text
stringlengths 0
923k
|
---|
Two Conceptions of Subjective Experience1
Justin Sytsma and Edouard Machery
ABSTRACT: Do philosophers and ordinary people conceive of subjective experience in the
same way? In this article, we argue that they do not and that the philosophical concept of
phenomenal consciousness does not coincide with the folk conception. We first offer
experimental support for the hypothesis that philosophers and ordinary people conceive of
subjective experience in markedly different ways. We then explore experimentally the folk
conception, proposing that for the folk, subjective experience is closely linked to valence. We
conclude by considering the implications of our findings for a central issue in the philosophy of
mind, the hard problem of consciousness.
Our first goal in this article is to examine whether ordinary people (viz. people without
training in philosophy or in consciousness studies) and philosophers conceive of subjective
experience in a similar way. Philosophers see subjective experiences as including such diverse
mental states as seeing red and feeling pain, treating them as having something in common,
namely that they are phenomenal—viz. that they share the second-order property that there is
“something it is like” (Nagel 1974) to be in these mental states. We provide suggestive evidence
that the folk, by contrast, do not conceive of subjective experience in this way. Our second goal
is to explore this folk conception for its own sake. We successively consider two accounts. We
first examine whether the folk treat perceptual states differently from bodily sensations or felt
emotions, taking the latter, but not the former, to be subjectively experienced. This might be
phrased in terms of the folk distinguishing between those states that tell us about the world
1
The first author did most of the work on this article. We would like to thank Dave Chalmers, David Danks, Tony
Jack, Joshua Knobe, Jonathan Livengood, Shaun Nichols, Peter Pagin, and Philip Robbins for their comments on
previous versions of this article. We also would like to thank Eric Schwitzgebel for his reply to a talk based on this
article at annual meeting of the Society for Philosophy and Psychology in 2008. Thanks also to the audiences in
Santa Cruz, Stockholm, Lund, and Gothenburg.
1
outside our skin (the products of the external senses) and those states that tell us about ourselves
from the skin in (the products of the internal senses). Rejecting this first account, we argue for an
alternative hypothesis: For the folk, subjective experience is tightly linked to valence.2 As a
result, people distinguish between states that essentially have a valence (such as feeling pain or
anger), those that do not have a valence (such as seeing red), and those that have a valence as
well as a prominent perceptual component (such as smelling banana).
While the folk conception of subjective experience is fascinating in its own right, it is
also of substantial philosophical importance. Our third goal in this article is to investigate the
philosophical implications of the divergence between ordinary people’s and philosophers’
conceptions of subjective experience. We argue, first, that our findings cast doubt on the claim
that the philosophical concept of phenomenal consciousness is shared by the folk or is a part of
folk psychology. Second, if our analysis of the folk conception is correct, then it raises serious
doubt about whether there is a hard problem of consciousness to be solved. The hard problem is
typically justified on the grounds that phenomenal consciousness is “the most central and
manifest aspect of our mental lives” (Chalmers 1995, 207). Our findings challenge this
justification: If the folk do not recognize that states such as seeing red and feeling pain are
phenomenal, then it is hardly credible that phenomenal consciousness is central and manifest.
This does not necessarily mean that there is no hard problem of consciousness, but it does call on
philosophers to provide a better justification for the reality of this problem.
2
Throughout we will use the term “valence” as follows: mental states have a valence if and only if they have a
hedonic value for the subject. That is, mental states have a valence if and only if they are pleasurable (they then have
a positive valence) or disagreeable (they then have a negative valence). Not all mental states have a valence, and
valenced states are more or less pleasurable or disagreeable. Typically, but perhaps not necessarily, disagreeable
mental states motivate people to act as to discontinue these, while pleasurable mental states motivate people to act so
as to perpetuate them.
2
We begin in Section 1 by briefly characterizing the philosophical conception of
subjective experience. In Section 2, we discuss the shortcomings of recent work in psychology,
philosophy, and experimental philosophy that investigates folk intuitions related to
consciousness. We conclude that this work is poorly designed to investigate whether
philosophers and ordinary people conceive of subjective experience similarly. In Sections 3, 4,
and 5, we aim to rectify this situation by examining people’s judgments about perceptual
experiences, bodily sensations, and felt emotions. In Section 6, we examine the philosophical
implications of our findings about the folk conception of subjective experience.
1. The Philosophical Conception of Subjective Experience
For most contemporary philosophers, subjective experience is characterized by its
phenomenality. There is, of course, much disagreement in the literature about what phenomenal
consciousness is. Still, according to one standard line (and the one we will be interested in),
mental states such as seeing red, feeling pain, hearing a C#, feeling anger, etc., all share the
second-order property that it is like something to be in these states. What it is like to be in pain is
distinct from what it is like to see red, but for both states, there is something it is like to be in
them. “Phenomenal consciousness” refers to this second-order property. As Ned Block puts it
(1995, 227): “Phenomenal consciousness is experience; what makes a state phenomenally
conscious is that there is something ‘it is like’ (Nagel 1974) to be in that state.” Similarly, John
Searle (1994, xi) holds that it is one of the “simple and obvious truths about the mind” that “[w]e
all have inner subjective qualitative states of consciousness.” Finally, Chalmers writes eloquently
(1995, 201):
The really hard problem of consciousness is the problem of experience. When we think
and perceive, there is a whir of information-processing, but there is also a subjective
3
aspect…. This subjective aspect is experience. When we see, for example, we experience
visual sensations: the felt quality of redness, the experience of dark and light, the quality
of depth in a visual field. Other experiences go with perception in different modalities:
the sound of a clarinet, the smell of mothballs. Then there are bodily sensations… mental
images… the felt quality of emotion…. What unites all of these states is that there is
something it is like to be in them. All of them are states of experience. (10; emphasis
added)
Phenomenally conscious mental states are typically divided into a number of types in the
philosophical literature. The most common type is perceptual experiences such as seeing,
hearing, or smelling, followed closely by bodily sensations such as pain and hunger (Levin
1998). Felt emotions such as fear, rage, joy and felt moods such as elation, depression, boredom
are typically added to this list (Tye 2003).3 These four types of phenomenal states (perceptual
experiences, bodily sensations, felt emotions, and felt moods) are typically contrasted with nonphenomenal intentional states like belief and desire.
Perceptual experiences of colors and bodily sensations of pains are easily the most
frequently discussed in the philosophical and scientific literature. For example, Francis Crick
describes qualia (the phenomenal properties of mental states) in terms of “the redness of red or
the painfulness of pain” (1995, 9fn). This strategy is typical—the concepts of phenomenal
consciousness and qualia are generally drawn out through examples; as David Papineau puts it,
“the idea is best introduced by examples rather than definitions” (2002, 13; see also Block 1995).
And the first examples are typically colors and pains; as Janet Levin opens her Routledge
Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry on “Qualia”:
The term… [is] most commonly understood to mean the qualitative, phenomenal or ‘felt’
properties of our mental states, such as the throbbing pain of my current headache, or the
peculiar blue of the afterimage I am experiencing now. Though it seems undeniable that
3
While we follow convention in referring to mental states like seeing red and smelling banana as perceptual
experiences, it is worth noting that some hold that mental states here classified as bodily sensations, felt emotions, or
felt moods are also perceptual (e.g., Prinz 2006). We wish to thank an anonymous referee for Philosophical Studies
for pointing this out.
4
at least some of our mental states have qualia, their existence raises a number of
philosophical problems. (§0)
Given the illustrative centrality of perceptual experiences and bodily sensations to
articulating the concept of phenomenal consciousness, if the folk and philosophers conceive
similarly of subjective experience, we should expect them to treat perceptual experiences and
bodily sensations analogously in these regards. In particular, we should expect the folk to deny
that an entity, be it a simple organism, a simple robot, or a zombie, is not phenomenally
conscious, that lacks phenomenal consciousness can see red just as readily as they deny that it
can be in pain. Daniel Dennett conforms with this expectation, for example, when he states that
the robot Cog4 “cannot yet see or hear or feel at all” (1996, 16).
2. Previous Research related to the Folk’s Conception of Subjective Experience
In this second section, we critically discuss three main lines of experimental research related to
the folk conception of subjective experience. While this work is intriguing in its own right, we
argue that none of the studies is adequate for determining whether the philosophical concept of
phenomenal consciousness really coincides with what Block (2004, 785) has called the
“common-sense conception of subjective experience.”
2.1 Experience and Agency
Heather Gray, Kurt Gray, and Daniel Wegner’s fascinating study on “Dimensions of Mind
Perception” (2007) reports empirical findings that people tend to distinguish between two broad
aspects of having a mind. Gray et al. label these dimensions Experience (including hunger, fear,
pain, pleasure, rage) and Agency (including self-control, morality, memory, emotion
4
See http://www.ai.mit.edu/projects/humanoid-robotics-group/cog/cog.html.
5
recognition). They had participants compare a host of characters (e.g., God, a 7-week-old fetus,
the robot Kismet5, a frog, a corpse) on a range of mental capacities. For instance, participants
were asked “whether a girl of 5 is more or less likely to feel pain than is a chimpanzee” (619).
They found a clear divide between experiential capacities and agentive capacities. The
possessions of mental capacities like hunger, fear, pain (etc.) were correlated with each other, as
were the possessions of mental capacities like self-control, morality, memory (etc.), while the
possessions of mental capacities across these two groupings were poorly correlated. Thus, while
a human baby scored low on Agency, but high on Experience, the robot Kismet scored very low
on Experience, but had a moderate Agency score.
These findings are no doubt very interesting, but they fail to show that the philosophical
concept of phenomenal consciousness coincides with the common-sense conception of
subjective experience, in spite of what the term “Experience”—Gray et al.’s name of their
second dimension of mind perception—might suggest.6 As we have seen in Section 1, for
philosophers, phenomenality is a second-order property shared by such diverse states as
perceptual experiences, bodily sensations, and felt emotions. Perceptual states like seeing red are
in fact the typical illustrative example of phenomenally conscious mental states. By contrast, the
states Gray et al. tested (e.g., pain, pleasure, rage, etc.) were all non-perceptual. As a result, it
remains unclear whether the folk think that mental states such as seeing red, feeling pain, and
feeling rage have in common that they are phenomenally conscious, as they should if they
conceive of subjective experience in the same way as philosophers.
5
See http://www.ai.mit.edu/projects/sociable.
Heather Gray explicitly equated her Experience dimension with phenomenal consciousness at the 2007
Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness conference.
6
6
2.2 Minds and Objects
In contrast to Piaget’s (1929) claim that “children are adualistic rather than dualistic in that they
fail to segregate two realms: the psychical and the physical, the subjective and the objective, the
mental and the real” (Wellman and Estes 1986, 910), psychologist Paul Bloom has argued that
“even very young babies treat people differently from objects” (2004, 14). He holds that we have
an “evolved capacity to understand and respond to the minds of other people” and “we also have
the evolved capacity to perceive and reason about material objects” (5). Bloom concludes that
from an early age on, people are intuitive dualists in the sense that they naturally distinguish
entities with minds from mere objects. Among other things, this corresponds with the fact that
“empathy comes early and easily” (114); from an early age people tend to empathize with some
entities (those with minds), but not others.
Philosopher Philip Robbins and cognitive neuroscientist Tony Jack (2006) have drawn on
Bloom’s work to argue that a further stance, rooted in our evolved “capacity for empathy and
moral understanding” (74), should be added to Dennett’s (1987) distinction between the
intentional and physical stances: “The phenomenal stance corresponds to a component of social
cognition that, like folk physics, is relatively independent of mindreading—namely, moral
cognition” (61; italics added). Moral cognition is then implicated in generating our “intuitive
dualism” and specifically identified as “generating intuitions about the non-physical nature of
consciousness” (61).
Robbins and Jack’s approach to the folk conception of subjective experience suffers from
the same problem as Gray et al.’s. They hold that “regarding something as a locus of experience
is a kind of emotional sensitivity” (70). Thus they note that “it is usually pleasant to observe
another’s pleasure, and distressing to observe their distress” and state that “the capacity for such
7
responses… is essential to the phenomenal stance” (70). The problem is that not all phenomenal
states are associated with pleasure or distress (think, e.g., about seeing a red patch). Robbins and
Jack might be correct that “phenomenal states typically have some hedonic value for the bearer,
either positive (e.g. pleasure, joy) or negative (e.g. pain, sadness)” (70; italics added), but this is
just to underline that the distinction between mental states that are associated with pleasure or
distress is distinct from the philosophical distinction between phenomenal and non-phenomenal
mental states.
2.3 Group Agents and Individuals
How the folk understand subjective experience has been investigated most specifically by Joshua
Knobe and Jesse Prinz (2008). In their second of five studies, Knobe and Prinz asked people to
evaluate how natural it is to ascribe a range of mental states to a group agent (Acme
Corporation). They found that people seem to be unwilling to ascribe phenomenally conscious
mental states (such as feeling depressed) to the corporation, while being disposed to ascribe
mental states that are not phenomenally conscious, such as propositional attitudes, to it. In
addition, in their fourth study, Knobe and Prinz provided some suggestive evidence that while
people are willing to ascribe a mental state such as being upset or regretting to a group agent,
they are reluctant to ascribe a mental state such as feeling upset or feeling regret to it. Knobe and
Prinz interpret this body of evidence as showing that (i) the folk distinguish between
phenomenally conscious mental states and mental states that are not phenomenally conscious and
(ii) that in contrast to the latter mental states, the ascription of phenomenally conscious mental
states does not depend merely on the functional properties of the ascribee’s states.
8
In contrast to Gray et al.’s and Robbins and Jack’s approaches, Knobe and Prinz’s study
seems to support the contention that philosophers’ concept of phenomenal consciousness
coincides with the common-sense conception of subjective experience (see also Huebner et al.
forthcoming). Indeed, they conclude that “ordinary people—people who have never studied
philosophy or cognitive science—actually have a concept of phenomenal consciousness” (68).
Unfortunately, there are a few problems with Knobe and Prinz’s study (Arico
forthcoming; Sytsma and Machery 2009). Particularly, as we have argued elsewhere (Sytsma and
Machery 2009), there is a confound inherent in this approach: Corporations differ in some
significant behavioral and functional ways from individuals. A group agent like Acme
Corporation is distributed; it does not have an individual body, although it is comprised of such
bodies. As such, Acme cannot smile in happiness or grimace in disgust. It is thus difficult to
determine whether people deny that Acme can experience great joy, feel excruciating pain, or
vividly imagine a purple square because they believe that a group agent like Acme cannot have a
phenomenal state or because they believe that a group agent like Acme does not have the proper
functional organization for having mental states like joy and pain. For these reasons, we find that
Knobe and Prinz’s study of the ascription of mental states to corporations is inconclusive about
the folk conception of subjective experience.
3. Study 1: Seeing Red and Feeling Pain
Previous research is by and large uninformative about whether philosophers’ concept of
phenomenal consciousness coincides with the common-sense conception of subjective
experience. In this section, we provide and discuss some new evidence that the folk and
philosophers conceive of subjective experience in markedly different ways.
9
The rationale behind our first study is straightforward. If the philosophical concept of
phenomenal consciousness coincides with the folk’s conception of subjective experience, we
would expect their judgments about robots like Cog to be in line with Dennett’s (Section 1):
They would treat perception analogously to bodily sensations, tending to deny both to a simple
robot. The Mental State Intuitions Study was designed to test this prediction. In the first
experiment, participants were given a description of a relatively simple, non-humanoid robot
performing tasks expected to elicit ascriptions of either a perceptual experience (seeing red) or a
bodily sensation (feeling pain) in humans. Given the role of visual experiences and bodily
sensations such as pain in spelling out the philosophical concept of phenomenal consciousness,
we hypothesized that philosophers’ attribution of the perceptual experience would not dissociate
from their attribution of the bodily sensation. If the folk conceive of subjective experience in the
same way as philosophers, they should give a similar pattern of answers.
671 participants completed surveys through the Mental State Intuitions Study website. 7, 8
Participants were divided into two groups based on their responses to biographical questions
concerning their philosophical training.9 They randomly received one of four scenarios
describing an agent manipulating a red object. The scenarios were varied along two dimensions.
In half of the scenarios, the agent was a simple robot (Jimmy), while in the other half, the agent
was a normal human male (Timmy). Moreover, in half of the scenarios, the manipulation was
successful and participants were asked whether the agent (either the robot or the human) “saw
red” on a 7-point scale anchored at 1 with “clearly no,” at 4 with “not sure,” and at 7 with
7
http://www.JustinSytsma.com/MSIS
See appendix for demographical information and data analysis for each experiment.
9
“Philosophers” were defined as participants who indicated at least some graduate training in philosophy or either
had already completed or were in the process of completing an undergraduate degree with a major in philosophy.
Note that the results do not change when we count as philosophers only the participants who have some graduate
training in philosophy.
8
10
“clearly yes.” In the other half, the agent was electrically shocked and participants were asked
whether the agent “felt pain” on the same 7-point scale. In each pair of vignettes the agents are
described in behaviorally identical ways; in the first pair, the agents’ behavior involves
discrimination between colors, while in the second, the behavior is typical of a pain-response.10
The two robot scenarios read as follows11:
Jimmy (shown below) is a relatively simple robot built at a state university. He has a
video camera for eyes, wheels for moving about, and two grasping arms
with touch sensors that he can move objects with. As part of a
psychological experiment, he was put in a room that was empty except for
one blue box, one red box, and one green box (the boxes were identical in
all respects except color). An instruction was then transmitted to Jimmy. It
read: “Put the red box in front of the door.” Jimmy did this with no
noticeable difficulty. Did Jimmy see red?
Jimmy (shown below12) is a relatively simple robot built at a state university. He has a
video camera for eyes, wheels for moving about, and two grasping arms with touch
sensors that he can move objects with. As part of a psychological experiment, he was put
in a room that was empty except for one blue box, one red box, and one green box (the
boxes were identical in all respects except color). An instruction was then transmitted to
Jimmy. It read: “Put the red box in front of the door.” When Jimmy grasped the red box,
however, it gave him a strong electric shock. He let go of the box and moved away from
it. He did not try to move the box again. Did Jimmy feel pain when he was shocked?
Participants were randomly ascribed to one of the four scenarios. After the participants
read the scenario they were asked the target question (“Did Timmy/Jimmy see red?” or “Did
Timmy/Jimmy feel pain?”), as well as a variation concerning other people: Participants were
asked whether ordinary people would say that the agent (either the robot or the human) saw red
10
We emphasize that the robot and the undergraduate behave in the same way. Thus, if participants were to ascribe
differently pain and seeing red to the robot and the undergraduate, this difference could not plausibly be explained
by reference to the functional and behavioral properties of the two agents; rather, it would result from participants
focusing on the phenomenal properties of these states. This stands in contrast with Knobe and Prinz’s (2008)
comparison of an individual agent and of a corporation.
11
The complete set of probes is available at: HTTP://www.JustinSytsma.com/MSIS/probes.html
12
The same image was used with each robot scenario in studies 1, 2, and 3; an image of a typical undergraduate was
used in each of the human scenarios.
11
or felt pain on the same 7-point scale. The questions were counterbalanced for order. Participants
were then asked to explain their answers and to fill out a short biographical survey.
3.1 Results
Figure 1 and Table 1 summarize our results.
Seeing Red
Feeling Pain
Folk
Philosophers
Folk
Philosophers
N = 55, 5.98
(1.25)***
N = 92, 5.90
(1.46)***
N = 62, 6.15
(1.01)***
N = 84, 6.44
(.87)***
N = 52, 5.15
N = 96, 3.48
Robot
(1.85)***
(1.94)**
* p < .05; ** p < .01; *** p < .005
N = 59, 2.54
(1.99)***
N = 100, 2.02
(1.53)***
Human
Table 1: Results of Study 1 (number of participants per condition, mean answer,
and standard deviation in parentheses; significance tests compare means to the
neutral answer, 4).
Consistent with our hypothesis, philosophers treated similarly feeling pain and seeing red. They
were unwilling to ascribe either the perceptual experience of seeing red or the bodily sensation of
feeling pain to the robot (the mean answers are significantly lower than 4). By contrast,
philosophers were willing to ascribe both states to a normal human male (the mean answers are
significantly higher than 4). Contrary to the hypothesis that the folk and philosophers conceive of
subjective experience similarly, however, ordinary people distinguished the perceptual state of
seeing red from the bodily sensation of feeling pain. They were willing to attribute the perceptual
experience to a simple robot that can effectively manipulate objects, but were not willing to
attribute feeling pain to this robot. In addition, the folk’s modal answer for feeling pain was 1
(like philosophers), while their modal answer for seeing red was 7 (unlike philosophers). By
12
contrast, ordinary people did not differ from philosophers in their willingness to ascribe the
perceptual state and the bodily sensation to a normal human male.
Figure 1: Results, Study 1 (error bars: 95% confidence interval).
3.2 Discussion
In contrast to the prediction derived from the hypothesis that the philosophical concept of
phenomenal consciousness coincides with the common-sense conception of subjective
experience, the results show a clear divergence between philosophers and the folk: On average,
the folk (but not philosophers) are willing to ascribe the perceptual state of seeing red to a simple
robot. Given the illustrative centrality of the example of the redness of red to the philosophical
concept of phenomenal consciousness, our results indicate that philosophers’ concept of
phenomenal consciousness is not how the folk understand subjective experience.
13
In addition, it is worth noting that philosophers are not aware that their conception of
subjective experience differs from the folk conception. Remember that in addition to asking
participants whether they thought that Jimmy was in pain and was seeing red, we also asked
them how ordinary people would answer these same questions. Philosophers’ answers are wellcalibrated for Timmy’s pain, Timmy’s perception of red, and Jimmy’s pain. By contrast, for the
robot’s perception of red, philosophers’ prediction about the ordinary people’s answers is offthe-mark: They expected ordinary people to give only a neutral answer (M = 4.18; SD = 1.81),
while ordinary people’s mean answer was above 5 (Figure 2).
Figure 2: Comparison of the folk’s mean answer for the question “Did Jimmy see
red?”, with how the folk and philosophers thought ordinary people would answer
(error bars: 95% confidence interval).
14
Philosophers’ expectation about ordinary people’s evaluation of the robot’s perception of red
follows their usual pattern for estimating ordinary people’s answer. Philosophers expected
ordinary people to give approximately the same answer as themselves, but to be a bit less
skeptical (by giving a somewhat higher answer). In contrast to philosophers, non-philosophers’
evaluation of whether ordinary people will ascribe seeing red to the robot is well calibrated. They
expected ordinary people to give a mean answer of 5.38, while ordinary people’s mean answer
was 5.15.
3.3 Objections
We now turn to two possible replies to the claim that philosophers and ordinary people conceive
of subjective experience differently. Our critic assumes that the folk understand subjective
experience similarly to philosophers. She must then explain the folk’s divergence from
philosophers for the case of Jimmy seeing red in another way. The most obvious ways to do this
are to argue that the folk understand the question “Did Jimmy see red?” differently than
philosophers, or that the folk have divergent beliefs about Jimmy. We will consider each
response in turn.13
First, it could be argued that “seeing red” is ambiguous.14 On one reading (which our
critic might call “informational”), a creature sees red if its behavior is responsive to the
distinction between red things and non-red things or, to put the same point somewhat differently,
13
We briefly mention a third possible reply (Tony Jack, personal communication). A critic could argue that our
hypothesis predicts that if we ask ordinary people whether Jimmy experience red, they would answer affirmatively.
If they would answer negatively (as our critic suggests they would), then we would have to conclude that the folk
conceive of subjective experience as philosophers do. In reply, we note that “experience” is a technical term and
does not have the same meaning in ordinary English and in philosophy. In ordinary English, an experience typically
is a significant interaction with an object (e.g., one might say “My encounter with the bear in the woods was a
frightening experience”). For this reason, it is dubious that asking ordinary English speakers about a robot’s
experience would be of much relevance to study how they understand subjective experience.
14
See, e.g., Huebner (forthcoming) for a related objection.
15
if it can pick some information about red things from its environment and act on the basis of this
information. In this sense, Jimmy certainly sees red (he performs the discrimination task). On a
second reading (which our critic might call “phenomenal”), a creature sees red only if it has the
appropriate phenomenal experience. In this sense, Jimmy does not see red, or so our critic
maintains. The critic can then argue that in contrast to “seeing red,” there is no informational
reading of “feeling pain”: one is in pain only if one has the appropriate phenomenal experience.
From this, our critic might argue that “seeing red” has the informational and the
phenomenal readings both for the folk and for philosophers. However, the folk tend to
understand “seeing red” according to its informational reading, while philosophers tend to
understand it according to its phenomenal reading, which explains their divergent answers.
Because “feeling pain” has only a phenomenal reading, philosophers and the folk give similar
answers. If this proposal were correct, experiment 1 would not show that the folk understand
phenomenal consciousness differently than philosophers, because for the folk as for
philosophers, “seeing red” would still have a phenomenal reading. The folk would just interpret
the question “Did Jimmy see red?” according to the informational reading of “seeing red,” while
philosophers would interpret it according to its phenomenal reading.
It should be noted that if the objection is to avoid being blatantly ad hoc, the critic owes
us an explanation for the folk’s divergence from philosophers in choosing the informational
reading over the phenomenal reading of “seeing red.” Regardless, the data simply do not bear out
our critic’s proposal. If she were right, we would expect that a reasonable proportion of the folk
would answer negatively to the question “Did Jimmy see red?”—as philosophers do—while the
remainder would answer positively. This is not the case, however. Figure 3 presents the
16
distribution of answers for the folk: Almost all non-philosophers (84.6%) gave an answer equal
or superior to 4.
Figure 3: Distribution of the folk’s answers for the question, “Did Jimmy see red?”
This first objection is further undermined by the explanations that participants gave for
their answers. Philosophers tended to refer to phenomenal consciousness (or to qualia, secondary
properties, etc.) in explaining their denial that the robot saw red. A few typical philosophical
explanations of an answer of 1 (“clearly no”—philosophers’ modal answer) to the question (“Did
Jimmy see red?”), read as follows: “To actually see red requires experiencing the sensation of
redness (qualia)”; “color is a secondary property”; “seeing red implies consciousness, not just
ability to identify red”; “seeing is perceiving, and perceiving is conscious.” In contrast, the three
explanations given by non-philosophers who answered 1 to the question do not suggest a
17
phenomenal reading; if anything they indicate a different analysis of “seeing”—an
anthropocentric reading that restricts the term to humans and animals (see Bennett and Hacker
2003, for a related conceptual analysis of the term): “I’m not sure how color is understood by
robots and computers”; “seeing is a human attribute”; “seeing is something which animals do.”
Second, a critic could offer an alternative explanation of our results. Consider the
following analogy. John and Joe might have the same concepts of right and wrong (say, both are
utilitarian), but they might nonetheless disagree about whether the death penalty is wrong. They
might disagree about the wrongness of the death penalty because they have different beliefs
about the death penalty (for example, about its efficiency as a deterrent). Similarly, the
disagreement between the folk and philosophers might not indicate that they conceive of
subjective experience differently; rather, it might reflect that they have different beliefs about the
robot Jimmy.
We have argued that if the philosophical concept of phenomenal consciousness coincides
with the folk’s conception of subjective experience, then we would expect them to treat seeing
red and feeling pain analogously in denying both to a simple robot. The critic challenges this:
Perhaps the folk do understand these states in the phenomenal sense, but unlike philosophers
they believe that Jimmy is capable of having phenomenal visual experiences. Our argument
assumes that the robot Jimmy (as described and pictured) is simple enough that if someone has
the concept of phenomenal consciousness, then she will not feel that it applies to Jimmy. The
critic denies this, arguing (in effect) that the folk are more lenient than philosophers in ascribing
phenomenal consciousness. Besides an argument for supposing the folk to be lenient in this way,
on the assumption that the folk really take Jimmy to be phenomenally conscious, the critic now
18
owes us an explanation of why they deny that he feels pain. One possibility is that the folk tend
to assume that Jimmy’s visual system is more complex than his touch system.
While we feel that these are indeed possibilities (that could be explored through further
experimental work), none of them strikes us as especially likely. As noted above, the
explanations that the folk offered for their responses do not suggest a phenomenal understanding
of “seeing red.” Further, the details of the story do not support the assumption that Jimmy’s
visual system is significantly more complex than his touch system. Finally, while post-hoc
explanations of our data that are compatible with the assumption that the folk’s understanding of
subjective experience coincides with philosophers’ can be given, our positive account of the
folk’s understanding of subjective experience suggests that this assumption is mistaken. We
present this positive account in the following two sections.
4. Study 2: Smelling Banana and Feeling Anger
In study 1, the folk deny that the robot Jimmy feels pain, but not that he sees red. What does this
indicate about the folk understanding of subjective experience? One proposal that is suggested
by the philosophical literature is that the folk’s understanding of subjective experience is based
on a distinction between the internal senses and the external senses: being subjective and being
internal would be identified according to this proposal. As Natika Newton put it, colors and pains
“seem to lie at opposite extremes of internality and externality” (1989, 571). Thus, the folk might
treat seeing red differently from feeling pain because the former is a product of an external sense
while the latter is a product of an internal sense. If this explanation is correct, then we would
expect the folk to be willing to ascribe other perceptual experiences (external) to Jimmy, but not
felt emotions (internal).
19
To test the internal/external hypothesis, participants were given variations on the
scenarios from the first experiment. If the hypothesis is correct, the folk should be willing to
ascribe the perceptual experience of odor to the robot Jimmy in the same way they were willing
to ascribe the perceptual experience of red to him in study 1, while being reluctant to ascribe the
felt emotion of anger to him. By contrast, they should ascribe both the perception of odor and the
emotion of anger to the human Timmy.
Participants were randomly assigned to one of four scenarios. The scenarios were varied
along two dimensions. In half of the scenarios the agent was a simple robot (Jimmy), while in the
other half the agent was a normal human male (Timmy). Moreover, in half of the scenarios the
agent successfully manipulated an object; participants were then asked whether the agent (either
the robot or the human) “smelt banana” on the 7-point scale used in Study 1. In the other half the
agent was prevented from successfully manipulating the object by a robot; participants were then
asked whether the agent “felt anger” on the same scale.15 The two robot scenarios read as
follows:
Jimmy (shown below) is a relatively simple robot built at a state university. He has a
scent detector, video camera for eyes, wheels for moving about, and two grasping arms
with touch sensors that he can move objects with. As part of a psychological experiment,
he was put in a room that was empty except for one box of peeled bananas, one box of
chocolate, and one box of peeled oranges. The boxes were closed, but had small holes to
let the scent through (Jimmy couldn’t see what was in the boxes). The boxes were
otherwise identical. An instruction was then transmitted to Jimmy. It read: “Put the box
of bananas in front of the door.” Jimmy did this with no noticeable difficulty. Did Jimmy
smell banana?
Jimmy (shown below) is a relatively simple robot built at a state university. He has a
video camera for eyes, wheels for moving about, and two grasping arms with touch
sensors that he can move objects with. As part of a psychological experiment, he was put
in a room with another simple robot; the room was otherwise empty except for one blue
15
We replicated the experiment with the question “Was Timmy/Jimmy angry…” instead of the question “Did
Timmy/Jimmy feel anger....” Since this variation had no effect on participants’ answers, we present only their
answers to the question formulated with “feel anger” to match the formulation used in study 1 for “feel pain.” For
discussion of the construction “feeling + psychological predicate” see Sytsma and Machery (2009).
20
box, one red box, and one green box (the boxes were identical in all respects except
color). An instruction was then transmitted to Jimmy. It read: “Put the red box in front of
the door.” When Jimmy went to move the red box, the other robot ran into him,
preventing him from reaching the box. Jimmy tried again and again and each time the
robot banged into him. Jimmy finally rammed the other robot; when the robot moved
away from him, Jimmy chased after the robot. Did Jimmy feel anger?
4.1 Results
Figure 4 and Table 2 summarize the results.
Smelling Banana
Feeling Anger
N =18, 5.83 (1.46)***
N = 25; 5.84 (.99)***
N = 28; 3.89 (2.42)
Robot
* p < .05; ** p < .01; *** p < .005
N = 35; 3.06 (2.22)*
Human
Table 2: Results of Study 2 (number of participants per condition, mean answer,
and standard deviation in parentheses; significance tests compare means to the
neutral answer, 4).
Unsurprisingly, participants were willing to ascribe both smelling banana and feeling anger to
Timmy. By contrast, participants were reluctant to ascribe feeling anger to the robot Jimmy (their
mean answer was significantly lower than 4) and were ambivalent about ascribing smelling
banana (their answer was not significantly different from 4). Thus, in contrast to seeing red,
people are not willing to ascribe smells to a simple robot. While most of the folk were willing to
ascribe seeing red to the robot (more than 80% of participants gave a score of 4 or higher), they
were more evenly split for the case of smelling banana (around 50% gave a score of 4 or higher).
21
Figure 4: Study 2, Results (error bars: 95% confidence interval).
4.2 Discussion
These results speak against the internal/external hypothesis as formulated: The folk do not
appear to treat all external senses the same—they do not treat smelling banana analogously to
seeing red. Our results suggest that the folk do not understand subjective experience in terms of a
distinction between being internal and being external.
One possible response is to charge that our characterization of the division between the
external and the internal is too coarse. For example, Newton (2000, 64) implies that not all the
external senses are equally external: Where colors are seen as properties of external objects, she
argues that this holds to only a lesser degree for sound. The folk might treat smell as yet more
borderline between external and internal: While the sense of smell gives us information about
22
external objects, the scent can seem to be located at or in the nostrils. A nuanced internal/external
hypothesis would predict that the folk’s willingness to ascribe perceptual states to a simple robot
varies inversely with how external the sense is.
An alternative response is also suggested by Newton (1989), as well as the discussion of
Robbins and Jack (2006) in section 2—it might be that the folk conception of subjective
experience is closely tied to those mental states that have a valence. Thus, Newton argues that
experiences of colors and pains differ in that the latter has an “affective aspect” that the former
lacks: “To have a pain is to have something that one does not like. Since not liking something is
a psychological state, it has seemed as if pains, even if they are associated with our physical
bodies, are also psychological in a way that e.g. colors, in this respect at least, fail to be.” (574).
We hypothesize that it is not whether a mental state is the product of the external senses that
matters for the folk understanding of subjective experience, but whether they associate that state
with some hedonic value for the subject.
Note that there is much correspondence between the division between states with or
without a valence and the internal/external division: the states explored in experiment 1 separate
under each distinction; seeing a red box is both external and lacks valence, while feeling pain
from an electric shock is both internal and has a valence. Nonetheless, not all external mental
states lack valence; like feeling pain, but unlike seeing colors, tastes and smells are typically
associated with hedonic value.
Thus, for a perceptual experience like seeing red that is neither liked nor disliked, the folk
readily attribute it to the robot Jimmy. For non-perceptual mental states with clear valence like
feeling pain or feeling anger, the folk readily deny them of Jimmy. For a perceptual state like
smelling banana that has an associated valence, however, the folk are divided. We conjecture
23
that they are divided because they hold that while Jimmy is capable of perceiving the scent of
banana, he is incapable of having the valence; he is incapable of liking the scent of banana. The
folk are divided, here, because unlike pain where its valence is essential to it being pain, for
smell they see the valence as potentially disassociating from the perceptual aspect. In other
words, there is an ambiguity in the question “did Jimmy smell banana”—not between an
“informational” and a “phenomenal” reading (see section 3.5), but between a “perceptual” and a
“valence” reading—that is not present for the questions about seeing red and feeling pain. This
ambiguity is suggested by the wide distribution of responses (Figure 5): 42.9% of the folk gave a
negative response (a score below 4) while 48.6% gave a positive response (a score above 4).
Figure 5: Distribution of the folk’s answers for the question, “Did Jimmy smell
banana?”
If this explanation is correct, then we would expect that downplaying the valence reading
for smell will increase the folk’s willingness to attribute the state to the robot Jimmy.
Specifically, we predict that for a “neutral” odor (an odor that participants are unfamiliar with
and thus associate no valence with), participants will be more willing to say that Jimmy smells it
than familiar odors like banana. Testing this prediction is the focus of our third experiment.
24
5. Study 3: The Valence of Smell
That the sense of smell has strong connections to emotion and emotional memory is well
recognized. It is obvious that we tend to find many odors distinctly pleasant or unpleasant. In
recent years, a great deal of scientific work has been conducted on the emotional processing of
olfactory stimuli. This work indicates that in contrast with visual stimuli, odors more readily
elicit emotional responses and more readily call forth emotional memories (see, for example,
Herz et al. 2004). Most recently, neuroimagining data has provided evidence that the emotional
potency of memories elicited through smell are correlated with activation of the amygdala, a
brain structure that is critical for processing emotive stimuli and for emotional memory (Winston
et al. 2005). It is therefore not surprising that the sense of smell would be tied to valence since
unlike the other sensory systems, the olfactory system projects directly to the amygdala.
Given this, it is reasonable to expect that participants associated each of the common
olfactory stimuli described in experiment 2—banana, orange, and chocolate—with a valence.
These are odors that most people are familiar with and find to be pleasant. We hold that this
valence explains people’s relative unwillingness to say that the robot Jimmy smelled banana in
comparison to saw red.
To test this we ran a further variation on the Timmy/Jimmy probes. We tested folk
responses for three sets of olfactory stimuli—familiar unpleasant stimuli (e.g., vomit), familiar
pleasant stimuli (e.g., banana), and unfamiliar stimuli (e.g., isoamyl acetate). We predicted that
the participants’ willingness to attribute smell to the robot is sensitive to whether a valence is
associated with the stimulus: Participants would be more willing to say that Jimmy could smell a
stimulus that they did not associate with a valence than one that they did.
25
Participants were randomly assigned to one of six scenarios. The scenarios were varied
along two dimensions. In half of the scenarios the agent was a simple robot (Jimmy), while in the
other half the agent was a normal human male (Timmy). In each of the scenarios the agent
successfully manipulated an object based on an olfactory cue. The scenarios were also varied
with respect to the valence typically associated with the olfactory cue. In one third of the
scenarios, the olfactory cue was unfamiliar and thus associated with no valence (isoamyl
acetate); in one third, it was familiar with a positive valence (banana); in one third, it was
familiar with a negative valence (vomit). Finally, participants were asked whether the agent
(either the robot or the human) smelt that stimulus on the 7-point scale used in previous studies.
The first of the three robot scenarios reads as follows:
Jimmy (shown below) is a relatively simple robot built at a state university. He is
equipped with a microphone, scent detector, video camera, wheels for moving about, and
two grasping arms with touch sensors that he can move objects with. As part of an
experiment, three chemical compounds were placed under Jimmy’s scent detector. The
compounds were presented one at a time. As they were presented their names were
transmitted to Jimmy: Isoamyl Acetate, 3-Methylbutanal, and Dipentene. The next day
Jimmy was put in a room that was empty except for one box of Isoamyl Acetate, one box
of 3-Methylbutanal, and one box of Dipentene. The boxes were closed, but had small
holes to let the scent through. The boxes were otherwise identical. An instruction was
then transmitted to Jimmy. It read: “Put the box of Isoamyl Acetate in front of the door.”
Jimmy did this with no noticeable difficulty. The test was repeated on three consecutive
days with the order of the boxes shuffled. Each time Jimmy performed the task with no
noticeable difficulty. Did Jimmy smell Isoamyl Acetate?
The other three scenarios varied only in the olfactory stimuli used. They were (the target is in
italics):
Banana, Orange, Chocolate;
Vomit, Human Feces, Rotting Dog Meat;
5.1 Results
Figure 6 and Table 3 summarize the results.
26
Human
Isoamyl Acetate
Banana
Vomit
N = 25, 5.68 (1.38)***
N = 26, 5.62 (1.56)***
N = 25, 5.48 (1.76)***
N = 35, 4.11 (1.98)
N = 34, 4.18 (2.30)
N = 32, 5.31 (2.13)***
Robot
* p < .05; ** p < .01; *** p < .005
Table 3: Results of Study 3 (number of participants per condition, mean answer and
standard deviation in parentheses; significance tests compare means to the neutral
answer, 4).
Participants were willing to ascribe each smell to Timmy. They were also willing to ascribe the
unfamiliar olfactory cue (isoamyl acetate) to Jimmy (the mean answer was significantly higher
than 4), but not the two familiar olfactory cues (the mean answers were not significantly different
from 4). Participants’ answer to the unfamiliar smell was also significantly higher than their
answer to the familiar smells and the latter were not different between each other.
Figure 6: Study 3, Results (error bars: 95% confidence interval).
27
5.2 Discussion
As we had predicted, people are more likely to ascribe the perception of an unknown olfactory
stimulus to the robot than the perception of familiar smells associated with either positive or
negative valence. The refined interior/exterior hypothesis discussed in section 4.2 can hardly
account for these findings, because we found that people’s disposition to ascribe a mental state to
the robot varied within a single modality. Because they are olfactory states, smelling banana and
smelling isoamyl acetate are equally external. Thus, the refined interior/exterior hypothesis
predicts that people should treat them similarly.
By contrast, the valence hypothesis predicts people’s answers. Because people are
unfamiliar with the smell of isoamyl acetate, they do not associate either a positive or a negative
valence with it. Absent a specific valence, people focus on the perceptual reading of “smell” to
decide whether Jimmy and Timmy can smell isoamyl acetate. By contrast, both the smell of
banana and the smell of vomit are associated with valence. Because people tend to believe that
only living creatures have likes and dislikes, they are relatively unwilling to ascribe these two
smells to the robot. This is consistent with the proposal that the folk conceive of subjective states
as states with an associated valence: People distinguish between different types of perceptual
experiences, bodily sensations, and felt emotions depending on their valence.
6. Phenomenal States and Valence
6.1 The Common-sense Understanding of Subjective Experience
The experimental studies reported on above offer preliminary evidence that the folk do not
recognize the phenomenality of mental states such as seeing a color, hearing a sound, smelling,
feeling pain, and experiencing some emotion. To put the same point differently, in clear contrast
28
to philosophers (Section 1), the folk do not seem to believe that there is something common to all
these mental states—namely that they are phenomenal. The evidence for this difference between
the folk and philosophers comes from three sources. First, study 1 showed that the folk are
willing to ascribe seeing red to a simple robot, but deny that it feels pain; in contrast,
philosophers deny that the robot can be in either state. Second, unlike philosophers, the
explanations given by those folk who deny that the robot could see red did not indicate that
phenomenality was at issue. Finally, studies 2 and 3 support our positive account of the folk
conception of subjective experience: The folk’s responses across modalities, and for a range of
stimuli within the olfactory modality, correspond with the valence of those states, but not with
their phenomenality.
We have seen that the folk are much more likely to ascribe mental states that lack valence
(seeing red or smelling isoamyl acetate) to the robot than they are to ascribe a mental state with
positive or negative valence (feeling pain, feeling anger, smelling banana, or smelling vomit).
While each of these states is phenomenal, only those states that the folk were willing to ascribe
to the robot Jimmy lacked a valence. Furthermore, people’s relative willingness to ascribe the
other mental states to the robot seems to correlate with traditional views about how essential
valence is to that state. Valence is strongly associated with mental states like feeling pain or
anger and the folk were unwilling to ascribe these states to Jimmy; in contrast, smelling banana
and smelling vomit involve perceptual discriminations that can be carried out in the absence of
any valence and participants were split in ascribing these states to Jimmy. For isoamyl acetate—
an olfactory stimulus with no known valence for most people—however, participants were
willing to say that Jimmy could smell it. Thus, across perceptual modalities, people’s willingness
to ascribe a mental state to a simple robot depends on the valence associated with the relevant
29
perceptual modality and within the olfactory modality, people distinguish between mental states
with and without a valence (Figure 7).
Figure 7: Folk’s mean answers for mental state ascriptions to the robot Jimmy,
within and across perceptual modality.
Of the accounts of the folk understanding of subjective experience considered in this
article, only our account predicts this pattern of answers. If people recognized the phenomenality
of mental states such as seeing red and feeling pain, they would treat them similarly. But they
don’t. If people conceived of subjective mental states in terms of internal states (in contrast to the
states produced by our external senses), they would treat similarly smelling banana and seeing
red on the one hand and smelling isoamyl acetate and smelling banana on the other. But they
don’t.
30
6.2 Philosophical Implications
What we have offered in this article in an initial empirical account of the common-sense
conception of subjective experience. We have also presented preliminary evidence that it differs
significantly from the philosophical concept of phenomenal consciousness. In contrast to
philosophers’ emphasis on the phenomenality of subjective mental states, for the folk, subjective
states seem to be primarily states with a valence. We are aware that much work remains to be
done to establish our hypothesis about the folk conception of subjective experience.16 For the
sake of the argument, however, we will assume in the remainder of the paper that it is by and
large correct. We believe that the preliminary evidence reported here at least justifies taking
seriously the hypothesis that philosophers’ and ordinary people’s conceptions of subjective
experience differ in the way we proposed.
Understanding the common-sense conception of subjective experience is fascinating in its
own right. It is also philosophically important. Although further research is needed to confirm
the valence hypothesis, if correct it has some significant philosophical implications. First, some
philosophers have claimed that philosophers and ordinary people conceive of subjective
experience in basically the same way. Block (2004) likens the philosophical conception of
subjective experience to the common-sense conception of subjective experience. Similarly,
Dennett holds that the concept of phenomenal consciousness is part of “the lore” of our folk
theory of consciousness that we pick up “in the course of our enculturation” (2005, 26-27),
Patricia Churchland talks of “the old folk notion of consciousness” (1988, 302), and Alvin
Goldman writes about “the folk-psychological notion of phenomenal consciousness” (1993,
16
Particularly, one might argue that the fact that ordinary people have no difficulty understanding the classical
thought experiments about consciousness, such as the inverted spectrum thought experiment, shows that the folk
conception of subjective experience coincides with the concept of phenomenal consciousness. We are currently
examining whether people really grasp these thought experiments.
31
364). In line with such claims, we found in study 1 that philosophers believe that ordinary people
will give approximately the same answers as themselves. Our findings belie such claims.
Second, and more important, if further research supports our finding that there is a
difference between the philosophical concept of phenomenal consciousness and the folk
conception of subjective experience, it will have some significant implications for some central
debates in philosophy of mind. We have particularly in mind Chalmers’s hard problem of
consciousness or Levine’s explanatory gap.
For the sake of space, we focus on Chalmers’s articulation of the problem. In substance,
this problem is the following: supposing that one were able to describe all the functional
properties of a mental state such as seeing red or feeling pain, something would remain
unexplained, namely the phenomenal aspect of red (the redness of red) and the phenomenal
aspect of pain (the painfulness of pain). Chalmers puts this problem as follows (1995, 203):
[E]ven when we have explained the performance of all the cognitive and behavioral
functions in the vicinity of experience—perceptual discrimination, categorization,
internal access, verbal report—there may still remain a further unanswered question: Why
is the performance of these functions accompanied by experience?
The sense of “experience” at issue is the philosophical conception of subjective experience,
which unites perceptual experiences, bodily sensations, and felt emotions as each having a
phenomenal aspect (see Chalmers’s quotation in Section 1).
At this juncture, it is important to ask why we should believe that there is really a hard
problem of consciousness. That is, why should we believe that there are experiences, as defined,
such that an aspect of them is expected to be left unexplained even after we have thoroughly
accounted for their functional roles? Chalmers’s answer is characteristically limpid. As noted
above, he suggests that phenomenal consciousness is undeniable because it is “the most central
and manifest aspect of our mental lives” (1995, 207). In other words, on the basis of their
32
introspective, first-person access to mental states such as seeing red or feeling pain, we are
supposed to know that these mental states have phenomenal properties. As such, phenomenal
consciousness has the status of an explanandum, but explaining it poses a hard problem:
Chalmers holds that when we compare our first-person knowledge of the phenomenal properties
of states such as feeling pain and seeing red to the functional accounts of these mental states, we
will conclude that these accounts have failed to explain what had to be explained—viz. what it is
like to be in pain and to see red.
Our findings cast some doubt on Chalmers’s and others’ justification of the hard problem
of consciousness. If the account of the folk conception of subjective experience presented in this
article is correct, then the folk do not find phenomenal experience manifest; their first-person
experience with mental states such as seeing red and feeling pain does not lead them to judge
that these mental states are united by each having a phenomenal aspect. But if most people do
not judge that mental states such as feeling pain or seeing red have phenomenal properties in
spite of their introspective experience with these states, then phenomenal consciousness can
hardly be supposed to be “the most familiar and manifest aspect of our mental lives,” as
Chalmers puts it. It would be unclear whether these mental states have phenomenal properties at
all. But, then, why should we view the hard problem of consciousness as a genuine problem?
It is worth contrasting the argument made here with the argument developed by Robbins
and Jack (2006). Like us, Robbins and Jack link the common-sense conception of subjective
experience to valence. They further argue that this common-sense conception is the source of the
philosophical concept of phenomenal consciousness and of the resulting hard problem of
consciousness. They conclude that while this problem is a pseudo-problem, “the gap intuition is
psychologically real and deep” (60). By contrast, we have argued that philosophers and ordinary
33
people conceive of subjective experience differently. If this is correct, then the folk conception of
subjective experience is not the origin of the hard problem of consciousness and cannot be used
to underwrite it. Our skeptical challenge concludes that this undermines the usual justification for
this supposed problem.
At this point, Chalmers and others might attempt to meet this skeptical challenge in two
different ways. (Remember that for the sake of the argument, we are taking for granted that
philosophers and ordinary people conceive of subjective experience differently). First, they
might argue that the fact that ordinary people do not conceive of subjective experience as being
phenomenal does not undermine the claim that subjective experience is phenomenal. Second,
they might reformulate the hard problem of consciousness by focusing on the valence of pain
and anger rather than on their phenomenality. We consider these two replies in turn, starting with
the latter.
Our results suggest that the folk do not treat the diverse states at issue as being united by
having phenomenal properties; rather they distinguish between them on the basis of valence. On
this basis, we have asked, in a skeptical manner, why we should believe that there is a hard
problem of consciousness. It is natural to reply that the valence of pain and anger raises a
problem that is similar to the hard problem of consciousness: even if we knew all the functional
and neural properties of pain and anger, one would not have explained why they have a valence.
This reply should be resisted. The hard problem specifically concerns phenomenal
properties: It is the phenomenal properties that are thought to resist functional explanation.
Valence, on the other hand, does not seem to raise this issue. It is far from clear why one would
expect states with a valence to resist functional or neuronal explanation: the hedonic value of a
stimulus or a bodily state seems to be an evaluation of its expected value to the organism. It
34
might, of course, be conjectured that the folk understand the valence of states like feeling pain in
such a way that they resist functional or neuronal explanation. Additional empirical work is
needed to articulate how the folk actually understand the valence of states like pain, but in
advance of such work we see little reason to expect that they understand valence in a way that
would raise a problem that is similar to the hard problem of consciousness. Furthermore, even if
it were to turn out that the folk understand valence in such a way, it is unclear that the resulting
problem would have the philosophical force that the hard problem of consciousness has been
thought to have, as opposed to being more akin to the problem raised by people holding a vitalist
conception of life: Regardless of whether or not people hold that valence resists explanation, it is
not clear why we should think that it actually does so.
Let’s turn now to the other reply to our skeptical challenge. Chalmers and others might
reply that justifying the hard problem of consciousness does not require that most people actually
judge that mental states such as seeing red or feeling pain have phenomenal properties. It only
requires that people who have carefully considered what it is like to be in such mental states
make this judgment. Chalmers might then add that as our quotations illustrate, most philosophers
have indeed done so.
It is currently unknown whether most people who have carefully considered what it is
like to see red or feel pain do make this judgment. Artists, physicians, practitioners of various
meditation practices, and so on, have presumably given due attention to such experiences, but we
doubt that this introspection makes the philosophical concept of phenomenal consciousness any
more obvious. Rather, we suspect that the proposition that subjective experience is phenomenal
only becomes obvious as one is trained into a particular way of thinking about the mind.17
17
While most philosophers seem to find phenomenal consciousness obvious, we suspect that this has not been the
case for scientists. In fact, philosophers have often criticized psychologists and neuropsychologists for failing to see
35
Now, if phenomenal consciousness only comes to seem obvious with philosophical
training, then it is unclear whether the hard problem should be seen as raising a genuine
challenge for philosophers, psychologists, and neuroscientists, as opposed to pointing out that
there is a problem with the philosophical concept of phenomenal consciousness. The hard
problem seems particularly cogent, because it is alleged that it is pretheoretically obvious that
mental states like seeing red and feeling pain are phenomenal. Because this judgment is
pretheoretical, it is difficult to challenge it on the ground that it is informed by one’s
philosophical perspective on consciousness. By contrast, if the judgment is not pretheoretical but
is informed by one’s philosophical perspective, then the hard problem can be rephrased as an
argument against taking the theoretical concept of phenomenal consciousness to pick out an
actual explanandum.
As an alternative reply to our argument, proponents of the hard problem of consciousness
might argue that even though most people do not actually conceive of subjective experience as
being phenomenal, they can easily be taught to conceive of them as phenomenal. It is important
that this be easy if the hard problem is to remain cogent. Thus, the response concedes that while
the folk do no spontaneously recognize phenomenal experience, it is nonetheless pretheoretical.
Consider the analogy of pointing out to someone that their missing keys are in plain view. Like
the keys, the proponent of the hard problem might argue that phenomenal experience is obvious,
but that until it is pointed out to them many people miss it. To support this claim, they could
appeal to their own experience of teaching undergraduates Nagel’s notion of what it is like to
have a conscious mental state or Levine’s explanatory gap.
that their account of consciousness failed to solve the hard problem (see Chalmers 1995, section IV, for example).
We suspect that many psychologists and neuropsychologists have not failed in this respect by accident. Rather, it
might be that like the folk, they do not conceive of subjective experience as being phenomenal, in spite of having
plausibly carefully considered “what it is like” for them to see red, feel pain, and so on. For this reason, they might
not recognize that there is a further aspect of these mental states that needs explaining.
36
We are not convinced, however. We concede that if people could easily be taught to
recognize the phenomenality of mental states such as seeing red and feeling pain, then the worry
we have been raising would be alleviated. However, it is unclear whether the antecedent of this
conditional is true. In our experience, many ordinary people either don’t understand or don’t take
seriously the philosophical concept of phenomenal consciousness even after a lengthy
explanation. It does not seem to us that the keys are in plain view.
7. Conclusion
We have provided some preliminary evidence that philosophers and ordinary people conceive of
subjective experience in markedly different ways. Philosophers propose that subjectively
experienced mental states have phenomenal properties: There is something it is like to see red,
smell banana, feel anger, and be in pain. By contrast, ordinary people do not recognize that there
is something common to all these states—viz. that they are phenomenal. Rather, they distinguish
between the states that have a valence, such as pain, anger, and smelling banana, and the states
that do not, such as seeing red and smelling isoamyl acetate. We have also argued that these
empirical findings cast some doubts on whether there is really a hard problem of consciousness.
The hard problem is typically justified on the grounds that we are acquainted with the
phenomenal properties of states such as pain and seeing red and that functional accounts of
mental states fail to explain how they can have such phenomenal properties. Our findings
challenge the first premise of this argument. Because people do not seem to conceptualize their
subjective mental life as phenomenal, it is at least unclear that we are pretheoretically acquainted
with the phenomenal properties of our conscious mental states.
37
Appendix
Study 1: Seeing Red and Feeling Pain
671 participants completed surveys through the Mental State Intuitions Study website. 68
participants were excluded because their biographical information was incomplete or because
their comments indicated they misunderstood the probe. Biographical information was
considered “incomplete” if we could not sort the participant into either the philosopher or the
non-philosopher groups (see footnote 8). Participants were judged to misunderstand the probe
mostly for the following reasons: they stated that the electric shock was not painful, they
understood “see red” as meaning “is angry,” or they stated that the robot was under remote
control. Of the remainder, 61% were male; the mean age was around 33 (range: 18-68). There
were 372 philosophers (71% male; mean age around 33) and 231 non-philosophers (46% male;
mean age around 31).
A three-way ANOVA with type of agent, type of mental state, and philosophical training
as between-participant factors yielded a main effect of the type of agent (Timmy > Jimmy), a
main effect of the type of mental state (seeing red > pain), a main effect of philosophical training
(non-philosophers > philosophers) and three two-way interaction (type of mental state by type of
agent; type of mental state by philosophical training; type of agent by philosophical training).
Planned analyses showed that philosophers’ mean answers for both feeling pain and seeing red
were significantly above 4 for Timmy (red: N=92, M=5.90, SD=1.46, p<.005; pain: N=84,
M=6.44, SD=.87, p<.005) and significantly below 4 for Jimmy (red: N=96, M=3.48, SD=1.94,
p<.01; pain: N=100, M=2.02, SD=1.53, p<.005); non-philosophers treated the states dissimilarly,
the mean answers for Timmy being significantly above 4 (red: N=55, M=5.98, SD=1.25, p<.005;
38
pain: N=62, M=6.15, SD=1.01, p<.005), as was the mean answer for Jimmy seeing red (N=52,
M=5.15, SD=1.85, p<.005), while the mean answer for Jimmy feeling pain was significantly
below 4 (N=59, M=2.54, SD=1.99, p<.005). The difference between the average folk ascription
of seeing red and of feeling pain is statistically significant (t (109)=7.12, p<.001) and the effect
size (d = 0.87) is large (Cohen 1992).
Study 2: Smelling Banana and Feeling Anger
253 participants completed surveys through the Mental State Intuitions Study website. 31
participants were excluded because their biographical information was incomplete, because they
had indicated they had already participated to the Mental State Intuitions Study, or because they
were not 18 year old. Since this study was aimed at exploring the pattern of folk responses seen
in our first experiment, an additional 63 participants were excluded based on their responses to
biographical questions concerning their philosophical training (see footnote 8). Of the remainder,
38% were male; the mean age was around 30 (range: 18-75).
A two-way ANOVA with type of agent and type of mental state as between-participant
factors yielded a main effect of the type of agent (Timmy > Jimmy; F(1, 102)=36.84, p<.001)
and no other main effect or interaction. Planned analyses showed that the mean answers for both
smelling banana and feeling anger were significantly higher than 4 for Timmy (banana: N=18,
M=5.83, SD=1.46, p<.005; anger: N=25, M=5.84, SD=0.99, p<.005); the mean answer was
significantly below 4 for Jimmy feeling anger (N=35, M=3.06, SD=2.22, p<.05) and neutral for
Jimmy smelling banana (N=28, M=3.89, SD=2.42).
39
Study 3: The Valence of Smell
211 participants completed our survey in a classroom setting. 34 participants were excluded
because their biographical information was incomplete, because they were philosophers (see
footnote 8), because they had already completed one of our surveys, or because they were not 18
years old. Of the remainder, 33.5% were male; the mean age was around 20 (range: 18-30).
A two-way ANOVA with type of agent and type of olfactory cue as between-participant
factors yielded a main effect of the type of agent (Timmy > Jimmy; F(1, 171)=13.17, p<.001)
and no other main effect or interaction. Planned analyses showed that participants’ mean answers
for each of the three target smells for Timmy were significantly above 4 (isoamyl acetate: N=25,
M=5.68, SD=1.38, p<.005; banana: N=26, M=5.62, SD=1.56, p<.005; vomit: N=25, M=5.48,
SD=1.76, p<.005); the mean for the unfamiliar smell (isoamyl acetate) for Jimmy was also
significantly above 4 (N=32, M=5.31, SD=2.13, p<.005), but the scores were neutral for the two
familiar smells for Jimmy (banana: N=35, M=4.11, SD=1.98; vomit: N=34, M=4.148, SD=2.30).
Participants mean answer to the unfamiliar smell was significantly higher than either familiar
smell (banana: t(65)=-2.28, p=.02; vomit: t(65)=-2.08, p=.04), while for the unfamiliar smells the
mean answers were not different between each other (t(67)=-.12, p=.9).
40
References
Arico, A. (forthcoming). Folk psychology, consciousness, and context effects. Review of
Philosophy and Psychology.
Bennett, M., & Hacker, P. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 18, 227–247.
Block, N. (2004). Qualia. In R. Gregory (Ed.), Oxford Companion to the Mind, Second Edition
(pp. 785–789). New York: Oxford University Press.
Bloom, P. (2004). Descartes’ baby: How the science of child development explains what makes
us human. London: William Heinemann.
Chalmers, D. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness
Studies, 2(3), 200–19.
Churchland, P. S. (1988). Reduction and the neurobiological basis of consciousness. In A. J.
Marcel & E. Bisiach (Eds.), Consciousness in contemporary science (pp. 273–304). Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Cohen, J. (1992). A power primer. Psychological Bulletin, 112, 155–159.
Crick, F. (1995). The astonishing hypothesis: The scientific search for the soul. New York:
Simon & Schuster.
Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Dennett, D. (1996). Kinds of minds: Toward an understanding of consciousness. Cambridge:
MIT Press.
Dennett, D. (2005). Sweet dreams: Philosophical obstacles to a science of consciousness. New
York: Basic Books.
Goldman, A. (1993). Consciousness, folk psychology, and cognitive science. Consciousness and
Cognition, 2, 364–382.
Gray, H., Gray, K., & Wegner, D. (2007). Dimensions of mind perception. Science, 619, 315.
Herz, R., Eliassen, J., Beland, S., & Souza, T. (2004). Neuroimaging evidence for the emotional
potency of odor-evoked memory. Neuropsychologia, 42, 371–378.
41
Huebner, B. (forthcoming). Commonsense concepts of phenomenal consciousness: Does anyone
care about functional zombies? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences.
Huebner, B., Bruno, M., & Sarkissian, H. (forthcoming). What does the nation of China think
about phenomenal states? Review of Philosophy and Psychology.
Knobe, J., & Prinz, J. (2008). Intuitions about consciousness: Experimental studies.
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7, 67–85.
Levin, J. (1998). Qualia. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London:
Routledge. http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/V029. Accessed 4 July 2007.
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450.
Newton, N. (1989). On viewing pain as a secondary quality. Noûs, 23(5), 569–598.
Newton, N. (2000). Humphrey’s solution. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 7(4), 62–66.
Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking about consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Piaget, J. (1929). The child’s conception of the world. New York: Harcourt.
Prinz, J. (2006). Gut Reactions: A perceptual theory of emotions. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Robbins, P., & Jack, A. (2006). The phenomenal stance. Philosophical Studies, 127, 59–85.
Searle, J. (1994). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2009). How to study folk intuitions about phenomenal consciousness.
Philosophical Psychology, 22(1), 21–35.
Tye, M. (2003). Qualia. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia. Accessed 4 July 2007.
Wellman, H. M., & Estes, D. (1986). Early understanding of mental entities: A reexamination of
childhood realism. Child Development, 57, 910–923.
Winston, J., Gottgried, J., Kilner, J., & Dolan, R. (2005). Integrated neural representations of
odor intensity and affective valence in human amygdala. The Journal of Neuroscience, 25(39),
8903–8907.
42 |
Aristotle on Consciousness1
Victor Caston
Aristotle’s discussion of perceiving that we perceive (On the Soul .) has
points of contact with two contemporary debates about consciousness: the
first over whether consciousness is an intrinsic feature of mental states or a
higher-order thought or perception; the second concerning the qualitative
nature of experience. In both cases, Aristotle’s views cut down the middle of
an apparent dichotomy, in a way that does justice to each set of intuitions,
while avoiding their attendant difficulties. With regard to the first issue—
the primary focus of this paper—he argues that consciousness is both intrinsic and higher-order, due to its reflexive nature. This, in turn, has consequences for the second issue, where again Aristotle seeks out the middle
ground. He is committed against qualia in any strong sense of the term. Yet
he also holds that the phenomenal quality of experience is not exhausted by
its representational content.
Over the last thirty years, philosophers have disagreed as to whether
Aristotle even had a concept of consciousness.2 Each side, it turns out,
is right, though in a fairly uninteresting way. Aristotle clearly distinguishes being awake and alert from being asleep or knocked out, where
the notion of consciousness comes close to that of perceiving.3 On the
other hand, he does not use any single word to pick out the phenomena
we have in mind—the terminology itself arises only much later4 —and
1
Earlier versions of this paper have been read at Brown, Dartmouth, Harvard, Leeds University,
the University of London, UC Davis, USC, and William and Mary. I am grateful to all of those who
participated for their keen and spirited replies. I would also like to thank several individuals for extensive comments, which have often forced me to rethink things: Juan Comesaña, Paul Neufeld,
David Rosenthal, Bob Sharples, Joe Shieber, and John Sisko (who responded to the paper at Harvard), not to the mention the anonymous referees and above all the editor-in-chief of Mind. Without their insights and prodding, the paper would have had even more mistakes than it no doubt
has.
2
Against: Hamlyn () , p. xiii; Hamlyn , p. ; Rorty , pp. –; Wilkes , pp.
–. For: Kahn () ; Hardie ; Modrak ; Modrak , Ch. .
3
See esp. Kahn () and Hardie .
See Siebeck ; Jung ; Zucker ; Schwyzer ; Lewis, C. S. ; Cancrini ;
Mayer . For the development of the terminology during the early modern period, see Lewis,
G. ; Aquila ; Davies ; Thiel ; Thiel ; Thiel ; Thiel ; Thiel .
4
Mind, Vol. 111 . 444 . October 2002
© Oxford University Press 2002
752 Victor Caston
he does not share the epistemological concerns distinctive of the Cartesian conception of consciousness, such as privacy or indubitability.
Neither of these results should make us pause. For it is not clear that
we have a single concept of ‘consciousness’, despite the word;5 and many
of the topics we discuss under this label are clearly issues about which
Aristotle has something to say. His treatment of perceiving that we perceive in particular has points of contact with a current debate over the
nature of consciousness, between those who take consciousness to be
an intrinsic feature of mental states and those who think it consists in a
higher-order thought or perception. Aristotle’s view, I shall argue, cuts
down the middle of this apparent dichotomy, in a way that does justice
to each set of intuitions, while avoiding their attendant difficulties. His
discussion has ramifications, in turn, for a related debate over the
nature of ‘qualia’, between those who think that qualia belong to our
experience and those who think they are merely represented as belonging to objects in the world. Here, too, Aristotle steers for a middle
course, but his comments are more sketchy and underdeveloped.
In what follows, I shall focus almost exclusively on perceptual consciousness. But many of Aristotle’s views are clearly meant to extend to
other mental states in a fairly obvious way. The qualifications required
do not substantially alter the framework laid out here.6
After a brief overview of the issues surrounding higher-order theories of consciousness (section ), we shall turn to a close examination of
Aristotle’s views, beginning with his conception of perceptual awareness in general (section ). I shall then offer a detailed analysis of his
arguments in On the Soul . concerning how ‘we perceive that we see
and hear’ (sections –). These arguments have been systematically
misconstrued in the past; once properly explicated, they offer a view
that has distinct advantages over both higher-order and intrinsic theories of consciousness (section ). The resulting sense in which consciousness is ‘transparent’ and ‘reflexive’ on Aristotle’s view is also
distinctive (sections –); and this has implications for his views about
the phenomenal quality of perceptual experience (section ). I shall
conclude by considering various objections to these views and possible
5
See, e. g., Dennett () , p. ff.; Wilkes ; Wilkes ; Lycan , Ch. ; Block ;
Block () .
6
The main qualifications concern the type or mode of awareness we have of our own thinking:
on this point, see the discussion below in nn. and . A full treatment would require discussion
of Aristotle’s views on the Divine Intellect, whose ‘thinking is a thinking of thinking’ (1 nÒhsiw
noÆsevw nÒhsiw, Metaph. ., b). But this is obviously a substantial topic in its own right
and would take us far afield from many of the concerns addressed here.
Aristotle on Consciousness 753
replies available to Aristotle (section ). A brief excursus on the inner
sense(s) has been appended to the end of the article.
1. Consciousness and higher-order mental states
Aristotle’s views constitute a fresh contribution to current debates over
the nature of consciousness. It is one of those cases where a distinctive
view emerges from a close reading of an historical figure, given his own
context and concerns, rather than one where a framework alien to his
own is forced onto his claims. To show this, a certain amount of exegetical detail is naturally required. Therefore it may be helpful to survey
the sorts of issues at stake first, so as to keep the larger picture in view.
These are obviously not the only issues one might be interested in when
thinking about consciousness, or even necessarily the most interesting
ones. But they are the ones relevant to Aristotle’s concerns.
To begin with a gross truism: throughout Western philosophy, there
has been a long-running concern with the relation between the soul or
mind, on the one hand, and the body, on the other. Humans and animals seem different from most other things, in both their abilities and
their behaviour; and so it is natural to ask whether that which distinguishes them—call it their ‘soul’—is in some sense continuous with
the natural world around, or whether it marks an abrupt infusion of
something wholly different into the world. At different times, different
features have been picked out as what is distinctive. Over the past few
centuries, one feature that has been repeatedly invoked is consciousness, a kind of awareness that we seem to have in many, if not all, of our
mental states, over and above the primary intentional content these
states possess: to use an overly familiar metaphor, it is as if, in addition
to the information they carry, these states were suffused with a kind of
light. Accordingly, consciousness has often been treated as if it were an
intrinsic feature of such states, which is not further analysable (a characteristic that might in fact help to explain the frequent resort to metaphors). The qualitative character of such states—their ‘felt’ quality in
consciousness—likewise seems inexpressible except by referring to the
qualities of the objects those states happen to be about. This has suggested to some that consciousness involves a kind of ineliminable subjectivity, a feature that constitutes a primitive and irreducible feature of
mentality.
Higher-order theories of consciousness suggest an alternative. A conscious state is one that we happen to be aware of; and we are aware of it,
according to these theories, in virtue of another mental state that is of
754 Victor Caston
or about the first mental state. Thus, if I am consciously looking at the
Golden Gate Bridge, I not only see the Golden Gate Bridge; I am also
aware that I am seeing the Golden Gate Bridge. According to higherorder theories, this is because I am in a second mental state that is
directed at the first; and this second state is of a higher-order precisely
because its content concerns a mental state and its content. Depending
on the theory, this second, higher-order mental state will either be a
kind of judgement or, on so-called ‘inner sense’ or ‘internal monitoring
capacity ’ views, a certain kind of perception.7 What makes a mental
state conscious on any of these views, then, is not an intrinsic feature of
that state, but one that depends on its relations to other mental states. If
so, consciousness is no longer an unanalysable primitive, but something that possesses an ‘articulated structure’, whose elements can be
further distinguished and specified.8 More precisely, consciousness on
this view is just a special case of intentionality, where certain kinds of
mental state are directed upon others, in a way that embeds their content. And this at least leaves the door open for a naturalistic approach to
the mind. For now it can be argued that consciousness can be accommodated within a naturalistic scheme to exactly the same extent that
intentionality can.
Such a move is not without its costs, of course. To begin with, the
very feature that promises to make consciousness tractable, theoretically speaking—the suggestion that it is a relational feature, and not an
intrinsic one —runs counter to a fairly deep-seated intuition that conscious states are not so much observed from without, as ‘illuminated’
from within. Second, such theories require us to posit many additional
mental states to account for the conscious states we do have. Even if
such proliferation is acceptable, it effectively rules out the possibility
that all mental states are conscious states and hence the possibility that
consciousness is an essential feature of mentality. For while higherorder mental states can themselves be conscious in virtue of still higherorder states, it seems that this regress cannot continue indefinitely; and
so at some point we will reach a higher-order state that makes another
state conscious without being conscious itself. Finally, it may be questioned whether such a theory provides a satisfying account of ‘qualia’
and the felt character of conscious states, especially if the higher-order
Recent theorists who have accepted these labels include D. M. Armstrong (, pp. –,
–) and William Lycan (; ; () ). The phrase ‘internal monitoring capacity’
comes from the latter; ‘inner sense’ is, of course, traditional. For a brief history of the term, and its
connection with the Aristotelian tradition, see the excursus at the end of the article (pp. –4 below).
7
8
For example, Rosenthal , pp. , , ; Rosenthal b, p. ; Rosenthal , p. .
Aristotle on Consciousness 755
state is held to be a kind of thought or judgement. Even when it is held
to be a kind of perception, it is unclear whether it locates the qualitative
aspect of experience in the right place.
Aristotle has much to say about these issues. To be sure, his primary
concern is not whether consciousness, much less subjectivity, is an irreducible feature of mentality. But he does believe that the presence of
higher-order awareness is something that distinguishes sentience and
other forms of cognition from noncognitive changes; and he speaks
directly and at length about how we perceive that we perceive. He offers
several arguments on the subject, against the sort of higher-order view
we have just been considering, while at the same time managing to coopt its most attractive features. On Aristotle’s view, the awareness that
we have of our own mental states is an intrinsic and essential feature of
those states; and yet it is to be explicated in terms of intentionality. It
therefore remains equally congenial to a naturalistic approach to the
mind, an approach I would argue he himself favours.
2. Perceptual awareness
Perceiving for Aristotle is a natural change brought about by the perceptible qualities of objects in the environment. But he still worries
whether this change is wholly distinct from other sorts of natural
change or, if there are continuities, in just what way it differs. At the end
of On the Soul ., for example, he asks whether perceptible qualities
can bring about any changes other than perception. A smell, by its very
essence, is the sort of thing that brings about smelling (b–). But it
also can have an effect on inanimate bodies—not, he stresses, simply in
virtue of concomitant properties that its material basis happens to
have, but precisely in so far as it is a smell (b–). A smell, he concludes, can also make air smelly, that is, make the air something that can
provoke further incidents of smelling (b–).
Such commonplaces, though, raise an obvious worry. Exactly what is
the difference between making something smell and just making it
stink? Whatever change the air does undergo, it is not sentient and so
cannot smell anything. How, then, does this change differ from what
happens in the nose of a animal? Or, as Aristotle puts it,
What, then, is smelling besides undergoing a certain change?9 (b)
His use of ‘besides’ (parã) here sharpens the difficulty. It presupposes
that a change is undergone (pãsxein ti, b) when someone smells just
9
Taking ti as an internal accusative, as in the previous line (pay2n ti, b). See also Hicks
, ad b and esp. a.
756 Victor Caston
as much as when the air takes on an odour (pay2n ti, b). Had Aristotle meant to contrast smelling with undergoing a change outright, he
would have used ‘instead of ’ (ént3).10 On the contrary, his worry stems
precisely from the fact that undergoing a certain kind of change is common to both cases, that there is a univocal sense in which both can be
said to change in this way. Otherwise, the problem evaporates. If perceiving is a special case of undergoing a change (Burnyeat () ,
p. ), it can only be because of what else is true of the event, and not
because it involves a distinct sense of ‘undergoing a change.’11
The difference between these two changes must therefore be
explained by some further difference. Here Aristotle limits himself to
the following observation:
Isn’t it that while smelling is perceiving, air becomes perceptible when it undergoes a sudden change? (b–)
A pregnant response, at best. It is certainly not ‘all he needs to say ’,
since ostensibly it is just a restatement of the difference that gives rise to
the problem, with genus substituted for species: ‘perceiving’ has taken
the place of ‘smelling’ and ‘perceptible’ of ‘smelly’. Without importing a
10
It is important to see that this point is independent of the recent disagreement between Johansen and Sorabji. Sorabji argues (, pp. –) that Aristotle’s use of ‘besides’ (parã) implies that smelling is itself a case of undergoing change. Johansen objects (, n. ), citing
the following passage from Nic. Eth. .: ‘It does not matter whether the ends of action are the activities themselves or something else besides these [parå taÊtaw êllo ti]’ (a–). In this
sentence, ‘X is something besides Y’ does not imply that ‘X is also Y’: the second disjunct explicitly
states that ends are ‘something other’ (êllo ti) than the activities. Johansen concludes that we
cannot therefore infer in On the Soul . that smelling is a case of undergoing change.
While Johansen is right that the use of parã does not imply that ‘X is also Y,’ it nevertheless
does presuppose that there is a Y as well as an X. This is true even in the passage Johansen cites
from the Nicomachean Ethics: according to the second disjunct there will be activities as well as
ends distinct from them. But that is all that is needed. For it follows that a change is undergone
when smelling occurs, whether (a) smelling is one and the same in number as this change, so that
it is a smelling as well as a change (as Sorabji claims); or (b) smelling merely accompanies this
change, as something else that occurs ‘alongside’ it. Although I would prefer the monism of (a) to
the parallelism of (b), it does not affect my argument above, since (b) equally implies that a change
of the relevant sort occurs. Neither reading is compatible with an interpretation that denies there is
a change in smelling of a sort that can occur in inanimate things (for example Burnyeat ,
p. ).
On Aristotle’s use of parã in general, see Bonitz () , a–; Eucken , pp. –.
11
As Sorabji has rightly pointed out (, pp. –), this reading does not depend on
Torstrik’s insertion of ka3, based on ms. E, which can easily be suspected of being an error resulting from dittography (see Kosman , pp. –). The point here depends on the use of parã instead: whatever additional truths hold of perceiving and not of inanimate things, it will still be true
that perceiving is either (a) a change of a sort that inanimate things can also undergo or (b) accompanied by such a change. See n. above. Burnyeat now acknowledges that perceiving involves
the same sort of change as occurs in the medium, which is inanimate; the only difference between
them is that the former occurs in a being with the power of perception and the latter does not
(, pp., –; cf. , pp. –). He still maintains, though, that both changes are quite
different from ‘ordinary changes’: see esp. his recent .
Aristotle on Consciousness 757
more comprehensive understanding of Aristotle’s views of perception,
we could not hope to find this statement illuminating. That the difference between perceiving and becoming perceptible has something to do
with the difference between the animate and the inanimate is beyond
doubt. The question is just what that difference consists in.
Obvious places to look include earlier in the same chapter or even
earlier in the same book, in On the Soul .. But there needn’t be just
one difference in any case. In Physics ., Aristotle notes several distinctions between the animate and the inanimate relevant to the present
discussion:
Whereas what is animate undergoes alteration in the ways that something
inanimate does as well, what is inanimate does not alter in all the ways that
something animate does. For [what is inanimate] does not alter in the manner of the senses; and what is [inanimate] is unaware, while what is [animate]
is not unaware, of undergoing change. Nothing, however, prevents what is animate from being unaware as well, whenever the alteration does not occur in
the manner of the senses.12 (b–a)
Aristotle begins with the obvious point that inanimate things do not
perceive objects in their environment. But he adds a further and more
interesting difference. Animate things are ‘not unaware of undergoing
change’ (oÈ lanyãnei pãsxon) when alteration occurs in the manner of
the senses, whereas nothing inanimate is aware of any such change
(b–a).13 The participial construction with lanyãnein assures us
that this is not the same point as the first.14 Animate things are not only
aware of objects in their environment through perception; they are also
aware of undergoing this alteration itself. This isn’t proprioception
either: it is not a question of being aware of eye movement or the like,
but of being aware of an alteration that in some sense constitutes perception (b–). To be aware of the changes one undergoes ‘in the
manner of the senses’ is to be aware in some sense of one’s perceiving.
This is still more evident from On Perception and Perceptibles ,
where Aristotle uses this assumption to reject a view held by some of
his predecessors. They believe that the eye is made of fire, on the
12
Following the main version, a, as printed in Ross’s edition (with slight alterations to his
punctuation).
13
For the qualification concerning alterations not ‘in the manner of the senses’, cf. On the Soul
., a–b; Plato Phlb. 33D–34A, 43AB.
14
The point is obscured in Wardy’s translation, which takes pãsxon to serve as the subject of
lanyãnein and supplies gignÒmenon as a dependent participle: ‘what is happening escapes the notice
of the thing affected if it is inanimate, while it does not if the thing is affected is animate’ (,
p. ; emphasis mine). Rendering lanyãnein as ‘escapes notice’ also has the unfortunate consequence in the present context of suggesting that inanimate things do notice other things.
758 Victor Caston
grounds that you can see it flash when you rub your eyes in the dark.
But Aristotle thinks that such a view leads to absurdity:
But this view faces another difficulty, since if it is not possible to be unaware
of perceiving and seeing something seen, then necessarily the eye will see itself.
Why, then, doesn’t this happen when it is left alone?15(a–)
If the eye were made of fire, as his predecessors claim, and this is something that we can see, then we should be able to see this even when we
aren’t rubbing our eyes. But we do not see any such thing, since we are
not aware of it; hence, the eye must not be made of fire. This argument
depends crucially on the assumption that it is impossible to be unaware
that one is perceiving something while one is perceiving it (cf. ,
a–). This is not an assumption Aristotle’s predecessors make,
but one he imports into the discussion—he is not trying to catch them
in a contradiction so much as show that their view is not in accordance
with the facts. He is not entitled to reject their view, therefore, unless he
himself accepts this assumption, as he evidently does.
Several features of Aristotle’s position are worth noting. Consider the
version of the thesis stated in Physics . (above p. ). First, it is
offered in a fully general form: it is meant to distinguish perception
from any change, animate or inanimate, that does not enter awareness
or ‘reach the soul’, to use Plato’s language from parallel passages of the
Philebus (§p‹ tØn cuxØn diejelye›n, d–A, AB).16 In Aristotle’s view,
alteration ‘in the manner of the senses’ is always accompanied by this
kind of awareness.17 In fact, he claims elsewhere that such awareness is
temporally continuous and so present in every subinterval during
which we perceive (On Perception and Perceptibles , a–).18
Aristotle on Consciousness 759
Second, if his remark is this general, Aristotle cannot plausibly mean
that animals are continually aware of such changes as a result of deliberately observing them and directing their attention to them. His manner of expression confirms this. He says only that animals are ‘not
unaware’ of such changes, the use of litotes suggesting that introspection, in any strong sense, is not at issue.19 The awareness in question
forms a part of one’s normal experience in an unobtrusive and effortless way.
Third, Aristotle appears to have phenomenal awareness in mind.
Consider his claim that there are the changes in our bodies of which we
are not, in fact, aware. Aristotle would not be in a position to make this
claim if we were completely without empirical access to them. But such
changes can of course be observed via the senses: by someone’s putting
her ear to my chest, for example, or through the more gruesome opportunities afforded by the operating theatre and battlefield. In fact, given
a little ingenuity (or misfortune), one can even witness them in oneself.
But there is still a sense in which we cannot feel or experience such
changes.20 When we perceive, in contrast, we not only have direct, internal access to the information that we are perceiving; our perceiving is
itself something that does not ‘escape our notice’ (oÈ lanyãnei).21 Sorabji is perhaps right to characterize this as Aristotle’s ‘most Cartesian
remark’ (() , p. , emphasis mine; cf. p. ). But it does not
presuppose anything more than phenomenal awareness.
19
15
Following the majority of the mss.; Ross’s emendations are entirely gratuitous.
Cf. also Tim. C: diå toË s2matow a9 kinÆseiw §p‹ tØn cuxØn ferÒmenai prosp3ptoien. D:
toÊtvn tåw kinÆseiw diadidÚn e7w ëpan tÚ s«ma m°xri t4w cux4w a‡syhsin par°sxeto taÊthn.
AB: §p‹ tÚ frÒnimon §lyÒnta §jagge3l5. B: m°xri cux4w plhgØn diadidom°nhn. Rep. .C: a·
ge diå toË s2matow §p‹ tØn cuxØn te3nousai. Similar expressions can also be found both earlier, in
the Hippocratic treatise On the Sacred Disease (§w d¢ tØn sÊnesin 6 §gk°falÒw §stin 6 diagg°llvn,
. Grensemann; cf. .). They also occur in Aristotle himself. Cf. On the Soul ., b–:
éllÉ 6t¢ m¢n m°xri §ke3nhw [sc. cux4w], 6t¢ dÉ épÉ §ke3nhw. On Perception and Perceptibles , b–
: 1 dÉ a‡syhsiw ˜ti diå s2matow g3gnetai tª cuxª.
16
17
He extends a similar view to quasi-perceptual cases: when one is using one’s personal memory, for example, it is not possible to be unaware of remembering (§nergoËnta d¢ tª mnÆm5 … lanyãnein memnhm°non oÈk ¶stin; On Memory and Recollection , b–).
18
This text together with a passage from the Nicomachean Ethics . (see below, p. 774) have led
several scholars to wonder whether Aristotle anticipated Descartes’s cogito: Bréhier –, Schuhl
; Braun . The connections, though, are fairly distant (as Bréhier recognized): see also, for
example, Oehler , pp. – and , pp. –.
For a survey of different conceptions of introspection, see Lyons .
20
In speaking of ‘phenomenal awareness,’ I do not intend the discussion to be restricted to perceptual experiences (or quasi-perceptual ones, for that matter). In the Posterior Analytics, for example, Aristotle describes mistakes that ‘can, as it were, be seen by thought, though we are not
aware of it in a verbal form’ (oÂon 6rçn tª noÆsei, §n d¢ to›w lÒgoiw lanyãnei; ., b). Similarly,
when he considers Plato’s theory of recollection, he rejects as absurd the consequence that we
could have such knowledge without being aware of it (lelÆyasin; ., b–). In this case, it is
clearly phenomenal consciousness that is at issue, not ‘access consciousness’ (on which, see the
next note). For Plato insists that we have access to such inborn knowledge even before we become
aware of it; indeed, Socrates’ elenctic method relies precisely on this fact. But until we have been
questioned in the appropriate way, we do not become aware of it and so ‘recollect’ it.
21
Thus, I would maintain that Aristotle is concerned with what some theorists have called ‘phenomenal consciousness’, as distinct from ‘access consciousness’ (see, e. g., Block () ). Access consciousness, roughly speaking, is a matter of what information is available to a cognitive
agent in such a way that it can be directly controlled for use in reasoning and action. But it seems
that a cognitive system might utilize informational content in this way without experiencing it
phenomenally (as a zombie or a robot might); hence, the need for a distinct notion of phenomenal
consciousness.
760 Victor Caston
3. Perceiving that we perceive
We needn’t rely on hints and suggestions, though. Aristotle has much to
say about perceptual awareness, most prominently in the opening arguments of On the Soul . (b–). Starting from the assumption that
we do in fact perceive that we see and hear, he asks what must be the
case in order for this to be possible. In his view, only two lines of explanations are available, and one of them is open to objection. It will be
useful to begin with a representative translation, such as Hamlyn’s, and
to keep the Greek alongside, as much will turn on its interpretation:
É Epe‹ dÉ a7syanÒmeya ˜ti 6r«men ka‹ ékoÊomen, énãgkh µ tª ˆcei a7syãnesyai ˜ti 6rò, µ •t°r&. éllÉ 1 aÈtØ ¶stai t4w ˆcevw ka‹ toË Ípokeim°nou
xr2matow, Àste µ dÊo toË aÈtoË ¶sontai µ aÈtØ aÍt4w. ¶ti dÉ e7 ka‹ •t°ra
e‡h 1 t4w ˆcevw a‡syhsiw, µ e3w êpeiron e‰sin µ aÈtÆ tiw ¶stai aÍt4w: ÀstÉ
§p‹ t4w pr2thw toËto poiht°on.
