art, meant only for one person at a time. Unfolding the case, one has on the left a rectangle of purple velvet, bordered with embossed gold leaves. The right-hand panel, seen straight on, is baffling: here is a small mirror in which one sees only part of one's face, superimposed onto three ghostlike shapes, graynegative faces with blank eyes atop the shape of some sort of clothing. But turn the mirror slightly and three full characters blaze out at you—a woman, man, and child. They are not merely an amalgam of mercury and silver on a copper surface, but a trace of life frozen forever in the sharpest detail of light and shadow.
india5_3-RC_2_10
[ "Passage B was written as a direct response to this statement.", "Passage B provides information that could be used to undermine this statement.", "Passage B presents an attitude suggesting disagreement with this statement.", "Passage B provides an example that illustrates this statement.", "Passage B provides the historical context necessary to understand this statement." ]
3
Which one of the following most accurately describes how passage B relates to the statement in passage A that the daguerreotype demands its own way of being seen and appreciated?
Passage A Though daguerreotypy and photography are obviously more closely related than daguerreotypy and painting, and though we do speak of them together, it is not mere pedantry to insist that the daguerreotype is not a photograph. The daguerreotype, like any art form, demands its own critical vocabulary, its own way of being seen and appreciated. For one thing, it had many inherent restrictions that would not have affected the painter or photographer. The daguerreotypist had to arrange a composition that would retain its authority when reduced to about 3 inches (7.62 cm) square, the most common plate size, and had to understand the nature of light and shadow on this highly polished silver plate at various distances from a lens. The length of the exposure in the daguerreotype necessitated the sitter's being quite still for some minutes, though this was eventually reduced to many seconds. Metal clamps were invented to hold the sitter's pose, and children were often tied in place; a stiff unnatural pose is one of the most common defects found in daguerreotypes, the blurred child another. The daguerreotypist had to rely on lighting, posing, composition, and a personal rapport with the sitter in order to overcome these potential problems. Still, those who witnessed the beauty of the form lamented its passing. Passage B In March 1839, Samuel Morse wrote that Daguerre's own daguerreotypes were "Rembrandt perfected." He understood what Daguerre had wrought, which was a beautiful leap, not of science, but of technology; here, for the first time, was art immaculately born of chemistry. The beauty of the daguerreotype was a compound of awe and delight. Other writers expressed their astonishment in terms that were quite uniform: "enchanting," "exquisitely perfect," "a piece of fairy work." Such fancy rhetoric is the expression of the unique thrill of seeing a brilliant and novel art form for the first time. And yet a great deal of this original pleasure remains for us today. Here in my hand is a daguerreotype. It is not famous, and it cannot be reproduced. The plate, as if it were a jewel, is enclosed in a case stamped with scrollwork. The image inside is the size of one's palm. Unlike any but the smallest paintings, it is an intimate art, meant only for one person at a time. Unfolding the case, one has on the left a rectangle of purple velvet, bordered with embossed gold leaves. The right-hand panel, seen straight on, is baffling: here is a small mirror in which one sees only part of one's face, superimposed onto three ghostlike shapes, graynegative faces with blank eyes atop the shape of some sort of clothing. But turn the mirror slightly and three full characters blaze out at you—a woman, man, and child. They are not merely an amalgam of mercury and silver on a copper surface, but a trace of life frozen forever in the sharpest detail of light and shadow.
india5_3-RC_2_11
[ "Lecture 1 includes an evaluation of a particular pantomime performance; lecture 2 includes an argument regarding the ways in which pantomime may have influenced other art forms.", "Lecture 1 includes an argument that pantomime is truly an art form; lecture 2 includes a classification of different types of pantomime performances.", "Lecture 1 includes a discussion of how pantomime developed out of other related performing arts; lecture 2 includes information about how pantomime has been discussed in literature", "Lecture 1 includes a conjecture about why pantomime is no longer performed very often; lecture 2 includes an argument that pantomimists rarely achieve high levels of skill in their art.", "Lecture 1 includes information about the difficulties that pantomimists face in practicing their art; lecture 2 includes a description of a particular pantomime performance." ]
4
Which one of the following pairs of lectures is most analogous to passage A and passage B in terms of how these two passages stand in relation to each other?