Since we perceive that we see and hear, it must either be by sight that one
perceives that one sees or by another [sense]. But in that case there will be
the same [sense] for sight and the colour which is the subject for sight. So
that either there will be two senses for the same thing or [the sense itself] will
be the one for itself. Again, if the sense concerned with sight were indeed different from sight, either there will be an infinite regress or there will be some
[sense] which is concerned with itself; so that we had best admit this of the
first in the series. (b–)
On Hamlyn’s reading, Aristotle hopes to identify the capacity responsible for this sort of awareness, and he proceeds by dichotomy: as he
Such a distinction, however, raises the question of how Aristotle might respond to cases such
as ‘blindsight’ is alleged to be or, better still, visual form agnosia (as in the case of D. F. in Milner
and Goodale’s recent study (, esp. Ch. )), where a cognitive agent is able to utilize visual information in the execution of certain motor tasks, but reports not seeing the relevant features or
fails to recognize the objects or features as such—cases, that is, where an agent appears to have
access to perceptual information, without having phenomenal awareness of the items in question. Given his distinction between the animate and the inanimate, Aristotle must deny that such
cases constitute perception, since the subject is unaware (in the relevant sense) that he is undergoing the change in question. But he needn’t deny that such information is in some sense present in
the body and as such can affect behaviour. For while he maintains that all cases of perception and
thought involve ‘receiving form without the matter’ (On the Soul ., a–), it is not clear
that he maintains, or should maintain, the converse. That is, while every case of perceiving and
understanding involves receiving form without the matter, there may still be cases like an impression in wax or an image in a mirror, where a form is received without the matter and yet no cognition takes place. Receiving form without the matter would then be necessary, but not sufficient,
for perception and understanding. If so, then the cases in question could be explained as ones
where we receive form without the matter and so have the relevant information present in us,
even though we lack phenomenal awareness of it.
Of course, we have no idea how Aristotle himself would have reacted, if confronted with such
cases—they might genuinely lead him to reconsider his views on perception. My point here is
simply that he needn’t: there is room in his stated doctrines as they stand to accommodate the relevant distinctions. (I am grateful to Mike Martin for the reference to Milner and Goodale.)
Aristotle on Consciousness 761
states in the first sentence, either it is (i) the same capacity by which we
originally perceive or (ii) a different one. It is a question, in effect, of
whether this awareness is somehow built into our perceptual abilities
from the start or results instead from some separate internal monitoring capacity — an ‘inner sense,’ if you will. Against the latter option,
Aristotle then offers two arguments, each a kind of reductio ad absurdum. According to the first, option (ii) leads to an unacceptable duplication of roles; according to the second, an infinite regress.
But option (i) is not without its problems. Aristotle immediately
goes on to pose an aporia concerning it, to which he offers two tentative
solutions — as he must, if his previous objections to option (ii) are
sound. Hamlyn renders this passage as follows:
¶xei dÉ épor3an: e7 går tÚ tª ˆcei a7syãnesya3 §stin 6rçn, 6rçtai d¢ xr«ma
µ tÚ ¶xon, e7 ˆceta3 tiw tÚ 6r«n, ka‹ xr«ma ßjei tÚ 6r«n pr«ton. fanerÚn
to3nun ˜ti oÈx ©n tÚ tª ˆcei a7syãnesyai: ka‹ går ˜tan mØ 6r«men, tª ˆcei
kr3nomen ka‹ tÚ skÒtow ka‹ tÚ f«w, éllÉ oÈx …saÊtvw. ¶ti d¢ ka‹ tÚ 6r«n
¶stin …w kexrvmãtistai: tÚ går a7syhtÆrion dektikÚn toË a7syhtoË êneu
t4w Ïlhw ßkaston: diÚ ka‹ épelyÒntvn t«n a7syht«n ¶neisin a7syÆseiw ka‹
fantas3ai §n to›w a7syhthr3oiw.
But this presents a difficulty; for if to perceive by sight is to see, and if one
sees colour or that which possesses colour, then, if one is to see that which
sees, that which sees primarily will have colour. It is clear then that to perceive by sight is not a single thing; for even when we do not see, it is by sight
that we judge both darkness and light, though not in the same way. Moreover, even that which sees is in a way coloured; for each sense-organ is receptive of the object of perception without its matter. That is why perceptions
and imaginings remain in the sense-organs even when the objects of perception are gone.(b–)
Aristotle does not offer any further elaboration or endorsement. But to
all appearances, he seems to think at least one of these solutions is sufficient to save (i): that it is by means of sight itself that one perceives that
one sees.
Despite their superficial plausibility, Aristotle’s initial arguments
(b–) have been found puzzling;22 and so, in an effort to illuminate their exact nature, several recent commentators have appealed to
the larger context.23 But insufficient attention may have been paid to
the passage itself, which contains a fundamental ambiguity in its terminology. The word that Hamlyn, and virtually every other modern
22
Hamlyn () , pp. –; Kosman , pp. –; Osborne , pp. –.
23
Kosman ; Osborne .
762 Victor Caston
translator,24 renders as ‘sense’—namely, the Greek a‡syhsiw—can signify either
a. the capacity (dÊnamiw) of perception, i. e., the sense
b. the activity (§n°rgeia) of this capacity, that is, the perception or
perceiving.
Aristotle places a great deal of emphasis on this distinction in his psychology. It is the central theme of an earlier chapter in the treatise, On
the Soul ., in which he lays the foundations of his theory of perception. And it figures prominently in the present chapter, just after the
passage we are considering; indeed, Aristotle chastises his predecessors
for not appreciating the difference (., b–a, esp. a–).
The word ‘hearing’ (ékoÆ), he notes, can be understood in both ways,
as can all the words used for perceptions and perceptibles (a–). In
some cases, there may be a word reserved specifically for the activity,
such as ‘seeing’ (˜rasiw, a–).25 But by itself the more common
term, ‘vision’ (ˆciw), remains unmarked and so can signify either a
capacity or activity.26 This distinction holds on a more general level as
well. Earlier in the treatise, Aristotle employs an analogy with vision
and perception in order to clarify his definition of the soul (., b–
a): the soul, like sight, is what a natural body capable of life first
attains (a–; cf. ., b–), namely, a capacity for certain
activities, in contrast with the activities themselves, like seeing, which
constitute its higher attainment.
If we look back at our passage, the words for ‘perception’ and ‘vision’
(or pronouns referring back to them) occur in every clause. Yet a simple reading, based exclusively on one sense or the other, seems to be
ruled out. Some occurrences are most plausibly construed as referring
to a capacity. For example, in his first attempt to answer the aporia,
Aristotle observes that ‘even when we are not seeing’ (ka‹ ˜tan mØ
6r«men) we can discriminate darkness by sight (tª ˆcei, b–), which
can only be the capacity. Other occurrences must refer to an activity,
though, as, for example, at the end of the passage, when Aristotle refers
in the plural to perceptions (a7syÆseiw, b) that persist in the organs
Aristotle on Consciousness 763
after the objects have gone. Clearly, then, a correct reading of the passage must employ both senses. Aristotle switches between them as his
argument requires, and, though potentially confusing, it need not
involve equivocation.
But obviously this leaves wide room for disagreement. The best
interpretation, I contend, against virtually all modern translations and
commentaries, construes this passage predominantly in terms of
activities—what I will call an ‘activity reading’ for short, even though it
does not construe every occurrence as referring to an activity. The easiest way to see this is by considering more closely what is involved in traditional ‘capacity readings’.
4. The duplication argument (capacity reading)
The motivation for a capacity reading appears to come directly from
context. Having finished his discussion of the individual senses, Aristotle begins Book of On the Soul by considering whether the five individual senses are sufficient to account for other perceptual abilities we
possess, such as perceiving common perceptibles, or discriminating the
perceptible qualities of one modality from another, or (on the capacity
reading) perceiving that we see or hear.27 On this reading, Aristotle
would be resisting here, as elsewhere, an unnecessary multiplication of
capacities, preferring instead to ground different abilities in a single
capacity.28
But construing the passage in this way puts it at odds, prima facie,
with other parts of his psychology. In On Sleep and Waking, Aristotle
expressly denies that we perceive that we see by the capacity of sight:
There is a certain common capacity that supervenes on the others, by which
one perceives that one is seeing and hearing. For it is surely not by sight that
one sees that one sees; and it is certainly not by taste or sight or both together
that one discerns, or is even capable of discerning, that sweet things are different from pale ones, but rather by a certain part common to all the sense
organs. For while there is a single sense and a single principal sense organ, its
27
24
For example, the translations of E. Wallace; J. A. Smith (Oxford translation); E. Rolfes; G. Rodier; Hett (Loeb); E. Barbotin (Budé); W. Theiler; Lawson-Tancred (Penguin), as well as the paraphrases in W. D. Ross’s commentary (, p. ) and Kosman , p. .
25
Cf. On the Soul ., b–a; ., a–; On Perception and Perceptibles , a–; On
Dreams , b–; Metaph. ., a, .
26
Against Horn , p. . See Bonitz () , a–b, esp. a–b.
Thus Hicks , ad loc.; Ross , ad loc.
See On the Soul ., a–b, for his general opposition to the unnecessary multiplication
of capacities in psychology. Aristotle frequently attempts to consolidate different abilities into a
single capacity: the ability to reproduce and the ability to digest, for example, are both said to belong to the nutritive capacity (., a); the capacity for phantasia (tÚ fantastikÒn) and for desire (tÚ ÙrektikÒn) are each held to be ‘one and the same’ as the capacity for perception (tÚ
a7syhtikÒn), though ‘different in being’ (On Dreams , a–; On the Soul ., a–); and
finally, while all the senses differ from one another in being, the capacity for perception is one and
the same in number (On Perception and Perceptibles , a–).
28
764 Victor Caston
Aristotle on Consciousness 765
. [If a sense other than sight is involved,]33 there will be a sense
for both sight and the azure colour of the sky.
being is different for the perception of each genus [of perceptible], such as
sound and colour.(, a–)
While seeing is proprietary to sight (‡dion, a–), perceiving that we
see belongs to the perceptual system as a whole, which, though unified,
can function in diverse ways.29 It is not specifically in so far as one is
exercising one’s visual capacity, that is, that one perceives that one sees.
One might try to explain this discrepancy in a number of ways. One
might appeal, for example, to one of a number of developmental
hypotheses, depending on which passage one takes to express Aristotle’s
more mature, considered view.30 Alternatively, one might question
whether Aristotle takes any definite view in On the Soul . in the first
place, construing his arguments instead as merely exploratory and dialectical.31 Or again, one might argue that in the end the two passages
amount to much the same thing, though expressed in different ways.32
A capacity reading must, however, give some answer to this question.
And it should not be one that makes Aristotle’s considered view vulnerable to the arguments at the opening of On the Soul .. A capacity
reading thus poses problems for the view that Aristotle is ultimately
committed to a distinct inner sense, by which we ‘perceive that we see
and hear’ (see pp. , ).
Assume a satisfactory answer can be found. The more pressing question is whether a capacity reading can make good sense of the arguments in On the Soul . themselves. Start with the first argument,
concerning an unacceptable duplication (b–). Suppose I am out
one day, admiring the azure colour of the sky: I see it and luxuriate in
the experience of it. On the capacity reading, the argument should then
run roughly as follows:
29
According to Osborne , the fact that Aristotle mentions the ability to perceive that we see
and the ability to discriminate the objects of different sense modalities in close proximity to one
another, in both On Sleep and Waking and On the Soul . (b–a), is not accidental: his
concern with perceiving that we see or hear is not about self-awareness, but only our ability to distinguish which modality is in use, to perceive that we are seeing, for example, rather than hearing.
See also Horn , –. Against this view, see p. 771 below.
30
For the view that On Sleep and Waking expresses Aristotle’s ultimate view, see Block ;
Block , esp. p. . For the contrary view, see Torstrik , pp. –, note *.
31
Hicks , pp. , ; Kahn () , p. ; Osborne , p. .
Neuhaeuser , pp. –; Baeumker , pp. –; Rodier , .–; Hamlyn ,
p. ; Kahn () , pp. –, ; Osborne , p. ; Modrak , pp. –.
32
. But if there is a sense for both sight and the azure colour of the
sky, then there will be two senses that have azure as their object
. But there cannot be two senses that have azure as their object.
If so, then we must reject the antecedent of (), and with it the antecedent of ():
∴ . No sense other than sight is involved.
Given the alternatives from which he starts, Aristotle can then easily
conclude that the first sense must be ‘of itself ’.
Several features of this argument seem odd.34 Why exactly should
azure, an object of the first sense, sight, also be an object of the second,
as () claims? After all, it starts from the assumption that the second
sense is different from sight. What, then, is the basis for thinking that a
different sense must share the same objects? Suppose, on the other
hand, that azure is an object of this second sense as well. Why would the
duplication mentioned in () be objectionable, as () claims? It seems
that any reason for endorsing () will count against (), and vice versa;
and thus it is hard to imagine someone having motivation to accept
both at once. But one must, if the argument is to offer a sound basis for
endorsing (). The intended conclusion, after all, is only a denial of the
antecedent of (). The conditional as a whole must nevertheless be true.
Most interpreters seek to defend () by appealing to Aristotle’s own
doctrines. As a colour, azure is a perceptible ‘proprietary ’ (‡dion) to
sight and so, by definition, cannot be the object of any sense other than
sight (., a–).35 Yet this should only make it harder for a good
33
The restriction to cases where there is a distinct sense is not actually in Aristotle’s text, but is
supplied by many translations and commentaries: Alex. Aphr. Quaest. ., .– Bruns; Themistius In De an. . Heinze; Ross , ad loc.; cf. also the translations of Wallace, Rodier, Hamlyn, Tricot, Barbotin. The translations of Hicks and Smith are more faithful to the text: they
represent the inference as following instead from the initial premiss—namely, that we perceive
that we see—which is neutral between the options Aristotle is considering (see below, p. and
Osborne , p. ).
This difference does not affect the final conclusion of the argument, since the crucial inference
still concerns the alternative where a different sense is involved. But it makes a difference as to the
logical structure of the argument.
34
See n. above.
Alexander Quaest. ., .–; Hicks , p. ad loc.; Ross , p. ad loc.; Hamlyn
() , p. ; Kosman , p. . One of the few exceptions is Osborne (, pp. –),
who rightly questions the introduction of this assumption into Aristotle’s argument.
35
766 Victor Caston
Aristotle on Consciousness 767
Aristotelian to accept () in the first place: on what principle can it be
demanded that a sense and its proprietary perceptibles must be objects
of the second sense? Not any of Aristotle’s own principles, on pain of
contradiction; nor any intuitive one, given how recondite the question
is to begin with.36 In any event, the appeal to proprietary perceptibles
does not suffice for rejecting the consequent of (). Suppose the second
sense is also a sense of sight, a possibility not obviously excluded here –
in positing a different sense, one needn’t assume that it is different in
kind. But then azure can be proprietary to both senses without contradiction, just as it in fact is for both eyes. We cannot validly infer, therefore, that no other sense is involved, nor that the first sense must sense
itself, as Aristotle claims (b). On this reading, then, the inferences
are both puzzling and inconclusive.
Consider the reading itself more closely, though. Taken literally, what
() states is that there will be a single sense for both azure and the capacity of sight (t4w ˆcevw, b). That is, it is not the activity of sight that
one perceives, according to this reading, but the capacity itself:
An azure sky
Sight
nd Sense
Diagram
So, too, in the upshot of the argument: once a duplication of capacities
has been excluded, it is supposed to follow that the first sense will be a
sense of itself (aÈtØ aÍt4w, b). In line with this, one could perhaps
even construe Aristotle’s opening remark that ‘we perceive that we see’
(b) as claiming only that we perceive that we are seeing creatures, the
sort of creatures that have the capacity to see, rather than that we are
exercising this capacity on a given occasion, that we are in fact now perceiving. The latter is something Aristotle countenances elsewhere (tÚ
a7syanÒmenon ˜ti §nergoËmen, Àste a7syano3meyÉ ín ˜ti a7syanÒmeya,
36
The intuitions most naturally invoked here would appeal to the activities involved. But at the
moment we are considering a reading exclusively in terms of capacities. For a reading that combines intuitions about activities with a capacity reading, see below pp. –.
Nic. Eth. ., a–; see below, p. 774). But on this way of construing the text, it would not be what was at stake here.
Though just possible as a reading of the Greek, this is surely an
unnatural way of taking Aristotle. To perceive that we have a given
capacity is a fairly reflective ability, presupposing a fairly rich conceptual repertoire—not something one could take for granted in all perceivers, or even all human perceivers, as Aristotle seems to at the
beginning of the chapter. In fact, as he himself insists earlier in On the
Soul, to arrive at an understanding of our capacities, one must already
grasp the activities that correspond to them (., a–). So even if
one were to insist on such a strong capacity reading—call it the extreme
capacity reading—one would still have to tell some story about how we
apprehend the activity of perceiving as well.
Most translations in fact conform to an extreme capacity reading.
But I doubt whether anyone has ever really considered it seriously. Most
discussions assume that we perceive that we are seeing on a given occasion (b); and that it is not sight, but seeing (t4w ˆcevw, b), that is
perceived along with the colour seen. One can make these modifications, moreover, without completely foregoing a capacity reading. The
argument’s main concern can still be over which capacities are required
for such perceptions. All that has changed is that the object of such perceptions will be the activity of these capacities, and not the capacities
themselves. Call this alternative the moderate capacity reading, a reading already developed at length by Alexander of Aphrodisias (Quaestiones ., .–. Bruns):
An azure sky
Seeing
Perceiving
Sight
nd Sense
Diagram
Such a reading smooths over some of the difficulties of the previous
one, while retaining the same general contour. As with the extreme
capacity reading, the objection still turns on a duplication of capacities;
and it still invokes the definition of proprietary perceptibles to rule out
this possibility (.–). But by introducing activities, the moderate
768 Victor Caston
capacity reading gives () above a more intuitive appeal. One cannot be
aware of seeing, at least not by perceiving it,37 without also being aware
of seeing something seen—precisely the assumption Aristotle makes in
On Perception and Perceptibles (, a–; quoted above, p. ). Perceiving what is initially seen will thus be an integral part of perceiving
one’s visual activity (.–; cf. Them. In De an. .–).
As a reading of the Greek, however, the moderate version is quite
strained. It requires us to take activities and capacities to be referred to
in rapid alternation: 6r«men and ékoÊomen at b signify activities; then
tª ˆcei, •t°r&, and 1 aÈtÆ at b signify capacities; t4w ˆcevw follows
again in the very next line at b, but this time it signifies an activity;
and then we switch back again to capacities with dÊo and aÈtÆ at b–
. This alternation reaches its nadir in the argument’s very last phrase.
According to the moderate capacity reading, the conclusion should be
that the sense in question is itself the sense for its own perceptual activity. But the Greek simply reads: ‘it [will be] of itself ’ (aÈtØ aÍt4w, b; cf.
b). To read an alternation within this phrase would be too harsh; and
the reflexive pronoun precludes it entirely. In this argument, then, Aristotle must be speaking either solely of capacities or solely of activities.
There is no reason to cling to a capacity reading. The advantages of
the moderate version are due entirely to the introduction of activities,
while its difficulties stem from the continued appeal to capacities. This
holds true even more for the subsequent regress argument. It is possible, on the other hand, to read the first section (b–) solely in terms
of activities, while making excellent sense of the arguments; and the
brief shift to capacities that occurs later at b and b, when Aristotle
raises the aporia, is easily explained (see p. – below). I will therefore leave capacity readings aside from here on out. The activity reading, as we shall see, is simpler and philosophically more compelling.
5. The duplication argument (activity reading)
The only activity readings I have been able to find are (i) in Franz Brentano’s Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (() , Book ,
Chs –)—not, it should be noted, in his earlier Psychology of Aristotle,
which adopts a moderate capacity reading (, pp. –)—and (ii) in
a dissertation by J. Herman Schell (). The dissertation, though, was
written under Brentano’s direction contemporaneously with Psychology
from an Empirical Standpoint; and, as Carl Stumpf was later to remark,
Brentano could get so involved in directing a dissertation that he would
37
Against Hamlyn () , pp. –; cf. Kosman , pp. –. See below, p. 771.
Aristotle on Consciousness 769
‘practically grab the pencil from your hand’ (, p. f.). Brentano is
setting forth his own theory of intentionality and consciousness in
these pages. But he frequently credits Aristotle as his inspiration: much
of the Psychology’s second book, in fact, can profitably be viewed as an
extended meditation on On the Soul .. Usually it is difficult to find
more than a hint of Brentano’s ideas in the Aristotelian texts he cites.
But in this case, I think he had genuine insight.
Consider the opening of On the Soul . again, but now construed
entirely in terms of activities:
Since we perceive that we see and hear, it is necessarily either by means of the
seeing that one perceives that one sees or by another [perception]. But the
same [perception] will be both of the seeing and of the colour that underlies
it, with the result that either two [perceptions] will be of the same thing, or
it [sc. the perception] will be of itself. (b–)
Aristotle’s interest, on this reading, is with the structure, if you will, of
perceptual activity, as it is in the passage that immediately follows
(b–a); and in both passages his aim is to show how the richness of perceptual encounters can be accounted for with a certain metaphysical economy. The duplication argument is a case in point. On
Aristotle’s view, perceiving that we perceive is integral to the original
perceiving. Treating it as a separate activity would produce a redundancy contrary to the phenomena.
On this reading, Aristotle speaks of ‘perceptions of perceptions’. Such
nominalizations can easily lead to misunderstandings and so need to be
handled with care. Two points should be kept in mind here about Aristotle’s usage:
First, Aristotle clearly intends such expressions to be cashed out in
terms of our perceiving that we perceive. He begins the passage ‘since
we perceive that we see and hear’ (§pe‹ a7syanÒmeya ˜ti 6r«men ka‹
ékouÒmen, b) and immediately continues by asking whether we do
this by means of the seeing or some other act (tª ˆcei … µ •t°r&, b).
It is not, therefore, mental states like perceptions that are aware, strictly
speaking, but rather the animals themselves who have these mental
states. (Compare his similar insistence that it is not the soul which perceives or thinks, but the person who has a soul: On the Soul ., b–
.) Aristotle can thus agree with current philosophers of mind who
stress that only animals can be conscious in the sense of being aware of
something or (in the current idiom) having ‘transitive consciousness’.38
Even when we identify certain mental states as ‘conscious states’, they
38
For example, Malcolm , p. ; Armstrong , pp. –; Rosenthal a; Rosenthal
, pp. –; Dretske , pp. –; Dretske , p. .
770 Victor Caston
are not aware of what they are about, but only the animals who are in
these states. Nevertheless, Aristotle can rejoin that it is precisely in virtue of certain mental states being directed at mental states that we are
transitively conscious. So it is natural for him to speak in terms of ‘perceptions of perceptions’ and it need not confuse matters.39
Secondly, in speaking of ‘perceptions of perceptions’, Aristotle is not
limiting such perception to what has been called the ‘awareness of
things’, as opposed to the ‘awareness of facts’.40 On the contrary, as he
states in the opening phrase, ‘we perceive that we see’: that is, we perceive a perception as being a certain kind of perception and as having a
certain content. Awareness of it under just any aspect or other would
not necessarily count (for example, as an event going on within my
body such as could be observed with an autocerebrescope or rather,
given Aristotle’s theory, an autocardioscope). The nominalized formulation, ‘a perception of ’, therefore, need not be restricted to the awareness of things. It can apply to both types of awareness. Aristotle’s
tolerance for this ambiguity can be excused on account of the argument’s focus on how many events there are, as opposed to the structure
of its content.41 For this purpose, the nominalized formulation is not
inappropriate.
On an activity reading, the argument can now be analysed as follows.
The first inference is meant to flow directly from the initial assumption
that we perceive that we see and hear, whichever of the two subsequent
alternatives turns out to be the case.42 It is meant to be neutral between
39
Rosenthal (, p. ) objects to the ‘metaphor of reflexivity’ on the grounds that only
‘creature consciousness’ can be transitive. But defending his own view later on, he acknowledges
that there is a sense after all in which we can speak of transitive states of consciousness, since of
course it is in virtue of some state that the owner is transitively conscious (p. ); in fact, such
states are crucial to Rosenthal’s own analysis. A similar response can be made to his objection that
such states would refer to themselves rather than the self (p. ). It is in virtue of such states’ being directed at themselves that we are conscious of ourselves having them (cf. On Perception and
Perceptibles , a–).
40
them:
1′. Given that we perceive that we see, there will be a single perception of both our seeing and the azure of the sky.
Put more simply, perceiving that we see is a perception both of our seeing and of the object seen. There are perhaps circumstances, in which it
is true to say that ‘I perceive that I see’ without my having perceived
what I am seeing.43 But Aristotle can simply respond that that is not the
kind of awareness he has in mind here—(′), that is, can serve to constrain the relevant sense in which Aristotle says we ‘perceive that we see’.
It is not a matter of being informed that we are seeing, rather than
merely dreaming; or discerning that we are seeing rather than, say, hearing.44 It is perceiving that we are undergoing a visual experience with a
particular content. Otherwise, (′) will seem gratuitous.
At this point, Aristotle can then invoke his initial dichotomy: is this
perception a different activity from the original act of seeing or is it the
same?
′. We perceive that we see either (i) by means of a distinct, new
perception or (ii) by means of the initial perception, the seeing.
Applying this dichotomy to (′) gives us the exact disjunction we find in
Aristotle’s text:
∴ ′. Either (a) there will be two perceptions of the same thing
(namely, azure), or (b) the one perception will also be of itself.
Aristotle’s reasoning here is straightforward, though compressed. Perceiving that we are seeing azure is directed at the colour azure as much
as seeing it is. Therefore, if (i) seeing and perceiving that we are seeing
are distinct activities, then (a) there will be two perceptions directed at
the same object:45
An azure sky
Dretske , pp. –; , pp. –; cf. , pp. –, p. .
41
Aristotle’s use of ‘that’ clauses, on the other hand, may leave him open to the objection that
his theory doesn’t really involve the perception of perceptions, but rather something more conceptual, like thought or belief—cf. Dretske , pp. –. A satisfactory answer to this objection will
depend on the details of Aristotle’s analysis of perceptual content, where matters are unfortunately
less clear. In general, Aristotle is comfortable using ‘that’ clauses in reporting the content of perceptions. But he also believes that nonhuman animals have perceptions while lacking the capacity
for thought and concepts (on his understanding of these terms). Whether this tension can be resolved and if so, how, constitutes a genuine difficulty that would require proper treatment in its
own right.
On this point, I agree with the translations of both Hicks and Smith (see n. above). The
phrases other translators are forced to insert here (e. g., ‘in the latter case’) misrepresent the actual
structure of Aristotle’s argument.
42
Aristotle on Consciousness 771
Seeing
Perceiving
Diagram
43
See n. above.
44
As Osborne argues.
45
Note that this objection holds whether there are two capacities involved or only one: it does
not matter which capacities each activity issues from, so long as there are two activities with the
relevant sort of contents. The activity reading thus addresses the problem of duplication more
generally than capacity readings do.
772 Victor Caston
On the other hand, if (ii) they are not distinct, then perceiving that we
are seeing azure will be one and the same activity as seeing it; and so (b)
a single activity will also be ‘of itself ’. Aristotle can then arrive at his
intended result by eliminating the first disjunct, (a):
′. But there are not two perceptions of the same thing (namely,
azure).
It does not matter whether the second activity is supposed to issue from
a distinct capacity, such as an inner sense, or from the original capacity
of sight. For alternative (a) is unacceptable on phenomenological
grounds: we are not constantly undergoing a kind of double vision or,
more generally, always attending reflectively to the content of our mental states.46 By rejecting any duplication of activities, Aristotle opts for a
more basic form of awareness. It does not consist in an activity extrinsic
to our perceptions, but is rather something intrinsic to the original
activity itself.
This reading finds external support from a parallel passage in Plato’s
Charmides.47 Under questioning, Charmides accepts a definition of
temperance as a kind of self-knowledge, one that ‘does not know anything except itself and all other knowledge’ (BC); and Socrates then
goes on to challenge it by offering other mental states as counterexamples (C–A). One cannot, he argues, have a vision that ‘sees only
itself and other visions, but no colour’ (ˆcevn ˆciw); nor, mutatis
mutandis, in other cases:
hearing of hearings (ékoÆn … éko«n)
perception of perceptions (a7syÆsevn a‡syhsiw)
desire of desires (§piyum3a … §piyumi«n)
intending intentions (boÊlhsiw … boulÆseiw boÊletai)
love of loves (¶rvw … §r2tvn)
fearing fears (fÒbon, 8w . . . fÒbouw fobe›tai)
belief of beliefs (doj«n dÒjan).
46
This is not to deny that in some cases we can have a kind of reflective awareness of this sort,
but just to insist that it is not always the case. Aristotle certainly allows that there can be reflective
awareness of one token mental state by means of another; but it is not the kind of awareness that
constitutes consciousness on his view (see below, p. –).
47
As noticed by both Shorey (, pp. –) and Hicks (, p. ), though it seems not sufficiently appreciated by either: neither recognizes the incompatibility of this passage with their
own (moderate) capacity readings of Aristotle.
Aristotle on Consciousness 773
The plurals plainly indicate activities of a given type, not a plurality of
capacities (either in oneself or in others). What Socrates denies is that
these activities can be the object of the same type of activity while their
own objects are not—precisely the assumption underlying the duplication argument’s first premiss, (′), on an activity reading (see pp. –
above). And the argument that immediately follows in the Charmides
closely resembles the subsequent aporia Aristotle develops as well. Socrates remarks, ‘and so I suppose that vision, if it sees itself, will necessarily have a certain colour, since visions could not ever see anything
uncoloured’ (DE).48 Such parallels cannot safely be ignored. Plato’s
arguments in the Charmides clearly supply the germ for Aristotle’s
duplication argument. But they also require an activity reading, and
that is a strong reason for reading Aristotle the same way.
6. The regress argument (activity reading)
Now consider the regress argument. Here is how it would be translated
on a straight activity reading:
Further, if the perception of seeing is a different [perception], either this will
proceed to infinity or some [perception] will be of itself; so that we ought to
posit this in the first instance.(b–)
Although abbreviated, Aristotle’s reasoning can be easily spelled out.
The argument would proceed as follows:
. I perceive that I see and so have a perception of a perception.
. Any perception of a perception is distinct from the earlier one
(namely, from the perception it is a perception of).
∴ . Whenever one perceives, there will be an infinite chain of perceptions, each new one being a perception of the earlier one.
. But it is impossible to have an infinite chain of perceptions—
any such chain would have to be finite.
∴ . Some perception—namely, the last member of a chain of
perceptions—will be a perception of itself.
48
Although Plato uses the word dÊnamiw (D) in setting out the underlying principle, it is not
used in the sense a capacity reading requires, since Socrates first applies this word to a mathematical case, being greater than, which does not admit of the activity/capacity distinction. His point
rather is that psychological activities, like comparatives, are relative: a perception, for example, is
always of something, just as what is greater is always greater than something (B). Gadamer perhaps overstates the case (, p. ), however, when he takes the meaning of the expression to be
the same as what Aristotle classes as ‘relatives’ (tå prÒw ti).
774 Victor Caston
. But there is no more reason for some perceptions rather than
others to be perceptions of themselves.
∴ . The first perception is already a perception of itself and there is
no need to posit a second.
As it stands, the argument is obviously invalid. () and () cannot produce the regress derived in () without additional premisses. Nevertheless, they may have been tacitly assumed by Aristotle, since both are
generalizations of points made earlier in the passage.
The first is fairly formal. Aristotle must exclude ‘loops’ of perceptions: no perception can be a perception-ancestor, as it were, of itself.
But this is guaranteed by an assumption from the duplication argument, once suitably generalized, namely,
A. A perception of a perception is also of what the earlier perception is of.
But so generalized, the principle is plainly transitive, in which case
loops will entail self-perception: if a is a perception of b, and b of g,
and g of a, then it follows from (A) that a will be a perception of itself.
But that is explicitly ruled out by () above; and hence there cannot be
any loops. (A) is sufficient, therefore, to close off this loophole.
The second premiss Aristotle needs to derive () is more substantive,
as it is this primarily that fuels the regress:
B. Whenever we have a perception, we have a perception of that
perception.
Without this assumption, there is no reason to posit a new perception
at each successive level. Aristotle may view it, however, as an acceptable
generalization of the opening of the chapter, when he claims that we
perceive that we see and hear (b). It is, at any rate, something he
believes. He states it explicitly in Nicomachean Ethics .:
The person seeing perceives that he is seeing, the person hearing [perceives]
that he is hearing, the person walking [perceives] that he is walking, and similarly in other cases there is something that perceives that we are in activity,
so that we will perceive that we perceive and think that we think. But [to perceive] that we perceive or [to think that] we think is [to perceive or think]
that we are (for in this case to be is to perceive or to think).49 (a–b; cf.
On Perception and Perceptibles , a–)
Aristotle on Consciousness 775
(B) appears to be genuinely Aristotelian, then. In fact, Aristotle seems
to accept an even more general version, which applies, among other
things, to all occurrent mental states (˜ti §nergoËmen).50 It is obviously
controversial.
49
Reading Àste a7syano3meyÉ ín ˜ti a7syanÒmeya ka‹ noo›men ˜ti nooËmen at a with the
mss., rather than Bywater’s emended version (, pp. –), which replaces a7syano3meyÉ ín with
ín a7syan2meyÉ and ka‹ noo›men with kín no«men. Although frequently accepted, these emendations are not necessary either for grammar or sense; and they have profound doctrinal ramifications (which Kahn ([] , –, for example, tries to exploit). By inserting subjunctives,
Bywater changes these phrases into general conditionals, in order to understand an implicit
a7syanÒmeya both before ˜ti a7syanÒmeya and ˜ti nooËmen, the latter being crucial for his reading,
since it suggests that all consciousness for Aristotle, much as for Locke, is a function of inner sense,
including the awareness of thoughts. But the text of the manuscripts makes a simple assertoric
claim about our perceiving that we perceive and thinking that we think, in line with the claim in
Metaph. ., b, a text Kahn is implausibly forced to dismiss as ‘only … a dialectical, aporetic
discussion’, in order to bring it in line with Bywater’s emendation (p. ). It is surely better to stay
with an intelligible manuscript reading, that connects easily with others in the corpus.
50
Interestingly, Aristotle does not insist that we perceive all such states, nor that we have
thoughts about all such states, but claims only that we perceive that we perceive and think that we
think. This might lead one to conjecture that Aristotle accepts all instances of the following
schema,
If one c’s, then one c’s that one c’s
where ‘c’ is replaced by a mental verb, like ‘perceives’ or ‘thinks’; and perhaps, even more strongly,
that the only modality such higher-order cognitions can have will be the same as the first. But such
a conjecture leads to absurdities, even in its weaker form. Not only would we have to taste that we
are tasting and smell that we are smelling, which seems strange enough; we would also have to desire that we are desiring and imagine that we are imagining, neither of which has much to do with
our being aware that we are desiring or imagining. Worse, it requires that whenever we doubt, we
must doubt that we are doubting and whenever we disbelieve something, we disbelieve that we are
disbelieving, both of which are plainly untrue.
But nothing Aristotle says requires such a hypothesis. It extrapolates crudely from the two examples he offers without reflecting sufficiently on his larger aims. To generalize his point to all occurrent mental states, he does not even need to go beyond the two modalities he mentions. The
higher-order modality, that is, need only be either a perception or a thought, depending on which
type of lower-order state is involved. Thus, for example, he might hold that
. If one c’s, then one perceives that one c’s
when ‘c’ expresses a perceptual activity (or perhaps even a quasi-perceptual activity, such as visualizing), and
. If one c’s, then one thinks that one c’s
when ‘c’ expresses a non-perceptual mental activity. Such restricted generalizations avoid all of the
consequences just mentioned. First, they avoid any commitment to specific modalities and quality
spaces for higher-order awareness, like tasting or smelling. More importantly, they preclude the alleged counterexamples on principled, rather than ad hoc grounds: () perceiving and thinking are
cognitive states, unlike desiring; () they are affirmative, involving a kind of endorsement, unlike
disbelieving, doubting, merely entertaining, considering, or imagining; and finally, () they are occurrent, unlike believing or knowing. Because such characteristics are necessary for the kind of
awareness Aristotle is interested in, they help motivate a restricted generalization; and the different
types of lower-order states involved motivate the combination of two such generalizations into a
hybrid account.
776 Victor Caston
7. Aristotle and higher-order theories
Faced with a similar regress, higher-order theories of consciousness
maintain that one should simply abandon (B) and with it the claim that
every mental state is conscious.51 Consciousness, on this view, is not an
intrinsic feature of mental states. It is something relational: roughly, a
mental state is conscious just in case a mental state of the right sort is
about, or directed at, the first. Different versions of the theory will spell
out ‘of the right sort’ differently. But all such views accept something
like (), since the higher-order state that makes a perception
conscious — whether it is a perception of a perception or a thought
about a perception—will be distinct from the original perception. But
this is not thought to be problematic, since regress no longer threatens
once (B) has been rejected. The central intuition behind such theories,
as mentioned above (see p. ), is that consciousness is a form of
intentionality; and it is this alone, according to the view’s proponents,
which permits an informative explanation of consciousness. Theories
that take consciousness to be an intrinsic feature of mental states, they
argue, have little choice but to take it as a primitive, irreducible
attribute, about which little more can be said. But if consciousness is
instead a special case of intentionality, as higher-order theories claim, it
will possess an ‘articulated structure’: one mental state is related to
another by being intentionally directed upon it. And this gives us the
means to explain consciousness in terms of simpler elements, each of
which is familiar and (allegedly) more tractable.52
What is interesting about Aristotle’s position is that he is equally able
to deliver what higher-order theories demand. For consciousness on his
view is a matter of intentionality too. Not only are we aware of other
things by means of intentional states; we can become aware of these
states themselves by means of intentional states, thus making the
former ‘conscious’ (in one sense of the word, at any rate).53 A percep51
Brentano himself (() , ., n. *) cites Herbart –, .., §, .– and ..,
sect. , .. And it occurs frequently after that: for example, Russell () , p. ; Grossmann , pp. –; Armstrong , pp. , ; Grossmann , pp. –; Rosenthal , p.
; Francescotti , p. . But the response is much older. Its kernel can already be found in
Hobbes’s second objection in the Third Set of Objections to Descartes’s Meditations (AT .) and
in Leibniz’s Nouveaux essais sur l’entendement .., .– Gerhardt.
52
See n. above. Occasionally, Rosenthal recognizes that a reflexive account like Aristotle’s and
Brentano’s can provide this benefit too (, n. ), but he complains that the theory is unmotivated. Against this, see p. below.
53
Dretske has recently called into question whether this is the pertinent sense of ‘conscious,’
thus challenging a higher-order account like Rosenthal’s. For Rosenthal, a mental state is not conscious unless it is the object of an appropriate higher-order state (; b; ). For Dretske, a
.
Aristotle on Consciousness 777
tion, for example, is conscious only if there is a perception of it, only if
we perceive that we perceive. But then Aristotle likewise relies on the
notion of higher-order states and a ‘relational’ conception of consciousness. And this, in turn, allows him the kind of informative explanation that higher-order theories claim they alone can provide: because
of the role of intentionality, consciousness will possess the sort of articulated structure that makes analysis and explanation possible. Yet Aristotle insists that this feature is intrinsic to the conscious state —
precisely the thesis that higher-order theories reject and their opponents demand. How can he have it both ways?
Higher-order theories typically assume that the higher-order mental
state is always a distinct token from the state it is directed upon.54 After
all, one might argue, no state can be of a higher-order than itself. But
when we speak of ‘higher-order mental states’ there is an ambiguity
between type and token; and what moves us to posit such states primarily concerns their type. The expressions ‘first-order’ and ‘higher-order’
refer to the type of content a mental state possesses, depending on
whether or not it has the content of other mental states embedded
within its content. Aristotle’s response to the regress argument distinguishes, in effect, between the question of how many types of content
are instantiated and the question of how many token mental states
there are. He agrees that there is a higher-order content —perceiving
that we perceive—as well as the first-order content of the original perception. But this is independent of how many token mental states are
mental state can be conscious even if this is not the case, so long as the state is itself directed at
something (Dretske , esp. p. ; , pp. –). But it is not clear whether they are simply
arguing past each other here, by considering different senses in which a mental state might be conscious. Brentano (() , .) correctly points out that there are two ways in which we can
speak of a mental state as ‘conscious’, by distinguishing active and passive senses of the term, depending on whether the state is itself an awareness of something (active) or whether there is an
awareness of it (passive). Dretske gives pride of place to the former, Rosenthal to the latter. But
apart from whether one of these constitutes ‘the’ primary sense of the word ‘conscious,’ many of
their points are compatible with one another
54
For example, Rosenthal , p. (though cf. Rosenthal b, pp. –). Armstrong
goes even further, arguing not only that the higher- and lower-order states are ‘distinct existences’
(p. ), but that it is logically impossible for them to be the same (p. ; cf. p. ). A more moderate position can be found in Gennaro , in so far as he makes the higher-order thought part
of a complex state that includes the lower-order state as a proper part. But he still requires the two
parts to be distinct and insists that the higher-order thought is not strictly speaking reflexive, but
directed at a distinct part of the complex state (p. ). The difference between these two versions of
the theory turns on the question of which features entail a difference in states and which merely a
difference in parts. But, as Rosenthal suggests (, p. ), there does not seem to be a non-arbitrary way of choosing between these two ways of describing a higher-order theory; and so it is not
clear whether the difference here is anything more than verbal. Making the relation reflexive, in
contrast, would introduce a substantive difference, and both reject it.
778 Victor Caston
Aristotle on Consciousness 779
involved.55 And he believes that no other token state is required to make
the original state conscious. The original state instantiates both lowerand higher-order contents:
Seeing
An azure sky
Perceiving
Diagram
Because a higher-order content type is involved, consciousness is still
intentional and hence relational. But in so far as only one token is
involved, it must be a reflexive relation: in addition to being directed
upon an external object, such as an azure sky, the token activity will be
directed upon itself.56 Such awareness is immediate. It is unmediated by
any further token activity, let alone a representation of itself; nor is
there is any transition between the perception and the awareness of it,
and hence no inference or causal relation between them. The relation is
more intimate: both aspects are essential to any token perception.
Rosenthal (b, ; , ) argues that the two must be distinct, because of the difference in their truth conditions. But this again only requires a difference in type, not in token.
55
56
The sense in which I am using ‘reflexive’ here is related to its logical sense and as such must be
carefully distinguished from the similar-sounding adjective, ‘reflective.’ I shall refer to a relation as
‘reflexive’ just in case
For any x and any y such that Rxy, it is the case that Rxx.
This is slightly weaker than what is technically referred to as a ‘reflexive relation’, in so far as the condition is only claimed to hold for the domain of the relation in question, rather than its entire field
(or the entire universe of discourse, if total, rather than partial, reflexivity is at issue). But these conditions are still analogous; and for convenience, I shall speak simply of ‘reflexivity’, without this
qualification. What is essential for our purposes is that any item that bears this sort of relation to
other things also bears that same relation to itself. For example, the relation is a divisor of is reflexive
in this sense: if x divides into y without remainder, it will also divide into itself without remainder;
but y will not in general divide into x (so long as y⫽x).
‘Reflective,’ in contrast, is a folk psychological term used to characterize our general state of
mind when we consider or ‘reflect on’ our own state of mind. But it need not imply reflexivity in
the sense I have given above: a theory could consistently hold that reflection always involves distinct token mental states.
For these reasons, Aristotle cannot accept an ‘inner sense’ or internal
scanner whose activities are distinct tokens from the activities they
monitor.57 The regress argument precludes any such view, by making
awareness intrinsic to the original perceptual activity. That having been
said, it no more follows that we perceive that we see by sight than it follows that we see that we see.58Aristotle always asserts that we perceive
that we see, never that we see that we see.59 In so far as this sort of
awareness is common to all perception, Aristotle is right to ascribe it to
the perceptual capacity as a whole in On Sleep and Waking (, a–
)—it is not something vision possesses in so far as it is specifically the
activity of sight. The perceptual system sees in virtue of its visual part.
But it perceives that it sees in virtue of the nature of perception more
generally (cf. On Perception and Perceptibles , a–, a–).60
These differences offer Aristotle several advantages over higher-order
theories. To mention just three:
(.) One of the costs of higher-order theories is that they are forced to
reject the strong intuition that consciousness is somehow intrinsic to
mental states.61 Aristotle’s account, in contrast, preserves this intuition,
without inviting the crude metaphors Ryle derided: Aristotle does not
accept a ‘phosphorescence-theory of consciousness’ any more than
higher-order theorists do (Ryle , p. , cf. pp. –); and perceptions are ‘self-luminous’ only in so far as we perceive them. What these
metaphors are grasping after is just the intuition that our awareness is
57
As appears to be maintained, for example, by Everson (, pp. –, but esp. p. ). For a
more nuanced variant of the inner sense interpretation and the difficulties it encounters, see p.
below.
58
Pace Grossmann (, p. ), whose worry is really a descendent of the objection raised at
the Charmides 168C–169A and repeated at On the Soul ., b–. But Aristotle’s answer shows
that he does not take the objection to be compelling: the activity of seeing is perceived, even if it is
not literally coloured and so not literally seen. See below, pp. –.
59
In the passage from On Sleep and Waking , Aristotle denies that we see that we see by sight
(a); and when ascribing our awareness to the ‘common capacity’, he affirms only that we perceive that we see (a–). Even if one were to follow conversational implicature and take his denial
to suggest that in some sense we do see that we see though not by sight, it needn’t pose an insurmountable difficulty. The verb ‘to see’ often has wider, epistemic uses in Indo-European languages
in a way that other perceptual verbs do not. Aristotle could not plausibly say that we ‘taste that we
taste’ or ‘smell that we smell’ (i. e., smell that we are are smelling).
60
Kosman argues that this is a matter of causal or functional dependence, that such awareness
cannot be achieved ‘in isolation from the powers of a whole living sentient being’ (, pp. –
). Although this is no doubt true, Aristotle’s argument in these passages is more modest, namely,
that such awareness is not peculiar (‡dion) to sight, but common (koinÒn) to sensitive capacities generally; and so sight does not possess it in so far as it is sight, but only in so far as it is perceptive.
61
See above, p. –. This is admitted by higher-order theorists themselves: Rosenthal ,
pp. , ; Rosenthal b, p. ; Gennaro , p. .
780 Victor Caston
not something extrinsic to the original states themselves. Higher-order
theories reject this, on the grounds that this awareness is relational. But
it does not follow: the intrinsic/extrinsic and relational/nonrelational
distinctions cut across one another. Thus Aristotle is free to hold that
this higher-order awareness is at once relational and intrinsic.
(.) A common objection to higher-order theories runs as follows.
When I am aware of a stone, it does not make the stone conscious; but
then why should my being aware of a mental state make it conscious?62
The point here, it should be stressed, is not a causal one, since it can be
rephrased without the causal suggestions of a verb like ‘makes.’ According to higher-order theories, a mental state is conscious in virtue of a
mental state being directed at it. But a stone is not said to be conscious,
even if a mental state is directed at it.
Higher-order theories seem to have only two responses available to
them: (i) to concede that stones are ‘conscious’, but insist that this must
be understood as a relational, rather than an intrinsic property;63 or (ii)
to deny that stones are conscious, on the grounds that only mental
states can be made conscious.64 The first solution seems to miss the
intuitive force of the objection, while the second seems ad hoc, in effect
labelling the problem, rather than solving it.
Aristotle has a more satisfying response. Since the consciousnessmaking relation is a reflexive form of awareness (see n. above), the
only thing that could be made conscious by a mental state is that mental
state itself. If stones had intentional states, they might also be eligible.
But they don’t. Aristotle can therefore maintain that stones are not conscious in any sense and explain why on principled grounds. Not having
intentional states of any sort, stones cannot have reflexively directed
ones either.
(.) Because higher-order theories maintain that the higher-order, consciousness-making state is a distinct token from the state it is directed
upon, there is room for error to creep in. The higher-order state may
not only misrepresent the character of the lower-order state; it may
62
Goldman () , p. ; Dretske , p. ; Stubenberg , pp. –.
63
In responding to the objection, Rosenthal makes the following points: a mental state is ‘made’
intransitively conscious in so far this consists in another state’s being transitively conscious of it,
not because some change is effected in it; hence, being intransitively conscious is a relational,
rather than intrinsic characteristic (, pp. –). But the same points, mutatis mutandum, can
be made about the stone. If Rosenthal’s response is supposed to refute the objection, it can only be
because he concedes that the stone is conscious, while denying that it is objectionable, properly understood.
64
See for example, Lycan () , pp. –.
Aristotle on Consciousness 781
even misrepresent the existence of such a state, by representing a lowerorder state that does not in fact exist at all.
A higher-order theorist might just accept this as a necessity and try
instead to make a virtue of it.65 But it seems grossly counterintuitive to
say that I am aware of a certain mental state, when no such state exists.
Aristotle can answer more naturally that the reflexive nature of consciousness presupposes the existence of its object: the higher-order state
and the lower-order state are not ‘distinct existences’ and so leave no
room for error on this score.66 The reflexive relation does not, on the
other hand, guarantee infallibility about the character of the target
state. If Aristotle accepts such infallibility, it will have to do with the
particular type of intentional state he thinks is reflexively directed, and
not its reflexivity as such.
None of this, in any case, requires Aristotle to maintain that all
higher-order states are infallible, and indeed he does not. He takes
some higher-order contents to be clearly subject to falsehood (those
discussed on pp. – below). But they are not the reflexive contents
that are constitutive of consciousness.
To take stock, then. Aristotle’s reflexive account of consciousness is
designed as a way of preventing an infinite regress. There are other ways
of doing this, as higher-order theories show. But Aristotle’s is the only
one that preserves our intuitions about the intrinsic nature of consciousness, while also providing an informative explanation in terms of
intentionality. Far from having an ‘idle air’ about it (Rosenthal b,
pp. –), the reflexive view is well-motivated.
Such a view, on the other hand, is incompatible with an assumption
widespread in recent discussions that ‘mental states are individuated by
their content’, that if a mental state A and a mental state B differ in content, then A and B are not only of different types; they are different
tokens as well. Aristotle can easily accept that different types are
involved—his arguments presuppose it. But his solution rests precisely
on the claim that a single token mental state can instantiate different
content types, and so at the very least he would have to offer a different
account of the individuation of mental states. It is not clear, however,
that this is a liability. The view that mental state tokens are individuated
by their content is not required by either of two prominent proposals
65
See esp. Rosenthal forthcoming, sect. ; also Rosenthal , pp. , ; Lycan , pp. –
; Lycan () , pp. –; Armstrong , pp. –; Armstrong , pp. –. Cf.
Stubenberg , p. .
66
Against Armstrong , pp. –.
782 Victor Caston
for individuating events;67 and it is difficult to find any other reason in
the literature for why contents should individuate tokens as well as
types. It seems to be a dogma that has generally gone unquestioned—it
would be implausible to parade such a theoretical position as an ‘intuition’. Abandoning such a view, then, need not be a costly move, especially if there are advantages in other quarters for doing so (as there are
here).
8. Transparency
There still remains a significant question as to how such awareness is
possible in the first place. According to one suggestion,68 it falls straight
out of Aristotle’s more fundamental views about perception, especially
as expressed in the passage immediately following ours, where he
claims that the activity of the perceptual capacity is ‘one and the same’
as the activity of the perceptible object (b–, a–). But then,
the suggestion runs, it follows that whenever we perceive an object, we
will perceive that we perceive it, precisely because of this sameness.
Aristotle’s concern, on this reading, is not self-awareness in any elevated sense, but simple perceptual awareness. Our perception of azure
is already impregnated with awareness, an awareness that is ‘transparent’, allegedly, in just the sense described by G. E. Moore (() ):
To be aware of the sensation of blue … is to be aware of an awareness of blue
… [T]he moment we try to fix our attention upon consciousness and to see
what, distinctly, it is, it seems to vanish: it seems as if we had before us a mere
67
On Davidson’s view, for example, events are individuated by their causes and effects (Davidson () ). Certainly some differences in content will imply causal differences, and this will
hold for some higher-order contents as well. But there seems no reason, prima facie, to assume
that this holds for the particular difference in content that Aristotle is interested in: the token event
that instantiates the higher-order content might well have the same causes and effects as the token
event that instantiates the lower-order content in question. On Kim’s view of events, in contrast,
an event x and an event y are identical, just in case they involve the same time, constitutive object
and constitutive property (Kim () ). In this case, the time and constitutive object will be
the same; and there seems to be no reason why the constitutive property could not be as well. For
the fact that we use different descriptions—one specifying a higher-order content, the other a
lower-order one — does not imply that different constitutive properties are at issue: as Kim
stresses, we cannot just ‘read off ’ the constitutive components of an event from sentences about
that event (() , pp. –). Therefore, even if the lower-order content type is the constitutive property, it doesn’t preclude the higher-order content type from being instantiated by the
same event. That would require additional assumptions, such as that there cannot be any differences in content type without a corresponding difference in the constitutive property of the relevant event. But that’s precisely the sort of principle that is being put in question.
68
.
Kosman , pp. , –; Modrak , p. ; Modrak , p. ; Osborne , pp. ,
Aristotle on Consciousness 783
emptiness. When we try to introspect the sensation of blue, all we can see is
the blue: the other element is as if it were diaphanous. (p. )
… the other element which I have called ‘consciousness’ … seems to escape
us: it seems, if I may use a metaphor, to be transparent —we look through it
and see nothing but the blue … (p. )
On this reading of Aristotle, the perception of a perception is supposed
to be ‘transparent’ because there isn’t anything else to perceive: the perception of the perception just is the perception of the object.69
A few moments’ reflection, however, reveals the argument behind
this reading to be invalid. It is clearly meant to work by substitution.
But there are difficulties in spelling it out and, more importantly, questions about substitution itself. Start with a simple version of the argument:
. I am having a perception of azure.
. The azure is the same as my perception of it.
∴ . I am having a perception of my perception of azure.
Here ‘my perception of azure’ is substituted for ‘azure’ in (), apparently based on the sameness claim made in (). But () is not an
instance of Aristotle’s general claim in this chapter, namely, that the
activity of the perceptible object is the same as the activity of the perceptual capacity. That claim at most supports
′. The activity of azure is the same as my perception of azure.
In fact, Aristotle actually argues against () in the very passage in question: the perceptible object exists external to the perceiver, even when it
is not in activity, and hence is independent of any perception of it. The
object’s activity, in contrast, is the same as the perception of the object
and so is present ‘in’ the perceiver (§n t“ a7syhtik“, a–), coming into being and perishing ‘at the same time as’ the perception (ëma
fye3resyai ka‹ s2zesyai, a–). This is in line with Aristotle’s
general commitment to some form of direct realism.70 To get out of the
starting blocks, then, the argument would have to appeal to (′) rather
than (). But (′) does not license substitution in (), which speaks only
69
Osborne departs slightly from Kosman on her formulation of this point, arguing that there is
a difference between merely seeing a colour and seeing that a colour is acting on us (, pp. ,
– n. , though she is less circumspect at ). On this point, she is correct, though it is at
odds with her analysis; Kosman is right about the implications of the analysis. See below, p. .
70
See esp. On Perception and Perceptibles , b–; Metaphysics ., b–a.
784 Victor Caston
of azure and not the activity of azure. So a different initial premiss is
needed, such as the following:
′. I am having a perception of the activity of azure.
And it is not clear whether Aristotle would accept (′). It certainly does
not follow from (), given the distinctions just mentioned. Independent
evidence would therefore be needed to show that Aristotle was committed to (′) as well as ().
Even if one grants some version of the premisses, however, the argument is still invalid.71 For us, the problem is one of the context into
which we substitute: as Aristotle is using it, the phrase ‘I am having a
perception of x’ creates a nonextensional context that is opaque to substitution, making the inference invalid.72 For Aristotle, the argument is
invalid too, but it is not the context that causes the problem. On the
contrary, he rejects the intersubstitutivity of coreferential terms salva
veritate as a fallacy, the so-called ‘fallacy of accident’, regardless of the
context in which these terms occur.73 Suppose two terms are coreferential. Aristotle would express this by means of the following schema:
(Sn) A and B are ‘one and the same in number’ (tÚ aÈtÚ ka‹ ©n ériym“).
Yet from such a claim, he contends, it does not follow that
(SUB) Anything that can be said of A can be said of B and vice versa.
In order for such inferences to be valid, it must further be the case that
(Sb) A and B are the same ‘in being’ (t“ e‰nai, tª oÈs3&).
Otherwise, A and B will constitute a unity only ‘accidentally’ or concomitantly (katå sumbebhkÒw). Now, while Aristotle does maintain
71
For a similar analysis of this fallacy in the case of thought, see Frank Lewis’s excellent article
(Lewis ), esp. pp. –. Although the account of the fallacy I develop here differs from Lewis’s
on certain key points, I have learned a great deal from his work, both in the article just mentioned
and his more extensive treatments of ‘accidental sameness’ and the fallacy of accident (Lewis ;
Lewis ).
72
It is possible, of course, to construe ‘I am having a perception of x’ extensionally and so as
transparent to substitution. But this would not suit Aristotle’s purposes in the opening of the
chapter, since he is ultimately trying to account for the fact that we perceive that we see and hear.
The aspect under which the object is perceived is thus not incidental to his argument and so not
transparent to substitution.
73
Soph. Ref. , esp. a–; Phys. ., b–. Aristotle explicitly rejects solutions that treat
contexts like the present one as exceptions to intersubstitutivity at Soph. Ref. , b–, since he
believes the fallacy in question can occur in any context, including those we take to be paradigmatically extensional.
Aristotle on Consciousness 785
that the activity of the perceptible object and the activity of the perceptual capacity are one and the same in number, he is careful to add that
‘their being is not the same’ (tÚ dÉ e‰nai oÈ tÚ aÈtÚ aÈta›w, b,
a–): what it is to be the activity of azure is different from what it
is to be the activity of sight. According to Aristotle, then, the sameness
mentioned in premiss (′) does not license substitution into (′). The
activity of azure and perceiving it are not ‘one and the same’ in the relevant sense.
To put the point briefly in our own terms: once again there is an
equivocation between type and token. According to Aristotle, there is a
single token event that is both an activity of azure and an activity of
sight—it instantiates both types of activity. But it does not follow that if
we perceive this token event as belonging to one type, we thereby perceive it as belonging to the other. So even if Aristotle accepts (′) and
holds that we perceive the activity of azure, it does not follow that we
perceive our perception of it. Perceiving that we perceive, therefore,
does not fall out from Aristotle’s analysis of the original perceptual
encounter, even though it is something to which he is clearly committed. It depends instead on the duplication and regress arguments, at the
beginning of On the Soul ..
This is all to the best, since if perceiving azure and perceiving that I
perceive azure were the same in a way that would license the inference
— if, that is, they were one and the same in being as well as in
number—it would not make the awareness in question ‘transparent’. It
would dissolve it entirely. We could no longer perceive that we perceive
as distinct from perceiving the object: what it is to perceive one and
what it is to perceive the other would be exactly the same, and there
would be nothing to distinguish them. But then the arguments at the
opening of On the Soul . could not even get started. For they presuppose that there is a difference between them. And that distinction is
meant to hold even in the reflexive case: it is different for a perception
to be of itself (aÈtØ aÍt4 w, b) than for it to be of a colour (toË
xr2matow, b).
9. The indirectness of reflexive awareness
In any event, Moore means something slightly different when he speaks
of ‘transparency’. For on his view consciousness is a distinct element in
sensation of which we can be aware. It is just that it is elusive: whenever
we try to focus on it, what we become directly aware of is its object, and
not the awareness itself. Aristotle can agree with this, though he uses a
786 Victor Caston
different metaphor. Unlike God, who thinks only of his own thinking,
we reflect on our mental states in a more indirect manner:
It seems that knowing, perceiving, believing and thinking are always of
something else, but of themselves on the side [§n par°rgƒ]. (Metaph. .,
b–)
Aristotle combines two distinctions here of cardinal importance. He
contrasts an intentional state’s
a. being directed at something else vs. being directed at itself
b. being directed at something primarily vs. being directed at it ‘on
the side’
While our intentional states are always directed at something else and
directed at themselves, he claims, they are primarily other-directed: our
intentional states are first and foremost a way of knowing about and
engaging with the world (On Perception and Perceptibles , b–
a).74 This is also Aristotle’s point—if he is consistent, at any rate—
when he claims in Metaphysics .
For in point of fact perception is not of itself, but of something else besides
the perception that is necessarily prior to the perception; for that which effects change is prior by nature to that which is changed.(b–)
Perception must be primarily of something distinct from itself, which
produces the perception and hence is causally prior. Our awareness of
this cognitive engagement, in contrast, is something that occurs only §n
par°rgƒ — in Ross’s rendering, ‘en passant’ (Ross , p. ) —
something that does not belong to the main function or purpose of
perception. To use Brentano’s phrase, it is a ‘bonus’ thrown in (als
Zugabe, Brentano () , Book II, Ch. , sect. , .), something
that supervenes on the central work.
Notice that Aristotle’s remarks do not rule out introspection, that is,
the awareness we have of our mental states when one of our token mental states is directed at another. In such cases, a mental state will still be
primarily directed at something other than itself, in conformity with
his claim above. And it is clear that Aristotle—unlike Brentano, who
rejects introspection entirely (Brentano () , Book I, Ch. , sect.
)—thinks that there are such cases. We can, for example, contemplate
the content of a memory trace or other representation just on its own
(kayÉ aÍtÒ) or as being from another earlier experience (êllou, On
74
Oehler (, esp. pp. –; cf. , pp. –) is right to emphasize these texts, even though
he uses ‘intentional’ exclusively for other-directed states and hence as incompatible with reflexivity. But if directedness is the hallmark of intentionality, reflexive states are no less intentional for
being directed at themselves.
Aristotle on Consciousness 787
Memory and Recollection , b–a);75 similarly, we can contemplate the content of a dream and consider whether it is in fact a dream
(On Dreams , a–). But precisely because introspection involves
an awareness that is primarily directed at another mental state, it cannot be the kind of awareness Aristotle has in mind here, which involves
a mental state being directed at itself on the side. Only the latter sort of
awareness, if any, could plausibly be held to accompany all mental acts.
To claim this for introspection would be very far-fetched indeed.
The distinction is crucial. For, as we have seen, reflexive awareness is
both intrinsic and immediate, occurring without the intervention of
further acts, causal relations, representations, or inferences. And yet
there remains a kind of indirectness about it. We are not aware of the act
itself in the same way that we are aware of its primary object. Thus,
while we can be said to perceive that we see, it will not be exactly like
perceiving an object. For in perceiving an object, our gaze is always primarily directed at the world and so passes itself by. In ordinary experience, we glimpse our perceiving only peripherally, as it were.
This suggests that it would be a mistake to attribute a second kind of
inner sense view to Aristotle. Earlier we rejected an inner sense interpretation on the grounds that it made the activity of the inner sense a
distinct token from the activity of the external sense it perceives (see
p. above), and so is vulnerable to Aristotle’s regress objection. But
an advocate of inner sense might respond by appealing to his analysis of
perception and argue that they are not distinct tokens: the activity of
the inner sense, just like the activity of the external senses, is one and
the same as the activity of its object, though different ‘in being’. Yet if
these two types of perception share the same analysis, then inner sense
should afford the same kind of direct observation that the external
senses do; and then the resulting awareness would not be indirect or
‘secondary’ in the way Metaphysics . demands. The awareness that
accompanies all perception is not the primary function of a second
sense, according to Aristotle, but a secondary function of the primary
ones.
75
For a discussion of this passage and others related to it, see my , pp. –, although it is
put in terms which, in the present context, might cause confusion. I speak there of the introspective awareness of one state by another as reflective awareness, which must be strictly distinguished
from what in the present paper I have described as reflexive awareness. The former is concerned
with ‘reflection’ in the quite ordinary sense of thinking about one’s own state of mind, in contrast
with the world; the latter is used in a more strict, logical sense. See n. above.
788 Victor Caston
10. The phenomenal quality of experience
This leaves us with a difficulty, however. If perceiving that we see is not
exactly like seeing an object—or, for that matter, like hearing or tasting
or smelling or touching something—what makes it a perception at all?
And more to the point, what makes our seeing perceptible?76
Both of these questions, I take it, are behind the aporia Aristotle
raises immediately after the regress argument (b–). Plato’s
Charmides again forms the backdrop. Socrates suggests we compare
cognition to other relations: the greater, for example, is always greater
than something lesser; but it is impossible that the greater be either
greater or less than itself (168AC). So, too, vision (ˆciw) is always of
something coloured; but it is incredible to think that vision itself could
be something coloured and so seen (168C–169A). Aristotle frames the
worry in terms of whether ‘that which sees’ (tÚ 6r«n) is coloured. But it
is clear on an activity reading that he must have the same problem in
mind. Neither the person who sees nor the eye pose a similar problem:
both are obviously coloured and so can be seen in a straightforward
sense.77 The problem is rather with the perceptual activity of sight.78 If
this activity does not itself have a colour (or sound or flavour or smell
or feel), in what sense is it perceptible?
Aristotle’s answers are only stabs at a solution, not an exposition of
settled views. He is openly struggling to find room within his theory to
provide an adequate account of the phenomena. The fact that he has to
reach for speculation is itself telling. For it suggests that he does not
hold any of a range of views that readily supply an answer. Consider a
sense-datum theory, according to which our experience contains
objects that possess perceptible qualities quite literally; or even a more
moderate view that abandons such objects, while keeping perceptible
qualities as literal features of the experience, for example, as properties
of the ‘visual field’, which is a mosaic of colours with shapes and positions. On either of these views, such qualities should be directly observ-
Aristotle on Consciousness 789
able; and if Aristotle was working with either, he should not hesitate to
say that visual experience either is, or includes parts that are, literally
coloured, without qualification. But he does hesitate and only allows
that vision is coloured in a way, ‘as though it is coloured’ (…w
kexrvmãtistai, b–). The same considerations equally rule out a
view at the other extreme, sometimes ascribed to Aristotle, that seeing
consists in the literal coloration of the eye (or of the central organ),
which becomes coloured in exactly the same sense that external objects
are coloured.79 On any of these views, there is a direct response to the
puzzle in the Charmides: there is a straightforward and literal sense in
which vision is coloured—Socrates is simply wrong. Aristotle’s preference for a vague and hedged remark effectively rules out all of these
views.80
This has consequences for recent debates over the nature of qualia. It
does not matter whether we take qualia to be ‘images on the silver
screen’ or part of ‘the celluloid’ instead (Stubenberg , pp. –),
that is, whether we take qualia to be a mental feature that we experience, or a physical feature of the experience. Aristotle resists literally
attributing the same perceptual qualities our perceptions are of to
either the experience itself or its physical basis in the experiencer. He
still believes that there is a sense in which our experience is genuinely
perceptible and so has a phenomenal character that is accessible to consciousness; and for this reason he does not dismiss the puzzle in the
Charmides out of hand. But it is not because our experience literally
shares the same quality as the object. In what sense, then, is it perceptible?
Aristotle’s first stab at a solution is suggestive, but not very promising. He begins by backing up and noting that not even a capacity like
sight has just one sort of activity.81 When we are in complete darkness
with our eyes open, we do not see something black; rather, we do not
79
A view defended recently at book length in Everson .
76
One could alleviate this difficulty straightaway by denying that such awareness is perception
after all, as Bernard (, pp. –) does, for example. On his view, Aristotle accepts Philoponus’s objections to such a claim, maintaining rather that such awareness belongs to reason or intellect (a position Bernard recognizes is Platonic—cf. Tht. 184CD). But such a reading goes hard
against the text, which is framed exclusively in perceptual terms that it never withdraws, but instead tries to reconstrue and qualify in a way that will escape the kind of objections Philoponus
raises. Perhaps Aristotle should have accepted Philoponus’s view. But that is another matter.
77
78
Against Ross , and Hamlyn () , p. .
Notice the use of the neuter tÚ 6r«n, which leaves it open what is being referred to: given Aristotle’s use of neuter substantives, it could refer to either the person, the sense organ, the visual capacity, the visual act. Ross’s emendation of 6r«n to 6rçn twice in b in the OCT text is
therefore unnecessary. For a similar view, cf. Horn , n. ; cf. n. .
Sorabji has recently argued (, p. ) that on a literalist reading the qualification should
be understood as follows: the eye jelly is transparent, but only takes on a ‘borrowed colour’ during
the sensory process, just like the sea (On Perception and Perceptibles , a–b). This occurs,
Sorabji explains (, pp. –), when each comes to share the formal cause of a particular colour
and so appears to be that colour, without undergoing any change in their material basis. Such a
reading can thus make some sense of Aristotle’s qualification, ‘in a way’. But it does not account
well for the hesitant nature of Aristotle’s remarks throughout b–, since if Sorabji’s reading
is correct, there is a still a direct response to the puzzle from the Charmides: for it would still be literally true that the organ is coloured and so capable of being seen.
80
81
Notice that in moving to talk of capacities here, Aristotle’s primary concern is still activities:
he is simply looking for a way to avoid thinking of the awareness that we are seeing as something
we do by seeing the seeing, with all that that entails.
790 Victor Caston
see anything. But we can still tell it is dark, and it is surely by sight that
we do this (b–). Of course, Aristotle needs a more robust ability
than being able to tell whether our inner lights, so to speak, have been
‘turned off ’ — a metaphor he himself uses (Àsper lÊxnou éposbesy°ntow, On Perception and Perceptibles , b–). He needs to be
able to explain beyond this our awareness of the contents of our experiences as well. The claim that we have certain perceptual capacities that
are not of perceptible qualities like azure is a welcome broadening of his
account. But it is hardly enough to do the job.
His second attempt at a solution appeals to the details of his own theory of perception. But here again it does no more than gesture at an
answer. Aristotle explains the suggestion that ‘that which sees is in a
way coloured’ (b–) by appealing to the fact that each sense organ
can receive the perceptible quality ‘without its matter’ (b–); and this
in turn is supposed to explain how there can be perceptual effects and
other traces after the perceived object has departed (b–). Aristotle
then goes on to elaborate the sense in which the perceptible object is
present in the act: its activity is ‘one and the same’ as the activity of perception, occurring simultaneously in the perceiver (b–a).
These doctrines make clear, at the very least, that a perceptual experience and certain subsequent experiences are as of a perceptible quality
like azure: that is, that they are either about something azure (in the
case of perception) or represent something azure (in the case of perceptual traces). But that only makes a point about their intentionality, the
fact that they have content. In using these doctrines to explain how the
experience itself is ‘in a way coloured’, Aristotle is attributing a property
to the experience, a property that is in some way connected to its being
about a colour and is somehow accessible to us. That is, he suggests that
(i) the experience has some characteristic in virtue of which it is about
this quality (or represents it) and (ii) this characteristic is itself, in some
extended sense, perceptible.82 Only then has he succeeded in addressing
the puzzle from the Charmides, which he would otherwise have to
reject out of hand.
In taking this characteristic to be perceptible, though, Aristotle parts
company with strict intentionalists too —theorists who take the phenomenal character of an experience to be exhausted by its intentional
properties, identifying qualia instead with the perceptible qualities
82
In this respect, Aristotle’s conception of qualia has a number of similarities to Shoemaker’s
earlier conception of qualia: see esp. Shoemaker () , pp. – (cf. ); Shoemaker ()
, pp. , .
Aristotle on Consciousness 791
objects are represented as literally having.83 By describing seeing as ‘in a
way coloured’, Aristotle seems to think the phenomenal character of the
experience goes beyond the fact that it is about (or represents) a colour.
The seeing is in some sense ‘like’ or ‘similar to’ the perceptible quality it
is about (or represents), in so far as it is something that has to do with
colour. But it is not the same quality — it is rather the ‘mental paint’
used to represent coloured objects that gives our experience the phenomenal character it has, and this somehow is available to us.84
Significantly, Aristotle can only tag this phenomenal quality by reference to the perceptible quality it is about — following Peacocke, he
might perhaps say that the activity of seeing azure itself possesses an
associated quality, azure′ (, Ch. ). But in the end, he may not be
able to say much more than this. He is referring here to what perceiving
such qualities is like, and he finds that we can only express the character
of such experience ‘on the side’, as it were, of reports of our primary
intentional experiences of objects. That is simply part of the elusiveness
of awareness.
Aristotle can thus agree with the intentionalist that nothing other
than perceptible objects need literally have the perceptible qualities in
question. But he can also agree with the proponent of qualia that the
phenomenal character of our experiences outruns their representational content. His view thus cuts down the middle of another alleged
dichotomy. Only in this way, he believes, can we preserve the appearances.
11. Objections and replies
Aristotle’s account of consciousness is bound to strike some as strange.
But it is a view that has been held by non-Aristotelians, such as Descartes,85 Arnauld,86 Husserl,87 and Sartre88 (and perhaps even Burge89),
83
For example, Harman () ; Dretske , Ch. ; cf. also Block .
See Block . The phrase itself is due to Harman, who vigorously rejects it: see esp. ,
p. ; , pp. , .
84
85
In Descartes’s conversation with Burman ( April ), he characterizes being conscious
(conscium esse) as ‘thinking something and reflecting on one’s own thought’ (quidem cogitare et reflectere supra suam cogitationem); and he insists, against Burman, that one can have both the higherand lower-order thought at the same time (AT .). In his reply to the Seventh Set of Objections, he
is still more explicit: ‘the first thought by which we attend to something no more differs from the
second thought by which we attend to our earlier attending to that thing, than this second differs
from a third by which we attend to our attending to our attending’ (AT .). Descartes does admit, in a letter to Arnauld ( July ), that the first thoughts of an infant are only direct and not
reflexive (directas, non reflexas, AT .). But this need only qualify his views on the extent of
792 Victor Caston
as well as Aristotelians like Brentano.90 Furthermore, most of these
thinkers are also non-naturalists, which suggests that the sort of analysis offered here has been found attractive on its own, independent of
any consequences it might have for mind–body issues. If it also makes
room for a naturalistic approach (as I believe Aristotle himself favours),
that is an added plus.
Many readers will still have reservations, however. In this section, I
will try to answer some of the concerns that might be raised against
such an account.
1.
One not uncommon suspicion is that the notion of reflexivity involved
is incoherent, either because it leads to contradiction or is viciously circular, and so does not constitute a viable solution to the infinite regress.
David Bell, for example, alleges that Brentano’s account of consciousness leads to contradiction. According to Brentano, whenever a mental
state is about something —whenever, that is, something forms the content of a mental state—the mental state ‘contains’ that item within itself
as a part. If, then, a mental state is to be about itself, it must contain
itself. But nothing can be both container and contained at once, since
consciousness and not its structure or nature, which would still consist in this reflexive awareness.
For discussion of this view, see Lewis, G. , –; Aquila , p. , pp. –, pp. –;
Nadler , pp. –. Against this interpretation, Thiel has objected (, pp. –) that, far
from identifying higher- and lower-order thoughts, Descartes distinguishes them. He does indeed.
But none of the evidence need commit him to anything more than a difference in types, thus leaving open the possibility of a token-identity view, such as is defended above.
Arnauld () , pp. , . For discussion, see Nadler , pp. –. The idea appears to have had a wider currency among other Cartesians as well, such as Louis de la Forge, Antoine Dilly, Pierre Sylvain Regis, and François Lamy: see Lewis , pp. –; Davies ,
pp. –; Thiel , pp. –.
86
87
Husserl (–) , esp. Beilage IX, .– and XII, .–.; cf. sections , .
For an interpretation of this text that differentiates Husserl’s views from those of Brentano, see Zahavi . It is worth noting that in his Logische Untersuchungen, Husserl elaborates Brentano’s
theory in order to criticize it (though largely on epistemological grounds): see Husserl (-)
–, Beilage, esp. sect. ff.
88
Sartre () ; () , pp. –, –, –, – (contrast pp. –, on ‘reflective’ consciousness); . For discussion, see Grossmann , pp. –; Wider .
89
Burge , –. For other related views, see Smith and .
90
Brentano () , .–, .–.
Aristotle on Consciousness 793
nothing can be a part of itself.91 A number of recent authors affiliated
with Heidelberg have argued that all such accounts in general are subject to a vicious circularities and therefore must be abandoned.92 In
Brentano’s case, the relevant circularity is related to Bell’s:93 to have genuine self-consciousness, it is not enough for a mental state to be about,
for example, its being a perception of azure; it must be about itself as a
whole, as a case of self-consciousness. But this requires that it is already
self-conscious, prior to being directed at itself, since if it were not selfconscious to begin with, no amount of reflexive directedness will make
it a genuine case of self-consciousness. But then this account already has
built in precisely what it is supposed to account for.94
Each of these arguments, however, relies crucially on assumptions,
explicit or implicit, to which Aristotle does not seem to be committed.
In Bell’s case, it turns on whether the notion of content implies, as the
metaphor suggests, that what a mental state is about is (a) contained
within that state (b) as a proper part. Otherwise, there is no contradiction: either content is not to be taken literally as a kind of containment,
or it permits improper parts as well, in which case the whole mental
state can be ‘contained’. Leaving aside whether Brentano is committed
to both of these assumptions, it is clear that Aristotle is not. One could,
perhaps, construe an object’s being ‘one and the same’ as a perception
or thought of it as that object’s being ‘contained’ within that state. But
even if one did, no problem arises over improper parts, since manifestly
a whole mental state can be ‘one and the same’ as itself.
The assumptions behind the second circle are somewhat more elusive. The first turns on a particularly strong notion of what self-consciousness requires. It is worth emphasizing that Aristotle’s account, as
I have reconstructed it, is not intended as an account of self-consciousness in any strong sense, much less consciousness of a Self, but just con91
Bell , pp. –. Bell cites Findlay, who remarks that ‘[t]here can be no doubt that the theory of Aristotle and Brentano is the purest nonsense imaginable’ (() , p. ). But the argument Findlay goes on to offer begs the question, by simply asserting that every mental state must
be about something distinct from itself, and so is different from Bell’s argument.
92
Henrich () ; Henrich ; Pothast ; Cramer ; see also Tugendhat for a
critique.
93
I do not consider here one form of circularity that is stressed especially by Henrich (()
, pp. –, ; , pp. –, ) and Cramer (, pp. , , , ), that traces back
to Schmitz’s succinct formulation (, pp. –). It alleges that to be aware of oneself, one
must know that it is oneself of which one is presently aware, and not something else; but this would
require one already to have self-awareness in order to have self-awareness in the first place. This
line of argument has been criticized within the school by Pothast (, p. . Teil, passim) and even
more effectively by Tugendhat (, Chs –).
94
Pothast , pp. –; Cramer , pp. –, ; Zahavi , pp. –.
794 Victor Caston
sciousness, in particular perceptual consciousness. And for this, it is
enough for an act to be about itself, for example, as a perception of
azure; it need not be about itself as anything further.95 The objection
also depends crucially on a second assumption as well, namely, that a
mental state’s being directed at itself could only detect the fact that it is
conscious of itself as an independent feature, rather than constituting
that very feature. But that just begs the question against Aristotelian
accounts, which hold that it is precisely in virtue of being directed at
itself that a mental state is conscious.
There seems to be nothing incoherent in maintaining a reflexive
account of consciousness of the kind we have considered here, without
being committed to any of these assumptions. And if Aristotle is not
committed to them, he is not vulnerable to these objections either.
2.
Someone might object that even if Aristotle’s account is not viciously
circular, the structure of consciousness he posits is still unnecessarily
rococo, involving a complex and artificial combination of elements:
each conscious state has two sorts of directedness, primary and secondary, of which the latter is always reflexive.
Aristotle, of course, is entitled to answer that it is only as complex as
is necessary and not artificial at all. He can justly demand that the
account be judged on the merit of the arguments, above all the regress
argument. And he can return the challenge: see if you can find a simpler alternative that honours both our intuitions and the theoretical
constraints imposed by this argument. If simplicity is to be purchased
at the cost of abandoning deeply held intuitions, he would urge, it is
not worth the price.
That may be enough to allay some unease about the account’s complexity, though certainly not all. Is it possible to pinpoint precisely the
source of such misgivings? It cannot be that a token event instantiates
two types; or that a reflexive relation is involved; or that some contents
are self-directed. There are uncontroversial examples for each of these
characteristics.96 The trouble must rather concern the specific claim
that mental events instantiate two types of content, one of which
embeds the other in a higher-order content. Just such an objection was
95
See below, pp. –.
96
A red circle, for example, is both coloured and shaped, a single token falling under two types;
the relation is a divisor of is reflexive in precisely the sense at issue here (see n. ); and when I
think that the very thought I am now having is about thinking, the content of my thought is selfdirected.
Aristotle on Consciousness 795
made against Locke by John Sergeant in his robustly titled Solid Philosophy Asserted ():
But if I be Conscious, or know that I know when I know the Object without
me, I must by the same Act know what’s within me and what’s without me
both at once; and so my Act of Direct Knowledge would be Reflex; or rather,
that one Act would be both Direct and Reflex, which makes it Chimerical.97
(pp. –)
Sergeant thinks that such a combination is fictitious, perhaps even
impossible.98 But if there is a contradiction here or some other incoherency, it has yet to be shown. All we have so far is counterassertion.
Perhaps one might question instead whether, just as a matter of fact,
such beasts can be found. Are there any other instances of this type of
complexity? There needn’t be, of course, for Aristotle’s account to hold
—it could be that awareness is the only case of this sort. But it would be
nice. It would relieve some of the pressure.
The following seems as though it might be such a case. Not all of us
are fun. But we all like having fun. That is, when we enjoy doing something (and in so far as we enjoy doing it), we enjoy our enjoyment.
What it is to enjoy F-ing is not, to be sure, the same as what it is to
enjoy enjoying F-ing. But it doesn’t follow that this higher-order enjoyment is a distinct token activity from our simple enjoyment of F-ing.
The connection between the two, in fact, seems to be conceptually necessary. To imagine someone who genuinely enjoys an activity, but is
indifferent to his enjoyment, who fails to enjoy it, seems repugnant to
the very notion. It would be comparable to someone not liking having
fun. Any grounds we might have for denying that someone enjoys his
enjoyment undermines the initial claim that he was actually enjoying
F-ing in the first place.
Note first that it isn’t part of the claim that one necessarily notices
such second-order enjoyment. Even with first-order enjoyment, one
can be entirely in the ‘flow’. One may be so absorbed in an activity that
one only realizes later that one did enjoy it; in fact, it seems possible
that one might enjoy something even if one never realized it. But then,
by parity of reasoning, the same point should hold for the higher-order
enjoyment: a failure to notice it is not conclusive evidence of its
absence. Second, the conceptual connection suggested here does not
97
Thiel has a brief discussion of the passage on p. . In the margins of his personal copy of
Solid Philosophy Asserted (reprinted by Garland Publishing, ), Locke implausibly takes Sergeant to be claiming that we could never have two objects at once, which would make comparison
impossible. For more on Sergeant, and Locke’s replies, see Bradish ; Yolton and Krook
.
98
Sergeant in fact prefers a distinct higher-order state, later in time (pp. –).
796 Victor Caston
preclude having other attitudes towards one’s enjoyment in addition. It
is admittedly possible to be repulsed by one’s enjoyment in an activity.
But that is not incompatible with enjoying one’s enjoyment. Indeed,
such higher-order enjoyment may be part of what repulses us.99
If there is a conceptual link, though, the higher-order enjoyment
cannot be a mere concomitant or causal consequence of the lowerorder enjoyment. Rather, it would be something intrinsic and essential
to someone’s enjoying F-ing in the first place. It would be an example
of a single token event, which instantiates two types of the relevant sort.
In the end, I am undecided as to whether there is in fact a conceptual
connection between enjoyment and enjoying one’s enjoyment. But
even if there isn’t, the following still seems right, namely, that there isn’t
anything incoherent in the hypothesis. If it is false, it is so because of the
nature of enjoyment, and not because the resulting structure would be
‘rococo’. And that’s all that Aristotle really needs in the end. His argument rests on premisses which are either specific to the case of consciousness or common, a priori principles. If these are true and his
reasoning is valid, then such structures must be exemplified.
3.
It might be objected that even if Aristotle’s analysis avoids an infinite
regress of token mental acts, it is still vulnerable to an infinite regress
nonetheless. The higher-order perception in question is not simply a
perception of the lower-order perception, that is, the perception of an
event which happens to be a lower-order perception. It is a perception
of it as a perception, indeed as a perception of some given object —
Aristotle’s duplication argument assumes that we perceive that we see,
for example, the azure of the sky. But then the higher-order content
type must be distinct from the lower-order content type. And this holds
quite generally. Therefore, even though Aristotle maintains that there is
only a single token activity involved—and so is entitled to reject premiss
() of the regress argument (see p. above)—he still appears to be
committed to a corresponding claim about a plurality of types:
′. Perceiving that we perceive is always distinct in type from the
earlier perceiving.
But then, one might worry, a regress will threaten, though it will be a
regress of contents, rather than mental states: having accepted (′),
Aristotle will have to posit a higher-order content, and then another,
and so on ad infinitum. Thus, even if he is not committed to an infinite
number of token activities, he will be forced to concede that each token
99
I would like to thank Dave Estlund and Jamie Dreier for valuable discussion on these points.
Aristotle on Consciousness 797
activity instantiates an infinite number of higher-order content types.
And that surely is absurd.100
It seems clear that a content or type regress does arise, if we must
perceive that we perceive at each successive level. But nothing said so far
requires that. In particular, the premiss used for the earlier regress,
namely,
B. Whenever we have a perception, we have a perception of that
perception.
is satisfied even if every perception were to instantiate only two contents, at the first- and second-orders. This can be shown straightforwardly. Suppose one perceives that one sees azure. On Aristotle’s view,
the perceiving will be ‘one and the same’ activity as the seeing it perceives, and so can correctly be described as being ‘itself of itself ’ (aÈtØ
aÍt4w, b): there is a single token activity, which is directed at itself.
There is, then, a perception of the second-order perception, in accordance with (B), without requiring a third-order perception. It does not
follow, however, that one perceives this activity as a second-order perception. In fact, nothing follows about the aspects involved, either (a)
with regard to what the object is perceived as or (b) with regard to the
manner of perception (one need not see that one sees either). To think
otherwise is to commit the same fallacy as the transparency argument
above, just a step higher: from the fact that (i) we perceive that we see
and (ii) this perceiving and this seeing are ‘one and the same’, it does
not follow that we perceive that we perceive that we see. We may merely
perceive that we see. Nevertheless, there is still a perception which is
‘itself of itself ’.
To generate a regress of content types, we need another premiss,
analogous to (B), but framed in terms of contents rather than objects:
B′. Whenever we perceive that p, we perceive that we perceive that
p.
Aristotle, I have argued earlier, is committed to (B). But is there any
reason to think he is committed to the stronger (B′)? It does not follow
from (B). And none of the textual evidence seems to justify anything as
strong as (B′) either. Nicomachean Ethics . is committed only to our
being aware of each activity we engage in. But that needn’t involve anything more than an awareness of each token activity. The arguments at
100
Ryle actually uses a similar regress in objecting to ‘phosphoresence’ theories of consciousness (, pp. –). It is also clearly laid out by Cramer, who describes it as an ‘intensive’ regress,
in contrast with an ‘extensive’ regress of mental states (, pp. , ; cf. Pothast , pp. –).
798 Victor Caston
the opening of On the Soul . go somewhat further, in so far as they
seem to commit Aristotle to the awareness of each token mental activity
as falling under some content type, such as seeing azure. But he states
this without further elaboration or clarification: in particular, he
doesn’t give any reason for thinking that, for every content type a token
perceptual activity falls under, we must be perceive that activity as falling under that type—in short, (B′). If, however, Aristotle isn’t committed to this principle, then he can allow that we might be aware of a
perceptual activity, without being aware of certain contents it instantiates, such as perceiving that we see azure. But then the type regress fails.
4.
Finally, it might be objected that even if the previous points are
granted, Aristotle is still committed to a form of Cartesianism, in so far
as he holds the view that every mental activity is conscious; but such a
view is implausible and ought to be rejected.
Does Aristotle think that every mental activity is conscious (in the
sense that we have awareness of it)? Yes and no. There is certainly a
sense in which every token mental activity is closed under the consciousness-making relation for Aristotle: each token mental activity
instantiates a reflexive relation of awareness. But it does not follow that
consciousness is comprehensive—we need not be aware of all the mental types that these tokens fall under. In particular, we need not be aware
of certain higher-order contents: I can perceive that I am seeing azure
without perceiving that I am perceiving that I am seeing azure. But then
Aristotle can avoid the Cartesian claim that all mental facts are ‘selfintimating’.101 The fact that an activity has a certain content does not
entail that I am aware that it has that content, even if I am aware of that
activity and aware of it as having some content or other.
But isn’t it absurd enough to claim that we are aware of every token
mental activity— to insist on ‘token self-intimation’, as it were, even
without ‘type self-intimation’? Not really. In the first place, Aristotle
isn’t making a claim about all mental states and so not about dispositional states in particular. He is only concerned with activities
(§n°rgeiai) in the strict sense of the term. Secondly, he need not make
any strong epistemic claims with regard to the contents of these activities, such as that we have some kind of omniscience or privileged
access. He need only maintain that we are aware (veridically) that each
token activity takes place and that it have a certain content. And this
restricted claim, even if it should turn out to be false, is not something
101
Ryle , pp. –; Armstrong , pp. –; Armstrong , pp. –.
Aristotle on Consciousness 799
that can be ruled directly out of court. On the contrary, by insisting on
this weaker claim, Aristotle can claim a key advantage over higherorder theories (see p. above): he can preserve our intuition that
consciousness is essential to mental activity, without his view collapsing
into a Cartesian strawman.
Aristotle’s conception is broader than Descartes in at least one
regard, however. The general principle enunciated in Nicomachean Ethics . should apply to the cognitive activities of any sort, including the
perceptual activities of animals, however rudimentary. One might seriously question how coherent Aristotle’s account of perceptual content
is when applied to lower animals. But however far it does extend, Aristotle’s core claim is that consciousness will extend just as far, since the
latter is essential to perception: anything genuinely capable of perception must, on his view, be capable of perceiving that it perceives. Descartes might well be able to accept this last claim. If so, then the
difference between them will be due to whether animals can be genuinely said to perceive or not.
12. Conclusion
Aristotle’s views on consciousness thus seem to cut down the middle of
two contemporary debates: first, whether perceptual awareness is
intrinsic to perception or relational (higher-order); and second,
whether perception itself instantiates perceptible qualities or merely
represents them. On the first, Aristotle holds that a single token perception can be about an external object and about itself. This sort of
awareness is therefore both intrinsic and relational. On the second,
Aristotle rejects the notion that our perceptions, or parts of them, literally embody the qualities they are about. But he also rejects a strict
intentionalist stance: qualia are not merely the qualities objects are represented as having either. Rather, our perceptions have a phenomenal
character, that has to do with the qualities they represent, but is not
exhausted by representational content. Aristotle thus attempts to do
justice to the intuitions on both sides, while avoiding their respective
errors; and we might well regard this as a step forward, fully in keeping
with his customary aim of saving the phenomena.
Department of Philosophy
University of California, Davis
California 95616-8673, USA
victor caston
800 Victor Caston
Appendix: A brief excursus on the inner sense(s)
Contemporary inner sense theorists frequently cite Kant and Locke as
sources for their own conception (see n. above). Kant, for example,
speaks of a single inner sense (innerer Sinn) that apprehends one’s state
of mind,102 ‘one’s self and one’s inner condition’.103 Locke identifies the
mind’s ‘reflecting on its own Operations within itself ’ with ‘internal
Sense’, from which we derive our ideas of ‘Perception, Thinking, Doubting, Believing, Reasoning, Knowing, Willing, and all the different actings
of our own Minds’.104 Indeed, such acts seem to have this quasi-perceptual awareness as a necessary concomitant: ‘ ’tis altogether as intelligible
to say, that a body is extended without parts, as that any thing thinks
without being conscious of it, or perceiving, that it does so … Consciousness is the perception of what passes in a Man’s own mind’.105
But neither the terminology nor the concept is original.106 Kant could
have encountered inner sense in Wolff (sensus internus),107for example,
or other lesser figures.108 Similarly, we find it not only in the works of
Locke’s contemporaries, such as Boyle109 or Malebranche,110 but also
102
KrV A/B. Cf. Anthrop. sect. , Ak. .–.
103
KrV A/B; cf. B, –. See also the recently discovered Leningrad fragment, with commentary, in Kant [c. ] ; and more generally, Mohr .
104
Essay II.i.; cf. II.i. and Draft B, sections , .
105
Essay II.i.; cf. II.xxvii. and Draft B, section .
106
I am particularly conscious here of poaching in others’ forests. For the early modern period
in particular, see the painstaking and detailed research of Udo Thiel on the concepts of consciousness and reflection (; ; ; ; ). Although inner sense is not his central focus, I
have learned much from his work, especially regarding some of the lesser figures cited below
(whom he often quotes generously).
107
Wolff, Philos. rat. sive Logica, Pars II, .., sect..
Such as Meiners and Hissmann, who are examined in detail by Thiel , as well as the others he mentions at –. See also Thiel .
108
109
From the appendix to the first part of his The Christian Virtuouso (): ‘… the rational
soul or human mind is, of all the incorporeal substances, that which we have the means, as well as
interest, to know the best; since it is not only a familiar object, but so intimate, as to be the noblest
part of ourselves; and that the chief, not to say the only thing that is essential to it, and in a sound
sense constitutes its nature, is, that it is conscious to its own actions and operations, and that, at
least for the most part, not as it knows the circulation of the blood in the veins, or the secretion of
gall in the liver, by a ratiocination upon sensible phænomena, but immediately by an internal
sense or perception.’ (The Works of the Honourable Robert Boyle (London, ), vol. , p. .)
For example, Rech. de la Verité ., section (= OC .); .., sect. (= OC .); Eclaircissement (= OC .). Cf. Rech. de la Verité ., sect. (= OC .); ., sect. (= OC .; .., sect.
(= OC .); .., sect. (= OC .); .. (= OC .). On Malebranche and le sentiment intérieur, see Lewis, G. , pp. –, –, –, –; Davies , pp. –.
110
Aristotle on Consciousness 801
before him in Gassendi, 111 La Forge, 112 Cudworth, 113 Tillotson, 114
Stanley,115 and Cumberland116 —authors with whom we know Locke to
have been familiar.117
Nor is this surprising. The term belongs to common philosophical
parlance, itself the precipitate of a scholastic tradition reaching back to
Aristotle. We already find Augustine speaking at length of an inner
sense (sensus interior), by means of which we perceive that we perceive.118 And there are traces of still earlier antecedents. Plotinus once
remarks that we are aware of appetite by means of an ‘inner perceptual
ability’(tª a7syhtikª tª ¶ndon dunãmei).119 The Stoics, more promisingly, speak of an ‘inner feeling in virtue of which we are also aware of
ourselves’ (§ntÚw èfÆn … kay’¥n ka‹ 1m«n aÈt«n éntilambanÒmeya).120
Arguably, something similar was held by the Epicureans too121 and even
before that by the Cyrenaics (tactus interior, tactus intimus), although
the connection with consciousness is less than fully explicit.122 Augus111
Syntagma (in the Lyons edition of the Opera), pars , sect. , VIII.i, a–b; see also VI.i,
.a, a, a; in Bernier, Abrégé, nd ed. (; st ed., ), .., –. Cf. Disquis. metaph.,
Med. , dub. , inst. ; in Bernier, ., , –.
112
Traité de l’esprit de l’homme (), ed. Pierre Claire (Paris, ), p. . See Lewis, G. ,
pp. –; Davies , p. , pp. –; Thiel , p. nn. –.
113
Ralph Cudworth, A Treatise on Freewill (ed. Sarah Hutton, Cambridge ), Ch. : ‘We are
certain by inward sense that we can reflect upon ourselves and consider ourselves, which is a reduplication of life in a higher degree. For all cogitative beings as such, are self-conscious’. (p. ) Cf.
also Ch. , p. . On Cudworth’s conception of consciousness, see esp. Thiel ; also Davies
, p. –.
114
Thiel quotes (, pp. –) the following passage from Tillotson’s third sermon on Tim.
:, ‘Of the Immortality of the Soul’. The soul ‘is the Principle whereby we are conscious to our
selves, that we perceive such and such Objects, that we see, or hear, or perceive any thing by any
other Sense; it is that whereby we think and remember, whereby we reason about any thing, and
do freely chuse and refuse such things as are presented to us. These Operations every one is conscious to himself of … those several Operations which by inward Sense and Experience we are
conscious to our selves of ’. (The Works of the most Reverend Dr. John Tillotson, London , .).
115
Thomas Stanley, History of Philosophy (London, ), .. Cf. Rabb , n. .
Richard Cumberland, De legibus naturae (London ), . See Gibson () , p. ;
Rabb , p. –.
116
117
See Harrison and Laslett [] .
De lib. arb. ..–..; cf. Confess. ... For discussion, see Mondolfo ; O’Daly ,
pp. –, –.
118
119
Plot. ...–.
120
Aet. .., = Doxogr. gr .–, = SVF ..
121
P. Herc. /, col. .–, .–. Cf. Lucr. DRN .–.
Cic. Acad. ., . The case for such a connection is made by Sedley , –; Tsouna
, –.
122
802 Victor Caston
tine’s characterization of inner sense, however, bears the closest resemblance to Aristotle’s characterization of the common sense, especially as
set forth in On Sleep and Waking (see above, p. –), a connection
that persists throughout the rest of the medieval tradition. According to
Augustine, the five senses each convey their information to this central
sense, which enables us to discriminate between their various objects
and adjudicate their conflicting reports, as well as perceive that we are
perceiving; and all of this is explicitly said to belong to nonrational animal souls as well as rational human ones. Augustine believes it is crucial
for the explanation of animal behaviour and in particular their ability
to perceive danger and advantage.123
Over the course of the medieval tradition, these functions are separated into different ‘inner senses’, whose number then proliferates. Typically there are five, located in different parts of the brain.124 The inner
senses as a group are then invoked to explain a broad range of cognitive
functions that are shared by animals, including even a form of rudimentary reasoning. Perceiving that we perceive is only one function of
one of these senses, typically the common sense.125 Much work has
already been done on the vicissitudes of the inner senses in the medieval period.126
The later fortunes of this theory, however, and its simplification in
the early modern period into a theory of a single inner sense, is a story
that has not been fully told. Its evolution is not, in any case, a straightforward one. For while the tradition provides the notion of an internal
123
O’Daly argues (, pp. –) that Augustine’s strongest antecedents come from within the
Neoplatonic tradition. But Neoplatonists expressly reject the notion that any sense could be capable of such reflection, which they believe belongs only to incorporeal rational faculties: see n.
below. Likewise, one might be tempted to look for Stoic influence, given their notion of a central
‘executive’ faculty (1gemonikÒn) and their views about an animal’s self-awareness of what is harmful and beneficial. But the parallels here are much more tenuous than those to the Aristotelian tradition.
124
E. g., Avicenna De an. . and .–; Albertus Magnus, De an. lib. tr. q. (b–b
Stroick), cf. De hom. q. a. (. Vivès ed.); Roger Bacon Opus maius pars dist. cap. –,
esp. ; Thomas Aquinas ST a q. a. , esp. ad .
125
Avicenna, it should be noted, does not assign perceiving that we perceive to the common
sense, but to either the estimative sense or the intellect (De an. ., .– Van Riet). This point
is directly confirmed at Kitab al-Mubahathat, para. (as translated by Pines , p. ) and indirectly by his claim that an animal must perceive that it wants something in order to move, something that would presumably belong to the estimative sense as well (De an. ., .–), a view
much like Augustine’s at De lib. arb. ..–. For further discussion of Avicenna’s views on higherorder awareness, cf. Pines , pp. –, –, ; Rahman , pp. –. (I would like to thank
Dr. Dag Hasse for the reference to Avicenna De an. . and helpful correspondence.)
126
Wolfson ; Klubertanz ; Steneck ; Harvey ; Strohmaier ; Kemp and
Fletcher ; Scheerer , pp. –, –; Kemp , pp. –; Theiss .
Aristotle on Consciousness 803
sense that is aware of certain mental activities, it does not yield a notion
of a single capacity that monitors all mental activity. On the contrary, in
so far as the inner sense is a perceptual faculty, its activity is typically
restricted to lower-order perceptual activities. The awareness of higher
cognitive activity is usually assigned to the rational faculties instead,
which are held to be the only faculties capable of genuine ‘reflection’
upon themselves.127
A more encompassing notion of awareness can, however, be found in
certain Greek Neoplatonists, who speak of an ‘attentive’ power (tÚ
prosektikÒn) that belongs to the rational soul and extends to all forms
of mental activity, from the highest to the lowest (Ps.-Philoponus In De
an. .–.):
They say that awareness of the senses’ activities belongs to the attentive part
of the rational soul. For the rational soul does not possesses just five abilities
(understanding, thinking, belief, will, and decision). They also add a certain
sixth ability to the rational soul, which they call the ‘attentive’ ability. The attentive part observes the events that transpire within a person and says, ‘I understood’, ‘I thought’, ‘I believed’, ‘I was angered’, and ‘I desired’. This
attentive part of the rational soul ranges over all abilities in general, rational,
irrational and vegetative. But if the attentive part is to range over all of them,
they say, then let it also encounter the senses and say, ‘I saw’, ‘I heard’. For
to say these things is characteristic of that which is aware of their activities;
if, then, the attentive part says these things, it is aware of the activities of the
senses. For there must be a single thing that is aware of all of them, since the
person is also a single thing. For if one thing were to be aware of these and
another of those, it would be similar to what [Aristotle] says elsewhere: it
would be as though you were perceiving this and I were perceiving that. That
which is attentive, therefore, must be one. For the attentive part consorts
with all abilities, both cognitive and vital. When it consorts with the cognitive abilities, it is called attentive; hence, when we wish to bring someone up
short who is unfocused in his cognitive activities, we say to him ‘mind
yourself’. But when it encounters the vital abilities, it is said to be conscious;
hence the tragedy speaks of ‘the understanding that I am conscious of having
done terrible things’. The attentive part is therefore that which is aware of the
activities of the senses. (.–.)
127
For example, Plot. ..; Porph. Sent. , .–. and , .– Lamberz; Proclus Elem.
theol. prop. ; Ps.-Philop. In De an. .–; Thomas Aquinas In De an. lect. , ll. – (= sect.
Marietti). This argument is later revived by Gassendi (Animadversiones in decimum librum
Diogenis Laertii (Lyons, ), .–; Syntagma pars , sect. , IX.ii, .), and from there gains
currency among British authors, such as Glanvill, Boyle, Charleton, and Stillingfleet (see Michael
and Michael , n. ; Michael and Michael , –, esp. n. ).
804 Victor Caston
As a distinct faculty, the attentive part operates independently of the
activities it monitors; and so some cognitive activities may go unnoticed128 (cf. Plot. ...–):
When reason is preoccupied with something, even if one’s sight sees, we do
not know that it sees, because reason is preoccupied. And after this, when
reason has returned to itself, even though it is not seeing a friend, it now says
that I saw him, as though it had retained a faint trace of what was seen, even
if it was preoccupied, but now having regained presence of mind says, ‘I saw’.
For to say that I saw belongs to reason. (.–)
Here, if anywhere, we have the closest forerunner of the early modern
notion of an internal monitor, if not an internal sense. And because it is
explicitly nonperceptual, it is more naturally expressed in terms of
higher-order judgements, precisely the point at which the metaphor of
‘inner sense’ strains.
On the other hand, there isn’t much question of influence on the
later tradition. It would be implausible to think that these texts were
pivotal for early modern authors. Still, that may not matter as much as
one might have thought. For the history of philosophy performs a valuable service when it examines the systematic connections between
positions not causal ones. It is difficult, if not impossible, to establish
genuine causal influences. But even if one could, they could never be as
interesting as the limits and possibilities of the systematic concerns
themselves.
References
Aquila, Richard E. : ‘The Cartesian and a Certain “Poetic” Notion
of Consciousness’. Journal of the History of Ideas, , pp. –.
Armstrong, D. M. : A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
——: ‘Consciousness and Causality’. In D. M. Armstrong and Norman Malcolm, Consciousness and Causality: A Debate on the Nature
of Mind, pp. –. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Arnauld, Antoine () : Des vraies et des fausses idées. Contre ce
qu’enseigne l’auteur de la Recherche de la vérité. (= Oeuvres de Messire Antoine Arnauld, Tome .) Paris: Sigismond D’Arnay et
Compagnie, . (Originally published, .)
128
For a discussion of the passage, see Bernard ; for the Neoplatonic background to this
theory, see Lautner ; Blumenthal , pp. –. A more extensive translation of the passage
in context can be found in Rahman , pp. –.
Aristotle on Consciousness 805
Baeumker, Clemens : Des Aristoteles Lehre von den äussern und
innern Sinnesvermögen. Ph. D. diss., Münster.
Bell, David : Husserl. London: Routledge.
Bernard, Wolfgang : ‘Philoponus on Self-Awareness’. In Richard
Sorabji (ed.), Philoponus and the Rejection of Aristotelian Science,
pp. –. London: Duckworth.
——: Rezeptivität und Spontaneität der Wahrnehmung bei Aristoteles: Versuch einer Bestimmung der spontanen Erkenntnisleistung der
Wahrnehmung bei Aristoteles in Abgrenzung gegen die rezeptive
Auslegung der Sinnlichkeit bei Descartes und Kant. (= Saecula Spiritalia, Band .) Baden-Baden: Verlag Valentin Koerner.
Block, Irving : ‘The Order of Aristotle’s Psychological Writings’.
American Journal of Philology, , pp. –.
——: ‘Three German Commentators on the Individual Senses and
the Common Sense in Aristotle’s Psychology’. Phronesis, , pp. –
.
Block, Ned : ‘Consciousness’. In Samuel Guttenplan A Companion
to the Philosophy of Mind, pp. –. (= Blackwell Companions to
Philosophy, vol. .) Oxford: Blackwell.
——() : ‘On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness’.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, , (): pp. –. Reprinted in
Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, Güven Güzeldere (eds), The Nature of
Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, pp. –. Cambridge,
Mass.: The MIT Press, .
——: ‘Mental Paint and Mental Latex’. In Enrique Villanueva (ed.),
Perception, pp. –. (= Philosophical Issues, vol. .) Atascadero,
Calif.: Ridgeview Publishing Company.
Blumenthal, H. J. : Aristotle and Neoplatonism in Late Antiquity:
Interpretations of the De Anima. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press.
Bonitz, Hermann () : Index Aristotelicus. Zweite Auflage. Graz:
Akademische Druck- u. Verlagsanstalt, . (First published .)
Bradish, Norman C. : ‘John Sergeant, A Forgotten Critic of Descartes and Locke’. The Monist, , pp. –.
Braun, Egon : ‘Vorläufer des “cogito ergo sum” bei Aristoteles’.
Annales Universitatis Saraviensis, , pp. –.
Bréhier, Emile –: ‘Une forme archaïque du “Cogito ergo sum”’.
Revue philosophique de la France et de l’Etranger, , pp. –.
Brentano, Franz : Die Psychologie des Aristoteles, insbesondere seine
Lehre vom NOUS POIHTIKOS. Mainz: Verlag von Franz Kirchheim.
806 Victor Caston
——() : Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Zweite
Auflage. Bände. Leipzig: Felix Meiner Verlag. (First edition, .)
Burge, Tyler : ‘Individualism and Self-Knowledge’. The Journal of
Philosophy, , pp. –.
Burnyeat, M. F. () : ‘Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still
Credible? (A Draft)’. In Nussbaum and Rorty pp. –. (First
published, .) Oxford: Clarendon Press.
——: How Much Happens when Aristotle Sees Red and Hears
Middle C? Remarks on De anima .–. In Nussbaum and Rorty
, p. –
——: ‘Aquinas on “Spiritual Change” in Perception’. In Dominik
Perler (ed.), Ancient and Medieval Theories of Intentionality, –.
(= Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, Band .)
Leiden: Brill.
——: ‘De anima II ’. Phronesis, , pp. –.
Bywater, Ingram : Contributions to the Textual Criticism of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Cancrini, Antonia : Syneidesis: Il tema semantico della ‘con-scientia’
nella Grecia antica. (= Lessico Intellettuale Europeo, vol. .) Rome:
Edizioni dell’ Ateneo.
Caston, Victor : ‘Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, , pp. –.
Cramer, Konrad : ‘ “Erlebnis”: Thesen zu Hegels Theorie des Selbstbewußtseins mit Rücksicht auf die Aporien eines Grundbegriffs
nachhegelscher Philosophie’. In Hans Georg Gadamer (Hrsg.),
Stuttgarter Hegel-Tage 1970, pp. –. (= Hegel Studien, Beiheft
.) Bonn: Bouvier Verlag.
Davidson, Donald () : ‘The Individuation of Events’. In Nicholas Rescher (ed.), Essays in honor of Carl G. Hempel, pp. –.
Dordrecht: D. Reidel, . Reprinted in his Essays on Actions and
Events, pp. –. Oxford: Clarendon Press, .
Davies, Catherine Glyn : Conscience as Consciousness: The Idea of
Self-Awareness in French Philosophical Writing from Descartes to
Diderot. (= Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century, vol. .)
Oxford: The Voltaire Foundation.
Dennett, D. C. () : Content and Consciousness. Second edition.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, . (First edition, .)
Dretske, Fred : ‘Conscious Experience’. Mind, , pp. –.
———: ‘Introspection’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, ,
pp. –.
Aristotle on Consciousness 807
———: Naturalizing the Mind. The Jean Nicod Lectures.
Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
Eucken, Rudolf : Ueber den Sprachgebrauch des Aristoteles: Beobacht u n g e n ü b e r d i e Prae p os i t i o n e n. B er l i n: Wei d ma n ns ch e
Buchhandlung.
Everson, Stephen : Aristotle on Perception. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Findlay, J. N. () : Meinong’s Theory of Objects and Values. Second edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (First edition, .)
Francescotti, Robert M. : ‘Higher-Order Thoughts and Conscious
Experience’. Philosophical Psychology, , pp. –.
Gadamer, Hans Georg : ‘Vorgestalten der Reflexion’. In Subjektivität und Metaphysik: Festschrift für Wolfgang Cramer, pp. –.
Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
Gennaro, Rocco J. : Consciousness and Self-Consciousness: A Defense
of the Higher-Order Thought Theory of Consciousness. (= Advances
in Consciousness Research, vol. .) Amsterdam: John Benjamins
Publishing Company.
Gibson, James () : Locke’s Theory of Knowledge and its Historical
Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (First printed,
.)
Goldman, Alvin I. () : ‘Consciousness, Folk Psychology, and
Cognitive Science’. Consciousness and Cognition, (), pp. –
. Reprinted in N. Block, O. Flanagan and G. Güzeldere (eds), The
Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical and Scientific Debates,
pp. –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, .
Grossmann, Reinhardt : The Structure of Mind. Madison: The University of Wisconsin Press.
——: Phenomenology and Existentialism: An Introduction. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Hamlyn, D. W. : ‘Koinê Aisthêsis’. The Monist, , pp. –.
——. ‘Aristotle’s Cartesianism’. Paideia, second special issue, pp. –
.
———() : Aristotle De anima, Books II and III (with passages
from Book I). Translated with Introduction and Notes by D. W.
Hamlyn. With a Report on Recent Work and a Revised Bibliography by Christopher Shields. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (First
edition, .)
Hardie, W. F. R. : ‘Concepts of Consciousness in Aristotle’. Mind,
, pp. –.
Harman, Gilbert : ‘Some Philosophical Issues in Cognitive Science:
Qualia, Intentionality, and the Mind–Body Problem’. In Michael I.
808 Victor Caston
Posner (ed.), Foundations of Cognitive Science, pp. –. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
——() : ‘The Intrinsic Quality of Experience’. In Ned Block,
Owen Flanagan and Güven Güzeldere (eds), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, pp. –. Cambridge, Mass.:
The MIT Press, . Reprinted in James Tomberlin (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, vol. , pp. –. Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview
Publishing Co., .
——: ‘Explaining Objective Color in terms of Subjective Experience’. In Enrique Villanueva (ed.), Perception, pp. –. (=
Philosophical Issues, vol. .) Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview Publishing Company.
Harrison, John and Peter Laslett. () . The Library of John Locke.
Second edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (First edition, .)
Harvey, E. Ruth : The Inward Wits: Psychological Theory in the Middle Ages and the Renaissance. (= Warburg Institute Surveys, vol. .)
London: The Warburg Institute.
Henrich, Dieter () : ‘Fichtes ursprüngliche Einsicht’. In Subjektivität und Metaphysik: Festschrift für Wolfgang Crämer, pp. -.
Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, . Reprinted in Fichtes ursprüngliche Einsicht (= Wissenschaft und Gegenwart, Heft ),
Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, .
——: ‘Selbstbewusstsein: Kritische Einleitung in eine Theorie’. In
Rüdiger Bubner, Konrad Cramer and Reiner Wiehl (Hrsg.), Hermeneutik und Dialektik: Aufsätze, Bände, Band I: Methode und
Wissenschaft, Lebenswelt und Geschichte, pp. –. Tübingen: J.
C. B. Mohr.
Herbart, Johann Friedrich –: Psychologie als Wissenschaft, neu
gegründet auf Erfahrung, Metaphysik und Mathematik. Bände.
Königsberg: August Wilhelm Unzer.
Hicks, Robert Drew : Aristotle, De anima. With translation, introduction and notes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Horn, Hans-Jürgen : Studien zum dritten Buch der aristotelischen
Schrift De anima. (= Hypomnemata, Heft .) Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht.
Husserl, Edmund (–) : Zur Phänomenologie des inneren
Zeitbewusstseins. Herausgegeben von Rudolf Boehm. (= Husserliana, Band .) Haag: Martinus Nijhoff. (Originally written, –
.)
——(–) –: Logische Untersuchungen. Elmar Holenstein
and Ursula Panzer. Bände in Teilen. (= Husserliana, Bände –
Aristotle on Consciousness 809
.) The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. (First edition, –
.)
Johansen, T. K. : Aristotle on the Sense-Organs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jung, Gertrud : ‘SUNEIDHSIS, Conscientia, Bewusstsein’. Archiv
für die gesamte Psychologie : –.
Kahn, Charles H. () : ‘Sensation and Consciousness in Aristotle’s Psychology’. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie (): –
. Reprinted in Jonathan Barnes, Malcolm Schofield, Richard Sorabji (eds), Articles on Aristotle, Vol. : Psychology and Aesthetics,
pp. –. London: Duckworth, .
Kant, Immanuel (c. ) : ‘Du sens interne’: Un texte inédit. Edité,
traduit, commenté par R. Brandt, G. Mohr, A. Perrinjaquet, G. Seel,
W. Stark. (= Cahiers de la Revue de Théologie et de Philosophie, no.
.). (Originally written, c. .)
Kemp, Simon : Cognitive Psychology in the Middle Ages. (= Contributions in Psychology, No. .) Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
Kemp, Simon and Garth J. O. Fletcher : ‘The Medieval Theory of
the Inner Senses’. American Journal of Psychology, , pp. –.
Kim, Jaegwon () : ‘Events as Property Exemplifications’. In
Myles Brand and Douglas Walton (eds), Action Theory, pp. –.
Dordrecht: D. Reidel, . Reprinted in his Supervenience and
Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays, pp. –. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, .
Klubertanz, George P. : The Discursive Power: Sources and Doctrine
of the Vis Cogitativa according to St. Thomas Aquinas. Saint Louis:
The Modern Schoolman.
Kosman, L. A. : ‘Perceiving that we Perceive: On the Soul III, ’. The
Philosophical Review, , pp. –.
Krook, Dorothea : John Sergeant and his Circle: A Study of three Seventeenth-century English Aristotelians. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
Lautner, Peter : ‘Rival Theories of Self-Awareness in Late Neoplatonism’. Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies, , pp. –.
Lewis, C. S. : ‘Conscience and Consciousness’. In his Studies in
Words, pp. –. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lewis, Frank A. : ‘Accidental Sameness in Aristotle’. Philosophical
Studies, , pp. –.
——: Substance and Predication in Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
——: ‘Self-Knowledge in Aristotle’. Topoi, , pp. –.
810 Victor Caston
Lewis, Geneviève : Le problème de l’inconscient et le cartésianisme.
Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
Lycan, William G. : Consciousness. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT
Press.
——() : ‘Consciousness as Internal Monitoring’. In J. E. Tomberlin (ed.), AI, Connectionism, and Philosophy of Psychology, pp. –
. (= Philosophical Perspectives, vol. .) Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview Publishing Company, . Reprinted in an expanded form
in Ned Block, Owen Flanagan, and Güven Güzeldere (eds), The
Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, pp. –. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, .
——: Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT
Press.
Lyons, William : The Disappearance of Introspection. Cambridge,
Mass.: The MIT Press.
Malcolm, Norman : ‘Consciousness and Causality’. In D. M. Armstrong and Norman Malcolm, Consciousness and Causality: A
Debate on the Nature of Mind, pp. –. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Mayer, Cornelius : ‘Conscientia’. In Cornelius Mayer (Hrsg.)
Augustinus-Lexikon, Band , –. Basel: Schwabe und Co. AG.
Michael, Emily and Fred S. Michael. . ‘Gassendi on Sensation and
Reflection: A Non-Cartesian Dualism’. History of European Ideas, ,
pp. –.
——: ‘Two Early Modern Concepts of Mind: Reflecting Substance
vs. Thinking Substance’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, ,
pp. –.
Milner, A. David and Melvyn A. Goodale : The Visual Brain in
Action. (= Oxford Psychology Series, No. .) Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Modrak, Deborah : ‘An Aristotelian Theory of Consciousness?’
Ancient Philosophy, , pp. –.
——: Aristotle: The Power of Perception. Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press.
Mohr, Georg : Das sinnliche Ich: Innerer Sinn und Bewußtsein bei
Kant. (= Epistemata, Reihe Philosophie, Band .) Würzburg:
Königshausen und Neumann.
Mondolfo, Rodolfo : ‘La teoria agostiniana del senso interno ed i
suoi antecedenti greci’. In his Momenti del pensiero greco e cristiano,
pp. –. (= Collana di Filosofia, vol. .) Naples: Morano Editore.
Moore, G. E. () : ‘The Refutation of Idealism’. Mind ():
pp. –. Reprinted in his Philosophical Studies, –. London:
Aristotle on Consciousness 811
Routledge and Kegan Paul, . (Originally published, .)
Nadler, Steven M. : Arnauld and the Cartesian Philosophy of Ideas.
Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Neuhaeuser, J. : Aristoteles’ Lehre von dem sinnlichen Erkenntnisvermögen und seinen Organen. Leipzig: Verlag von Erich Koschny.
Nussbaum, Martha C. and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds) : Essays
on Aristotle’s De anima. First paperback edition, including an additional essay by M. F. Burnyeat. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
O’Daly, Gerard : Augustine’s Philosophy of Mind. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Oehler, Klaus : Die Lehre vom noetischen und dianoetischen Denken
bei Platon und Aristoteles: Ein Beitrag zur Erforschung der Geschichte
des Bewußtseinsproblems in der Antike. Munich: C.H. Beck’sche Verlagsbuchhandlung.
——: ‘Aristotle on Self-Knowledge’. Proceedings of the American
Philosophical Society, , pp. –.
——: Subjektivität und Selbstbewußtsein in der Antike. Würzburg:
Königshausen und Neumann.
Osborne, Catherine : ‘Aristotle, De anima .: How do We Perceive
that We See and Hear?’ Classical Quarterly, n. s. , pp. –.
Peacocke, Christopher : Sense and Content: Experience, Thought,
and their Relations. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Pines, S. : ‘La conception de la conscience de soi chez Avicenne et
chez Abu’l-Barakat al-Baghdadi’. Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Age, , pp. –.
Pothast, Ulrich : Über einige Fragen der Selbstbeziehung. (= Philosophische Abhandlungen, Band .) Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio
Klostermann.
Rabb, J. Douglas : John Locke on Reflection: A Phenomenology Lost.
(= Current Contintental Research, vol. .) Washington, D. C.: University Press of America.
Rahman, F. : Avicenna’s Psychology. An English translation of Kitab
al-Najat, Book II, Chapter VI, with historico-philosophical notes
and textual improvements on the Cairo edition. London: Oxford
University Press.
Rodier, G. (ed.) : Aristote, Traité de l’âme. Traduit et annoté.
tomes. Paris: Ernest Leroux.
Rorty, Richard : Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Rosenthal, David M. . ‘Two Concepts of Consciousness’. Philosophical Studies, , pp. –.
812 Victor Caston
——. ‘The Independence of Consciousness and Sensory Quality’.
In Enrique Villanueva Consciousness, pp. –. (= Philosophical
Issues, vol. .) Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview Publishing Company.
——a. ‘State Consciousness and Transitive Consciousness’. Consciousness and Cognition, , pp. –.
——b. ‘Thinking that One Thinks’. In Martin Davies and Glyn W.
Humphreys (eds), Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical
Essays, pp. –. (= Readings in Mind and Language, vol. .)
Oxford: Blackwell.
——: ‘A Theory of Consciousness’. In N. Block, O. Flanagan and G.
Güzeldere (eds), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical and Scientific Debates, pp. –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
——forthcoming: ‘Explaining Consciousness’. In David J. Chalmers
(ed.) Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Ross, W. D. : Aristotle, De anima. Edited, with introduction and
commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Russell, Bertrand: () . Theory of Knowledge: The 1913 Manuscript. Edited by Elizabeth Ramsden Eames. London: Routledge.
(Originally written, .)
Ryle, Gilbert : The Concept of Mind. New York: Barnes and Noble,
Inc.
Sartre, Jean-Paul () : La transcendance de l’Ego: Esquisse d’une
description phénoménologique. Introduction, notes et appendices
par Sylvie Le Bon. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin. (Originally
published, .)
——() : L’être et le néant. Paris: Librairie Gallimard. (Originally published, .)
——: ‘Conscience de soi et connaissance de soi’. Bulletin de la
Société française de Philosophie, , pp. –.
Scheerer, E. : ‘Die Sinne’. In Joachim Ritter and Karlfried Gründer
(Hrsg.), Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, Bände, Band ,
–. Völlig neubearbeitete Ausgabe des Wörterbuchs der philosophischen Begriffe von Rudolf Eisler. Basel: Schwabe & Co.
Schell, J. Hermann : Die Einheit des Seelenlebens aus den Principien
der Aristotelischen Philosophie. Freiburg im Breisgau: F. J. Scheuble.
Schmitz, Hermann : System der Philosophie. Bände. Erster Band:
Die Gegenwart. Bonn: H. Bouvier u. Co. Verlag.
Schuhl, Pierre-Maxime : ‘Y a-t-il une source aristotélicienne du
“Cogito”?’ Revue philosophique de la France et de l'Etranger, ,
pp. –.
Aristotle on Consciousness 813
Schwyzer, H.-R. : ‘ “Bewusst” und “unbewusst” bei Plotin’. In Les
sources de Plotin, pp. –. (= Entretiens sur l’Antiquité Classique,
Tome .) Geneva: Fondation Hardt.
Sedley, David : ‘Epicurus on the Common Sensibles’. In Pamela
Huby and Gordon Neal (eds), The Criterion of Truth, pp. –.
Essays written in honour of George Kerferd together with a text and
translation (with annotations) of Ptolemy’s On the Kriterion and
Hegemonikon. Liverpool: Liverpool University Press.
Shoemaker, Sydney: () : ‘Qualities and Qualia: What’s in the
Mind?’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, suppl. vol.
(), pp. –. Reprinted in Sydney Shoemaker, The First–Person Perspective and Other Essays, pp. –. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, .
——() . ‘Qualia and Consciousness’. Mind, (), pp. –
. Reprinted in Sydney Shoemaker, The First–Person Perspective
and Other Essays, pp. –. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, .
Shorey, Paul : Review of G. Rodier, Aristote Traité de l’Âme. American Journal of Philology, , pp. –.
Siebeck, H. : ‘Der Begriff des Bewußtseins in der alten Philosophie’.
Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, n. F. ,
pp. –.
Smith, David Woodruff : ‘The Structure of (Self-) Consciousness’.
Topoi, , pp. –.
——: The Circle of Acquaintance: Perception, Consciousness, and
Empathy. (= Synthese Library, vol. .) Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Sorabji, Richard. () . ‘Body and Soul in Aristotle’. Philosophy,
(), pp. –. Reprinted in Jonathan Barnes, Malcolm
Schofield, Richard Sorabji (eds), Articles on Aristotle, Vol. : Psychology and Aesthetics, pp. –. London: Duckworth, .
——: ‘Intentionality and Physiological Processes: Aristotle’s Theory of Sense-Perception’. In Martha C. Nussbaum and Amélie
Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De anima, pp. –.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
——: ‘Aristotle on Sensory Processes and Intentionality ’. In
Dominik Perler (ed.), Ancient and Medieval Theories of Intentionality, pp. –. (=Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des
Mittelalters, Band .) Leiden: E. J. Brill.
Steneck, Nicholas H. : ‘Albert the Great on the Classification and
Localization of the Internal Senses’. Isis, , pp. –.
814 Victor Caston
Strohmaier, Gotthard : ‘Avicennas Lehre von den “inneren Sinnen”
und ihre Voraussetzungen bei Galen’. In Paola Manuli and Mario
Vegetti (eds), Le opere psicologiche di Galeno, pp. –. Atti del
terzo colloquio galenico internazionale, Pavia, - settembre .
(= Elenchos, vol. .) Naples: Bibliopolis.
Stubenberg, Leopold : Consciousness and Qualia. (= Advances in
Consciousness Research, vol. .) Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
Stumpf, Carl : ‘Erinnerungen an Franz Brentano’. In Oskar Kraus
(Hrsg.), Franz Brentano: Zur Kenntnis seines Lebens und seiner
Lehre, Anhang I. Munich: C. H. Beck’sche Verlagsbuchhandlung.
Theiss, Peter : Die Wahrnehmungspsychologie und Sinnesphysiologie
des Albertus Magnus: Ein Modell der Sinnes- und Hirnfunktion aus
der Zeit des Mittelalters. (= Europäische Hochschulschriften, Reihe
III: Geschichte und ihre Hilfswissenschaften, Band .) Frankfurt
am Main: Peter Lang.
Thiel, Udo : Lockes Theorie der personalen Identität. (= Abhandlungen zur Philosophie, Psychologie und Pädogogik, Band .) Bonn:
Bouvier Verlag.
——: ‘Cudworth and Seventeenth-Century Theories of Consciousness’. In Stephen Gaukroger (ed.), The Uses of Antiquity: The
Scientific Revolution and the Classical Tradition, pp. –. (= Australian Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, vol. .)
Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
——: ‘Hume’s Notions of Consciousness and Reflection in Context’. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, , pp. –.
——: ‘Between Wolff and Kant: Merian’s Theory of Apperception’.
Journal of the History of Philosophy, , pp. –.
——: ‘Varieties of Inner Sense: Two Pre-Kantian Theories’. Archiv
für Geschichte der Philosophie, , pp. –.
Torstrik, Adolf (ed.) : Aristotelis De anima, Libri III. Berlin:
Weidmann.
Tsouna, Voula : The Epistemology of the Cyrenaic School. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tugendhat, Ernst : Selbstbewusstsein und Selbstbestimmung: sprachanalytische Interpretationen. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Wardy, Robert : The Chain of Change: A Study of Aristotle’s Physics
VII. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wider, Kathleen : The Bodily Nature of Consciousness: Sartre and
Contemporary Philosophy of Mind. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press.
Aristotle on Consciousness 815
Wilkes, Kathleen V. : ‘Is Consciousness Important?’ British Journal
for the Philosophy of Science, , pp. –.
——: ‘——, yìshì, duh, um and consciousness’. In A. J. Marcel and
E. Bisiach (eds), Consciousness in Contemporary Science, pp. –.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wolfson, Harry Austryn : ‘The Internal Senses in Latin, Arabic, and
Hebrew Philosophic Texts’. Harvard Theological Review, , pp. –
.
Yolton, John W. : ‘Locke’s Unpublished Marginal Replies to John
Sergeant’. Journal of the History of Ideas, , pp. –.
Zahavi, Dan. : ‘Brentano and Husserl on Self-Awareness’. Etudes
Phénoménologiques, nos. –, pp. –.
Zucker, Friedrich : Syneidesis–Conscientia: Ein Versuch zur Geschichte des sittlichen Bewußtseins im griechischen und im griechischrömischen Altertum. Rede gehalten zur Feier der akademischen Preisverteilung am . Juni im Volkshaus zu Jena. (= Jenaer
akademische Reden, Heft .) Jena: Verlag von Gustav Fischer. |
JULIAN JAYNES
T H E ORIGIN OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
IN T H E BREAK
DOWN OF T H E
BICAMERAL MIND
Julian Jaynes
THE ORIGIN OF
CONSCIOUSNESS IN
THE BREAKDOWN OF THE
BICAMERAL
MIND
A Mariner Book
HOUGHTON MIFFLIN COMPANY
BOSTON
•
NEW Y O R K
First Mariner Books edition 2000
Copyright © 1976,1990 by Julian Jaynes
All rights reserved.
For information about permission to reproduce selections from
this book, write to Permissions, Houghton Mifflin Company,
215 Park Avenue South, New York, New York 10003.
Visit our Web site: www.hmco.com/trade.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Jaynes, Julian.
The origin of consciousness in the breakdown of the
bicameral mind.
Includes no index. Scanned in May 2011 by LnZ.
1. Consciousness. 2. Consciousness — History. I. Title.
BF311.J36 I28‘.2 76-28748
ISBN 0 - 6 1 8 - 0 5 7 0 7 - 2 ( p b k . )
Printed in the United States of America
D O C 20 19 18 17 16 15 14
See last page of book for credits.
PREFACE
T
HE CENTRAL ideas of this inquiry were first summarized
publicly in an Invited Address to the American Psychological Association in Washington in September 1969. Since then, I
have been something of an itinerant lecturer, various parts of this
work having been given at colloquia and lectures at various places.
The resulting attention and discussion have been very helpful.
Book I presents these ideas as I arrived at them.
Book II examines the historical evidence.
Book III makes deductions to explain some modern phenomena.
Originally, I had planned Books IV and V to complete the
central positions of the theory. These will now become a separate
volume, whose working title is The Consequences of Consciousness, not yet scheduled for publication.
PRINCETON
UNIVERSITY,
I982
CONTENTS
P R E F A C E
V
I N T R O D U C T I O N : T H E P R O B L E M O F CONSCIOUSNESS
I
Book I
The Mind of Man
1. The Consciousness of Consciousness
2. Consciousness
3. The Mind of Iliad
4. The Bicameral Mind
5. The Double Brain
6. The Origin of Civilization
21
48
67
84
100
126
Book II
The Witness of History
1. Gods, Graves, and Idols
2. Literate Bicameral Theocracies
3. The Causes of Consciousness
4. A Change of Mind in Mesopotamia
5. The Intellectual Consciousness of Greece
6. The Moral Consciousness of the Khabiru
149
176
204
223
255
293
Book III
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
1. The Quest for Authorization
2. Of Prophets and Possession
3. Of Poetry and Music
4. Hypnosis
5. Schizophrenia
6. The Auguries of Science
317
339
361
379
404
433
A F T E R W O R D
447
I N D E X
471
The Origin of Consciousness
in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind
INTRODUCTION
The Problem of Consciousness
O
, W H A T A WORLD of unseen visions and heard silences, this
insubstantial country of the mind! What ineffable essences,
these touchless rememberings and unshowable reveries! And the
privacy of it all! A secret theater of speechless monologue and
prevenient counsel, an invisible mansion of all moods, musings,
and mysteries, an infinite resort of disappointments and discoveries. A whole kingdom where each of us reigns reclusively alone,
questioning what we will, commanding what we can. A hidden
hermitage where we may study out the troubled book of what we
have done and yet may do. An introcosm that is more myself
than anything I can find in a mirror. This consciousness that is
myself of selves, that is everything, and yet nothing at a l l 一
what is it?
And where did it come from?
And why?
Few questions have endured longer or traversed a more perplexing history than this, the problem of consciousness and its
place in nature. Despite centuries of pondering and experiment,
of trying to get together two supposed entities called mind and
matter in one age, subject and object in another, or soul and body
in still others, despite endless discoursing on the streams, states,
or contents of consciousness, of distinguishing terms like intuitions, sense data, the given, raw feels, the sensa, presentations
and representations, the sensations, images, and affections of
structuralist introspections, the evidential data of the scientific
positivist, phenomenological fields, the apparitions of Hobbes, the
phenomena of Kant, the appearances of the idealist, the elements
of Mach, the phanera of Peirce, or the category errors of Ryle, in
2
Introduction
spite of all of these, the problem of consciousness is still with us.
Something about it keeps returning, not taking a solution.
It is the difference that will not go away, the difference between what others see of us and our sense of our inner selves and
the deep feelings that sustain it. The difference between the youand-me of the shared behavioral world and the unlocatable location of things thought about. Our reflections and dreams, and the
imaginary conversations we have with others, in which never-tobe-known-by-anyone we excuse, defend, proclaim our hopes and
regrets, our futures and our pasts, all this thick fabric of fancy is
so absolutely different from handable, standable, kickable reality
with its trees, grass, tables, oceans, hands, stars — even brains!
How is this possible? How do these ephemeral existences of our
lonely experience fit into the ordered array of nature that somehow surrounds and engulfs this core of knowing?
Men have been conscious of the problem of consciousness
almost since consciousness began. And each age has described
consciousness in terms of its own theme and concerns. In the
golden age of Greece, when men traveled about in freedom while
slaves did the work, consciousness was as free as that. Heraclitus, in particular, called it an enormous space whose boundaries,
even by traveling along every path, could never be found out.1 A
millennium later, Augustine among the caverned hills of Carthage was astonished at the “mountains and hills of my high imaginations,” “the plains and caves and caverns of my memory” with
its recesses of “manifold and spacious chambers, wonderfully
furnished with unnumberable stores.”2 Note how the metaphors
of mind are the world it perceives.
The first half of the nineteenth century was the age of the
great geological discoveries in which the record of the past was
written in layers of the earth’s crust. And this led to the popularization of the idea of consciousness as being in layers which
1 Diels, Fragment, 45.
2 Confessions, 9:7; 10:26,
65.
T H E
P R O B L E M
3
recorded the past of the individual, there being deeper and deeper
layers until the record could no longer be read. This emphasis on
the unconscious grew until by 1875 most psychologists were
insisting that consciousness was but a small part of mental life,
and that unconscious sensations, unconscious ideas, and unconscious judgments made up the majority of mental processes.3
In the middle of the nineteenth century chemistry succeeded
geology as the fashionable science, and consciousness from
James Mill to Wundt and his students, such as Titchener, was the
compound structure that could be analyzed in the laboratory into
precise elements of sensations and feelings.
And as steam locomotives chugged their way into the pattern
of everyday life toward the end of the nineteenth century, so they
too worked their way into the consciousness of consciousness, the
subconscious becoming a boiler of straining energy which demanded manifest outlets and when repressed pushed up and out
into neurotic behavior and the spinning camouflaged fulfillments
of going-nowhere dreams.
There is not much we can do about such metaphors except to
state that that is precisely what they are.
Now originally, this search into the nature of consciousness
was known as the mind-body problem, heavy with its ponderous
philosophical solutions. But since the theory of evolution, it has
bared itself into a more scientific question. It has become the
problem of the origin of mind, or, more specifically, the origin of
consciousness in evolution. Where can this subjective experience
which we introspect upon, this constant companion of hosts of
associations, hopes, fears, affections, knowledges, colors, smells,
toothaches, thrills, tickles, pleasures, distresses, and desires —
where and how in evolution could all this wonderful tapestry of
inner experience have evolved? How can we derive this inwardness out of mere matter? And if so, when?
3 For a statement of this effect, see G. H. Lewes, The Physical Basis of Mind (London: Trübner, 1877), p. 365.
4
Introduction
This problem has been at the very center of the thinking of the
twentieth century. And it will be worthwhile here to briefly look
at some of the solutions that have been proposed. I shall mention
the eight that I think are most important.
Consciousness as a Property of Matter
The most extensive possible solution is attractive mostly to
physicists. It states that the succession of subjective states that
we feel in introspection has a continuity that stretches all the way
back through phylogenetic evolution and beyond into a fundamental property of interacting matter. The relationship of consciousness to what we are conscious of is not fundamentally
different from the relationship of a tree to the ground in which it
is rooted, or even of the gravitational relationship between two
celestial bodies. This view was conspicuous in the first quarter of
this century. What Alexander called compresence or Whitehead
called prehension provided the groundwork of a monism that
moved on into a flourishing school called Neo-Realism. If a piece
of chalk is dropped on the lecture table, that interaction of chalk
and table is different only in complexity from the perceptions and
knowledges that fill our minds. The chalk knows the table just
as the table knows the chalk. That is why the chalk stops at the
table.
This is something of a caricature of a very subtly worked out
position, but it nevertheless reveals that this difficult theory is
answering quite the wrong question. We are not trying to explain
how we interact with our environment, but rather the particular
experience that we have in introspecting. The attractiveness of
this kind of neo-realism was really a part of an historical epoch
when the astonishing successes of particle physics were being
talked of everywhere. The solidity of matter was being dissolved
into mere mathematical relationships in space, and this seemed
like the same unphysical quality as the relationship of individuals
conscious of each other.
THE
PROBLEM
5
Consciousness as a Property of Protoplasm
The next most extensive solution asserts that consciousness is
not in matter per se; rather it is the fundamental property of all
living things. It is the very irritability of the smallest one-celled
animals that has had a continuous and glorious evolution up
through coelenterates, the protochordates, fish, amphibians, reptiles, and mammals to man.
A wide variety of nineteenth- and twentieth-century scientists,
including Charles Darwin and E. B. Titchener, found this thesis
unquestionable, initiating in the first part of this century a great
deal of excellent observation of lower organisms. The search for
rudimentary consciousnesses was on. Books with titles such as
The Animal Mind or The Psychic Life of Micro-Organisms were
eagerly written and eagerly read.4 And anyone who observes
amoebas hunting food or responding to various stimuli, or paramecia avoiding obstacles or conjugating, will know the almost
passionate temptation to apply human categories to such behavior.
And this brings us to a very important part of the problem —
our sympathy and identification with other living things. Whatever conclusions we may hold on the matter, it is certainly a part
of our consciousness to ‘see’ into the consciousness of others, to
identify with our friends and families so as to imagine what they
are thinking and feeling. And so if animals are behaving such as
we would in similar situations, so well are we trained in our
human sympathies that it requires a particular vigor of mind to
suppress such identifications when they are not warranted. The
explanation for our imputing consciousness to protozoa is simply
that we make this common and misleading identification. Yet the
explanation for their behavior resides entirely in physical chemistry, not in introspective psychology.
Even in animals with synaptic nervous systems, the tendency
4 By Margaret Floy Washburn, a Titchenerian, and by Alfred Binet respectively.
The real classic in the field of early evolved animals is H. S. Jennings, Behavior of
the Lower Organisms (New York: Macmillan, 1906).
6
Introduction
to read consciousness into their behavior comes more from ourselves than from our observations. Most people will identify with
a struggling worm. But as every boy who has baited a fish hook
knows, if a worm is cut in two, the front half with its primitive
brain seems not to mind as much as the back half, which writhes
in ‘agony’. 5 But surely if the worm felt pain as we do, surely it
would be the part with the brain that would do the agonizing.
The agony of the tail end is our agony, not the worm’s; its
writhing is a mechanical release phenomenon, the motor nerves
in the tail end firing in volleys at being disconnected from their
normal inhibition by the cephalic ganglion.
Consciousness as Learning
To make consciousness coextensive with protoplasm leads, of
course, to a discussion of the criterion by which consciousness
can be inferred. And hence a third solution, which states that
consciousness began not with matter, nor at the beginning of
animal life, but at some specific time after life had evolved. It
seemed obvious to almost all the active investigators of the subject that the criterion of when and where in evolution consciousness began was the appearance of associative memory or learning. If an animal could modify its behavior on the basis of its
experience, it must be having an experience; it must be conscious. Thus, if one wished to study the evolution of consciousness, one simply studied the evolution of learning.
This was indeed how I began my search for the origin of
consciousness. My first experimental work was a youthful attempt to produce signal learning (or a conditional response) in
an especially long suffering mimosa plant. The signal was an
intense light; the response was the drooping of a leaf to a care5 Since an earthworm ‘writhes’ from the tactile stimulation of simply being handled,
the experiment is best performed with a razor blade as the worm is crawling over
some hard ground or a board. The unbelieving and squeamish may suppress their
anguish with the consciousness that they are helping the worm population (and therefore the robin population) since both ends regenerate.
THE
PROBLEM
7
fully calibrated tactile stimulus where it joined the stem. After
over a thousand pairings of the light and the tactile stimulus, my
patient plant was as green as ever. It was not conscious.
That expected failure behind me, I moved on to protozoa, delicately running individual paramecia in a T-maze engraved in wax
on black Bakelite, using direct current shock to punish the animal
and spin it around if it went to the incorrect side. If paramecia
could learn, I felt they had to be conscious. Moreover I was
extremely interested in what would happen to the learning
(and the consciousness) when the animal divided. A first suggestion of positive results was not borne out in later replications.
After other failures to find learning in the lower phyla, I moved
on to species with synaptic nervous systems, flatworms, earthworms, fish, and reptiles, which could indeed learn, all on the
naive assumption that I was chronicling the grand evolution of
consciousness.6
Ridiculous! It was, I fear, several years before I realized that
this assumption makes no sense at all. When we introspect, it is
not upon any bundle of learning processes, and particularly not
the types of learning denoted by conditioning and T-mazes. Why
then did so many worthies in the lists of science equate consciousness and learning? And why had I been so lame of mind as
to follow them?
The reason was the presence of a kind of huge historical
neurosis. Psychology has many of them. And one of the reasons
that the history of science is essential to the study of psychology
is that it is the only way to get out of and above such intellectual
disorders. The school of psychology known as Associationism in
the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries had been so attractively
presented and so peopled with prestigious champions that its
basic error had become imbedded in common thought and lan6 For the most recent discussion of this important but methodologically difficult
problem of the evolution of learning, see M. E. Bitterman’s Thorndike Centenary
Address, “The Comparative Analysis of Learning,” Science, 1975, 188:699-709.
Other references may be found in R. A. Hinde’s Animal Behavior, 2nd ed. (New
York: McGraw-Hill, 1970), particularly pp. 658-663.
Introduction
8
guage. That error was, and still is, that consciousness is an
actual space inhabited by elements called sensations and ideas,
and the association of these elements because they are like each
other, or because they have been made by the external world to
occur together, is indeed what learning is and what the mind is
all about. So learning and consciousness are confused and muddled up with that vaguest of terms, experience.
It is this confusion that lingered unseen behind my first struggles with the problem, as well as the huge emphasis on animal
learning in the first half of the twentieth century. But it is now
absolutely clear that in evolution the origin of learning and the
origin of consciousness are two utterly separate problems. We
shall be demonstrating this assertion with more evidence in the
next chapter.
Consciousness as a Metaphysical Imposition
A l l the theories I have so far mentioned begin in the assumption that consciousness evolved biologically by simple natural
selection. But another position denies that such an assumption is
even possible.
Is this consciousness, it asks, this enormous influence of ideas,
principles, beliefs over our lives and actions, really derivable from
animal behavior? Alone of species, all alone! we try to understand ourselves and the world. We become rebels or patriots or
martyrs on the basis of ideas. We build Chartres and computers,
write poems and tensor equations, play chess and quartets, sail
ships to other planets and listen in to other galaxies — what have
these to do with rats in mazes or the threat displays of baboons?
The continuity hypothesis of Darwin for the evolution of mind is
a very suspicious totem of evolutionary mythology. 7 The yearning for certainty which grails the scientist, the aching beauty
7 To
demonstrate such continuity was the purpose of Darwin’s second most important work, The Descent of Man.
THE
PROBLEM
9
which harasses the artist, the sweet thorn of justice which fierces
the rebel from the eases of life, or the thrill of exultation with
which we hear of true acts of that now difficult virtue of courage,
of cheerful endurance of hopeless suffering — are these really
derivable from matter? Or even continuous with the idiot hierarchies of speechless apes?
The chasm is awesome. The emotional lives of men and of
other mammals are indeed marvelously similar. But to focus
upon the similarity unduly is to forget that such a chasm exists at
all. The intellectual life of man, his culture and history and
religion and science, is different from anything else we know of
in the universe. That is fact. It is as if all life evolved to a certain
point, and then in ourselves turned at a right angle and simply
exploded in a different direction.
The appreciation of this discontinuity between the apes and
speaking civilized ethical intellectual men has led many scientists
back to a metaphysical view. The interiority of consciousness
just could not in any sense be evolved by natural selection out of
mere assemblages of molecules and cells. There has to be more
to human evolution than mere matter, chance, and survival.
Something must be added from outside of this closed system to
account for something so different as consciousness.
Such thinking began with the beginning of modern evolutionary theory, particularly in the work of Alfred Russel Wallace, the
codiscoverer of the theory of natural selection. Following their
twin announcements of the theory in 1858, both Darwin and
Wallace struggled like Laocoons with the serpentine problem of
human evolution and its encoiling difficulty of consciousness.
But where Darwin clouded the problem with his own naivete,
seeing only continuity in evolution, Wallace could not do so. The
discontinuities were terrifying and absolute. Man’s conscious
faculties, particularly, “could not possibly have been developed by
means of the same laws which have determined the progressive
development of the organic world in general, and also of man’s
10
Introduction
physical organism.”8 He felt the evidence showed that some
metaphysical force had directed evolution at three different
points: the beginning of life, the beginning of consciousness, and
the beginning of civilized culture. Indeed, it is partly because
Wallace insisted on spending the latter part of his life searching
in vain among the seances of spiritualists for evidence of such
metaphysical imposition that his name is not as well known as is
Darwin’s as the discoverer of evolution by natural selection. Such
endeavors were not acceptable to the scientific Establishment. To
explain consciousness by metaphysical imposition seemed to be
stepping outside the rules of natural science. And that indeed
was the problem, how to explain consciousness in terms of natural science alone.
The Helpless Spectator Theory
In reaction to such metaphysical speculations, there grew up
through this early period of evolutionary thinking an increasingly
materialist view. It was a position more consistent with straight
natural selection. It even had inherent in it that acrid pessimism
that is sometimes curiously associated with really hard science.
This doctrine assures us consciousness does nothing at all, and
in fact can do nothing. Many tough-minded experimentalists still
agree with Herbert Spencer that such a downgrading of consciousness is the only view that is consistent with straight evolutionary theory. Animals are evolved; nervous systems and their
mechanical reflexes increase in complexity; when some unspecified degree of nervous complexity is reached, consciousness
appears, and so begins its futile course as a helpless spectator of
cosmic events.
What we do is completely controlled by the wiring diagram of
the brain and its reflexes to external stimuli. Consciousness is not
8 Darwinism, an Exposition of the Theory of Natural Selection (London: Macmillan, 1889), p. 475; see also Wallace’s Contributions to the Theory of Natural
Selection, Ch. 1o.
THE
PROBLEM
11
more than the Heat given off by the wires, a mere epiphenomenon. Conscious feelings, as Hodgson put it, are mere colors laid
on the surface of a mosaic which is held together by its stones,
not by the colors.9 Or as Huxley insisted in a famous essay, “we
are conscious automata."10 Consciousness can no more modify
the working mechanism of the body or its behavior than can the
whistle of a train modify its machinery or where it goes. Moan as
it will, the tracks have long ago decided where the train will go.
Consciousness is the melody that floats from the harp and cannot pluck its strings, the foam struck raging from the river that
cannot change its course, the shadow that loyally walks step for
step beside the pedestrian, but is quite unable to influence his
journey.
It is William James who has given the best discussion of the
conscious automaton theory. 11 His argument here is a little like
Samuel Johnson’s downing philosophical idealism by kicking a
stone and crying, “I refute it thus!” It is just plain inconceivable
that consciousness should have nothing to do with a business
which it so faithfully attends. If consciousness is the mere impotent shadow of action, why is it more intense when action is most
hesitant? And why are we least conscious when doing something
most habitual? Certainly this seesawing relationship between
consciousness and actions is something that any theory of consciousness must explain.
Emergent
Evolution
The doctrine of emergent evolution was very specifically welcomed into court to rescue consciousness from this undignified
9 Shadworth Hodgson, The Theory of Practice (London: Longmans Green, 1870),
1:416.
10 And volitions merely symbols of brain-states. T. H. Huxley, Collected Essays
(New York: Appleton, 1896), Vol. 1, p. 244.
11 William James, Principles of Psychology (New York: Holt, 1890), Vol. 1, Ch.
5), but also see William McDougall, Body and Mind (London: Methuen, 1911),
Chs. 11, 12.
12
Introduction
position as a mere helpless spectator. It was also designed to
explain scientifically the observed evolutionary discontinuities
that had been the heart of the metaphysical imposition argument.
And when I first began to study it some time ago, I, too, felt with
a shimmering flash how everything, the problem of consciousness and all, seemed to shiveringly fall into accurate and wonderful place.
Its main idea is a metaphor: Just as the property of wetness
cannot be derived from the properties of hydrogen and oxygen
alone, so consciousness emerged at some point in evolution in a
way underivable from its constituent parts.
While this simple idea goes back to John Stuart Mill and G. H.
Lewes, it was Lloyd Morgan’s version in his Emergent Evolution
of 1923 that really captured the cheering. This book is a thoroughgoing scheme of emergent evolution vigorously carried all
the way back into the physical realm. A l l the properties of matter
have emerged from some unspecified forerunner. Those of complex chemical compounds have emerged from the conjunction of
simpler chemical components. Properties distinctive of living
things have emerged from the conjunctions of these complex
molecules. And consciousness emerged from living things. New
conjunctions bring about new kinds of relatedness which bring
about new emergents. So the new emergent properties are in
each case effectively related to the systems from which they
emerge. In fact, the new relations emergent at each higher level
guide and sustain the course of events distinctive of that level.
Consciousness, then, emerges as something genuinely new at a
critical stage of evolutionary advance. When it has emerged, it
guides the course of events in the brain and has causal efficacy in
bodily behavior.
The whoop with which this antireductionist doctrine was
greeted by the majority of prominent biological and comparative
psychologists, frustrated dualists all, was quite undignified. Biologists called it a new Declaration of Independence from physics
and chemistry. “No longer can the biologist be bullied into sup-
THE
PROBLEM
13
pressing observed results because they are not discovered nor
expected from work on the non-living. Biology becomes a science
in its own right. Prominent neurologists agreed that now we no
longer had to think of consciousness as merely dancing an assiduous but futile attendance upon our brain processes.12 The
origin of consciousness seemed to have been pointed at in such a
way as to restore consciousness to its usurped throne as the
governor of behavior and even to promise new and unpredictable
emergents in the future.
But had it? If consciousness emerged in evolution, when? In
what species? What kind of a nervous system is necessary? And
as the first flush of a theoretical breakthrough waned, it was seen
that nothing about the problem had really changed. It is these
specifics that need to be answered. What is wrong about emergent evolution is not the doctrine, but the release back into old
comfortable ways of thinking about consciousness and behavior,
the license that it gives to broad and vacuous generalities.
Historically, it is of interest here to note that all this dancing in
the aisles of biology over emergent evolution was going on at the
same time that a stronger, less-educated doctrine with a rigorous
experimental campaign was beginning its robust conquest of psychology. Certainly one way of solving the problem of consciousness and its place in nature is to deny that consciousness exists at
all.
Behaviorism
It is an interesting exercise to sit down and try to be conscious
of what it means to say that consciousness does not exist. History
has not recorded whether or not this feat was attempted by the
early behaviorists. But it has recorded everywhere and in large
12 The quote here is from H. S. Jennings and the paraphrase from C. Judson
Herrick. For these and other reactions to emergent evolution, see F. Mason, Creation
by Evolution (London: Duckworth, 1928) and W. McDougall, Modern Materialism
and Emergent Evolution (New York: Van Nostrand, 1929).
14
Introduction
the enormous influence which the doctrine that consciousness does
not exist has had on psychology in this century.
And this is behaviorism. Its roots rummage far back into the
musty history of thought, to the so-called Epicureans of the
eighteenth century and before, to attempts to generalize tropisms
from plants to animals to man, to movements called Objectivism,
or more particularly, Actionism. For it was Knight Dunlap’s attempt to teach the latter to an excellent but aweless animal
psychologist, John B. Watson, that resulted in a new word, Behaviorism.13 At first, it was very similar to the helpless spectator
theory we have already examined. Consciousness just was not
important in animals. But after a World War and a little invigorating opposition, behaviorism charged out into the intellectual
arena with the snorting assertion that consciousness is nothing at
all.
What a startling doctrine! But the really surprising thing is
that, starting off almost as a flying whim, it grew into a movement that occupied center stage in psychology from about 1920
to 1960. The external reasons for the sustained triumph of such
a peculiar position are both fascinating and complex. Psychology
at the time was trying to wriggle out of philosophy into a separate
academic discipline and used behaviorism to do so. The immediate adversary of behaviorism, Titchenerian introspectionism, was
a pale and effete opponent, based as it was on a false analogy
between consciousness and chemistry. The toppled idealism
after World War I created a revolutionary age demanding new
philosophies. The intriguing successes of physics and general
technology presented both a model and a means that seemed
more compatible with behaviorism. The world was weary and
13 For a less ad hominem picture of the beginnings of behaviorism, see John C.
Burnham, “On the origins of behaviorism.” Journal of the History of the Behavioral
Sciences, 1968, 4: 143-151. And for a good discussion, Richard Herrnstein’s “Introduction to John B. Watson’s Comparative Psychology” in Historical Conceptions of
Psychology, M. Henle, J. Jaynes, and J. J. Sullivan, eds. (New York: Springer, 1974),
98 —115.
THE
PROBLEM
15
wary of subjective thought and longed for objective fact. And in
America objective fact was pragmatic fact. Behaviorism provided
this in psychology. It allowed a new generation to sweep aside
with one impatient gesture all the worn-out complexities of the
problem of consciousness and its origin. We would turn over a
new leaf. We would make a fresh start.
And the fresh start was a success in one laboratory after
another. But the single inherent reason for its success was not its
truth, but its program. And what a truly vigorous and exciting
program of research it was! with its gleaming stainless-steel
promise of reducing all conduct to a handful of reflexes and
conditional responses developed from them, of generalizing the
spinal reflex terminology of stimulus and response and reinforcement to the puzzles of headed behavior and so seeming to solve
them, of running rats through miles and miles of mazes into more
fascinating mazes of objective theorems, and its pledge, its solemn pledge to reduce thought to muscle twitches and personality
to the woes of Little Albert. 14 In all this there was a heady
excitement that is difficult to relate at this remove. Complexity
would be made simple, darkness would be made light, and philosophy would be a thing of the past.
From the outside, this revolt against consciousness seemed to
storm the ancient citadels of human thought and set its arrogant
banners up in one university after another. But having once been
a part of its major school, I confess it was not really what it
seemed. Off the printed page, behaviorism was only a refusal to
talk about consciousness. Nobody really believed he was not
conscious. And there was a very real hypocrisy abroad, as those
interested in its problems were forcibly excluded from academic
psychology, as text after text tried to smother the unwanted
problem from student view. In essence, behaviorism was a
method, not the theory that it tried to be. And as a method, it
14 The
unfortunate subject of Watson's experiments on conditioned fear.
16
Introduction
exorcised old ghosts. It gave psychology a thorough house cleaning. And now the closets have been swept out and the cupboards
washed and aired, and we are ready to examine the problem
again.
Consciousness as the Reticular Activating System
But before doing so, one final approach, a wholly different
approach, and one that has occupied me most recently, the
nervous system. How often in our frustrations with trying to
solve the mysteries of mind do we comfort our questions with
anatomy, real or fancied, and think of a thought as a particular
neuron or a mood as a particular neurotransmitter! It is a temptation born of exasperation with the untestableness and vagueness of all the above solutions. Away with these verbal subtleties!
These esoteric poses of philosophy and even the paper theories
of behaviorists are mere subterfuges to avoid the very material
we are talking about! Here we have an animal — make him a
man if you will — here he is on the table of our analysis. If he is
conscious, it has to be here, right here in him, in the brain in
front of us, not in the presumptuous inklings of philosophy back
in the incapable past! And today we at last have the techniques
to explore the nervous system directly, brain to brain. Somewhere here in a mere three-and-a-half pound lump of pinkishgray matter, the answer has to be.
A l l we have to do is to find those parts of the brain that are
responsible for consciousness, then trace out their anatomical
evolution, and we will solve the problem of the origin of consciousness. Moreover, if we study the behavior of present-day
species corresponding to various stages in the development of
these neurological structures, we will be able at last to reveal with
experimental exactness just what consciousness basically is.
Now this sounds like an excellent scientific program. Ever
since Descartes chose the brain’s pineal body as the seat of consciousness and was roundly refuted by the physiologists of his
THE
PROBLEM
17
day, there has been a fervent if often superficial search for where
in the brain consciousness exists.15 And the search is still on.
At the present, a plausible nominee for the neural substrate of
consciousness is one of the most important neurological discoveries of our time. This is that tangle of tiny internuncial
neurons called the reticular formation, which has long lain hidden and unsuspected in the brainstem. It extends from the top of
the spinal cord through the brainstem on up into the thalamus
and hypothalamus, attracting collaterals from sensory and motor
nerves, almost like a system of wire-tabs on the communication
lines that pass near it. But this is not all. It also has direct lines
of command to half a dozen major areas of the cortex and
probably all the nuclei of the brainstem, as well as sending fibers
down the spinal cord where it influences the peripheral sensory
and motor systems. Its function is to sensitize or “awaken”
selected nervous circuits and desensitize others, such that those
who pioneered in this work christened it “the waking brain” 1 6
The reticular formation is also often called by its functional
name, the reticular activating system. It is the place where general anesthesia produces its effect by deactivating its neurons.
Cutting it produces permanent sleep and coma. Stimulating it
through an implanted electrode in most of its regions wakes up a
sleeping animal. Moreover, it is capable of grading the activity of
most other parts of the brain, doing this as a reflection of its own
internal excitability and the titer of its neurochemistry. There
are exceptions, too complicated for discussion here. But they are
not such as to diminish the exciting idea that this disordered
network of short neurons that connect up with the entire brain,
this central transactional core between the strictly sensory and
motor systems of classical neurology, is the long-sought answer to
the whole problem.
15 I have discussed this at greater length in my paper, “The Problem of Animate
Motion in the Seventeenth Century,” Journal of the History of Ideas, 1970, 31: 219234.
16 See H. W. Magoun, The Waking Brain (Springfield, Illinois: Thomas, 1958).
18
Introduction
If we now look at the evolution of the reticular formation,
asking if it could be correlated with the evolution of consciousness, we find no encouragement whatever. It turns out to be one
of the oldest parts of the nervous system. Indeed, a good case
could be made that this is the very oldest part of the nervous
system, around which the more orderly, more specific, and more
highly evolved tracts and nuclei developed. The little that we at
present know about the evolution of the reticular formation does
not seem to indicate that the problem of consciousness and its
origin will be solved by such a study.
Moreover, there is a delusion in such reasoning. It is one that
is all too common and unspoken in our tendency to translate
psychological phenomena into neuro-anatomy and chemistry.
We can only know in the nervous system what we have known
in behavior first. Even if we had a complete wiring diagram of the
nervous system, we still would not be able to answer our basic
question. Though we knew the connections of every tickling
thread of every single axon and dendrite in every species that
ever existed, together with all its neurotransmitters and how they
varied in its billions of synapses of every brain that ever existed,
we could still never — not ever — from a knowledge of the brain
alone know if that brain contained a consciousness like our own.
We first have to start from the top, from some conception of
what consciousness is, from what our own introspection is. We
have to be sure of that, before we can enter the nervous system
and talk about its neurology.
We must therefore try to make a new beginning by stating
what consciousness is. We have already seen that this is no easy
matter, and that the history of the subject is an enormous confusion of metaphor with designation. In any such situation, where
something is so resistant to even the beginnings of clarity, it is
wisdom to begin by determining what that something is not. And
that is the task of the next chapter.
BOOK ONE
The Mind of Man
CHAPTER 1
The Consciousness
of Consciousness
W
HEN ASKED the question, what is consciousness? we become
conscious of consciousness. And most of us take this consciousness of consciousness to be what consciousness is. This is
not true.
In being conscious of consciousness, we feel it is the most selfevident thing imaginable. We feel it is the defining attribute of
all our waking states, our moods and affections, our memories,
our thoughts, attentions, and volitions. We feel comfortably certain that consciousness is the basis of concepts, of learning and
reasoning, of thought and judgment, and that it is so because it
records and stores our experiences as they happen, allowing us to
introspect on them and learn from them at will. We are also
quite conscious that all this wonderful set of operations and
contents that we call consciousness is located somewhere in the
head.
On critical examination, all of these statements are false.
They are the costume that consciousness has been masquerading
in for centuries. They are the misconceptions that have prevented a solution to the problem of the origin of consciousness.
To demonstrate these errors and show what consciousness is not,
is the long but I hope adventurous task of this chapter.
The Extensiveness of Consciousness
To begin with, there are several uses of the word consciousness
which we may immediately discard as incorrect. We have for
22
The Mind of Man
example the phrase "to lose consciousness” after receiving a blow
on the head. But if this were correct, we would then have no
word for those somnambulistic states known in the clinical literature where an individual is clearly not conscious and yet is responsive to things in a way in which a knocked-out person is not.
Therefore, in the first instance we should say that the person
suffering a severe blow on the head loses both consciousness and
what I am calling reactivity, and they are therefore different
things.
This distinction is also important in normal everyday life. We
are constantly reacting to things without being conscious of them
at the time. Sitting against a tree, I am always reacting to the
tree and to the ground and to my own posture, since if I wish to
walk, I will quite unconsciously stand up from the ground to do so.
Immersed in the ideas of this first chapter, I am rarely conscious even of where I am. In writing, I am reacting to a pencil
in my hand since I hold on to it, and am reacting to my writing
pad since I hold it on my knees, and to its lines since I write upon
them, but I am only conscious of what I am trying to say and
whether or not I am being clear to you.
If a bird bursts up from the copse nearby and flies crying to the
horizon, I may turn and watch it and hear it, and then turn back
to this page without being conscious that I have done so.
In other words, reactivity covers all stimuli my behavior takes
account of in any way, while consciousness is something quite
distinct and a far less ubiquitous phenomenon. We are conscious
of what we are reacting to only from time to time. And whereas
reactivity can be defined behaviorally and neurologically, consciousness at the present state of knowledge cannot.
But this distinction is much more far-reaching. We are continually reacting to things in ways that have no phenomenal
component in consciousness whatever. Not at any time. In seeing any object, our eyes and therefore our retinal images are
reacting to the object by shifting twenty times a second, and yet
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
23
we see an unshifting stable object with no consciousness whatever of the succession of different inputs or of putting them
together into the object. An abnormally small retinal image of
something in the proper context is automatically seen as something at a distance; we are not conscious of making the correction. Color and light contrast effects, and other perceptual
constancies all go on every minute of our waking and even
dreaming experience without our being in the least conscious of
them. And these instances are barely touching the multitude of
processes which by the older definitions of consciousness one
might expect to be conscious of, but which we definitely are not.
I am here thinking of Titchener’s designation of consciousness as
“the sum total of mental processes occurring now.” We are now
very far from such a position.
But let us go further. Consciousness is a much smaller part of
our mental life than we are conscious of, because we cannot be
conscious of what we are not conscious of. How simple that is to
say; how difficult to appreciate! It is like asking a flashlight in a
dark room to search around for something that does not have any
light shining upon it. The flashlight, since there is light in whatever direction it turns, would have to conclude that there is light
everywhere. And so consciousness can seem to pervade all mentality when actually it does not.
The timing of consciousness is also an interesting question.
When we are awake, are we conscious all the time? We think
so. In fact, we are sure so! I shut my eyes and even if I try not to
think, consciousness still streams on, a great river of contents in
a succession of different conditions which I have been taught to
call thoughts, images, memories, interior dialogues, regrets,
wishes, resolves, all interweaving with the constantly changing
pageant of exterior sensations of which I am selectively aware.
Always the continuity. Certainly this is the feeling. And whatever we’re doing, we feel that our very self, our deepest of deep
24
The Mind of Man
identity, is indeed this continuing flow that only ceases in sleep
between remembered dreams. This is our experience. And many
thinkers have taken this spirit of continuity to be the place to
start from in philosophy, the very ground of certainty which no
one can doubt. Cogito, ergo sum.
But what could this continuity mean? If we think of a minute
as being sixty thousand milliseconds, are we conscious for every
one of those milliseconds? If you still think so, go on dividing the
time units, remembering that the firing of neurons is of a finite
order — although we have no idea what that has to do with our
sense of the continuity of consciousness. Few persons would
wish to maintain that consciousness somehow floats like a mist
above and about the nervous system completely ununited to any
earthly necessities of neural refractory periods.
It is much more probable that the seeming continuity of consciousness is really an illusion, just as most of the other metaphors about consciousness are. In our flashlight analogy, the
flashlight would be conscious of being on only when it is on.
Though huge gaps of time occurred, providing things were generally the same, it would seem to the flashlight itself that the
light had been continuously on. We are thus conscious less of the
time than we think, because we cannot be conscious of when we
are not conscious. And the feeling of a great uninterrupted
stream of rich inner experiences, now slowly gliding through
dreamy moods, now tumbling in excited torrents down gorges of
precipitous insight, or surging evenly through our nobler days, is
what it is on this page, a metaphor for how subjective consciousness seems to subjective consciousness.
But there is a better way to point this out. If you close your left
eye and stare at the left margin of this page, you are not at all
conscious of a large gap in your vision about four inches to the
right. But, still staring with your right eye only, take your finger
and move it along a line of print from the left margin to the right,
and you will see the top of it disappear into this gap and then
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
25
reappear on the other side. This is due to a two-millimeter gap on
the nasal side of the retina where the optic nerve fibers are
gathered together and leave the eye for the brain.1 The interesting thing about this gap is that it is not so much a blind spot as it
is usually called; it is a non-spot. A blind man sees his darkness.2
But you cannot see any gap in your vision at all, let alone be
conscious of it in any way. Just as the space around the blind
spots is joined without any gap at all, so consciousness knits
itself over its time gaps and gives the illusion of continuity.
Examples of how little we are conscious of our everyday behavior can be multiplied almost anywhere we look. Playing the
piano is a really extraordinary example.3 Here a complex array
of various tasks is accomplished all at once with scarcely any
consciousness of them whatever: two different lines of near
hieroglyphics to be read at once, the right hand guided to one and
the left to the other; ten fingers assigned to various tasks, the
fingering solving various motor problems without any awareness,
and the mind interpreting sharps and flats and naturals into
black and white keys, obeying the timing of whole or quarter or
sixteenth notes and rests and trills, one hand perhaps in three
beats to a measure while the other plays four, while the feet are
softening or slurring or holding various other notes. And all this
1 A better technique of noticing- the blind spot is to take two pieces of paper about
a half-inch square, and while holding- them about a foot and a half in front of you,
fixate on one with one eye, and move the other piece of paper out on the same side
until it disappears.
2 Except when the cause of blindness is in the brain. For example, soldiers wounded
in one or the other occipital areas of the cortex, with large parts of the visual field
destroyed, are not conscious of any alteration in their vision. Looking straight ahead,
they have the illusion of seeing a complete visual world, as you or I do.
3 This example with similar phrasing was used by W. B. Carpenter to illustrate
his "unconscious cerebration," probably the first important statement of the idea in
the nineteenth century. It was first described in the fourth edition of Carpenter's
Human Physiology in 1852, but more extensively in his later works, as in his influential Principles of Mental Physiology (London: Kegan Paul, 1874), Book 2,
Ch. 13.
26
The Mind of Man
time the performer, the conscious performer, is in a seventh
heaven of artistic rapture at the results of all this tremendous
business, or perchance lost in contemplation of the individual
who turns the leaves of the music book, justly persuaded he is
showing her his very soul! Of course consciousness usually has a
role in the learning of such complex activities, but not necessarily
in their performance, and that is the only point I am trying to
make here.
Consciousness is often not only unnecessary; it can be quite
undesirable. Our pianist suddenly conscious of his fingers during
a furious set of arpeggios would have to stop playing. Nijinsky
somewhere says that when he danced, it was as if he were in the
orchestra pit looking back at himself; he was not conscious of
every movement, but of how he was looking to others. A sprinter
may be conscious of where he is relative to the others in the race,
but he is certainly not conscious of putting one leg in front of the
other; such consciousness might indeed cause him to trip. And
anyone who plays tennis at my indifferent level knows the exasperation of having his service suddenly ‘go to pieces’ and of
serving consecutive double faults! The more doubles, the more
conscious one becomes of one’s motions (and of one’s disposition!) and the worse things get.4
Such phenomena of exertion are not to be explained away on
the basis of physical excitement, for the same phenomena in
regard to consciousness occur in less strenuous occupations.
Right at this moment, you are not conscious of how you are
sitting, of where your hands are placed, of how fast you are
reading, though even as I mentioned these items, you were. And
as you read, you are not conscious of the letters or even of the
words or even of the syntax or the sentences and punctuation,
4 The present writer improvises on the piano, and his best playing is when he is
not conscious of the performance side as he invents new themes or developments, but
only when he is somnambulistic about it and is conscious of his playing only as if he
were another person.
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
27
but only of their meaning. As you listen to an address, phonemes
disappear into words and words into sentences and sentences
disappear into what they are trying to say, into meaning. To be
conscious of the elements of speech is to destroy the intention of
the speech.
And also on the production side. Try speaking with a full
consciousness of your articulation as you do it. You will simply
stop speaking.
And so in writing, it is as if the pencil or pen or typewriter
itself spells the words, spaces them, punctuates properly, goes to
the next line, does not begin consecutive sentences in the same
way, determines that we place a question here, an exclamation
there, even as we ourselves are engrossed in what we are trying
to express and the person we are addressing.
For in speaking or writing we are not really conscious of what
we are actually doing at the time. Consciousness functions in the
decision as to what to say, how we are to say it, and when we say
it, but then the orderly and accomplished succession of phonemes
or of written letters is somehow done for us.
Consciousness Not a Copy of Experience
Although the metaphor of the blank mind had been used in the
writings ascribed to Aristotle, it is really only since John Locke
thought of the mind as a tabula rasa in the seventeenth century
that we have emphasized this recording aspect of consciousness,
and thus see it crowded with memories that can be read over
again in introspection. If Locke had lived in our time, he would
have used the metaphor of a camera rather than a slate. But the
idea is the same. And most people would protest emphatically
that the chief function of consciousness is to store up experience,
to copy it as a camera does, so that it can be reflected upon at
some future time.
So it seems. But consider the following problems: Does the
28
The Mind of Man
door of your room open from the right or the left? Which is your
second longest finger? At a stoplight, is it the red or the green
that is on top? How many teeth do you see when brushing your
teeth? What letters are associated with what numbers on a
telephone dial? If you are in a familiar room, without turning
around, write down all the items on the wall just behind you, and
then look.
I think you will be surprised how little you can retrospect in
consciousness on the supposed images you have stored from so
much previous attentive experience. If the familiar door suddenly opened the other way, if another finger suddenly grew
longer, if the red light were differently placed, or you had an
extra tooth, or the telephone were made differently, or a new
window latch had been put on the window behind you, you would
know it immediately, showing that you all along ‘knew’, but not
consciously so. Familiar to psychologists, this is the distinction
between recognition and recall. What you can consciously recall
is a thimbleful to the huge oceans of your actual knowledge.
Experiments of this sort demonstrate that conscious memory is
not a storing up of sensory images, as is sometimes thought.
Only if you have at some time consciously noticed your finger
lengths or your door, have at some time counted your teeth,
though you have observed these things countless times, can you
remember. Unless you have particularly noted what is on the
wall or recently cleaned or painted it, you will be surprised at
what you have left out. And introspect upon the matter. Did you
not in each of these instances ask what must be there? Starting
with ideas and reasoning, rather than with any image? Conscious
retrospection is not the retrieval of images, but the retrieval of
what you have been conscious of before,5 and the reworking of
these elements into rational or plausible patterns.
5 See in this connection the discussion of Robert S. Wood worth in his Psychological Issues (New York: Columbia University Press, 1939), Ch. 7.
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
29
Let us demonstrate this in another way. Think, if you will, of
when you entered the room you are now in and when you picked
up this book. Introspect upon it and then ask the question: are
the images of which you have copies the actual sensory fields as
you came in and sat down and began reading? Don’t you have an
image of yourself coming through one of the doors, perhaps even
a bird’s-eye view of one of the entrances, and then perhaps
vaguely see yourself sitting down and picking up the book?
Things which you have never experienced except in this introspection! And can you retrieve the sound fields around the
event? Or the cutaneous sensations as you sat, took the pressure
off your feet, and opened this book? Of course, if you go on with
your thinking you can also rearrange your imaginal retrospection
such that you do indeed ‘see’ entering the room just as it might
have been; and ‘hear’ the sound of the chair and the book opening, and ‘feel’ the skin sensations. But I suggest that this has a
large element of created imagery — what we shall call narratizing a little later — of what the experience should be like, rather
than what it actually was like.
Or introspect on when you last went swimming: I suspect you
have an image of a seashore, lake, or pool which is largely a
retrospection, but when it comes to yourself swimming, lo! like
Nijinsky in his dance, you are seeing yourself swim, something
that you have never observed at all! There is precious little of the
actual sensations of swimming, the particular waterline across
your face, the feel of the water against your skin, or to what
extent your eyes were underwater as you turned your head to
breathe.6 Similarly, if you think of the last time you slept out of
doors, went skating, or — if all else fails — did something that
you regretted in public, you tend not to see, hear, or feel things as
you actually experienced them, but rather to re-create them in
objective terms, seeing yourself in the setting as if you were
6 An example taken from Donald Hebb’s provocative discussion, “ T h e mind’s eye,”
Psychology Today, 1961, 2.
30
The Mind of Man
somebody else. Looking back into memory, then, is a great deal
invention, seeing yourself as others see you. Memory is the
medium of the must-have-been. Though I have no doubt that in
any of these instances you could by inference invent a subjective
view of the experience, even with the conviction that it was the
actual memory.
Consciousness Not Necessary for Concepts
A further major confusion about consciousness is the belief
that it is specifically and uniquely the place where concepts are
formed. This is a very ancient idea: that we have various concrete conscious experiences and then put the similar ones together into a concept. This idea has even been the paradigm of a
slew of experiments by psychologists who thought they were thus
studying concept formation.
Max Müller, in one of his fascinating discussions in the last
century, brought the problem to a point by asking, whoever saw a
tree? “No one ever saw a tree, but only this or that fir tree, or oak
tree, or apple tree . . . Tree, therefore, is a concept, and as such
can never be seen or perceived by the senses.”7 Particular trees
alone were outside in the environment, and only in consciousness
did the general concept of tree exist.