Passage A Though daguerreotypy and photography are obviously more closely related than daguerreotypy and painting, and though we do speak of them together, it is not mere pedantry to insist that the daguerreotype is not a photograph. The daguerreotype, like any art form, demands its own critical vocabulary, its own way of being seen and appreciated. For one thing, it had many inherent restrictions that would not have affected the painter or photographer. The daguerreotypist had to arrange a composition that would retain its authority when reduced to about 3 inches (7.62 cm) square, the most common plate size, and had to understand the nature of light and shadow on this highly polished silver plate at various distances from a lens. The length of the exposure in the daguerreotype necessitated the sitter's being quite still for some minutes, though this was eventually reduced to many seconds. Metal clamps were invented to hold the sitter's pose, and children were often tied in place; a stiff unnatural pose is one of the most common defects found in daguerreotypes, the blurred child another. The daguerreotypist had to rely on lighting, posing, composition, and a personal rapport with the sitter in order to overcome these potential problems. Still, those who witnessed the beauty of the form lamented its passing. Passage B In March 1839, Samuel Morse wrote that Daguerre's own daguerreotypes were "Rembrandt perfected." He understood what Daguerre had wrought, which was a beautiful leap, not of science, but of technology; here, for the first time, was art immaculately born of chemistry. The beauty of the daguerreotype was a compound of awe and delight. Other writers expressed their astonishment in terms that were quite uniform: "enchanting," "exquisitely perfect," "a piece of fairy work." Such fancy rhetoric is the expression of the unique thrill of seeing a brilliant and novel art form for the first time. And yet a great deal of this original pleasure remains for us today. Here in my hand is a daguerreotype. It is not famous, and it cannot be reproduced. The plate, as if it were a jewel, is enclosed in a case stamped with scrollwork. The image inside is the size of one's palm. Unlike any but the smallest paintings, it is an intimate art, meant only for one person at a time. Unfolding the case, one has on the left a rectangle of purple velvet, bordered with embossed gold leaves. The right-hand panel, seen straight on, is baffling: here is a small mirror in which one sees only part of one's face, superimposed onto three ghostlike shapes, graynegative faces with blank eyes atop the shape of some sort of clothing. But turn the mirror slightly and three full characters blaze out at you—a woman, man, and child. They are not merely an amalgam of mercury and silver on a copper surface, but a trace of life frozen forever in the sharpest detail of light and shadow.
india5_3-RC_2_12
[ "The daguerreotype should not be considered a type of photograph.", "There is no compelling reason for daguerreotypy not to be practiced today.", "Though there are striking exceptions, most daguerreotypes are aesthetically unremarkable.", "Daguerreotypy was not useful for creating landscapes.", "The demise of daguerreotypy represents a significant aesthetic loss." ]
4
It can be inferred that the authors of both passages believe which one of the following?
A commission appointed by the government of the Canadian province of Ontario offered recommendations to assist judges and lawyers in recognizing language or actions that may cause some participants to feel excluded and therefore disenfranchised during court proceedings. One area of focus was the use of courtroom interpreters for people who are not fluent speakers of English or French. Although the Supreme Court of Canada had given explicit direction in 1994 concerning an accused person's right to interpreter assistance, many participants in the Canadian legal system still had concerns about the use of interpreters. In response to these concerns, the commission emphasized that all those involved in proceedings must understand the role of the interpreter. With this objective in mind, the commission stressed that all parties involved in legal proceedings must be made aware of the nature of interpretation. In order for judges and lawyers to make effective use of an interpreter in the courtroom, they must understand when an interpreter is necessary, appreciate the time required for interpretation, and develop an awareness of the nature of culturally informed interpretation as contrasted with mere literal interpretation. For example, uninformed judges and lawyers often expect interpreters to translate what is said word for word. In practice, however, this type of translation frequently fails to convey culturally specific meaning accurately and effectively, and is sometimes simply impossible because each language is structurally unique. One interpreter interviewed by the commission explained that while one language may use a word or short phrase to express a particular idea, others have no similarly concise equivalent, requiring the interpreter to use long descriptions of ideas in one language that can be expressed briefly in another. Many interpreters find that in the courtroom, uninformed judges and lawyers may suspect an interpreter of embellishing if the interpreter takes a long time to explain a point. Canadian law insists on impartiality in interpretation services. Parties to proceedings, relatives and friends of such parties, or persons otherwise close to the events giving rise to an accusation are ordinarily viewed as inappropriate interpreters in criminal proceedings. However, because some linguistic-minority communities, such as aboriginal communities, are small, in practice, court participants often know the court interpreter. In many cases, prior acquaintance does not matter and may be unavoidable. But to ensure fair proceedings, a defendant, victim, or other witness must fully understand the interpreter's role and be able to object to an interpreter whom he or she does not trust to be impartial. To these ends, the commission recommended that judges make clear in open court that the interpreter is a neutral professional, employed by the court to translate what is being said; that a defendant or any witness may object to a potentially biased interpreter; and that a defendant or an interpreter may request clarification at any time.
india5_3-RC_3_13
[ "According to a commission in Ontario, the accuracy of courtroom translations can never really be guaranteed, and so judicial fairness can only be ensured by assigning this role to professional interpreters.", "A commission in Ontario has found that impartiality in interpretation services is not fully achievable in certain kinds of communities, so it is vital that all participants in courtroom proceedings held in such communities be able to reject interpreters they believe to be biased.", "An Ontario commission has advised that in order to ensure fairness in court proceedings, the role of the courtroom interpreter must be clearly defined and all courtroom participants must understand the nature of that role.", "An Ontario commission recommends that because existing judicial guidelines for the use of courtroom interpreters do not adequately ensure the impartiality guaranteed by Canadian law for members of small linguistic communities, these guidelines must be amplified so as to accommodate the needs of such communities.", "An Ontario commission has determined that ensuring fair and equitable treatment for all citizens in all judicial proceedings is impossible unless interpreters are neutral professionals with no bias for or against any of the people involved in the case." ]
2
Which one of the following most accurately states the main point of the passage?