Now the relation between concepts and consciousness could
have an extensive discussion. But let it suffice here simply to
show that there is no necessary connection between them. When
Müller says no one has ever seen a tree, he is mistaking what he
knows about an object for the object itself. Every weary wayfarer
after miles under the hot sun has seen a tree. So has every cat,
squirrel, and chipmunk when chased by a dog. The bee has a
concept of a flower, the eagle a concept of a sheer-faced rocky
7 Max Müller, The Science of Thought (London: Longmans Green, 1887), 78-79.
Eugenio Rignano in his The Psychology of Reasoning (New York: Harcourt, Brace,
1923), p. 108f., makes a similar criticism to mine.
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
31
ledge, as a nesting thrush has a concept of a crotch of upper
branch awninged with green leaves. Concepts are simply classes
of behaviorally equivalent things. Root concepts are prior to
experience. They are fundamental to the aptic structures that
allow behavior to occur at all.8 Indeed what Müller should have
said was, no one has ever been conscious of a tree. For consciousness, indeed, not only is not the repository of concepts; it
does not usually work with them at all! When we consciously
think of a tree, we are indeed conscious of a particular tree, of
the fir or the oak or the elm that grew beside our house, and let it
stand for the concept, just as we can let a concept word stand for
it as well. In fact, one of the great functions of language is to let
the word stand for a concept, which is exactly what we do in
writing or speaking about conceptual material. And we must do
this because concepts are usually not in consciousness at all.
Consciousness Not Necessary for Learning
A third important misconception of consciousness is that it is
the basis for learning. Particularly for the long and illustrious
series of Associationist psychologists through the eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries, learning was a matter of ideas in consciousness being grouped by similarity, contiguity, or occasionally some
other relationship. Nor did it matter whether we were speaking
of a man or an animal; all learning was “profiting from experience” or ideas coming together in consciousness — as I said in
the Introduction. And so contemporary common knowledge,
without realizing quite why, has culturally inherited the notion
that consciousness is necessary for learning.
The matter is somewhat complex. It is also unfortunately
8 Aptic structures are the neurological basis of aptitudes that are composed of an
innate evolved aptic paradigm plus the results of experience in development. The
term is the heart of an unpublished essay of mine and is meant to replace such problematic words as instincts. They are organizations of the brain, always partially innate, that make the organism apt to behave in a certain way under certain conditions.
32
The Mind of Man
disfigured in psychology by a sometimes forbidding jargon, which
is really an overgeneralization of the spinal-reflex terminology of
the nineteenth century. But, for our purposes, we may consider
the laboratory study of learning to have been of three central
kinds, the learning of signals, skills, and solutions. Let us take
up each in turn, asking the question, is consciousness necessary?
Signal learning (or classical or Pavlovian conditioning) is the
simplest example. If a light signal immediately followed by a
puff of air through a rubber tube is directed at a person’s eye
about ten times, the eyelid, which previously blinked only to the
puff of air, will begin to blink to the light signal alone, and this
becomes more and more frequent as trials proceed.9 Subjects
who have undergone this well-known procedure of signal learning report that it has no conscious component whatever. Indeed,
consciousness, in this example the intrusion of voluntary eye
blinks to try to assist the signal learning, blocks it from occurring.
In more everyday situations, the same simple associative learning can be shown to go on without any consciousness that it has
occurred. If a distinct kind of music is played while you are
eating a particularly delicious lunch, the next time you hear the
music you will like its sounds slightly more and even have a little
more saliva in your mouth. The music has become a signal for
pleasure which mixes with your judgment. And the same is true
for paintings.10 Subjects who have gone through this kind of
test in the laboratory, when asked why they liked the music or
paintings better after lunch, could not say. They were not conscious they had learned anything. But the really interesting thing
here is that if you know about the phenomenon beforehand and
9 G. A. Kimble, “Conditioning as a function of the time between conditioned and
unconditioned stimuli," Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1947, 37: 1-15.
10 These studies are those of Gregory Razran and are discussed on page 232 of his
Mind in Evolution (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1971). They are discussed critically
in relation to the whole problem of unintentional learning by T. A. Ryan, Intentional
Behavior (New York: Ronald Press, 1970), pp. 235-236.
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
33
are conscious of the contingency between food and the music or
painting, the learning does not occur. Again, consciousness actually reduces our learning abilities of this type, let alone not being
necessary for them.
As we saw earlier in the performance of skills, so in the
learning of skills, consciousness is indeed like a helpless spectator,
having little to do. A simple experiment will demonstrate this fact.
Take a coin in each hand and toss them both, crossing them in the
air in such a way that each coin is caught by the opposite hand. This
you can learn in a dozen trials. As you do, ask, are you conscious
of everything you, or Is consciousness necessary at all? I think
you will find that learning is much better described as being
Organic5 rather than conscious. Consciousness takes you into the
task, giving you the goal to be reached. But from then on,
apart perhaps from fleeting neurotic concerns about your abilities
at such tasks, it is as if the learning is done for you. Yet the
nineteenth century, taking consciousness to be the whole architect of behavior, would have tried to explain such a task as
consciously recognizing the good and bad motions, and by free
choice repeating the former and dropping out the latter!
The learning of complex skills is no different in this respect.
Typewriting has been extensively studied, it generally being
agreed in the words of one experimenter “that all adaptations and
short cuts in methods were unconsciously made, that is, fallen
into by the learners quite unintentionally. The learners suddenly
noticed that they were doing certain parts of the work in a new
and better way.” 11
In the coin-tossing experiment, you may have even discovered
that consciousness if present impeded your learning. This is a
very common finding in the learning of skills, just as we saw it
was in their performance. Let the learning go on without your
being too conscious of it, and it is all done more smoothly and
11
W. F. Book, The Psychology of Skill (New York: Gregg, 1925).
34
The Mind of Man
efficiently. Sometimes too much so, for, in complex skills like
typing, one may learn to consistently type ‘hte’ or ‘the’. The
remedy is to reverse the process by consciously practicing the
mistake ‘hte’, whereupon contrary to the usual idea of ‘practice
makes perfect’, the mistake drops away — a phenomenon called
negative practice.
In the common motor skills studied in the laboratory as well,
such as complex pursuit-rotor systems or mirror-tracing, the subjects who are asked to be very conscious of their movements do
worse.12 And athletic trainers whom I have interviewed are
unwittingly following such laboratory-proven principles when
they urge their trainees not to think so much about what they are
doing. The Zen exercise of learning archery is extremely explicit
on this, advising the archer not to think of himself as drawing the
bow and releasing the arrow, but releasing himself from the
consciousness of what he is doing by letting the bow stretch itself
and the arrow release itself from the fingers at the proper time.
Solution learning (or instrumental learning or operant conditioning) is a more complex case. Usually when one is acquiring
some solution to a problem or some path to a goal, consciousness
plays a very considerable role in setting up the problem in a
certain way. But consciousness is not necessary. Instances can
be shown in which a person has no consciousness whatever of
either the goal he is seeking or the solution he is finding to
achieve that goal.
Another simple experiment can demonstrate this. Ask someone to sit opposite you and to say words, as many words as he can
think of, pausing two or three seconds after each of them for you
to write them down. If after every plural noun (or adjective, or
abstract word, or whatever you choose) you say “good” or “right”
as you write it down, or simply ‘‘mmm-hmm” or smile, or repeat
the plural word pleasantly, the frequency of plural nouns (or
12 H. L. Waskom, “An experimental analysis of incentive and forced application
and their effect upon learning,” Journal of Psychology, 1936, 2: 393-408.
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
35
whatever) will increase significantly as he goes on saying words.
The important thing here is that the subject is not aware that
he is learning anything at all. 13 He is not conscious that he is
trying to find a way to make you increase your encouraging
remarks, or even of his solution to that problem. Every day, in all
our conversations, we are constantly training and being trained
by each other in this manner, and yet we are never conscious of it.
Such unconscious learning is not confined to verbal behavior.
Members of a psychology class were asked to compliment any
girl at the college wearing red. Within a week the cafeteria was a
blaze of red (and friendliness), and none of the girls was aware
of being influenced. Another class, a week after being told about
unconscious learning and training, tried it on the professor.
Every time he moved toward the right side of the lecture hall,
they paid rapt attention and roared at his jokes. It is reported
that they were almost able to train him right out the door, he
remaining unaware of anything unusual.14
The critical problem with most of these studies is that if the
subject decided beforehand to look for such contingencies, he
would of course be conscious of what he was learning to do. One
way to get around this is to use a behavioral response which is
imperceptible to the subject. And this has been done, using a
very small muscle in the thumb whose movements are imperceptible to us and can only be detected by an electrical recording
apparatus. The subjects were told that the experiments were
concerned with the effect of intermittent unpleasant noise com13 J. Greenspoon, ‘‘The reinforcing effect of two spoken sounds on the frequency
of two responses," American Journal of Psychology 1955, 68: 409-416. But there
is considerable controversy here, particularly in the order and wording of postexperimental questions. There may even be a kind of tacit contract between subject and
experimenter. See Robert Rosenthal, Experimenter Effects in Behavioral Research
(New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1966). In this controversy, I presently agree
with Postman that the learning occurs before the subject becomes conscious of the
reinforcement contingency, and indeed that consciousness would not occur unless this
had been so. L. Postman and L. Sassenrath, “The automatic action of verbal rewards
and punishment,” Journal of General Psychology, 1961, 65: 109—136.
14 W. Lambert Gardiner, Psychology: A Story of a Search (Belmont, California:
Brooks/Cole, 1970), p. 76.
36
The Mind of Man
bined with music upon muscle tension. Four electrodes were
placed on their bodies, the only real one being the one over the
small thumb muscle, the other three being dummy electrodes.
The apparatus was so arranged that whenever the imperceptible
thumb-muscle twitch was electrically detected, the unpleasant
noise was stopped for 15 seconds if it was already sounding, or
delayed for 15 seconds if was not turned on at the time of the
twitch. In all subjects, the imperceptible thumb twitch that
turned off the distressing noise increased in rate without the
subjects’ being the slightest bit conscious that they were learning
to turn off the unpleasant noise.15
Thus, consciousness is not a necessary part of the learning
process, and this is true whether it be the learning of signals,
skills, or solutions. There is, of course, much more to say on this
fascinating subject, for the whole thrust of contemporary research in behavior modification is along these lines. But, for the
present, we have simply established that the older doctrine that
conscious experience is the substrate of all learning is clearly and
absolutely false. At this point, we can at least conclude that it is
possible — possible I say — to conceive of human beings who are
not conscious and yet can learn and solve problems.
Consciousness Not Necessary for Thinking
As we go from simple to more complicated aspects of mentality, we enter vaguer and vaguer territory, where the terms we use
become more difficult to travel with. Thinking is certainly one of
these. And to say that consciousness is not necessary for thinking makes us immediately bristle with protest. Surely thinking is
the very heart and bone of consciousness! But let us go slowly
15 R. F. Hefferline, B. Keenan, R. A. Harford, “Escape and avoidance conditioning in human subjects without their observation of the response,” Science, 1959, 130:
1338-1339. Another study which shows unconscious solution learning" very clearly
is that of J. D. Keehn: ‘‘Experimental Studies of the Unconscious: operant conditioning of unconscious eye blinking,” Behavior Research and Therapy, 1967, 5: 95-102.
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
37
here. What we would be referring to would be that type of free
associating which might be called thinking-about or thinking-of,
which, indeed, always seems to be fully surrounded and immersed in the image-peopled province of consciousness. But the
matter is really not that clear at all.
Let us begin with the type of thinking that ends in a result to
which may be predicated the terms right or wrong. This is what
is commonly referred to as making judgments, and is very similar
to one extreme of solution learning that we have just discussed.
A simple experiment, so simple as to seem trivial, will bring us
directly to the heart of the matter. Take any two unequal objects,
such as a pen and pencil or two unequally filled glasses of water,
and place them on the desk in front of you. Then, partly closing
your eyes to increase your attention to the task, pick up each one
with the thumb and forefinger and judge which is heavier. Now
introspect on everything you are doing. Y o u will find yourself
conscious of the feel of the objects against the skin of your
fingers, conscious of the slight downward pressure as you feel the
weight of each, conscious of any protuberances on the sides of
the objects, and so forth. And now the actual judging of which is
heavier. Where is that? L o ! the very act of judgment that one
object is heavier than the other is not conscious. It is somehow
just given to you by your nervous system. If we call that process
of judgment thinking, we are finding that such thinking is not
conscious at all. A simple experiment, yes, but extremely important. It demolishes at once the entire tradition that such thought
processes are the structure of the conscious mind.
This type of experiment came to be studied extensively back at
the beginning of this century in what came to be known as the
Würzburg School. It all began with a study by Karl Marbe in
1901, which was very similar to the above, except that small
weights were used. 16 T h e subject was asked to lift two weights
16 K. Marbe, Experimentell-Psychologische Untersuchungen über das Urteil, eine
Einleitung in die Logik (Leipzig: Engelmann, 1901).
38
The Mind of Man
in front of him, and place the one that was heavier in front of the
experimenter, who was facing him. And it came as a startling
discovery both to the experimenter himself and to his highly
trained subjects, all of them introspective psychologists, that the
process of judgment itself was never conscious. Physics and
psychology always show interesting contrasts, and it is one of the
ironies of science that the Marbe experiment, so simple as to
seem silly, was to psychology what the so-difficult-to-set-up Michaelson-Morley experiment was to physics. Just as the latter
proved that the ether, that substance supposed to exist throughout space, did not exist, so the weight-judgment experiment
showed that judging, that supposed hallmark of consciousness,
did not exist in consciousness at all.
But a complaint can be lodged here. Maybe in lifting the
objects the judging was all happening so fast that we forgot it.
After all, in introspecting we always have hundreds of words to
describe what happens in a few seconds. (What an astonishing
fact that is!) And our memory fades as to what just happened
even as we are trying to express it. Perhaps this was what was
occurring in Marbe’s experiment, and that type of thinking called
judging could be found in consciousness, after all, if we could
only remember.
This was the problem as Watt faced it a few years after
Marbe. 17 To solve it, he used a different method, word associations. Nouns printed on cards were shown to the subject, who
was to reply by uttering an associate word as quickly as he could.
It was not free association, but what is technically called partially constrained: in different series the subject was required to
associate to the visual word a superordinate (e.g. oak-tree), coordinate (oak-elm), or subordinate (oak-beam); or a whole (oakforest), a part (oak-acorn), or another part of a common whole
17 H. J. Watt, “Experimentelle Beitrage zur einer Theorie des Denkens,” Archiv
für geshihte der Psychologie, 1905, 4.: 289-436.
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
39
(oak-path). The nature of this task of constrained associations
made it possible to divide the consciousness of it into four periods: the instructions as to which of the constraints it was to be
(e.g., superordinate), the presentation of the stimulus noun
(e.g., oak), the search for an appropriate association, and the
spoken reply (e.g., tree). The introspecting observers were asked
to confine themselves first to one period and then to another, and
thus get a more accurate account of consciousness in each.
It was expected that the precision of this fractionation method
would prove Marbe’s conclusions wrong, and that the consciousness of thinking would be found in Watt's third period, the period
of the search for the word that would suit the particular constrained association. But nothing of the sort happened. It was
the third period that was introspectively blank. What seemed to
be happening was that thinking was automatic and not really
conscious once a stimulus word had been given, and, previous to
that, the particular type of association demanded had been adequately understood by the observer. This was a remarkable result. Another way of saying it is that one does one’s thinking
before one knows what one is to think about. The important part
of the matter is the instruction, which allows the whole business
to go off automatically. This I shall shorten to the term struction,
by which I mean it to have the connotation of both instruction
and construction.18
Thinking, then, is not conscious. Rather, it is an automatic
process following a struction and the materials on which the
struction is to operate.
But we do not have to stay with verbal associations; any type of
problem will do, even those closer to voluntary actions. If I say to
18 The terms set, determining tendency, and struction need to be distinguished. A
set is the more inclusive term, being an engaged aptic structure which in mammals
can be ordered from a general limbic component of readiness to a specific cortical
component of a determining tendency, the final part of which in humans is often a
struction.
40
The Mind of Man
myself, I shall think about an oak in summer, that is a struction,
and what I call thinking about is really a file of associated images
cast up on the shores of my consciousness out of an unknown
sea, just like the constrained associations in Watt's experiment.
If we have the figures 6 and 2, divided by a vertical line,
6|2, the ideas produced by such a stimulus will be eight, four, or
three, according to whether the struction prescribed is addition,
subtraction, or division. The important thing is that the struction
itself, the process of addition, subtraction, or division, disappears
into the nervous system once it is given. But it is obviously there
‘in the mind’ since the same stimulus can result in any of three
different responses. And that is something we are not in the least
aware of, once it is put in motion.
Suppose we have a series of figures such as the following:
What is the next figure in this series? How did you arrive at your
answer? Once I have given you the struction, you automatically
‘see’ that it is to be another triangle. I submit that if you try to
introspect on the process by which you came up with the answer
you are not truly retrieving the processes involved, but inventing
what you think they must have been by giving yourself another
struction to that effect. In the task itself, all you were really
conscious of was the struction, the figures before you on the page,
and then the solution.
Nor is this different from the case of speech which I mentioned
earlier. When we speak, we are not really conscious either of the
search for words, or of putting the words together into phrases,
or of putting the phrases into sentences. We are only conscious
of the ongoing series of structions that we give ourselves, which
then, automatically, without any consciousness whatever, result
in speech. The speech itself we can be conscious of as it is
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
41
produced if we wish, thus giving some feedback to result in
further structions.
So we arrive at the position that the actual process of thinking,
so usually thought to be the very life of consciousness, is not
conscious at all and that only its preparation, its materials, and
its end result are consciously perceived.
Consciousness Not Necessary for Reason
The long tradition of man as the rational animal, the tradition
that enthroned him as Homo sapiens, rests in all its pontifical
generality on the gracile assumption that consciousness is the
seat of reason. Any discussion of such an assumption is embarrassed by the vagueness of the term reason itself. This vagueness
is the legacy we have from an older ‘faculty’ psychology that
spoke of a ‘faculty’ of reason, which was of course situated ‘in’
consciousness. And this forced deposition of reason and consciousness was further confused with ideas of truth, of how we
ought to reason, or logic — all quite different things. And hence
logic was supposed to be the structure of conscious reason confounding generations of poor scholars who knew perfectly well
that syllogisms were not what was on their side of introspection.
Reasoning and logic are to each other as health is to medicine,
or — better — as conduct is to morality. Reasoning refers to a
gamut of natural thought processes in the everyday world. Logic
is how we ought to think if objective truth is our goal — and the
everyday world is very little concerned with objective truth.
Logic is the science of the justification of conclusions we have
reached by natural reasoning. My point here is that, for such
natural reasoning to occur, consciousness is not necessary. The
very reason we need logic at all is because most reasoning is not
conscious at all.
Consider to begin with the many phenomena we have already
established as going on without consciousness which can be
42
The
Mind
of
Man
called elementary kinds of reasoning. Choosing paths, words,
notes, motions, the perceptual corrections in size and color constancies — all are primitive kinds of reasoning that go on without
any prod, nudge, or even glance of consciousness.
Even the more standard types of reasoning can occur without
consciousness. A boy, having observed on one or more past occasions that a particular piece of wood floats on a particular pond,
will conclude directly in a new instance that another piece of
wood will float on another pond. There is no collecting together
of past instances in consciousness, and no necessary conscious
process whatever when the new piece of wood is seen directly as
floating on the new pond. This is sometimes called reasoning
from particulars, and is simply expectation based on generalization. Nothing particularly extraordinary. It is an ability common
to all the higher vertebrates. Such reasoning is the structure of
the nervous system, not the structure of consciousness.
But more complex reasoning without consciousness is continually going on. Our minds work much faster than consciousness can keep up with. We commonly make general assertions
based on our past experiences in an automatic way, and only as
an afterthought are we sometimes able to retrieve any of the past
experiences on which an assertion is based. How often we reach
sound conclusions and are quite unable to justify them! Because
reasoning is not conscious. And consider the kind of reasoning
that we do about others’ feelings and character, or in reasoning
out the motives of others from their actions. These are clearly
the result of automatic inferences by our nervous systems in
which consciousness is not only unnecessary, but, as we have
seen in the performance of motor skills, would probably hinder
the process.19
Surely, we exclaim, this cannot be true of the highest processes
of intellectual thought! Surely there at last we will come to
19 Such instances were early recognized as not conscious and were called “automatic inference” or “common sense.” Discussions can be found in Sully, Mill, and
other nineteenth-century psychologists.
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
43
the very empire of consciousness, where all is spread out in a
golden clarity and all the orderly processes of reason go on in
a full publicity of awareness. But the truth has no such grandeur. The picture of a scientist sitting down with his problems
and using conscious induction and deduction is as mythical as a
unicorn. The greatest insights of mankind have come more mysteriously. Helmholtz had his happy thoughts which “often
enough crept quietly into my thinking without my suspecting their
importance . . . in other cases they arrived suddenly, without any
effort on my part . . . they liked especially to make their appearance while I was taking an easy walk over wooded hills in sunny
weather !" 20
And Gauss, referring to an arithmetical theorem which he had
unsuccessfully tried to prove for years, wrote how “like a sudden
flash of lightning, the riddle happened to be solved. I myself
cannot say what was the conducting thread which connected
what I previously knew with what made my success possible.”21
And the brilliant mathematician Poincare was particularly interested in the manner in which he came upon his own discoveries. In a celebrated lecture at the Société de Psychologie in
Paris, he described how he set out on a geologic excursion: “The
incidents of the journey made me forget my mathematical work.
Having reached Coutances, we entered an omnibus to go some
place or other. At the moment when I put my foot on the step,
the idea came to me, without anything in my former thoughts
seeming to have paved the way for it, the transformation I had
used to define the Fuchsian functions were identical with those of
non-Euclidian geometry!” 22
It does seem that it is in the more abstract sciences, where the
materials of scrutiny are less and less interfered with by everyday
20 As quoted by Robert S. Woodworth, Experimental Psychology (New York:
Holt, 1938), p. 818.
21 As quoted by Jacques Hadamard, The Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1945), p. 15.
22 Henri Poincare, “Mathematical creation,” in his The Foundations of Science,
G. Bruce Halsted, trans. (New York: The Science Press, 1913), p. 387.
44
The Mind of Man
experience, that this business of sudden flooding insights is most
obvious. A close friend of Einstein’s has told me that many of the
physicist’s greatest ideas came to him so suddenly while he was
shaving that he had to move the blade of the straight razor very
carefully each morning, lest he cut himself with surprise. And a
well-known physicist in Britain once told Wolfgang Köhler, “We
often talk about the three B’s, the Bus, the Bath, and the Bed.
That is where the great discoveries are made in our science.”
The essential point here is that there are several stages of
creative thought: first, a stage of preparation in which the problem is consciously worked over then a period of incubation without any conscious concentration upon the problem; and then the
illumination which is later justified by logic. The parallel between these important and complex problems and the simple
problems of judging weights or the circle-triangle series is obvious. The period of preparation is essentially the setting up of a
complex struction together with conscious attention to the materials on which the struction is to work. But then the actual
process of reasoning, the dark leap into huge discovery, just as in
the simple trivial judgment of weights, has no representation in
consciousness. Indeed, it is sometimes almost as if the problem
had to be forgotten to be solved.
The Location of Consciousness
The final fallacy which I wish to discuss is both important and
interesting, and I have left it for the last Because I think it deals
the coup de grace to the everyman theory of consciousness. Where
does consciousness take place?
Everyone, or almost everyone, immediately replies, in my
head. This is because when we introspect, we seem to look
inward on an inner space somewhere behind our eyes. But what
on earth do we mean by ‘look’? We even close our eyes sometimes to introspect even more clearly. Upon what? Its spatial
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
45
character seems unquestionable. Moreover we seem to move or
at least ‘look’ in different directions. And if we press ourselves
too strongly to further characterize this space (apart from its
imagined contents), we feel a vague irritation, as if there were
something that did not want to be known, some quality which to
question was somehow ungrateful, like rudeness in a friendly
place.
We not only locate this space of consciousness inside our own
heads. We also assume it is there in others’. In talking with a
friend, maintaining periodic eye-to-eye contact (that remnant of
our primate past when eye-to-eye contact was concerned in establishing tribal hierarchies), we are always assuming a space behind our companion’s eyes into which we are talking, similar to
the space we imagine inside our own heads where we are talking
from.
And this is the very heartbeat of the matter. For we know
perfectly well that there is no such space in anyone’s head at all!
There is nothing inside my head or yours except physiological
tissue of one sort or another. And the fact that it is predominantly neurological tissue is irrelevant.
Now this thought takes a little thinking to get used to. It
means that we are continually inventing these spaces in our own
and other people’s heads, knowing perfectly well that they don't
exist anatomically; and the location of these ‘spaces’ is indeed
quite arbitrary. The Aristotelian writings,23 for example, located
consciousness or the abode of thought in and just above the
heart, believing the brain to be a mere cooling organ since it was
insensitive to touch or injury. And some readers will not have
found this discussion valid since they locate their thinking selves
somewhere in the upper chest. For most of us, however, the
habit of locating consciousness in the head is so ingrained that it
23 It is so obvious that the writings ascribed to Aristotle were not written by the
same hand that I prefer this designation.
46
The Mind of Man
is difficult to think otherwise. But, actually, you could, as you
remain where you are, just as well locate your consciousness
around the corner in the next room against the wall near the
floor, and do your thinking there as well as in your head. Not
really just as well. For there are very good reasons why it is
better to imagine your mind-space inside of you, reasons to do
with volition and internal sensations, with the relationship of
your body and your ‘I’ which will become apparent as we go on.
That there is no phenomenal necessity in locating consciousness in the brain is further reinforced by various abnormal instances in which consciousness seems to be outside the body. A
friend who received a left frontal brain injury in the war regained
consciousness in the corner of the ceiling of a hospital ward
looking down euphorically at himself on the cot swathed in
bandages. Those who have taken lysergic acid diethylamide commonly report similar out-of-the-body or exosomatic experiences,
as they are called. Such occurrences do not demonstrate anything
metaphysical whatever; simply that locating consciousness can be
an arbitrary matter.
Let us not make a mistake. When I am conscious, I am always
and definitely using certain parts of my brain inside my head.
But so am I when riding a bicycle, and the bicycle riding does not
go on inside my head. The cases are different of course, since
bicycle riding has a definite geographical location, while consciousness does not. In reality, consciousness has no location
whatever except as we imagine it has.
Is Consciousness Necessary?
Let us review where we are, for we have just found our way
through an enormous amount of ramous material which may
have seemed more perplexing than clarifying. We have been
brought to the conclusion that consciousness is not what we
generally think it is. It is not to be confused with reactivity. It is
THE
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
47
not involved in hosts of perceptual phenomena. It is not involved
in the performance of skills and often hinders their execution.
It need not be involved in speaking, writing, listening, or reading.
It does not copy down experience, as most people think. Consciousness is not at all involved in signal learning, and need not
be involved in the learning of skills or solutions, which can go on
without any consciousness whatever. It is not necessary for making judgments or in simple thinking. It is not the seat of reason,
and indeed some of the most difficult instances of creative reasoning go on without any attending consciousness. And it has no
location except an imaginary one! The immediate question
therefore is, does consciousness exist at all? But that is the
problem of the next chapter. Here it is only necessary to conclude that consciousness does not make all that much difference
to a lot of our activities. If our reasonings have been correct, it is
perfectly possible that there could have existed a race of men
who spoke, judged, reasoned, solved problems, indeed did most of
the things that we do, but who were not conscious at all. This is
the important and in some ways upsetting notion that we are
forced to conclude at this point. Indeed I have begun in this
fashion, and place great importance on this opening chapter, for
unless you are here convinced that a civilization without consciousness is possible, you will find the discussion that follows
unconvincing and paradoxical.
CHAPTER 2
Consciousness
T
away some of the major misconceptions about consciousness, what then have we left? If consciousness is not all these things, if it is not so extensive as we
think, not a copy of experience, or the necessary locus of learning,
judgment, or even thought, what is it? And as we stare into the
dust and rubble of the last chapter, hoping Pygmalion-like to see
consciousness newly step forth pure and pristine out of the detritus,
let us ramble out and around the subject a little way as the dust
settles, talking of different things.
HUS HAVING CHISELED
Metaphor and Language
Let us speak of metaphor. The most fascinating property of
language is its capacity to make metaphors. But what an understatement! For metaphor is not a mere extra trick of language,
as it is so often slighted in the old schoolbooks on composition; it
is the very constitutive ground of language. I am using metaphor
here in its most general sense: the use of a term for one thing to
describe another because of some kind of similarity between
them or between their relations to other things. There are thus
always two terms in a metaphor, the thing to be described, which
I shall call the metaphrand, and the thing or relation used to
elucidate it, which I shall call the metaphier. A metaphor is
always a known metaphier operating on a less known meta-
CONSCIOUSNESS
49
phrand.1 I have coined these hybrid terms simply to echo multiplication where a multiplier operates on a multiplicand.
It is by metaphor that language grows. The common reply to
the question “what is it?” is, when the reply is difficult or. the
experience unique, “well, it is like —.” In laboratory studies,
both children and adults describing nonsense objects (or metaphrands) to others who cannot see them use extended metaphiers that with repetition become contracted into labels.2 This
is the major way in which the vocabulary of language is formed.
The grand and vigorous function of metaphor is the generation
of new language as it is needed, as human culture becomes more
and more complex.
A random glance at the etymologies of common words in a
dictionary will demonstrate this assertion. Or take the naming of
various fauna and flora in their Latin indicants, or even in their
wonderful common English names, such as stag beetle, lady’sslipper, darning needle, Queen Anne’s lace, or buttercup. The
human body is a particularly generative metaphier, creating previously unspeakable distinctions in a throng of areas. The head
of an army, table, page, bed, ship, household, or nail, or of steam
or water; the face of a clock, cliff, card, or crystal; the eyes of
needles, winds, storms, targets, flowers, or potatoes; the brow of
a hill; the cheeks of a vise; the teeth of cogs or combs; the lips of
pitchers, craters, augers; the tongues of shoes, board joints, or
railway switches; the arm of a chair or the sea; the leg of a table,
compass, sailor’s voyage, or cricket field; and so on and on. Or
1 This distinction is not connotatively the same as I. A. Richards’ ‘tenor’ and
‘vehicle’. See his Philosophy of Rhetoric (New York: Oxford University Press, 1936),
pp. 96, 120-121. Nor as Christine Brooke-Rose’s ‘proper’ and ‘metaphor’ terms, both
of which make the matter too literary. See her A Grammar of Metaphor (London:
Seeker and Warburg, 1958), the first chapter of which is a good historical introduction to the subject.
2 See S. Glucksberg, R. M. Krauss, and R. Weisberg, “Referential communication in nursery school children: Method and some preliminary findings,” Journal of
Experimental Child Psychology, 1966, 3: 333-342.
50
The Mind of Man
the foot of this page. Or the leaf you will soon turn. All of these
concrete metaphors increase enormously our powers of perception of the world about us and our understanding of it, and
literally create new objects. Indeed, language is an organ of perception, not simply a means of communication.
This is language moving out synchronically (or without reference to time) into the space of the world to describe it and
perceive it more and more definitively. But language also moves
in another and more important way, diachronically, or through
time, and behind our experiences on the basis of aptic structures
in our nervous systems to create abstract concepts whose referents are not observables except in a metaphorical sense. And
these too are generated by metaphor. This is indeed the nub
(knob), heart, pith, kernel, core, marrow, etc. of my argument,
which itself is a metaphor and ‘seen’ only with the mind’s ‘eye’.
In the abstractions of human relations, the skin becomes a
particularly important metaphier. We get or stay ‘in touch’ with
others who may be ‘thick-’ or ‘thin-skinned’ or perhaps ‘touchy’
in which case they have to be ‘handled’ carefully lest we ‘rub’
them the wrong way; we may have a ‘feeling’ for another person
with whom we may have a ‘touching’ experience.3
The concepts of science are all of this kind, abstract concepts
generated by concrete metaphors. In physics, we have force,
acceleration (to increase one's steps), inertia (originally an indolent person), impedance, resistance, fields, and now charm. In
physiology, the metaphier of a machine has been at the very
center of discovery. We understand the brain by metaphors to
everything from batteries and telegraphy to computers and holograms. Medical practice is sometimes dictated by metaphor. In
the eighteenth century, the heart in fever was like a boiling pot,
and so bloodletting was prescribed to reduce its fuel. And even
today, a great deal of medicine is based upon the military meta3 See
Ashley Montagu, Touching (New York: Columbia University Press, 1971).
CONSCIOUSNESS
51
phor of defense of the body against attacks of this or that. The
very concept of law in Greek derives from nomos, the word for
the foundations of a building. To be liable, or bound in law, comes
from the Latin ligare, meaning to bind with cord.
In early times, language and its referents climbed up from the
concrete to the abstract on the steps of metaphors, even, we may
say, created the abstract on the bases of metaphors.
It is not always obvious that metaphor has played this allimportant function. But this is because the concrete metaphiers
become hidden in phonemic change, leaving the words to exist on
their own. Even such an unmetaphorical-sounding word as the
verb 'to be' was generated from a metaphor. It comes from the
Sanskrit bhu, “to grow, or make grow,” while the English forms
‘am’ and ‘is’ have evolved from the same root as the Sanskrit
asmiy “to breathe.” It is something of a lovely surprise that the
irregular conjugation of our most nondescript verb is thus a
record of a time when man had no independent word for ‘existence’ and could only say that something ‘grows’ or that it
“breathes.”4 Of course we are not conscious that the concept of
being is thus generated from a metaphor about growing and
breathing. Abstract words are ancient coins whose concrete
images in the busy give-and-take of talk have worn away with
use.
Because in our brief lives we catch so little of the vastnesses of
history, we tend too much to think of language as being solid as a
dictionary, with a granite-like permanence, rather than as the
rampant restless sea of metaphor which it is. Indeed, if we consider the changes in vocabulary that have occurred over the last
few millennia, and project them several millennia hence, an
interesting paradox arises. For if we ever achieve a language
that has the power of expressing everything, then metaphor will
4 A paraphrase of Phillip Wheelwright in his The Burning Fountain (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1954).
52
The Mind of Man
no longer be possible. I would not say, in that case, my love is
like a red, red rose, for love would have exploded into terms for
its thousands of nuances, and applying the correct term would
leave the rose metaphorically dead.
The lexicon of language, then, is a finite set of terms that by
metaphor is able to stretch out over an infinite set of circumstances, even to creating new circumstances thereby.
(Could consciousness be such a new creation?)
Understanding as Metaphor
We are trying to understand consciousness, but what are we
really trying to do when we try to understand anything? Like
children trying to describe nonsense objects, so in trying to
understand a thing we are trying to find a metaphor for that
thing. Not just any metaphor, but one with something more
familiar and easy to our attention. Understanding a thing is to
arrive at a metaphor for that thing by substituting something
more familiar to us. And the feeling of familiarity is the feeling
of understanding.
Generations ago we would understand thunderstorms perhaps
as the roaring and rumbling about in battle of superhuman gods.
We would have reduced the racket that follows the streak of
lightning to familiar battle sounds, for example. Similarly today,
we reduce the storm to various supposed experiences with friction, sparks, vacuums, and the imagination of bulgeous banks of
burly air smashing together to make the noise. None of these
really exist as we picture them. Our images of these events of
physics are as far from the actuality as fighting gods. Yet they
act as the metaphor and they feel familiar and so we say we
understand the thunderstorm.
So, in other areas of science, we say we understand an aspect
of nature when we can say it is similar to some familiar theoretical model. The terms theory and model, incidentally, are some-
CONSCIOUSNESS
53
times used interchangeably. But really they should not be. A
theory is a relationship of the model to the things the model is
supposed to represent. The Bohr model of the atom is that of a
proton surrounded by orbiting electrons. It is something like the
pattern of the solar system, and that is indeed one of its metaphoric sources. Bohr’s theory was that all atoms were similar to
his model. The theory, with the more recent discovery of new
particles and complicated interatomic relationships, has turned
out not to be true. But the model remains. A model is neither
true nor false; only the theory of its similarity to what it represents.
A theory is thus a metaphor between a model and data. And
understanding in science is the feeling of similarity between
complicated data and a familiar model.
If understanding a thing is arriving at a familiarizing metaphor for it, then we can see that there always will be a difficulty
in understanding consciousness. For it should be immediately
apparent that there is not and cannot be anything in our immediate experience that is like immediate experience itself. There is
therefore a sense in which we shall never be able to understand
consciousness in the same way that we can understand things
that we are conscious of.
Most of the errors about consciousness that we have been
studying have been errors of attempted metaphors. We spoke of
the notion of consciousness being a copy of experience coming
out of the explicit metaphor of a schoolboy’s slate. But of course
no one really meant consciousness copies experience; it was as if
it did. And we found on analysis, of course, that it did no such
thing.
And even the idea behind that last phrase, that consciousness
does anything at all, even that is a metaphor. It is saying that
consciousness is a person behaving in physical space who does
things, and this is true only if ‘does’ is a metaphor as well. For to
54
The Mind of Man
do things is some kind of behavior in a physical world by a living
body. And also in what Space' is the metaphorical 'doing' being
done? (Some of the dust is beginning to settle.) This 'space* too
must be a metaphor of real space. All of which is reminiscent of
our discussion of the location of consciousness, also a metaphor.
Consciousness is being thought of as a thing, and so like other
things must have a location, which, as we saw earlier, it does not
actually have in the physical sense.
I realize that my argument here is becoming fairly dense. But
before coming out into the clearing, I wish to describe what I
shall mean by the term analog. An analog is a model, but a
model of a special kind. It is not like a scientific model, whose
source may be anything at all and whose purpose is to act as an
hypothesis of explanation or understanding. Instead, an analog
is at every point generated by the thing it is an analog of. A map
is a good example. It is not a model in the scientific sense, not a
hypothetical model like the Bohr atom to explain something unknown. Instead, it is constructed from something well known, if
not completely known. Each region of a district of land is allotted a corresponding region on the map, though the materials of
land and map are absolutely different and a large proportion of
the features of the land have to be left out. And the relation
between an analog map and its land is a metaphor. If I point to a
location on a map and say, "There is Mont Blanc and from Chamonix we can reach the east face this way," that is really a
shorthand way of saying, " T h e relations between the point labeled
'Mont Blanc' and other points is similar to the actual Mont Blanc
and its neighboring regions."
The Metaphor Language of Mind
I think it is apparent now, at least dimly, what is emerging
from the debris of the previous chapter. I do not now feel myself
proving my thesis to you step by step, so much as arranging in
CONSCIOUSNESS
55
your mind certain notions so that, at the very least, you will not
be immediately estranged from the point I am about to make. My
procedure here in what I realize is a difficult and overtly diffuse
part of this book is to simply state in general terms my conclusion
and then clarify what it implies.
Subjective conscious mind is an analog of what is called the
real world. It is built up with a vocabulary or lexical field whose
terms are all metaphors or analogs of behavior in the physical
world. Its reality is of the same order as mathematics. It allows
us to shortcut behavioral processes and arrive at more adequate
decisions. Like mathematics, it is an operator rather than a thing
or repository. And it is intimately bound up with volition and
decision.
Consider the language we use to describe conscious processes.
The most prominent group of words used to describe mental
events are visual. We ‘see’ solutions to problems, the best of
which may be ‘brilliant’, and the person ‘brighter’ and ’clearheaded’ as opposed to 'dull', 'fuzzy-minded', or 'obscure' solutions. These words are all metaphors and the mind-space to which
they apply is a metaphor of actual space. In it we can 'approach' a
problem, perhaps from some 'viewpoint', and 'grapple' with its
difficulties, or seize together or 'com-prehend' parts of a problem,
and so on, using metaphors of behavior to invent things to do in
this metaphored mind-space.
And the adjectives to describe physical behavior in real space
are analogically taken over to describe mental behavior in mindspace when we speak of our minds as being 'quick,' 'slow', 'agitated' (as when we cogitate or co-agitate), 'nimble-witted',
'strong-' or 'weak-minded.' The mind-space in which these metaphorical activities go on has its own group of adjectives; we can
be 'broad-minded', 'deep', 'open', or 'narrow-minded'; we can be
'occupied'; we can 'get something off our minds', 'put something
out of mind', or we can 'get it', let something 'penetrate', or 'bear',
'have', 'keep', or 'hold' it in mind.
As with a real space, something can be at the 'back' of our
56
The Mind of Man
mind, in its 'inner recesses', or 'beyond' our mind, or 'out' of our
mind. In argument we try to 'get things through' to someone, to
'reach' their 'understanding' or find a 'common ground', or 'point
out', etc., all actions in real space taken over analogically into the
space of the mind.
But what is it we are making a metaphor of? We have seen
that the usual function of metaphor is a wish to designate a
particular aspect of a thing or to describe something for which
words are not available. That thing to be designated, described,
expressed, or lexically widened is what we have called the metaphrand. We operate upon this by some similar, more familiar
thing, called a metaphier. Originally, of course, the purpose was
intensely practical, to designate an arm of the sea as a better
place for shellfish, or to put a head on a nail that it might better
hold a board to a stanchion. The metaphiers here were arm and
head, and the metaphrands a particular part of the sea and
particular end of the nail that already existed. Now when we say
mind-space is a metaphor of real space, it is the real 'external'
world that is the metaphier. But if metaphor generates consciousness rather than simply describes it, what is the metaphrand?
Paraphiers and Paraphrands
If we look more carefully at the nature of metaphor (noticing
all the while the metaphorical nature of almost everything we are
saying), we find (even the verb “find”!) that it is composed of
more than a metaphier and a metaphrand. There are also at the
bottom of most complex metaphors various associations or attributes of the metaphier which I am going to call paraphiers. And
these paraphiers project back into the metaphrand as what I
shall call the paraphrands of the metaphrand. Jargon, yes, but
absolutely necessary if we are to be crystal clear about our referents.
CONSCIOUSNESS
57
Some examples will show that the unraveling of metaphor into
these four parts is really quite simple, as well as clarifying what
otherwise we could not speak about.
Consider the metaphor that the snow blankets the ground.
The metaphrand is something about the completeness and even
thickness with which the ground is covered by snow. The metaphier is a blanket on a bed. But the pleasing nuances of this
metaphor are in the paraphiers of the metaphier, blanket. These
are something about warmth, protection, and slumber until some
period of awakening. These associations of blanket then automatically become the associations or paraphrands of the original
metaphrand, the way the snow covers the ground. And we thus
have created by this metaphor the idea of the earth sleeping and
protected by the snow cover until its awakening in spring. All
this is packed into the simple use of the word ‘blanket’ to pertain
to the way snow covers the ground.
Not all metaphors, of course, have such generative potential.
In that often-cited one that a ship plows the sea, the metaphrand
is the particular action of the bow of the ship through the water,
and the metaphier is plowing action. The correspondence is
exact. And that is the end of it.
But if I say the brook sings through the woods, the similarity of
the metaphrand of the brook's bubbling and gurgling and the
metaphier of (presumably) a child singing is not at all exact. It
is the paraphiers of joy and dancingness becoming the paraphrands of the brook that are of interest.
Or in the many-poemed comparison of love to a rose, it is not
the tenuous correspondence of metaphrand and metaphier but
the paraphrands that engage us, that love lives in the sun, smells
sweet, has thorns when grasped, and blooms for a season only.
Or suppose I say less visually and so more profoundly something
quite opposite, that my love is like a tinsmith's scoop, sunk past
its gleam in the meal-bin.5 The immediate correspondence here
5 From “Mossbawn (for Mary Heaney)” by Seumas Heaney, North (London:
Faber, 1974).
58
The Mind of Man
of metaphrand and metaphier, of being out of casual sight, is
trivial. Instead, it is the paraphrands of this metaphor which
create what could not possibly be there, the enduring careful
shape and hidden shiningness and holdingness of a lasting love
deep in the heavy manipulable softnesses of mounding time, the
whole simulating (and so paraphranding) sexual intercourse
from a male point of view. Love has not such properties except
as we generate them by metaphor.
Of such poetry is consciousness made. This can be seen if we
return to some of the metaphors of mind we have earlier looked
at. Suppose we are trying to solve some simple problem such as
the circle-triangle series in the previous chapter. And suppose we
express the fact that we have obtained the solution by exclaiming
that at last we 'see' what the answer is, namely, a triangle.
This metaphor may be analyzed just as the blanket of snow or
the singing brook. The metaphrand is obtaining the solution, the
metaphier is sight with the eyes, and the paraphiers are all those
things associated with vision that then create paraphrands, such
as the mind's 'eye', 'seeing the solution clearly’ etc., and, most
important, the paraphrand of a 'space' in which the 'seeing' is
going on, or what I am calling mind-space, and 'objects' to 'see.'
I do not mean this brief sketch to stand in for a real theory of
how consciousness was generated in the first place. That problem we shall come to in Book II. Rather I intend only to suggest
the possibility that I hope to make plausible later, that consciousness is the work of lexical metaphor. It is spun out of the
concrete metaphiers of expression and their paraphiers, projecting paraphrands that exist only in the functional sense. Moreover, it goes on generating itself, each new paraphrand capable
of being a metaphrand on its own, resulting in new metaphiers
with their paraphiers, and so on.
Of course this process is not and cannot be as haphazard as I
am making it sound. The world is organized, highly organized,
CONSCIOUSNESS
59
and the concrete metaphiers that are generating consciousness
thus generate consciousness in an organized way. Hence the
similarity of consciousness and the physical-behavioral world we
are conscious of. And hence the structure of that world is echoed
— though with certain differences — in the structure of consciousness.
One last complication before going on. A cardinal property of
an analog is that the way it is generated is not the way it is
used — obviously. The map-maker and map-user are doing two
different things. For the map-maker, the metaphrand is the
blank piece of paper on which he operates with the metaphier of
the land he knows and has surveyed. But for the map-user, it is
just the other way around. The land is unknown; it is the land
that is the metaphrand, while the metaphier is the map which he
is using, by which he understands the land.
And so with consciousness. Consciousness is the metaphrand
when it is being generated by the paraphrands of our verbal
expressions. But the functioning of consciousness is, as it were,
the return journey. Consciousness becomes the metaphier full of
our past experience, constantly and selectively operating on such
unknowns as future actions, decisions, and partly remembered
pasts, on what we are and yet may be. And it is by the generated
structure of consciousness that we then understand the world.
What kinds of things can we say about that structure? Here I
shall briefly allude to only the most important.
The Features of Consciousness
I. Spatialization. The first and most primitive aspect of consciousness is what we already have had occasion to refer to, the
paraphrand of almost every mental metaphor we can make, the
mental space which we take over as the very habitat of it all. If I
ask you to think of your head, then your feet, then the breakfast
60
The Mind of Man
you had this morning, and then the Tower of London, and then
the constellation of Orion, these things have the quality of being
spatially separated; and it is this quality I am here referring to.
When we introspect (a metaphor of seeing into something), it is
upon this metaphorical mind-space which we are constantly renewing and 'enlarging' with each new thing or relation consciousized.
In Chapter 1, we spoke of how we invent mind-space inside our
own heads as well as the heads of others. The word invent is
perhaps too strong except in the ontological sense. We rather
assume these 'spaces' without question. They are a part of what
it is to be conscious and what it is to assume consciousness in
others.
Moreover, things that in the physical-behavioral world do not
have a spatial quality are made to have such in consciousness.
Otherwise we cannot be conscious of them. This we shall call
spatialization.
Time is an obvious example. If I ask you to think of the last
hundred years, you may have a tendency to excerpt the matter in
such a way that the succession of years is spread out, probably
from left to right. But of course there is no left or right in time.
There is only before and after, and these do not have any spatial
properties whatever — except by analog. You cannot, absolutely
cannot think of time except by spatializing it. Consciousness is
always a spatialization in which the diachronic is turned into the
synchronic, in which what has happened in time is excerpted and
seen in side-by-sideness.
This spatialization is characteristic of all conscious thought. If
you are now thinking of where in all the theories of mind my
particular theory fits, you are first habitually 'turning' to your
mind-space where abstract things can be 'separated out' and
'put beside' each other to be 'looked at' — as could never happen
physically or in actuality. You then make the metaphor of theories as concrete objects, then the metaphor of a temporal sue-
CONSCIOUSNESS
61
cession of such objects as a synchronic array, and thirdly, the
metaphor of the characteristics of theories as physical characteristics, all of some degree so they can be 'arranged' in a kind of
order. And you then make the further expressive metaphor of
'fit'. The actual behavior of fitting, of which 'fit' here is the analog
in consciousness, may vary from person to person or from culture
to culture, depending on personal experience of arranging things
in some kind of order, or of fitting objects into their receptacles,
etc. The metaphorical substrate of thought is thus sometimes
very complicated, and difficult to unravel. But every conscious
thought that you are having in reading this book can by such an
analysis be traced back to concrete actions in a concrete world.
2. Excerption. In consciousness, we are never 'seeing' anything in its entirety. This is because such 'seeing' is an analog of
actual behavior j and in actual behavior we can only see or pay
attention to a part of a thing at any one moment. And so in
consciousness. We excerpt from the collection of possible attentions to a thing which comprises our knowledge of it. And this is
all that it is possible to do since consciousness is a metaphor of
our actual behavior.
Thus, if I ask you to think of a circus, for example, you will
first have a fleeting moment of slight fuzziness, followed perhaps
by a picturing of trapeze artists or possibly a clown in the center
ring. Or, if you think of the city which you are now in, you will
excerpt some feature, such as a particular building or tower or
crossroads. Or if I ask you to think of yourself, you will make
some kind of excerpts from your recent past, believing you are
then thinking of yourself. In all these instances, we find no
difficulty or particular paradox in the fact that these excerpts are
not the things themselves, although we talk as if they were.
Actually we are never conscious of things in their true nature,
only of the excerpts we make of them.
The variables controlling excerption are deserving of much
62
The Mind of Man
more thought and study. For on them the person's whole consciousness of the world and the persons with whom he is interacting depend. Your excerptions of someone you know well are
heavily associated with your affect toward him. If you like him,
the excerpts will be the pleasant things; if not, the unpleasant.
The causation may be in either direction.
How we excerpt other people largely determines the kind of
world we feel we are living in. Take for example one's relatives
when one was a child. If we excerpt them as their failures, their
hidden conflicts, their delusions, well, that is one thing. But if we
excerpt them at their happiest, in their idiosyncratic delights, it is
quite another world. Writers and artists are doing in a controlled
way what happens 'in' consciousness more haphazardly.
Excerption is distinct from memory. An excerpt of a thing is
in consciousness the representative of the thing or event to which
memories adhere, and by which we can retrieve memories. If I
wish to remember what I was doing last summer, I first have an
excerption of the time concerned, which may be a fleeting image
of a couple of months on the calendar, until I rest in an excerption of a particular event, such as walking along a particular
riverside. And from there I associate around it and retrieve memories about last summer. This is what we mean by reminiscence,
and it is a particular conscious process which no animal is capable of. Reminiscence is a succession of excerptions. Each socalled association in consciousness is an excerption, an aspect or
image, if you will, something frozen in time, excerpted from the
experience on the basis of personality and changing situational
factors.6
3. The Analog 'I'. A most important 'feature' of this metaphor 'world' is the metaphor we have of ourselves, the analog 'I',
which can 'move about' vicarially in our 'imagination', 'doing'
6 Individual differences and changes in the excerptions with age or health are an
exceedingly interesting study. For example, if we are depressed or suffering, the excerptions of the world in consciousness change dramatically.
CONSCIOUSNESS
63
things that we are not actually doing. There are of course many
uses for such an analog 'I'. We imagine 'ourselves' 'doing' this or
that, and thus 'make' decisions on the basis of imagined 'outcomes' that would be impossible if we did not have an imagined
'self' behaving in an imagined 'world'. In the example in the
section on spatialization, it was not your physical behavioral self
that was trying to 'see' where my theory 'fits' into the array of
alternative theories. It was your analog 'I'.
If we are out walking, and two roads diverge in a wood, and we
know that one of them comes back to our destination after a
much more circuitous route, we can 'traverse' that longer route
with our analog 'I' to see if its vistas and ponds are worth the
longer time it will take. Without consciousness with its vicarial
analog 'I', we could not do this.
4. The Metaphor 'Me'. The analog 'I' is, however, not simply
that. It is also a metaphor 'me'. As we imagine ourselves strolling
down the longer path we indeed catch 'glimpses' of 'ourselves', as
we did in the exercises of Chapter 1, where we called them autoscopic images. We can both look out from within the imagined self
at the imagined vistas, or we can step back a bit and see ourselves
perhaps kneeling down for a drink of water at a particular brook.
There are of course quite profound problems here, particularly in
the relationship of the 'I' to the 'me'. But that is another treatise.
And I am only indicating the nature of the problem.
5. Narratization. In consciousness, we are always seeing our
vicarial selves as the main figures in the stories of our lives. In
the above illustration, the narratization is obvious, namely, walking along a wooded path. But it is not so obvious that we are
constantly doing this whenever we are being conscious, and this I
call narratization. Seated where I am, I am writing a book and
this fact is imbedded more or less in the center of the story of my
life, time being spatialized into a journey of my days and years.
64
The Mind of Man
New situations are selectively perceived as part of this ongoing
story, perceptions that do not fit into it being unnoticed or at least
unremembered. More important, situations are chosen which are
congruent to this ongoing story, until the picture I have of myself
in my life story determines how I am to act and choose in novel
situations as they arise.
The assigning of causes to our behavior or saying why we did a
particular thing is all a part of narratization. Such causes as
reasons may be true or false, neutral or ideal. Consciousness is
ever ready to explain anything we happen to find ourselves doing.
The thief narratizes his act as due to poverty, the poet his as due
to beauty, and the scientist his as due to truth, purpose and cause
inextricably woven into the spatialization of behavior in consciousness.
But it is not just our own analog 'I' that we are narratizing; it is
everything else in consciousness. A stray fact is narratized to fit
with some other stray fact. A child cries in the street and we
narratize the event into a mental picture of a lost child and a
parent searching for it. A cat is up in a tree and we narratize the
event into a picture of a dog chasing it there. Or the facts of
mind as we can understand them into a theory of consciousness.
6. Conciliation. A final aspect of consciousness I wish to mention here is modeled upon a behavioral process common to most
mammals. It really springs from simple recognition, where a
slightly ambiguous perceived object is made to conform to some
previously learned schema, an automatic process sometimes called
assimilation. We assimilate a new stimulus into our conception, or
schema about it, even though it is slightly different. Since we
never from moment to moment see or hear or touch things in
exactly the same way, this process of assimilation into previous
experience is going on all the time as we perceive our world. We
are putting things together into recognizable objects on the basis
of the previously learned schemes we have of them.
CONSCIOUSNESS
65
Now assimilation consciousized is conciliation. A better term
for it might be compatibilization, but that seems something too
rococo. What I am designating by conciliation is essentially doing
in mind-space what narratization does in mind-time or spatialized
time. It brings things together as conscious objects just as narratization brings things together as a story. And this fitting together
into a consistency or probability is done according to rules built up
in experience.
In conciliation we are making excerpts or narratizations compatible with each other, just as in external perception the new
stimulus and the internal conception are made to agree. If we are
narratizing ourselves as walking along a wooded path, the succession of excerpts is automatically made compatible with such a
journey. Or if in daydreaming two excerpts or narratizations happen to begin occurring at the same time, they are fused or conciliated.
If I ask you to think of a mountain meadow and a tower at the
same time, you automatically conciliate them by having the tower
rising from the meadow. But if I ask you to think of the mountain
meadow and an ocean at the same time, conciliation tends not
to occur and you are likely to think of one and then the other.
You can only bring them together by a narratization. Thus there
are principles of compatibility that govern this process, and such
principles are learned and are based on the structure of the
world.
Let me summarize as a way of 'seeing' where we are and the
direction in which our discussion is going. We have said that
consciousness is an operation rather than a thing, a repository, or
a function. It operates by way of analogy, by way of constructing
an analog space with an analog 'I' that can observe that space,
and move metaphorically in it. It operates on any reactivity,
excerpts relevant aspects, narratizes and conciliates them together in a metaphorical space where such meanings can be
66
The Mind of Man
manipulated like things in space. Conscious mind is a spatial
analog of the world and mental acts are analogs of bodily acts.
Consciousness operates only on objectively observable things.
Or, to say it another way with echoes of John Locke, there is
nothing in consciousness that is not an analog of something that
was in behavior first.
This has been a difficult chapter. But I hope I have sketched
out with some plausibility that the notion of consciousness as a
metaphor-generated model of the world leads to some quite
definite deductions, and that these deductions are testable in our
own everyday conscious experience. It is only, of course, a beginning, a somewhat rough-hewn beginning, which I hope to develop
in a future work. But it is enough to return now to our major
inquiry of the origin of it all, saving further amplification of the
nature of consciousness itself for later chapters.
If consciousness is this invention of an analog world on the
basis of language, paralleling the behavioral world even as the
world of mathematics parallels the world of quantities of things,
what then can we say about its origin?
We have arrived at a very interesting point in our discussion,
and one that is completely contradictory to all of the alternative
solutions to the problem of the origin of consciousness which we
discussed in the introductory chapter. For if consciousness is
based on language, then it follows that it is of a much more
recent origin than has heretofore been supposed. Consciousness
come after language! The implications of such a position are
extremely serious.
CHAPTER 3
The Mind of Iliad
T
H E R E IS an awkward moment at the top of a Ferris wheel
when, having come up the inside curvature, where we are
facing into a firm structure of confident girders, suddenly that
structure disappears, and we are thrust out into the sky for the
outward curve down.
Such perhaps is the present moment. For all the scientific
alternatives that we faced into in the Introduction, including my
own prejudgments about the matter, all assured us that consciousness was evolved by natural selection back somewhere in
mammalian evolution or before. We felt assured that at least
some animals were conscious, assured that consciousness was
related in some important way to the evolution of the brain and
probably its cortex, assured certainly that early man was conscious as he was learning language.
These assurances have now disappeared, and we seem thrust
out into the sky of a very new problem. If our impressionistic
development of a theory of consciousness in the last chapter is
even pointing in the right direction, then consciousness can only
have arisen in the human species, and that development must
have come after the development of language.
Now if human evolution were a simple continuity, our procedure at this point would normally be to study the evolution of language, dating it as best we could. We would then try to trace out
human mentality thereafter until we reached the goal of our
68
The Mind of Man
inquiry, where we could claim by some criterion or other that
here at last is the place and the date of the origin and beginning
of consciousness.
But human evolution is not a simple continuity. Into human
history around 3000 B.C. comes a curious and very remarkable
practice. It is a transmutation of speech into little marks on
stone or clay or papyrus (or pages) so that speech can be seen
rather than just heard, and seen by anybody, not just those
within earshot at the time. So before pursuing the program of
the preceding paragraph, we should first try to date the origin of
consciousness either before or after the invention of such seen
speech by examining its earliest examples. Our present question
then is: what is the mentality of the earliest writings of mankind?
As soon as we go back to the first written records of man to
seek evidence for the presence or absence of a subjective conscious mind, we are immediately beset with innumerable technical problems. The most profound is that of translating writings
that may have issued from a mentality utterly different from our
own. And this is particularly problematic in the very first human
writings. These are in hieroglyphics, hieratic, and cuneiform,
all — interestingly enough — beginning about 3000 B.C. None
of these is entirely understood. When the subjects are concrete,
there is little difficulty. But when the symbols are peculiar and
undetermined by context, the amount of necessary guesswork
turns this fascinating evidence of the past into a Rorschach test
in which modern scholars project their own subjectivity with
little awareness of the importance of their distortion. The indications here as to whether consciousness was present in the early
Egyptian dynasties and in the Mesopotamian cultures are thus
too ambiguous for the kind of concerned analysis which is required. We shall return to these questions in Book II.
The first writing in human history in a language of which we
have enough certainty of translation to consider it in connection
THE
MIND
OF
ILIAD
69
with my hypothesis is the Iliad. Modern scholarship regards this
revenge story of blood, sweat, and tears to have been developed
by a tradition of bards or aoidoi between about 1230 B.C. when,
according to inferences from some recently found Hittite
tablets,1 the events of the epic occurred and about 900 or 850
B.C., when it came to be written down. I propose here to regard
the poem as a psychological document of immense importance.
And the question we are to put to it is: What is mind in the
Iliad?
The Language of the Iliad
The answer is disturbingly interesting. There is in general no
consciousness in the Iliad. I am saying 'in general' because I shall
mention some exceptions later. And in general therefore, no words
for consciousness or mental acts. The words in the Iliad that in a
later age come to mean mental things have different meanings, all
of them more concrete. The word psyche, which later means soul
or conscious mind, is in most instances life-substances, such as
blood or breath: a dying warrior bleeds out his psyche onto the
ground or breathes it out in his last gasp. The thumos, which
later comes to mean something like emotional soul, is simply
motion or agitation. When a man stops moving, the thumos
leaves his limbs. But it is also somehow like an organ itself, for
when Glaucus prays to Apollo to alleviate his pain and to give
him strength to help his friend Sarpedon, Apollo hears his prayer
and "casts strength in his thumos" (Iliad, 16:529). The thumos
can tell a man to eat, drink, or fight. Diomedes says in one place
that Achilles will fight "when the thumos in his chest tells him to
and a god rouses him" (9:702f.). But it is not really an organ and
not always localized; a raging ocean has thumos. A word of somewhat similar use is phren, which is always localized anatomi1 V. R. d'A. Desborough, The Last Mycenaeans and Their Successors: An Archeological Survey, c. 1200-c. 1000 B.C. (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1964).
70
The Mind of Man
cally as the midriff, or sensations in the midriff, and is usually
used in the plural. It is the phrenes of Hector that recognize
that his brother is not near him (22:296); this means what we
mean by "catching one's breath in surprise". It is only centuries
later that it comes to mean mind or 'heart' in its figurative sense.
Perhaps most important is the word noos which, spelled as
nous in later Greek, comes to mean conscious mind. It comes
from the word noeein, to see. Its proper translation in the Iliad
would be something like perception or recognition or field of
vision. Zeus "holds Odysseus in his noos." He keeps watch over
him.
Another important word, which perhaps comes from the
doubling of the word meros (part), is mermera, meaning in two
parts. This was made into a verb by adding the ending -izo, the
common suffix which can turn a noun into a verb, the resulting
word being mermerizein, to be put into two parts about something.
Modern translators, for the sake of a supposed literary quality in
their work, often use modern terms and subjective categories
which are not true to the original. Mermerizein is thus wrongly
translated as to ponder, to think, to be of divided mind, to be
troubled about, to try to decide. But essentially it means to be in
conflict about two actions, not two thoughts. It is always behavioristic. It is said several times of Zeus (20:17, 16:647), as well
as of others. The conflict is often said to go on in the thumosy or
sometimes in the phrenes, but never in the noos. The eye cannot
doubt or be in conflict, as the soon-to-be-invented conscious mind
will be able to.
These words are in general, and with certain exceptions, the
closest that anyone, authors or characters or gods, usually get to
having conscious minds or thoughts. We shall be entering the
meaning of these words more carefully in a later chapter.
There is also no concept of will or word for it, the concept
developing curiously late in Greek thought. Thus, Iliadic men
have no will of their own and certainly no notion of free will.
THE
MIND
OF
ILIAD
71
Indeed, the whole problem of volition, so troubling, I think, to
modern psychological theory, may have had its difficulties because the words for such phenomena were invented so late.
A similar absence from Iliadic language is a word for body in
our sense. The word soma, which in the fifth century B.C. comes
to mean body, is always in the plural in Homer and means dead
limbs or a corpse. It is the opposite of psyche. There are several
words which are used for various parts of the body, and, in
Homer, it is always these parts that are referred to, and never the
body as a whole. 2 So, not surprisingly, the early Greek art of
Mycenae and its period shows man as an assembly of strangely
articulated limbs, the joints underdrawn, and the torso almost
separated from the hips. It is graphically what we find again and
again in Homer, who speaks of hands, lower arms, upper arms,
feet, calves, and thighs as being fleet, sinewy, in speedy motion,
etc., with no mention of the body as a whole.
Now this is all very peculiar. If there is no subjective consciousness, no mind, soul, or will, in Iliadic men, what then
initiates behavior?
The Religion of the Early Greeks
There is an old and general idea that there was no true religion
in Greece before the fourth century B.C.3 and that the gods in the
Homeric poems are merely a "gay invention of poets," as it has
been put by noted scholars.4 The reason for this erroneous view
is that religion is being thought of as a system of ethics, as a kind
2 Bruno Snell, The Discovery of Mind, T. G. Rosenmeyer, trans. (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1953). I was well along into the ideas and material of
this chapter before knowing of Snell's parallel work on Homeric language. Our
conclusions, however, are quite different.
3 Except E. R. Dodds in his superb book The Greeks and the Irrational (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1951).
4 For example, Maurice Bowra, Tradition and Design in the Iliad (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930), p. 222.
72
The Mind of Man
of bowing down to external gods in an effort to behave virtuously.
And indeed in this sense the scholars are right. But to say that
the gods in the Iliad are merely the inventions of the authors of
the epic is to completely misread what is going on.
The characters of the Iliad do not sit down and think out what
to do. They have no conscious minds such as we say we have,
and certainly no introspections. It is impossible for us with our
subjectivity to appreciate what it was like. When Agamemnon,
king of men, robs Achilles of his mistress, it is a god that grasps
Achilles by his yellow hair and warns him not to strike Agamemnon (I :197ff.). It is a god who then rises out of the gray sea and
consoles him in his tears of wrath on the beach by his black
ships, a god who whispers low to Helen to sweep her heart with
homesick longing, a god who hides Paris in a mist in front of the
attacking Menelaus, a god who tells Glaucus to take bronze for
gold (6:234ff.), a god who leads the armies into battle, who speaks
to each soldier at the turning points, who debates and teaches
Hector what he must do, who urges the soldiers on or defeats
them by casting them in spells or drawing mists over their visual
fields. It is the gods who start quarrels among men (4:437ff.)
that really cause the war (3:164ff.), and then plan its strategy
(2:56ff.). It is one god who makes Achilles promise not to go into
battle, another who urges him to go, and another who then clothes
him in a golden fire reaching up to heaven and screams through
his throat across the bloodied trench at the Trojans, rousing in
them ungovernable panic. In fact, the gods take the place of
consciousness.
The beginnings of action are not in conscious plans, reasons,
and motives; they are in the actions and speeches of gods. To
another, a man seems to be the cause of his own behavior. But
not to the man himself. When, toward the end of the war,
Achilles reminds Agamemnon of how he robbed him of his mistress, the king of men declares, "Not I was the cause of this act,
but Zeus, and my portion, and the Erinyes who walk in darkness:
THE
MIND
OF
ILIAD
73
they it was in the assembly put wild ate upon me on that day
when I arbitrarily took Achilles' prize from him, so what could I
do? Gods always have their way." (19:86-90). And that this
was no particular fiction of Agamemnon's to evade responsibility
is clear in that this explanation is fully accepted by Achilles, for
Achilles also is obedient to his gods. Scholars who in commenting on this passage say that Agamemnon's behavior has become
"alien to his ego," 5 do not go nearly far enough. For the question
is indeed, what is the psychology of the Iliadic hero? And I
am saying that he did not have any ego whatever.
Even the poem itself is not wrought by men in our sense. Its
first three words are Menin aedie Thea, Of wrath sing, O Goddess! And the entire epic which follows is the song of the goddess
which the entranced bard 'heard' and chanted to his iron-age listeners among the ruins of Agamemnon's world.
If we erase all our preconceptions about poetry and act toward
the poem as if we had never heard of poetry before, the abnormal
quality of the speech would immediately arrest us. We call it
meter nowadays. But what a different thing, these steady hexameters of pitch stresses, from the looser jumble of accents in
ordinary dialogue! The function of meter in poetry is to drive the
electrical activity of the brain, and most certainly to relax the
normal emotional inhibitions of both chanter and listener. A
similar thing occurs when the voices of schizophrenics speak in
scanning rhythms or rhyme. Except for its later accretions, then,
the epic itself was neither consciously composed nor consciously
remembered, but was successively and creatively changed with
no more awareness than a pianist has of his improvisation.
Who then were these gods that pushed men about like robots
and sang epics through their lips? They were voices whose
speech and directions could be as distinctly heard by the Iliadic
heroes as voices are heard by certain epileptic and schizophrenic
5 Among- others, Martin P. Nilsson, A History of Greek Religion (New York:
Norton, 1964).
74
The Mind of Man
patients, or just as Joan of Arc heard her voices. The gods were
organizations of the central nervous system and can be regarded
as personae in the sense of poignant consistencies through time,
amalgams of parental or admonitory images. The god is a part of
the man, and quite consistent with this conception is the fact that
the gods never step outside of natural laws. Greek gods cannot
create anything out of nothing, unlike the Hebrew god of Genesis.
In the relationship between the god and the hero in their dialectic, there are the same courtesies, emotions, persuasions as might
occur between two people. The Greek god never steps forth in
thunder, never begets awe or fear in the hero, and is as far from
the outrageously pompous god of Job as it is possible to be. He
simply leads, advises, and orders. Nor does the god occasion
humility or even love, and little gratitude. Indeed, I suggest
that the god-hero relationship was — by being its progenitor
— similar to the referent of the ego-superego relationship of
Freud or the self-generalized other relationship of Mead. The
strongest emotion which the hero feels toward a god is amazement or wonder, the kind of emotion that we feel when the
solution of a particularly difficult problem suddenly pops into our
heads, or in the cry of eureka! from Archimedes in his bath.
The gods are what we now call hallucinations. Usually they
are only seen and heard by the particular heroes they are speaking to. Sometimes they come in mists or out of the gray sea or a
river, or from the sky, suggesting visual auras preceding them.
But at other times, they simply occur. Usually they come as
themselves, commonly as mere voices, but sometimes as other
people closely related to the hero.
Apollo's relation to Hector is particularly interesting in this
regard. In Book 16, Apollo comes to Hector as his maternal
uncle; then in Book 17 as one of his allied leaders; and then later
in the same book as his dearest friend from abroad. The denouement of the whole epic comes when it is Athene who, after telling
Achilles to kill Hector, then comes to Hector as his dearest
THE
MIND
OF
ILIAD
75
brother, Deiphobus. Trusting in him as his second, Hector challenges Achilles, demands of Deiphobus another spear, and turns
to find nothing is there. We would say he has had an hallucination. So has Achilles. The Trojan War was directed by hallucinations. And the soldiers who were so directed were not at all
like us. They were noble automatons who knew not what they
did.
The Bicameral Mind
The picture then is one of strangeness and heartlessness and
emptiness. We cannot approach these heroes by inventing mindspaces behind their fierce eyes as we do with each other. Iliadic
man did not have subjectivity as do we; he had no awareness of
his awareness of the world, no internal mind-space to introspect
upon. In distinction to our own subjective conscious minds, we
can call the mentality of the Myceneans a bicameral mind. Volition, planning, initiative is organized with no consciousness
whatever and then 'told' to the individual in his familiar language, sometimes with the visual aura of a familiar friend or
authority figure or 'god', or sometimes as a voice alone. The
individual obeyed these hallucinated voices because he could not
'see' what to do by himself.
The evidence for the existence of such a mentality as I have
just proposed is not meant to rest solely on the Iliad. It is rather
that the Iliad suggests the hypothesis that in later chapters I shall
attempt to prove or refute by examining the remains of other
civilizations of antiquity. Nevertheless, it would be persuasive at
this time to bring up certain objections to the preceding which
will help clarify some of the issues before going on.
Objection: Is it not true that some scholars have considered the
poem to be entirely the invention of one man, Homer, with no
historical basis whatever, even doubting whether Troy evei: ex-
76
The Mind of Man
isted at all, in spite of Schliemann's famous discoveries in the
nineteenth century?
Reply: This doubt has recently been put to rest by the discovery
of Hittite tablets, dating from 1300 B.C., which clearly refer to
the land of the Achaeans and their king, Agamemnon. The
catalogue of Greek places that send ships to Troy in Book 2
corresponds remarkably closely to the pattern of settlement
which archaeology has discovered. The treasures of Mycenae,
once thought to be fairy tales in the imagination of a poet, have
been dug out of the silted ruins of the city. Other details mentioned in the Iliad, the manners of burial, the kinds of armor,
such as the precisely described boars'-tusk helmet, have been
unearthed in sites relevant to the poem. There is thus no question of its historical substrate. The Iliad is not imaginative creative literature and hence not a matter for literary discussion. It is
history, webbed into the Mycenaean Aegean, to be examined by
psychohistorical scientists.
The problem of single or multiple authorship of the poem has
been endlessly debated by classical scholars for at least a century.
But this establishment of an historical basis, even of artifacts
mentioned in the poem, must indicate that there were many
intermediaries who verbally transmitted whatever happened in
the thirteenth century to succeeding ages. It is thus more plausible to think of the creation of the poem as part of this verbal
transmission than as the work of a single man named Homer in
the ninth century B.C. Homer, if he existed, may simply have
been the first aoidos to be transcribed.
Objection: Even if this is so, what basis is there to suppose that
an epic poem, whose earliest manuscript that we know of is a
recension from Alexandrian scholars of the fourth or third century B.C., which obviously must have existed in many forms, and
as we read it today was put together out of them, how can a poem
of this sort be regarded as indicative of what the actual Mycenaeans of the thirteenth century B.C. were like?
THE
MIND
OF
ILIAD
77
Reply: This very serious objection is made even stronger by
certain discrepancies between the descriptions in the poem and
plausibility. The disappointing mounds of grassy rubble identified today by archaeologists as the city of Priam cover but a few
acres, while the Iliad counts its defenders at 50,000 men. Even
the trivial is sometimes moved up by hyperbole into impossibility:
the shield of Ajax, if it were made of seven oxhides and a layer of
metal, would have weighed almost 300 pounds. History has definitely been altered. The siege lasts ten years, an absolutely impossible duration given the problems of supply on both sides.
There are two general periods during which such alterations of
the original history could have occurred: the verbal transmission
period from the Trojan War to the ninth century B.C., when the
Greek alphabet comes into existence and the epic is written down,
and the literate period thereafter up to the time of the scholars
of Alexandria in the third and second centuries B.C. whose puttogether recension is the version we have today. As to the second period, there can be no doubt that there would be differences
among various copies, and that extra parts and variations, even
events belonging to different times and places, could have been
drawn into the vortex of this one furious story. But all these
additions were probably kept in check both by the transcribers'
reverence for the poem at this time, as is indicated in all other
Greek literature, and by the requirements of public performances. These were held at various sites, but particularly at the
Panathenaea every four years at Athens, where the Iliad was
devoutly chanted along with the Odyssey to vast audiences by the
so-called rhapsodes. It is probable therefore that with the exception of some episodes which contemporary scholars believe are
late additions (such as the ambushing of Dolon and the references
to Hades), the Iliad as we have it is very similar to what was
first written down in the ninth century B.C.
But further back in the dim obscurities of earlier time stand
the shadowy aoidoi. And it is they certainly who successively
78
The Mind of Man
altered the original history. Oral poetry is a very different species
from written poetry.6 The way we read it and judge it must be
completely different. Composition and performance are not
separate; they are simultaneous. And each new composing of the
Iliad down the swift generations was on the basis of auditory
memory and traditional bardic formulae, each aoidos with set
phrases of varying lengths filling out the unremembered hexameters and with set turns of plot filling out unremembered action.
And this was over the three or four centuries following the
actual war. The Iliad, then, is not so much a reflection of the
social life of Troy as it is of several stages of social development
from that time up to the literate period. Treated as a sociological document, the objection is sustained.
But as a psychological document, the case is quite different.
Whence these gods? And why their particular relationship to
the individuals? My argument has stressed two things, the lack
of mental language and the initiation of action by the gods.
These are not archaeological matters. Nor are they matters
likely to have been invented by the aoidoi. And any theory about
them has to be a psychological theory about man himself. The
only other alternative is the following.
Objection: Are we not making a great deal out of what might
be merely literary style? That the gods are mere poetic devices of
the aoidoi to make the action vivid, devices which may indeed go
back to the earliest bards of Mycenae?
Reply: This is the well-known problem of the gods and their
overdetermination of the action. The gods seem to us quite unnecessary. W h y are they there? And the common solution is as
above, that they are a poetic device. The divine machinery duplicates natural conscious causations simply to present them in
concrete pictorial form, because the aoidoi were without the refinements of language to express psychological matters.
6 See Milman Parry, Collected Papers (New York, Oxford University Press,
1971). I wish to thank both Randall Warner and Judith Griessman for discussion on
some of these points.
THE
MIND
OF
ILIAD
79
Not only is there no reason to believe that the aoidoi had any
conscious psychology they were trying to express, such a notion is
quite foreign to the whole texture of the poem. The Iliad is about
action and it is full of action — constant action. It really is about
Achilles' acts and their consequences, not about his mind. And as
for the gods, the Iliadic authors and the Iliadic characters all
agree in the acceptance of this divinely managed world. To say
the gods are an artistic apparatus is the same kind of thing as to
say that Joan of Arc told the Inquisition about her voices merely
to make it all vivid to those who were about to condemn her.
It is not that the vague general ideas of psychological causation
appear first and then the poet gives them concrete pictorial form
by inventing gods. It is, as I shall show later in this essay, just
the other way around. And when it is suggested that the inward
feelings of power or inward monitions or losses of judgment are
the germs out of which the divine machinery developed, I return
that the truth is just the reverse, that the presence of voices
which had to be obeyed were the absolute prerequisite to the
conscious stage of mind in which it is the self that is responsible
and can debate within itself, can order and direct, and that the
creation of such a self is the product of culture. In a sense, we
have become our own gods.
Objection: If the bicameral mind existed, one might expect
utter chaos, with everybody following his own private hallucinations. The only possible way in which there could be a bicameral
civilization would be that of a rigid hierarchy, with lesser men
hallucinating the voices of authorities over them, and those authorities hallucinating yet higher ones, and so on to the kings and
their peers hallucinating gods. Yet the Iliad does not present any
such picture with its concentration on the heroic individual.
Reply: This is a very telling objection that puzzled me for a
long time, particularly as I studied the history of other bicameral
civilizations in which there was not the freedom for individual
action that there was in the social world of the Iliad.
The missing pieces in the puzzle turn out to be the well-known
80
The Mind of Man
Linear B Tablets from Knossos, Mycenae, and Pylos. They were
written directly in what I am calling the bicameral period. They
have long been known, yet long resistant to the most arduous
labors of cryptographers. Recently, however, they have been
deciphered and shown to contain a syllabic script, the earliest
written Greek used only for record purposes.7 And it gives us an
outline picture of Mycenaean society much more in keeping with
the hypothesis of a bicameral mind: hierarchies of officials, soldiers, or workers, inventories of goods, statements of goods owed
to the ruler and particularly to gods. The actual world of the
Trojan War, then, was in historical fact much closer to the rigid
theocracy which the theory predicts than to the free individuality
of the poem.
Moreover, the very structure of the Mycenaean state is profoundly different from the loose assemblage of warriors depicted
in the Iliad. It is indeed quite similar to the contemporary
divinely ruled kingdoms of Mesopotamia (as described later in
this essay, particularly in II.2). These records in Linear B call
the head of the state the wanax, a word which in later classical
Greek is only used for gods. Similarly, the records call the land
occupied by his state as his temenos, a word which later is used
only for land sacred to the gods. The later Greek word for king is
basileus, but the term in these tablets denotes a much less important person. He is more or less the first servant of the wanax,
just as in Mesopotamia the human ruler was really the steward of
the lands 'owned' by the god he heard in hallucination — as we
shall see in II.2. The material from the Linear B tablets is
difficult to piece together, but they do reveal the hierarchical and
leveled nature of centralized palace civilizations which the succession of poets who composed the Iliad in the oral tradition
completely ignored.
7 M. C. F. Ventris and J. Chadwick, Documents in Mycenaean Greek (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1973). A summary of this material and its relationship to archaeological finds may be found in T. B. L. Webster, From Mycenae to
Homer (London: Methuen, 1958).
THE
MIND
OF
ILIAD
81
This loosening of the social structure in the fully developed
Iliad may in part have been caused by the bringing together of
other much later stories into the main theme of the Trojan War.
One of the most telling pieces of evidence that the Iliad is a
composite of different compositions is the large number of inconsistencies in the poem, some in very close proximity. For example, when Hector is withdrawing from the battle, one line
(6:117) says, "The black hide beat upon his neck and ankles."
This can only be the early Mycenaean body-shield. But the next
line refers to "The rim which ran round the outside of the bossed
shield," and this is a very different kind and a much later type of
shield. Obviously, the second line was added by a later poet who
in his auditory trance was not even visualizing what he was
saying.
Further Qualifications
Indeed, since this is the chaotic period when the bicameral
mind breaks down and consciousness begins (as we shall see in a
later chapter), we might expect the poem to reflect both this
breakdown of civil hierarchies as well as more subjectification
side by side with the older form of mentality. As it is, I have in
the previous pages omitted certain discrepancies to the theory
which I regard as such incursions. These outcroppings of something close to subjective consciousness occur in parts of the Iliad
regarded by scholars as later additions to the core poem.8
Book 9, for example, which was written and added to the poem
only after the great migration of the Achaeans into Asia Minor,
contains references to human deception unlike any in the other
books. Most of these occur in the great, long rhetorical reply of
Achilles to Odysseus about Agamemnon's treatment of him
(9:344, 371, and 375). In particular is Achilles' slur on Agamemnon: "Hateful to me as the gates of Hades is the man who
8 I am here drawing on Walter Leaf, A Companion to the Iliad (London: Macmillan, 1892), pp. 170-173.
82
The Mind of Man
hides one thing in his heart and speaks another." (9:3123f.). This
is definitely an indication of subjective consciousness. So also
may be the difficult-to-translate optative constructions of Helen
(3:173ff.; 6:344ff.) or the apparent reminiscence of Nestor
(1:26off.).
There are also two extraordinary places in the text where first
Agenor (21:553) and then Hector (22:99)
t0 themselves.
The fact that these two speeches occur late in the poem, in close
proximity, have highly inappropriate content (they contradict the
previous characterizations of the speakers), and use some identical phrases and lines, all suggest that they are formulaic insertions into the story by the same aoidos at a later time.9 But not
much later. For they are sufficiently unusual to surprise even
their speakers. After these soliloquies, both heroes exclaim
precisely the same astonished words, "But wherefore does my life
say this to me?" If, indeed, such talks to oneself were common, as
they would be if their speakers were really conscious, there would
be no cause for surprise. We shall have occasion to return to
these instances when we discuss in more detail how consciousness arose.10
The main point of this chapter is that the earliest writing of
men in a language that we can really comprehend, when looked
at objectively, reveals a very different mentality from our own.
And this must, I think, be accepted as true. Such instances of
narratization, analog behavior, or mind-space as occasionally occur are regarded by scholars as of later authorship. The bulk of
the poem is consistent in its lack of analog consciousness and
points back to a very different kind of human nature. Since we
know that Greek culture very quickly became a literature of
9 Even Leaf, p. 356, regards these two passages as spurious.
10 A further analysis might be made, establishing dates for the various parts of
the poem as they are thought by some scholars to have been assembled around the
much shorter core poem, and then demonstrating that the frequencies of occurrence
of these subjective outcroppings increase with recency.
THE
MIND
OF
ILIAD
83
consciousness, we may regard the Iliad as standing at the great
turning of the times, and a window back into those unsubjective
times when every kingdom was in essence a theocracy and every
man the slave of voices heard whenever novel situations occurred.
CHAPTER 4
The Bicameral Mind
W
E ARE conscious human beings. We are trying to understand human nature. The preposterous hypothesis we have
come to in the previous chapter is that at one time human nature
was split in two, an executive part called a god, and a follower
part called a man. Neither part was conscious. This is almost
incomprehensible to us. And since we are conscious, and wish to
understand, we wish to reduce this to something familiar in our
experience, as we saw was the nature of understanding in Chapter 2. And this is what I shall attempt in the present chapter.
THE
BICAMERAL
MAN
Very little can be said to make the man side of it seem familiar to
us, except by referring back to the first chapter, to remember all
the things we do without the aid of consciousness. But how
unsatisfying is a list of nots! Somehow we still wish to identify
with Achilles. We still feel that there must, there absolutely must
be something he feels inside. What we are trying to do is to
invent a mind-space and a world of analog behaviors in him just
as we do in ourselves and our contemporaries. And this invention, I say, is not valid for Greeks of this period.
Perhaps a metaphor of something close to that state might be
helpful. In driving a car, I am not sitting like a back-seat driver
directing myself, but rather find myself committed and engaged
THE
BICAMERAL
MIND
85
with little consciousness.1 In fact my consciousness will usually
be involved in something else, in a conversation with you if you
happen to be my passenger, or in thinking about the origin of
consciousness perhaps. My hand, foot, and head behavior, however, are almost in a different world. In touching something, I
am touched; in turning my head, the world turns to me; in
seeing, I am related to a world I immediately obey in the sense
of driving on the road and not on the sidewalk. And I am not
conscious of any of this. And certainly not logical about it. I am
caught up, unconsciously enthralled, if you will, in a total interacting reciprocity of stimulation that may be constantly threatening or comforting, appealing or repelling, responding to the
changes in traffic and particular aspects of it with trepidation or
confidence, trust or distrust, while my consciousness is still off on
other topics.
Now simply subtract that consciousness and you have what a
bicameral man would be like. The world would happen to him
and his action would be an inextricable part of that happening
with no consciousness whatever. And now let some brand-new
situation occur, an accident up ahead, a blocked road, a flat tire, a
stalled engine, and behold, our bicameral man would not do what
you and I would do, that is, quickly and efficiently swivel our
consciousness over to the matter and narratize out what to do.
He would have to wait for his bicameral voice which with the
stored-up admonitory wisdom of his life would tell him nonconsciously what to do.
THE
BICAMERAL
GOD
But what were such auditory hallucinations like? Some people
find it difficult to even imagine that there can be mental voices
1
owe the idea of this example to Erwin W. Straus' insightful essay, "Phenomenology of Hallucinations," in L. J. West, ed., Hallucinations (New York: Grune and
Stratton, 1962), pp. 220-232.
86
The Mind of Man
that are heard with the same experiential quality as externally
produced voices. After all, there is no mouth or larynx in the
brain!
Whatever brain areas are utilized, it is absolutely certain that
such voices do exist and that experiencing them is just like hearing actual sound. Further, it is highly probable that the bicameral voices of antiquity were in quality very like such auditory
hallucinations in contemporary people. They are heard by many
completely normal people to varying degrees. Often it is in times
of stress, when a parent's comforting voice may be heard.
Or in the midst of some persisting problem. In my late twenties, living alone on Beacon Hill in Boston, I had for about a week
been studying and autistically pondering some of the problems in
this book, particularly the question of what knowledge is and how
we can know anything at all. My convictions and misgivings had
been circling about through the sometimes precious fogs of epistemologies, finding nowhere to land. One afternoon I lay down in
intellectual despair on a couch. Suddenly, out of an absolute
quiet, there came a firm, distinct loud voice from my upper right
which said, "Include the knower in the known!" It lugged me to
my feet absurdly exclaiming, " H e l l o ? " looking for whoever was in
the room. The voice had had an exact location. No one was
there! Not even behind the wall where I sheepishly looked. I do
not take this nebulous profundity as divinely inspired, but I do
think that it is similar to what was heard by those who have in
the past claimed such special selection.
Such voices may be heard by perfectly normal people on a
more continuing basis. After giving lectures on the theory in this
book, I have been surprised at members of the audience who have
come up afterwards to tell me of their voices. One young biologist's wife said that almost every morning as she made the beds
and did the housework, she had long, informative, and pleasant
conversations with the voice of her dead grandmother in which
the grandmother's voice was actually heard. This came as something of a shock to her alarmed husband, for she had never
THE
BICAMERAL
MIND
87
previously mentioned it, since "hearing voices" is generally supposed to be a sign of insanity. Which, in distressed people, of
course, it is. But because of the dread surrounding this disease,
the actual incidence of auditory hallucinations in normal people
on such a continuing basis is not known.
The only extensive study was a poor one done in the last
century in England. 2 Only hallucinations of normal people when
they were in good health were counted. Of 7717 men, 7.8 percent had experienced hallucinations at some time. Among 7599
women, the figure was 12 percent. Hallucinations were most
frequent in subjects between twenty and twenty-nine years of
age, the same age incidentally at which schizophrenia most commonly occurs. There were twice as many visual hallucinations as
auditory. National differences were also found. Russians had
twice as many hallucinations as the average. Brazilians had even
more because of a very high incidence of auditory hallucinations.
Just why is anyone's conjecture. One of the deficiencies of this
study, however, is that in a country where ghosts are exciting
gossip, it is difficult to have accurate criteria of what is actually
seen and heard as an hallucination. There is an important need for
further and better studies of this sort.3
Hallucinations in Psychotics
It is of course in the distress of schizophrenia that auditory
hallucinations similar to bicameral voices are most common and
best studied. This is now a difficult matter. At a suspicion of
hallucinations, distressed psychotics are given some kind of
chemotherapy such as Thorazine, which specifically eliminates
hallucinations. This procedure is at least questionable, and may
be done not for the patient, but for the hospital which wishes to
2 Henry Sidgewick et al., "Report on the census of hallucinations," Proceedings of
the Society for Psychical Research, 1894, 34: 25-394.
3 An example of what not to do may be found in D. J. West, "A mass-observation
questionnaire on hallucinations," Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 1948,
34:187-196.
88
The Mind of Man
eliminate this rival control over the patient. But it has never been
shown that hallucinating patients are more intractable than
others. Indeed, as judged by other patients, hallucinating schizophrenics are more friendly, less defensive, more likable, and have
more positive expectancies toward others in the hospital than
nonhallucinating patients.4 And it is possible that even when
the effect is apparently negative, hallucinated voices may be
helpful to the healing process.
At any rate, since the advent of chemotherapy the incidence of
hallucinatory patients is much less than it once was. Recent
studies have revealed a wide variation among different hospitals,
ranging from 50 percent of psychotics in the Boston City Hospital, to 30 percent in a hospital in Oregon 5 and even lower in
hospitals with long-term patients under considerable sedation.
Thus, in what follows, I am leaning more heavily on some of the
older literature in the psychoses, such as Bleuler's great classic,
Dementia Praecox, in which the hallucinatory aspect of schizophrenia in particular is more clearly seen.6 This is important if
we are to have an idea of the nature and range of the bicameral
voices heard in the early civilizations.
The Character of the Voices
The voices in schizophrenia take any and every relationship to
the individual. They converse, threaten, curse, criticize, consult,
often in short sentences. They admonish, console, mock, command, or sometimes simply announce everything that's happen4 P. M. Lewinsohn, "Characteristics of patients with hallucinations," Journal of
Clinical Psychology, 1968, 24: 423.
5 P. E. Nathan, H. F. Simpson, and M. M. Audberg, "A systems analytic model
of diagnosis II. The diagnostic validity of abnormal perceptual behavior," Journal
of Clinical Psychology, 1969, 25: 115-136.
6 Eugen Bleuler, Dementia Praecox or The Group of Schizophrenias, Joseph
Zinkin, trans. (New York: International Universities Press, 1950). Other sources
for the sections to follow include my own observations and interviews with patients, works footnoted on subsequent pages, various chapters in L. J. West, and
miscellaneous case reports.
THE
BICAMERAL
MIND
89
ing. They yell, whine, sneer, and vary from the slightest whisper
to a thunderous shout. Often the voices take on some special
peculiarity, such as speaking very slowly, scanning, rhyming, or
in rhythms, or even in foreign languages. There may be one
particular voice, more often a few voices, and occasionally many.
As in bicameral civilizations, they are recognized as gods, angels,
devils, enemies, or a particular person or relative. Or occasionally they are ascribed to some kind of apparatus reminiscent of
the statuary which we will see was important in this regard in
bicameral kingdoms.
Sometimes the voices bring patients to despair, commanding
them to do something and then viciously reproaching them after
the command is carried out. Sometimes they are a dialogue, as of
two people discussing the patient. Sometimes the roles of pro
and con are taken over by the voices of different people. The
voice of his daughter tells a patient: " H e is going to be burnt
alive!" While his mother's voice says: " H e will not be burnt!" 7
In other instances, there are several voices gabbling all at once, so
that the patient cannot follow them.
Their Locality and Function
In some cases, particularly the most serious, the voices are not
localized. But usually they are. They call from one side or
another, from the rear, from above and below 3 only rarely do they
come from directly in front of the patient. They may seem to
come from walls, from the cellar and the roof, from heaven and
from hell, near or far, from parts of the body or parts of the
clothing. And sometimes, as one patient put it, "they assume the
nature of all those objects through which they speak — whether
they speak out of walls, or from ventilators, or in the woods and
fields." 8 In some patients there is a tendency to associate the
good consoling voices with the upper right, while bad voices
7 Bleuler, p. 97f.
8 T. Hennell, The Witnesses (London: Davis,
1938), p. 182.
90
The Mind of Man
come from below and to the left. In rare instances, the voices
seem to the patient to come from his own mouth, sometimes
feeling like foreign bodies bulging up in his mouth. Sometimes
the voices are hypostasized in bizarre ways. One patient claimed
that a voice was perched above each of his ears, one of which was
a little larger than the other, which is reminiscent of the ka's and
the way they were depicted in the statues of the pharaohs of
ancient Egypt, as we shall see in a subsequent chapter.
Very often the voices criticize a patient's thoughts and actions.
Sometimes they forbid him to do what he was just thinking of
doing. And sometimes this occurs even before the patient is
aware of his intention. One intelligent paranoid who came from
the Swiss canton of Thurgau harbored hostile feelings toward his
personal attendant. As the latter stepped into his room, the voice
said in its most reproachful tone before the patient had done
anything, "There you have it! A Thurgauer beats up a perfectly
decent private attendant!" 9
Of immense importance here is the fact that the nervous system of a patient makes simple perceptual judgments of which the
patient's 'self' is not aware. And these, as above, may then be
transposed into voices that seem prophetic. A janitor coming
down a hall may make a slight noise of which the patient is not
conscious. But the patient hears his hallucinated voice cry out,
"Now someone is coming down the hall with a bucket of water."
Then the door opens, and the prophecy is fulfilled. Credence in
the prophetic character of the voices, just as perhaps in bicameral times, is thus built up and sustained. The patient then
follows his voices alone and is defenseless against them. Or else,
if the voices are not clear, he waits, catatonic and mute, to be
shaped by them or, alternatively, by the voices and hands of his
attendants.
Usually the severity of schizophrenia oscillates during hospitalization and often the voices come and go with the undulations of
the illness. Sometimes they occur only when the patients are
9 Bleuler, p.
98.
THE
BICAMERAL
MIND
91
doing certain things, or only in certain environments. And in
many patients, before the present-day chemotherapy, there was
no single waking moment free from them. When the illness is
most severe, the voices are loudest and come from outside; when
least severe, voices often tend to be internal whispers; and when
internally localized, their auditory qualities are sometimes vague.
A patient might say, "They are not at all real voices but merely
reproductions of the voices of dead relatives." Particularly intelligent patients in mild forms of the illness are often not sure
whether they are actually hearing the voices or whether they are
only compelled to think them, like "audible thoughts," or "soundless voices," or "hallucinations of meanings."
Hallucinations must have some innate structure in the nervous
system underlying them. We can see this clearly by studying the
matter in those who have been profoundly deaf since birth or
very early childhood. For even they can — somehow — experience auditory hallucinations. This is commonly seen in deaf
schizophrenics. In one study, 16 out of 22 hallucinating, profoundly deaf schizophrenics insisted they had heard some kind of
communication.10 One thirty-two-year-old woman, born deaf,
who was full of self-recrimination about a therapeutic abortion,
claimed she heard accusations from God. Another, a fifty-yearold congenitally deaf woman, heard supernatural voices which
proclaimed her to have occult powers.
The Visual Component
Visual hallucinations in schizophrenia occur less commonly,
but sometimes with extreme clarity and vividness. One of my
schizophrenic subjects, a vivacious twenty-year-old writer of folk
songs, had been sitting in a car for a long time, anxiously waiting
for a friend. A blue car coming along the road suddenly, oddly,
10 J. D. Rainer, S. Abdullah, and J. C. Altshuler, "Phenomenology of hallucinations in the deaf" in Origin and Mechanisms of Hallucinations, Wolfram Keup, ed.
(New York: Plenum Press, 1970), pp. 449-465.
92
The Mind of Man
slowed, turned rusty brown, then grew huge gray wings and
slowly flapped over a hedge and disappeared. Her greater alarm,
however, came when others in the street behaved as if nothing
extraordinary had happened. Why? Unless all of them were
somehow in league to hide their reactions from her. And why
should that be? It is often the narratization of such false events
by consciousness, fitting the world in around them in a rational
way, that brings on other tragic symptoms.
It is interesting that profoundly deaf schizophrenics who do
not have auditory hallucinations often have visual hallucinations
of sign language. A sixteen-year-old girl who became deaf at the
age of eight months indulged in bizarre communication with
empty spaces and gesticulated to the walls. An older, congenitally deaf woman communicated with her hallucinated boyfriend
in sign language. Other deaf patients may appear to be in constant communication with imaginary people using a word salad
of signs and finger spelling. One thirty-five-year-old deaf woman,
who lost her hearing at the age of fourteen months, lived a life of
unrestrained promiscuity alternating with violent temper outbursts. On admission, she explained in sign language that every
morning a spirit dressed in a white robe came to her, saying
things in sign language which were at times frightening and
which set the pace of her mood for the day. Another deaf patient
would spit at empty space, saying that she was spitting at the
angels who were lurking there. A thirty-year-old man, deaf since
birth, more benignly, would see little angels and Lilliputian
people around him and believed he had a magic wand with which
he could achieve almost anything.
Occasionally, in what are called acute twilight states, whole
scenes, often of a religious nature, may be hallucinated even in
broad daylight, the heavens standing open with a god speaking to
the patient. Or sometimes writing will appear before a patient as
before Belshazzar. A paranoid patient saw the word poison in
the air at the very moment when the attendant made him take
THE
BICAMERAL
MIND
93
his medicine. In other instances, the visual hallucinations may
be fitted into the real environment, with figures walking about the
ward, or standing above the doctor's head, even as I suggest
Athene appeared to Achilles. More usually, when visual hallucinations occur with voices, they are merely shining light or cloudy
fog, as Thetis came to Achilles or Yahweh to Moses.
The Release of the Gods
If we are correct in assuming that schizophrenic hallucinations
are similar to the guidances of gods in antiquity, then there
should be some common physiological instigation in both instances. This, I suggest, is simply stress. In normal people, as
we have mentioned, the stress threshold for release of hallucinations is extremely high ; most of us need to be over our heads in
trouble before we would hear voices. But in psychosis-prone
persons, the threshold is somewhat lower; as in the girl I described, only anxious waiting in a parked car was necessary.
This is caused, I think, by the buildup in the blood of breakdown
products of stress-produced adrenalin which the individual is, for
genetical reasons, unable to pass through the kidneys as fast as a
normal person.
During the eras of the bicameral mind, we may suppose that
the stress threshold for hallucinations was much, much lower
than in either normal people or schizophrenics today. The only
stress necessary was that which occurs when a change in behavior is necessary because of some novelty in a situation. Anything
that could not be dealt with on the basis of habit, any conflict
between work and fatigue, between attack and flight, any choice
between whom to obey or what to do, anything that required any
decision at all was sufficient to cause an auditory hallucination.
It has now been clearly established that decision-making (and
I would like to remove every trace of conscious connotation from
the word 'decision') is precisely what stress is. If rats have to
94
The Mind of Man
cross an electric grid each time they wish to get food and water,
such rats develop ulcers.11 Just shocking the rats does not do
this to them. There has to be the pause of conflict or the decisionmaking stress of whether to cross a grid or not to produce this
effect. If two monkeys are placed in harnesses, in such a way
that one of the monkeys can press a bar at least once every
twenty seconds to avoid a periodic shock to both monkeys' feet,
within three or four weeks the decision-making monkey will
have ulcers, while the other, equally shocked monkey will not.12
It is the pause of unknowingness that is important. For if the
experiment is so arranged that an animal can make an effective
response and receive immediate feedback of his success, executive ulcers, as they are often called, do not occur.13
So Achilles, repulsed by Agamemnon, in decision-stress by the
gray sea, hallucinates Thetis out of the mists. So Hector, faced
with the decision-suffering of whether to go outside the walls of
Troy to fight Achilles or stay within them, in the stress of the
decision hallucinates the voice that tells him to go out. The
divine voice ends the decision-stress before it has reached any
considerable level. Had Achilles or Hector been modern executives, living in a culture that repressed their stress-relieving gods,
they too might have collected their share of our psychosomatic
diseases.
THE
AUTHORITY
OF
SOUND
We must not leave this subject of the hallucinatory mechanism
without facing up to the more profound question of why such
11 W. L. Sawrey and J. D. Weisz, "An experimental method of producing gastric
ulcers," Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 1956, 49: 269—270.
12 J. V. Brady, R. W. Porter, D. G. Conrad, and J. W. Mason, "Avoidance behavior and the development of gastro-duodenal ulcers," Journal of the Experimental
Analysis of Behavior, 1958, 1: 69-72.
13 J. M. Weiss, "Psychological Factors in Stress and Disease," Scientific American,
1972, 226: 106.
THE
BICAMERAL
95
MIND
voices are believed, why obeyed. For believed as objectively real,
they are, and obeyed as objectively real in the face of all the
evidence of experience and the mountains of common sense.
Indeed, the voices a patient hears are more real than the doctor's
voice. He sometimes says so. " I f that is not a real voice, then I
can just as well say that even you are not now really talking to
me," said one schizophrenic to his physicians. And another when
questioned replied:
Y e s , Sir.
I hear voices distinctly, even l o u d l y ; they interrupt us
at this m o m e n t . It is more easy for me to listen to them than to
you. I can more easily believe in their significance and actuality,
and they do not ask questions. 14
That he alone hears the voices is not of much concern. Sometimes he feels he has been honored by this gift, singled out by
divine forces, elected and glorified, and this even when the voice
reproaches him bitterly, even when it is leading him to death. He
is somehow face to face with elemental auditory powers, more
real than wind or rain or fire, powers that deride and threaten
and console, powers that he cannot step back from and see
objectively.
One sunny afternoon not long ago, a man was lying back in a
deck chair on the beach at Coney Island. Suddenly, he heard a
voice so loud and clear that he looked about at his companions,
certain that they too must have heard the voice. When they acted
as if nothing had happened, he began to feel strange and moved
his chair away from them. And then
. . . suddenly, clearer, deeper, and even louder than before,
the deep voice came at me again, right in my ear this time, and
getting me tight and shivery inside.
before you w e r e n ' t any good.
" L a r r y Jayson, I told you
W h y are you sitting here making
believe you are as good as anyone else w h e n you're not?
are you fooling ?"
14 Hennell,
pp. 181-182.
Whom
96
The Mind of Man
The deep voice was so loud and so clear, everyone must have
heard it. He got up and walked slowly away, down the stairs of
the boardwalk to the stretch of sand below. He waited to see if
the voice came back. It did, its words pounding in this time, not
the way you hear any words, but deeper,
. . . a s though all parts o f m e had become ears, with m y fingers
hearing the words, and my legs, and my head too.
" Y o u ' r e no
g o o d , " the voice said slowly, in the same deep tones.
"You've
never been any good or use on earth. T h e r e is the ocean. Y o u
might just as well d r o w n yourself. Just w a l k in, and keep w a l k ng."
As soon as the voice w a s through, I k n e w by its cold c o m m a n d , I had to obey it. 1 5
The patient walking the pounded sands of Coney Island heard his
pounding voices as clearly as Achilles heard Thetis along the
misted shores of the Aegean. And even as Agamemnon "had to
obey" the "cold command" of Zeus, or Paul the command of Jesus
before Damascus, so Mr. Jayson waded into the Atlantic Ocean to
drown. Against the will of his voices, he was saved by lifeguards and brought to Bellevue Hospital, where he recovered to
write of this bicameral experience.
In some less severe cases, the patients, when accustomed to
the voices, can learn to be objective toward them and to attenuate
their authority. But almost all autobiographies of schizophrenic
patients are consistent in speaking of the unquestioning submission, at least at first, to the commands of the voices. W h y should
this be so? W h y should such voices have such authority either in
Argos, on the road to Damascus, or the shores of Coney Island?
Sound is a very special modality. We cannot handle it. We
cannot push it away. We cannot turn our backs to it. We can
close our eyes, hold our noses, withdraw from touch, refuse to
taste. We cannot close our ears though we can partly muffle
15 L.
N. Jayson, Mania (New York: Funk and Wagnall, 1937), pp. 1-3.
THE
BICAMERAL
MIND
97
them. Sound is the least controllable of all sense modalities, and
it is this that is the medium of that most intricate of all evolutionary achievements, language. We are therefore looking at a problem of considerable depth and complexity.
The Control of Obedience
Consider what it is to listen and understand someone speaking
to us. In a certain sense we have to become the other person; or
rather, we let him become part of us for a brief second. We
suspend our own identities, after which we come back to ourselves and accept or reject what he has said. But that brief
second of dawdling identity is the nature of understanding language; and if that language is a command, the identification of
understanding becomes the obedience. To hear is actually a kind
of obedience. Indeed, both words come from the same root and
therefore were probably the same word originally. This is true in
Greek, Latin, Hebrew, French, German, Russian, as well as in
English, where 'obey' comes from the Latin obedire, which is a
composite of ob + audire, to hear facing someone.16
The problem is the control of such obedience. This is done in
two ways.
The first but less important is simply by spatial distance.
Think, if you will, of what you do when hearing someone else
talk to you. You adjust your distance to some culturally established standard.17 When the speaker is too close, it seems he is
trying to control your thoughts too closely. When too far, he is
not controlling them enough for you to understand him comfortably. If you are from an Arabian country, a face-to-face distance
of less than twelve inches is comfortable. But in more northern
Straus, p. 229.
For those interested in pursuing this subject, see Edward T. Hall's The Hidden
Dimension (New York: Doubleday, 1966), which stresses the cultural differences, and
Robert Sommer's Personal Space: The Behavioral Basis of Design (Englewood
Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1969), which examines spatial behavior in depth.
16
17
98
The Mind of Man
countries, the conversation distance most comfortable is almost
twice that, a cultural difference, which in social exchanges can
result in a variety of international misunderstandings. To converse with someone at less than the usual distance means at least
an attempted mutuality of obedience and control, as, for example, in a love relationship, or in the face-to-face threatening of
two men about to fight. To speak to someone within that distance
is to attempt to truly dominate him or her. To be spoken to
within that distance, and there remain, results in the strong
tendency to accept the authority of the person who is speaking.
The second and more important way that we control other
people's voice-authority over us is by our opinions of them. W h y
are we forever judging, forever criticizing, forever putting people
in categories of faint praise or reproof? We constantly rate
others and pigeonhole them in often ridiculous status hierarchies
simply to regulate their control over us and our thoughts. Our
personal judgments of others are filters of influence. If you wish
to allow another's language power over you, simply hold him
higher in your own private scale of esteem.
And now consider what it is like if neither of these methods
avail, because there is no person there, no point of space from
which the voice emanates, a voice that you cannot back off
from, as close to you as everything you call you, when its presence eludes all boundaries, when no escape is possible — flee and
it flees with you — a voice unhindered by walls or distances,
undiminished by muffling one's ears, nor drowned out with anything, not even one's own screaming — how helpless the hearer!
And if one belonged to a bicameral culture, where the voices
were recognized as at the utmost top of the hierarchy, taught you
as gods, kings, majesties that owned you, head, heart, and foot,
the omniscient, omnipotent voices that could not be categorized
as beneath you, how obedient to them the bicameral man!
The explanation of volition in subjective conscious men is still
a profound problem that has not reached any satisfactory solu-
THE
BICAMERAL
MIND
99
tion. But in bicameral men, this was volition. Another way to
say it is that volition came as a voice that was in the nature of a
neurological command, in which the command and the action
were not separated, in which to hear was to obey.
CHAPTER 5
The Double Brain
W
H A T HAPPENS in the brain of a bicameral man?
Anything as
important in the history of our species as a completely different kind of mentality existing only a hundred generations ago
demands some statement of what is going on physiologically.
How is it possible? Given this profoundly subtle structure of
nerve cells and fibers inside our skulls, how could that structure
have been organized so that a bicameral mentality was possible?
This is the great question of the present chapter.
Our first approach to an answer is obvious. Since the bicameral mind is mediated by speech, the speech areas of the brain
must be concerned in some important way.
Now in discussing these areas, and throughout this chapter,
and indeed in the rest of this essay, I shall be using terms suitable
only to right-handed people, in order to avoid a certain clumsiness of expression. Thus, it is the left cerebral hemisphere of the
brain, controlling the right side of the body, which in righthanded people contains the speech areas. It is therefore commonly called the dominant hemisphere, while the right
hemisphere, controlling the left side of the body, is commonly
called the nondominant. I shall be speaking as if the left hemisphere were dominant in all of us. Actually, however, lefthanded persons have a variety of degrees of lateral dominance,
some being completely switched (the right hemisphere doing
what the left usually does), others not, and still others with
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
101
T h e three speech areas of the left hemisphere have different functions and values. T h e supplementary motor area is mostly involved
in articulation; Broca's area in articulation, vocabulary, inflection,
and grammar; and Wernicke's area in vocabulary, syntax, meaning,
and understanding speech.
mixed dominance. But being exceptional, only 5 percent of the
population, they can be left out of the present discussion.
The speech areas then are three, all on the left hemisphere in
the great majority of mankind.1 They are: (I) the supplementary motor cortex, on the very top of the left frontal lobe, removal
of which by surgery produces a loss of speech which clears up in
several weeks; (2) Broca's area, lower down at the back of the
left frontal lobe, the removal of which produces a loss of speech
which is sometimes permanent and sometimes not; and (3)
Wernicke's area, chiefly the posterior part of the left temporal
lobe with parts of the parietal area, any large destruction of
1 I am here following the late Wilder Penfield and Lamar Roberts, Speech and
Brain-Mechanisms (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1959), the traditional
authority although some of it is out of date in the present explosion of knowledge
in this area.
102
The Mind of Man
which after a certain age produces a permanent loss of meaningful speech.
It is thus Wernicke's area that is the most indispensable to normal speech. As we might expect, the cortex in Wernicke's area is
quite thick with large, widely spaced cells, indicating considerable
internal and external connections. While there is some disagreement as to its precise boundaries,2 there is none about its importance to meaningful communication.
Of course it is extremely hazardous thinking to isomorphize between a conceptual analysis of a psychological phenomenon and
its concomitant brain structure, yet this is what we cannot avoid
doing. And among these three areas on the left hemisphere, or
even in their more subtle interrelationships, it is difficult to imagine a duplication of some speech function to the extent and
separation which my theory of the bicameral mind would
demand.
Let us sit down with this problem a moment. Speech areas all
on the left side. Why? One intriguing puzzle which has long
fascinated me and anyone else who has considered the evolution
of all this is why language function should be represented in only
one hemisphere. Most other important functions are bilaterally
represented. This redundancy in everything else is a biological
advantage to the animal, since, if one side is injured, the other
side can compensate. W h y then was not language? Language,
that most urgent and significant of skills, the pre-emptory and
exigent ground of social action, the last communicant thread on
which life itself in the post-glacial millennia must often have
depended! W h y was not this without-which-nothing of human
culture represented on both hemispheres?
The problem drifts off into even more mystery when we remember that the neurological structure necessary for language
2 Joseph Bogen with his usual helpfulness has taken the time to point out to me
the slipperiness of the evidence for just what regions are to be included in Wernicke's
area. I am also indebted to my former student, Stevan Hamad, for invaluable discussion on many of these issues.
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
103
exists in the right hemisphere as well as the left. In a child, a
major lesion of Wernicke's area on the left hemisphere, or of the
underlying thalamus which connects it to the brainstem, produces transfer of the whole speech mechanism to the right hemisphere. A very few ambidextrous people actually do have speech
on both hemispheres. Thus the usually speechless right hemisphere can under certain conditions become a language hemisphere, just like the left.
And a further range of the problem is what did happen in the
right hemisphere as the aptic structures for language were evolving in the left? Just consider those areas on the right hemisphere corresponding to the speech areas of the left: what is their
function? Or, more particularly, what is their important function, since it must have been such to preclude its development as
an auxiliary speech area? If we stimulate such areas on the right
hemisphere today, we do not get the usual "aphasic arrest"
(simply the stopping of ongoing speech) which occurs when the
normal language areas of the left hemisphere are stimulated.
And because of this apparent lack of function, it has often been
concluded that large portions of the right hemisphere are simply
unnecessary. In fact, large amounts of right hemisphere tissue,
including what corresponds to Wernicke's area, and even in some
instances the entire hemisphere, have been cut out in human
patients because of illness or injury, with surprisingly little deficit
in mental function.
The situation then is one where the areas on the right hemisphere that correspond to the speech areas have seemingly no
easily observable major function. W h y this relatively less essential part of the brain? Could it be that these silent 'speech' areas
on the right hemisphere had some function at an earlier stage in
man's history that now they do not have?
The answer is clear if tentative. The selective pressures of
evolution which could have brought about so mighty a result are
those of the bicameral civilizations. The language of men was
104
The Mind of Man
involved with only one hemisphere in order to leave the other
free for the language of gods.
If so, we might expect that there would have to be certain
tracts by which the bicameral voices would relate between the
right nondominant temporal lobe and the left. The major interconnection between the hemispheres is of course the huge corpus
callosum of over two million fibers. But the temporal lobes in
men have their own private callosum, so to speak, the much
smaller anterior commissures. In rats and dogs, the anterior
commissures connect the olfactory parts of the brain. But in
men, as seen in my rather imprecise sketch, this transverse band
of fibers collects from most of the temporal lobe cortex but particularly the middle gyrus of the temporal lobe included in Wernicke's area, and then squeezes into a tract only slightly more
than one eighth of an inch in diameter as it plunges over the
amygdala across the top of the hypothalamus toward the other
temporal lobe. Here then, I suggest, is the tiny bridge across
which came the directions which built our civilizations and founded
In ancient times, what corresponds to Wernicke's area on the right
hemisphere may have organized admonitory experience and coded
it into 'voices' which were then 'heard' over the anterior commissure
by the l e f t or dominant hemisphere.
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
105
the world's religions, where gods spoke to men and were obeyed
because they were human volition.3
There are two forms in which this hypothesis can be specified.
The stronger form, and the one I favor because it is simpler
and more specific (and thus more easily verified or disconfirmed
by empirical investigation), is that the speech of the gods was
directly organized in what corresponds to Wernicke's area on the
right hemisphere and 'spoken' or 'heard' over the anterior commissures to or by the auditory areas of the left temporal lobe.
(Note how I can only express this metaphorically, personifying
the right temporal lobe as a person speaking or the left temporal
lobe as a person listening, both being equivalent and both literally
false.) Another reason I am inclined to this stronger form is its
very rationality in terms of getting processed information or
thought from one side of the brain to the other. Consider the
evolutionary problem: billions of nerve cells processing complex
experience on one side and needing to send the results over to the
other through the much smaller commissures. Some code would
have to be used, some way of reducing very complicated processing into a form that could be transmitted through the fewer
neurons particularly of the anterior commissures. And what better code has ever appeared in the evolution of animal nervous
systems than human language? Thus in the stronger form of our
model, auditory hallucinations exist as such in a linguistic manner because that is the most efficient method of getting complicated cortical processing from one side of the brain to the other.
The weaker form of the hypothesis is more vague. It states
that the articulatory qualities of the hallucination were of left
hemisphere origin like the speech of the person himself, but that
3 I do not mean to imply that the bicameral transmission was the only function
of the anterior commissure. This commissure interconnects most of the two temporal
lobes, including a good part of the posterior portion of the inferior temporal convolution. This region is fed by a strong system of fibers sweeping down from the
occipital lobe and is centrally important to visual gnostic functions. See E. G. Ettlinger, Functions of the Corpus Callosum (Boston: Little, Brown, 1965).
106
The Mind of Man
its sense and direction and different relation to the person were
due to right temporal lobe activity sending excitation over the
anterior commissures and probably the splenium (the back part
of the corpus callosum) to the speech areas of the left hemisphere, and 'heard' from there.
At the present time, it does not really matter which form of the
hypothesis we take. The central feature of both is that the amalgamating of admonitory experience was a right hemisphere function and it was excitation in what corresponds to Wernicke's area
on the right hemisphere that occasioned the voices of the gods.
The evidence to support this hypothesis may be brought together as five observations: (I) that both hemispheres are able
to understand language, while normally only the left can speak;
(2) that there is some vestigial functioning of the right Wernicke's area in a way similar to the voices of gods; (3) that the
two hemispheres under certain conditions are able to act almost
as independent persons, their relationship corresponding to that
of the man-god relationship of bicameral times; (4) that contemporary differences between the hemispheres in cognitive functions at least echo such differences of function between man and
god as seen in the literature of bicameral man; and (5) that the
brain is more capable of being organized by the environment than
we have hitherto supposed, and therefore could have undergone
such a change as from bicameral to conscious man mostly on the
basis of learning and culture.
The rest of this chapter will be devoted to these five observations.
1.
That Both Hemispheres Understand Language
The gods, I have said with some presumption, were amalgams
of admonitory experience, made up of meldings of whatever
commands had been given the individual. Thus, while the divine
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
107
areas would not have to be involved in speech, they would have to
be involved in hearing and in understanding language. And this
is the case even today. We do in fact understand language with
both hemispheres. Stroke patients who have hemorrhages on the
left side of the cortex cannot speak, but still can understand.4
If sodium amytal is injected into the left carotid artery leading to
the left hemisphere (the Wada test), the entire hemisphere is
anesthetized, leaving only the right hemisphere working; but the
subject still can follow directions.5 Tests on commissurotomized
patients (which I shall describe more fully in a moment) demonstrate considerable understanding by the right hemisphere.6
Named objects can usually be retrieved by the left hand, and
verbal commands obeyed by the left hand. Even when the entire
left hemisphere, the speech hemisphere, remember, is removed
in human patients suffering from glioma, the remaining right
hemisphere immediately after the operation seems to understand
the surgeon's questions, though unable to reply.7
2. That There Exists Vestigial Godlike Function in the Right
Hemisphere
If the preceding model is correct, there might be some residual
indication, no matter how small, of the ancient divine function of
the right hemisphere. We can, indeed, be more specific here.
Since the voices of the gods did not, of course, entail articulate
This is a general observation — true of cases I have interviewed personally.
T h e Wada test is presently part of presurgical procedures before brain surgery
in the Montreal Neurological Institute. See J. Wada and T. Rasmussen, "Intracarotid
Injection of Sodium Amytal for the Lateralization of Cerebral Speech Dominance,"
Journal of Neurosurgery, 1960, 1 7 : 266-282.
6 M. S. Gazzaniga, J. E. Bogen, R. W. Sperry, "Laterality effects in somesthesis
following cerebral commissurotomy in man," Neuropsychologia, 1: 209-215. See
also Stuart Dimond's excellent discussion of the problem in his The Double Brain
(Edinburgh and London: Churchill Livingstone, 1 9 7 2 ) , p. 84.
4
5
7 Aaron Smith, "Speech and other functions after left (dominant) hemispherectomy," Journal of Neurology Neurosurgical Psychiatry, 29 : 4 6 7 - 4 7 1 .
108
The Mind of Man
speech, did not entail the use of the larynx and mouth, we can
rule out what corresponds to Broca's area and the supplementary
motor area, to a certain extent, and concentrate on what corresponds to Wernicke's area or the posterior part of the temporal
lobe on the right or so-called nondominant side. If we stimulate it
in this location, would we hear then the voices of the gods as of
yore? Or some remnant of them? Something that would allow
us to think that three thousand years ago its function was that of
the divine direction of human affairs?
We may recall that this was indeed the very area which had
been stimulated by Wilder Penfield in a famous series of studies a
few years ago.8 Let me describe them in some detail.
These observations were made on some seventy patients with a
diagnosis of epilepsy caused by lesions somewhere in the temporal lobe. As a preliminary to the removal of the damaged brain
tissue by surgery, various points on the surface of the temporal
lobe were stimulated with a gentle electric current. The intensity
of the stimulation was approximately the least current needed to
excite tingling in the thumb by stimulation of the appropriate
motor area. If it be objected that the phenomena resulting from
this stimulation are corrupted by the presence of some focal area
of gliosis, or sclerosis, or meningo-cerebral cicatrix, all typically
found in such patients, I think such objections would be dissipated by reviewing the original report. These abnormalities,
when found, were circumscribed in location and were not in any
way influencing the responses of the subject as they were being
stimulated.9 It can thus be assumed with some confidence that
the results of these studies are representative of what would be
found in normal individuals.
In the great majority of these cases, it was the right temporal
8 Wilder Penfield and Phanor Perot, "The brain's record of auditory and visual
experience: a final summary and discussion," Brain, 1963, 86: 595—702.
9 Though presumably the particular aura of the epilepsy had been occasioned by
the spread of cortical excitation from the lesion to these same areas.
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
109
lobe that was stimulated, particularly the posterior part of the
temporal lobe toward its superior convolution, Wernicke's area on
the right side. A remarkable series of responses from the patients was obtained. This is, to repeat myself, the point at which
we might expect to hear the gods of antiquity calling to us again,
as if from the other part of our bicameral minds. Would these
patients hear some vestiges of the ancient divinities?
Here are some representative data.
When stimulated in this region, Case 7, a twenty-year-old college student, cried out, "Again I hear voices, I sort of lost touch
with reality. Humming in my ears and a small feeling like a
warning." And when stimulated again, "Voices, the same as before. I was just losing touch with reality again." When asked, he
replied that he could not understand what the voices were saying.
They sounded "hazy."
In the majority of cases, the voices were similarly hazy. Case
8, a twenty-six-year-old housewife, stimulated in approximately
the same area, said there seemed to be a voice a way, way off. "It
sounded like a voice saying words but it was so faint I couldn't get
it." Case 12, a twenty-four-year-old woman, stimulated at successive points of the superior gyrus of the posterior temporal lobe,
said, "I could hear someone talking, murmuring or something."
And then further on, "There was talking or murmuring, but I
cannot understand it." And then stimulated about three quarters
of an inch along the gyrus, she was at first silent, and then gave a
loud cry. "I heard the voices and then I screamed. I had a feeling
all over." And then stimulated a little back toward the first
stimulations, she began to sob. "That man's voice again! The
only thing I know is that my father frightens me a lot." She did
not recognize the voice as her father's; it only reminded her of
him.
Some patients heard music, unrecognized melodies that could
be hummed to the surgeon (Cases 4 and 5). Others heard relatives, particularly their mothers. Case 32, a twenty-two-year-old
110
The Mind of Man
woman, heard her mother and father talking and singing, and
then stimulated on another point, her mother “just yelling.”
Many patients heard the voices as emanating from strange and
unknown places. Case 36, a twenty-six-year-old woman, stimulated somewhat anteriorly on the superior gyrus of the right
temporal lobe, said, “Yes, I heard voices down along the river
somewhere — a man’s voice and a woman’s voice, calling.”
When asked how she could tell it was down along the river, she
said, “I think I saw the river.” When asked what river, she said,
“I do not know, it seems to be one I was visiting when I was a
child.” And at other stimulation points, she heard voices of
people calling from building to building somewhere. And at an
adjacent point, the voice of a woman calling in a lumberyard,
though she insisted that she had “never been around any lumberyard.”
When the voices were located as coming from one side or the
other, as rarely happened, it was from the contralateral side.
Case 29, a twenty-five-year-old man, stimulated in the middle of
the right temporal gyrus, said, “Someone telling me in my left
ear, ‘Sylvere, Sylvere!’ It could have been my brother.”
The voices and the music, whether garbled or recognized, were
experienced as actually heard, and the visual hallucinations were
experienced as-actually seen, just as Achilles experienced Thetis,
or Moses heard Yahweh out of the burning bush. Case 29, the
same as above, when stimulated again, also saw “someone speaking to another and he mentioned the name, but I could not
understand it.” And when asked whether he saw the person he
replied, “It was just like a dream.” And when asked further if the
person was there, he said, “Yes, sir, about where the nurse with
the eyeglasses is sitting over there.”
In some slightly older patients, only exploratory stimulation
produced an hallucination. A thirty-four-year-old French-Canadian, Case 24, after previous stimulations had produced nothing,
when stimulated on the posterior part of the middle gyrus of the
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
111
right temporal lobe, suddenly said, "Wait a minute, I see someone! " And then about an inch higher, "Oui, la, la, la! It was he,
he came, that fool!" And then stimulated somewhat higher
though still within what corresponds to Wernicke's area on the
right side, "There, there, j'entend! It is just that somebody
wanted to speak to me, and he was going, 'vite, vite, vite!'
But at younger ages, there is a definite suggestion that hallucinations caused by stimulating the right temporal lobe are more
striking, vivid, and admonitory. A fourteen-year-old boy (Case
34) saw two men sitting in armchairs singing at him. A fourteenyear-old girl, Case 15, when stimulated on the superior posterior
gyrus of the right temporal lobe, cried out, "Oh, everybody is
shouting at me again, make them stop!" The stimulus duration
was two seconds; the voices lasted eleven seconds. She explained, "They are yelling at me for doing something wrong,
everybody is yelling." At all stimulation points along the posterior
temporal lobe of the right hemisphere, she heard yelling. And
even when stimulated an inch and a half posterior to the first
point, she cried out, "There they go, yelling at me; stop them!"
And the voices coming from just one stimulation lasted twentyone seconds.
I should not give the impression that it is all this simple. I
have selected these cases. In some patients, there was no response at all. Occasionally such experiences involved autoscopic
illusions such as we referred to in I.2. A further complication is
that stimulation of corresponding points on the left or usually
dominant hemisphere may also result in similar hallucinations.
In other words, such phenomena are not confined to the right
temporal lobe. But the instances of response to stimulation on
the left are much less frequent and occur with less intensity.
The important thing about almost all these stimulation-caused
experiences is their otherness, their opposition from the self,
rather than the self's own actions or own words. With a few
112
The Mind of Man
exceptions, the patients never experienced eating, talking, sex,
running, or playing. In almost all instances, the subject was
passive and being acted upon, exactly as a bicameral man was
acted upon by his voices.
Being acted upon by what? Penfield and Perot think it is
simply past experience, flashbacks to earlier days. They try to
explain the failure of recognition so consistently observed as
mere forgetfulness. They assume that these were actual specific
memories that with more time during the operation could have
been pushed into full recognition. In fact, their questions to the
patients during stimulation were guided by this hypothesis.
Sometimes, indeed, the patient did become specific in his replies.
But far more representative of the data as a whole is the patients' persistence under questioning that these experiences could
not be called memories.
Because of this, and because of the general absence of personal active images, which are the usual kind of memories that
we have, I suggest that the conclusions of Penfield and Perot are
incorrect. These areas of the temporal lobe are not "the brain's
record of auditory and visual experience," nor are they its retrieval, but combinations and amalgamations of certain aspects
of that experience. The evidence does not, I think, warrant the
assertion that these areas "play in adult lives some role in the
subconscious recall of past experience, making it available for
present interpretation." Rather the data lead away from this, to
hallucinations that distill particularly admonition experiences,
and perhaps become embodied or rationalized into actual experiences in those patients who reported them on being questioned.
3.
That the Two Hemispheres Can Behave Independently
In our brain model of the bicameral mind, we have assumed
that the god part and the man part behaved and thought somewhat independently. And if we now say that the duality of this
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
113
ancient mentality is represented in the duality of the cerebral
hemispheres, is this not personifying parts of the brain without
warrant? Is it possible to think of the two hemispheres of the
brain almost as two individuals, only one of which can overtly
speak, while both can listen and both understand?
The evidence that this is plausible comes from another group of
epileptics. These are the dozen or so neurosurgical patients who
have undergone complete commissurotomy, the cutting down the
midline of all interconnections between the two hemispheres.10
This so-called split-brain operation (which it is not — the deeper
parts of the brain are still connected) usually cures the otherwise untreatable epilepsy by preventing the spread of abnormal
neural excitation over the whole cortex. Immediately after operation, some patients lose speech for up to two months, while
others have no problem whatever — no one knows why. Perhaps
each of us has a slightly different relationship between our hemispheres. Recovery is gradual, all patients showing short-term
memory deficits (perhaps due to the cutting of the small hippocampal commissures), some orientation problems, and mental
fatigue.
Now the astonishing thing is that such patients after a year or
so of recovery do not feel any different from the way they felt
before the operation. They sense nothing wrong. At the present
time they are watching television or reading the paper with no
complaints about anything peculiar. Nor does an observer notice
anything different about them.
But under rigorous control of sensory input, fascinating and
important defects are revealed.
10 The literature on these patients of Joseph E. Bogen is still expanding. I would
recommend his classical papers, particularly "The other side of the brain, II: An
appositional mind," Bulletin of the Los Angeles Neurological Society, 1969, 34 (3) :
135-162. For a discussion by one of the pioneers in hemispheric research, R. W.
Sperry, "Hemisphere Deconnection and Unity in Conscious Awareness," American
Psychologist, 1968, 23: 723-733. And for a readable account by the man whose ingenuity devised ways of testing these patients, read Michael Gazzaniga's The Bisected
Brain (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1970).
114
The Mind of Man
As you look at anything, say, the middle word of this line of
print, all the words to the left are seen only by the right hemisphere, and all the words to the right only by the left. With the
connections between the hemispheres intact, there is no particular problem in co-ordinating the two, although it really is astonishing that we can read at all. But if you had your hemispheric
connections cut, the matter would be very different. Starting at
the middle of this line, all the print to your right would be seen as
before and you would be able to read it off almost as usual. But
all the print and all the page to your left would be a blank. Not a
blank really, but a nothing, an absolute nothing, far more nothing
than any nothing you can imagine. So much nothing that you
would not even be conscious that there was nothing there,
strange as it seems. Just as in the phenomenon of the blind
spot, the 'nothing' is somehow 'filled in', 'stitched together', as
if nothing were wrong with nothing. Actually, however, all that
nothing would be in your other hemisphere which would be
seeing all that 'you' were not, all the print to the left, and seeing it
perfectly well. But since it does not have articulated speech, it
cannot say that it sees anything. It is as if 'you' — whatever that
means — were 'in' your left hemisphere and now with the commissures cut could never know or be conscious of what a quite
different person, once also 'you', in the other hemisphere was
seeing or thinking about. Two persons in one head.
This is one of the ways these commissurotomized patients are
tested. The patient fixates on the center of a translucent screen;
photographic slides of objects projected on the left side of the
screen are thus seen only by the right hemisphere and cannot be
reported verbally, though the patient can use his left hand (controlled by the right hemisphere) to point to a matching picture or
search out the object among others, even while insisting vocally
that he did not see it.11 Such stimuli seen by the right nondomi11 M.
S. Gazzaniga, J. E. Bogen, and R. W. Sperry, "Observations on visual perception after disconnection of the cerebral hemispheres in man," Brain, 8: 221-236,
1965.
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
115
nant hemisphere alone are there imprisoned, and cannot be ‘told’
to the left hemisphere where the language areas are because the
connections have been cut. The only way we know that the right
hemisphere has this information at all is to ask the right hemisphere to use its left hand to point it out — which it can readily do.
If two different figures are flashed simultaneously to the right
and left visual fields, as, for example, a “dollar sign” on the left
and a “question mark” on the right, and the subject is asked to
draw what he saw, using the left hand out of sight under a screen,
he draws the dollar sign. But asked what he has just drawn out of
sight, he insists it was the question mark. In other words, the one
hemisphere does not know what the other hemisphere has been
doing.
Again, if the name of some object, like the word ‘eraser’, is
flashed to the left visual field, the subject is then able to search
out an eraser from among a collection of objects behind a screen
using only the left hand. If the subject is then asked what the
item is behind the screen after it has been selected correctly, ‘he’
in the left hemisphere cannot say what the dumb ‘he’ of the right
hemisphere is holding in his left hand. Similarly, the left hand
can do this if the word ‘eraser’ is spoken, but the talking hemisphere does not know when the left hand has found the object.
This shows, of course, what I have said earlier, that both hemispheres understand language, but it has never been possible to
find out the extent of language understanding in the right hemisphere previously.
Further, we find that the right hemisphere is able to understand complicated definitions. Flashing “shaving instrument”
onto the left visual field and so into the right hemisphere, the left
hand points to a razor, or with “dirt remover” to soap, and with
“inserted in slot machines” to a twenty-five-cent piece.12
Moreover, the right hemisphere in these patients can respond
emotionally without the left talking hemisphere knowing what it
12 M. S. Gazzaniga and R. W. Sperry, “Language after section of the cerebral
commissures,” Brain, 1967, 90.131-148.
116
The Mind of Man
is all about. If among a series of neutral geometric figures being
flashed to the right and left visual fields at random, which means
respectively into the left and right hemispheres, and then a picture of a nude girl by surprise is flashed on the left side going into
the right hemisphere, the patient (really the patient's left hemisphere) says that it saw nothing or just a flash of light. But the
grinning, blushing, and giggling during the next minute contradicts what the speech hemisphere has just said. Asked what all
the grinning is about, the left or speech hemisphere replies that it
has no idea.13 These facial expressions and blushings, incidentally, are not confined to one side of the face, being mediated
through the deep interconnections of the brainstem. The expression of affect is not a cortical matter.
Similarly with other sensory modalities. Odors presented to
the right nostril and so to the right hemisphere (olfactory fibers
do not cross) in these patients cannot be named by the talking
hemisphere, though the latter can say very well whether the smell
is pleasant or unpleasant. The patient may even grunt, make
aversive reactions, or exclaim " P h e w ! " to a stench, but cannot
say verbally whether it is garlic, cheese, or decayed matter.14 The
same odors presented to the left nostril can be named and described perfectly well. What this means is that the emotion of
disgust gets across to the speaking hemisphere through the intact
limbic system and brainstem, while the more specific information
processed by the cortex does not.
Indeed, there is some indication that it is the right hemisphere
that commonly triggers the emotional reactions of displeasure
from the limbic system and brainstem. In test situations, where
the speechless right hemisphere is made to know the correct
answer, and then hears the left dominant hemisphere making
R. W. Sperry, "Hemisphere Deconnection."
W. Gordon and R. W. Sperry, "Olfaction following surgical disconnection
of the hemisphere in man," Proceedings of the Psychonomic Society, 1968.
13
14 H.
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
117
obvious verbal mistakes, the patient may frown, wince, or shake
his head. It is not simply a way of speaking to say that the right
hemisphere is annoyed at the erroneous vocal responses of the
other. And so perhaps the annoyance of Pallas Athene when she
grasped Achilles by his yellow hair and twisted him away from
murdering his king (Iliad, 1 .-197). Or the annoyance of Yahweh
with the iniquities of his people.
Of course there is a difference. Bicameral man had all his
commissures intact. But I shall suggest later that it is possible for
the brain to be so reorganized by environmental changes that the
inferences of my comparison here are not entirely foolish. At any
rate, the studies of these commissurotomy patients demonstrate
conclusively that the two hemispheres can function so as to seem
like two independent persons, which in the bicameral period were,
I suggest, the individual and his god.
4. That Hemispheric Differences in Cognitive Function Echo the
Differences of God and Man
If this brain model of the bicameral mind is correct, it would
predict decided differences in cognitive function between the two
hemispheres. Specifically, we would expect that these functions
necessary for the man-side would be in the left or dominant
hemisphere, and those functions necessary to the gods would be
more emphasized in the right hemisphere. Moreover, there is no
reason not to think that the residuals of these different functions
at least are present in the brain organization of contemporary
man.
The function of the gods was chiefly the guiding and planning
of action in novel situations. The gods size up problems and
organize action according to an ongoing pattern or purpose, resulting in intricate bicameral civilizations, fitting all the disparate
parts together, planting times, harvest times, the sorting out of
commodities, all the vast putting together of things in a grand
118
The Mind of Man
design, and the giving of the directions to the neurological man in
his verbal analytical sanctuary in the left hemisphere. We might
thus predict that one residual function of the right hemisphere
today would be an organizational one, that of sorting out the
experiences of a civilization and fitting them together into a
pattern that could 'tell' the individual what to do. Perusal of
various speeches of gods in the Iliad, the Old Testament, or other
ancient literatures is in agreement with this. Different events,
past and future, are sorted out, categorized, synthesized into a
new picture, often with that ultimate synthesis of metaphor. And
these functions should, therefore, characterize the right hemisphere.
Clinical observations are consistent with this hypothesis. From
the commissurotomized patients of a few pages past, we know
that the right hemisphere with its left hand is excellent at sorting
out and categorizing shapes, sizes, and textures. From braindamaged patients, we know that damage to the right hemisphere
interferes with spatial relations and with gestalt, synthetic
tasks.15 Mazes are problems in which various elements of a
spatial pattern must be organized in learning. Patients in whom
the right temporal lobe has been removed find learning the pathways of visual and tactile mazes almost impossible, while patients
with lesions of equal extent on the left temporal lobe have little
difficulty. 16
Another task involving the organization of parts into a spatial
pattern is Koh's Block Test, commonly used in many intelligence
tests. The subject is shown a simple geometric pattern, and
asked to duplicate it with blocks that have its elements painted on
them. Most of us can do it easily. But patients with brain lesions
15 H. Hecaen, "Clinical Symptomatology in Right and Left Hemispheric Lesions,"
in Inter hemispheric Relations and Cerebral Dominance, V. B. Mountcastle, ed.
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press, 1962).
16 Brenda Milner, "Visually guided maze learning in man: effects of bilateral,
frontal, and unilateral cerebral lesions," Neuropsychologia, 1965, 3: 317-338.
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
119
in the right hemisphere find this extremely difficult, so much so
that the test is used to diagnose right hemisphere damage. In the
commissurotomy patients referred to earlier, the right hand often
cannot succeed at all in putting the design together with the
blocks. The left hand, in a sense the hand of the gods, has no
problem whatever. In some of the commissurotomy patients, the
left hand had even to be held back by the observer as it tried to
help the right hand in its fumbling attempts at this simple task.17
The inference has thus been drawn from these and other studies
that the right hemisphere is more involved in synthetic and
spatial-constructive tasks while the left hemisphere is more
analytic and verbal. The right hemisphere, perhaps like the gods,
sees parts as having a meaning only within a context; it looks at
wholes. While the left or dominant hemisphere, like the man
side of the bicameral mind, looks at parts themselves.
These clinical results have been confirmed in normal people in
what promises to be the first of many future studies.18 E E G
electrodes were placed over the temporal and parietal lobes on
both sides of normal subjects who were then given various tests.
When asked to write various kinds of letters involving verbal and
analytic abilities, the E E G records show low-voltage fast waves
over the left hemisphere, denoting that the left hemisphere is
doing the work, while slow alpha waves (seen on both hemispheres in a resting subject with the eyes closed) are seen over
the right hemisphere, indicating that it is not doing the work.
When such subjects are given spatial synthetic tests, such as
Koh's Block Test as used in the clinical studies above, the reverse
is found. It is now the right hemisphere that is doing the work.
Further deductions can be made about what particular functions might be residual in the right hemisphere by considering
R. W. Sperry, Film presented at Princeton, February 1971.
David Galin and R. E. Ornstein, "Lateral specialization of cognitive mode: an
EEG study," Psychofhysiology, 1972, 9: 412-418.
17
18
120
These faces are mirror images of
each other. Stare at the nose of
each. Which face is happier?
The Mind of Man
what it is that the divine voices of the bicameral mind would have to do in particular situations. To sort out and synthesize experience
into directives to action, the gods would have
to make certain kinds of recognitions.
Throughout the speeches of gods in ancient
literature, such recognitions are common. I do
not mean recognitions of individuals in particular, but more generally of types of people, of
classifications, as well as of individuals. One
important judgment for a human being of any
century is the recognition of facial expression,
particularly in regard to friendly or unfriendly intent. If a bicameral man saw an
unrecognized man coming toward him, it
would be of considerable survival value for
the god-side of his mentality to decide if the
person was of friendly or unfriendly intent.
The adjoining figure is an experiment I designed about ten years ago out of such a supposition. The two faces are mirror images of
each other. I have so far asked almost a thousand people which face looks happier. Quite
consistently, about 80 percent of right-handed
people chose the bottom face with the smile
going up on their left. They were thus judging the face with their right hemispheres, assuming, of course, that they were glancing at
the center of the face. This result can be made
stronger by tachistoscopic presentation. With
the focal point in the center and flashed at one
tenth of a second, the bottom face always looks
happier to right-handed persons.
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
121
An alternative hypothesis, of course, is that this tendency to
judge facial expression by the left visual field is a carry-over of
reading from left to right. And in our cultures it certainly enhances the effect. But that the hemispheric explanation is at the
bottom of it is suggested by the results for left-handed people.
Fifty-five percent of left-handers chose the upper face as happier, suggesting that it was the left hemisphere making the judgment. And this cannot be understood on the reading-direction
hypothesis. Also, in people who are completely left-lateralized,
left-handed in every way, the likeliho6d of seeing the top face as
happier seems to be much higher.
Recently we have made a similar finding, using photographs of
an actor expressing sadness, happiness, disgust, and surprise.19
Our subjects, carefully screened for right-handedness, first
stared at the fixation point in a tachistoscope, then were presented with one photograph flashed for a few milliseconds in the
central position, and then with another either in the right or left
visual field for the same duration. The subjects were asked to
say whether the photographs were the same or different, and the
time taken to make this decision was recorded. Most of the
subjects were able to match facial expressions more correctly and
in less time when the face was presented on the left and hence to
the right hemisphere. In a control condition, scrambled pictures
of the same facial expressions (which were really nonsense patterns) also could be matched more quickly and correctly when
presented on the left, but not nearly as well as the facial expressions themselves.
Recent clinical evidence is in clear agreement. Failure to
recognize faces, not just facial expressions, is much more frequently associated with damage to the right hemisphere than to
the left. In clinical testing, the patient is asked to match the
frontal view of a face with three-quarter views of the same face
19 These experiments were done by Jack Shannon. We are both grateful to Stevan
Harnad for his criticism and suggestions.
122
The Mind of Man
under different lighting conditions. Patients with lesions in the
right hemisphere find this extremely difficult in comparison with
normal subjects or patients who have lesions in the left hemisphere.20 Recognition of both faces and facial expression is
therefore primarily a right hemisphere function.
And to tell friend from non-friend in novel situations was one
of the functions of a god.
6. A New Look at the Brain
How, it may be argued, can such a system as this, a brain structured into what I have called a bicameral mind, this substrate
of human civilization for thousands of years, involving such loci
as we have mentioned in the model, how can its function change
over so short a period of time, such that the admonitory voices
are heard no more and that we have this new organization called
consciousness? While the amount of genocide going on in the
world during these changes was enough to allow some natural
selection and evolution, I in no way wish to rest the case upon
that. Such natural selection as did occur during these periods of
the development of consciousness certainly assisted in its perpetuation, but could not be said to have evolved consciousness out
of the bicameral mind in the sense that a seaPs flipper is evolved
out of an ancestral paw.
A true understanding of the situation requires a different view
of the brain from that which was usual a few decades ago. Its
emphasis is the brain's plasticity, its redundant representation of
psychological capacities within a specialized center or region, the
multiple control of psychological capacities by several centers
either paired bilaterally or as what Hughlings Jackson recognized
as "representations" of a function lying at successively higher
20 H. Hecaen and R. Angelergues, "Agnosia for Faces (Prosopagnosia)," Archives
of Neurology 7: 92-100, 1962; A. L. Benton and M. W. Allen, "Impairment in Facial Recognition in Patients with Cerebral Disease," Cortex, 1968, 4: 345-358.
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
123
and phylogenetically younger levels of the nervous system.21
The organization of the mammalian brain in this fashion allows
for those experimental phenomena brought together under the
rubric of "recovery of function." Its emphasis gives a view of the
brain much more plastic than usual, with a dramatic surplus of
neurons such that, for example, 98 percent of the optic tracts can
be cut in the cat, and brightness and pattern discrimination will
remain.22 The brain teems with redundant centers, each of
which may exert direct influence on a final common pathway, or
modulate the operation of others, or both, their arrangements
able to assume many forms and degrees of coupling between
constituent centers.
All this redundant representation in multiple control gives us
the notion of a much more changeable kind of brain than the
earlier neurologists described. A particular behavior or group of
behaviors engage a host of similar neurons in a given center and
may call into play several different centers arranged in various
patterns of inhibition and facilitation, depending upon their evolutionary status. And the tightness of the coupling between centers varies tremendously from one function to another.23 In
other words, the amount of changeableness that the locus of
cortical functions can undergo is different among different functions, but that such changeableness is a pronounced feature of
the higher mammalian brain is becoming more and more apparent. The biological purpose or selective advantage of such
redundant representation and multiple control and its resulting
plasticity is twofold: it protects the organism against the effects
of brain damage, and, perhaps more important, it provides an
21 Hughlings Jackson, "Evolution and Dissolution of the Nervous System," in
Selected Writings of John Hughlings Jackson, J. Taylor, ed. (London: Staples Press,
1958), 2: 45-75.
22 R. Galambos, T. T. Norton, and G. P. Fromer, "Optic tract lesions sparing pattern vision in cats," Experimental Neurology, 1967, 18: 18-25.
23 I am paraphrasing the superb recent review of this problem by Burton Rosner,
"Brain functions," Annual Review of Psychology, 1970, 21: 555-594.
124
The Mind of Man
organism of far greater adaptability to the constantly changing
environmental challenges. I am thinking here of such challenges
as characterize the successive glaciations of primate man's existence, and, of course, that even greater challenge of the breakdown of the bicameral mind to which man adapted with
consciousness.
But this does not mean just that adult man's behavior is less
rigid than his forebear's, though this is of course true. More
important, it provides an organism where the early developmental history of the individual can make a great difference in
how the brain is organized. Some years ago, an idea such as this
would have seemed very far-fetched indeed. But the increasing
tide of research has eroded any rigid concept of the brain, and
has emphasized the remarkable degree to which the brain can
compensate for any structures missing either by injury or by
congenital malformation. Many studies show that brain injury to
animals in infancy may make little difference in adult behavior,
while similar injury to adults may have profound changes. We
have already noted that early injury to the left hemisphere usually results in the switch of the entire speech mechanism to the
right hemisphere.
One of the most astonishing of the cases that demonstrate this
resiliency of the brain is that of a thirty-five-year-old man who
died of an abdominal malignancy. At autopsy, it was revealed
that he had a congenital absence of the hippocampal fimbria, the
fornix, septum pellucidum, and the mass intermedia thalami,
with an abnormally small hippocampus and abnormally small
hippocampal and dentate gyri. In spite of these remarkable abnormalities, the patient had always displayed an "easygoing" personality and had even led his class in school!24
Thus, the growing nervous system compensates for genetic or
environmental damage by following other but less preferred de24 P. W. Nathan and M. C. Smith, "Normal mentality associated with a maldeveloped Rhinencephalon," Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery and Psychiatry,
1950, 13: 191—197, as cited in Rosner.
THE
DOUBLE
BRAIN
125
velopmental paths which utilize intact tissue. In adults, with
development completed, this is no longer possible. The normally
preferred modes of neural organization have already been
achieved. It is only in early development that such reorganization of the systems of multiple control can take place. And this is
definitely true of the relationship between the hemispheres so
central to this discussion.25
With this as a background, I do not see the difficulty in considering that, in the bicameral epochs, what corresponds to Wernicke's area on the right nondominant hemisphere had its strict
bicameral function, whereas after a thousand years of psychological reorganization in which such bicamerality was discouraged when it appeared in early development, such areas function
in a different way. And similarly, it would be wrong to think that
whatever the neurology of consciousness now may be, it is set
for all time. The cases we have discussed indicate otherwise,
that the function of brain tissue is not inevitable, and that perhaps different organizations, given different developmental programs, may be possible.
2 5 R. E. Saul and R. W. Sperry, "Absence of commissurotomy symptoms with
agenesis of the corpus callosum," Neurology, 1968, 18: 307; D. L. Reeves and
C. B. Carville, "Complete agenesis of corpus callosum: report of four cases," Bulletin
of Los Angeles Neurological Society, 1938, 3 : 169—181.
CHAPTER 6
T h e Origin of Civilization
B
U T W H E R E F O R E should there be such a thing as the bicameral
mind? And why are there gods? What can be the origin of
things divine? And if the organization of the brain in bicameral
times was as I have suggested in the previous chapter, what could
the selective pressures in human evolution have been to bring
about so mighty a result?
The speculative thesis which I shall try to explain in this
chapter — and it is very speculative — is simply an obvious
corollary from what has gone before. The bicameral mind is a
form of social control and it is that form of social control which
allowed mankind to move from small hunter-gatherer groups to
large agricultural communities. The bicameral mind with its
controlling gods was evolved as a final stage of the evolution of
language. And in this development lies the origin of civilization.
Let us begin by looking at what we mean by social control.
THE
EVOLUTION
OF
GROUPS
Mammals in general show a wide variety of social groupings, all
the way from the solitariness of certain predatory animals to the
very close social cohesiveness of others. The latter animals are
the more preyed upon, and a social group is itself a genetic
adaptation for protection against predators. The structure of
THE
ORIGIN
OF
CIVILIZATION
127
herds in ungulates is relatively simple, utilizing precise genetically
given anatomical and behavioral signals that are all evolved for
group protection. Primates have a similar vulnerability, and for
the same reason are evolved to live in close association with
others. In dense protective forests, the social group may be as
small as six, as in gibbons, while on the more exposed terrains,
the group may be up to eighty, as in the Cape baboons.1 In exceptional ecosystems, the group size may be even larger.
It is the group then that evolves. When dominant individuals
give a warning cry or run, others of the group flee without
looking for the source of danger. It is thus the experience of one
individual and his dominance that is an advantage to the whole
group. Individuals do not generally respond even to basic physiological needs except within the whole pattern of the group's
activity. A thirsty baboon, for example, does not leave the group
and go seeking water; it is the whole group that moves or none.
Thirst is satisfied only within the patterned activity of the group.
And so it is with other needs and situations.
The important thing for us here is that this social structure
depends upon the communication between the individuals. Primates have therefore evolved a tremendous variety of complex
signals: tactile communication ranging from mounting and
grooming to various kinds of embracing, nuzzling, and fingering;
sounds ranging from assorted grunts, barks, screeching, and yakking, all grading into each other; nonvocal signals such as grinding teeth or beating branches;2 visual signals in a variety of facial
expressions, the threatening, direct eye-to-eye gaze, eyelid fluttering in baboons in which the brows are raised and the lids are
lowered to expose their pale color against the darker background
1 Irven DeVore and K, R. L. Hall, "Baboon E c o l o g y , " Ch. 2 in Primate Behavior,
I. DeVore, ed. (New Y o r k : Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1 9 6 5 ) , pp. 20—52.
2 K. R. L. Hall, " T h e sexual, agonistic, and derived social behaviour patterns of
the wild chacma baboon, Pafio ursinus" Proceedings of the Zoological Society,
London, 1962, 139: 283—327.
128
The Mind of Man
of the face, together with a yawn that bares the teeth aggressively; various postural signals such as lunging, head jerking,
feinting with the hands, and all these in various constellations.3
This huge redundant complexity of signaling is essentially devoted to the requisites of the group, its organization into patterns
of dominance and subordination, the maintenance of peace, reproduction, and care for the young. Except for signifying potential group danger, primate signals rarely apply to events outside
the group, such as the presence of food or water.4 They are
totally within group affairs and are not evolved to give environmental information in the way human languages are.
Now this is what we start with. Within a specific ecology, for
most species, it is this communication system that limits the size
of the group. Baboons are able to achieve groups as high as
eighty or more because they have a strict geographical structure
as they move about on the open plains, with dominant hierarchies being maintained within each circle of the group. But in
general the usual primate group does not exceed thirty or forty, a
limit determined by the communication necessary for the dominance hierarchy to work.
In gorillas, for example, the dominant male, usually the largest
silver-backed male, together with all the females and young,
occupies the central core of each group of about twenty, the other
males tending to be peripheral. The diameter of a group at any
given moment rarely exceeds 200 feet, as every animal remains
attentive to the movements of others in the dense forest environment.5 The group moves when the dominant male stands motion3 Peter Marler, "Communication in monkeys and apes," Ch. 16, in Primate Behavior.
4 As is known in some birds. See M. Konishi, "The role of auditory feedback in
the vocal behavior of the domestic fowl," Zeitschrift fur Tierpsychologie, 1963, 20:
349-367.
5 G. Schaller, The Mountain Gorilla: Ecology and Behavior (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1963).
THE
ORIGIN
OF
CIVILIZATION
129
less with his legs spread and faces a certain direction. The other
members of the group then crowd around him, and the troop
moves off on its leisurely day’s journey of about a third of a mile.
The important thing here is that the complex channels of communication are open between the top of the dominance hierarchy
and all the rest.
There is no reason to think that early man from the beginning
of the genus Homo two million years ago lived any differently.
Such archaeological evidence as has been obtained indicates the
size of a group to be about thirty.6 This number, I suggest, was
limited by the problem of social control and the degree of openness of the communication channels between individuals.7 And
it is the problem of this limitation of group size which the gods
may have come into evolutionary history to solve.
But first we must consider the evolution of language as the
necessary condition for there to be gods at all.
THE
EVOLUTION
OF
LANGUAGE
When Did Language Evolve?
It is commonly thought that language is such an inherent part
of the human constitution that it must go back somehow through
the tribal ancestry of man to the very origin of the genus Homo,
that is, for almost two million years. Most contemporary linguists of my acquaintance would like to persuade me that this is
true. But with this view, I wish to totally and emphatically
*6 Glynn L. Isaac, “Traces of Pleistocene Hunters: An East African Example,” in
Man the Hunter, Richard B. Lee and Irven DeVore, eds. (Chicago: Aldine Press,
1968).
7 This group size is approximately the same for modern tribal hunters when
they are nomadic. But the case is not the same. See Joseph B. Birdsell, “On population structure in generalized hunting and collecting populations,” Evolution, 1958,
12: 189-205.
130
The Mind of Man
disagree. If early man, through these two million years, had even
a primordial speech, why is there so little evidence of even simple
culture or technology? For there is precious little archaeologically up to 40,000 B.C., other than the crudest of stone tools.
Sometimes the reaction to a denial that early man had speech
is, how then did man function or communicate? The answer is
very simple: just like all other primates, with an abundance of
visual and vocal signals which were very far removed from the
syntactical language that we practice today. And when I even
carry this speechlessness down through the Pleistocene Age,
when man developed various kinds of primitive pebble choppers
and hand axes, again my linguist friends lament my arrogant
ignorance and swear oaths that in order to transmit even such
rudimentary skills from one generation to another, there had to
be language. But consider that it is almost impossible to describe
chipping flints into choppers in language. This art was transmitted solely by imitation, exactly the same way in which chimpanzees transmit the trick of inserting straws into ant hills to get
ants. It is the same problem as the transmission of bicycle riding;
does language assist at all?
Because language must make dramatic changes in man's attention to things and persons, because it allows a transfer of
information of enormous scope, it must have developed over a
period that shows archaeologically that such changes occurred.
Such a one is the late Pleistocene, roughly from 70,000 B.C. to
8000 B.C. This period was characterized climactically by wide
variations in temperature, corresponding to the advance and retreat of glacial conditions, and biologically by huge migrations of
animals and man caused by these changes in weather. The
hominid population exploded out of the African heartland into
the Eurasian subarctic and then into the Americas and Australia.
The population around the Mediterranean reached a new high
and took the lead in cultural innovation, transferring man's cultural and biological focus from the tropics to the middle lati-
THE
ORIGIN
OF
CIVILIZATION
131
tudes.8 His fires, caves, and furs created for man a kind of
transportable microclimate that allowed these migrations to take
place.
We are used to referring to these people as late Neanderthalers. At one time they were thought to be a separate species of
man supplanted by Cro-Magnon man around 35,000 B.C. But the
more recent view is that they were part of the general human
line, which had great variation, a variation that allowed for an
increasing pace of evolution, as man, taking his artificial climate
with him, spread into these new ecological niches. More work
needs to be done to establish the true patterns of settlement, but
the most recent emphasis seems to be on its variation, some
groups continually moving, others making seasonal migrations,
and others staying at a site all the year round.9
I am emphasizing the climate changes during this last glacial
age because I believe these changes were the basis of the selective pressures behind the development of language through several stages.
Calls, Modifiers, and Commands
The first stage and the sine qua non of language is the development out of incidental calls of intentional calls, or those which
tend to be repeated unless turned off by a change in behavior of
the recipient. Previously in the evolution of primates, it was only
postural or visual signals such as threat postures which were
intentional. Their evolution into auditory signals was made necessary by the migration of man into northern climates, where
there was less light both in the environment and in the dark
caves where man made his abode, and where visual signals could
8 See J. D. Clark, “Human ecology during the Pleistocene and later times in
Africa south of the Sahara,” Current Anthropology, 1960, 1: 307-324.
9 See Karl W. Butzer, Environment and Archaeology: An Introduction to Pleistocene Geography (Chicago: Aldine Press, 1964), p. 378.
132
The Mind of Man
not be seen as readily as on the bright African savannahs. This
evolution may have begun as early as the Third Glaciation Period
or possibly even before. But it is only as we are approaching the
increasing cold and darkness of the Fourth Glaciation in northern
climates that the presence of such vocal intentional signals gave a
pronounced selective advantage to those who possessed them.
I am here summarizing a theory of language evolution which I
have developed more fully and with more caution elsewhere.10
It is not intended as a definitive statement of what occurred in
evolution so much as a rough working hypothesis to approach it.
Moreover, the stages of language development that I shall describe are not meant to be necessarily discrete. Nor are they
always in the same order in different localities. The central
assertion of this view, I repeat, is that each new stage of words
literally created new perceptions and attentions, and such new
perceptions and attentions resulted in important cultural changes
which are reflected in the archaeological record.
The first real elements of speech were the final sounds of
intentional calls differentiating on the basis of intensity. For
example, a danger call for immediately present danger would be
exclaimed with more intensity, changing the ending phoneme.
An imminent tiger might result in 'wahee!5 while a distant tiger
might result in a cry of less intensity and so develop a different
ending such as 'wahoo'. It is these endings, then, that become the
first modifiers meaning 'near' and 'far'. And the next step was
when these endings, 'hee' and 'hoo', could be separated from the
particular call that generated them and attached to some other
call with the same indication.
The crucial thing here is that the differentiation of vocal qualifiers had to precede the invention of the nouns which they modified, rather than the reverse. And what is more, this stage of
speech had to remain for a long period until such modifiers
10 Julian Jaynes, "The evolution of language in the Late Pleistocene," Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences, Vol. 280, 1976, in press.
THE
ORIGIN
OF
CIVILIZATION
133
became stable. This slow development was also necessary so that
the basic repertoire of the call system was kept intact to perform
its intentional functions. This age of modifiers perhaps lasted up
to 40,000 B.C., where we find archaeologically retouched hand
axes and points.
The next stage might have been an age of commands, when
modifiers, separated from the calls they modify, now can modify
men's actions themselves. Particularly as men relied more and
more on hunting in the chilled climate, the selective pressure for
such a group of hunters controlled by vocal commands must have
been immense. And we may imagine that the invention of a
modifier meaning 'sharper' as an instructed command could
markedly advance the making of tools from flint and bone, resulting in an explosion of new types of tools from 40,000 B.C. up to
25,000 B.C.
Nouns
Once a tribe has a repertoire of modifiers and commands, the
necessity of keeping the integrity of the old primitive call system
can be relaxed for the first time, so as to indicate the referents of
the modifiers or commands. If 'wahee! 5 once meant an imminent
danger, with more intensity differentiation, we might have 'wak
ee!' for an approaching tiger, or "wab ee!' for an approaching
bear. These would be the first sentences with a noun subject and
a predicative modifier, and they may have occurred somewhere
between 25,000 and 15,000 B.C.
These are not arbitrary speculations. The succession from
modifiers to commands and, only when these become stable, to
nouns is no arbitrary succession. Nor is the dating entirely arbitrary. Just as the age of modifiers coincides with the making
of much superior tools, so the age of nouns for animals coincides
with the beginning of drawing animals on the walls of caves or
on horn implements.
134
The Mind of Man
The next stage is the development of thing nouns, really a
carry-over from the preceding. And just as life nouns began
animal drawings, so nouns for things beget new things. This
period corresponds, I suggest, to the invention of pottery, pendants, ornaments, and barbed harpoons and spearheads, the last
two tremendously important in spreading the human species into
more difficult climates. From fossil evidence we know factually
that the brain, particularly the frontal lobe in front of the central
sulcus, was increasing with a rapidity that still astonishes the
modern evolutionist. And by this time, perhaps what corresponds
to the Magdalenian culture, the language areas of the brain as we
know them had developed.
The Origin of Auditory Hallucinations
At this point, let us consider another problem in the origin of
gods, the origin of auditory hallucinations. That there is a problem here comes from the very fact of their undoubted existence
in the contemporary world, and their inferred existence in the
bicameral period. The most plausible hypothesis is that verbal
hallucinations were a side effect of language comprehension which
evolved by natural selection as a method of behavioral control.
Let us consider a man commanded by himself or his chief to
set up a fish weir far upstream from a campsite. If he is not
conscious, and cannot therefore narratize the situation and so
hold his analog 'I' in a spatialized time with its consequences fully
imagined, how does he do it? It is only language, I think, that
can keep him at this time-consuming all-afternoon work. A Middle Pleistocene man would forget what he was doing. But lingual
man would have language to remind him, either repeated by
himself, which would require a type of volition which I do not
think he was then capable of, or, as seems more likely, by a
repeated 'internal' verbal hallucination telling him what to do.
To someone who has not fully understood the previous chapters, this type of suggestion will sound extremely strange and far-
THE
ORIGIN
OF
CIVILIZATION
135
fetched. But if one is facing directly and conscientiously the
problem of tracing out the development of human mentality,
such suggestions are necessary and important, even though we
cannot at the present time think how we can substantiate them.
Behavior more closely based on aptic structures (or, in an older
terminology, more 'instinctive') needs no temporal priming. But
learned activities with no consummatory closure do need to be
maintained by something outside of themselves. This is what
verbal hallucinations would supply.
Similarly, in fashioning a tool, the hallucinated verbal command of "sharper" enables nonconscious early man to keep at his
task alone. Or an hallucinated term meaning "finer" for an individual grinding seeds on a stone quern into flour. It was indeed
at this point in human history that I believe articulate speech,
under the selective pressures of enduring tasks, began to become
unilateral in the brain, to leave the other side free for these
hallucinated voices that could maintain such behavior.
The Age of Names
This has been an all too brief sketch of what must have been
involved in the evolution of language. But before there could be
gods, one further step had to be taken, the invention of that most
important social phenomenon — names.
It is somehow startling to realize that names were a particular
invention that must have come into human development at a
particular time. When? What changes might this make in human culture? It is, I suggest, as late as the Mesolithic era, about
10,000 B.C. to 8000 B.C. when names first occurred. This is the
period of man's adaptation to the warmer postglacial environment. The vast sheet of ice has retreated to the latitude of
Copenhagen, and man keys in to specific environmental situations, to grassland hunting, to life in the forest, to shellfish collecting, or to the exploitation of marine resources combined with
terrestrial hunting. Such living is characterized by a much
136
The Mind of Man
greater stability of population, rather than the necessary mobility
of the hunting groups which preceded them with their large
mortality. With these more fixed populations, with more fixed
relationships, longer life-spans, and probably larger numbers in
the group which had to be distinguished, it is not difficult to see
both the need and the likelihood of a carry-over of nouns into
names for individual persons.
Now, once a tribe member has a proper name, he can in a
sense be recreated in his absence. ' H e ' can be thought about,
using 'thought5 here in a special nonconscious sense of fitting into
language structures. While there had been earlier graves of a
sort, occasionally somewhat elaborate, this is the first age in
which we find ceremonial graves as a common practice. If you
think of someone close to you who has died, and then suppose
that he or she had no name, in what would your grief consist?
How long could it last? Previously, man, like other primates,
had probably left his dead where they fell, or else hidden them
from view with stones, or in some instances roasted and eaten
them. 11 But just as a noun for an animal makes that relationship a much more intense one, so a name for a person. And
when the person dies, the name still goes on, and hence the
relationship, almost as in life, and hence burial practices and
mourning. The Mesolithic midden-dwellers of Morbihan, for example, buried their dead in skin cloaks fastened by bone pins and
sometimes crowned them with stag antlers and protected them
with stone slabs.12 Other graves from the period show burials
with little crowns, or various ornaments, or possibly flowers in
carefully excavated places, all, I suggest, the result of the invention of names.
But a further change occurs with names. Up to this time auditory hallucinations had probably been casually anonymous and
11 As at Choukoutien during the Middle Pleistocene and later in the Croatian cave
of Krapina. See Grahame Clark and Stewart Piggott, Prehistoric Societies (London: Hutchinson, 1965), p. 61.
12 Grahame Clark, The Stone Age Hunters (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967),
p. 105.
THE
ORIGIN
OF
CIVILIZATION
137
not in any sense a significant social interaction. But once a specific
hallucination is recognized with a name, as a voice originating
from a particular person, a significantly different thing is occurring. The hallucination is now a social interaction with a much
greater role in individual behavior. And a further problem here is
just how hallucinated voices were recognized, as whom, and if
there were many, how sorted out. Some light on these questions
comes from the autobiographical writings of schizophrenic patients. But not enough to pursue the matter here. We are greatly
in need of specific research in this area of schizophrenic experience to help us in understanding Mesolithic man.
The Advent of Agriculture
We are now at the threshold of the bicameral period, for the
mechanism of social control which can organize large populations of men into a city is at hand. Everyone agrees that the
change from a hunting and gathering economy to a food-producing economy by the domestication of plants and animals is the
gigantic step that made civilization possible. But there is wide
disagreement as to its causes and the means by which it came
about.
The traditional theory emphasizes the fact that when the
glaciers covered most of Europe during the Late Pleistocene, the
whole area from the Atlantic coast across North Africa and the
Near East to the Zagros Mountains in Iran enjoyed such an
abundant rainfall that it was indeed a vast procreant Eden, luxuriant with plant life ample to support a wide range of fauna,
including Paleolithic man. But the recession of the polar ice cap
moved these Atlantic rain-winds northward, and the entire Near
East became increasingly arid. The wild food-plants and the
game on which man had preyed were no longer sufficient to allow
him to live by simple food-gathering, and the result was that
many tribes emigrated out of the area into Europe, while those
who remained — in the words of Pumpelly, who originated this
138
The Mind of Man
hypothesis from his own excavations — "concentrating on the
oases and forced to conquer new means of support, began to
utilize the native plants; and from among these he learned to use
seeds of different grasses growing on the dry land and in marshes
at the mouths of larger streams on the desert." 13 And this view
has been followed by a series of more recent authors, including
Childe, 14 as well as Toynbee, 15 who called this supposed desiccation of the Near East environment the "physical challenge" to
which agricultural civilization was the response.
Recent evidence16 shows that there was no such extensive
desiccation, and that agriculture was not economically 'forced* on
anyone. I have been placing an overwhelming importance on
language in the development of human culture in Mesolithic
times and I would do so here as well. As we saw in Chapter 3,
language allows the metaphors of things to increase perception
and attention, and so to give new names to things of new importance. It is, I think, this added linguistic mentality, surrounded
as it was in the Near East by a fortuitous grouping of suitable
domesticates, wild wheats and wild barley, whose native distribution overlaps with the much broader habitats of the herd animals
of southwestern Asia, goats, sheep, cattle, and wild pigs, that
resulted in agriculture.
THE
FIRST
GOD
Let us look more directly for a moment at the best defined and
most fully studied Mesolithic culture, the Natufian, named after
the Wadi en-Natuf in Israel, where the first of the sites was
13 R. Pumpelly, Explorations in Turkestan: Expedition of 1904: Prehistoric
Civilizations of Anau (Washington: Carnegie Institution, 1908), pp. 65-66.
14 V. G. Childe, The Most Ancient East, 4th ed. (London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1954).
15 A. J. Toynbee, A Study of History (London: Oxford University Press, 1962),
Vol. 1, pp. 304—305.
16 Butzer, p. 416.
THE
ORIGIN
OF
CIVILIZATION
139
found. In 10,000 B.C., like their Paleolithic predecessors, the
Natufians were hunters, about five feet tall, often living in the
mouths of caves, were skillful in working bone and antler and in
chipping retouched blades and burins out of flint, drew animals
almost as well as the artists of the cave drawings of Lascaux, and
wore perforated shells or animal teeth as ornaments.
By 9000 B.C., they are burying their dead in ceremonial graves
and adopting a more settled life. The latter is indicated by the
first signs of structural building, such as the paving and walling
of platforms with much plaster, and cemeteries sometimes large
enough for eighty-seven burials, a size unknown in any previous
age. It is, as I have suggested, the age of names, with all that it
implies.
It is the open-air Natufian settlement at Eynan which shows
this change most dramatically.17 Discovered in 1959, this heavily investigated site is about a dozen miles north of the Sea of
Galilee on a natural terrace overlooking the swamps and pools of
Lake Huleh. Three successive permanent towns dating from
about 9000 B.C. have been carefully excavated. Each town comprised about fifty round stone houses with reed roofs, with diameters up to 23 feet. The houses were arranged around an open
central area where many bell-shaped pits had been dug and
plastered for the storage of food. Sometimes these pits were
reused for burials.
Now here is a very significant change in human affairs. Instead of a nomadic tribe of about twenty hunters living in the
mouths of caves, we have a town with a population of at least
200 persons. It was the advent of agriculture, as attested by the
abundance of sickle blades, pounders and pestles, querns and
mortars, recessed in the floor of each house, for the reaping and
preparation of cereals and legumes, that made such permanence
and population possible. Agriculture at this time was exceedingly
17 See J. Perrot, "Excavations at Eynan, 1959 season," Israel Exploration Journal
}
1961, 10: ij James Mellaart, Earliest Civilizations of the Near East (New York:
McGraw-Hill, 1965), Ch. 2; Clark and Piggott, p. 15 off.
140
The Mind of Man
primitive and only a supplement to the wide variety of animal
fauna — wild goats, gazelles, boars, fox, hare, rodents, birds,
fish, tortoises, crustaceans, mussels, and snails — which, as carbondated remains show, were the significant part of the diet.
The Hallucinogenic King
A town! Of course it is not impossible that one chief could
dominate a few hundred people. But it would be a consuming
task if such domination had to be through face-to-face encounters
repeated every so often with each individual, as occurs in those
primate groups that maintain strict hierarchies.
I beg you to recall, as we try to picture the social life of Eynan,
that these Natufians were not conscious. They could not narratize and had no analog selves to 'see' themselves in relation to
others. They were what we could call signal-bound, that is, responding each minute to cues in a stimulus-response manner,
and controlled by those cues.
And what were the cues for a social organization this large?
What signals were the social control over its two or three hundred inhabitants?
I have suggested that auditory hallucinations may have
evolved as a side effect of language and operated to keep individuals persisting at the longer tasks of tribal life. Such hallucinations began in the individual's hearing a command from himself
or from his chief. There is thus a very simple continuity between
such a condition and the more complex auditory hallucinations
which I suggest were the cues of social control in Eynan and
which originated in the commands and speech of the king.
Now we must not make the error here of supposing that these
auditory hallucinations were like tape recordings of what the king
had commanded. Perhaps they began as such. But after a time
there is no reason not to suppose that such voices could 'think'
and solve problems, albeit, of course, unconsciously. The 'voices'
THE
ORIGIN
OF
CIVILIZATION
141
heard by contemporary schizophrenics ‘think’ as much and often
more than they do. And thus the ‘voices’ which I am supposing
were heard by the Natufians could with time improvise and ‘say’
things that the king himself had never said. Always, however,
we may suppose that all such novel hallucinations were strictly
tied in consistency to the person of the king himself. This is not
different from ourselves when we inherently know what a friend
is likely to say. Thus each worker, gathering shellfish or trapping
small game or in a quarrel with a rival or planting seed where the
wild grain had previously been harvested, had within him the
voice of his king to assist the continuity and utility to the group of
his labors.
The God-King
We have decided that the occasion of an hallucination was
stress, as it is in our contemporaries. And if our reasonings have
been correct, we may be sure that the stress caused by a person’s
death was far more than sufficient to trigger his hallucinated
voice. Perhaps this is why, in so many early cultures, the heads
of the dead were often severed from the body, or why the legs of
the dead were broken or tied up, why food is so often in the
graves, or why there is evidence so often of a double burial of the
same corpse, the second being in a common grave after the voices
have stopped.
If this were so for an ordinary individual, how much more so
for a king whose voice even while living ruled by hallucination.
We might therefore expect a very special accordance given to the
house of this unmoving man whose voice is still the cohesion of
the entire group.
At Eynan, still dating about 9000 B.C., the king’s tomb — the
first such ever found (so far) — is a quite remarkable affair.
The tomb itself, like all the houses, was circular, about 16 feet in
diameter. Inside, two complete skeletons lay in the center ex-
142
The Mind of Man
tended on their backs, with legs detached after death and bent
out of position. One wore a headdress of dentalia shells and was
presumed to have been the king's wife. The other, an adult male,
presumably the king, was partly covered with stones and partly
propped up on stones, his upright head cradled in more stones,
facing the snowy peaks of Mount Hermon, thirty miles away.
At some later time, soon after or years later, we do not know,
the entire tomb was surrounded by a red-ochered wall or parapet. Then, without disturbing its two motionless inhabitants,
large flat stones were paved over the top, roofing them in. Then,
on the roof a hearth was built. Another low circular wall of
stones was built still later around the roof-hearth, with more
paving stones on top of that, and three large stones surrounded
by smaller ones set in the center.
I am suggesting that the dead king, thus propped up on his
pillow of stones, was in the hallucinations of his people still
giving forth his commands, and that the red-painted parapet and
T h e first god: the dead king of
Eynan propped up on a pillow of
stones in about 9000 B.C., as discovered by excavations in 1 9 5 9 .
THE
ORIGIN
OF
CIVILIZATION
143
its top tier of a hearth were a response to the decomposition of
the body, and that, for a time at least, the very place, even the
smoke from its holy fire, rising into visibility from furlongs
around, was, like the gray mists of the Aegean for Achilles, a
source of hallucinations and of the commands that controlled
the Mesolithic world of Eynan.