A commission appointed by the government of the Canadian province of Ontario offered recommendations to assist judges and lawyers in recognizing language or actions that may cause some participants to feel excluded and therefore disenfranchised during court proceedings. One area of focus was the use of courtroom interpreters for people who are not fluent speakers of English or French. Although the Supreme Court of Canada had given explicit direction in 1994 concerning an accused person's right to interpreter assistance, many participants in the Canadian legal system still had concerns about the use of interpreters. In response to these concerns, the commission emphasized that all those involved in proceedings must understand the role of the interpreter. With this objective in mind, the commission stressed that all parties involved in legal proceedings must be made aware of the nature of interpretation. In order for judges and lawyers to make effective use of an interpreter in the courtroom, they must understand when an interpreter is necessary, appreciate the time required for interpretation, and develop an awareness of the nature of culturally informed interpretation as contrasted with mere literal interpretation. For example, uninformed judges and lawyers often expect interpreters to translate what is said word for word. In practice, however, this type of translation frequently fails to convey culturally specific meaning accurately and effectively, and is sometimes simply impossible because each language is structurally unique. One interpreter interviewed by the commission explained that while one language may use a word or short phrase to express a particular idea, others have no similarly concise equivalent, requiring the interpreter to use long descriptions of ideas in one language that can be expressed briefly in another. Many interpreters find that in the courtroom, uninformed judges and lawyers may suspect an interpreter of embellishing if the interpreter takes a long time to explain a point. Canadian law insists on impartiality in interpretation services. Parties to proceedings, relatives and friends of such parties, or persons otherwise close to the events giving rise to an accusation are ordinarily viewed as inappropriate interpreters in criminal proceedings. However, because some linguistic-minority communities, such as aboriginal communities, are small, in practice, court participants often know the court interpreter. In many cases, prior acquaintance does not matter and may be unavoidable. But to ensure fair proceedings, a defendant, victim, or other witness must fully understand the interpreter's role and be able to object to an interpreter whom he or she does not trust to be impartial. To these ends, the commission recommended that judges make clear in open court that the interpreter is a neutral professional, employed by the court to translate what is being said; that a defendant or any witness may object to a potentially biased interpreter; and that a defendant or an interpreter may request clarification at any time.
india5_3-RC_3_14
[ "is a limitation of which some lawyers and judges are unaware", "is less noticeable to interpreters than to other participants in legal proceedings", "makes some courtroom participants feel disenfranchised", "makes fair and impartial trials impossible to achieve", "results in needlessly lengthy embellishments on the part of interpreters" ]
0
According to the passage, the inadequacy of word-for-word translations in legal proceedings involving interpreters
A commission appointed by the government of the Canadian province of Ontario offered recommendations to assist judges and lawyers in recognizing language or actions that may cause some participants to feel excluded and therefore disenfranchised during court proceedings. One area of focus was the use of courtroom interpreters for people who are not fluent speakers of English or French. Although the Supreme Court of Canada had given explicit direction in 1994 concerning an accused person's right to interpreter assistance, many participants in the Canadian legal system still had concerns about the use of interpreters. In response to these concerns, the commission emphasized that all those involved in proceedings must understand the role of the interpreter. With this objective in mind, the commission stressed that all parties involved in legal proceedings must be made aware of the nature of interpretation. In order for judges and lawyers to make effective use of an interpreter in the courtroom, they must understand when an interpreter is necessary, appreciate the time required for interpretation, and develop an awareness of the nature of culturally informed interpretation as contrasted with mere literal interpretation. For example, uninformed judges and lawyers often expect interpreters to translate what is said word for word. In practice, however, this type of translation frequently fails to convey culturally specific meaning accurately and effectively, and is sometimes simply impossible because each language is structurally unique. One interpreter interviewed by the commission explained that while one language may use a word or short phrase to express a particular idea, others have no similarly concise equivalent, requiring the interpreter to use long descriptions of ideas in one language that can be expressed briefly in another. Many interpreters find that in the courtroom, uninformed judges and lawyers may suspect an interpreter of embellishing if the interpreter takes a long time to explain a point. Canadian law insists on impartiality in interpretation services. Parties to proceedings, relatives and friends of such parties, or persons otherwise close to the events giving rise to an accusation are ordinarily viewed as inappropriate interpreters in criminal proceedings. However, because some linguistic-minority communities, such as aboriginal communities, are small, in practice, court participants often know the court interpreter. In many cases, prior acquaintance does not matter and may be unavoidable. But to ensure fair proceedings, a defendant, victim, or other witness must fully understand the interpreter's role and be able to object to an interpreter whom he or she does not trust to be impartial. To these ends, the commission recommended that judges make clear in open court that the interpreter is a neutral professional, employed by the court to translate what is being said; that a defendant or any witness may object to a potentially biased interpreter; and that a defendant or an interpreter may request clarification at any time.