This was a paradigm of what was to happen in the next eight
millennia. The king dead is a living god. The king's tomb is the
god's house, the beginning of the elaborate god-house or temples
which we shall look at in the next chapter. Even the two-tiered
formation of its structure is prescient of the multitiered ziggurats,
of the temples built on temples, as at Eridu, or the gigantic
pyramids by the Nile that time in its majesty will in several
thousand years unfold.
We should not leave Eynan without at least mentioning the
difficult problem of succession. Of course, we have next to nothing to go on in Eynan. But the fact that the royal tomb contained
previous burials that had been pushed aside for the dead king and
his wife suggests that its former occupants may have been earlier kings. And the further fact that beside the hearth on the
second tier above the propped-up king was still another skull
suggests that it may have belonged to the first king's successor,
and that gradually the hallucinated voice of the old king became
fused with that of the new. The Osiris myth that was the power
behind the majestic dynasties of Egypt had perhaps begun.
The king's tomb as the god's house continues through the
millennia as a feature of many civilizations, particularly in Egypt.
But, more often, the king's-tomb part of the designation withers
away. This occurs as soon as a successor to a king continues to
hear the hallucinated voice of his predecessor during his reign, and
designates himself as the dead king's priest or servant, a pattern
that is followed throughout Mesopotamia. In place of the tomb is
simply a temple. And in place of the corpse is a statue, enjoying
even more service and reverence, since it does not decompose.
144
The Mind of Man
We shall be discussing these idols, or replacements for the
corpses of kings, more fully in the next two chapters. They are
important. Like the queen in a termite nest or a beehive, the
idols of a bicameral world are the carefully tended centers of
social control, with auditory hallucinations instead of pheromones.
The Success of Civilization
Here then is the beginning of civilization. Rather abruptly,
archaeological evidence for agriculture such as the sickle blades
and pounding and milling stones of Eynan appear more or less
simultaneously in several other sites in the Levant and Iraq
around 9000 B.C., suggesting a very early diffusion of agriculture
in the Near Eastern highlands. At first, this is as it was at
Eynan, a stage in which incipient agriculture and, later, animal
domestication were going on within a dominant food-collecting
economy.18
But by 7000 B.C., agriculture has become the primary subsistence of farming settlements found in assorted sites in the
Levant, the Zagros area, and southwestern Anatolia. The crops
consisted of einkorn, emmer, and barley, and the domesticated
animals were sheep, goats, and sometimes pigs. By 6000 B.C.,
farming communities spread over much of the Near East. And
by 5000 B.C., the agricultural colonization of the alluvial valleys
of the Tigris-Euphrates and Nile was rapidly spreading, swelling
populations into an intensive cultural landscape.19 Cities of
10,000 inhabitants, as at Merinde on the western edge of the Nile
delta, were not uncommon.20 The great dynasties of Ur and of
Egypt begin their mighty impact on history. The date 5000 B.C.,
18 See R. J. Braidwood, "Levels in pre-history: A model for the consideration of
the evidence," in Evolution After Darwin, S. Tax, ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, i960), Vol. 2, pp. 143-15 1.
19 Butzer, p. 464.
20 See K. W. Butzer, "Archaeology and geology in ancient Egypt," Science, 1960,
132: 1617—1624.
THE
ORIGIN
OF
CIVILIZATION
145
or perhaps five hundred years earlier, is also the beginning of
what is known to geologists as the Holocene Thermal Maximum,
lasting to approximately 3000 B.C., in which the world's climate,
particularly as revealed by pollen studies, was considerably
warmer and moister than today, allowing even further agricultural dispersal into Europe and northern Africa, as well as more
productive agriculture in the Near East. And in this immensely
complex civilizing of mankind, the evidence, I think, suggests
that the modus operandi of it all was the bicameral mind.
It is to that evidence that we now turn.
BOOK TWO
The Witness of History
CHAPTER 1
Gods, Graves, and Idols
C
is the art of living in towns of such size that
everyone does not know everyone else. Not a very inspiring
definition, perhaps, but a true one. We have hypothesized that it
is the social organization provided by the bicameral mind that
made this possible. In this and the ensuing chapter, I am attempting to integrate without excessive particularization the worldwide
evidence that such a mentality did in fact exist wherever and
whenever civilization first began.
IVILIZATION
While the matter is in much current debate, the view I am
adopting is that civilization began independently in various sites in
the Near East, as described in the previous chapter, then spread
along the valleys of the Tigris and Euphrates rivers, into Anatolia
and the valley of the Nile; then into Cyprus, Thessaly, and Crete;
and then somewhat later by diffusion into the Indus River valley
and beyond, and into the Ukraine and Central Asia; then, partly
by diffusion and partly spontaneously, along the Yangtze; then
independently in Mesoamerica; and again, partly by diffusion and
partly independently, in the Andean highlands. In each of these
areas, there was a succession of kingdoms all with similar characteristics that, somewhat prematurely, I shall call bicameral.
While there were certainly other bicameral kingdoms in the
history of the world, perhaps along the margins of the Bay of
Bengal or the Malay peninsular, in Europe, certainly in central
Africa by diffusion from Egypt, and possibly among the North
The Witness of History
150
American Indians during the so-called Mississippi Period, too little
has been recovered of these civilizations to be of assistance in
checking out the main hypothesis.
Given the theory as I have outlined it, I suggest that there are
several outstanding archaeological features of ancient civilizations which can only be understood on this basis. These silent
features are the subject of this chapter, the literate civilizations
of Mesopotamia and Egypt being reserved for the next.
THE
HOUSES
OF
GODS
Let us imagine ourselves coming as strangers to an unknown
land and finding its settlements all organized on a similar
plan: ordinary houses and buildings grouped around one larger
and more magnificent dwelling. We would immediately assume
that the large magnificent dwelling was the house of the prince
who ruled there. And we might be right. But in the case of older
civilizations, we would not be right if we supposed such a ruler
was a person like a contemporary prince. Rather he was an
hallucinated presence, or, in the more general case, a statue,
often at one end of his superior house, with a table in front of
him where the ordinary could place their offerings to him.
Now, whenever we encounter a town or city plan such as this,
with a central larger building that is not a dwelling and has no
other practical use as a granary or barn, for example, and particularly if the building contains some kind of human effigy, we
may take it as evidence of a bicameral culture or of a culture
derived from one. This criterion may seem fatuous, simply because it is the plan of many towns today. We are so used to the
town plan of a church surrounded by lesser houses and shops
that we see nothing unusual. But our contemporary religious and
city architecture is partly, I think, the residue of our bicameral
past. The church or temple or mosque is still called the House of
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
151
God. In it, we still speak to the god, still bring offerings to be
placed on a table or altar before the god or his emblem. My
purpose in speaking in this objective fashion is to defamiliarize
this whole pattern, so that standing back and seeing civilized man
against his entire primate evolution, we can see that such a
pattern of town structure is unusual and not to be expected from
our Neanderthal origins.
From Jericho to Ur
With but few exceptions, the plan of human group habitation
from the end of the Mesolithic up to relatively recent eras is of a
god-house surrounded by man-houses. In the earliest villages,1
such as the excavated level of Jericho corresponding to the ninth
millennium B.C., such a plan is not entirely clear and is perhaps
debatable. But the larger god-house at Jericho, surrounded by
what were lesser dwellings, at a level corresponding to the
seventh millennium B.C., with its perhaps columned porchway
leading into a room with niches and curvilinear annexes, defies
doubt as to its purpose. It is no longer the tomb of a dead king
whose corpse is propped up on stones. The niches housed nearly
life-sized effigies, heads modeled naturalistically in clay and set
on canes or bundles of reeds and painted red. Of similar hallucinogenic function may have been the ten human skulls, perhaps
of dead kings, found at the same site, with features realistically
modeled in plaster and white cowrie shells inserted for eyes. And
the Hacilar culture in Anatolia of about 7000 B.C. also had human crania set up on floors, suggesting similar bicameral control
to hold the members of the culture together in their food-producing and protection enterprise.
1 General sources consulted here include Grahame Clark and Stuart Piggott, Prehistoric Societies (London: Hutchinson, 1965); James Mellaart, Earliest Civilizations of the Near East (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1965); and Grahame Clark,
World Prehistory: A New Outline (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969).
152
The Witness of History
Plan of building-level VI B at Çatal Hüyük, about 6000 B.C. Note
that there is a shrine signified by S in almost every household.
The largest Neolithic site in the Near East is the 32-acre Çatal
Hüyük, of which only one or two acres have been as yet excavated. Here the arrangement was slightly different. Excavations
at levels dating from about 6000 B.C. show that almost every
house had a series of four to five rooms nestled around a god's
room. Numerous groups of statues in stone or baked clay have
been found within these god's rooms.
At Eridu, five centuries later, god-houses were set on mud-brick
platforms, which were the origin of ziggurats. In a long central
room, the god-idol on a platform at one end looked at an offering
table at the other. And it is this Eridu sequence of sanctuaries up
to the Ubaid culture in southern Iraq which, spreading over the
whole of Mesopotamia around 4300 B.C., lays the foundations of
the Sumerian civilization and its Babylonian successor which I
consider in the next chapter. With cities of many thousands
came the building of the huge monumental god-houses which
characterize and dominate cities from then on, perhaps being
hallucinogenic aids to everyone for miles around. To stand even
today under such mountainous ziggurats as that of Ur, still heaving up above the excavated ruins of its once bicameral civiliza-
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
153
tion, with its ramps of staircases rising to but half the height it
once had, and to imagine its triple tier of temples on top rising
into the sun is to feel the grip such architecture alone can have
upon one’s mentality.
A Hittite Variation
The Hittites in the center of their capital, Hattusas, now
Boghazkoy in central Turkey, 2 had four huge temples with great
granite sanctuaries that projected beyond the main fagades of the
limestone walls to obtain lateral lighting for some huge idols.
But, perhaps taking the place of a ziggurat, that is, of a high
place that could be seen wherever lands were being farmed, is the
beautiful outdoor mountain shrine of Yazilikaya just above the
city, its sanctuary walls streaming with reliefs of gods.3 That the
mountains themselves were hallucinatory to the Hittites is indicated by relief sculptures still clearly visible on the rocks within
the sanctuary, showing the usual stereotyped drawings of mountains topped with the heads and headdresses used for gods. As
the Psalmist sings, “I will lift up mine eyes unto the hills whence
cometh my help.”
On one of the faces of this mountain temple, the robed king is
carved in profile. Just behind him in the stone relief towers a god
with a much loftier crown; the god’s right arm is outstretched,
showing the king the way, while the god’s left arm is hugged
around the king’s neck and grasps the king’s right wrist firmly. It
is testament to an emblem of the bicameral mind.
The depicting of gods in long files, unique I think to the Hit2 The Hittites may be an example of a group of nomadic tribes learning’ a bicameral civilization from their neighbors. It is the sudden intrusion of brightly
decorated polychrome pottery among the burnished monochrome pottery of the
Cappadocian plateau in the archaelogical record dating about 2100 b.c. that is taken
to be the indication of their arrival, probably from the steppes of southern Russia.
3 Good photographs of Yazilikaya may be seen in Ch. 3 of Seton Lloyd, Early
Highland Peoples of Anatolia (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967). An explanatory
discussion may be found in Ekron Akurgal, Ancient Civilizations and Ruins of Turkey
(Istanbul, 1969).
154
The Witness of History
Rock relief at Yazilikaya, about
1250 B.C.
The god Sharruma
holds his steward-king, Tudhaliys, in his embrace. The pretzellike hieroglyph for deity is seen
both as the head in the god's
ideogram on the upper left and
repetitively on the god's crown.
It is also seen in the king's ideogram on the upper right, indicating, I think, that the king too was
'heard' in hallucination by his
subjects.
tites, suggests a solution to an old problem in Hittite research.
This is the translation of the important word pankush. Scholars
originally interpreted it as signifying the whole human community, perhaps some sort of national assembly. But other texts
have forced a revision of this to some kind of an elite. A further
possibility, I suggest, is that it indicates the whole community of
these many gods, and, particularly, the choice-decisions in which
all the bicameral voices were in agreement. The fact that during
the last century or so of Hittite rule, from around 1300 B.C., no
mention of the pankush appears in any text could indicate their
collective silence and the beginning of the troublous change
toward subjectivity.
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
155
Olmec and Maya
The earliest bicameral kingdoms of America are also characterized by these huge, otherwise useless centrally located buildings: the queer-shaped clumsy Olmec pyramid at La Venta of
about 500 B.C. with its corridor of lesser mounds smothering
mysterious jaguar-face mosaics; or the rash of great temple pyramids constructed about 200 B.C.4 The largest of them, the gigantic pyramid of the sun at Teotihuacan (literally “Place of the
Gods”) has a greater cubic content than any in Egypt, being an
eighth of a mile long on each side, and higher than a twenty-story
building.5 A room for a god on its summit was reached by
systems of steep stairs. And on top of the god-room, tradition
states, there was a gigantic statue of the sun. A processional way
flanked by other pyramids leads toward it, and, for miles around
on the Mexican plateau, one can still see the remains of a great
city, houses for priests, numerous courtyards, and smaller buildings, all of one story so that from anywhere in the city one could
see the great pyramidal houses of gods.6
Beginning somewhat later, but co-temporaneous with Teotihuacan, are the many Maya cities in the Yucatan peninsula7
showing the same bicameral architecture, each city centering
upon steeply rising pyramids topped with god-houses and richly
decorated with Olmec-type jaguar masks and other murals and
carvings, in which an endless variety of dragons with human
faces crawl fiercely through the intricate stone decoration. Exceptionally interesting is the fact that some of the pyramids
4 See in this connection C. A. Burland, The Gods of Mexico (London: Eyre and
Spottiswoode, 1967) ; and also G. H. S. Bushnell, The First Americans: The PreColumbian Civilizations (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1968).
5 It was constructed of nearly 3 million tons of clay adobes, thus requiring* a
tremendous number of man-hours. For a way of understanding such hand labor
(Mesoamerica did not have the wheel), see p. 427.
6 See S. Linne, Archaeological Researches at Teotihuacan, Mexico (Stockholm:
Ethnographic Museum of Sweden, 1934); also Miguel Covarrubias, Indian Art of
Mexico and Central America (New York: Knopf, 1957).
7 See Victor W. von Hagen, World of the Maya (New York: New American
Library, 1960).
156
The Witness of History
contain burials as in Egypt, perhaps indicating a phase in which
the king was a god. In front of these Mayan pyramids are usually
stelae carved with the figures of gods and glyphic inscriptions
which have yet to be fully understood. Since this kind of writing
is always in connection with religious images, it is possible that
the hypothesis of the bicameral mind may assist in unwinding
their mysteries.
I also think that the curious unhospitable sites on which Mayan
cities were often built and their sudden appearance and disappearance can best be explained on the basis that such sites and
movements were commanded by hallucinations which in certain
periods could be not only irrational but downright punishing —
as was Jahweh sometimes to his people, or Apollo (through the
Delphic Oracle) to his, by siding with the invaders of Greece
(see III.1, III.2, n. 12).
Occasionally, there are actual depictions of the bicameral act.
On two stone reliefs from Santa Lucia Cotz umalhaupa, a nonMayan site on the Pacific slope of Guatemala, this is very clearly
the case. A man is shown prostrate on the grass being spoken to
by two divine figures, one half-human, half-deer, and the other a
death figure. That this is an actual bicameral scene is clear from
modern observations of the so-called chilans or prophets of the
area. Even today, they hallucinate voices while face down in this
identical posture, although it is thought by some that such contemporary hallucinations are aided by eating peyote.8
Andean Civilizations
The half dozen or so civilizations of the Andes that precede the
Inca are even more lost in the overgrowth of time.9 The earliest,
8 J. Erik S. Thompson, Maya History and Religion (Norman: University of
Oklahoma Press, 1970), p. 186. Peyote, incidentally, was used by most Mesoamerican
Indians when their bicamerality was breaking down. The exceptions were the Maya
and they are the only ones to have any kind of writing". Is it possible that 'reading'
or hallucinating from glyphs functioned for the Maya as did hallucinogenic peyote
for others?
9 This is partly due to the fact that a new bicameral civilization in an area tends to
obliterate the remains of its predecessor. Bicameral gods are jealous gods.
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
157
Kotosh, dating before 1800 B.C., is centered about a rectangular
god-house built on a stepped platform 25 feet high on a large
mound, where it was surrounded by the remains of other buildings. Its interior walls had a few tall rectangular niches in each,
in one of which was a pair of crossed hands modeled in plaster,
perhaps part of a larger idol, now dust. How similar to Jericho
five millennia earlier!
While it is possible that Kotosh was the work of migrants from
Mexico, the next civilization, the Chavin, beginning about 1200
B.C., shows decided Olmec features: the cultivation of maize, a
number of pottery characteristics, and the jaguar theme in its
religious sculpture. At Chavin itself in the north highlands, a
great platformlike temple, honeycombed with passages, houses
an impressive idol in the form of a prismatic mass of granite
carved in low relief to represent a human being with a jaguar
head.10 Following them, the Mochicas,11 ruling the northern
Peruvian desert from A.D. 400 to 1000, built huge pyramids for
their gods, towering in front of walled enclosures which probably
contained the cities, as can be seen today in the Chicama valley
near Trujillo. 12
Then on the bleak uplands near Lake Titicaca from A . D . I O O Q
to 1300 came the great empire of Tiahuanaco, with an even
larger stone-faced pyramid, set about with giant pillarlike gods
weeping tears (why?) of condor heads and snake heads.13
Then the Chimu, on an even vaster scale. Its capital of Chan10 The next culture, the Paracas, from about 400 B.C. to a.d. 400, is a mysterious
anomaly. They left no building sites, only 400 or so brightly robed mummies in deep
subterranean caverns on the Paracas peninsular.
11 So-called. As in all these early civilizations we have no idea what they called
themselves.
12 Aerial views of their cities look very similar to those of Mesopotamia in the
bicameral period. Other cultures, such as the lea Nazca, also existed at the same
time to the south. Little, however, remains except the mysterious lines and figures,
some running for miles in length in the dry valleys of Nazca, and gigantic bird or
insect outlines, acres in area, for which no one can suggest an explanation.
13 So complete and swift was their collapse around a.d. 1300, perhaps due to overexpansion (see II.3 for reasons why bicameral kingdoms are unstable), that 250
years later, after the European invasion, no one had heard anything about them.
158
The Witness of History
Chan, covering eleven square miles, was walled off into ten great
compounds, each a city in miniature with its own pyramid, its
own palacelike structure, its own irrigated areas, reservoirs, and
cemeteries. Precisely what these neighboring separated walled
compounds could mean in the light of the bicameral hypothesis
is a fascinating problem for research.
The Golden Realm of the Incas
And then the Incas themselves, like a synthesis of Egypt and
Assyria. At least at the beginning of their power about A.D. 1200,
their realm was suggestive of a god-king type of bicameral kingdom. But within a century, the Incas had conquered all before
them, perhaps thereby weakening their own bicamerality, as did
Assyria in another age and another clime.
The Inca empire at the time of its conquest by Pizarro was
perhaps a combination of things bicameral and things protosubjective. This meeting was probably the closest thing there is to a
clash between the two mentalities this essay is about. On the
subjective side was the vast empire which, if we suppose it was
administered with the horizontal and vertical social mobility
such an administration demands today,14 would be very difficult
to control in a purely bicameral fashion. From hearsay reports, it
is believed that conquered chiefs were allowed to retain their
titles, and their sons sent to Cuzco for training and perhaps held
as hostages, a difficult conception in a bicameral world. Conquered peoples seem to have retained their own speech, although
all officials had to learn the religious language, Quechua.
But on the bicameral side, there are a large number of features
which are most certainly bicameral in origin, even though they
may have been acted out partially through the inertia of tradition,
as the small city-state of Cuzco on the upper reaches of the
Amazon exploded into this Roman empire of the Andes. The
14 J. H. Rowe, "Inca Culture at the time of the Spanish Conquest," in J. H.
Steward, Handbook of South American Indians, Vol. 2 (Washington, D.C., 1946-50).
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
159
Inca himself was the god-king, a pattern so similar to Egypt’s that
less conservative historians of American antiquity have felt that
there must have been some diffusion. But I suggest that given
man, language, and cities organized on a bicameral basis, there
are only certain fixed patterns into which history can fit.
The king was divine, a descendant of the sun, the creator-god
of land and earth, of people, of the sun’s sweat (gold) and the
moon’s tears (silver). Before him, even his highest lords might
tremble with such awe as to shake them from their feet, 15 an
awe that is impossible for modern psychology to appreciate. His
daily life was deep in elaborate ritual. His shoulders were
mantled in quilts of fresh bat-webs, and his head circled with a
fringe of red tassels, like a curtain before his eyes to protect his
lords from too awesome a view at his unwatchable divinity.
When the Inca died, his concubines and personal servants first
drank and danced, and then were eagerly strangled to join him
on his journey to the sun, just as had previously happened in
Egypt, Ur, and China. The Inca’s body was mummified and
placed in his house, which thereafter became a temple. A life-sized
golden statue was made of him sitting on his golden stool as in
his life, and served daily with food as in the kingdoms of the Near
East.
While it is possible that the sixteenth-century Inca and his
hereditary aristocracy were walking through bicameral roles
established in a much earlier truly bicameral kingdom, even as
perhaps the Emperor Hirohito, the divine sun god of Japan, does
to this day, the evidence suggests that it was much more than this.
The closer an individual was to the Inca, the more it seems his
mentality was bicameral. Even the gold and jeweled spools
which the top of the hierarchy, including the Inca, wore in their
ears, sometimes with images of the sun on them, may have
indicated that those same ears were hearing the voice of the
sun.
15 As reported by Pedro Pizarro, a cousin of the Conquistador, quoted by V. W.
von Hagen, Realm of the Incas, p. 113.
160
The Witness of History
But perhaps most suggestive of all is the manner in which this
huge empire was conquered.16 The unsuspicious meekness of
the surrender has long been the most fascinating problem of the
European invasions of America. The fact that it occurred is
clear, but the record as to why is grimy with supposition, even in
the superstitious Conquistadors who later recorded it. How could
an empire whose armies had triumphed over the civilizations of
half a continent be captured by a small band of 150 Spaniards in
the early evening of November 16, 1532?
It is possible that it was one of the few confrontations between
subjective and bicameral minds, that for things as unfamiliar as
Inca Atahualpa was confronted with — these rough, milkskinned men with hair drooling from their chins instead of from
their scalps so that their heads looked upside down, clothed in
metal, with avertive eyes, riding strange llamalike creatures with
silver hoofs, having arrived like gods in gigantic huampus tiered
like Mochican temples over the sea which to the Inca was
unsailable — that for all this there were no bicameral voices
coming from the sun, or from the golden statues of Cuzco in their
dazzling towers. Not subjectively conscious, unable to deceive or
to narratize out the deception of others,17 the Inca and his lords
were captured like helpless automatons. And as its people
mechanically watched, this shipload of subjective men stripped
the gold sheathing from the holy city, melted down its golden
images and all the treasures of the Golden Enclosure, its fields of
golden corn with stems and leaves all cunningly wrought in gold,
murdered its living god and his princes, raped its unprotesting
women, and, narratizing their Spanish futures, sailed away with
the yellow metal into the subjective conscious value system from
which they had come.
It is a long way from Eynan.
16 For a detailed readable recent account, see John Hemming, The Conquest of
the Incas (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1970).
17 There were no thieves in Cuzco and no doors: a stick crosswise in front of the
open doorway was a sign that the owner was not in and nobody would enter.
GODS,
THE
GRAVES,
AND
LIVING
IDOLS
161
DEAD
The burial of the important dead as if they still lived is common
to almost all these ancient cultures whose architecture we have
just looked at. This practice has no clear explanation except that
their voices were still being heard by the living, and were perhaps
demanding such accommodation. As I have suggested at Eynan
in 1.6, these dead kings, propped up on stones, whose voices were
hallucinated by the living, were the first gods.
Then as these early cultures develop into bicameral kingdoms,
the graves of their important personages are more and more filled
with weapons, furniture, ornaments, and particularly vessels of
food. This is true of the very first chamber tombs all over Europe
and Asia after 7000 B.C. and is elaborated to an extraordinary
degree as bicameral kingdoms develop both in size and complexity. The magnificent burials of Egyptian pharaohs in a whole
succession of intricately built pyramids are familiar to everyone
(see next chapter). But similar emplacements, if less awesome,
are found elsewhere. The kings of Ur, during the first half of the
third millennium B.C., were entombed with their entire retinues
buried, sometimes alive, in a crouched position around them as
for service. Eighteen of such tombs have been found, their
vaulted subterranean rooms containing food and drink, clothing,
jewelry, weapons, bull-headed lyres, even sacrificed draft animals
yoked to ornate chariots.18 Others, dating from slightly later
periods, have been found at Kish and Ashur. In Anatolia, at
Alaca Hliyiik, the royal graves were roofed with whole carcasses
of roasted oxen to ease the sepulchral appetites of their motionless inhabitants.
Even the ordinary dead man in many cultures is treated as still
living. The very oldest inscriptions on funerary themes are
Mesopotamian lists of the monthly rations of bread and beer to be
18 See C. L. Woolley, Ur Excavations, Vol. 2
(London and Philadelphia, 1934).
162
The Witness of History
given to the common dead. About 2500 B.C., in Lagash, a dead
person was buried with 7 jars of beer, 420 flat loaves of bread, 2
measures of grain, 1 garment, 1 head support, and 1 bed. 19
Some ancient Greek graves not only have the various appurtenances of life, but actual feeding tubes which seem to indicate
that archaic Greeks poured broths and soups down into the livid
jaws of a moldering corpse.20 And in the Metropolitan Museum
in New York is a painted krater or mixing bowl (numbered
14.130.15) which dates from about 850 B.C.; it shows a boy seemingly tearing his hair with one hand as with the other he stuffs
food into the mouth of a corpse, probably his mother's. This is
difficult to appreciate unless the feeder was hallucinating something from the dead at the time.
T h e evidence in the Indus civilizations21 is more fragmentary
because of the successive coverings of alluvium, the rotting away
of all their writings on papyrus, and the incompleteness of
archaeological investigations. But the Indus sites so far excavated often have the cemetery next to the citadel in a high place
with fifteen or twenty food-pots per dead person, consistent with
the hypothesis that they were still felt to be living when buried.
And the Neolithic burials of the Yang-Shao cultures of China 22 ,
wholly undated except insofar as they precede the middle of the
second millennium B.C., similarly show burials in plank-lined
graves, the corpse accompanied by pots of food and stone tools.
19 This information is given on a cone by Urukagina, king of Lagash, who proceeded to reduce these amounts somewhat. See Alexander Heidel, The Gilgamesh
Epic and Old Testament Parallels (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1949),
p. 151.
20 E. R. Dodds, The Greeks and the Irrational,
21 Sir Mortimer Wheeler, Civilizations of the Indus Valley and Beyond (New
York: McGraw-Hill, 1966), and, more extensively, his The Indus Civilization,
2nd ed., supplementary volume to The Cambridge History of India (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1960).
22 See William Watson, Early Civilization in China (New York: McGraw-Hill,
1966)-, and also Chang Kwang-Chih, The Archaeology of Ancient China (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1963).
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
163
By 1200 B.C., the Shang dynasty has royal tombs with slaughtered retinues and animals so similar to those of Mesopotamia
and Egypt a millennium earlier as to convince some scholars that
civilization came to China by diffusion from the West. 23
Similarly in Mesoamerica, Olmec burials from about 800 to
300 B.C. were richly furnished with pots of food. In the Mayan
kingdoms, the noble dead were buried as if living in the plazas of
temples. A chieftain’s tomb recently found under a temple at
Palenque is as elaborately splendid as anything found in the Old
World. 24 At the site of Kaminal-juyu, dating A.D. 500, a chieftain was buried in a sitting position along with two adolescents, a
child, and a dog for his company. Ordinary men were buried
with their mouths full of ground maize in the hard-mud floors of
their houses, with their tools and weapons, and with pots filled
with drink and food, just as in previous civilizations on the other
side of the world. Also I should mention the portrait statues of
Yucatan that held the ashes of a deceased chief, the resculptured
skulls of Mayapan, and the small catacombs for Andean commoners bound in a sitting position in the midst of bowls of chicha
and the tools and things used in their lives.25 The dead were
then called huaca or godlike, which I take to indicate that they
were sources of hallucinated voices. And when it was reported by
the Conquistadors that these people declared that it is only a long
time after death that the individual ‘dies,’ I suggest that the
proper interpretation is that it takes this time for the hallucinated
voice to finally fade away.
That the dead were the origin of gods is also found in the
writings of those bicameral civilizations that became literate. In
23 Chariot burials complete with slaughtered horses and charioteers become more
frequent toward the end of the Shang dynasty in the eleventh century b.c. and
continue into the Chou dynasty of the eighth century b.c. when they cease. Why all
this? Unless the dead kings were thought to still live and need their chariots and
servants because their speech was still heard?
24 Von Hagen, World of the Maya, p. 109.
25 Von Hagen, Realm of the Incas, p. 121.
164
The Witness of History
a bilingual incantation text from Assyria, the dead are directly
called Ilani or gods.26 And on the other side of the world three
millennia later, Sahagun, one of the earliest reporters of the
Mesoamerican scene, reported that the Aztecs "called the place
Teotihuacan, burial place of the kings; the ancients said: he who
has died became a god; or when someone said — he who has
become a god, meant to say — he has died." 27
Even in the conscious period there was the tradition that gods
were men of a previous age who had died. Hesiod speaks of a
golden race of men who preceded his own generation and became
the "holy demons upon the earth, beneficent, averters of ills,
guardians of mortal men."28 Similar references can be found up
to four centuries later, as when Plato refers to heroes who after
death become the demons that tell people what to do.29
I do not wish to give the impression that the presence of pots of
food and drink in the graves of these civilizations is universal
throughout all these eras; it is general. But exceptions here often
prove the rule. For example, Sir Leonard Woolley, when he first
started excavating the personal graves at Larsa in Mesopotamia
(which date from about 1900 B . C . ) , was both surprised and
disappointed by the poverty of their contents. Even the most
elaborately built vault would have no furnishings other than a
couple of clay pots at the tomb door perhaps, but nothing of the
kind of thing found in graves elsewhere. The explanation came
when he realized that these tombs were always underneath particular houses, and that the dead man of the Larsa Age needed no
tomb furniture or large amounts of food because everything in
the house was still at his disposal. The food and drink at the
tomb door may have been like an emergency measure, so that
when the dead man 'mixed5 with the family, he came forth in a
kindly mood.
Heidel, The Gilgamesh E f i c , pp. 153, 196.
Quoted by Covarrubias, p. 123.
28 Hesiod, Works and Days, 12 of.
29 Republic, 469A; and also Cratylus, 398.
26
27
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
165
Thus, from Mesopotamia to Peru, the great civilizations have at
least gone through a stage characterized by a kind of burial as if
the individual were still living. And where writing could record
it, the dead were often called gods. At the very least, this is
consistent with the hypothesis that their voices were still heard in
hallucination.
But is this a necessary relationship? Could not grief itself
promote such practices, a kind of refusal to accept the death of a
loved one or a revered leader, calling dead persons gods as a kind
of endearment? Possibly. This explanation, however, is not
sufficient to account for the entire pattern of the evidence, the
pervasion of references to the dead as gods in different regions of
the world, the vastness of some of the enterprise as in the great
pyramids, and even the contemporary vestiges in lore and literature of ghosts returning from their graves with messages for the
living.
IDOLS
THAT
SPEAK
A third feature of primitive civilization that I take to be indicative of bicamerality is the enormous numbers and kinds of
human effigies and their obvious centrality to ancient life. The
first effigies in history were of course the propped-up corpses of
chiefs, or the remodeled skulls we have referred to earlier. But
thereafter they have an astonishing development. It is difficult to
understand their obvious importance to the cultures involved
with them apart from the supposition that they were aids in
hallucinating voices. But this is far from a simple matter, and
quite different principles may be intertwined in the full explanation.
Figurines
The smallest of these effigies are figurines, which have been
found in almost all of the ancient kingdoms, beginning with the
166
The Witness of History
first stationary settlements of man. During the seventh and sixth
millennia B.C, they are extremely primitive, small stones with
incised features or grotesque clay figures. Evidence of their importance in cultures of about 5600 B.C. is provided by the excavations at Hacilar in southwest Turkey. Flat standing female
effigies, made of baked clay or stone with incised eyes, nose, hair,
and chin were found in each house,30 as if, I suggest, they were
its occupant's hallucinatory controls. The Amatrian and Gerzean
cultures of Egypt, about 3600 B.C., had carved tusks with bearded
heads and black 'targets' for eyes, each about six to eight inches
and suitable to be held in the hand.31 And these were so important
that they were stood upright in the grave of their owner when he
died.
Figurines in huge numbers have been unearthed in most of the
Mesopotamian cultures, at Lagash, Uruk, Nippur, and Susa.32
At Ur, clay figures painted in black and red were found in boxes
of burned brick placed under the floor against the walls but with
one end opened, facing into the center of the room.
The function of all these figurines, however, is as mysterious
as anything in all archaeology. The most popular view goes back
to the uncritical mania with which ethnology, following Frazer,
wished to find fertility cults at the drop of a carved pebble. But if
such figurines indicate something about Frazerian fertility, we
should not find them where fertility was no problem. But we do.
In the Olmec civilization of the most fertile part of Mexico, the
figurines are of an astonishing variety, often with open mouths
and exaggerated ears, as might be expected if they were fashMellaart, p. 106; see also Clark and Piggott, p. 204.
See Flinders Petrie, Prehistoric Egypt (London: British School of Archaeology
in Egypt, 1920), pp. 27, 36. Even gods are sometimes shown using hand-held idols.
An Anatolian example may be found in Seton Lloyd, Early Highland Peoples of
Anatolia (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967), p. 51; and a Mayan example on the
north face of Stela F in A. P. Maudslay, Archaeology in Biologia Centrali-Americana
(New York: Arte Primitivo, 1975), Vol. II, Plate 36.
32 For later rituals of giving them supernatural power, see H. W. F. Saggs, The
Greatness That Was Babylon (New York: Mentor Books, 1962), pp. 301-303.
30
31
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
167
ioned as embodiments of heard voices with whom dialogue could
be carried on.33
The explanation, however, is not simple. Figurines seemed to
go through an evolution, just as did the culture of which they are
a part. The early Olmec figurines, to stay with the same example, develop through their first period an exaggerated prognathism until they look almost like animals. And then, in the
period of Teotihuacan, they are more refined and delicate, with
huge hats and capes, painted with daubs of fugitive red, yellow,
and white paint, looking much like Olmec priests. A third period
of Olmec figurines has them more carefully modeled and realistic, some with jointed arms and legs, some with hollow reliquaries in their torsos closed by a small square lid and containing
other minute figurines, perhaps denoting the confusion of bicameral guidance that occurred just before the great Olmec civilization collapsed. For it was at the end of this period of a profusion
of figurines, as well as of huge new half-finished open-mouth
statues, that the great city of Teotihuacan was deliberately destroyed, its temples burned, its walls leveled, and the city abandoned, around A.D. 700. Had the voices ceased, resulting in the
increased effigy making? Or had they multiplied into confusion?
Because of their size and number, it is doubtful if the majority
of figurines occasioned auditory hallucinations. Some indeed may
have been mnemonic devices, reminders to a nonconscious
people who could not voluntarily retrieve admonitory experience,
perhaps functioning like the quipu or knot-string literature of the
Incas or the beads of rosaries of our own culture. For example,
the Mesopotamian bronze foundation figurines buried at the
corners of new buildings and under thresholds of doors are of
three kinds: a kneeling god driving a peg into the ground, a
basket carrier, and a recumbent bull. The current theory about
them, that they are to pin down evil spirits beneath the building,
33 See
p. 37f.
Burland, The Gods of Mexico, p. 22f.; Bushnell, The First Americans,
168
The Witness of History
is scarcely sufficient. Instead it is possible that they were semihallucinatory mnemonic aids for a nonconscious people in setting
the posts straight, in carrying the materials, or using oxen to pull
the larger materials to the site.
But some of these small objects, we may be confident, were
capable of assisting with the production of bicameral voices.
Consider the eye-idols in black and white alabaster, thin crackerlike bodies surmounted by eyes once tinted with malachite paint,
which have been found in the thousands, particularly at Brak
on one of the upper branches of the Euphrates, that date about
3000 B.C. Like the earlier Amatrian and Gerzean tusk idols
One of many thousands of alabaster "eye idols" that can be
held in the hand.
From about
3300 B.C., excavated at Brak on
an upper tributary of the Euphrates. T h e stag is the symbol
of the goddess Ninhursag.
of Egypt, they are suitable to be held in the hand. Most have one
pair of eyes, but some have two; some wear crowns and some
have markings clearly indicating gods. Larger eye-idols made of
terra cotta have been found at other sites, Ur, Mari, and Lagash;
and, because the eyes are open loops, have been called spectacleidols. Others, made of stone and placed on podiums and altars,34
are like two cylindrical doughnuts positioned a distance above
an incised square platform that could be a mouth.
34 See M. E. L. Mallowan, Early Mesopotamia and Iran (New York: McGrawHill) 1965, Ch. 2.
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
169
A Theory of Idols
Now this needs a little more psychologizing. Eye-to-eye contact in primates is extremely important. Below humans, it is
indicative of the hierarchical position of the animal, the submissive animal turning away grinning in many primate species. But
in humans, perhaps because of the much longer juvenile period,
eye-to-eye contact has evolved into a social interaction of great
importance. An infant child, when its mother speaks to it, looks
at the mother’s eyes, not her lips. This response is automatic and
universal. The development of such eye-to-eye contact into
authority relationships and love relationships is an exceedingly
important trajectory that has yet to be traced. It is sufficient here
merely to suggest that you are more likely to feel a superiors
authority when you and he are staring straight into each other’s
eyes. There is a kind of stress, an unresolvedness about the
experience, and withal something of a diminution of consciousness, so that, were such a relationship mimicked in a statue, it
would enhance the hallucination of divine speech.
The eyes thus become a prominent feature of most temple
statuary throughout the bicameral period. The diameter of the
human eye is about 10 percent of the height of the head, this
proportion being what I shall call the eye index of an idol. The
famous group of twelve statues discovered in the Favissa of the
temple of Abu at Tell Asmar,35 the symbols carved on their bases
indicating that they are gods, have eye indices of as high as 18
percent — huge globular eyes hypnotically staring out of the unrecorded past of 5000 years ago with defiant authority.
Other idols from other sites show the same thing. A particularly beautiful and justly famous white marble head from Uruk 36
has an eye index of over 20 percent, the sculpture showing
that the eyes and the eyebrows were once encrusted with dazzling
gems, the face colored, the hair tinted, the head part of a life35
Illustrated in many general texts including Mallowan, pp. 43, 45.
36 See Mallowan, Early Mesopotamia, p. 55.
170
The Witness of History
sized wooden statue now dust. Around 2700
B.C. alabaster and calcite statues of fluffily
skirted gods, rulers, and priests abounded
in the luxurious civilization on the middle
Euphrates called Mari, their eyes up to 18
percent of the height of the head and heavily
outlined with black paint. In the main temple
of Mari ruled the famous Goddess with the
Flowering Vase, her huge empty eye sockets
having once contained hypnotic gems, her
hands holding a tilted aryballos. A pipe from
a tank going within the idol allowed the aryballos to overflow with water which streamed
down the idol's robe, clothing her lower parts
with a translucent liquid veil, and adding a
sibilant sound suitable to be molded into
hallucinated speech. And then the famous
series of statues of the enigmatic Gudea, ruler
of Lagash, about 2100 B.C., carved in the
hardest stone, with eye indices of approximately 17 or 18 percent.
The eye indices of temple and tomb sculptures of pharaohs in Egypt are sometimes as
high as 20 percent. The few wooden statues
from Egypt that have remained show that
their enlarged eyes were once made of quartz
and crystal inserted in a copper surround. As
might be expected from its god-king type of
theocracy (see next chapter) idols in Egypt
do not seem to have played so prominent a
role as in Mesopotamia.
Few examples of Indus stone sculpture
survive, but these few show pronounced eye
indices of over 20 percent.37 No idols are
37 See,
for example, the illustrations in Wheeler, Civilizations of the Indus Valley.
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
171
yet known from the bicameral period of China. But as civilization begins again in Mesoamerica around 900 B.C., it is as if we
were back in the Near East several millennia earlier, though with
certain unique prospects: huge heads carved out of hard basalt,
often eight feet tall, usually with a cap, sometimes with large ear
pads like a football helmet, resting bodiless on the ground near
La Venta and Tres Zapoltes (some of them now removed to
Olmec Park at Villahermosa). The eye indices of these heads
ranged from a normal 11 percent to over 19 percent. Usually the
mouth is half open as in speech. There are also many Olmec
ceramic idols of a strange sexless child, always seated with legs
spread-eagled as if to expose his sexlessness, and leaning forward
to stare intently through wide slits of eyes, the full-lipped mouth
half open as in speech. The eye index, if the eyes were open, in
the several of them I have examined averaged 17 percent. Figurines in the Olmec culture were sometimes half life-sized with
even larger eye indices 3 they are often found in burials as at the
Olmec-influenced site of Tlatilco, near Mexico City, of about
T h e god Abu, with an unknown
goddess on facing page.
Both
were found in a temple at T e l l
Asmar near present-day Baghdad
and
are
now
in
its
From about 2600 B.C.
museum.
172
The Witness of History
Mayan god, a stela about twelve
feet high, from Copan in Honduras.
It
was
carved
700 A.D.
38 As quoted by von
39
about
500 B.C., as if the deceased was buried with his
own personal idol which still could tell him
what to do.
Mayan idols do not usually show such abnormal eye indices. But in the great cities of
Yucatan, portrait statues were made of deceased leaders for, I think, the same hallucinogenic purpose. The back of the head was
left hollow and .the cremated ashes of the dead
placed in it. And according to Landa, who
witnessed this practice in the sixteenth century, "they preserved these statues with a
great deal of veneration."38
The Cocoms that once ruled Mayapan,
around A.D. 1200, repeated what the Natufian
culture of Jericho had done 9000 years earlier. They decapitated their dead "and after
cooking the heads, they cleaned off the flesh
and then sawed off half the crown at the back,
leaving entire the front part with jaws and
teeth. Then they replaced the flesh . . .
with a kind of bitumen [and plaster] which
gave them a natural and lifelike appearance
. . . these they kept in the oratories in their
houses and on festive days offered food to
them . . . they believed that their souls reposed within and that these gifts were useful
to them." 39 There is nothing here inconsistent
with the notion that such prepared heads were
so treated because they 'contained' the voices
of their former owners.
Hagen, World of the Maya, p. 109.
Landa as quoted by von Hagen, World of the Maya, p. 110.
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
173
Many other kinds of idols were also used by the Maya, and in
such profusion that when, in 1565, a Spanish mayor ordered the
abolition of idolatry in his city, he was aghast when "in my
presence, upwards of a million were brought."40 Another type of
Mayan idol was made of cedar which the Maya called kuche or
holy wood. "And this they called to make gods." They were
carved by fasting priests called chaks, in great fear and trembling, shut into a little straw hut blessed with incense and
prayer, the god-carvers "frequently cutting their ears and with
the blood anointing the gods and burning incense to them."
When finished, the gods were lavishly dressed and placed upon
daises in small buildings, some of which by being in more inaccessible places have escaped the ravages of Christianity or of
time, and are still being discovered. According to a sixteenthcentury observer, "the unhappy dupes believed the idols spoke to
them and so sacrificed to it birds, dogs, their own blood and even
men." 41,42
The Speech of Idols
How can we know that such idols 'spoke' in the bicameral
sense? I have tried to suggest that the very existence of statuary
and figurines requires an explanation in a way that has not
previously been perceived. The hypothesis of the bicameral mind
renders such an explanation. The setting up of such idols in
religious places, the exaggerated eyes in the early stages of every
civilization, the practice of inserting gems of brilliant sorts into
the eye sockets in several civilizations, an elaborate ritual for the
40 Von Hagen, World of the Maya, p. 32.
41 All quotations here are from Landa, a Spaniard who was describing what he
saw in the sixteenth century as quoted by J. Eric S. Thompson, Maya History and
Religion, pp. 189—91.
42 The Incas too had a variety of idols that they called gods, some life-sized, cast
of gold or silver, others of stone crowned and dressed in robes, all these found by
Spaniards in outlying temples of the Inca empire. See von Hagen, Realm of the
Incas, pp. 134, 152.
The Witness of History
174
opening of the mouth for new statues in the two most important
early civilizations (as we shall see in the next chapter), all these
present a pattern of evidence at least.
Cuneiform literature often refers to god-statues speaking.
Even as late as the early first millennium B.C., a royal letter
reads:
I have taken note of the portents . . . I had them recited
in order before Shamash . . . the royal image [a statue] of
A k k a d brought up visions before me and cried out: " W h a t pernicious portent have you tolerated in the royal i m a g e ? "
it spoke: "Say to the Gardener . . .
Again
[and here the cunei-
form becomes unreadable, but then goes on] . . . it made inquiry
concerning
Marduk.
Ningal-Iddina,
Shamash-Ibni,
and
Na'id-
Concerning the rebellion in the land it said: " T a k e
the wall cities one after the other, that a cursed one will not be
able to stand before the Gardener." 4 3
The Old Testament also indicated that one of the types of idol
there referred to, the Terap, could speak. Ezekiel, 21:21, describes the king of Babylon as consulting with several of them.
Further direct evidence comes from America. The conquered
Aztecs told the Spanish invaders how their history began when a
statue from a ruined temple belonging to a previous culture spoke
to their leaders. It commanded them to cross the lake from
where they were, and to carry its statue with them wherever they
went, directing them hither and thither, even as the unembodied
bicameral voices led Moses zigzagging across the Sinai desert.44
And finally the remarkable evidence from Peru. A l l the first
reports of the conquest of Peru by the Inquisition-taught Spaniards are consistent in regarding the Inca kingdom as one commanded by the Devil. Their evidence was that the Devil himself
43 R. H. Pfeiffer, State Letters of Assyria (New Haven: American Oriental Society, 1935), p. 174.
44 C. A. Burland, The Gods of Mexico, p. 47.
GODS,
GRAVES,
AND
IDOLS
175
actually spoke to the Incas out of the mouths of their statues. To
these coarse dogmatized Christians, coming from one of the most
ignorant counties of Spain, this caused little astonishment. The
very first report back to Europe said, "in the temple [of
Pachacamac] was a Devil who used to speak to the Indians in a
very dark room which was as dirty as he himself." 45 And a later
account reported that
. . . it was a thing very common and approved at the Indies,
that the Devill spake and answered in these false sanctuaries
. . . It was commonly in the night they entered backward to
their idoll and so went bending their bodies and head, after an
uglie manner, and so they consulted with him.
T h e answer he
made, was commonly like unto a fearefull hissing, or to a
gnashing which did terrifie them; and all that he did advertise
or command them, was but the w a y to their perdition and
ruine. 46
45 Anonymous, The Conquest of Peru, with a translation and annotations by
J. H. Sinclair (New York: New York Public Library, 1929), p. 37f.
46 Father Joseph De Acosta, The Natural and Moral History of the Indies (London :
Hakluyt Society, 1880), 2: 325f.
CHAPTER 2
Literate Bicameral Theocracies
W
HAT is writing? Writing proceeds from pictures of visual
events to symbols of phonetic events. And that is an amazing transformation! Writing of the latter type, as on the present
page, is meant to tell a reader something he does not know. But,
the closer writing is to the former, the more it is primarily a
mnemonic device to release information which the reader already
has. The protoliterate pictograms of Uruk, the iconography in
the early depictions of gods, the glyphics of the Maya, the picture
codices of the Aztecs, and, indeed, our own heraldry are all of this
sort. The informations they are meant to release in those who
look upon them may be forever lost and the writing therefore
forever untranslatable.
The two kinds of writing which fall between these two extremes, half picture and half symbol, are those on which this
chapter is based. They are Egyptian hieroglyphics with its
abridged and somewhat cursive form, hieratic, the terms meaning "writing of the gods," and the more widely used writing which
later scholars called cuneiform from its wedge-shaped characters.
The latter is for us the most important, and the remains we
have of it, far more extensive. Thousands of tablets wait to be
translated and more thousands to be unburied. It was used for at
least four languages, Sumerian, Akkadian, Hurrian, and later the
Hittite. Instead of an alphabet of twenty-six letters, as in ours, or
of twenty-two letters, as in the Aramaic (which except for religious texts replaced cuneiform around 200 B . C . ) , it is a clumsy
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
177
and ambiguous communication system of over 600 signs. Many
of these are ideographic, in which the same sign can be a syllable, an idea, a name, or a word with more than one meaning,
according to the class it belonged to, this class irregularly being
shown by a special mark. Only by the context are we able to
means nine
unravel which it is. For example, the sign
different things: when pronounced as samsu it means sun; when
pronounced ūmu, it means day; when pisu it means white; and it
also stands for the syllables ud, tu, tam, pir, lah, and his. The
difficulties of being crystal clear in such a contextual mess were
great enough in its own day. But when we are exiled from the
culture that the language describes by 4000 years, translation is
an enormous and fascinating problem. The same is true in general for hieroglyphic and hieratic writing.
When the terms are concrete, as they usually are, for most of
the cuneiform literature is receipts or inventories or offerings for
gods, there is little doubt of the correctness of translation. But as
the terms tend to the abstract, and particularly when a psychological interpretation is possible, then we find well-meaning
translators imposing modern categories to make their translations comprehensible. The popular and even the scholarly literatures are full of such sugared emendations and palatablized
glosses to make ancient men seem like us, or at least talk like the
King James Bible. A translator often reads in more than he reads
out. Many of those texts that seem to be about decision-making,
or so-called proverbs, or epics, or teachings, should be reinterpreted with concrete behavioral precision if we are to trust them
as data for the psycho-archaeology of man. And I am warning
the reader that the effect of this chapter is not in accord with
popular books on the subject.
With these cautions in mind, then, let us proceed.
When, in the third millennium B.C., writing, like a theater
curtain going up on these dazzling civilizations, lets us stare
directly if imperfectly at them, it is clear that for some time there
178
The Witness of History
have been two main forms of theocracy: (1) the steward-king
theocracy in which the chief or king is the first deputy of the
gods, or, more usually, a particular city’s god, the manager and
caretaker of his lands. This was the most important and widespread form of theocracy among bicameral kingdoms. It was the
pattern in the many Mesopotamian bicameral city-states, of
Mycenae as we saw in I.3, and, so far as we know, in India,
China, and probably Mesoamerica. (2) the god-king theocracy in
which the king himself is a god. The clearest examples of this
form existed in Egypt and at least some of the kingdoms of the
Andes, and probably the earliest kingdom of Japan. I have earlier suggested in I.6 that both types developed out of the more
primitive bicameral situation where a new king ruled by obeying
the hallucinated voice of a dead king.
I shall take these up in turn in the two greatest ancient civilizations.
MESOPOTAMIA: THE
AS OWNERS
GODS
Throughout Mesopotamia, from the earliest times of Sumer and
Akkad, all lands were owned by gods and men were their slaves.
Of this, the cuneiform texts leave no doubt whatever. 1 Each citystate had its own principal god, and the king was described in the
very earliest written documents that we have as "the tenant
farmer of the god."
The god himself was a statue. The statue was not of a god (as
we would say) but the god himself. He had his own house, called
1 Most of this material is well known and may be found in a number of excellent
works, including H. W. F. Saggs, The Greatness That Was Babylon (New York:
Mentor Books, 1962); The Cambridge Ancient History, Vols. 1-3 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press); George Roux, Ancient Iraq (Baltimore: Penguin
Books, 1966); and A. L. Oppenheim, Ancient Mesopotamia: Portrait of a Dead
Civilization (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964).
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
179
by the Sumerians the "great house." It formed the center of a
complex of temple buildings, varying in size according to the importance of the god and the wealth of the city. The god was
probably made of wood to be light enough to be carried about on
the shoulders of priests. His face was inlaid with precious metals
and jewels. He was clothed in dazzling raiment, and usually
resided on a pedestal in a niche in a central chamber of his
house. The larger and more important god-houses had lesser
courts surrounded by rooms for the use of the steward-kings and
subsidiary priests.
In most of the great city sites excavated in Mesopotamia, the
house of a chief god was the ziggurat, a great rectangular tower,
rising by diminishing stages to a shining summit on which there
was a chapel. In the center of the ziggurat was the gigunu, a large
chamber in which most scholars believe the statue of the chief
god resided, but which others believe was used only for ritual
purposes. Such ziggurats or similar towering temple structures
are common to most of the bicameral kingdoms in some period.
Since the divine statue was the owner of the land and the
people were his tenants, the first duty of the steward-king was to
serve the god not only in the administration of the god's estates
but also in more personal ways. The gods, according to cuneiform texts, liked eating and drinking, music and dancing; they
required beds to sleep in and for enjoying sex with other godstatues on connubial visits from time to time; they had to be
washed and dressed, and appeased with pleasant odors; they had
to be taken out for drives on state occasions; and all these things
were done with increasing ceremony and ritual as time went on.
The daily ritual of the temple included the washing, dressing,
and feeding of the statues. The washing was probably done
through the sprinkling of pure water by attendant priests, the
origin, perhaps, of our christening and anointing ceremonies.
The dressing was by enrobing the figure in various ways. In
front of the god were tables, the origin of our altars, on one of
18o
The Witness of History
which flowers were placed, and on the other food and drink for
the divine hunger. Such food consisted of bread and cakes, the
flesh of bulls, sheep, goats, deer, fish, and poultry. According to
some interpretations of the cuneiform, the food was brought in
and then the statue-god was left to enjoy his meal alone. Then,
after a suitable period of time, the steward-king entered the
shrine room from a side entrance and ate what the god had
left.
The divine statues also had to be kept in good temper. This
was called "appeasing the liver" of the gods, and consisted in
offerings of butter, fat, honey, sweetmeats placed on the tables as
with regular food. Presumably, a person whose bicameral voice
was condemnatory and angry would come bringing such offerings
to the god's house.
How is all this possible, continuing as it did in some form for
thousands of years as the central focus of life, unless we posit
that the human beings heard the statues speak to them even as
the heroes of the Iliad heard their gods or Joan of Arc heard
hers? And indeed had to hear them speak to know what to do.
We can read this directly in the texts themselves. The great
Cylinder B of Gudea (about 2100 B.C.) describes how in a new
temple for his god Ningirsu, the priestesses placed
. . . the goddesses Zazaru, Impae, Urentaea, Khegirnunna,
Kheshagga, Guurmu, Zaarmu, who are the seven children of
the brood of Bau that were begotten by the lord Ningirsu, to
utter favorable decisions by the side of the lord Ningirsu.2
The particular decisions to be uttered here were about various
aspects of agriculture that the grain might "cover the banks of
the holy field5' and "all the rich graineries of Lagash to make to
2 Column 11, lines 4-14, as in George A. Barton, The Royal Inscriptions of
burner and Akkad (New Haven: American Oriental Society, 1929). Italics mine as in
quotations following.
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
181
overflow." And a clay cone from the dynasty of Larsa about 1700
B.C. praises the goddess Ninegal as
. . . counsellor, exceeding wise commander, princess of all
the great gods, exalted speaker, whose utterance is unrivaled. 3
Everywhere in these texts, it is the speech of gods who decide
what is to be done. A cone from Lagash reads:
Mesilin king of Kish at the command of his deity Kadi concerning the plantation of that field set up a stele in that place. Ush,
patesi of U m m a , incantations to seize it formed; that stele he
broke
in
pieces;
into
the
plain
of
Lagash
he
advanced.
Ningirsu, the hero of Enlil, by his righteous command, upon
U m m a war made.
snared.
At the command of Enlil his great net en-
Their burial mound on the plain in that place he
erected. 4
It is not the human beings who are the rulers, but the hallucinated voices of the gods Kadi, Ningirsu, and Enlil. Note that this
passage is about a stele, or stone column, engraved with a god's
words in cuneiform and set up in a field to tell how that field was
to be farmed. That such stelae themselves were epiphanous is
suggested by the way they were attacked and defended and
smashed or carried away. And that they were sources of auditory
hallucinations is suggested in other texts. One particularly pertinent passage from a different context describes reading a stele at
night:
T h e polished surface of its side his hearing makes known; its
writing which is engraved his hearing makes k n o w n ; the light
of the torch assists his hearing?
3 Ibid., p. 327.
4 Ibid
p. 61. Inim-ma is here translated as "incantations."
5 Ibid., p. 47.
182
The Witness of History
Reading in the third millennium B.C. may therefore have been a
matter of hearing the cuneiform, that is, hallucinating the speech
from looking at its picture-symbols, rather than visual reading of
syllables in our sense.
The word for ‘hearing’ here is a Sumerian sign that transliterates GIŠ-TUG-PI. Many other royal inscriptions state how the king
or other personage is endowed by some god with this GIŠ-TUG-PI
hearing which enables him to great things. Even as late as 1825
B.C., Warad-Sin, king of Larsa, claims in an inscription on a clay
cone that he rebuilt the city with GIŠ-TUG-PI DAGAL, or “hearing
everywhere” his god Enki. 6
The Mouth-Washing Ceremonies
Further evidence that such statues were aids to the hallucinated voices is found in other ceremonies all described precisely
and concretely on cuneiform tablets. The statue-gods were made
in the bit-mummu, a special divine craftsman’s house. Even the
craftsmen were directed in their work by a craftsman-god,
Mummuy who ‘dictated’ how to make the statue. Before being
installed in their shrines, the statues underwent mis-pi which
means mouth-washing, and the ritual of pit-pi or “opening of the
mouth.”
Not only when the statue was being made, but also periodically, particularly in the later bicameral era when the hallucinated voices may have become less frequent, an elaborate
washing-of-the-mouth ceremony could renew the god's speech.
The god with its face of inlaid jewels was carried by dripping
torchlight to the riverbank, and there, imbedded in ceremonies
and incantation, his wood mouth washed several times as the god
was faced east, west, north, and then south. The holy water with
which the mouth was washed out was a solution of a multitude of
exotic ingredients: tamarisks, reeds of various kinds, sulphur,
6 Ibid., p.
320.
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
183
various gums, salts, and oils, date honey, with various precious
stones. Then after more incantations, the god was "led by the
hand" back into the street with the priest incanting "foot that
advanceth, foot that advanceth . .
At the gate of the temple,
another ceremony was performed. The priest then took "the
hand" of the god and led him in to his throne in the niche, where
a golden canopy was set up and the statue's mouth washed again.7
Bicameral kingdoms should not be thought of as everywhere
the same or as not undergoing considerable development through
time. The texts from which the above information has come are
from approximately the late third millennium B.C. They may
therefore represent a late development of bicamerality in which
the very complexity of the culture could have been making the
hallucinated voices less clear and frequent, thus giving rise to
such a cleansing ritual in hope of rejuvenating the voice of the
god.
The Personal God
But it is not to be supposed that the ordinary citizen heard
directly the voices of the great gods who owned the cities; such
hallucinatory diversity would have weakened the political fabric.
He served the owner gods, worked their estates, took part in their
festivals. But he appealed to them only in some great crisis, and
then only through intermediaries. This is shown on countless
cylinder seals. A large proportion of the inventory type of cuneiform tablets have impressions on the reverse side rolled from
such seals; commonly, they show a seated god and another minor
divinity, usually a goddess, conducting the owner of the tablet
by the right hand into the divine presence.
Such intermediaries were the personal gods. Each individual,
king or serf, had his own personal god whose voice he heard and
7 See the translation of this text by Sidney Smith in the Journal of the Royal
Asiatic Society, January 1925, as quoted by S. H. Hooke, Babylonian and Assyrian
Religion (Norman: University of Oklahoma Press, 1963), pp. 118-121.
184
The Witness of History
obeyed.8 In almost every house excavated, there existed a shrineroom that probably contained idols or figurines as the inhabitant's
personal gods. Several late cuneiform texts describe rituals for
them similar to the mouth-washing ceremonies for the great
gods.9
These personal gods could be importuned to visit other gods
higher up in the divine hierarchy for some particular boon. Or, in
the other direction, strange as it seems to us: when the owner
gods had chosen a prince to be a steward-king, the city-god informed the appointee's personal god of the decision first, and only
then the individual himself. According to my discussion in I. 5,
all this layering was going on in the right hemisphere and I am
well aware of the problem of authenticity and group acceptance
of such selection. As elsewhere in antiquity, it was the personal
god who was responsible for what the king did, as it was for the
commoner.
Other cuneiform texts state that a man lived in the shadow of
his personal god, his Hi. So inextricably were a man and his personal god bound together that the composition of his personal
name usually included the name of the personal god, thus making obvious the bicameral nature of the man. It is of considerable
interest when the name of the king is indicated as the personal
god: Rim-Sin-Ili, which means "Rim-Sin is my god," Rim-Sin
being a king of Larsa, or, more simply, Sharru-Ili, "the king is
my god." 10 These instances suggest that the steward-king himself
could sometimes be hallucinated.
When the King Becomes a God
This possibility shows that the distinction I have made between
the steward-king type of theocracy and the god-king is not an
8 Thorkild Jacobsen has felt that the personal god "appears as the personification
of a man's luck and success." I am insisting that this is an unwarranted modern
imposition. See his "Mesopotamia," in The Intellectual Adventure of Ancient Man,
H. Frankfort, et al., eds. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1946), p. 203.
9 Saggs, p. 301f.
10 Frankfort et al., p. 306.
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
185
absolute one. Moreover, on several cuneiform tablets, a number
of the earlier Mesopotamian kings have beside their names the
eight-pointed star which is the determinative sign indicating
deity. In one early text, eleven out of a larger number of kings of
Ur and Isin are given this or another divine determinative. A
number of theories have been proposed as to what this means,
none of them very gripping.
The clues to look at are, I think, that the divine determinative
is often given to these kings only late in their reigns, and then
only in certain of their cities. This may mean that the voice of a
particularly powerful king may have been heard in hallucination
but only by a certain proportion of his people, only after he had
reigned for some time, and only in certain places.
Yet even in these instances, there seems throughout Mesopotamia a significant and continuing distinction between such
divine kings and the gods proper.11 But this is not at all true of
Egypt, to which we now turn.
EGYPT:
THE
KINGS
AS
GODS
The great basin of the Euphrates and Tigris rivers looses its
identity, feature by feature, into the limitless deserts of Arabia
and the gradual foothills of the mountain chains of Persia and
Armenia. But Egypt, except in the south, is clearly defined by
bilaterally symmetrical immutable frontiers. A pharaoh extending his authority in the Nile Valley soon reached what he might
raid but never conquer. And thus Egypt was always more uniform both geographically and ethnologically, both in space and in
time. Its people through the ages were also of a remarkably
similar physique, as has been shown from studies of remaining
skulls.12 It is this protected homogeneity, I suggest, which alSaggs, p. 343f.
G. M. Morant, "Study of Egyptian craniology from prehistoric to Roman times,"
Biometrika, 1925, 17: 1-52.
11
12
186
The Witness of History
lowed the perpetuation of that more archaic form of theocracy,
the god-king.
The Memphite Theology
Let us begin with the famous "Memphite Theology." 1 3 This is
an eighth-century B.C. granite block on which a previous work
(presumably a rotting leather roll of around 3000 B.C.) was
copied. It begins with a reference to a "creator" god Ptah, proceeds through the quarrels of the gods Horus and Seth and their
arbitration by Geb, describes the construction of the royal godhouse at Memphis, and then, in a famous final section, states that
the various gods are variations of Ptah's voice or "tongue."
Now when "tongue" here is translated as something like the
"objectified conceptions of his mind," as it so often is, this is
surely an imposing of modern categories upon the texts.14 Ideas
such as objectified conceptions of a mind, or even the notion of
something spiritual being manifested, are of much later development. It is generally agreed that the ancient Egyptian language,
like the Sumerian, was concrete from first to last. To maintain
that it is expressing abstract thoughts would seem to me an
intrusion of the modern idea that men have always been the
same. Also, when the Memphite Theology speaks of the tongue
or voices as that from which everything was created, I suspect
that the very word "created" may also be a modern imposition, and
the more proper translation might be commanded. This theology, then, is essentially a myth about language, and what Ptah is
really commanding is indeed the bicameral voices which began,
controlled, and directed Egyptian civilization.
13 In addition to texts otherwise cited, I have used for this part of the chapter
John A. Wilson, The Culture of Ancient Egypt (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1951); Cyril Aldred, Egypt to the End of the Old Kingdom (New York:
McGraw-Hill, 1965); W. W. Hallo and W. K. Simpson, The Ancient Near East: A
History (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1971).
14 Henri Frankfort, Kingship and the Gods (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1948), p. 28.
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
187
Osiris} the Dead King's Voice
There has been some astonishment that mythology and reality
should be so mixed that the heavenly contention of Horus and
Seth is over real land, and that the figure of Osiris in the last
section has a real grave in Memphis, and also that each king at
death becomes Osiris, just as each king in life is Horus. If it is
assumed that all of these figures are particular voice hallucinations heard by kings and their next in rank, and that the voice of
a king could continue after his death and 'be' the guiding voice of
the next, and that the myths about various contentions and relationships with other gods are attempted rationalizations of conflicting admonitory authoritative voices mingled with the
authoritative structure in the actuality of the society, at least we
are given a new way to look at the subject.
Osiris, to go directly to the important part of this, was not a
"dying god," not "life caught in the spell of death," or "a dead
god," as modern interpreters have said. He was the hallucinated
voice of a dead king whose admonitions could still carry weight.
And since he could still be heard, there is no paradox in the fact
that the body from which the voice once came should be mummified, with all the equipment of the tomb providing life's necessities: food, drink, slaves, women, the lot. There was no
mysterious power that emanated from him; simply his remembered voice which appeared in hallucination to those who had
known him and which could admonish or suggest even as it had
before he stopped moving and breathing. And that various natural phenomena such as the whispering of waves could act as the
cue for such hallucinations accounts for the belief that Osiris, or
the king whose body has ceased to move and is in his mummy
cloths, continues to control the flooding of the Nile. Further, the
relationship between Horus and Osiris, 'embodied' in each new
king and his dead father forever, can only be understood as the
assimilation of an hallucinated advising voice into the king's own
voice, which then would be repeated with the next generation.
188
The Witness of History
Mansions for Voices
That the voice and therefore the power of a god-king lived on
after his body stopped moving and breathing is certainly suggested by the manner of his burial. Yet burial is the wrong word.
Such divine kings were not morosely entombed, but gaily empalaced. Once the art of building with stone was mastered shortly
after 3000 B.C., what once had been the stepped matsaba tombs
leap up into those playhouses of bicameral voices in immortal life
we call the pyramids: complexes of festive courts and galleries
merry with holy pictures and writing, often surrounded by acres
of the graves of the god's servants, and dominated by the god's
pyramidal house itself, soaring sunward like a shining ziggurat
with an almost too confident exterior austerity, and built with an
integrity that did not scruple to use the hardest of stones, polished basalts, granites, and diorites, as well as alabaster and
limestone.
The psychology of all this is yet to be uncovered. So seriously
has the evidence been torn away by collectors of all ranks of guilt
that the whole question may be forever wrapped in unanswerableness. For the unmoving mummy of the god-king is often in a
curiously plain sarcophagus, while the gaudy effigies made of
him are surrounded with a different reverence — perhaps because it was from them that the hallucinations seemed to come.
Like the god-statues of Mesopotamia they were life-sized or
larger, sometimes elaborately painted, usually with jewels for eyes
long since hacked out of their sockets by conscious nonhallucinating
robbers. But unlike their eastern cousins, they did not have to be
moved and so were finely chiseled out of limestone, slate, diorite,
or other stone, and only in certain eras carved from wood. Usually, they were set permanently in niches, some seated, some
standing free, some in multiples of the god-king in standing or
seated rows, and some walled up in small chapels called serdabs
with two small eyeholes in front of the jewel-eyes so that the god
could see out into the room before him, where there were offer-
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
189
ings of food and treasure and we know not what else, so have
these tombs been plundered. Occasionally the actual voices hallucinated from the deceased god-king came to be written down as
in "The Instructions which the Majesty of King Amenemhet I
justified, gave when he spoke in a dream-revelation to his son."
The commoner also was buried in a manner as if he still lived.
The peasant since predynastic times had been buried with pots
of food, tools, and offerings for his continued life. Those higher
in the social hierachy were given a funeral feast in which the
corpse itself somehow took part. Scenes showing the deceased
eating at his own funerary table came to be carved on slabs and
set into a niche in the wall of the grave-mound or mastaba. Later
graves elaborated this into stone-lined chambers with painted
reliefs and serdabs with statues and offerings as in the pyramids
proper.
Often, "true-of-voice" was an epithet added to the name of a
dead person. This is difficult to understand apart from the present
theory. "True-of-voice" originally applied to Osiris and Horus
with reference to their victories over their opponents.
Letters too were written to the dead as if they still lived.
Probably this occurred only after some time when the person so
addressed could no longer be 'heard' in hallucinations. A man
writes his dead mother asking her to arbitrate between himself
and his dead brother. How is this possible unless the living
brother had been hearing his dead brother in hallucination? Or a
dead man is begged to awaken his ancestors to help his widow
and child. These letters are private documents dealing with
everyday matters, and are free of official doctrine or makebelieve.
A New Theory of the Ka
If we could say that ancient Egypt had a psychology, we would
then have to say that its fundamental notion is the ka, and the
problem becomes what the ka is. Scholars struggling with the
The Witness of History
190
meaning of this particularly disturbing concept, which we find
constantly in Egyptian inscriptions, have translated it in a litter
of ways, as spirit, ghost, double, vital force, nature, luck, destiny,
and what have you. It has been compared to the life-spirit of the
Semites and Greeks, as well as to the genius of the Romans. But
obviously, these later concepts are the hand-me-downs of the
bicameral mind. Nor can this slippery diversity of meanings be
explained by positing an Egyptian mentality in which words were
used in several ways as approaches to the same mysterious entity,
or by assuming "the peculiar quality of Egyptian thought which
allows an object to be understood not by a single and consistent
definition, but by various and unrelated approaches."15 None of
this is satisfactory.
The evidence from hieratic texts is confusing. Each person
has his ka and speaks of it as we might of our will power. Yet
when one dies, one goes to one's ka. In the famous Pyramid
Texts around 2200 B.C., the dead are called "masters of their
ka's." The symbol in hieroglyphics for the ka is one of admonishing: two arms uplifted with flat outspread hands, the whole
placed upon a stand which in hieroglyphics is only used to support the symbols of divinities.
It is obvious from the preceding chapters that the ka requires a
reinterpretation as a bicameral voice. It is, I believe, what the ili
or personal god was in Mesopotamia. A man's ka was his articulate directing voice which he heard inwardly, perhaps in parental
or authoritative accents, but which when heard by his friends or
relatives even after his own death, was, of course, hallucinated as
his own voice.
If we can here relax our insistence upon the unconsciousness
of these people, and, for a moment, imagine that they were
something like ourselves, we could imagine a worker out in the
fields suddenly hearing the ka or hallucinated voice of the vizier
over him admonishing him in some way. If, after he returned to
15
Ibid., p. 61.
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
191
his city, he told the vizier that he had heard the vizier's ka
(which in actuality there would be no reason for his doing), the
vizier, were he conscious as are we, would assume that it was the
same voice that he himself heard and which directed his life.
Whereas in actuality, to the worker in the fields, the vizier's ka
sounded like the vizier's own voice. While to the vizier himself,
his ka would speak in the voices of authorities over him, or some
amalgamation of them. And, of course, the discrepancy could
never be discovered.
Consistent with this interpretation are several other aspects of
the ka. The Egyptians' attitude toward the ka is entirely passive.
Just as in the case of the Greek gods, hearing it is tantamount to
obeying it. It empowers what it commands. Courtiers in some of
their inscriptions referring to the king say, "I did what his ka
loved" or "I did that which his ka approved," 16 which may be
interpreted as the courtier hearing the hallucinated voice of his
king approving his work.
In some texts it is said that the king makes a man's ka, and
some scholars translate ka in this sense as fortune.17 Again, this
is a modern imposition. A concept such as fortune or success is
impossible in the bicameral culture of Egypt. What is meant here
according to my reading is that the man acquires an admonitory
hallucinated voice which then can direct him in his work. Frequently the ka crops up in names of Egyptian officials as did the
ili with Mesopotamian officials. Kaininesut, "my ka belongs to
the king," or Kainesut, "the king is my ka." 18 In the Cairo
Museum, stela number 20538 says, "the king gives his servants
Ka's and feeds those who are faithful."
The ka of the god-king is of particular interest. It was heard, I
suggest, by the king in the accents of his own father. But it was
Ibid., p. 68.
But see Alan H. Gardiner, Egyptian Grammar (Oxford, 1957), p. 172, note 12.
18 Frankfort, p. 68; cf. also John A. Wilson, "Egypt: the values of life," Ch. 4
in Frankfort, et al., p. 97.
16
17
192
The Witness of History
heard in the hallucinations of his courtiers as the king's own
voice, which is the really important thing. Texts state that when a
king sat at a meal and ate, his ka sat and ate with him. The
pyramids are full of false doors, sometimes simply painted on the
limestone walls, through which the deceased god-king's ka could
pass out into the world and be heard. It is only the king's ka
which is pictured on monuments, sometimes as a standard bearer
holding the staff of the king's head and the feather, or as a bird
perched behind the king's head. But most significant are the
representations of the king's ka as his twin in birth scenes. In
one such scene, the god Khnum is shown forming the king and
his ka on his potter's wheel. They are identical small figures
except that the ka has his left , hand pointing to his mouth,
obviously suggesting that he is what we might describe as a
persona of speech.19
Perhaps evidence for a growing complexity in all this are
several texts from the eighteenth dynasty or 1500 B.C. onward,
The god Khnum forming the
future king with the right hand
and the king's ka with the left
on the potter's wheel. Note that
the ka points with its left hand
to
its
mouth,
indicating
its
verbal function. T h e lateralization throughout is in accordance
with the neurological model presented in I.5.
19 Illustrated in Figure 23 in Frankfort.
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
193
which casually say that the king has fourteen ka's! This very
perplexing statement may indicate that the structure of the government had become so complicated that the king's hallucinated
voice was heard as fourteen different voices, these being the
voices of intermediaries between the king and those who were
carrying out his orders directly. The notion of the king having
fourteen ka's is inexplicable by any other notion of what a ka is.
Each king then is Horus, his father dead becoming Osiris, and
has his ka, or in later ages, his several ka's, which could best be
translated now as voice-persona. An understanding of this is
essential for the understanding of the entire Egyptian culture
since the relation of king, god, and people is defined by means of
the ka. The king's ka is, of course, the ka of a god, operates as
his messenger, to himself is the voice of his ancestors, and to his
underlings is the voice they hear telling them what to do. And
when a subject in some of the texts says, "my ka derives from the
king" or "the king makes my ka" or "the king is my ka," this
should be interpreted as an assimilation of the person's inner
directing voice, derived perhaps from his parents, with the voice
or supposed voice of the king.
Another related concept in ancient Egyptian mentality is the
ba. But at least in the Old Kingdom, the ba is not really on the
same level as the ka. It is more like our common ghost, a visual
manifestation of what auditorily is the ka. In funerary scenes,
the ba is usually depicted as a small humanoid bird, probably
because visual hallucinations often have flitting and birdlike
movements. It is usually drawn attendant on or in relationship to
the actual corpse or to statues of the person. That after the fall
of the more king-dominated Old Kingdom, the ba takes on some
of the bicameral functions of the ka is indicated by a change in its
hieroglyph from a small bird to one beside a lamp (to lead the
way), and by its auditory hallucinatory role in the famous Papyrus Berlin 3024, which dates about 1900 B.C. A l l translations of
this astounding text are full of modern mental impositions, in-
194
The Witness of History
eluding the most recent,20 otherwise a fascinating chore of
scholarship. And no commentator has dared to take this "Dispute
of a man with his Ba" at face value, as a dialogue with an
auditory hallucination, much like that of a contemporary schizophrenic.
THE
TEMPORAL CHANGES
THEOCRACIES
IN
In the previous chapter, I stressed the uniformities among bicameral kingdoms, the large central worshiping places, treatment of
the dead as if they were still living, and the presence of idols. But
over and beyond these grosser aspects of ancient civilizations are
many subtleties which space has not permitted me to mention.
For just as we know that cultures and civilizations can be strikingly different, so we must not assume that the bicameral mind
resulted in precisely the same thing everywhere it occurred. Differences in populations, ecologies, priests, hierarchies, idols, industries, all would, I think, result in profound differences in the
authority, frequency, ubiquity, and affect of hallucinatory control.
In this chapter, on the other hand, I have been making my
emphasis the differences between the two greatest of such civilizations. But I have been speaking of them as if unchanging over
time. And this is untrue. To give the impression of a static
stability through time and space of bicameral theocracies is entirely mistaken. And I would like to redress the balance in this
last section of this chapter by mentioning the changes and differences in the structure of bicameral kingdoms.
The Complexities
The most obvious fact of theocracies is their success in a
biological sense. Populations were continually increasing. As
20 Hans Goedicke, The Report About the Dispute of a Man with his Ba, Papyrus
Berlin 3024 (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press, 1970).
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
195
they did so, problems of social control by hallucinations called
gods became more and more complex. The structuring of such
control in a village of a few hundred back at Eynan in the ninth
millennium B.C. is obviously enormously different from what it
was in the civilizations we have just discussed with their hierarchical layer of gods, priests, and officers.
Indeed, I suggest that there is a built-in periodicity to bicameral
theocracies, that the complexities of hallucinatory control with
their very success increase until the civil state and civilized relations can no longer be sustained, and the bicameral society collapses. As I noted in the previous chapter, this occurred many
times in the pre-Columbian civilizations of America, whole populations suddenly deserting their cities, with no external cause,
and anarchically melting back into tribal living in surrounding
terrain, but returning to their cities and their gods a century or so
later.
In the millennia we have been looking at in this chapter, the
complexities were apparently mounting. Many of the ceremonies
and practices I have described were initiated as ways of reducing
this complexity. Even in writing, the first pictographs were to
label and list and sort out. And some of the first syntactical
writing speaks of the overpopulation. The Sumerian epic known
to us as Atrahasis bursts open with the problem:
T h e people became numerous . . .
T h e god was depressed by their uproar
Enlil heard their noise,
He exclaimed to the great gods
T h e noise of mankind has become burdensome . . . 2 1
as if the voices were having difficulty. The epic goes on to describe how the great gods send plagues, famines, and finally a
great flood (the origin of the story of the Biblical flood) to get rid
of some of the "black headed ones" as the Mesopotamian gods
disparagingly referred to their human slaves.
21 Quoted by Saggs, Greatness That Was Babylon, pp. 384-385.
196
The Witness of History
The apparatus of divinity was becoming strained. In the early
millennia of the bicameral age, life had been simpler, confined to
a small area, with a simpler political organization, and the
needed gods were then few. But as we approach and continue
through to the end of the third millennium B.C., the tempo and
complexity of social organization demand a far greater number
of decisions in a far greater number of contexts in any week or
month. And hence, the enormous proliferation of deities which
could be invoked in whatever situation a man might find himself.
From the great god-houses of the Sumerian and Babylonian
cities of the major gods, to the personal gods enchapeled in each
household, the world must have literally swarmed with sources of
hallucination, and hence the increasing need for priests to order
them into strict hierarchies. There were gods for everything one
might do. One finds, for example, the coming into existence of
obviously popular wayside shrines, such as the Pa-Sag Chapel
where the statue-god Pa-Sag helped in making decisions about
journeys through the desert.22
The response of these Near Eastern theocracies to this increasing complexity is both different and extremely illuminating. In
Egypt, the older god-king form of government is less resilient,
less developing of human potential, less allowing of innovation,
of individuality among subordinate domains. Yet it stretched out
for huge distances along the Nile. Regardless of what theory of
civil cohesion one may hold, there is no doubt that in the last
century of the third millennium B.C., all authority in Egypt broke
down. There may have been a triggering cause in some geological catastrophe: some ancient texts referring back to the period
of 2100 B.C. seem to speak of the Nile becoming dry, of men
crossing it on foot, of the sun being hidden, of crops being diminished. Whatever the immediate cause, the pyramid of authority
headed by the god-king at Memphis simply collapsed at about
22 According to cuneiform tablets found by Sir Leonard Woolley in association
with Pa-Sag's rather poorly carved limestone effigy. See C. L. Woolley, Excavations
at Ur: A Record of Twelve Years Work (London: Benn, 1954), pp. 190-192.
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
197
that time. Literary sources describe people fleeing towns, noblemen grubbing for food in the fields, brothers fighting, men killing
their parents, pyramids and tombs ransacked. Scholars are insistent that this total disappearance of authority was due to no
outside force but to some unfathomable internal weakness. And I
suggest that this is indeed the weakness of the bicameral mind,
its fragility in the face of increasing complexity, and that the
collapse of authority in so absolute a manner can only be so
understood. Egypt at the time had extremely important separated districts stretching from the delta to the upper Nile that
could have been self-sustaining. But the very fact that in the
midst of this anarchy there was no rebellion, no striving of these
sections for independence is, I think, indicative of a very different
mentality from our own.
This breakdown of the bicameral mind in what is called the
Intermediate Period is reminiscent at least of those periodic
breakdowns of Mayan civilizations when all authority suddenly
collapsed, and the population melted back into tribal living in the
jungles. And just as the Maya cities became inhabited again or
new ones formed after a period of breakdown, so Egypt after less
then a century of breakdown has unified itself at the beginning of
the second millennium under a new god-king, beginning what is
called the Middle Kingdom. The same breakdown occurred elsewhere in the Near East from time to time, as in Assur about 1700
B.C., as we shall see in the next chapter.
The Idea of Law
But nothing of this extent ever happens in southern Mesopotamia. Of course there are wars. City-states fought each other
over whose god and therefore which steward was to rule over
which fields. But there was never any total collapse of authority
as occurred in Mesoamerica and in Egypt at the end of the Old
Kingdom.
One of the reasons, I think, was the greater resiliency of the
198
The Witness of History
steward-king type of theocracy. And another, not unconnected
reason was the use to which writing was put. Unlike in Egypt,
writing in Mesopotamia was early put to civil use. By 2100 B.C.
in Ur, the judgments of gods through their steward mediums
began to be recorded. This is the beginning of the idea of law.
Such written judgments could be in several places and be continuous through time, thus allowing the cohesiveness of a larger
society. We know of nothing similar in Egypt until almost a
millennium later.
In 1792 B.C., the civil use of writing in this way breaks open an
almost new kind of government in that commanding figure of
Mesopotamian history, the greatest of all steward kings, Hammurabi, steward of Marduk, the city god of Babylon. His long
stewardship, lasting to 1750 B.C., is a pulling together of most of
the city-states of Mesopotamia into an hegemony under his god
Marduk in Babylon. This process of conquest and influence is
made possible by letters and tablets and stelae in an abundance
that had never been known before. It is even thought that he was
the first literate king who did not need a scribe, since all his
cuneiform letters are apparently incised in wet clay by the same
hand. Writing was a new method of civil direction, indeed the
model that begins our own memo-communicating government.
Without it such a unification of Mesopotamia could not have
been accomplished. It is a method of social control which by
hindsight we know will soon supplant the bicameral mind.
His most famous remains are the somewhat overinterpreted
and perhaps misnamed Code of Hammurabi.23 Originally, it was
an eight-foot-high black basalt stele erected at the end of his
reign beside a statue or possibly idol of himself. So far as we can
make out, someone seeking redress from another would come to
the steward's statue, to "hear my words" (as the stele says at the
bottom), and then move over to the stele itself, where the previ23 For a translation I have used Robert Francis Harper, The Code of Hammurabi,
King of Babylon (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1904).
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
199
Hammurabi hallucinating judgments from his god Marduk (or
possibly Shamash) as carved on the top of a stele listing those judgments. About 1750 B.C.
ous judgments of the steward's god are recorded. His god, as I
have said, was Marduk, and the top of the stele is sculptured to
depict the scene of judgment-giving. The god is seated on a
raised mound which in Mesopotamian graphics symbolizes a
mountain. An aura of flames flashes up from his shoulders as he
speaks (which has made some scholars think it is Shamash, the
sun-god). Hammurabi listens intently as he stands just below
him ("under-stands"). The god holds in his right hand the attributes of power, the rod and circle very common to such divine
depictions. With these symbols, the god is just touching the left
elbow of his steward, Hammurabi. One of the magnificent things
about this scene is the hypnotic assurance with which both god
and steward-king intently stare at each other, impassively majestic, the steward-king's right hand held up between us, the observers, and the plane of communication. Here is no humility, no
begging before a god, as occurs just a few centuries later. Ham-
200
The Witness of History
murabi has no subjective-self to narratize into such a relationship. There is only obedience. And what is being dictated by
Marduk are judgments on a series of very specific cases.
As written on the stele beneath this sculptured relief, the
judgments of Marduk are sandwiched in between an introduction
and an epilogue by Hammurabi himself. Here with pomp and
fury he boasts of his deeds, his power, his intimacy with Marduk,
describes the conquests he has made for Marduk, the reason for
the setting up of this stele, and ends with dire implications as to
the evil that will befall anyone who scratches out his name. In
vainglory and naivete both prologue and epilogue remind us of
the Iliad.
But in between are the 282 quiet pronouncements of the god.
They are serenely reasoned decisions about the apportioning of
commodities among different occupations, how house slaves or
thieves or unruly sons were punished, the eye-for-an-eye-andtooth-for-a-tooth kind of recompensing, judgments about gifts
and deaths and adopting children (which seems to have been a
considerable practice), and of marriage and servants and slaves
— all in a cold economy of words in contrast to the bellicose
blustering of the prologue and epilogue. Indeed they sound like
two very different 'men' and in the bicameral sense I think they
were. They were two separately integrated organizations of
Hammurabi's nervous system, one of them in the left hemisphere
writing the prologue and epilogue and standing in effigy at the
side of the stele, and the other in the right hemisphere composing
judgments. And neither of them was conscious in our sense.
While the stele itself is clearly evidence for the bicameral
mind in some form, the problems to which the god's words are
addressed are indeed complex. It is very difficult to imagine
doing the things that these laws say men did in the eighteenth
century B.C. without having a subjective consciousness in which
to plan and devise, deceive and hope. But it should be remembered how rudimentary all this was and how misleading our
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
201
modern words can be. The word that is incorrectly translated as
"money" or even as "loan" is simply kaspu, meaning silver. It
cannot mean money in our sense since no coins have ever been
found. Similarly, what has been translated as rents is really
tithing, an agreement marked on a clay tablet to return a portion
of the produce of a field to its owner. Wine was not so much
purchased as exchanged, one measure of wine for one measure
of grain. And the use of some modern banking terms in some
translations is downright inaccurate. As I have mentioned before, in many translations of cuneiform material, there is the
constant attempt on the part of scholars to impose modern categories of thought on these ancient cultures in order to make them
more familiar and therefore supposedly more interesting to modern readers.
These rules of the stele should not be thought of in the modern
terms of laws which are enforced by police, something unknown
at that time. Rather they are lists of practices in Babylon itself,
the statements of Marduk, which needed no more enforcement
than their authenticity on the stele itself.
The fact that they were written down and, more generally, the
wide use of visual writing for communication indicate, I think, a
reduction in the auditory hallucinatory control of the bicameral
mind. Together, they put into motion cultural determinants
which, coming together with other forces a few centuries later,
resulted in a change in the very structure of the mind itself.
Let me summarize.
I have endeavored in these two chapters to examine the record
of a huge time span to reveal the plausibility that man and his
early civilizations had a profoundly different mentality from our
own, that in fact men and women were not conscious as are we,
were not responsible for their actions, and therefore cannot be
given the credit or blame for anything that was done over these
vast millennia of time; that instead each person had a part of his
202
The Witness of History
nervous system which was divine, by which he was ordered about
like any slave, a voice or voices which indeed were what we call
volition and empowered what they commanded and were related
to the hallucinated voices of others in a carefully established
hierarchy.
The total pattern, I suggest, is in agreement with such a view.
It is, of course, not conclusive. However, the astonishing consistency from Egypt to Peru, from Ur to Yucatan, wherever civilizations arose, of death practices and idolatry, of divine government
and hallucinated voices, all are witness to the idea of a different
mentality from our own.
But it would be an error, as I have tried to show, to regard the
bicameral mind as a static thing. True, it developed from the
ninth millennium B.C. to the second millennium B.C. with the
slowness that makes any single century seem as static as its
ziggurats and temples. Millennia are its units of time. But the
tempo of development at least in the Near East picks up as we
reach the second millennium B.C. The gods of Akkad, like the
ka's of Egypt, have multiplied in complexity. And as this complexity develops, there is the first unsureness, the first need for
personal gods to intercede with the higher gods, who seem to be
receding into the heavens where in one brief millennium they
will have disappeared.
From the royal corpse propped up on its stones under its red
parapet in Eynan, still ruling its Natufian village in the hallucinations of its subjects, to the mighty beings that cause thunder
and create worlds and finally disappear into heavens, the gods
were at the same time a mere side effect of language evolution
and the most remarkable feature of the evolution of life since the
development of Homo sapiens himself. I do not mean this simply
as poetry. The gods were in no sense 'figments of the imagination' of anyone. They were man's volition. They occupied his
nervous system, probably his right hemisphere, and from stores
of admonitory and preceptive experience, transmuted this experi-
LITERATE
BICAMERAL
THEOCRACIES
203
ence into articulated speech which then 'told' the man what to do.
That such internally heard speech often needed to be primed
with the props of the dead corpse of a chieftain or the gilded
body of a jewel-eyed statue in its holy house, of that I have really
said nothing. It too requires an explanation. I have by no means
dared the bottom of the matter, and it is only to be hoped that
complete and more correct translations of existing texts and the
increasing tempo of archaeological excavation will give us a truer
understanding of these long long millennia which civilized mankind.
CHAPTER 3
The Causes of Consciousness
A
has been translated as “Act
promptly, make your god happy.” 1 If we forget for a moment that these rich English words are but a probing approximation of some more unknowable Sumerian thing, we may say that
this curious exaction arches over into our subjective mentality as
saying, “Don’t think: let there be no time space between hearing
your bicameral voice and doing what it tells you.”
N
OLD
SUMERIAN
PROVERB
This was fine in a stable hierarchical organization, where the
voices were the always correct and essential parts of that hierarchy, where the divine orders of life were trussed and girdered
with unversatile ritual, untouched by major social disturbance.
But the second millennium B.C. was not to last that way. Wars,
catastrophes, national migrations became its central themes.
Chaos darkened the holy brightnesses of the unconscious world.
Hierarchies crumpled. And between the act and its divine source
came the shadow, the pause that profaned, the dreadful loosening that made the gods unhappy, recriminatory, jealous. Until,
finally, the screening off of their tyranny was effected by the
invention on the basis of language of an analog space with an
analog ‘I’. The careful elaborate structures of the bicameral mind
had been shaken into consciousness.
These are the momentous themes of the present chapter.
*
*
*
*
1 Proverb 1:145 in Edmund I. Gordon, Sumerian Proverbs (Philadelphia: University Museum, 1959), p. 113.
THE
CAUSES
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
205
The Instability of Bicameral Kingdoms
In the contemporary world, we associate rigid authoritarian
governments with militarism and police repression. This association should not be applied to the authoritarian states of the
bicameral era. Militarism, police, rule by fear, are all the desperate measures used to control a subjective conscious populace
restless with identity crises and divided off into their multitudinous privacies of hopes and hates.
In the bicameral era, the bicameral mind was the social control, not fear or repression or even law. There were no private
ambitions, no private grudges, no private frustrations, no private
anything, since bicameral men had no internal ‘space’ in which to
be private, and no analog
to be private with. All initiative was
in the voices of gods. And the gods needed to be assisted by their
divinely dictated laws only in the late federations of states in the
second millennium B.C.
Within each bicameral state, therefore, the people were probably more peaceful and friendly than in any civilization since.
But at the interfaces between different bicameral civilizations,
the problems were complex and quite different.
Let us consider a meeting between two individuals from two
different bicameral cultures. Let us assume they do not know
each other’s language and are owned by different gods. The
manner of such meetings would be dependent upon the kind of
admonitions, warnings, and importunings with which the individual had been reared.
In peaceful times, with the god of the city basking in prosperity, the human tilling of his fields, the harvesting, storing, and
sorting out of his produce all going on without hitch or question,
as in a colony of ants, it could be expected that his divine voice
would be basically amicable, and that indeed all man’s voicevisions would tend to be beautiful and peaceful, exaggerating the
very harmony this method of social control was evolved to preserve.
206
The Witness of History
Thus, if the bicameral theocracies of both individuals meeting
have been unthreatened for their generation, both their directive
gods would be composed of friendly voices. The result may have
been a tentative exchange of gestural greetings and facial expressions that might grow to friendship, or even an exchange of gifts.
For we can be very certain that the relative rarity of each other's
possessions (coming from different cultures) would make such
an exchange mutually wished for.
This is probably how trade began. The beginning of such
exchanges goes back to food sharing in the family group which
grew into exchanges of goods and produce within the same city.
Just as the harvested grain of the first agricultural settlements
had to be doled out by certain god-given rules, so, as labor became
more specialized, other products, wine, adornments, clothes, and
the building of houses, all had to have their god-set equivalents to
each other.
Trade between different peoples is simply the extension of
such exchanging of goods to another kingdom. Texts from 2500
B.C. found in Sumer speak of such exchanging as far away as the
Indus Valley. And the recent discovery of a new city site at Tepe
Yahya, halfway between Sumer and the Indus Valley, at the
mouth of the Persian Gulf, whose artifacts clearly indicate that it
was the main source of steatite or soapstone, used for utensils
extensively in Mesopotamia, establish it as a center of exchange
between these bicameral kingdoms.2 Small two-inch-square tablets have been found with counting marks on them which were
probably simple exchange rates. All this was during a peaceful
era in the middle of the third millennium B.C. I shall suggest
later that extensive exchanging of goods between bicameral theocracies may in itself have weakened the bicameral structure that
made civilization possible.
Now let us return to our two individuals from different cultures. We have been discussing what occurs in a peaceful world
2 New
York Times, December 20, 1970, p. 53.
THE
CAUSES
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
207
with peaceful gods. But what if the opposite were the case? If
both came from threatened cultures, both would probably hear
warlike hallucinated voices directing each to kill the other,
whereupon hostilities would follow. But the same result would
happen if either came from a threatened culture, putting the
other into a posture of defense, as either the same god or another
directed him as well to engage in fighting.
There is thus no middle ground in intertheocracy relations.
Admonitory voices echoing kings, viziers, parents, etc., are unlikely to command individuals into acts of compromise. Even
today, our ideas of nobility are largely residues of bicameral
authority: it is not noble to whine, it is not noble to plead, it is not
noble to beg, even though these postures are really the most
moral of ways to settle differences. And hence the instability of
the bicameral world, and the fact that during the bicameral era
boundary relations would, I think, be more likely to end in all-out
friendship or all-out hostility than anything between these
extremes.
Nor is this the bottom of the matter. The smooth working of a
bicameral kingdom has to rest on its authoritarian hierarchy.
And once the priestly or secular hierarchy is disputed or upset,
its effects would be exaggerated in a way that in a police state
would not occur. Once cities become a certain size, as we have
already seen, the bicameral control must be extremely precarious. The hierarchy of priests to sort out the various voices and
give them their recognitions must have become a major preoccupation as bicameral cities grew in size. One jar to this balance of
human and hallucinated authority, and, like a house of cards, the
whole thing might collapse. As I have mentioned in both previous chapters, such theocracies occasionally did indeed suddenly
collapse without any known external cause.
In comparison with conscious nations, then, bicameral nations
were more susceptible to collapse. The directives of gods are
limited. If on top of this inherent fragility, something really new
208
The Witness of History
occurred, such as a forced intermingling of bicameral peoples,
the gods would be hard pressed to sort anything out in a peaceable way.
The Weakening of Divine Authority with Writing
These limitations of gods were both relieved and greatly
exacerbated in the second millennium B.C. by the success of
writing. On the one hand, writing could allow a civil structure
such as that of Hammurabi to remain stable. But, on the other, it
was gradually eroding the auditory authority of the bicameral
mind. More and more, the accountings and messages of government were placed in cuneiform tablets particularly. Whole libraries of them are still being discovered. Letters of officials
became a commonplace. By 1500 B.C., even miners high in the
rocky wastes of Sinai incised their names and their relationships
to the goddess of the mine on its walls. 3
The input to the divine hallucinatory aspect of the bicameral
mind was auditory. It used cortical areas more closely connected
to the auditory parts of the brain. And once the word of god was
silent, written on dumb clay tablets or incised into speechless
stone, the god's commands or the king's directives could be
turned to or avoided by one's own efforts in a way that auditory
hallucinations never could be. The word of a god had a controllable location rather than an ubiquitous power with immediate
obedience. This is extremely important.
The Failure of the Gods
This loosening of the god-man partnership perhaps by trade
and certainly by writing was the background of what happened.
But the immediate and precipitate cause of the breakdown of the
3 Romain F. Butin, "The Sarabit Expedition of 1930: IV, The Protosinaitic Inscriptions." Harvard Theological Review, 1932, 25, pp. 130-204.
THE
CAUSES
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
209
bicameral mind, of the wedge of consciousness between god and
man, between hallucinated voice and automaton action, was that
in social chaos the gods could not tell you what to do. Or if they
did, they led to death, or at the intimate least to an increase in the
stress that physiologically occasioned the voice in the first place,
until voices came in an unsolvable Babel of confusion.
The historical context of all this was enormous. The second
millennium B.C. was heavy laden with profound and irreversible
changes. Vast geological catastrophes occurred. Civilizations
perished. Half the world’s population became refugees. And
wars, previously sporadic, came with hastening and ferocious
frequency as this important millennium hunched itself sickly into
its dark and bloody close.
It is a complex picture, the variables evoking these changes
multileveled, the facts as we have them now not at all certain.
Almost yearly they are revised as each new generation of archaeologists and ancient historians finds fault with its predecessors.
As an approximation to these complexities, let us look at the two
major elements of these upheavals. One was the mass migrations and invasions of peoples all around the eastern Mediterranean due to the volcanic eruption of Thera, and the other was the
rise of Assyria, in three great phases, warring its way reign by
reign westward to Egypt, northward to the Caspian, incorporating all of Mesopotamia, forming a very different kind of empire
from any that the world had known before.
The Assyrian Spring
Let us first look at the situation in northern Mesopotamia
around the city that belongs to the god Ashur, as the second
millennium B.C. opens.4 Originally a part of Akkad, and then of
Old Babylonia two hundred miles south, by 1950 B.C., this peace4 For the overall contours of Assyrian history I have relied on various authorities,
but particularly H. W. F. Saggs, The Greatness That Was Babylon (New York:
Mentor Books, 1962) ; and various articles by William F. Albright.
210
The Witness of History
ful bicameral city on an upper reach of the gentle Tigris has been
left pretty much to itself. Under the guidance of Ashur's chief
human servant, Puzen-Ashur I, its benign influence and wealth
begin to expand. More than in any nation before it, the feature of
that expansion is exchange of goods with other theocracies.
About two hundred years later, the city owned by Ashur becomes
Assyria, with exchange posts as much as seven hundred miles by
road away to the northeast in Anatolia or present-day Turkey.
Exchange of goods between cities had been going on for some
time. But it is doubtful if it was as extensive as that practiced by
the Assyrians. Recent excavations have revealed karums or, in
smaller towns, ubartums, the exchange posts just outside several
Anatolian cities in which the trading took place. Particularly
interesting excavations have been made of the karum just outside
Kiiltepe: small buildings whose walls have no windows, stone
and wooden shelves on which are cuneiform tablets yet to be
translated, and sometimes jars with what appear to be counters
within them.5 The writing, indeed, is old Assyrian, and, presumably brought there by these traders, is the first writing known in
Anatolia.
Such trade was not, however, a true market. There were no
prices under the pressures of supply and demand, no buying and
selling, and no money. It was trade in the sense of equivalences
established by divine decree. There is a complete lack of reference to business profits or loss in any of the cuneiform tablets
that have so far been translated. There are occasional exceptions, even a suggestion of 'inflation,' perhaps during a famine
year when the exchanges became different, but they do not seriously impair Polanyi's view, which I am following here.6
Let us consider these Assyrian merchants for a moment. They
5 Nimet Osguc, "Assyrian trade colonies in Anatolia," Archeology, 1965, 4: 250255.
6 Karl Polanyi, Trade and Market in the Early Empires (Glencoe: Free Press,
I957).
THE
CAUSES
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
211
were, we may presume, merely agents, holding their position by
descent and apprenticeship, and carrying out exchanges much as
their fathers had done for centuries. But there are so many
questions that face the psychohistorian at this point. What would
happen to the bicameral voices of these merchants as much as
seven hundred miles from the source of their city-god’s voice, and
in daily contact and probably (though not necessarily) speaking
the language of bicameral men ruled by a different pantheon of
voices? Is it possible that something like a protosubjective consciousness occurred in these traders at the boundaries of different
civilizations? Did they, returning periodically to Ashur, bring
with them a weakened bicamerality that perhaps spread to a new
generation? So that the bicameral tie between gods and men was
loosened?
The causes of consciousness are multiple, but at least I do not
think it is a coincidence that the key nation in this development
should also have been that nation most involved in exchanges of
goods with others. If it is true that the power of the gods and
particularly of Ashur were being weakened at this time, it could
account for the absolute collapse of his city in 1700 B.C., beginning the dark ages of Assyrian anarchy that lasted two hundred
years. For this event there is no explanation whatever. No historian understands it. And there is little hope of ever doing so,
for not a single Assyrian cuneiform inscription from this period
has ever been found.
The reorganization of Assyria after its collapse had to wait
upon other events. In 1450 B.C., Egypt pushed the Mitanni out of
Syria right across the Euphrates into lands between the two great
rivers that had once been Assyrian. But a century later the
Mitanni were conquered by the Hittites from the north, thus
making possible the rebuilding of an Assyrian empire in 1380
B.C. after two centuries of anarchic darkness.
And what an empire it is! No nation had been so militaristic
before. Unlike any previous inscriptions anywhere, those of mid-
212
The Witness of History
die Assyria now bristle with brutal campaigns. T h e change is
dramatic. But the success of the Assyrian invasions as they
relentlessly savage their way toward world domination is like a
ratchet catching at the whorl of catastrophes of another kind.
Eruption, Migration, Conquest
The collapse of the bicameral mind was certainly accelerated
by the collapse under the ocean of a good part of the Aegean
people's land. This followed an eruption or series of eruptions of
the volcano on the island of Thera, also called Santorini, now an
Aegean tourist attraction, barely sixty-two miles north of Crete.7
Then, it had been part of what Plato 8 and later legend called the
lost continent of Atlantis, which with Crete made up the Minoan
empire. The major part of it and perhaps parts of Crete as well
were suddenly 1ooo feet underwater. Most of the remaining land
of Thera was covered with a 150-foot-deep crust of volcanic ash
and pumice.
Geologists have hypothesized that the black cloud caused by
the eruption darkened the sky for days and affected the atmosphere for years. The air shock waves have been estimated at
350 times more powerful than a hydrogen bomb. Thick poisonous
vapors puffed out over the blue sea for miles. A tsunami or huge
tidal wave followed. Towering 700 feet high and traveling at 350
miles per hour, it smashed into the fragile coasts of the bicameral
kingdoms along the Aegean mainland and its islands. Everything
for two miles inland was destroyed. A civilization and its gods
had ended.
Just when it happened, whether it was a series of eruptions or
a two-stage affair with a year between the eruption and the
collapse, will require better scientific methods of dating volcanic
7 See Jerome J. Pollit, "Atlantis and Minoan Civilization: An archeological nexus";
and Robert S. Brumbaugh, "Plato's Atlantis,'' both in the Yale Alumni Magazine,
1970, 33, 20-29.
8 See particularly Critias, 1o8e-119e, passim.
THE
CAUSES
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
213
ash and pumice. Some believe it to have occurred in 1470 B.C.9
Others have dated the collapse of Thera between 1180 and 1170
B.C. when the whole of the Mediterranean, including Cyprus, the
Nile delta, and the coast of Israel, suffered universal calamity of
a magnitude that dwarfed the 1470 B.C. destruction.10
Whenever it was, whether it was one or a series of eruptions, it
set off a huge procession of mass migrations and invasions which
wrecked the Hittite and Mycenaean empires, threw the world into
a dark ages within which came the dawn of consciousness. Only
Egypt seems to have retained the elaboration of its civilized life,
although the exodus of the Israelites about the time of the Trojan
War, perhaps 1230 B.C., is close enough to be considered a part
of this great world event. The legend of the parting of the Red
Sea probably refers to tidal changes in the Sea of Reeds related to
the Thera eruption.
The result is that, in the space of a single day, whole populations or what survive of them are suddenly refugees. Like files of
dominoes, anarchy and chaos ripple and lurch across the frightened land as neighbor invades neighbor. And what can the gods
say in these ruins? What can the gods say, with hunger and
death more strict than they, with strange people staring at
strange people, and strange language bellowed at uncomprehending ears? The bicameral man was ruled in the trivial circumstance of everyday life by unconscious habit, and in his encounters with anything new or out of the ordinary in his own behavior
or others' by his voice-visions. Ripped out of context in the larger
hierarchical group, where neither habit nor bicameral voice could
assist and direct him, he must have been a pitiable creature
indeed. How could the storings up and distillings of admonitory
experience gained in the peaceful authoritarian ordering of a
bicameral nation say anything that would work now?
Huge migrations begin moving into Ionia and then south. The
9 S. Marinatos, Crete and Mycaenae
10
(New York: Abrams, 1960).
New York Times, Sept. 28, 1966, p. 34.
214
The Witness of History
coastal lands of the Levant are invaded by land and sea by
peoples from eastern Europe, of whom the Philistines of the Old
Testament were a part. The pressure of the refugees is so great
in Anatolia that in 1200 B.C. the puissant Hittite empire collapses, driving the Hittites down into Syria where other refugees
are seeking new lands. Assyria was inland and protected. And
the chaos resulting from these invasions allowed the cruel Assyrian armies to push all the way into Phrygia, Syria, Phoenicia,
and even to the subjugation of the mountain peoples of Armenia
in the north and those of the Zagros Mountains to the east. Could
Assyria do this on a strictly bicameral basis?
The most powerful king of this middle Assyria was TiglathPileser I ( 1 1 1 5 - 1 0 7 7 B . C . ) . Note how he no longer joins the
name of his god to his name. His exploits are well known from a
large clay prism of monstrous boasts. His laws have come down
to us in a collection of cruel tablets. Scholars have called his
policy "a policy of frightfulness." 11 And so it was. The Assyrians
fell like butchers upon harmless villagers, enslaved what refugees they could, and slaughtered others in thousands. Bas-reliefs
show what appear to be whole cities whose populace have been
stuck alive on stakes running up through the groin and out the
shoulders. His laws meted out the bloodiest penalties yet known
in world history for even minor misdemeanors. They make a
dramatic contrast to the juster admonishments that the god of
Babylon dictated to bicameral Hammurabi six centuries earlier.
W h y this harshness? And for the first time in the history of
civilization? Unless the previous method of social control had
absolutely broken down. And that form of social control was the
bicameral mind. The very practice of cruelty as an attempt to
rule by fear is, I suggest, at the brink of subjective consciousness.
The chaos is widespread and continuing. In Greece it is darkly
known as the Dorian invasions. The Acropolis is in flames by the
11 H. W. F. Saggs, The Greatness That Was Babylon (New York: Mentor Books,
1962), p. 101.
THE
CAUSES
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
215
end of the thirteenth century B.C. Mycenae no longer exists by
the end of the twelfth century B.C. It has been ground out into
legend and wonder. And we can imagine the first aoidos, still
bicameral, wandering entranced from ruined camp to camp of
refugees, singing the bright goddess through his white lips of the
wrath of Achilles in a golden age that was and is no more.
Even from somewhere around the Black Sea, hordes that some
called the Mushku, known in the Old Testament as Meshech,
thrust down into the ruined Hittite kingdom. Then twenty thousand of them drifted further south invading the Assyrian province of Kummuh. Hordes of Aramaeans continuously pressed in
on the Assyrian from the western deserts and continued to do so
up into the first millennium B.C.
In the south, more of these refugees, called in hieroglyphics
the “People from the Sea,” attempt to invade Egypt by the Nile
delta at the beginning of the eleventh century B.C. Their defeat
by Rameses III can still be seen on the north wall of his funerary
temple at Medinet Habu in western Thebes. 12 The invaders in
ships, chariots, and on foot, with families and oxcarts of possessions, stream through these murals in refugee fashion. Had the
invasion been successful, it is possible that Egypt might have
done for the intellect what Greece was to do in the next millennium. And so the People from the Sea are pressed back eastward into the clutch of Assyrian militarism.
And finally all these pressures become too great for even Assyrian cruelty. In the tenth century B.C., Assyria itself cannot
control the situation and shrivels back into poverty behind the
Tigris. But only to breathe. For in the very next century, the
Assyrians begin their reconquest of the world with unprecedented
sadistic ferocity, butchering and terroring their way back to their
former empire and then beyond and all the way to Egypt and up
the fertile Nile to the holy sun-god himself, even as Pizarro was
12 For illustrations of these see William Stevenson Smith, Interconnections in the
Ancient Near East (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1965), pp. 220-221.
216
The Witness of History
to take the divine Inca captive two and a half millennia later on
the opposite side of the earth. And by this time, the great transilience in mentality had occurred. Man had become conscious of
himself and his world.
How Consciousness Began
So far, all our analysis has been about how and why the
bicameral mind collapsed. It could indeed be asked at this point
why man did not simply revert to his previous condition. Sometimes he did. But the inertia of the more complex cultures prevented the return to tribal life. Man was trapped in his own
civilization. Huge cities simply are there, and their ponderous
habits of working keep going even as their divine control lapses
away. Language too is a brake upon social change. The bicameral mind was an offshoot of the acquisition of language, and
language by this time had a vocabulary demanding such attention
to a civilized environment as to make a reversion to something of
at least 5000 years earlier almost impossible.
The facts of the transition from the bicameral mind to the
subjective conscious mind are what I try to develop in the ensuing
two chapters. But just how it happened is the consideration here,
and this needs a great deal more research. What we need is a
paleontology of consciousness, in which we can discern stratum by
stratum how this metaphored world we call subjective consciousness was built up and under what particular social pressures. A l l
that I can present here is a few suggestions.
I would also remind the reader of two things. First, I am not
talking here of the metaphoric mechanisms by which consciousness was generated that I discussed in I.3. Here I am concerned
with their origin in history, why those features were generated by
metaphors at a particular time. Secondly, we are speaking only
about the Near East. Once consciousness is established, there are
quite different reasons why it is so successful, and why it spreads
THE
CAUSES
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
217
to the remaining bicameral peoples, problems which we shall
take up in a later chapter.
The observation of difference may be the origin of the analog
space of consciousness. After the breakdown of authority and of
the gods, we can scarcely imagine the panic and the hesitancy
that would feature human behavior during the disorder we have
described. We should remember that in the bicameral age men
belonging to the same city-god were more or less of similar opinion and action. But in the forced violent intermingling of peoples
from different nations, different gods, the observation that
strangers, even though looking like oneself, spoke differently,
had opposite opinions, and behaved differently might lead to the
supposition of something inside of them that was different. Indeed, this latter opinion has come down to us in the traditions of
philosophy, namely, that thoughts, opinions, and delusions are
subjective phenomena inside a person because there is no room
for them in the ‘real,’ ‘objective’ world. It is thus a possibility that
before an individual man had an interior self, he unconsciously
first posited it in others, particularly contradictory strangers, as
the thing that caused their different and bewildering behavior. In
other words, the tradition in philosophy that phrases the problem
as the logic of inferring other minds from one’s own has it the
wrong way around. We may first unconsciously (sic) suppose
other consciousnesses, and then infer our own by generalization.
The Origin of Narratization in Epics
It sounds strange to speak about gods learning. But occupying
a good part of the right temporal-parietal region (if the model of
I.5 is correct), they, too, like the left temporal-parietal region, or
perhaps even more so, would learn new abilities, storing up new
experience, reworking their admonitory function in new ways to
meet new needs.
218
The Witness of History
Narratization is a single word for an extremely complex set of
patterning abilities which have, I think, a multiple ancestry. But
the thing in its larger patterning, such as lifetimes, histories, the
past and future, may have been learned by dominantly lefthemisphered men from a new kind of functioning in the right
hemisphere. The new kind of functioning was narratization, and
it had previously been learned, I suggest, by the gods at a certain
period of history.
When could this have been? It is doubtful if there can ever be
a certain answer, partly because there is no sharp boundary
between the relation of an event that has just happened and an
epic. Also our search into the past is always confounded with the
development of writing. But it is interesting that about the middle of the third millennium B.C., or just before, there seems to
arise a new feature of civilization in southern Mesopotamia. Before what is known as the Early Dynastic II period, excavations
show that towns or cities in this area were not fortified, had no
defenses. But thereafter, in the principal regions of urban development, walled cities arose at a fairly constant distance from one
another, the inhabitants farming the intervening fields and occasionally fighting each other for control of them. At about this
same period came the first epics that we know of, such as the
several about Emmerkar, the builder of Uruk, and his relations
with the neighboring city-state of Aratta. And their topics are
precisely this relationship between neighboring states.
My suggestion is that narratization arose as a codification of
reports of past events. Writing up to this time — and it is only a
few centuries since its invention —- had been primarily an inventory device, a way of recording the stores and exchanges of a
god's estates. Now it becomes a way of recording god-commanded events, whose recitation after the fact becomes the narratization of epics. Since reading, as I have suggested in the
previous chapter, may have been hallucinating from the cuneiform, it may, then, have been a right temporal lobe function.
THE
CAUSES
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
219
And since these were the recordings of the past, it is the right
hemisphere that becomes at least the temporary seat of the reminiscence of gods.
We should note in passing how different the reading from
stable cuneiform tablets in Mesopotamia was from the oral recomposing of the epics in Greece by a succession of aoidoi: It is
possible that the oral tradition in Greece was an immense benefit
in its demand that ‘Apollo’ or the ‘Muses’ in the right hemisphere
become the sources of memory and learn how to narratize so as
to keep the memories of Achilles together in the epic pattern.
And then, in the chaos of transilience to consciousness, man
assimilates both this memory ability and the ability to narratize
memories into patterns.
The Origin of the Analog ‘I’ in Deceit
Deceit may also be a cause of consciousness. But we must
begin any discussion of the topic by making a distinction between
instrumental or short-term deceit and long-term deceit, which
might better be expressed as treachery. Several examples of the
former have been described in chimpanzees. Female chimpanzees will ‘present5 in sexual posture to a male to whisk away his
banana when his prandial interest is thus distracted. In another
instance, a chimpanzee would fill his mouth with water, coax a
disliked keeper over to the cage bars, and spit the water in his
face. In both such instances, the deceit involved is a case of
instrumental learning, a behavior pattern that is followed immediately by some rewarding state of affairs. And it needs no
further explanation.
But the kind of deceit that is treachery is quite another matter.
It is impossible for an animal or for a bicameral man. Long-term
deceit requires the invention of an analog self that can ‘do’ or ‘be’
something quite different from what the person actually does or
is, as seen by his associates. It is an easy matter to imagine how
220
The Witness of History
important for survival during these centuries such an ability
would be. Overrun by some invader, and seeing his wife raped, a
man who obeyed his voices would, of course, immediately strike
out, and thus probably be killed. But if a man could be one thing
on the inside and another thing on the outside, could harbor his
hatred and revenge behind a mask of acceptance of the inevitable, such a man would survive. Or, in the more usual situation
of being commanded by invading strangers, perhaps in a strange
language, the person who could obey superficially and have
'within him' another self with 'thoughts' contrary to his disloyal
actions, who could loathe the man he smiled at, would be much
more successful in perpetuating himself and his family in the
new millennium.
Natural Selection
My last comment brings up the possibility that natural selection may have played a role in the beginning of consciousness.
But in putting up this question, I wish to be very clear that
consciousness is chiefly a cultural introduction, learned on the
basis of language and taught to others, rather than any biological
necessity. But that it had and still has a survival value suggests
that the change to consciousness may have been assisted by a
certain amount of natural selection.
It is impossible to calculate what percentage of the civilized
world died in these terrible centuries toward the end of the second millennium B.C. I suspect it was enormous. And death
would come soonest to those who impulsively lived by their unconscious habits or who could not resist the commandments of
their gods to smite whatever strangers interfered with them. It is
thus possible that individuals most obdurately bicameral, most
obedient to their familiar divinities, would perish, leaving the
genes of the less impetuous, the less bicameral, to endow the
ensuing generations. And again we may appeal to the principle
THE
CAUSES
OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
221
of Baldwinian evolution as we did in our discussion of language.
Consciousness must be learned by each new generation, and
those biologically most able to learn it would be those most likely
to survive. There is even Biblical evidence, as we shall see in a
future chapter, that children obdurately bicameral were simply
killed. 13
Conclusion
This chapter must not be construed as presenting any evidence
about the origin of consciousness. That is the burden of several
ensuing chapters. My purpose in this chapter has been descriptive and theoretical, to paint a picture of plausibility, of how and
why a huge alteration in human mentality could have occurred
toward the end of the second millennium B.C.
In summary, I have sketched out several factors at work in
the great transilience from the bicameral mind to consciousness:
(1) the weakening of the auditory by the advent of writing; (2)
the inherent fragility of hallucinatory control; (3) the unworkableness of gods in the chaos of historical upheaval; (4) the
positing of internal cause in the observation of difference in
others; (5) the acquisition of narratization from epics; (6) the
survival value of deceit; and (7) a modicum of natural selection.
I would conclude by bringing up the question of the strictness
of all this. Did consciousness really come de novo into the world
only at this time? Is it not possible that certain individuals at
least might have been conscious in much earlier time? Possibly
yes. As individuals differ in mentality today, so in past ages it
might have been possible that one man alone, or more possibly a
cult or clique, began to develop a metaphored space with analog
selves. But such aberrant mentality in a bicameral theocracy
13 Zechariah,
13 : 3-4.
222
The Witness of History
would, I think, be short-lived and scarcely what we mean by
consciousness today.
It is the cultural norm that we are here concerned with, and
the evidence that that cultural norm underwent a dramatic
change is the substance of the following chapters. The three
areas of the world where this transilience can be most easily
observed are Mesopotamia, Greece, and among the bicameral
refugees. We shall be discussing these in turn.
CHAPTER 4
A Change of Mind in
Mesopotamia
A
1230 B . C . , Tukulti-Ninurta I, tyrant of Assyria, had a
stone altar made that is dramatically different from anything
that preceded it in the history of the world. In the carving on its
face, Tukulti is shown twice, first as he approaches the throne of
his god, and then as he kneels before it. The very double image
fairly shouts aloud about this beggarly posture unheard of in a
king before in history. As our eyes descend from the standing
king to the kneeling king just in front of him, it is as emphatic as
a moving picture, in itself a quite remarkable artistic discovery.
But far more remarkable is the fact that the throne before which
this first of the cruel Assyrian conquerors grovels is empty.
No king before in history is ever shown kneeling. No scene
before in history ever indicates an absent god. The bicameral
mind had broken down.
Hammurabi, as we have seen in II.2, is always carved standing
and listening intently to a very present god. And countless cylinder seals from his period show other personages listening eye to
eye or being presented to the just-as-real figures of humanshaped gods. The Ashur altar of Tukulti is in shocking contrast
to all previous depictions of the relations of gods and men. Nor is
it simply some artistic idiosyncrasy. Other altar scenes of Tukulti
are similarly devoid of gods. And cylinder seals of Tukulti's
period also show the king approaching other nonpresent divinities, sometimes represented by a symbol. Such comparisons
BOUT
224
The Witness of History
Carving on the front of the Tukulti Altar now in the Berlin Museum. Tukulti stands and then kneels before the empty throne of
his god. Note the emphasis of the pointing forefinger.
strongly suggest that the time of the breakdown of the bicameral
mind in Mesopotamia is some time between Hammurabi and
Tukulti.
This hypothesis is confirmed in the cuneiform remains of
Tukulti and his period. What is known as the Epic of TukultiNinurta1 is the next clearly dated and well-preserved cuneiform
document of note after Hammurabi. In the latter's time there is
no doubt of the gods' eternal undeviant presence among men,
directing them in their activities. But at the beginning of Tukulti's somewhat propagandalike epic, the gods of the Babylonian
cities are angry with the Babylonian king for his inattention to
them. They therefore forsake their cities, leaving the inhabitants
1 Translations of this and the other texts discussed in this section can be found in
W. G. Lambert, Babylonian Wisdom Literature (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1960).
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
225
without divine guidance, so that the victory of Tukulti's Assyrian
armies is assured. This conception of gods forsaking their human slaves under any circumstances whatever is impossible in
the Babylon of Hammurabi. It is something new in the world.
Moreover, it is found throughout whatever literature remains
of the last three centuries of the second millennium B.C.
One who has no god, as he walks along the street,
Headache envelops him like a garment.
So one cuneiform tablet from about the reign of Tukulti.
If the breakdown of the bicameral mind involved the involuntary inhibition of temporal lobe areas of the right hemisphere, as
we have conjectured earlier, this statement takes on an added interest.
Also from about the same period come the famous three tablets
and a questionable fourth named for its first words, Ludlul bel
nemeqiy usually translated as "I will praise the lord of wisdom."
"Wisdom" here is an unwarranted modern imposition. The translation should be something closer to 'skill' or 'ability to control
misfortune,' the lord here being Marduk, the highest god of Babylon. The first completely readable lines of the damaged first
tablet are:
My god has forsaken me and disappeared,
My goddess has failed me and keeps at a distance.
T h e good angel who walked beside me has departed.
This is de facto the breakdown of the bicameral mind. The
speaker is one Shubshi-Meshre-Shakkan (as we are told in the
third tablet), a feudal lord possibly under Tukulti. He goes on to
describe how, with the departure of his gods, his king becomes
irreconciliably angry at him, how his feudal position of ruling a
226
The Witness of History
city is taken away, how he thus becomes a social outcast. The
second tablet describes how, in this godless state, he is the target
of all disease and misfortune. W h y have the gods left him? And
he catalogs the prostrations, the prayers, and the sacrifices which
have not brought them back. Priests and omen-readers are consulted, but still
My god has not come to the rescue in taking me by the hand,
Nor has my goddess shown pity on me by going at my side.
In the third tablet, he realizes that it is the almighty Marduk who
is behind all that is happening to him. In dreams, the angels of
Marduk appear to him in bicameral fashion, and speak messages
of consolation and promises of prosperity from Marduk himself.
At this assurance, Shubshi is then delivered from his toils and
illnesses and goes to the temple of Marduk to give thanks to the
great god who "made the wind bear away my offenses."
T h e mighty themes of the religions of the world are here
sounded for the first time. W h y have the gods left us? Like
friends who depart from us, they must be offended. Our misfortunes are our punishments for our offenses. We go down on our
knees, begging to be forgiven. And then find redemption in some
return of the word of a god. These aspects of present-day religion
find an explanation in the theory of the bicameral mind and its
breakdown during this period.
The world had long known rules and dues. They were divinely
ordained and humanly obeyed. But the idea of right and wrong,
the idea of a good man and of redemption from sin and divine
forgiveness only begin in this uneasy questioning of why the
hallucinated guidances can no longer be heard.
The same dominant theme of lost gods cries out to us from the
tablets known as The Babylonian Theodicy.2 This dialogue be2 A fascinating problem is why the reference to gods at this time becomes plural
even when it takes a singular verb. This occurs in contexts which in previous literature would have meant it was the personal god. This occurs in both the Ludlul,
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
227
tween a sufferer and his advising friend is of an obviously later
date, perhaps 900 B.C., but wails with the same pleas. Why have
the gods left us? And since they control everything, why did they
shower misfortune upon us? The poem also shimmers with a
new sense of an individual or what we would call an analog self
denoting a new consciousness. It ends with the cry which has
echoed through all later history:
May the gods who have thrown me off give help,
May the goddess who has abandoned me show mercy.
From here to the psalms of the Old Testament is no great
journey. There is no trace whatever of such concerns in any
literature previous to the texts I am describing here.
The consequences of the disappearance of auditory hallucinations from human mentality are profound and widespread, and
occur on many different levels. One thing is the confusion of
authority itself. What is authority? Rulers without gods to guide
them are fitful and unsure. They turn to omens and divination,
which we shall take up shortly. And as I have mentioned earlier,
cruelty and oppression become the ways in which a ruler imposes
his rule upon his subjects in the absence of auditory hallucinations. Even the king’s own authority in the absence of gods
becomes questionable. Rebellion in the modern sense becomes
possible.
Indeed this new kind of rebellion is what happened to Tukulti
himself. He had founded a whole new capital for Assyria across
the Tigris from Ashur, naming it godlessly after himself — KarTukultininurta. But, led by his own son and successor, his more
conservative nobles imprisoned him in his new city, put it to the
torch, and burned it to the ground, his fiery death leading his reign
II:12, 25, 33, as w e l l as through the Theodicy, and later in the plural elohim of the
Eloist contributions to the O l d Testament. One should remember here the Muses of
the Greeks and possibly the pankush of Hittite tablets. Do and did hallucinations
sound like choirs as their reliability is being neurologically weakened?
228
The Witness of History
into legend. ( H e glimmers in the murky history of the Old
Testament as Nimrod 3 [Genesis:1o] and in Greek myths as King
Ninos. 4 ) Disorders and social chaos had of course happened
before. But such a premeditated mutiny and parricide of a king
is impossible to imagine in the god-obedient hierarchies of the
bicameral age.
But of much greater importance are the beginnings of some
new cultural themes which are responses to this breakdown of
the bicameral mind and its divine authority. History does not
move by leaps into unrelated novelty, but rather by the selective
emphasis of aspects of its own immediate past. And these new
aspects of human history in response to the loss of divine authority are all developments and emphases out of the bicameral
age.
Prayer
In the classical bicameral mind, that is, before its weakening
by writing about 2500 B.C., I suggest that there was no hesitancy
in the hallucinated voice and no occasion for prayer. A novel
situation or stress, and a voice told you what to do. Certainly this
is so in contemporary schizophrenic patients who are hallucinating. They do not beg to hear their voices; it is unnecessary. In
those few patients where this does happen, it is during recovery
when the voices are no longer heard with the same frequency.
But as civilizations and their interrelationships become more
complex toward the end of the third millennium B.C., the gods
are occasionally asked to respond to various requests. Usually,
however, such requests are not what we think of as prayer. They
consist of several stylized imprecations, such as the common
ending of statue inscriptions:
3 E. A. Speiser, "In Search of Nimrod," in Oriental and Biblical Studies, Collected
Writings of E. A. Sfeiser, J. J. Finkelstein and Mosh Greenberg, eds. (Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press, 1967), pp. 41-52.
4 H. Lewy, "Nitokoris-Naqi'a," Journal of Near Eastern Studies, 1952, 11, 264286.
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
229
Whoever this image shall deface may Enlil his name destroy and
his weapon break! 5
or the kind of praising which Gudea bestows on his gods in the
great cylinder inscriptions from Lagash. A notable exception,
however, are the very real prayers of Gudea in Cylinder A to his
divine mother, asking her to explain the meaning of a dream.
But this, like so much else with the enigmatic Gudea, is exceptional. Prayers as the central important act of divine worship
only become prominent after the gods are no longer speaking to
man “face to face” (as Deuteronomy 34:10 expresses it). What
was new in the time of Tukulti becomes everyday during the first
millennium B.C., all, I suggest, as a result of the breakdown of
the bicameral mind. A typical prayer begins:
O lord, the strong one, the famous one, the one who knows
all, splendid one, self-renewing one, perfect one, first-begotten
of Marduk . . .
and so on for many more lines of titles and attributes,
the one who holds cult-centers firm, the one who gathers to
himself all cults . . .
perhaps indicating the chaos of the hierarchy of divinities when
they could no longer be heard,
you watch over all men, you accept their supplications . . .
The suppliant then introduces himself and his petition:
I, Balasu, son of his god, whose god is Nabu, whose goddess is
Tashmeturn . . . I am one who is weary, disturbed, whose
body is very sick, I bow before thee . . . O lord, Wise O n e
5 George A. Barton, The Royal Inscriptions of Sumer and Akkad (New Haven:
Yale University Press, 1924), p. 113.
The Witness of History
230
of the gods, by thy mouth command good for me; O Nabu,
Wise O n e of the gods, by thy mouth may I come forth alive. 6
The general form of prayer, beginning with emphatic praise of
the god and ending with a personal petition, has not really
changed since Mesopotamian times. The very exaltation of the
god, and indeed the very idea of divine worship, is in contrast to
the more matter-of-fact everyday relationship of god and man a
thousand years earlier.
An Origin of Angels
In the so-called Neo-Sumerian period, at the end of the third
millennium B.C., graphics, particularly cylinder seals, are full of
'presentation' scenes: a minor god, often female, introduces an
individual, presumably the owner of the seal, to a major god.
This is entirely consistent with what we have suggested was
likely in a bicameral kingdom, namely that each individual had
his personal god who seemed to intercede with higher gods on the
person's behalf. And this type of presentation or intercession
scene continues well into the second millennium B.C.
But then a dramatic change occurs. First, the major gods
disappear from such scenes, even as from the altar of TukultiNinurta. There then occurs a period where the individual's personal god is shown presenting him to the god's symbol only. And
then, at the end of the second millennium B.C., we have the
beginning of hybrid human-animal beings as the intermediaries
and messengers between the vanished gods and their forlorn
followers. Such messengers were always part bird and part human, sometimes like a bearded man with two sets of wings,
crowned like a god, and often holding a kind of purse supposedly
containing ingredients for a purification ceremony. These supposed personnel of the celestial courts are found with increasing
6 Translated
by H. W. F. Saggs in his The Greatness That Was Babylon (New
York: Mentor Books, 1962), p. 312.
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
231
frequency in Assyrian cylinder seals and carvings. In early instances, such angels, or genii, as Assyriologists more often call
them, are seen introducing an individual to the symbol of a god as
in the old presentation scenes. But soon even this is abandoned.
And by the beginning of the first millennium B.C., we find such
angels in a countless diversity of scenes, sometimes with humans, sometimes in various struggles with other hybrid beings.
Sometimes they have the heads of birds. Or they are winged
bulls or winged lions with human heads to act as wardens for
such palaces as that at Nimrud in the ninth century or guarding
the gates of Khorsabad in the eighth century B.C. Or, hawkheaded and broad-winged, they may be seen following around
behind a king, with a cone which has been dipped in a small pail,
as in a wall carving of Assurnasirpal in the ninth century B.C., a
scene like the anointing of baptism. In none of these depictions
does the angel seem to be speaking or the human listening. It is a
silent visual scene in which the auditory actuality of the earlier
bicameral act is becoming a supposed and assumed silent relationship. It becomes what we would call mythological.
Demons
But angels were not enough to fill in the initiative vacuum left
by the retreating gods. And besides, being messengers from the
great gods, they were usually associated with the king and his
lords. For the common people, whose personal gods no longer
help them, a very different kind of semidivine being now casts a
terrible shadow over everyday life.
Why should malevolent demons have entered human history
at this particular time? Speech, even if incomprehensible, is
man’s chief way of greeting others. And if the other does not
reply to an initiated greeting, a readiness for the other’s hostility
will follow. Because the personal gods are silent, they must be
angry and hostile. Such logic is the origin of the idea of evil
232
The Witness of History
which first appears in the history of mankind during the breakdown of the bicameral mind. Since there is no doubt whatever
that the gods rule over us as they will, what can we do to appease
their wishes to harm us, and propitiate them into friendship once
again? Thus the prayer and sacrifice that we have referred to
earlier in this chapter, and thus the virtue of humility before a
god.
As the gods recede into special people called prophets or oracles, or are reduced to darkly communicating with men in angels
and omen, there whooshes into this power vacuum a belief in
demons. The very air of Mesopotamia became darkened with
them. Natural phenomena took on their characteristics of hostility toward men, a raging demon in the sandstorm sweeping the
desert, a demon of fire, scorpion-men guarding the rising sun
beyond the mountains, Pazuzu the monstrous wind demon, the
evil Croucher, plague demons, and the horrible Asapper demons
that could be warded off by dogs. Demons stood ready to seize a
man or woman in lonely places, while sleeping or eating or
drinking, or particularly at childbirth. They attached themselves
to men as all the illnesses of mankind. Even the gods could be
attacked by demons, and this sometimes explained their absence
from the control of human affairs.
Protection against these evil divinities — something inconceivable in the bicameral age — took many forms. Dating from early
in the first millennium B.C. are many thousands of prophylactic
amulets, to be worn around the neck or wrist. They usually
depict the particular demon whose power is to be inhibited, surmounted perhaps by gesticulating priests shooing the evil away,
and often underwritten with an incantation invoking the great
gods against the threatened horror, such as:
Incantation. T h a t one that has approached the house scares me
from my bed, rends me, makes me see nightmares.
To the
god Bine, gatekeeper of the underworld, may they appoint him,
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
233
by the decree of Ninurta prince of the underworld. By the decree of Marduk who dwells in Esagilia in Babylon. Let door
and bolt know that I am under the protection of the two Lords.
Incantation.7
Innumerable rituals were devoutly mumbled and mimed all over
Mesopotamia throughout the first millennium B.C. to counteract
these malign forces. The higher gods were beseeched to intercede. All illnesses, aches, and pains were ascribed to malevolent
demons until medicine became exorcism. Most of our knowledge
of these antidemoniac practices and their extent comes from the
huge collection made about 630 B.C. by Ashurbanipal at Nineveh.
Literally thousands of extant tablets from this library describe
such exorcisms, and thousands more list omen after omen, depicting a decaying civilization as black with demons as a piece of
rotting meat with flies.
A New Heaven
As we have seen in earlier chapters, the gods customarily had
locations, even though their voices were ubiquitously heard by
their servants. These were often dwellings such as ziggurats or
household shrines. And while some gods could be associated with
celestial bodies such as the sun, moon, or stars, and the greatest,
such as Anu, lived in the sky, the majority of gods were earthdwellers along with men.
All this changes as we enter the first millennium B.C., when, as
we are proposing, the gods’ voices are no longer heard. As the
earth has been left to angels and demons, so it seems to be
accepted that the dwelling place of the now absent gods is with
Anu in the sky. And this is why the forms of angels are always
winged: they are messengers from the sky where the gods live.8
7
Translated by Saggs, p. 291.
8
If later copies of the w e l l - k n o w n Enuma Elish, the Neo-Babylonian name f o r
the epic of creation, are to be taken on their face value, this celestialization of the
234
The Witness of History
The use of the word for sky or heaven in conjunction with gods
becomes more and more common in Assyrian-literature. And
when the story of the great flood (the origin of the Biblical story)
is added into the Gilgamesh stories in the seventh century B.C., it
is used as a rationalization for the departure of the gods from
earth:
Even the gods were terror-stricken at the deluge.
T h e y fled and ascended to the heaven of Anu. 9
This celestialization of the once-earthly gods is confirmed by
an important change in the building of ziggurats. As we saw in
11.2, the original ziggurats of Mesopotamian history were built
around a central great hall called the gigunu where the statue of
the god 'lived' in the rituals of his human slaves. But by the end
of the second millennium B.C., the entire concept of the ziggurat
seems to have become altered. It now has no central room whatever and the statues of the major gods are less and less the
centers of elaborate ritual. For the sacred tower of the ziggurat
was now a landing stage to facilitate the gods' descent to earth
from the heaven to which they had vanished. This is definitely
known from texts of the first millennium B.C., which even make
references to the "boat of heaven." The exact date at which this
change took place is a difficult matter, for the extant ziggurats
have been badly damaged and, even worse, sometimes 'restored'.
But I suggest that all of the many ziggurats which the Assyrians
built beginning with the reign of Tulkulti-Ninurta were of this
major gods began as early as the latter half of the second millennium b.c. See the
translation by E. A. Speiser in Near Eastern Texts Relating to the Old Testament,
J. B. Pritchard, ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1950). Its title is its
first two words and means "When on high . .
Like so much else, it was
discovered in the great library of Ashurbanipal of the seventh century b.c. It is a
copy, and the originals may have dated back to the second millennium b.c.
9 Gilgamesh, Tablet II, lines 113-114, in Alexander Heidel, The Gilgamesh Efic
and Old Testament Parallels, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1949).
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
235
sort, huge pedestals for the return of the gods from heaven and
not houses for earthly gods as before.
The ziggurat built by Sargon in the eighth century B.C. for his
huge new city of Khorsabad is calculated from recent excavations
to have surged up in seven stages 140 feet above the surrounding
city, its summit shining with a temple dedicated to Ashur, still the
owning, if unheard, god of Assyria. There is no other temple to
Ashur at Khorsabad. Descending from the temple was no ordinary stairway as in previous ziggurats, but a long spiral ramp
winding around the core of the tower down which Ashur could
walk, when or if he ever landed and did return to the city.
Similarly, the Ziggurat of Neo-Babylon, the Biblical Tower of
Babel, was no god’s house as in the truly bicameral age, but a
heavenly landing for the now celestialized gods. Built in the
seventh and sixth centuries B.C., it soared 300 feet high, again
with seven stages, pinnacling in a brilliant blue-glazed temple for
Marduk. Its very name indicates this use: E-temen-an-ki, temple
( E ) of the receiving platform (temen) between heaven (an) and
earth (ki). 10 The otherwise senseless passage of Genesis (11:29) is certainly a rewrite of some Neo-Babylonian legend of just
such a landing by Yahweh who in the company of other gods
“come down to see the city and the tower,” and thereupon “confound their language that they may not understand one another’s
speech.” The latter may be a narratization of the garbling of hallucinated voices in their decline.
The tirelessly curious Herodotus in the fifth century B.C.
trudged up the steep stairs and spiraling ramps of Etemenanki to
see if there was a god or idol at the top: as in the altar-face of
Tukulti, there was nothing but an empty throne.11
* * *
For my translation of temen and possible alternatives, see James B. Nies’ glossary in Ur Dynasty Tablets (Leipzig: Hinrichs, 1920), p. 171.
11 Histories, 1: 181. Another empty throne scene is shown on Stela 91027 in the
British Museum with Esarhaddon in a pose similar to Tukulti’s.
10
236
The Witness of History
DIVINATION
So far, we have just looked at the evidence for the breakdown of
the bicameral mind. This evidence is, I feel, fairly substantial.
The absence of gods in bas-reliefs and cylinder seals, the cries
about lost gods that wail out of the silent cuneiforms, the emphasis on prayer, the introduction of new kinds of silent divinities,
angels and demons, the new idea of heaven, all strongly indicate
that the hallucinated voices called gods are no longer the guiding
companions of men.
What then takes over their function? How is action initiated?
If hallucinated voices are no longer adequate to the escalating
complexities of behavior, how can decisions be made?
Subjective consciousness, that is, the development on the basis
of linguistic metaphors of an operation space in which an ‘I’ could
narratize out alternative actions to their consequences, was of
course the-great world result of this dilemma. But a more primitive solution, and one that antedates consciousness as well as
paralleling it through history, is that complex of behaviors known
as divination.
These attempts to divine the speech of the now silent gods
work out into an astonishing variety and complexity. But I suggest that this variety is best understood as four main types, which
can be ordered in terms of their historical beginning and which
can be interpreted as successive approaches toward consciousness. These four are omens, sortilege, augury, and spontaneous
divination.
Omen and Omen Texts
The most primitive, clumsy, but enduring method of discovering the will of silent gods is the simple recording of sequences of
unusual or important events. In contrast to all other types of
divination, it is entirely passive. It is simply an extension of
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
237
something common to all mammalian nervous systems, namely,
that if an organism experiences B after A, he will have a tendency to expect B the next time that A occurs. Since omens are
really a particular example of this when expressed in language,
we can say that the origin of omens is simply in animal nature
rather than in civilized culture per se.
Omens or sequences of events that might be expected to recur
were probably present in a trivial way throughout bicameral
times. But they had little importance. Nor was there any necessity to study such sequences, since the hallucinated voices of gods
made all the decisions in novel situations. There are, for example, no Sumerian omen texts whatever. While the first traces
of omens occur among the Semitic Akkadians, it is really only
after the loss of the bicameral mind toward the end of the second
millennium B.C. that such omen texts proliferate everywhere and
swell out to touch almost every aspect of life imaginable. By
the first millennium B.C., huge collections of them are made. In
the library of King Ashurbanipal at Nineveh about 650 B.C., at
least 30 percent of the twenty to thirty thousand tablets come
into the category of omen literature. Each entry in these tedious
irrational collections consists of an if-clause or protasis followed
by a then-clause or apodosis. And there were many classes of
omens, terrestrial omens dealing with everyday life:
If a town is set on a hill, it will not
be good for the dweller within that town.
If black ants are seen on the foundations
which have been laid, that house will get
built; the owner of that house will live to
grow old.
If a horse enters a man's house, and bites
either an ass or a man, the owner of the
house will die and his household will be
scattered.
238
The Witness of History
If a fox runs into the public square,
that town will be devastated.
If a man unwittingly treads on a lizard
and kills it, he will prevail over his
adversary. 12
And so on endlessly, bearing on all those aspects of life that in a
previous age would have been under the guidance of gods. They
can be construed as a kind of first approach to narratization,
doing by verbal formulae what consciousness does in a more
complex way. Rarely are we able to see any logical dependency
of prediction on portent, the connection often being as simple as
word associations or connotations.
There were also teratological omens beginning, " I f a foetus,
etc.," dealing with abnormal births both human and animal.13
The science of medicine is actually founded in medical omens, a
series of texts that begin, "When the conjuration priest comes to
the house of a sick man," and follow with more or less reasonable
prognoses correlated with various symptoms.14 And omens
based on the appearance of facial and bodily characteristics in
the client or in persons he encounters, which, incidentally, give
us the best description we have of what these people looked
like. 15 And omens in the time dimension: menologies which
stated which months were favorable or unfavorable for given
undertakings, and hemerologies that concerned themselves with
propitious or unpropitious days of each month. And omens that
are the beginning of meteorology and astronomy, whole series of
tablets being devoted, to phenomena of the sun, the planets, the
stars and the moon, their times and circumstances of disappearance, eclipses, omens connected with halos, strange cloud formaThese illustrations are all taken from Saggs, pp. 308-309.
Erie Leichty, "Teratological omens," La Divination en Mesopotamie Ancienne
et dans les Regions Voisines, pp. 131-139.
14 J. V. Kinnier Wilson, "Two medical texts from Nimrud," Iraq, 1956, 18:
12
13
1 30-46.
15 J. V. Kinnier Wilson,
"The Nimrud catalog of medical and physiognomical
omina," Iraq, 1962, 24: 52-62.
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
239
tions, the divine meaning of thunder and rain, hail and earthquakes as predictions of peace and war, harvest and flood, or the
movement of planets, particularly Venus, among the fixed stars.
By the fifth century B.C., this use of stars to obtain the intentions
of the silent gods who now live among them has become our
familiar horoscopes, in which the conjunction of the stars at birth
results in predictions of the future and personality of the child.
History also begins, if vaguely, in omen texts, the apodoses or
"then-clauses" of some early texts perhaps preserving some faint
historical information in a unique and characteristically Mesopotamian variety of historiography.16 Mankind deprived of his
gods, like a child separated from his mother, is having to learn
about his world in fear and trembling.
Dream omens became (as they still are) a major source of
divination.17 Particularly in the late Assyrian period during the
first millennium B.C., dream omens were collected into dream
books such as the Ziqiqu where some associative principle between the dream event and its apodosis is apparent, e.g., a dream
of the loss of one's cylinder seal portends the death of a son. But
omens of whatever type can only decide so much. One has to
wait for the portent to occur. Novel situations do not wait.
Sortilege
Sortilege or the casting of lots differs from omens in that it is
active and designed to provoke the gods' answers to specific questions in novel situations. It consisted of throwing marked sticks,
stones, bones, or beans upon the ground, or picking one out of a
group held in a bowl, or tossing such markers in the lap of a tunic
until one fell out. Sometimes it was to answer yes or no, at other
16 See J. J. Finkelstein, uMesopotamian historiography," Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 1963, pp. 461-472.
17 See A. Leo Oppenheim, "Mantic dreams in the Ancient Near East," in G. E.
von Grunbaum and Roger Caillois, eds., The Dream and Human Societies (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1966), pp. 341-350.
240
The Witness of History
times to choose one out of a group of men, plots, or alternatives.
But this simplicity — even triviality to us — should not blind us
from seeing the profound psychological problem involved, as well
as appreciating its remarkable historical importance. We are so
used to the huge variety of games of chance, of throwing dice,
roulette wheels, etc., all of them vestiges of this ancient practice
of divination by lots, that we find it difficult to really appreciate
the significance of this practice historically. It is a help here to
realize that there was no concept of chance whatever until very
recent times. Therefore, the discovery (how odd to think of it as
a discovery!) of deciding an issue by throwing sticks or beans on
the ground was an extremely momentous one for the future of
mankind. For, because there was no chance, the result had to be
caused by the gods whose intentions were being divined.
As to the psychology of sortilege, I would call your attention to
two points of interest. First, this practice is very specifically
invented in culture to supplement right hemisphere function
when that function, following the breakdown of the bicameral
mind, is no longer as accessible as when it was coded linguistically in the voices of gods. We know from laboratory studies that
it is the right hemisphere that predominately processes spatial
and pattern information. It is better at fitting parts of things into
patterns as in Koh's Block Test, at perceiving the location and
quantity of dots in a pattern or of patterns of sound such as
melodies.18 Now the problem that sortilege is trying to solve is
something of the same kind, that of ordering parts of the pattern,
of choosing who is to do what, or what piece of land goes to
which person. Originally, I suggest, in simpler societies, such
decisions were easily made by the hallucinated voices called gods,
which were involved primarily with the right hemisphere. And
when the gods no longer accomplished this function, perhaps
because of the increasing complication of such decisions, sorti18 D. Kimura, "Functional Asymmetry of the Brain in Dichotic Listening," Cortex,
1967, 3: 163. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1971, 23: 46.
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
241
lege came into history as a substitute for this right hemisphere
function.
The second point of psychological interest is that the throwing
of lots, like consciousness itself, has metaphor as its basis. In the
language of I.2, the unexpressed commands of the gods compose
the metaphrand which is to be lexically widened, and the metaphier is the pair or assembly of lots, be they sticks, beans, or
stones. The paraphiers are the distinguishing marks or words on
the lots which then project back into the metaphrand as the
command of the particular god invoked. What is important here
is to understand provoked divination such as sortilege as involving the same kind of generative processes that develop consciousness, but in an exopsychic nonsubjective manner.
As with omen texts, the roots of sortilege go back into the
bicameral age. The earliest mention of throwing lots appears to
be in legal tablets dating from the middle of the second millennium B.C., but it is only toward its end that the practice becomes
widespread in important decisions: to assign shares of an estate
among the sons (as at Susa), or shares of temple income to
certain officials of the sanctuary, to establish a sequence among
persons of equal status for various purposes. This was not simply
for practical purposes, as it would be with us, but always to find
out the commands of a god. Around 833 B.C., the new year in
Assyria was always named after some high official. The particular official to be so honored was chosen by means of a clay die on
the faces of which the names of the various high officials were
inscribed, the various sides of the cube being inscribed with
prayers to Ashur to make that particular side turn up.19 While
many Assyrian texts from this time on refer to various types of
sortilege, it is difficult to estimate just how widespread the practice was in decision-making, and whether it was used by the
19 An illustration of this may be found in W. W. Hallo and W. K. Simpson,
Ancient Near East (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1971), p, 150; see also
Oppenheim, p. 100.
242
The Witness of History
ordinary people in more mundane decisions. We know that it
became common among the Hittites, and its occurrence in the
Old Testament will be referred to in a later chapter.
Augury
A third type of divination and one that is closer to the structure of consciousness is what I shall call qualitative augury. Sortilege is ordinal, ordering by rank a set of given possibilities. But
the many methods of qualitative augury are designed to divine a
great deal more information from the unspeaking gods. It is the
difference between a digital and an analog computer. Its first
form, as described in three cuneiform texts dating from about the
middle of the second millennium B.C., consisted of pouring oil
into a bowl of water held in the lap, the movement of the oil in
relation to the surface or to the rim of the bowl portending the
gods' intentions concerning peace or prosperity, health or disease.
Here the metaphrand is the intention or even action of a god, not
just his words as in sortilege. The metaphier is the oil moving
about the surface of the water, to which the movements and
commands of the gods are similar. The paraphiers are the specific shapes and proximities of the oil whose paraphrands are the
contours of the gods' decisions and actions.
Augury in Mesopotamia always has a cultic status. It was
performed by a special priest called the baru, surrounded with
ritual, and preceded by a prayer to the god to reveal his intentions
through the oil or whatever medium.20 And as we enter the first
millennium B.C., the methods and techniques of the baru break
out into an astonishing diversity of metaphiers for the gods' intentions: Not only oil but the movements of smoke rising from a
censer of incense held in the lap of the diviner,21 or the form of
See Oppenheim, pp. 208, 212.
A lack of later cuneiform tablets referring to oil on water suggests this practice
went out of use fairly early. An exception is the reference of Joseph in Genesis-44:5
to the precious silver cup which he uses for drinking and for private divining, the
date of this being about 600 B.C. See my II.6, note 4.
20
21
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
243
hot wax dropped into water, or the patterns of dots made at
random, or the shapes and patterns of ashes, and then sacrificed
animals.
Extispicy, as divining from the exta of sacrificed animals is
called, becomes the most important type of induced analog
augury during the first millennium B.C. The idea of sacrifice
itself, of course, originated in the feeding of the hallucinogenic
idols as we saw in II.2. With the breakdown of the bicameral
mind, the idols lost their hallucinogenic properties and became
mere statues, but the feeding ceremonies now addressed to absent gods remained in the various ceremonies as sacrifices. It is
thus not surprising that animals rather than oil, wax, smoke, etc.,
became the more important media of communication with the
gods.
Extispicy differs from other methods in that the metaphrand is
explicitly not the speech or actions of gods, but their writing. The
baru first addressed the gods Shamash and Adad with requests
that they "write" their message upon the entrails of the animal,22
or occasionally whispered this request into its ears before it was
killed. He then investigated in traditional sequence the animal's
organs — windpipe, lungs, liver, gall bladder, how the coils of
the intestines were arranged — looking for deviations from the
normal state, shape, and coloring. Any atrophy, hypertrophy,
displacement, special markings, or other abnormalities, particularly of the liver, was a divine message metaphorically related to
divine action. The corpus of texts dealing with extispicy outnumbers all other kinds of augury texts and deserves much more
careful study. From its earliest and very cursory mention in the
second millennium, to the extensive collections of the Seleucid
period around 250 B.C., the history and local development of
extispicy as a means of exopsychic thought is an area where the
tablets are simply awaiting the ordering of proper research. Of
particular interest is that in the late period the markings and
22 See J. Nougayrol "Presages medicaux de Tharuspicine babylonierine," Semittca,
1956, 6, 5 - 1 4 .
244
The Witness of History
discolorations are described in an arcane technical terminology
similar to what occurred among medieval alchemists.23 Parts of
the exta of the sacrificed animal are referred to as "door of the
palace," "path," "yoke," and "embankment" and symbolize these
locations and objects, creating a metaphor world from which to
read out what to do. Some of the late tablets even have diagrams
of the coils of the intestines and their meaning. Clay and bronze
models of the liver and lungs, sometimes elaborate, sometimes
crude, have been unearthed in various sites; some were probably
used for instructional purposes. But since the raw organs themselves were sometimes sent to the king as proof of a particular
divine message, such models may also have served as a less
redolent way of reporting an actual observation.24
Please remember the metaphorical nature of all such activity,
for the actual functions here are similar to though on a different
level from the very inner workings of consciousness. That the
size and shape of the liver or other organ is a metaphier of the size
and shape of the intentions of a god is, on an ultrasimple level,
similar to what we do in consciousness in making metaphor spaces
Containing' metaphor obj ects and actions.
Spontaneous Divination
Spontaneous divination differs from the three preceding types
only by being unconstrained and free from any particular
medium. It is really a generalization of all types. As before, the
gods' commands, intentions, or purposes are the metaphrand
while the metaphier is anything that might be seen at the moment and related to the concern of the diviner. The outcomes of
undertakings or the intentions of a god are thus read out from
whatever object the diviner happens to see or hear.
23 See Mary I. Hussey, "Anatomical nomenclature in an Akaadian omen text,"
Journal of Cuneiform Studies, 1948, 2: 21-32, as mentioned by Oppenheim on p. 216.
24 Robert H. Pfeiffer, State Letters of Assyria (New Haven: American Oriental
Society, 1935), Letter 335.
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
245
The reader may try it for himself. Think of some problem or
concern in a vague kind of way. Then look out the window
suddenly or around where you are and take the first thing your
eye lights upon, and try to 'read' out of it something about your
problem. Sometimes nothing will happen. But at other times the
message will simply flash into your mind. I have just done this as
I write and from my north window see a television aerial against
a twilight sky. I may divine this as meaning I am being much too
speculative, picking up fleeting suggestions from flimsy air — an
unfortunate truth if I am to face these matters at all. I again
think vaguely of my concerns and, walking about, suddenly cast
my eyes on the floor of an adjoining room where an assistant has
been building an apparatus, and see a frayed wire with several
strands at the end. I divine that my problem in this chapter is to
tie together several different strands and loose ends of evidence.
And so on.
I have not come upon this type of divining in a Mesopotamian
text. Yet I feel sure that it must have become a common practice,
if only because spontaneous divination is both common and important in the Old Testament, as we shall see in a future chapter.
And it remains a common method among many types of seers
well into the Middle Ages. 25
These then are the four main types of divination, omens, sortilege, augury, and spontaneous divination. And I would draw to
your attention that they can be considered as exopsychic methods
of thought or decision-making, and that they are successively
closer and closer proximations to the structure of consciousness.
The fact that all of them have roots that go back far into the
bicameral period should not detract from the force of the general25 Spontaneous divination was commonly used by Bedouin prognosticators around
A.D. 1ooo, for example. See Alfred Guillaume, Prophecy and Divination Among the
Hebrews and Other Semites (New York: Harper, 1938), p. 127. It is indeed an
ingredient of everyday thought processes as well as prominent in intellectual discovery.
The Witness of History
246
ization that they became the important media of decision only
after the breakdown of the bicameral mind as described in the
first part of this chapter.
THE
EDGE
OF
SUBJECTIVITY
So far in this heterogeneous chapter, we have been dealing with
the breakdown of the bicameral mind in Mesopotamia, and
the responses to this alteration in human mentality, the effort to
find out what to do by other means when voices are no longer
heard in hallucination. That a further method for finding out
what to do was consciousness, and that it first occurs in the
history of this planet here in Mesopotamia toward the end of the
second millennium B.C. is a much more difficult proposition. The
reasons are chiefly in our inability to translate cuneiform with the
same exactness with which we can translate Greek or Hebrew,
and to proceed with the kind of analysis which I attempt in the
next chapter. The very words in cuneiform that might be relevant to tracing the metaphorical buildup of consciousness and
mind-space are precisely those that are extremely difficult to
translate with precision. Let me state categorically that a truly
definitive study of changes in Mesopotamian mentality over this
second millenium B.C. will have to wait for another level of
scholarship in cuneiform studies. Such a task will include tracing out the changes in referent and frequency of words that later
come to describe events which we call conscious. One, for example, is Sha (also transliterated as Shah or Shag), a word in
Akkadian, whose basic meaning seems to be "in" or "inside." Prefixed to the name of a city, it means "in the city." Prefixed to the
name of a man, it means "in the man," possibly a beginning of
the interiorization of attribution.
I hope to be forgiven for saying rather tritely that these questions and so many others must remain for further research. So
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
247
swiftly are new sites being discovered and new texts translated,
that even ten years frarn now we shall have a much clearer
picture, particularly if the data are looked at from the point of view
of this chapter. The most I feel I can establish here at this time is
simply a few comparisons of a literary kind which suggest that
such a psychological change as consciousness actually took place.
These comparisons will be among letters, building inscriptions,
and versions of Gilgamesh.
Assyrian and Old Babylonian betters Compared
My first comparison to suggest this change from bicamerality
to subjectivity is between the cuneiform tablet letters of the seventh century B.C., Assyria, and those of the old Babylonian kings
a millennium earlier. The letters of Hammurabi and his era are
factual, concrete, behavioristic, formalistic, commanding, and
without greeting. They are not addressed to the recipient, but
actually to the tablet itself, and always begin: unto A say, thus
says B. And then follows what B has to say to A. We should
remember here what I have suggested elsewhere, that reading,
having developed from hallucinating from idols and then from
pictographs, had become during later bicameral times a matter of
hearing the cuneiform. And hence the addressee of the tablets.
The subjects of Old Babylonian letters are always objective.
Hammurabi's letters, for example (all possibly written by Hammurabi himself since they are cut by the same hand), are written
for vassal kings and officers in his hegemony about sending such
a person to him, or directing so much lumber to Babylon, specifying in one instance, "only vigorous trunks shall they cut down," or
regulating the exchanges of corn for cattle, or where workmen
should be sent. Rarely are reasons given. Purposes never.
Unto Sin-idinnam say: thus says Hammurabi.
I wrote you
telling you to send Enubi-Marduk to me. W h y , then, haven't
The Witness of History
248
you sent him?
W h e n you see this tablet, send Enubi-Marduk
into my presence.
See that he travels night and day, that he
may arrive swiftly. 2 6
And the letters rarely go beyond this in complication of 'thought'
or relationship.
A more interesting letter is a command to bring several conquered idols to Babylon:
Unto Sin-idinnam say: thus says Hammurabi.
I am sending
now Zikir-ilisu the officer, and Hammarabi-bani the Dugabofficer to bring the goddesses of Emutbalum. Let the goddesses
travel in a processional boat as in a shrine as they come to Babylon. A n d the temple-women shall follow after them.
For the
food of the goddesses, you shall provide sheep . . . Let them
not delay, but swiftly reach Babylon. 27
This letter is interesting in showing the everyday nature of the
relationship of god and man in Old Babylon, as well as the fact
that the deities are somehow expected to eat on their trip.
Going from Hammurabi's letters to the state letters of Assyria
of the seventh century B.C. is like leaving a thoughtless tedium of
undisobeyable directives and entering a rich sensitive frightened
grasping recalcitrant aware world not all that different from our
own. The letters are addressed to people, not tablets, and probably were not heard, but had to be read aloud. The subjects
discussed have changed in a thousand years to a far more extensive list of human activities. But they are also imbedded in a
texture of deceit and divination, speaking of police investigations,
complaints of lapsing ritual, paranoid fears, bribery, and pathetic
appeals of imprisoned officers, all things unknown, unmentioned,
and impossible in the world of Hammurabi. Even sarcasm, as in
26 Transliterated
and translated by L. W. King in Letters and Inscriptions of
Hammurabi (London: Luzac, 1900), Vol. 3, Letter 46, p. 9+f.
27 Ibid., Vol. 3, Letter 2 p. 6f.
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
249
a letter from an Assyrian king to his restive acculturated deputies
in conquered Babylon about 670 B.C. :
W o r d of the king to the pseudo-Babylonians. I am well . . .
So you, so help you heaven, have turned yourselves into Babylonians!
A n d you keep bringing up against my servants charges
— false charges, — which you and your master have concocted
. . . T h e document (nothing but windy words and importunities! ) which you have sent me, I am returning to you, after
replacing it into its seals. Of course you will say, " W h a t is he
sending back to u s ? "
From the Babylonians, my servants and
my friends are writing me: W h e n I open and read, behold,
the goodness of the shrines, birds of sin . . , 28
And then the tablet is broken off.
A further interesting difference is their depiction of an Assyrian king. The Babylonian kings of the early second millennium
were confident and fearless, and probably did not have to be too
militaristic. The cruel Assyrian kings, whose palaces are virile
with muscular depictions of lion hunts and grappling with clawing beasts, are in their letters indecisive frightened creatures
appealing to their astrologers and diviners to contact the gods and
tell them what to do and when to do it. These kings are told by
their diviners that they are beggars or that their sins are making
a god angry; they are told what to wear, or what to eat, or not to
eat until further notice:29 "Something is happening in the skies $
have you noticed? As far as I am concerned, my eyes are fixed. I
say, 'What phenomenon have I failed to see, or failed to report to
the king? Have I failed to observe something that does not
pertain to his lot?' . . . As to that eclipse of the sun of which
the king spoke, the eclipse did not take place. On the 27th I shall
look again and send in a report. From whom does the lord my
king fear misfortune? I have no information whatsoever."30
28 Pfeiffer, Letter 80.
29 Pfeiffer, Letters 265, 439, and 553.
30 Pfeiffer, Letter
315.
250
The Witness of History
Does a comparison of these letters, a thousand years apart,
demonstrate the alteration of mentality with which we are here
concerned? Of course, a great deal of discussion could follow
such a question. And research: content analyses, comparisons of
syntax, uses of pronouns, questions, and future tenses, as well as
specific words which appear to indicate subjectivity in the Assyrian letters and which are absent in the Old Babylonian. But
such is our knowledge of cuneiform at present that a thorough
analysis is not possible at this time. Even the translations I have
used are hedged in favor of smooth English and familiar syntax
and so are not to be completely trusted. Only an impressionist
comparison is possible, and the result, I think, is clear: that the
letters of the seventh century B.C. are far more similar to our own
consciousness than those of Hammurabi a thousand years earlier.
The Serialization of Time
A second literary comparison can be made about the sense of
time as shown in building inscriptions. In 1.2, I suggested that
one of the essential properties of consciousness was the metaphor
of time as a space that could be regionized such that events and
persons can be located therein, giving that sense of past, present,
and future in which narratization is possible.
The beginning of this characteristic of consciousness can be
dated with at least a modicum of conviction at about 1300 B.C.
We have just seen how the development of omens and augury
suggests this inferentially. But more exact evidence is found in
the inscriptions on buildings. In the typical inscription previous
to this date, the king gave his name and titles, lavished praise on
his particular god or gods, mentioned briefly the season and
circumstances when the building was started, and then described
something of the building operation itself. After 1300 B.C., there
is not only a mention of the event immediately preceding the
building, but also a summary of all the king's past military ex-
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
251
ploits to date. And in the next centuries, this information comes
to be arranged systematically according to the yearly campaigns,
and ultimately bursts out into the elaborate annal form that is
almost universal in the records of the Assyrian rulers of the first
millennium B.C. Such annals continue to swell beyond the recountal of raw fact into statements of motive, criticisms of
courses of action, appraisals of character. And then further to
include political changes, campaign strategies, historical notes on
particular regions — all evidence, I insist, of the invention of
consciousness. None of these characteristics is seen in the earlier
inscriptions.
This is, of course, the invention of history as well, commencing
exactly in the development of these royal inscriptions.31 How
strange it seems to think of the idea of history having to be
invented! Herodotus, usually famed as "the father of history,"
wrote his history only after a visit through Mesopotamia in the
fifth century B.C., and may have picked up the very idea of
history from these Assyrian sources. What is interesting to me in
this speculation is the possibility that as consciousness develops, it
can develop in slightly different ways, and the importance of the
writing of Herodotus to the later development of Greek consciousness would make an interesting project. My essential point
here, however, is that history is impossible without the spatialization of time that is characteristic of consciousness.
Gilgamesh
And finally a comparison from this best-known example of
Assyrian literature. The Epic of Gilgamesh proper is a series of
twelve numbered tablets found in Nineveh among the ruins of
the temple library of the god Nabu and the palace library of the
Assyrian king, Ashurbanipal. It was written for the king out of
previous stories in about 650 B.C., and its hero is a demi-god,
31
See Saggs, p. 47 2f.
252
The Witness of History
Gilgamesh, whom his father, Esarhaddon, had worshiped. Certainly the name Gilgamesh goes far back into Mesopotamian
history. And numerous other tablets have been found which
relate to him and to this series in some way.
Prominent among them are three apparently older tablets
which parallel some of the Assyrian tablets. Where they were
found and their archaeological contexts are not at all clear. They
were not found by archaeologists, but were bought by private
buyers from a dealer in Baghdad. Their dating and provenance
therefore are a questionable matter. From internal evidence I
would place them at about the same time as some Hittite and
Hurrian fragments about Gilgamesh, perhaps 1200 B.C. The more
usual date given them is 1700 B.C. But whatever their date, there
is certainly no warrant to suppose, as have some popularizers of
the epic, that the seventh century B.C. rendering of the story of
Gilgamesh goes back to the Old Babylonian era.
What we are interested in are the changes which have been
made between the few older tablets and their Assyrian versions of
650 B.C. 3 2 The most interesting comparison is in Tablet X. In
the older version (called the Yale Tablet because of its present
location), the divine Gilgamesh, mourning the death of his
mortal friend Enkidu, has a dialogue with the god Shamash, and
then with the goddess Siduri. The latter, called the divine barmaid, tells Gilgamesh that death for mortals is inevitable. These
dialogues are nonsubjective. But in the later Assyrian version,
the dialogue with Shamash is not even included, and the barmaid
is described in very human earthly terms, even as self-consciously
wearing a veil. To our conscious minds, the story has become
humanized. At one point in the later Assyrian tablet, the barmaid
sees Gilgamesh approaching. She is described as looking out into
the distance and speaking to her own heart, saying to herself,
"Surely this man is a murderer! Whither is he bound?" This is
subjective thinking. And it is not in the older tablet at all.
32 All references here are to the translation by Alexander Heidel.
A
CHANGE
OF
MIND
IN
MESOPOTAMIA
253
The Assyrian tablet goes on with great elaboration (as well as
with great beauty) to bring out the subjective sadness in the
heart of Gilgamesh at the loss of his friend. One of the literary
devices here (at least as translators have restored a damaged
part) is repeated questions that describe the outward demeanor
of Gilgamesh rhetorically, asking why his appearance and behavior are thus and so, so that the reader is constantly imagining the
interior 'space' and analog T of the hero.
W h y is thy heart so sad, and why are thy features so distorted?
W h y is there woe in thy heart?
And why is thy face like unto one who has made a far journey?
None of this psalmlike concern is in the old version of Tablet X.
Another character is the god Utnapishtim, the Distant, who is
mentioned only briefly in the old version of Tablet X. But, in the
650 B.C. version, he is looking into the distance and speaking
words to his hearty asking it questions and coming to his own
conclusions.
Conclusion
The evidence we have just examined is strong in some areas
and weak in others. The literature on the loss of the gods is an
unquestionable change in the history of Mesopotamia, unlike
anything that preceded it. It is indeed the birth of modern religious attitudes and we can discover ourselves in the very psalmlike yearnings for religious certainty that are expressed in the
literature from the time of Tukulti up into the first millennium
B.C.
The sudden flourishing of all kinds of divination and its huge
importance in both political and private life is also an unquestionable historical fact. And while these practices date back to earlier
time, perhaps even suggesting that as civilization became more
254
The Witness of History
complicated toward the end of the third millennium B.C., the bicameral gods needed some auxiliary method of decision-making,
they only achieve their dominance and universal position in civilized life after the breakdown of the gods.
It is also unquestionable that the very nature of divinities was
altered in these times, and that the belief in a world darkened
with hostile demons, causing disease and misfortune, can only be
understood as an expression of the deep and irreversible uncertainty which followed the loss of the hallucinated decisions of the
bicameral mind.
What is weak in our survey is indeed the evidence of consciousness itself. There is something unsatisfying in my saltatory
comparisons among questionable translations of cuneiform tablets of various ages. What we would like is to see in front of us a
continuous literature wherein we could watch more carefully the
unfolding of subjective mind-space and its operator function in
initiating decision. This is indeed what occurs in Greece a few
centuries later, and it is to that analysis that we now turn.
CHAPTER 5
The Intellectual Consciousness
of Greece
T
H E Y H A V E C A L L E D I T the Dorian invasions. And classicists
will tell you that indeed they could have called it anything
or everything, so groping our knowledge, and so dark these particular profundities of past time. But continuities in pottery designs from one archaeological site to another do fetch a few
candles into this vast and silent darkness, and they reveal, albeit
in flickering fashion, the huge jagged outlines of complex successions of migrations and displacements that lasted from 1200 to
1000 B.C.1 That much is fact.
The rest is inference. Even who the so-called Dorians were is
unclear. In an earlier chapter, I have suggested that the beginning of all this chaos may have been the Thera eruption and its
consequences. As Thucydides at the last edge of a verbal tradition describes it, "migrations were a frequent occurrence, the
several tribes readily abandoning their homes under the pressure
of superior numbers." Palaces and villages that once held
fealty to Agamemnon and his gods were looted and burned by
other bicameral peoples who, following their own admonitory
visions, probably could not communicate with nor have pity on
the natives. Survivors were slaves or refugees, and refugees
conquered or died. Our greatest certainties are negative. For all
that the Mycaenaean world had produced with such remarkable
1 V. R. d'A. Desborough, The Last Mycenaeans and Their Successors: An Archaeological Survey, c 1200-c IOOO b.c. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1964).
256
The Witness of History
uniformity everywhere — the massive stone architecture of its
god-ordered palaces and fortifications, its undulant frescoes of
delicate clarity, its shaft-graves with their elaborate contents, the
megaron plan of its houses, the terra-cotta idols and figurines, the
death masks of beaten gold, the bronze and ivory work and
distinctive pottery — all stopped and was never known thereafter.
This ruin is the bitter soil for the growth of subjective consciousness in Greece. And the difference here from the huge
Assyrian cities stumbling on into a fumbling demon-ridden consciousness out of their own momentum is important. In contrast,
Mycaenae had been a loose and spread-out system of divinely
commanded cities of smaller size. The breakdown of the bicameral mind resulted in an even greater dispersion as all society
broke down.
It is even plausible that all this political havoc was the very
challenge to which the great epics were a defiant response, and
that the long narrative chants of the aoidoi from refugee camp to
camp worked out into an eager unity with the cohesive past on
the part of a newly nomadic people reaching at lost certainties.
Poems are rafts clutched at by men drowning in inadequate
minds. Arid this unique factor, this importance of poetry in a
devastating social chaos, is the reason why Greek consciousness
specifically fluoresces into that brilliant intellectual light which is
still illuminating our world.
What I shall do in this chapter is to conduct you on a tour
through all the early extant literature of Greece. It is unfortunately a short list of texts. Beginning with the Iliad, we shall
travel consecutively up through the Odyssey and the Boeotian
poems ascribed to Hesiod, and then into the fragments of the
lyric and elegiac poets of the seventh century B.C. and a little
beyond. In doing so, I shall not be giving you any running
description of the scenery we are passing through. The several
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
257
good histories of early Greek poetry can do that better than I.
Instead I shall be directing your attention to selected things as
we pass by that are of particular interest from the point of view
of our theory of consciousness.
But before we do so, we must make a few preliminary excursions, particularly into a more thorough analysis of mindlike
terms in the Iliad.
LOOKING
FORWARD THROUGH
THE
ILIAD
In an earlier chapter, I made the statement that the Iliad was our
window upon the immediate bicameral past. Here, I propose that
we stand on the other side of that window and peer forward into
the distant conscious future, regarding this great mysterious
paean to anger, not so much as the end point of the verbal
tradition that preceded it, but rather as the very beginning of the
new mentality to come.
In I.3, we saw that the words which in later Greek indicate
aspects of conscious functioning have in the Iliad more concrete
and bodily referents. But the very fact that these words come to
have mental meanings later suggests that they may be some kind
of key to understanding the manner in which Greek consciousness is developed.
The words we shall look at here are seven: thumos, phrenes,
noos, and psyche, all of them variously translated as mind, spirit,
or soul, and kradie, ker, and etor, often translated as heart or
sometimes as mind or spirit. The translation of any of these
seven as mind or anything similar is entirely mistaken and without any warrant whatever in the Iliad. Simply, and without
equivocation, they are to be thought of as objective parts of the
environment or of the body. We shall discuss these terms fully in
a moment.
258
The Witness of History
Now the first question to ask is why these entities are in the
poem at all. I have earlier stressed the fact that the major
instigations to action here are in the voices of the gods, not in the
thumo, phrenes, etor, et al. The latter are entirely redundant. In
fact they often seem to get in the way of the simple command-obedience relation between god and man, like a wedge between the two
sides of the bicameral mind. W h y then are they there?
Let us examine more closely what would have happened at the
beginning of the breakdown of the bicameral mind. In I.4, we
found that the physiological cuing of an hallucinated voice,
whether in a bicameral man or in a contemporary schizophrenic,
is the stress of some decision or conflict. Now, as the voices of
gods become more inadequate and suppressed during this social
chaos, we may suppose that the amount of that stress necessary
to occasion an hallucinated voice would be raised.
It is quite likely, then, that as the bicameral organization of
mind began to diminish, the decision-stress in novel situations
would be much greater than previously, and both the degree and
duration of that stress would have to become progressively more
intense before the hallucination of a god would occur. And such
increased stress would be accompanied by a variety of physiological concomitants, vascular changes resulting in burning sensations, abrupt changes in breathing, a pounding or fluttering
heart, etc., responses which in the Iliad are called thumos,
phrenes and kradie respectively. And this is what these words
mean, not mind or anything like it. As the gods are heard progressively less and less, these internal response-stimuli of progressively greater stress are associated more and more with men's
subsequent actions, whatever they may be, even coming to take
on the godlike function of seeming to initiate action themselves.
The evidence that we are on the right track in these suppositions can be found in the Iliad itself. At the very beginning,
Agamemnon, king of men but slave of gods, is told by his voices
to take the fair-cheeked Briseis away from Achilles, who had
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
259
captured her. As he does so, the response of Achilles begins in
his etor, or what I suggest is a cramp in his guts, where he is in
conflict or put into two parts (mermerizo) whether to obey his
thumosy the immediate internal sensations of anger, and kill the
pre-emptory king or not. It is only after this vacillating interval
of increasing belly sensations and surges of blood, as Achilles is
drawing his mighty sword, that the stress has become sufficient to
hallucinate the dreadfully gleaming goddess Athene who then
takes over control of the action (1:188ff.) and tells Achilles
what to do.