india5_3-RC_3_15
[ "who tend to elicit the suspicion that they are embellishing rather than merely interpreting", "without previous experience or training as courtroom translators", "who have little understanding of the Canadian legal system", "who are non-native speakers of the language they interpret", "with a lesser likelihood of being impartial than is ordinarily regarded as desirable" ]
4
By "inappropriate interpreters" (lines 46-C47) the author most likely is referring to interpreters
A commission appointed by the government of the Canadian province of Ontario offered recommendations to assist judges and lawyers in recognizing language or actions that may cause some participants to feel excluded and therefore disenfranchised during court proceedings. One area of focus was the use of courtroom interpreters for people who are not fluent speakers of English or French. Although the Supreme Court of Canada had given explicit direction in 1994 concerning an accused person's right to interpreter assistance, many participants in the Canadian legal system still had concerns about the use of interpreters. In response to these concerns, the commission emphasized that all those involved in proceedings must understand the role of the interpreter. With this objective in mind, the commission stressed that all parties involved in legal proceedings must be made aware of the nature of interpretation. In order for judges and lawyers to make effective use of an interpreter in the courtroom, they must understand when an interpreter is necessary, appreciate the time required for interpretation, and develop an awareness of the nature of culturally informed interpretation as contrasted with mere literal interpretation. For example, uninformed judges and lawyers often expect interpreters to translate what is said word for word. In practice, however, this type of translation frequently fails to convey culturally specific meaning accurately and effectively, and is sometimes simply impossible because each language is structurally unique. One interpreter interviewed by the commission explained that while one language may use a word or short phrase to express a particular idea, others have no similarly concise equivalent, requiring the interpreter to use long descriptions of ideas in one language that can be expressed briefly in another. Many interpreters find that in the courtroom, uninformed judges and lawyers may suspect an interpreter of embellishing if the interpreter takes a long time to explain a point. Canadian law insists on impartiality in interpretation services. Parties to proceedings, relatives and friends of such parties, or persons otherwise close to the events giving rise to an accusation are ordinarily viewed as inappropriate interpreters in criminal proceedings. However, because some linguistic-minority communities, such as aboriginal communities, are small, in practice, court participants often know the court interpreter. In many cases, prior acquaintance does not matter and may be unavoidable. But to ensure fair proceedings, a defendant, victim, or other witness must fully understand the interpreter's role and be able to object to an interpreter whom he or she does not trust to be impartial. To these ends, the commission recommended that judges make clear in open court that the interpreter is a neutral professional, employed by the court to translate what is being said; that a defendant or any witness may object to a potentially biased interpreter; and that a defendant or an interpreter may request clarification at any time.
india5_3-RC_3_16
[ "In court cases involving members of small linguistic communities, certain factors that are conducive to accurate and effective interpretation also make complete impartiality of the interpreter more difficult to ensure.", "The recognition of the need for impartiality in interpretation services was the primary reason for the formation of the Ontario commission.", "Because skill in providing a truly accurate translation is dependent on a sensitive awareness of the original speaker's culture, the goals of impartiality and accuracy in translation are irreconcilable.", "The need for impartiality in translation services is more likely to be satisfied by an alteration of the attitudes and beliefs of judges and lawyers than by an alteration of courtroom procedure.", "Only if witnesses and defendants are free to appoint their own courtroom interpreters can the need for impartiality in interpretation services be satisfied." ]
0
With which one of the following statements concerning impartiality in interpretation services would the author be most likely to agree?
A commission appointed by the government of the Canadian province of Ontario offered recommendations to assist judges and lawyers in recognizing language or actions that may cause some participants to feel excluded and therefore disenfranchised during court proceedings. One area of focus was the use of courtroom interpreters for people who are not fluent speakers of English or French. Although the Supreme Court of Canada had given explicit direction in 1994 concerning an accused person's right to interpreter assistance, many participants in the Canadian legal system still had concerns about the use of interpreters. In response to these concerns, the commission emphasized that all those involved in proceedings must understand the role of the interpreter. With this objective in mind, the commission stressed that all parties involved in legal proceedings must be made aware of the nature of interpretation. In order for judges and lawyers to make effective use of an interpreter in the courtroom, they must understand when an interpreter is necessary, appreciate the time required for interpretation, and develop an awareness of the nature of culturally informed interpretation as contrasted with mere literal interpretation. For example, uninformed judges and lawyers often expect interpreters to translate what is said word for word. In practice, however, this type of translation frequently fails to convey culturally specific meaning accurately and effectively, and is sometimes simply impossible because each language is structurally unique. One interpreter interviewed by the commission explained that while one language may use a word or short phrase to express a particular idea, others have no similarly concise equivalent, requiring the interpreter to use long descriptions of ideas in one language that can be expressed briefly in another. Many interpreters find that in the courtroom, uninformed judges and lawyers may suspect an interpreter of embellishing if the interpreter takes a long time to explain a point. Canadian law insists on impartiality in interpretation services. Parties to proceedings, relatives and friends of such parties, or persons otherwise close to the events giving rise to an accusation are ordinarily viewed as inappropriate interpreters in criminal proceedings. However, because some linguistic-minority communities, such as aboriginal communities, are small, in practice, court participants often know the court interpreter. In many cases, prior acquaintance does not matter and may be unavoidable. But to ensure fair proceedings, a defendant, victim, or other witness must fully understand the interpreter's role and be able to object to an interpreter whom he or she does not trust to be impartial. To these ends, the commission recommended that judges make clear in open court that the interpreter is a neutral professional, employed by the court to translate what is being said; that a defendant or any witness may object to a potentially biased interpreter; and that a defendant or an interpreter may request clarification at any time.
india5_3-RC_3_17
[ "is more of a problem in civil cases than in criminal cases", "constitutes evidence that the Ontario commission's recommendations are inadequate", "does not always affect the fairness of the proceedings negatively", "is inconsistent with standards of impartiality demanded by Canadian law", "often leads interpreters to embellish the testimony they are translating" ]
2
According to the passage, the situation in which a courtroom interpreter is acquainted with other participants in courtroom proceedings
A commission appointed by the government of the Canadian province of Ontario offered recommendations to assist judges and lawyers in recognizing language or actions that may cause some participants to feel excluded and therefore disenfranchised during court proceedings. One area of focus was the use of courtroom interpreters for people who are not fluent speakers of English or French. Although the Supreme Court of Canada had given explicit direction in 1994 concerning an accused person's right to interpreter assistance, many participants in the Canadian legal system still had concerns about the use of interpreters. In response to these concerns, the commission emphasized that all those involved in proceedings must understand the role of the interpreter. With this objective in mind, the commission stressed that all parties involved in legal proceedings must be made aware of the nature of interpretation. In order for judges and lawyers to make effective use of an interpreter in the courtroom, they must understand when an interpreter is necessary, appreciate the time required for interpretation, and develop an awareness of the nature of culturally informed interpretation as contrasted with mere literal interpretation. For example, uninformed judges and lawyers often expect interpreters to translate what is said word for word. In practice, however, this type of translation frequently fails to convey culturally specific meaning accurately and effectively, and is sometimes simply impossible because each language is structurally unique. One interpreter interviewed by the commission explained that while one language may use a word or short phrase to express a particular idea, others have no similarly concise equivalent, requiring the interpreter to use long descriptions of ideas in one language that can be expressed briefly in another. Many interpreters find that in the courtroom, uninformed judges and lawyers may suspect an interpreter of embellishing if the interpreter takes a long time to explain a point. Canadian law insists on impartiality in interpretation services. Parties to proceedings, relatives and friends of such parties, or persons otherwise close to the events giving rise to an accusation are ordinarily viewed as inappropriate interpreters in criminal proceedings. However, because some linguistic-minority communities, such as aboriginal communities, are small, in practice, court participants often know the court interpreter. In many cases, prior acquaintance does not matter and may be unavoidable. But to ensure fair proceedings, a defendant, victim, or other witness must fully understand the interpreter's role and be able to object to an interpreter whom he or she does not trust to be impartial. To these ends, the commission recommended that judges make clear in open court that the interpreter is a neutral professional, employed by the court to translate what is being said; that a defendant or any witness may object to a potentially biased interpreter; and that a defendant or an interpreter may request clarification at any time.
india5_3-RC_3_18
[ "indicate why some judges and lawyers may harbor doubts about the accuracy of certain courtroom translations", "emphasize why translations in a judicial context cannot convey the culturally specific meaning of the testimony being interpreted", "stress the lack of awareness of cultures and languages other than English and French on the part of many judges and lawyers", "illustrate why it is often difficult to find a competent interpreter", "explain why an interpreter's translation of courtroom testimony may be considerably briefer than the original testimony" ]
0
The author mentions the fact that ideas expressed concisely in one language may take much longer to express in another language (lines 32-C38) primarily in order to
A commission appointed by the government of the Canadian province of Ontario offered recommendations to assist judges and lawyers in recognizing language or actions that may cause some participants to feel excluded and therefore disenfranchised during court proceedings. One area of focus was the use of courtroom interpreters for people who are not fluent speakers of English or French. Although the Supreme Court of Canada had given explicit direction in 1994 concerning an accused person's right to interpreter assistance, many participants in the Canadian legal system still had concerns about the use of interpreters. In response to these concerns, the commission emphasized that all those involved in proceedings must understand the role of the interpreter. With this objective in mind, the commission stressed that all parties involved in legal proceedings must be made aware of the nature of interpretation. In order for judges and lawyers to make effective use of an interpreter in the courtroom, they must understand when an interpreter is necessary, appreciate the time required for interpretation, and develop an awareness of the nature of culturally informed interpretation as contrasted with mere literal interpretation. For example, uninformed judges and lawyers often expect interpreters to translate what is said word for word. In practice, however, this type of translation frequently fails to convey culturally specific meaning accurately and effectively, and is sometimes simply impossible because each language is structurally unique. One interpreter interviewed by the commission explained that while one language may use a word or short phrase to express a particular idea, others have no similarly concise equivalent, requiring the interpreter to use long descriptions of ideas in one language that can be expressed briefly in another. Many interpreters find that in the courtroom, uninformed judges and lawyers may suspect an interpreter of embellishing if the interpreter takes a long time to explain a point. Canadian law insists on impartiality in interpretation services. Parties to proceedings, relatives and friends of such parties, or persons otherwise close to the events giving rise to an accusation are ordinarily viewed as inappropriate interpreters in criminal proceedings. However, because some linguistic-minority communities, such as aboriginal communities, are small, in practice, court participants often know the court interpreter. In many cases, prior acquaintance does not matter and may be unavoidable. But to ensure fair proceedings, a defendant, victim, or other witness must fully understand the interpreter's role and be able to object to an interpreter whom he or she does not trust to be impartial. To these ends, the commission recommended that judges make clear in open court that the interpreter is a neutral professional, employed by the court to translate what is being said; that a defendant or any witness may object to a potentially biased interpreter; and that a defendant or an interpreter may request clarification at any time.
india5_3-RC_3_19
[ "The importance of this role is underestimated by most judges and lawyers.", "A precise understanding of this role is only likely to be useful to people in small communities.", "This role can never be occupied by someone who is personally acquainted with the participants in courtroom proceedings.", "The person playing this role is most likely to achieve his or her legal purpose if everyone involved understands the nature of the role.", "This role cannot be satisfactorily filled by someone who is unaware of the Ontario commission's definition of the role." ]
3
The passage most strongly suggests which one of the following about the role of courtroom interpreters?
For biologists, the term "eye" describes any lightsensitive organ consisting of more than one cell. Although most animals have eyes, eye structures vary widely. The compound eyes of insects and other arthropods, for example, have an architecture strikingly different from the single-lens eyes of vertebrates and mollusks. Until recently, most biologists believed that all the different kinds of eyes evolved independently from as many as forty ancestral prototypes, and not from a single ancestral prototype eye. Traditional means of tracking the evolutionary development of eyes included examinations of internal eye structures, which tended to support the multiple origin theory despite some anomalies such as the resemblance between mammals' eyes and the eyes of the nautilus mollusk—animals that are not closely related. Proponents of the multiple origin theory dismissed such examples as textbook cases of evolutionary convergence: the idea that even strikingly different prototype eyes could evolve into kinds of eyes remarkably similar to each other. In support of their theory, these biologists point to the fact that different species inhabiting the same environment frequently have very different eye structures from one another. This lack of correlation between eye structures and physical environments has provided what is perhaps the strongest support for the multiple origin theory. Adherents of the theory argue that if eyes originated from a single ancestral prototype, then there should be similarity in the patterns of eye evolution in species that evolved under the same environmental conditions. The inability of biologists to identify such evolutionary patterns is arguably the primary reason for this theory's widespread acceptance. In 1993, however, a crucial link was discovered: a control gene that activates the many genes needed for complete eye formation in fruit flies. Analogues to this gene have since been identified in many organisms, including earthworms, mice, and humans, and are expected to exist in all eye-bearing organisms. Researchers discovered that inserting the control gene present in mice into fruit flies results in the formation of functional fruit fly eyes. This suggests that the control genes in mice and in fruit flies are interchangeable and hence evolved from a single, common ancestral gene. The same may be true of all of these control genes, which would argue convincingly against the multiple origin theory and call for a reevaluation of the evidence that seemed to support the theory. For example, the lack of correlation between eye structures and physical environments may have resulted from the advantage bestowed by eyes. The survival value of sight is perhaps so great that even variations in eyes that might be less than optimal for some individuals in a particular environment are sufficiently advantageous that they allow the individuals to survive and propagate the variation, thus facilitating the proliferation of variations in eyes even in the absence of an environmental difference.
india5_3-RC_4_20
[ "the lack of fossil evidence of a common ancestor for all eye-bearing species", "the lack of correlation between eye structures and physical environments", "the lack of correlation between physical environments and control genes for eye development", "the resemblance between the eyes of mammals and the nautilus mollusk, species that are not closely related", "the obvious evolutionary advantage bestowed by some kinds of eyes as compared with others" ]
1
The author mentions that biologists accepted which one of the following as evidence for the theory that eyes evolved from multiple origins?
For biologists, the term "eye" describes any lightsensitive organ consisting of more than one cell. Although most animals have eyes, eye structures vary widely. The compound eyes of insects and other arthropods, for example, have an architecture strikingly different from the single-lens eyes of vertebrates and mollusks. Until recently, most biologists believed that all the different kinds of eyes evolved independently from as many as forty ancestral prototypes, and not from a single ancestral prototype eye. Traditional means of tracking the evolutionary development of eyes included examinations of internal eye structures, which tended to support the multiple origin theory despite some anomalies such as the resemblance between mammals' eyes and the eyes of the nautilus mollusk—animals that are not closely related. Proponents of the multiple origin theory dismissed such examples as textbook cases of evolutionary convergence: the idea that even strikingly different prototype eyes could evolve into kinds of eyes remarkably similar to each other. In support of their theory, these biologists point to the fact that different species inhabiting the same environment frequently have very different eye structures from one another. This lack of correlation between eye structures and physical environments has provided what is perhaps the strongest support for the multiple origin theory. Adherents of the theory argue that if eyes originated from a single ancestral prototype, then there should be similarity in the patterns of eye evolution in species that evolved under the same environmental conditions. The inability of biologists to identify such evolutionary patterns is arguably the primary reason for this theory's widespread acceptance. In 1993, however, a crucial link was discovered: a control gene that activates the many genes needed for complete eye formation in fruit flies. Analogues to this gene have since been identified in many organisms, including earthworms, mice, and humans, and are expected to exist in all eye-bearing organisms. Researchers discovered that inserting the control gene present in mice into fruit flies results in the formation of functional fruit fly eyes. This suggests that the control genes in mice and in fruit flies are interchangeable and hence evolved from a single, common ancestral gene. The same may be true of all of these control genes, which would argue convincingly against the multiple origin theory and call for a reevaluation of the evidence that seemed to support the theory. For example, the lack of correlation between eye structures and physical environments may have resulted from the advantage bestowed by eyes. The survival value of sight is perhaps so great that even variations in eyes that might be less than optimal for some individuals in a particular environment are sufficiently advantageous that they allow the individuals to survive and propagate the variation, thus facilitating the proliferation of variations in eyes even in the absence of an environmental difference.
india5_3-RC_4_21
[ "distinguish between two theories and explain the theoretical basis for each of those theories", "argue that a particular discovery provides insufficient evidence for the rejection of a particular widely accepted theory", "explain how a particular piece of evidence challenges a particular theory that has been widely accepted", "provide grounds for a reexamination of the assumptions underlying a recent challenge to a commonly held theory", "suggest some practical implications of a particular theoretical finding that conflicts with a particular commonly held theory" ]
2
The primary purpose of the passage is to
For biologists, the term "eye" describes any lightsensitive organ consisting of more than one cell. Although most animals have eyes, eye structures vary widely. The compound eyes of insects and other arthropods, for example, have an architecture strikingly different from the single-lens eyes of vertebrates and mollusks. Until recently, most biologists believed that all the different kinds of eyes evolved independently from as many as forty ancestral prototypes, and not from a single ancestral prototype eye. Traditional means of tracking the evolutionary development of eyes included examinations of internal eye structures, which tended to support the multiple origin theory despite some anomalies such as the resemblance between mammals' eyes and the eyes of the nautilus mollusk—animals that are not closely related. Proponents of the multiple origin theory dismissed such examples as textbook cases of evolutionary convergence: the idea that even strikingly different prototype eyes could evolve into kinds of eyes remarkably similar to each other. In support of their theory, these biologists point to the fact that different species inhabiting the same environment frequently have very different eye structures from one another. This lack of correlation between eye structures and physical environments has provided what is perhaps the strongest support for the multiple origin theory. Adherents of the theory argue that if eyes originated from a single ancestral prototype, then there should be similarity in the patterns of eye evolution in species that evolved under the same environmental conditions. The inability of biologists to identify such evolutionary patterns is arguably the primary reason for this theory's widespread acceptance. In 1993, however, a crucial link was discovered: a control gene that activates the many genes needed for complete eye formation in fruit flies. Analogues to this gene have since been identified in many organisms, including earthworms, mice, and humans, and are expected to exist in all eye-bearing organisms. Researchers discovered that inserting the control gene present in mice into fruit flies results in the formation of functional fruit fly eyes. This suggests that the control genes in mice and in fruit flies are interchangeable and hence evolved from a single, common ancestral gene. The same may be true of all of these control genes, which would argue convincingly against the multiple origin theory and call for a reevaluation of the evidence that seemed to support the theory. For example, the lack of correlation between eye structures and physical environments may have resulted from the advantage bestowed by eyes. The survival value of sight is perhaps so great that even variations in eyes that might be less than optimal for some individuals in a particular environment are sufficiently advantageous that they allow the individuals to survive and propagate the variation, thus facilitating the proliferation of variations in eyes even in the absence of an environmental difference.
india5_3-RC_4_22
[ "concern that biologists have accepted the single origin theory without carefully evaluating the assumptions it is based on", "concern that biologists may have prematurely abandoned the multiple origin theory", "confidence that the discovery will imminently lead to the complete abandonment of the multiple origin theory", "optimism that its discovery might foster a reevaluation of the assumptions biologists utilize when researching evolution in general", "anticipation that the discovery will foster further efforts to determine whether all varieties of eyes have evolved from a single ancestral prototype eye" ]
4
The passage provides the strongest support for the inference that the author's attitude regarding the discovery of a control gene responsible for activating eye formation in fruit flies can be accurately described as
For biologists, the term "eye" describes any lightsensitive organ consisting of more than one cell. Although most animals have eyes, eye structures vary widely. The compound eyes of insects and other arthropods, for example, have an architecture strikingly different from the single-lens eyes of vertebrates and mollusks. Until recently, most biologists believed that all the different kinds of eyes evolved independently from as many as forty ancestral prototypes, and not from a single ancestral prototype eye. Traditional means of tracking the evolutionary development of eyes included examinations of internal eye structures, which tended to support the multiple origin theory despite some anomalies such as the resemblance between mammals' eyes and the eyes of the nautilus mollusk—animals that are not closely related. Proponents of the multiple origin theory dismissed such examples as textbook cases of evolutionary convergence: the idea that even strikingly different prototype eyes could evolve into kinds of eyes remarkably similar to each other. In support of their theory, these biologists point to the fact that different species inhabiting the same environment frequently have very different eye structures from one another. This lack of correlation between eye structures and physical environments has provided what is perhaps the strongest support for the multiple origin theory. Adherents of the theory argue that if eyes originated from a single ancestral prototype, then there should be similarity in the patterns of eye evolution in species that evolved under the same environmental conditions. The inability of biologists to identify such evolutionary patterns is arguably the primary reason for this theory's widespread acceptance. In 1993, however, a crucial link was discovered: a control gene that activates the many genes needed for complete eye formation in fruit flies. Analogues to this gene have since been identified in many organisms, including earthworms, mice, and humans, and are expected to exist in all eye-bearing organisms. Researchers discovered that inserting the control gene present in mice into fruit flies results in the formation of functional fruit fly eyes. This suggests that the control genes in mice and in fruit flies are interchangeable and hence evolved from a single, common ancestral gene. The same may be true of all of these control genes, which would argue convincingly against the multiple origin theory and call for a reevaluation of the evidence that seemed to support the theory. For example, the lack of correlation between eye structures and physical environments may have resulted from the advantage bestowed by eyes. The survival value of sight is perhaps so great that even variations in eyes that might be less than optimal for some individuals in a particular environment are sufficiently advantageous that they allow the individuals to survive and propagate the variation, thus facilitating the proliferation of variations in eyes even in the absence of an environmental difference.
india5_3-RC_4_23
[ "determine how each species' characteristic eye structure will differ from that of other species", "probably occur in all animals but only activate eye formation in just a few", "may be interchangeable among mice, fruit flies, and humans without causing members of those species to develop eyes that are atypical for their species", "regulate specific aspects of eye evolution in certain species, suggesting that those species need not be assumed to stem from a common ancestor", "activate eye formation in species including humans and mice, and this helps explain how evolutionary convergence occurs" ]
2
ccording to the author, control genes have been found that
For biologists, the term "eye" describes any lightsensitive organ consisting of more than one cell. Although most animals have eyes, eye structures vary widely. The compound eyes of insects and other arthropods, for example, have an architecture strikingly different from the single-lens eyes of vertebrates and mollusks. Until recently, most biologists believed that all the different kinds of eyes evolved independently from as many as forty ancestral prototypes, and not from a single ancestral prototype eye. Traditional means of tracking the evolutionary development of eyes included examinations of internal eye structures, which tended to support the multiple origin theory despite some anomalies such as the resemblance between mammals' eyes and the eyes of the nautilus mollusk—animals that are not closely related. Proponents of the multiple origin theory dismissed such examples as textbook cases of evolutionary convergence: the idea that even strikingly different prototype eyes could evolve into kinds of eyes remarkably similar to each other. In support of their theory, these biologists point to the fact that different species inhabiting the same environment frequently have very different eye structures from one another. This lack of correlation between eye structures and physical environments has provided what is perhaps the strongest support for the multiple origin theory. Adherents of the theory argue that if eyes originated from a single ancestral prototype, then there should be similarity in the patterns of eye evolution in species that evolved under the same environmental conditions. The inability of biologists to identify such evolutionary patterns is arguably the primary reason for this theory's widespread acceptance. In 1993, however, a crucial link was discovered: a control gene that activates the many genes needed for complete eye formation in fruit flies. Analogues to this gene have since been identified in many organisms, including earthworms, mice, and humans, and are expected to exist in all eye-bearing organisms. Researchers discovered that inserting the control gene present in mice into fruit flies results in the formation of functional fruit fly eyes. This suggests that the control genes in mice and in fruit flies are interchangeable and hence evolved from a single, common ancestral gene. The same may be true of all of these control genes, which would argue convincingly against the multiple origin theory and call for a reevaluation of the evidence that seemed to support the theory. For example, the lack of correlation between eye structures and physical environments may have resulted from the advantage bestowed by eyes. The survival value of sight is perhaps so great that even variations in eyes that might be less than optimal for some individuals in a particular environment are sufficiently advantageous that they allow the individuals to survive and propagate the variation, thus facilitating the proliferation of variations in eyes even in the absence of an environmental difference.
india5_3-RC_4_24
[ "Traditional Italian pizza is very similar in form and ingredients to a traditional Southern French food, which, like Italian pizza, has its origins in earlier Mediterranean cultures.", "Mexican traditional cuisine uses round, flat tortillas made from corn or wheat, and traditional cuisines of India use tortilla-like flat, round bread made from wheat flour, even though the Mexican and Indian cultures have no traditional connection with each other.", "Yogurt is superficially unlike cheese, although both are made almost entirely of milk and both are traditional ingredients in Middle Eastern and European cuisines.", "Mozzarella cheese is traditionally made from cow's milk in the United States, even though Italian mozzarella, which is the original model for the US version and has almost the same flavor, color, and texture, is traditionally made from buffalo's milk.", "The culinary use of corn—a vegetable that was originally available only to various Native American cultures—has spread to many cultures throughout the world, some of which are very distant and different from one another." ]
1
Proponents of the multiple origin theory would likely regard the relationship between the development of human eyes and the development of the eyes of the nautilus mollusk as most analogous to which one of the following?