I mean to suggest here that the degree and extent of these
internal sensations were neither so evident nor so named in the
true bicameral period. If we may propose that there was an UrIliad, or the verbal epic as it came from the lips of the first several
generations of aoidoi, then we can expect that it had no such
interval, no etor or thumos preceding the voice of the god, and
that the use and, as we shall see, the increasing use of these
words in this way reflects the alteration of mentality, the wedge
between god and man which results in consciousness.
Preconscious Hypostases
We may call these mind-words that later come to mean something like conscious functioning, the preconscious hypostases.
The latter term means in Greek what is caused to stand under
something. The preconscious hypostases are the assumed causes
of action when other causes are no longer apparent. In any novel
situation, when there are no gods, it is not a man who acts, but
one of the preconscious hypostases which causes him to act. They
are thus seats of reaction and responsibility which occur in the
transition from the bicameral mind to subjective consciousness.
What we shall see is that the frequency and the meaning of
these terms gradually change as we go from text to text from
about 850 to 600 B.C., and how in the sixth century B.C. their
260
The Witness of History
referents join together in what we would call the subjective conscious mind.2
I would like here to translate and expand what I have just said
into a clearer statement by suggesting that this temporal development of the preconscious hypostases can be roughly divided into
four phases:
Phase I:
Objective: Occurred in the bicameral age when
these terms referred to simple external observations.
Phase I I :
Internal: Occurred when these terms have come
to mean things inside the body, particularly certain
internal sensations.
Phase I I I : Subjective: W h e n these terms refer to processes
that we would call
mental;
they
have
moved
from internal stimuli supposedly causing actions
to internal spaces where metaphored actions may
occur.
Phase I V :
Synthetic: W h e n the various hypostases unite into
one conscious self capable of introspection.
The reason I am setting these out, perhaps pretentiously, as four
separate phases is to call your attention to the important psychological differences of transition between these phases.
The transition from Phase I to Phase II occurred at the beginning of the breakdown period. It comes from the absence or the
inappropriateness of gods and their hallucinated directions. The
buildup of stress for want of adequate divine decisions increases
the psychological concomitants of such stress until they are
labeled with terms that previously applied to only external perception.
The transition from Phase II to Phase III is a much more
2 Professor A. D. H. Adkins has made this drawing-together of the various mindwords into one the theme of his book From the Many to the One (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1970).
I N T E L L E C T U A L
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
261
complicated matter. And much more interesting. It is due to the
paraphrand generator of metaphor described in 1.2. In that chapter, I outlined the four-part process of metaphor, how we begin
with a less-known term called a metaphrand which is to be
described, and then describe it by applying to it a better-known
metaphier which is similar to it in some way. Usually there are
simple associations of the metaphier which I have called paraphiers, which then project back as associates of the original
metaphrand, these new associates being called paraphrands.
Such paraphrands are generative in a sense that they are new in
their association with the metaphrand. And this is how we are
able to generate the kind of 'space' which we introspect upon and
which is the necessary substrate of consciousness. This is really
quite simple as we shall see shortly.
And, finally, the synthesis of the separate hypostases into the
unitary consciousness of Phase IV is a different process also. I
suggest that as the subjective Phase III meanings of thumos,
phrenes, et al. become established, their original anatomical
bases in different internal sensations wither away, leaving them
to become confused and to join together on the basis of their
shared metaphiers, e.g., as 'containers' or 'persons.' But this
synthetic unity of consciousness may also have been helped by
what can be called the laicization of attention and its consequent
recognition of individual differences in the seventh century B.C., a
process which resulted in a new concept of self.
Before looking at the evidence for these matters, let us first
investigate the preconscious hypostases and their Iliadic meanings in these phases with more detail. In the general order of
their importance in the Iliad, they are:
Thumos
This is by far the most common and important hypostatic word
in the whole poem. It occurs three times as often as any other.
262
The Witness of History
Originally, in the Objective Phase, I suggest, it meant simply
activity as externally perceived. And nothing internal about it.
This Mycaenaean usage is found frequently in the Iliad, particularly in the battle scenes, where a warrior aiming a spear in the
right place causes the thumos or activity of another to cease.
The internal Phase II, as we have seen in Achilles' wrath
occurs in a novel stressful situation during the breakdown period when the stress threshold for the hallucinated voice was
higher. Thumos then refers to a mass of internal sensations in
response to environmental crises. It was, I suggest, a pattern of
stimulation familiar to modern physiology, the so-called stress or
emergency response of the sympathetic nervous system and its
liberation of adrenalin and noradrenalin from the adrenal glands.
This includes the dilation of the blood vessels in striate muscles
and in the heart, an increase in tremor of striate muscles, a burst
of blood pressure, the constriction of blood vessels in the abdominal viscera and in the skin, the relaxing of smooth muscles, and
the sudden increased energy from the sugar released into the
blood from the liver, and possible perceptual changes with the
dilation of the pupil of the eye. This complex was, then, the
internal pattern of sensation that preceded particularly violent
activity in a critical situation. And by doing so repeatedly, the
pattern of sensation begins to take on the term for the activity
itself. Thereafter, it is the thumos which gives strength to a
warrior in battle, etc. All the references to thumos in the Iliad as
an internal sensation are consistent with this interpretation.
Now the important transition to the subjective Phase III is
already beginning even in the Iliad, although not in a very conspicuous way. We see it in the unvoiced metaphor of the thumos
as like a container: in several passages, menos or vigor is 'put' in
someone's thumos ( i 6 : 5-8; 17: 4 5 1 ; 22: 312). The thumos is
also implicitly compared to a person: it is not Ajax who is zealous
to fight but his thumos (13: 7 3 ) ; nor is it Aeneas who rejoices
but his thumos (13: 494; see also 14: 156). If not a god, it is the
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
263
thumos that most often 'urges' a man into action. And as if it were
another person, a man may speak to his thumos ( u : 403), and
may hear from it what he is to say (7: 68), or have it reply to
him even as a god (9: 702).
A l l these metaphors are extremely important. Saying that the
internal sensations of large circulatory and muscular changes are
a thing into which strength can be put is to generate an imagined
'space,5 here located always in the chest, which is the forerunner
of the mind-space of contemporary consciousness. And to compare the function of that sensation to that of another person or
even to the less-frequent gods is to begin those metaphor processes that will later become the analog 'I 5 .
Phrenes
The second most common hypostasis in the Iliad is the
phrenes. Its Objective Phase origin is more questionable. But the
fact that it is almost always plural may indicate that the phrenes
objectively referred to the lungs and perhaps were associated with
phrasis or speech.
In the Internal Phase, phrenes become the temporal pattern
of sensations associated with respiratory changes. These come
from the diaphragm, the intercostal muscles of the rib-cage, and
the smooth muscles surrounding the bronchial tubes which regulate their bore and so the resistance of them to the passage of air,
this mechanism being controlled by the sympathetic nervous system. We should remember here how extremely responsive our
breathing is to various types of environmental stimulation. A
sudden stimulus, and we 'catch our breath'. Sobbing and laughing have obvious distinct internal stimulation from the diaphragm and intercostals. In great activity or excitement, there is
an increase in both the rate and depth of breathing with the
resulting internal stimulation. Either pleasantness or unpleasantness usually shows increased breathing. Momentary attention
264
The Witness of History
is clearly correlated with partial or complete inhibition of breathing. A surprise, and our rate of breathing increases and becomes
irregular.
Apart from rate, there are also unique changes in the proportion of time occupied by inspiration and by expiration in a single
breath cycle. This is best measured by determining the percent
of the duration of the breath cycle taken up by inspiration. This
is about 16 percent in speech, 23 percent in laughter, 30 percent
in attentive mental work, 43 percent when at rest, 60 percent or
more in excitement, 71 percent in subjects imagining a wonderful or surprising situation, and 75 percent in sudden fright. 3
The point I am trying to make here is that our phrenes or
respiratory apparatus can almost be looked at as recording everything we do in quite distinct and distinguishable ways. It is at
least possible that this internal mirror of behavior loomed much
larger in the total stimulus world of the preconscious mind than
it does in ourselves. And certainly its changing pattern of internal stimulation makes us understand why the phrenes are so
important during the transition to consciousness, and why the
term is used in so many functionally different ways in the poetry
we are examining in this chapter.
In the Iliad, it can often be translated simply as lungs. Agamemnon's black phrenes fill with anger (1:103) and we can
visualize the king's deep breathing as his fury mounts. Automedon fills his dark phrenes with valor and strength, or takes
deep breaths (17:499). Frightened fawns have no strength in
their phrenes after running} they are out of breath (4:245). In
weeping, grief 'comes to' the phrenes (1:362; 8:124) or the
respiratory phrenes can 'hold' fear (10:10), or joy (9:186). Even
these statements are partly metaphoric, and thus associate a kind of
container space in the phrenes.
A very few instances are more clearly in Phase III in the sense
3 By inspiration here I mean from the beginning of taking a breath to the beginning
of exhaling. The measure thus includes holding one's breath. These determinations
collected from various sources. See Robert S. Woodworth, Exferimental Psychology
(New York: Holt, 1938), p. 264.
I N T E L L E C T U A L
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
265
of inner mind-space. These are where the phrenes are said to
'contain' and perhaps 'retain' information. Sometimes this information comes from a god (1:55) or at other times from another
human (1:297).
Laboratory studies have demonstrated that even simple sensory experience of an object, its recognition, and the recall of the
name associated with it, all can be observed in recordings of
respiration taken simultaneously.4 It is thus not surprising that
when some internal sensation is first connected to such functions
as recognition and recall, it is located in the phrenes. Once it is
said that the phrenes can recognize events (22:296), it is making a metaphor of the phrenes with a person, and the paraphrands of 'person,' that is, something that can act in a space
projects back into the phrenes to make it metaphorically spatial
and capable of other human activities metaphorically. Similarly
we find that like a person the phrenes of a man can occasionally
'be persuaded' by another man (7:120), or even by a god
(4:104). The phrenes can perhaps even 'speak' like a god, as
when Agamemnon says he obeyed his baneful phrenes (9:119).
These instances are quite rare in the Iliad, but they do point
toward what will develop into consciousness over the next two
centuries.
Kradie
This term, which later comes to be spelled kardia, and results
in our familiar adjective 'cardiac,' is not quite so important or
mysterious as other hypostases. It refers to the heart. In fact, it
is the most common hypostasis still in use. When we in the
twentieth century wish to be sincere, we still speak out of our
hearts, not out of our consciousness. It is in our hearts that we
have our most profound thoughts and cherish our closest beliefs.
And we love with our hearts. It is curious that the lungs or
4 Mario Ponzo, "La misura del decorso di processi psichici esequita per mezzo delle
grafiche del respiro," Archives Italiennes de Psicologia, 1920-21, 1: 214.-238.
266
The Witness of History
phrenes have never maintained their hypostatic role as has the
kradie.
Originally, I suggest, it simply meant quivering, coming from
the verb kroteo, to beat. Kradie even means in some passages of
early Greek a quivering branch. Then, in the internalization of
Phase II that went on during the Dorian invasions, the quivering
that was seen with the eye and felt with the hand externally
becomes the name of the internal sensation of the heartbeat in
response to external situations. With few exceptions, this is its
referent in the Iliad. No one believes anything in his heart as
yet.
Again I would remind you of the extensive modern literature
on the responsiveness of our hearts to how we perceive the world.
Like respiration or the action of the sympathetic nervous system,
the cardiac system is extremely sensitive to particular aspects of
the environment. At least one recent commentator has introduced the concept of the cardiac mind, calling the heart a specific
sense organ for anxiety, as the eyes are the sense organ for
sight.5 Anxiety in this view is not any of the poetic homologues
which we in our consciousness might use to describe it. Rather it
is an inner tactile sensation in the sensory nerve endings of
cardiac tissue which reads the environment for its anxiety potential.
While this notion is doubtful as it stands, it is good Homeric
psychology. A coward in the Iliad is not someone who is afraid,
but someone whose kradie beats loudly (13:282). The only
remedy is for Athene to ‘put’ strength in the kradie (2:452), or
for Apollo to ‘put’ boldness in it (21:547). The metaphier of a
container here is building a ‘space’ into the heart in which later
men may believe, feel, and ponder things deeply.
Etor
Philologists usually translate both kradie and etor as heart.
5 Ludwig Braun, Herz und Angst (Vienna: Deuticke, 1932), p.
38.
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
267
And certainly a word can have synonyms. But in instances so
important as the assigning of particular locations of sensations
and forces of action, I would demur on a priori grounds, and
insist that to the ancient Greek these terms had to represent
different locations and sensations. Sometimes they are even
clearly distinct in the text (20:169). I have thus the temerity to
suggest that etor in Phase I came from the noun etron — belly,
and that in Phase II, it becomes internalized into sensations of
the gastro-intestinal tract, particularly the stomach. Indeed, there
is even evidence for this in the Iliad, where it is precisely stated
that food and drink are taken to satisfy the etor (19:307). 6 This
translation is also more apt in other situations, as when a warrior
loses his etor or guts in the front ranks of the battle by being disemboweled ( 5:215 ).
But more important is the stimulus field it provides for mental
functioning. We know that the gastro-intestinal tract has a wide
repertoire of responses to human situations. Everyone knows the
sinking feeling on receiving bad news, or the epigastric cramp
before a near automobile accident. The intestine is equally responsive to emotional stimuli of lesser degree, and these responses can be easily seen on the fluoroscopic screen.7 Stomach
contractions and peristalsis stop at an unpleasant stimulus, and
may even be reversed if the unpleasantness is increased. The
secretory activity of the stomach is also extremely susceptible to
emotional experience. The stomach is indeed one of the most
responsive organs in the body, reacting in its spasms and emptying and contractions and secretory activity to almost every emotion and sensation. And this is the reason why illnesses of the
gastro-intestinal system were the first to be thought of as psychosomatic.
It is therefore plausible that this spectrum of gastro-intestinal
sensations was what was being referred to by the etor. When
6 See also Hesiod: Works and Days, 593.
7 Howard E. Ruggles, “Emotional influence on the gastro-intestinal tract,” California and Western Medicine} 1928, 29: 221-223.
268
The Witness of History
Andromache hears the groaning Hecuba, her etor heaves up in
her throatj she is close to vomiting (22:452). 8 When Lycaon's
plea to live is mocked by Achilles, it is Lycaon's etor along with
his knees that are 'loosened' and made weak ( 2 1 : 1 1 4 ) . We
would say he has a sinking feeling in the pit of his stomach. And
when the gods themselves join in the battle, it is the etor of Zeus
that laughs with joy, or what we would call a belly-laugh
(21:389),
The container metaphor is not used as with the other hypostases, probably because the stomach already contains food. For
this very reason we will see that it does not grow into an important part of any conscious mentality in the literature to follow.
I think it is obvious to the medical reader that these matters we
are discussing under the topic of the preconscious hypostases
have a considerable bearing on any theory of psychosomatic disease. In the thumos, phrenes, kradie, and etor, we have covered
the four major target systems of such illness. And that they
compose the very groundwork of consciousness, a primitive partial type of consciousizing, has important consequences in medical theory.
I shall only indicate the ker in passing, partly because it plays a
diminishing role in this story of consciousness, but also because
its derivation and significance is somewhat cloudy. While it is
possible that it could have come from cheir and then become
somatized into trembling hands and limbs, it is more probably
from the same root as kardia in a different dialect. Certainly the
passage in the Odyssey which states that a warrior is wounded
where the phrenes or lungs are set close about the throbbing ker
(16:481) leaves little doubt. It is almost always referred to as
the organ of grief and is of limited importance.
But of utmost importance is the next hypostasis. Let it be
immediately stated that it is an uncommon term in the Iliad — so
8 And just as the stomach pulsates like the heart, so they sometimes become confused, as when in the wounded lion's kradie his valiant etor groans (20:169).
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
269
uncommon as to make us suspect that it could have been added
by the later generations of aoidoi. But starting from such small
beginnings in the Iliad, it soon comes into the very center of our
topic. And this is
Noos
Up to now, we have been dealing with large, ummistakable
internal sensations that only needed to be named in times of
turmoil and crisis, and which then took their names from objective external perception. Noos, deriving from noeo = to see, is
perception itself. And in coming to it we are in a much more
powerful region in our intellectual travels.
For, as we saw in an earlier chapter, the great majority of the
terms we use to describe our conscious lives are visual. We 'see'
with the mind's 'eye' solutions which may be 'brilliant' or 'obscure,' and so on. Vision is our distance receptor far excellence.
It is our sense of space in a way that no other modality can even
approach. And it is that spatial quality, as we have seen, that is
the very ground and fabric of consciousness.
It is interesting to note parenthetically that there is no hypostasis for hearing as there is for sight. Even today, we do not
hear with the mind's ear as we see with the mind's eye. Nor do
we refer to intelligent minds as loud, in the same way we say they
are bright. This is probably because hearing was the very essence
of the bicameral mind, and as such has those differences from
vision which I discussed in 1.4. The coming of consciousness can
in a certain vague sense be construed as a shift from an auditory
mind to a visual mind.
This shift is first seen somewhat fitfully in the Iliad. The
Mycenaean objective origin of the term is present in objective
statements about seeing, or in noos as a sight or show. In urging
his men into battle, a warrior may say there is no better noos
than a hand-to-hand battle with the enemy (15:510). And Zeus
keeps Hector in his noos (151461).
270
The Witness of History
But the second phase of internalization of noos is also evident
in the Iliad. It is located in the chest (3:63). How curious to us
that it was not placed in the eyes! Perhaps this is because in its
new role it was becoming melded with the thumos. Indeed, noos
takes on adjectives more suitable to the thumos, such as fearless
(3:63) and strong (16:688). And Odysseus dissuades the
Achaeans from putting their ships to sea by telling them that they
do not yet know what sort of noos is in Agamemnon (2:192).
And one of the most modern-sounding instances occurs in the
very first episode, when Thetis, consoling the sobbing Achilles,
asks him, " W h y has grief come upon your phrenes? Speak,
conceal not in noos, so that we both may know" (1:363). 9 Apart
from this, there is no other subjectification in the Iliad. No one
makes any decisions in his noos. Thinking does not go on in the
noos, or even memory. These are still in the voices of those
organizations of the right temporal lobe that are called gods.
The precise causes of this internalization of sight into a container in which the seeing can be 'held' will require a much more
careful study than we can go into here. Perhaps it was simply
the generalization of internalization which I suggest had occurred
earlier in those internalizations correlated with large internal
sensations. Or it may have been that the observation of external
difference in the mingling of refugees, as mentioned in II.3,
demanded the positing of this visual hypostasis, which could be
different in different men, making them see different things.
Psyche
And so finally to the word that gives psychology its name.
Probably coming from the term psychein = to breathe, it has
become internalized into life substances in its main usage in the
9 A further exception to what I am saying can be found in the comparison of the
swiftness of Hera with the swiftness of a man's nous wishing in his phrenes to be in
distant places he has once visited (15 : 8of.). On the peculiarity of such an expression
in Homer, see Walter Leaf, A Companion to the Iliad (London: Macmillan, 1892),
p. 257. This is obviously a late incursion.
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
271
Iliad. Most often, psyche seems to be used in just the way we
would use life. But this can be very misleading. For 'life' to us
means something about a period of time, a span between birth and
death, full of events and developments of a certain character.
There is absolutely nothing of this sort in the Iliad. When a
spear strikes the heart of a warrior, and his psyche dissolves
(5:296), is destroyed (22:325), or simply leaves him (16:453),
or is coughed out through the mouth (9:409), or bled out
through a wound (14:518; 16:505), there is nothing whatever
about time or about the end of anything. There is in one part of
Book 23 a different meaning of psyche, a discussion of which is
deferred to the end of this chapter. But generally, it is very
simply a property that can be taken away, and is similar to the
taking away, under the same conditions, of thumos or activity, a
word with which psyche is often coupled.
In trying to understand these terms, we must refrain from our
conscious habit of building space into them before this has happened historically. In a sense, psyche is the most primitive of
these preconscious hypostases; it is simply the property of
breathing or bleeding or what not in that physical object over
there called a man or an animal, a property which can be taken
from him like a prize (22:161) by a spear in the right place.
And in general, that is, with the exceptions I discuss at the end
of this chapter, the main use of psyche in the Iliad does not
progress beyond that. No one in any way ever sees, decides,
thinks, knows, fears, or remembers anything in his psyche.
These then are the supposed substantives inside the body that
by literary metaphor, by being compared to containers and persons, accrue to themselves spatial and behavioral qualities which
in later literature develop into the unified mind-space with its
analog CP that we have come to call consciousness. But in pointing out these beginnings in the Iliad, let me remind you that the
contours of the main actions of the poem are as divinely dictated
and as nonconscious as I have insisted in 1.3. These precon-
272
The Witness of History
scious hypostases do not enter into any major decisions. But they
are definitely there playing a subsidiary role. It is indeed as if the
unitary conscious mind of the later age is here in the Iliad beginning as seven different entities, each with a slightly different
function and a distinction from the others which is almost impossible for us to appreciate today.
THE WILES
OF
THE
ODYSSEY
After the Iliad, the Odyssey. And anyone reading these poems
freshly and consecutively sees what a gigantic vault in mentality
it is! There are of course some scholars who still like to think of
these two huge epics as being written down and even composed
by one man named Homer, the first in his youth and the second
in his maturity. The more reasonable view, I think, is that the
Odyssey followed the Iliad by at least a century or more, and, like
its predecessor, was the work of a succession of aoidoi rather than
any one man.
But, unlike its predecessor, the Odyssey is not one epic but
a series of them. The originals were probably about different
heroes, and brought together around Odysseus at a later time.
W h y this happened is not hard to unravel. Odysseus, at least in
some parts of Greece, had become the center of a cult that
enabled conquered peoples to survive. He becomes "wily Odysseus" and later aoidoi perhaps inserted this epithet into the Iliad
to remind their listeners of the Odyssey. Archaeological evidence
indicates important dedications made to Odysseus some time
after iooo b . C . and definitely before 800 B . C .
These were
sometimes of bronze tripod caldrons curiously connected with the
cult. They were such dedications as formerly would have been
to a god. Contests in worship of him were held in Ithaca at least
1 0
10 S. Benton, as cited in T. B. L. Webster, From Mycenae to Homer (London:
Methuen, 1958), p. 138.
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
273
from the ninth century B.C., even as that island was about to be
overrun again by new invasions from Corinth. In a word, Odysseus
of the many devices is the hero of the new mentality of how to get
along in a ruined and god-weakened world.
The Odyssey announces this in its very fifth word, polutropon
= much turning. It is a journey of deviousness. It is the very
discovery of guile, its invention and celebration. It sings of indirections and disguises and subterfuges, transformations and
recognitions, drugs and forgetfulness, of people in other people's
places, of stories within stories, and men within men.
The contrast with the Iliad is astonishing. Both in word and
deed and character, the Odyssey describes a new and different
world inhabited by new and different beings. The bicameral gods
of the Iliad, in crossing over to the Odyssey, have become defensive and feeble. They disguise themselves more and even indulge
in magic wands. The bicameral mind by its very definition directs much less of the action. The gods have less to do, and like
receding ghosts talk more to each other — and that so tediously!
The initiatives move from them, even against them, toward the
work of the more conscious human characters, though overseen
by a Zeus who in losing his absolute power has acquired a Learlike interest in justice. Seers and omens, these hallmarks of the
breakdown of bicamerality, are more common. Semi-gods, dehumanizing witches, one-eyed giants, and sirens, reminiscent of
the genii that we saw marked the breakdown of bicamerality in
Assyrian bas-reliefs a few centuries earlier, are evidence of a
profound alteration in mentality. And the huge Odysseyan
themes of homeless wanderings, of kidnapings and enslavements, of things hidden, things regained, are surely echoes of the
social breakdown following the Dorian invasions when subjective consciousness in Greece first took its mark.
Technically, the first thing to note is the change in the frequency with which the preconscious hypostases are used. Such
data can be compiled easily from concordances of the Iliad and
274
The Witness of History
Odyssey, and the results are dramatic in showing a very definite
rise in frequency for phrenes, noos, and psyche, and a striking
drop in the use of the word thumos. Of course we can say that the
decrease for thumos from the Iliad to the Odyssey is due to what
the poem is about. But that is begging the question. For the very
change in theme is indeed a part of this whole transition in the
very nature of man. The other hypostases are passive. Thumosy
the adrenalin-produced emergency reaction of the sympathetic
nervous system to novel situations, is the antithesis of anything
passive. The kind of metaphors that can be built up around this
metaphrand of a sudden surge of energy are not the passive
visual ones that are more conducive to solving problems.
In contrast, over this period, phrenes doubles in frequency,
while both noos and psyche triple in frequency. Again, the point
could be made that the increase in the use of these words is
simply an echo of the change in topics. And again that is precisely the point. Poetry, from describing external events objectively, is becoming subjectified into a poetry of personal conscious
expression.
But it is not just their frequency that we are interested in. It is
also the change in their inherent meanings and the metaphiers
used for them. As the gods decrease in their direction of human
affairs, the preconscious hypostases take over some of their
divine function, moving them closer to consciousness. Thumos,
though decreased, is still the most common hypostatic word. And
its function is different. It has reached the subjective phase and
is like another person. It is the thumos of the swineherd that
'commands' him to return to Telemachus (16:466). In the Iliad,
it would have been a god speaking. In the earlier epic, a god can
'place' menos or vigor into the 'container' of the thumos; but in
the Odyssey, it is an entire recognition that can be 'placed'
therein. Eurycleia recognizes Odysseus under his disguise by his
scar because a god has 'put' that recognition in her thumos
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
275
(19:485)- (Note that she has recognition but not recall.) And
the servants of Penelope have knowledge of her son's departure
in their thumos (4:730).
Phrenes too has acquired the spatial qualities of Phase III.
Even the description of a possible future event can be put in the
phrenes, as when Telemachus, as a pretext for depriving the
suitors of weapons, is asked to claim that a daimon (it would
have at least been a god in the Iliad) has put fears of quarrels
among them into his phrenes (19:10). There are no secrets in
the Iliad. But the Odyssey has many of them, and they are 'held'
in the phrenes (16:459). Whereas in the Iliad the preconscious
hypostases were almost always clearly located, their increasingly
metaphorical nature is muddling up their anatomical distinction
in the Odyssey. Even the thumos is at one point located inside the
lungs or phrenes (22:38).
But there is another and even more important use of fhrenes,
this word that originally referred to the lungs and then to the
complex sensations in breathing. And this is in the first beginnings of morality. No one is moral among the god-controlled
puppets of the Iliad. Good and evil do not exist. But in the
Odyssey, Clytaemnestra is able to resist Aegisthus because her
phrenes are agathai, which may have been derived from roots
that would make it mean 'very like a god'. And in another place,
it is tht agathai. godly, or good phrenes of Eumaeus which has
him remember to make offerings to the gods (14:421). And
similarly it is the agathai or good phrenes that are responsible for
Penelope's chastity and loyalty to the absent Odysseus (12:194).
It is not yet Penelope who is agathe, only the metaphor-space in
her lungs.
And similarly with the other preconscious hypostases. Warnings of destruction are 'heard' from the kradie or pounding heart
of Odysseus when he is wrecked and thrown into tempestuous
seas (5:389). And it is his ker, again his trembling heart or
perhaps his trembling hands, that makes plans for the suitors'
276
The Witness of History
downfall (18:344). In the Iliad, these would have been gods
speaking. Noos, while being referred to more frequently, is sometimes not changed. But more often it is also in Phase III of
subjectification. At one point, Odysseus is deceiving Athene (unthinkable in the Iliad!) and looks at her ever revolving in his noos
thoughts of great cunning (13:255). Or noos can be like a
person who is glad (8:78) or cruel (18:381) or not to be fooled
(10:329) or learned about (1:3). Psyche again usually means
life, but perhaps with more sense of a time span. Some very important exceptions to this will be referred to later.
Not only is the growth toward subjective consciousness in the
Odyssey seen in the increasing use and spatial interiority and
personification of its preconscious hypostases, but even more
clearly in its incidents and social interrelationships. These include the emphasis on deceit and guile which I have already
referred to. In the Iliad, time is referred to sloppily and inaccurately, if at all. But the Odyssey shows an increased spatialization of time in its use of time words, such as begin, hesitate,
quickly, endure, etc., and the more frequent reference to the
future. There is also an increased ratio of abstract terms to
concrete, particularly of what in English would be nouns ending
in ‘ness’. And with this, as might be expected, a marked drop in
similes: there is less need for them. Both the frequency and the
manner with which Odysseus refers to himself is on a different
level altogether from instances of self-reference in the Iliad. All
this is relevant to the growth of a new mentality.
Let me close this necessarily short entry on a toweringly important poem by calling your attention to a mystery. This is that
the overall contour of the story itself is a myth of the very matter
with which we are concerned. It is a story of identity, of a voyage
to the self that is being created in the breakdown of the bicameral
mind. I am not pretending here to be answering the profound
question of why this should be so, of why the muses, those
patternings of the right temporal lobe, who are singing this epic
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
277
through the aoidoi, should be narratizing their own downfall,
their own fading away into subjective thought, and celebrating
the rise of a new mentality that will overwhelm the very act of
their song. For this seems to be what is happening.
I am saying — and finding it work to believe myself — that all
this highly patterned legend, which so clearly can be taken as a
metaphor of the huge transilience toward consciousness, was not
composed, planned, and put together by poets conscious of what
they were doing. It is as if the god-side of the bicameral man was
approaching consciousness before the man-side, the right hemisphere before the left. And if belief does stick here, and we are
inclined to ask scoffingly and rhetorically, how could an epic that
may itself be a kind of drive toward consciousness be composed
by nonconscious men? We can also ask with the same rhetorical
fervor, how could it have been composed by conscious men? And
have the same silence follow. We do not know the answer to
either question.
But so it is. And as this series of stories sweeps from its lost
hero sobbing on an alien shore in bicameral thrall to his beautiful
goddess Calypso, winding through its world of demigods, testings,
and deceits, to his defiant war whoops in a rival-routed home,
from trance through disguise to recognition, from sea to land,
east to west, defeat to prerogative, the whole long song is an
odyssey toward subjective identity and its triumphant acknowledgment out of the hallucinatory enslavements of the past. From
a will-less gigolo of a divinity to the gore-spattered lion on his
own hearth, Odysseus becomes 'Odysseus'.
FOOLISH
PERSES
Some of the chronologically next group of poems I shall merely
gloss over. Among these are the so-called Homeric Hymns, most
of which have turned out to be of a much later date. There are
278
The Witness of History
also the poems that originated in Boeotia northeast of Athens in
the eighth century B.C., many of which were once ascribed to a
cult figure named Hesiod. Unfortunately, their extant texts are
often mixtures of parts of poems from obviously different
sources, badly emended. Most of them contribute little to our
present concern. The often tedious recital of the relationships of
gods in the Theogony is usually dated shortly after the Odyssey,
but its hypostatic words are fewer and without development. Its
chief interest is that its concern with the intimate lives of gods is
perhaps a result of their silence, another expression of the nostalgia for the Golden Age before the Dorian invasions.
But of much greater interest is the fascinating problem presented by the text ascribed to Hesiod known as the Works and
Days.11 It is obviously a hodgepodge of various things, a kind of
Shepherd's Calendar for a Boeotian farmer, and a very poor and
scrubbing farmer at that. Its world is worlds away from the
world of the great Homeric epics. Instead of a hero at the command of his gods working through a narrative of grandeur, we
have instruction to the countryman, who may or may not obey his
gods, on ways of work, which days are lucky, and a very interesting new sense of justice.
On the surface, this medley of scruffy detail of farm life and
nostalgia for the Golden Age that is no more seems to be written
by a farmer whom scholars take to be Hesiod. He is supposedly
railing at his brother, Perses, over the unfairness of a judgment
dividing their father's farm, curiously giving Perses advice on
everything from morality to marriage, on how to treat slaves to
the problems of planting and sewage disposal. It is full of such
things as:
Foolish Perses!
W o r k the work which the gods ordained for
men, lest in bitter anguish of thumosy you with your wife and
children seek your livelihood amongst your neighbors. ( 3 9 7 f f . )
11 I have used throughout the Loeb edition of Hesiod (London: Heinemann,
1936).
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
279
At least this is what most scholars take the poem to be. But
another interpretation is at least possible. This is that the older
portions of the poem may actually have been written not by
Hesiod, who is never mentioned in the poem, but by none other
than the hand of foolish Perses himself, and that these main
parts of the poem are the admonitions of his divine bicameral
voice advising him what to do. If this jolts your sense of possibility, I would remind you of the schizophrenic patients who all day
may hear similarly authoritative critical voices constantly admonishing them in a similar vein.
Perhaps I should not say written. More probably the poem was
dictated to a scribe, even as were the bicameral admonitions of
Perses’ contemporary, Amos, the herdsman of Israel. And I
should also have said a previous recension of the main poem, and
that the protest lodged in the crucial lines 37-39 were added later
(even as everyone since Plutarch has agreed that 654-662 were).
It is also possible that these lines originally referred to some kind
of bicameral struggle for the control of Perses’ too subjective and
therefore (at this time) unprofitable behavior.
The preconscious hypostases in the Works and Days occur in
approximately the same frequencies as in the Odyssey. Thumos
is the most common and in about half of its eighteen occurrences
it is a simple Phase II internal impulse to some activity or locus of
joy or sorrow. But the rest of the time, it is a Phase III space in
which information (27), advice (297, 491), sights (296), or
mischief (499) can be ‘put’, ‘kept’, or ‘held’. The phrenes also are
like a cupboard, where the advice that is constantly given in the
poem (107, 274) is to be laid up, and where foolish Perses is to
‘look’ at it carefully (688). The kradie has the metaphier of a
person more than a container, and can be gracious (340), vexed
(451), or can like and dislike things (681). But psyche (686) and
etor (360, 593) are undeveloped and are simply life and belly
respectively.
Noos in the Works and Days is interesting because, in all four
280
The Witness of History
of its instances, it is like a person relating to moral conduct. In
two instances (67, 714) it has shame or not, and in another, it is
adikon, without good direction (260). A proper study of the
matter would point out in detail the particular development of the
term dike. Its original meaning was to point (from which comes
the original meaning of digit, as a finger), and in the Iliad its
most parsimonious translation is as “direction,” in the sense of
pointing out what to do. Sarpedon guarded Lycia by his dike
(Iliad 16:542). But in the Works and Days, it has come to mean
god-given right directions or justice, perhaps as a replacement for
the god's voice.12 It is a silent Zeus, son of a now spatialized
time, who here for the first time dispenses dike or justice more or
less as we know it in later Greek literature. (See for example
267ff.). How absolutely alien to the amoral world of the Iliad,
that a whole city can suffer for one evil man (240)!
Our sense of justice depends on our sense of time. Justice is a
phenomenon only of consciousness, because time spread out in a
spatial succession is its very essence. And this is possible only in
a spatial metaphor of time. Instances of this increased spatialization are common. Committing violence at one time begets a
punishment at some time to follow (245f.). Long and steep is
the path to goodness (290). A good man is he who sees what
will be better afterward (294). Add little to little and it will
become great (362). Work with work upon work to gain wealth
(382). These notions are impossible unless the before and after
of time are metaphored into a spatial succession. This basic
ingredient of consciousness, which began in Assyrian building
inscriptions in 1300 B.C. (see the previous chapter), has indeed
come a long way.
It is important here to understand how closely coupled this
12 But that the
origin of this new sense of god-sent justice is possibly in an hallucinated messenger from Zeus is suggested where Dike is said to moan and weep
when men take bribes and do evil (22of). My derivation here of dike is not the
usual one.
281
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
new sense of time and justice is to what can be called the secularization of attention. By this I mean the shift in attention toward
the everyday problems of making a living, something that is
totally foreign to the mighty god-devised epics which preceded it.
Whether the poem itself is divinely inspired, or, as the majority
of scholars think, the sulky exhortations of Perses' brother
Hesiod, it is a dramatic turning point in the direction of human
concern. Instead of grand impersonal narrative, we have a detailed personal expression. Instead of an ageless past, we have a
vivid expression of a present wedged in between a past and a
future. And it is a present of grim harshness that described the
post-Dorian rural reality, full of petty strife and the struggle of
wresting a living from the land, while around its edges hovers the
nostalgia for the mighty golden world of bicameral Mycaenae,
whose people were a race
. . . which was more lawful and more righteous, a god-like
race of hero-men who are called half-gods, the race before our
own, throughout the boundless earth. ( 1 5 8 5 . ) .
L Y R I C
A N D
T O
E L E G Y
600
F R O M
700
B.C.
I was about to write that Greek consciousness is nearing completion in the Works and Days. But that is a very misleading metaphor, that consciousness is a thing that is built, formed, shaped
into something that has a completion. There is no such thing as
a complete consciousness.
What I would have been indicating was that the basic metaphors of time with space, of internal hypostases as persons in a
mental space have begun to work themselves into the guides and
guardians of everyday life.
282
The Witness of History
Against this development, the Greek poetry of the seventh
century B.C., which follows chronologically, is something of an
anticlimax. But this is because so little of these elegiac and lyric
poets has escaped the eager ravages of time. If we take only those
who have at least a dozen lines extant, there are only seven poets
to be considered.
The first thing to say about them is that they are not simply
poets, as we regard the term. As a group, they are something like
their contemporaries, the prophets of Israel, holy teachers of men,
called by kings to settle disputes and to lead armies, resembling
in some of their functions the shamans of contemporary tribal
cultures. At the beginning of the century, they were probably
still associated with holy dancing. But gradually the dance and
its religious aura are lost in a secularity that is chanted to the lyre
or the sounds of flutes. These artistic changes, however, are
merely coincident to changes of a much more important kind.
The Works and Days expressed the present. The new poetry
expresses the person in that present, the particular individual
and how he is different from others. And celebrates that difference. And as it does so, we can trace a progressive filling out and
stretching of the earlier preconscious hypostases into the mindspace of consciousness.
In the first part of the century is Terpander, the inventor of
drinking songs, according to Pindar, one of whose thirteen extant
lines cries out over the centuries:
Of the Far-flinging Lord come sing to me, O Phrenes! 1 3
This is interesting. The Lord here is Apollo. But note that while
the poem itself is to be a nostalgic poem to a lost god, it is not a
13 Fragment
2 in the Loeb edition, Lyra Graeca, edited by J. M. Edmonds (London: Heinemann, 1928). All references in this section are to this volume or to the
companion Loeb volumes, Elegy and Iambus, Vols. 1 and 2, also edited by Edmonds (London: Heinemann, 1931).
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
283
god or a muse who is invoked to compose it. In the Odyssey, a
god puts songs into the phrenes which the minstrel then sings as
if he were reading the music (22:347). But for Terpander, who
hears no gods, it is his own phrenes that are begged to compose a
song just as if they were a god. And this implicit comparison, I
suggest, with its associated paraphrands of a space in which the
deiform phrenes could exist, is well on the way to creating the
mind-space with its Analog 'I' of consciousness.
It is not just in such word usages that this transition in the
seventh century is apparent, but also in the subject matter. For
the secularization and personalization of content begun in the
Works and Days fairly explodes in midcentury in the angry iambics of Archilochus, the wandering soldier-poet of Paros. According to the inscription of his tomb, it was he who "first dipt a bitter
Muse in snake-venom and stained gentle Helicon with blood," a
reference to the story that he could provoke suicides with the
power of his iambic abuse.14 Even using poetry this way, to
engage in personal vendettas and state personal preferences, is a
new thing to the world. And so close to modern reflective consciousness do some of these fragments come, that the loss of
most of Archilochus' work opens one of the greatest gaps in
ancient literature.
But the gods, though never heard by Archilochus, still control
the world. " T h e ends of victory are among the gods" (Fragment
55). And the hypostases remain. The bad effects of drink
(Fragment 77) or of old age (Fragment 94) occur in the
phrenes; and when he is troubled, it is his thumos which is
thrown down like a weak warrior and is told to "look up and
defend yourself against your enemies" (Fragment 66). Archilochus talks to his thumos as to another person, the implicit
comparison and its paraphrands of space and self-'observed' 'self'
14 According to the Palatine Anthology collected about a.d. 920 from previous
sources. See Edmonds, Elegy and Iambus, 2:97.
284
The Witness of History
being a further step toward the consciousness of the next century.
Chronologically next come two other soldier-poets, Tyrtaeus
and Callinus, whose remaining fragments are of little interest.
Their most common hypostasis is thumos, and they do little
more than urge us to keep an unfaltering thumos in battle.
And then, about 630 B.C., two poets of a different kind, Alcman
and Mimnermus. They urge nothing, but celebrate their own
subjective feelings in a way that had never been done before.
" W h o may report the noos of another?" (Fragment 55) asks the
former, making the metaphor of noos as a happening with its
obvious paraphrand consequences. And Mimnermus complains
of the ill cares that wear and wear his phrenes (Fragment 1) and
of the "sorrows that rise in the thumos" (Fragment 2). This is a
long way from the simple hypostases of the Homeric epics.
At the end of this presageful century come the poems of
Alcaeus and, particularly, the empty-armed passions of virile
Sappho, the tenth muse as Plato calls her. Both these poets of
Lesbos say the usual things about their thumos and phrenes>
using both about equally. Sappho even sings about the theloi or
arrangements of her thumos which become our desires and volitions (Fragment 36:3). And she practically invents love in its
romantic modern sense. Love wrings her thumos with anguish
(Fragment 43) and shakes her phrenes as a hurricane shakes an
oak tree (Fragment 54).
But more important is the development of the term noema.
By the late seventh century, it is clear that noema has come to
mean a composite of what we mean by thoughts, wishes, intents,
etc., and joining up with the theloi of the thumos. Alcaeus says,
" I f Zeus will accomplish what is our noema" (Fragment 43). He
describes a speaker as not "prevaricating (or excusing) his
noema at all" (Fragment 144). In those shards of Sappho that
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
285
remain, the word is used three times: toward those she loves,
"my noema can never change" (Fragment 14); her "noema is not
so softly disposed to the anger of a child" (Fragment 35) ; and in
her complaint, "I know not what to do; my noemata are in two
parts . .
(Fragment 52). This puts the emphasis on the
imagined internal metaphor-thing that is hypostasized into a
thought. It is love that is teaching mankind to introspect. And
there is even another word in Sappho, sunoiday whose roots would
indicate that it means to know together, which, when Latinized,
becomes the word 'conscious' (Fragment 15).
In these seven poets of the seventh century, then, we find a
remarkable development, that, as the subject matter changed
from martial exhortations to personal expressions of love, the
manner in which the mental hypostases are used and their contexts become much more what we think of as subjective consciousness.
These are murky historical waters, and we may be sure that
these seven poets, with their few fragments bobbing in the extant
surface of the seventh century B.C., are but an indication of the
many that probably then existed and helped develop the new
mentality we are calling consciousness.
SOLON'S
MIND
I particularly feel that these seven cannot be representative of
the time, for the very next poet chronologically that we know of is
dramatically different from any of them. He is the morning star
of the Greek intellect, the man who alone, so far as we know,
really filled out the idea of human justice. This is Solon of
Athens, who stands at the beginning of the great sixth century
B.C., the century of Thales, Anaximander, and Pythagoras. It is
the century where, for the first time, we can feel mentally at
286
The Witness of History
home among persons who think in somewhat the way we do.
The swiftness of the unfolding of these greatnesses of Greek
culture is astonishing. And if for no other reason, Solon, at the
beginning of all this, is astonishing for his use of the word noos.
The word is rarely used by any of the poets we have previously
looked at. But in the mere 280 (approximately) lines that have
come down to us, he uses noos eight times. This is an extremely
high frequency of 44 per 10,000) words. It indicates Phase IV, in
which the several hypostases are joining into one. Thumos is
used only twice, and phrenes and etor once each.
But it is also the way he speaks about the noos that is the first
real statement of the subjective conscious mind. He speaks of
those whose noos is not artios, which means intact or whole
(Fragment 6). How impossible to say of a recognition! It is the
noos that is wrong in a bad leader (Fragment 4). The Homeric
meaning of noos could not take moral epithets. At about age
forty-two, "a man's noos is trained in all things." Certainly this is
not his visual perception. And in his fifties, he is "at his best in
noos and tongue" (Fragment 27).
Another fragment describes the true beginning of personal
responsibility, where he warns his fellow Athenians not to blame
the gods for their misfortunes, but themselves. How contrary to
the mind of the Iliad! And then adds,
Each one of you walks with the steps of a fox; the noos of
all of you is chaunos [porous, spongy, or loose-grained as in
wood] : for you look to a man's tongue and rapidly shifting
speech, and never to the deed he does. (Fragment 10).
Not Achilles nor artful Odysseus nor even foolish Perses (or his
brother) could have 'understood' this admonition.
Consciousness and morality are a single development. For
without gods, morality based on a consciousness of the consequences of action must tell men what to do. The dike or justice
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
287
of the Works and Days is developed even further in Solon. It is
now moral right that must be fitted together with might in government (Fragment 36) and which is the basis of law and lawful
action.
Sometimes attributed to Solon are certain other injunctions,
such as his exhortation to "moderation in all things." But more
germane to the present topic is the famous "Know thyself," which
is often ascribed to him but may have come from one of his
contemporaries. This again was something inconceivable to the
Homeric heroes. How can one know oneself? By initiating by
oneself memories of one's actions and feelings and looking at
them together with an analog 'I', conceptualizing them, sorting
them out into characteristics, and narratizing so as to know what
one is likely to do. One must 'see' 'oneself' as in an imaginary
'space,' indeed what we were calling autoscopic illusions back in
an early chapter.
Suddenly, then, we are in the modern subjective age. We can
only regret that the literature of the seventh century B.C. is so
shredded and scant as to make this almost full appearance of
subjective consciousness in Solon almost implausible, if we regard him as simply a part of the Greek tradition. But the legends
about Solon are many. And several of them insist that he was
widely traveled, having visited countries of Asia Minor before
returning to Athens to live out his life and write most of his
poems. It is thus certainly a suggestion that his particular use of
the word noos and his reification of the term into the imaginary
mind-space of consciousness was due to the influence of these
more developed nations.
With Solon, partly because he was the political leader of his
time, the operator of consciousness is firmly established in
Greece. He has a mind-space called a noos in which an analog of
himself can narratize out what is dike or right for his people to
do. Once established, once a man can 'know himself,' as Solon
288
The Witness of History
advised, can place 'times' together in the side-by-sideness of mindspace, can 'see' into himself and his world with the 'eye' of his
noos, the divine voices are unnecessary, at least to everyday life.
They have been pushed aside into special places called temples
or special persons called oracles. And that the new unitary nous
(as it came to be spelled), absorbing the functions of the other
hypostases, was successful is attested by all the literature that
followed, as well as the reorganization of behavior and society.
But we are somewhat ahead of our story. For there is another
development in this important sixth century B.C., and one which
is a huge complication for the future. It is an old term, psychey
used in an unpredictably new way. In time it comes to parallel and
then to become interchangeable with nous, while at the same
time it engenders that consciousness of consciousness which was
held up as false at the beginning of Book I. Moreover, I shall
suggest that this new concept is an almost artifactual result of a
meeting between Greek and Egyptian cultures.
THE
INVENTION
OF
THE
SOUL
Psyche is the last of these words to come to have 'space' inside it.
This is due, I think, to the fact that psyche or livingness did not
lend itself to a container-type metaphor until the conscious spatialization of time had so far developed that a man had a life in
the sense of a time span, rather than just in the sense of breath
and blood. But the progress of psyche toward the concept of soul
is not that clear at all.
For, more than the other hypostases, psyche is sometimes used
in confusing ways that seem on the surface to defy a chronological
ordering. Its primary use is always for life, as I have stated.
After the Homeric poems, Tyrtaeus, for example, uses psyche in
that sense (Fragments 10 and 11), as does Alcaeus (Fragment
77B). And even as late as the fifth century B.C., Euripides uses
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
289
the phrase "to be fond of one's psyche" in the sense of clinging to
life (Iphigenia at Aulis, 1385). Some of the Aristotelian writings
also use psyche as life, and this usage even extends into much of
the New Testament. "I am the good shepherd: the good shepherd giveth his psyche for his sheep" (John, 10:11). Jesus did not
mean his mind or soul.
But in Achilles' dream at the beginning of Book 23 of the Iliad,
the psyche of the dead Patroclus visits him, and when he tries to
hug it in his arms, it sinks gibbering into the earth. The grizzly
scenes in Hades in Books 11 and 24 of the Odyssey use psyche in a
similar way. The term in these instances has an almost opposite
sense from its meaning in the rest of both Iliad and Odyssey. Not
life, but that which exists after life has ceased. Not what is bled
out of one's veins in battle, but the soul or ghost that goes to
Hades, a concept that is otherwise unheard of in Greek literature
until Pindar, around 500 B.C. In all the intervening writers we
have been looking at through the eighth and seventh centuries
B.C., psyche is never the ghost-soul, but always has its original
meaning of life or livingness.
Now, no amount of twisting about in semantic origins can
reconcile these two gratingly different significations for psyche}
one relating to life and the other to death. The obvious suggestion here is that these alien incongruities in Homer are interpolations of a period much later than the ostensible period of the
poems. And indeed this is what the majority of scholars are sure
of on much more ample grounds than we can go into here. Since
this meaning of psyche does not appear until Pindar, we may be
fairly confident that these passages about Hades and the souls of
the dead abiding there in its shades were added into the Homeric
poems shortly before Pindar, sometime in the sixth century B.C.
The problem then is how and why did this dramatically different concept of psyche come about? And let us be clear here that
the only thing we are talking about is the application of the old
word for life to what survives after death and its separability
from the body. The actual survival, as we have seen in previous
290
The Witness of History
chapters, is not in doubt. According to the theory of the bicameral mind, hallucinations of a person in some authority could
continue after death as an everyday matter. And hence the almost universal custom of feeding the corpses after death, and
burying them with the appurtenances of life.
I am unable to suggest a truly satisfactory solution. But certainly a part of it is the influence of that towering legend-laden
figure of antiquity, Pythagoras. Flourishing around the middle of
the sixth century B.C., he is thought to have traveled, as did
Solon, to several countries of Asia Minor, particularly Egypt. He
then returned and established a kind of mystical secret society in
Crotona in southern Italy. They practiced mathematics, vegetarianism, and a firm illiteracy — to write things down was a source
of error. Among these teachings, as we have them at least at
third hand from later writers, was the doctrine of the transmigration of souls. After death, a man's soul enters the body of a
newborn infant or animal and so lives another life.
Herodotus has been flouted for saying Pythagoras learned this
in Egypt. But if one agrees with the theory of the bicameral
mind, the origin of soul transmigration in Egyptian ideas is not
difficult to trace. I suggest it was a Greek misunderstanding of
the functions of the ba, which, as we saw in II.2, was often the
seeming physical embodiment of the ka, or hallucinated voice
after death. Often the ba had the form of a bird. Greek, however, had no word for ka (other than a god — clearly inappropriate), or for ba, indeed no word for a 'life' which could be
transferred from one material body to another. Hence psyche
was pressed into this service. A l l references to this Pythagorean
teaching use psyche in this new sense, as a clearly separable soul
that can migrate from one body to another as could an hallucinated voice in Egypt.
Now this does not really solve our problem. For there is nothing here of dead strengthless souls wailing about in a netherworld, guzzling hot blood to get their strength back — which is
INTELLECTUAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
GREECE
291
the lively scene added into the Odyssey as Rook u. But the
psyche here is somewhat the same, a something of a man which
leaves the body at death. And what the Hades view of psyche
may be is a composite of the Pythagorean teaching with the older
view of the buried dead in Greek antiquity.
A l l this curious development of the sixth century B.C. is extremely important for psychology. For with this wrenching of
psyche = life over to psyche = soul, there came other changes to
balance it as the enormous inner tensions of a lexicon always do.
The word soma had meant corpse or deadness, the opposite of
psyche as livingness. So now, as psyche becomes soul, so soma
remains as its opposite, becoming body. And dualism, the supposed separation of soul and body, has begun.
But the matter does not stop there. In Pindar, Heraclitus, and
others around 500 B.C., psyche and nous begin to coalesce. It is
now the conscious subjective mind-space and its self that is opposed to the material body. Cults spring up about this new
wonder-provoking division between psyche and soma. It both
excites and seems to explain the new conscious experience, thus
reinforcing its very existence. The conscious psyche is imprisoned in the body as in a tomb. It becomes an object of wide-eyed
controversy. Where is it? And the locations in the body or outside it vary. What is it made of? Water (Thales), blood, air
(Anaximenes), breath (Xenophanes), fire (Heraclitus), and so
on, as the science of it all begins in a morass of pseudoquestions.
So dualism, that central difficulty in this problem of consciousness, begins its huge haunted career through history, to be firmly
set in the firmament of thought by Plato, moving through Gnosticism into the great religions, up through the arrogant assurances of Descartes to become one of the great spurious
quandaries of modern psychology.
This has been a long and technical chapter that can be briefly
summarized in a metaphor. At the beginning, we noted that
archaeologists, by brushing the dust of the ages from around the
292
The Witness of History
broken shards of pottery from the period of the Dorian invasions,
have been able to reveal continuities and changes from site to
site, and so to prove that a complex series of migrations was
occurring. In a sense, we have been doing the same thing with
language throughout this chapter. We have taken broken-off bits
of vocabulary, those that came to refer to some kind of mental
function, and by their contexts from text to text, attempted to
demonstrate that a huge complex series of changes in mentality
was going on during these obscure periods that followed the
Dorian invasions in Greece.
Let no one think these are just word changes. Word changes
are concept changes and concept changes are behavioral changes.
The entire history of religions and of politics and even of
science stands shrill witness to that. Without words like soul,
liberty, or truth, the pageant of this human condition would have
been filled with different roles, different climaxes. And so with
the words we have designated as preconscious hypostases, which
by the generating process of metaphor through these few centuries unite into the operator of consciousness.
I have now completed that part of the story of Greek consciousness that I intended to tell. More of it could be told, how
the two nonstimulus-bound hypostases come to overshadow the
rest, how nous and psyche come to be almost interchangeable in
later writers, such as Parmenides and Democritus, and take on
even new metaphor depths with the invention of logosy and of the
forms of truth, virtue, and beauty.
But that is another task. The Greek subjective conscious mind,
quite apart from its pseudostructure of soul, has been born out of
song and poetry. From here it moves out into its own history, into
the narratizing introspections of a Socrates and the spatialized
classifications and analyses of an Aristotle, and from there into
Hebrew, Alexandrian, and Roman thought. And then into the
history of a world which, because of it, will never be the same
again.
CHAPTER 6
The Moral Consciousness
of the Khabiru
T
HE THIRD great area where we can look at the development
of consciousness is certainly the most interesting and profound. All through the Middle East toward the end of the second
millennium B.C., there were large amorphous masses of halfnomadic peoples with no fixed dira or grazing ground. Some
were the refugees from the Thera destruction and the terrible
Dorian invasions which followed. One cuneiform tablet specifically speaks of migrations pouring down through the Lebanon.
Others were probably refugees from the Assyrian invasions and
were joined by the Hittite refugees when that empire fell to a
further invasion from the north. And still others may have been
the resistant bicameral individuals of the cities who could not
silence the gods so easily, and who, if not killed, would be progressively sifted out into the desert wilderness.
A mixture of men, then, coming together precariously for a
time, and then separating out, some perishing, others organizing
into unstable tribes; some raiding more settled lands, or fighting
over water holes 3 or sometimes, perhaps, caught like exhausted
animals and made to do their captor's will, or, in the desperation
of hunger, bartering control over their lives for bread and seed, as
described on some fifteenth-century B.C. tablets unearthed at
Nuzi, as well as in Genesis 47:18-26. Some perhaps were still
trying to follow inadequate bicameral voices, or clinging to the
edge of settled land, fearing to launch out, becoming breeders of
sheep and camels, while others, having struggled unsuccessfully
294
The Witness of History
to mingle with more settled peoples, then pushed out into the
open desert where only the ruthless survive, perhaps in precarious pursuit of some hallucinated vision, some back parts of a god,
some new city or promised land.
To the established city-states, these refugees were the desperate outcasts of the desert wilderness. The city people thought of
them collectively as robbers and vagrants. And so they often
were, either singly, as miserable homeless wretches stealing by
night the grapes which the vine-dressers scorned to pick, or as
whole tribes raiding the city peripheries for their cattle and produce, even as nomadic Bedouins occasionally do today. The word
for vagrants in Akkad, the language of Babylon, is khabiru and
so these desert refugees are referred to on cuneiform tablets.1
And khabiru softened in the desert air, becomes Hebrew.
The story or imagined story of the later Khabiru or Hebrews is
told in what has come down to us as the Old Testament. The
thesis to which we shall give our concern in this chapter is that
this magnificent collection of history and harangue, of song,
sermon, and story is in its grand overall contour the description
of the loss of the bicameral mind, and its replacement by subjectivity over the first millennium B.C.
We are immediately, however, presented with an orthological
problem of immense proportions. For much of the Old Testament, particularly the first books, so important to our thesis, are,
as is well known, forgeries of the seventh, sixth, and fifth centuries B.C., brilliant workings of brightly colored strands gathered
from a scatter of places and periods.2 In Genesis, for example,
the first and second chapters tell different creation stories; the
Much of this information may be found in the Bampton Lectures of Alfred
Guillaume, Prophecy and Divination among the Hebrews and Other Semites (New
York: Harper, 1938). This chapter owes a particular debt to Guillaume's richness
of discussion of these matters.
2 In matters of dating, authorship, and other exegetical material on the Old
Testament here and elsewhere in this chapter, I have relied on several authorities but
primarily the respective articles in the Encyclopaedia Britannica.
1
MORAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
THE
KHABIRU
295
story of the flood is a monotheistic rewrite of old Sumerian inscriptions;3 the story of Jacob may well date to before 1000 B.C.,
but that of Joseph, his supposed son, on the very next pages
comes from at least 500 years later.4 It had all begun with the
discovery of the manuscript of Deuteronomy in Jerusalem in 621
B.C. by King Josiah, after he ordered the temple cleaned and
cleared of its remaining bicameral rites. And Khabiru history,
like a nomad staggering into a huge inheritance, put on these rich
clothes, some not its own, and belted it all together with some
imaginative ancestry. It is thus a question whether the use of
this variegated material as evidence for any theory of mind whatever is even permissible.
Amos and Ecclesiastes Compared
Let me first address such skeptics. As I have said, most of the
books of the Old Testament were woven together from various
sources from various centuries. But some of the books are considered pure in the sense of not being compilations, but being
pretty much all of one piece, mostly what they say they are, and
to these a thoroughly accurate date can be attached. If we confine ourselves for the moment to these books, and compare the
oldest of them with the most recent, we have a fairly authentic
comparison which should give us evidence one way or another.
Among these pure books, the oldest is Amos, dating from the
eighth century B.C., and the most recent is Ecclesiastes, from the
second century B.C. They are both short books, and I hope that
you will turn to them before reading on, that you may for yourself sense authentically this difference between an almost bicameral man and a subjective conscious man.
For this evidence is dramatically in agreement with the hy3 Alexander Heidel, The Gilgamesh Efic and Old Testament Parallels, 2nd ed.
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1949), p. 224$.
4 Donald B. Redford, A Study of the Biblical Story of Joseph, Genesis 37-50
(Leiden: Brill, 1970). The original may be a secular story from Mesopotamia on the
art of divination.
296
The Witness of History
pothesis. Amos is almost pure bicameral speech, heard by an
illiterate desert herdsman, and dictated to a scribe. In Ecclesiastes, in contrast, god is rarely mentioned, let alone ever speaking
to its educated author. And even these mentions are considered
by some scholars to be later interpolations, to allow this magnificent writing into the canon.
In Amos there are no words for mind or think or feel or
understand or anything similar whatever 3 Amos never ponders
anything in his heart; he can't; he would not know what it meant.
In the few times he refers to himself, he is abrupt and informative without qualification; he is no prophet, but a mere "gatherer
of sycamore fruit"; he does not consciously think before he
speaks; in fact, he does not think as we do at all: his thought is
done for him. He feels his bicameral voice about to speak and
shushes those about him with a "Thus speaks the L o r d ! " and
follows with an angry forceful speech which he probably does not
understand himself.
Ecclesiastes is the opposite on all these points. He ponders
things as deep in the paraphrands of his hypostatic heart as is
possible. And who but a very subjective man could say, "Vanity
of vanities, all is vanity," (1:2), or say that he sees that wisdom
excels folly (2:13). One has to have an analog ‘I’ surveying a
mind-space to so see. And the famous third chapter, " T o everything there is a season, and a time to every purpose under heaven
. . ." is precisely the spatialization of time, its spreading out in
mind-space, so characteristic of consciousness as we saw in I.2.
Ecclesiastes thinks, considers, is constantly comparing one thing
and another, and making brilliant metaphors as he does so.
Amos uses external divination, Ecclesiastes never. Amos is fiercely
righteous, absolutely assured, nobly rude, speaking a blustering
god-speech with the unconscious rhetoric of an Achilles or a
Hammurabi. Ecclesiastes would be an excellent fireside friend,
mellow, kindly, concerned, hesitant, surveying all of life in a way
that would have been impossible for Amos.
These then are the extremes in the Old Testament. Similar
MORAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
THE
KHABIRU
297
comparisons can be made with other early and late books, or
early and late parts of the same book, all revealing the same
pattern, which is difficult to account for apart from the theory of
the bicameral mind.
Some Observations on the Pentateuch
We are so used to the wonderful stories of the first five books
specifically that it is almost impossible for us to see them freshly
for what they are. Indeed, in trying to do so, whatever our
religious backgrounds, we feel, if not blasphemous, at least disrespectful to the profoundest meanings of others. Such disrespect
is certainly not my intention, but it is only by a cold unworshipful
reading of these powerful pages that we can appreciate the magnitude of the mental struggle that followed the breakdown of the
bicameral mind.
Why were these books put together? The first thing to realize
is that the very motive behind their composition around Deuteronomy at this time was the nostalgic anguish for the lost bicamerality of a subjectively conscious people. This is what religion is.
And it was done just as the voice of Yahweh in particular was
not being heard with any great clarity or frequency. Whatever
their sources, the stories themselves, as they have been arranged,
reflect human psychologies from the ninth century up to the fifth
century B.C., the period during which there is progressively less
and less bicamerality.
The Elohim. Another observation I would like to make concerns that very important word which governs the whole first
chapter of Genesis, elohim. It is usually incorrectly translated in
the singular as God. 'Elohim' is a plural form; it can be used
collectively taking a, singular verb, or as a regular plural taking a
plural verb. It comes from the root of 'to be powerful', and better
translations of ‘elohim’ might be the great ones, the prominent
ones, the majesties, the judges, the mighty ones, etc.
From the point of view of the present theory, it is clear that
298
The Witness of History
elohim is a general term referring to the voice-visions of the
bicameral mind. The creation story of the first chapter of Genesis is thus a rationalization of the bicameral voices at the edge of
subjectivity. "In the beginning the voices created heaven and
earth." Taken as such, it becomes a more general myth that
could have been indigenous to all of the ancient bicameral civilizations.
He-who-is, At the particular time in history that we pick up
the story as the Pentateuch has put it together, there are only a
few remaining elohim in contrast to the large number that probably previously existed. The most important is one recognized as
Yahweh, which among several possibilities is most often translated as He-who-is. 5 Evidently one particular group of the
Khabiru, as the prophetic subjective age was approaching, was
following only the voice of He-who-is, and rewrote the elohim
creation story in a much warmer and more human way, making
He-who-is the only real elohah. And this becomes the creation
story as told from Genesis 2:4 et seq. And these two stories then
interweave with other elements from other sources to form the
first books of the Bible.
Other elohim are occasionally mentioned throughout the older
parts of the Old Testament. The most important of them is Ba'al,
usually translated as the Owner. In the Canaan of the times,
there were many Owners, one to each village, in the same way
that many Catholic cities today have their own Virgin Marys, and
yet they are all the same one.
5 The derivation of Exodus 3: 14, that Yahweh means I AM T H A T I AM, is
regarded by most scholars as folk etymology, as if somebody should claim that the
derivation of Manhattan came from a man on the island with a hat on. More serious scholarship traces the name back to an epithet, such as he who casts down or
the Downcaster. But the sense of the majority, including- the Septuagint and Latin
Vulgate, seems to be more in line with He-who-is. Cf. William Gesenius, Hebrew
and English Lexicon of the Old Testament, E. Robinson, trans., F. Brown, ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952), p. 218. I must ask the forbearance of professional'
scholars for my inconsistency in straining for the English here while keeping other
terms such as elohim and nabi in the Hebrew. My purpose is the defamiliarization
which I feel is essential for my main point.
MORAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
THE
KHABIRU
299
Paradise Lost. A further observation could be made upon the
story of the Fall and how it is possible to look upon it as a myth of
the breakdown of the bicameral mind. The Hebrew arum> meaning crafty or deceitful, surely a conscious subjective word, is only
used three or four times throughout the entire Old Testament. It
is here used to describe the source of the temptation. The ability
to deceive, we remember, is one of the hallmarks of consciousness. The serpent promises that "you shall be like the elohim
themselves, knowing good and evil" (Genesis 3:5), qualities that
only subjective conscious man is capable of. And when these first
humans had eaten of the tree of knowledge, suddenly "the eyes of
them both were opened," their analog eyes in their metaphored
mind-space, "and they knew that they were naked" (Genesis
3:7), or had autoscopic visions and were narratizing, seeing
themselves as others see them.6 And so is their sorrow "greatly
multipled" (Genesis 3:16) and they are cast out from the garden
where He-who-is could be seen and talked with like another
man.
As a narratization of the breakdown of the bicameral mind and
the coming of consciousness, the story should be rationalistically
contrasted with the Odyssey as discussed in the previous chapter.
But the problems are similar, as is the awe we should feel toward
its unknown composition.
The Nabiim who naba. The Hebrew word nabi,7 which has
been misleadingly translated by the Greek designation of
'prophet', presents an extremely interesting difficulty. To prophesy in its modern connotations is to foretell the future, but this is
not what is indicated by the verb naba, whose practitioners were
the nabiim (plural of nabi). These terms come from a group of
cognate words which have nothing to do with time, but rather
6 It is interesting in this connection to read Maimonides, Guide of the Perplexed, I:2.
7 Transliteration from Hebrew into English is always misleading. Perhaps a better
case here might be made for nbi or nvi. That its meaning was ambiguous even at the
time seems to be indicated in I Samuel 9:9. See also John L. McKenzie, A Theology
of the Old Testament (New York: Doubleday, 1974), p. 85.
300
The Witness of History
with flowing and becoming bright. Thus we may think of a nabi
as one who metaphorically was flowing forth or welling up with
speech and visions. They were transitional men, partly subjective and partly bicameral. And once the bright torrent was released and the call came, the nabi must deliver his bicameral
message, however unsuspecting (Amos 7:14-15), however unworthy the nabi felt (Exodus 3:113 Isaiah 6; Jeremiah 1:6),
however distrustful at times of his own hearing (Jeremiah 20:710). What does it feel like to be a nabi at the beginning of one of
his bicameral periods? Like a red hot coal in one's mouth (Isaiah
6:7) or a raging fire shut up in one's bones that cannot be
contained (Jeremiah 20:9) and that only the flowing forth of
divine speech can quench.
The story of the nabiim can be told in two ways. One is
external, tracing out their early role and the acceptance of their
leadership to their massacre and total suppression in about the
fourth century B.C. But as evidence for the theory in this book, it
is more instructive to look at the matter from the internal point of
view, the changes in the bicameral experience itself. These
changes are: the gradual loss of the visual component, the growing inconsistency of the voices in different persons, and the increasing inconsistency within the same person, until the voices of
the elohim vanish from history. I shall take each of these up in
turn.
The Loss of the Visual Component
In the true bicameral period, there was usually a visual component to the hallucinated voice, either itself hallucinated or as the
statue in front of which one listened. The quality and frequency
of the visual component certainly varied from one culture to
another, as can be indicated by the presence of hallucinogenic
statuary in some cultures and not in others.
If only because its sources are so chronologically diverse, it is
MORAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
THE
KHABIRU
301
somewhat astonishing to find the Pentateuch consistently and
successively describing the loss of this visual component. In the
beginning, He-who-is is a visual physical presence, the duplicate
of his creation. He walks in his garden at the cool of the day,
talking to his recent creation, Adam. He is present and visible at
the sacrifice of Cain and Abel, shuts the door of Noah's Ark with
his own hand, speaks with Abraham at Sichem, Bethel, and
Hebron, and scuffles all night with Jacob like a hoodlum.
But by the time of Moses, the visual component is very different. Only in a single instance does Moses speak with He-who-is
"face to face, as a man speaketh to his friend" (Exodus 33:11).
And another time, there is a group hallucination when Moses
and the seventy elders all see He-who-is at a distance standing on
sapphire pavement (Exodus 24:9-10). But in all the other instances, the hallucinated meetings are less intimate. Visually, Hewho-is is a burning bush, or a cloud, or a huge pillar of fire. And
as visually the bicameral experience recedes into the thick darkness, where thunders and lightnings and driving clouds of dense
blackness crowd in on the inaccessible heights of Sinai, we are
approaching the greatest teaching of the entire Old Testament,
that, as this last of the elohim loses his hallucinatory properties,
and is no longer an inaccessible voice in the nervous system of a
few semi-bicameral men, and becomes something written upon
tablets, he becomes law, something unchanging, approachable by
all, something relating to all men equally, king and shepherd,
universal and transcendent.
Moses himself reacts to this loss of the visual quality by hiding
his face from a supposed brilliance. At other times, his bicameral
voice itself rationalizes the loss of its visual hallucinatory components by saying to Moses, " N o man shall see me and live . . . I
will put thee in a cleft of rock, and will cover thee with my hand
while I pass by: and I will take away mine hand, and thou shalt
see my back parts, but my face shall not be seen" (Exodus 33:2023).
302
The Witness of History
The very conception of a cupboard called the ark, for some
tablets of written word as a replacement for an hallucinogenic
image of a more usual kind, like a golden calf, is illustrative of
the same point. The importance of writing in the breakdown of
the bicameral voices is tremendously important. What had to be
spoken is now silent and carved upon a stone to be taken in
visually.
After the Pentateuch, the bicameral voice retreats even further. When the writer of Deuteronomy (34:10) says that no
nabi has been like Moses "whom He-who-is knew face to face," he
is indicating the loss of the bicameral mind. The voices are heard
less frequently and less conversationally. Joshua is more spoken
to by his voice than speaking with it; and, halfway between
bicamerality and subjectivity, he has to draw lots to make decisions.
Inconsistency Between Persons
In the bicameral period, the strict hierarchy of society, the
settled geography of its limits, its ziggurats, temples, and statuary, and the common upbringing of its citizens, all co-operated in
the organization of different men's bicameral voices into a stable
hierarchy. Whose bicameral voice was the correct one was immediately decided by that hierarchy, and the recognition signals
as to which god was speaking were known by everyone and
reinforced by priests.
But with the breakdown of bicamerality, particularly when a
previously bicameral people has become nomadic as in the Exodus, the voices will begin to say different things to different
people and the problem of authority becomes a considerable difficulty. Something of the sort might be referred to in Numbers
12:1-2, where Miriam, Aaron, and Moses, who all hear the voice
of He-who-is, are not sure which is the most authentic.
But the problem is much more acute in the later books, particu-
MORAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
THE
KHABIRU
303
larly in the competition between the remaining bicameral voices.
Joash has a bicameral voice that he recognizes as the Owner to
whom he builds an altar; but his son Gideon hears a voice he
recognizes as He-who-is which tells him to tear down his father's
altar to the Owner and build another to himself (Judges 6:2526). The jealousy of the remaining elohim is the direct and
necessary result of social disorganization.
Such a dissonance of bicameral voices in this unorganized
breakdown period inaugurates the importance of signs or magical
proofs as to which voice is valid. Thus Moses is constantly compelled to produce magical proofs of his mission. Such signs, of
course, continue all through the first millennium even into present times. The miracles that today are required as criteria of
sainthood are of precisely the same order as when Moses hallucinates his rod into a serpent and back again, or his healthy hand
into a leprous one and back (Exodus 4:1-7).
Some of our present-day enjoyment of magic and prestidigitation is possibly a holdover from this desire for signs, in which in
some part of ourselves we are enjoying the thrill of recognizing
the magician as a possible bicameral authority.
And if there are no signs, what then? In the seventh century
B.C., this is particularly the problem of Jeremiah, the illiterate
wailer at the wall of Israel's iniquity. Even though he has had the
sign of the hand of He-who-is upon him ( 1 : 9; 25:17) has heard
the word of He-who-is continually like a fire in his bones, and has
been sent (23:21, 32, etc.), yet still he is unsure: whose voice is
the right one? "Wilt thou be altogether unto me as a liar?"
Jeremiah mistrustfully jabs back at his bicameral voice (15:19).
But on this point, it is sure in its answering. It breaks down what
authority Jeremiah's rational consciousness may have had, and
commands him to denounce all other voices. Chapter 28 is a
particular example, with the somewhat ridiculous competition
between Hananiah and Jeremiah as to whose bicameral voice is
the right one. And it was only the death of Hananiah two months
304
The Witness of History
later that was the sign of which to choose. Had Jeremiah died,
we would probably have had the Book of Hananiah instead of his
competitor's.
Inconsistency Within Persons
In the absence of a social hierarchy that provides stability and
recognitions, the bicameral voices not only become inconsistent
among persons, but inconsistent within the same person as well.
Particularly in the Pentateuch, the bicameral voice is often as
petty and foot-stampingly petulant as any human tyrant under
questioning. "I will be gracious to whom I will be gracious, and
will show mercy on whom I will show mercy." (Exodus 33:19).
There is no question of virtue or of justice. So He-who-is prefers
Abel to Cain, slays Er, the first-born of Judah, having taken a
dislike to him, first tells Abraham to beget a son, and then later
orders him to kill the son, even as criminal psychotics might be
directed today. Similarly, the bicameral voice of Moses possibly
has a sudden impulse to kill him (Exodus 4:24) for no reason at
all.
This same inconsistency is found in the non-Israelite prophet,
Balaam. His bicameral voice first tells him not to go with the
princes of Moab (Numbers 22:12), then reverses itself (22:20).
Then when Balaam obeys, it is furious. Then a visual-auditory
hallucination out to kill Balaam blocks his way, but then this too
reverses its commands (Numbers 22:35). Also in the selfrecriminating category is the self-punishing voice of the ashfaced nabi who tries to get passersby to punch him because his
voice commands him to (I Kings 20:35-38). And also, the "nabi
from Judah" whose bicameral voice drives him out of the city and
tries to starve him (1 Kings 13, 9-17). A l l of these inconsistent
voices are coming close to the voices heard by schizophrenics
which we noted in Chapter 4 of Book I.
*
*
*
MORAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
THE
KHABIRU
305
Divination by Gods
The deciding things by casting gorals or lots, probably throwing dice, bones, or beans, runs through much of the Old Testament. As we saw in II.4 of this essay, it is the making of an
analog god. The goral by metaphor becomes the word of god
deciding lands and tribes, what to do or whom to destroy, taking
the place of the older bicameral authority. As mentioned earlier,
it is a help in appreciating how authoritative such practices could
be when we realize that there was no concept of chance until well
into the subjective eras.
But of much greater interest is the occurrence of the spontaneous divination from immediate sensory experience that in the end
becomes the subjective conscious mind. Its interest here is because it begins not in the man-side of the bicameral mind but in
the bicameral voices themselves.
It is, then, another way that the bicameral voices show their
uncertainty when they too, like men, turn to divination, and need
to be primed or instigated. In the ninth century B.C., the voice of
one of the nabiim before Ahab divines by metaphor from a pair of
horns how an army may be defeated (I Kings 22:11). The
bicameral voice of Jeremiah several times takes what he, Jeremiah, is looking at and divines from it what to say. When he sees
a boiling wind-blown pot facing north, He-who-is metaphorizes it
into an evil invasion blowing down from the north, consuming all
before it like a fire driven by the wind (Jeremiah 1:13-15).
When he sees two baskets of figs, one good and one bad, his right
hemisphere has He-who-is speaking about picking good and bad
people (Jeremiah 24:1-10). And when Amos sees a builder
judging the straightness of a wall by holding a plumb line to it,
his mind hallucinates the builder into He-who-is, who then metaphorizes the act into judging people by their righteousness
(Amos 7:8).
Particularly when spontaneous divinations are being made by
306
The Witness of History
gods (who after all cannot perform other types of divination),
puns may 'seed' the analogy. Thus, when Amos stands looking at
a basket of summer fruit, his bicameral voice puns over on the
Hebrew qayits (summer fruit) to gets (end) and starts talking
about the end of Israel (Amos 8:1-2). Or when Jeremiah sees
an almond branch (shaqed), his bicameral voice says it will
watch over him (shaqad) because the Hebrew words for the two
are similar (Jeremiah 1:11-12).
The Book of I Samuel
The Book of I Samuel is an instructive register of all this, and a
reading of it gives one the feeling of what it was like in this partly
bicameral, partly subjective world as the first millennium B.C.
moved into consciousness. Represented across its intriguing
chapters is almost the entire spectrum of transition mentalities in
what is perhaps the first written tragedy in literature. Bicamerality in a rather decadent form is represented in the wild gangs of
nabiim, the winnowed-out bicameral chaff of the Khabiru that we
spoke of earlier in this chapter, roaming outside the cities in the
hills, speaking the voices they hear within themselves but believe
to come from outside them, answering the voices, using music and
drums to increase their excitement.
Partly bicameral is the boy Samuel, prodded from sleep by a
voice he is taught is the voice of He-who-is, encouraged at the
critical age and trained into the bicameral mode by the old priest
Eli, and then acknowledged from Dan to Beersheba as the
medium of He-who-is. Though even Samuel must at times stoop
to divining, as he does from his own torn garment (15:27-29).
Next in bicamerality is David, whom Samuel chooses from all
the sons of Jesse in a bicameral manner, and who is only so
bicameral as to obtain short sharp "Go up"s from He-who-is. His
subjective consciousness is demonstrated in his ability to deceive
Achish (I Samuel 21:13). And then Jonathan, subjectively able
MORAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
THE
KHABIRU
307
to deceive his father, but having to rely on cledonomancy, or
divining by first words spoken by someone, for military decisions
(14:8-13). That idols were common in the period is shown by
the casual reference to what must have been a life-sized "image"
that, with the help of some goat hair, is made to resemble David in
bed (19:13). The casual presence of such an idol in David's house
may point to some common hallucinogenic practice of the time
that has been suppressed from the text.
And finally, the subjective Saul, the gaunt bewildered country
boy whisked into politics at the irrational behest of Samuel's
bicameral voice, trying to be bicameral himself by joining a band
of the wild nabiim until he, too, to the throbbing of drums and
strumming zithers, feels he hears the divine voices (10:5). But
so unconvincing are these to his consciousness that, even with the
three confirmed signs, he tries to hide from his destiny. Subjective Saul seeks wildly about him for what to do. A new situation,
as when the irresponsible Samuel does not keep an appointment,
with the Israelites hoveled up in caves, the Philistines knotting
together against him, and he tries to force a voice with burnt
offerings (13:12), only to be called foolish by the tardy Samuel.
And Saul building an altar to He-who-is, whom he has never
heard, to ask it questions in vain (14:37). W h y doesn't the god
speak to him? Saul, divining by lot the supposed culprit that
must be the cause of the divine silence, and, obedient to his
divination, even though it is his own son, condemning him to
death. But even that must be wrong, because his people rebel
and refuse to carry out the execution — a behavior impossible in
bicameral times. And Saul, too consciously kind to his enemies
for Samuel's archaic hallucination. And when Saul's jealousy of
David and of his son's love for David reaches its extremity, suddenly losing his conscious mind, becoming bicameral, stripping
off his clothes, naba-ing with the bicameral men of the hills
(19:23-24). But then when such nabiim cannot tell him what to
do, driving them along with other bicameral wizards out of the
308
The Witness of History
city (28:3) , seeking some divine certainty in dreams or in gazing
into crystal (if we may translate urim as such) (28:6). And
despairing Saul, at the end of his consciousness, disguising himself, something only a subjective man could do, and consulting at
night that last resort, the Witch of Endor, or rather the bicameral
voice that takes possession of her, as confounded conscious Saul
grovels before it, crying that he knows not what to do, and then
hears from the weird woman's lips what he takes to be the dead
Samuel's words, that he will die and Israel will fall (28:19).
And then, when the Philistines have all but captured the remnant of Israel's army, his sons and hopes all slain, the committing
of that most terrible subjective act, the first in history — suicide,
to be followed immediately by the second, that of his armor
bearer.
The date of the story is the eleventh century B.C.; of the
writing of it, the sixth century B.C.; of the psychology of it, therefore, perhaps the eighth century B.C.
The Idols of the Khabiru
As holdovers from the bicameral period are the hallucinogenic
statuary that are mentioned throughout the Old Testament. As
might be expected in this late stage of civilization, there are many
kinds. While there are some general terms for idols, such as the
elily which is Isaiah's word for them, or matstsebah for anything
set up on a pillar or altar, it is the more specific words which are
of greater interest.
The most important type of idol was the tselem, a cast or
molten statue usually fashioned with a graving tool, often of gold
or silver, made by a founder from melted money (Judges 17:4)
or melted jewelry (Exodus 32:4), and sometimes expensively
dressed (Ezekiel 16:17). Isaiah scoffingly describes their construction in Judah around 700 B.C. (44:12). They could be
images either of animals or of men. Sometimes the tselem may
MORAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
THE
KHABIRU
309
have been just a head placed high on a pedestal or high altar (II
Chronicles 14:3) or even the huge golden tselem which Nebuchadnezzar placed upon a pillar 90 feet high (Daniel 3:1). More
often, they seemed to have been placed in an asherah, probably
one of the wooden shrines hung with rich fabric that the King
James scholars translated as "groves."
Next in importance seems to be the carved statue or pesel, of
which very little is known. It was probably chiseled out of wood
and was the same as the atsab, which is what the Philistines, who
destroyed Saul's army, worshiped. After Saul's death and the
defeat of Israel, the Philistines run to tell their atsabim first of their
victory and then their people (I Samuel 31:95 I Chronicles
10:9). That they were painted gold or silver is indicated by
several references in the Psalms, and that they were of wood by
the fact that David in wreaking his revenge on the Philistines
makes a bonfire out of them (II Samuel 5:21). There were also
some kind of sun idols of unknown shape called chammanim,
which seem also to have been set up on pedestals, since they are
ordered cut down by Leviticus (26:30), Isaiah (27:9), and Ezekiel (6:6).
If not the most important, perhaps the most common hallucinogenic idol was the terap. We are told directly that a terap
could seem to speak, since the king of Babylon at one point
consults with several of them (Ezekiel 21:21). Sometimes they
were probably small figurines, since Rachel can steal a group of
prized terafhim (to use the Hebrew plural) from her furious
father and hide them (Genesis 31:19). They also could be lifesized, since it is a terap that is substituted for the sleeping David
(I Samuel 19:13). As we have already seen, the very casualness of this last reference seems to indicate that such teraphim
were common enough around the houses of leaders. But in the
hills, such idols must have been rare and highly prized. In
Judges we are told of Micah, who builds a house of elohim
containing a tselem, a pesel, a terap, and an ephod, the latter
310
The Witness of History
being usually an ornate ritual robe which, perhaps put over a
frame, could be made into an idol. And these he calls his elohim,
which are then stolen by the children of Dan (Judges: 17 and
18 passim). We would probably have more archaeological evidence of these hallucinogenic idols of the Hebrews today had not
King Josiah had them all destroyed in 641 B.C. (II Chronicles 34:
3-7.
A further vestige from the bicameral era is the word ob, often
translated as a "familiar spirit." "A man also or woman that
have an ob . . . shall surely be put to death," says Leviticus
(20:27). And similarly Saul drives out from Israel all those that
had an ob (I Samuel 28:3). Even though an ob is something
that one consults with (Deuteronomy, 18:11), it probably had no
physical embodiment. It is always bracketed with wizards or
witches, and thus probably refers to some bicameral voice that
was not recognized by the Old Testament writers as religious.
This word has so puzzled translators that when they found it in
Job 32:19, they translated it absurdly as "bottle," when clearly
the context is that of the young frustrated Elihu, who feels as if
he had a bicameral voice about to burst forth into impatient
speech like an overfull wineskin.
The Last of the Nabiim
We began this chapter with a consideration of the refugee
situation in the Near East around the latter part of the second
millennium B.C., and of the roving tribes uprooted from their
lands by various catastrophes, some of them certainly bicameral
and unable to move toward subjective consciousness. Probably
in the editing of the historical books of the Old Testament, and
the fitting of it together into one story in the sixth or fifth century
B.C., a great deal has been suppressed. And among such items of
information that we would like is a clear account of what happened to these last communities of bicameral men. Here and
MORAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
THE
KHABIRU
311
there through the Old Testament, they appear like sudden
glimpses of a strange other world during these periods which
historians have paid too little attention to.
Groups of bicameral men certainly persisted until the downfall
of the Judean monarchy, but whether in association with other
tribes or with any organization to their hallucinated voices in the
form of gods, we don't know. They are often referred to as the
"sons of nabiim," indicating that there was probably a strong
genetic basis for this type of remaining bicamerality. It is, I
think, the same genetic basis that remains with us as part of the
etiology of schizophrenia.
Edgy kings consulted them. Ahab, king of Israel in 835 B.C.,
rounded up 400 of them like cattle to listen to their hue and
clamor (I Kings 22:6). Later, in all his robes, he and the king of
Judah sit on thrones just outside the gates of Samaria, and have
hundreds of these poor bicameral men herded up to them, raving
and copying each other even as schizophrenics in a back ward (I
Kings 22:10).
What happened to them? From time to time, they were
hunted down and exterminated like unwanted animals. Such a
massacre in the ninth century B.C. seems to be referred to in
I Kings 18:4, where out of some unknown, much larger number,
Obadiah took a hundred nabiim and hid them in caves, and
brought them bread and water until the massacre was over.
Another such massacre is organized by Elijah a few years later
(I Kings 18:40).
We hear no more of these bicameral groups thereafter. What
remained for a few centuries more are the individual nabiim,
men whose voices do not need the group support of other hallucinating men, men who can be partly subjective and yet still hear
the bicameral voice. These are the famous nabiim whose bicameral messages we have already selectively touched upon: Amos,
the gatherer of sycamore fruit, Jeremiah, staggering under his
yoke from village to village, Ezekiel with his visions of lofty
312
The Witness of History
thrones on wheels moving through the clouds, the several nabiim
whose religious agonies are ascribed to Isaiah. These of course
merely represent the handful of that much larger number whose
bicameral voices seemed to be most consistent with Deuteronomy. And then the voices are as a rule no longer actually heard.
In their place is the considered subjective thought of moral
teachers. Men still dreamed visions and heard dark speech perhaps. But Ecclesiastes and Ezra seek wisdom, not a god. They
study the law. They do not roam out into the wilderness "inquiring of Yahweh." By 400 B.C., bicameral prophecy is dead. "The
nabiim shall be ashamed everyone of his visions." If parents
catch their children naba-ing or in dialogue with bicameral
voices, they are to kill them on the spot (Zechariah 13, 3-4). 8
That is a severe injunction. If it was carried out, it is an evolutionary selection which helped move the gene pool of humanity
toward subjectivity.
Scholars have long debated the reason for the decline and fall
of prophecy in the post-exilic period of Judaism. They have
suggested that the nabiim had done their work, and there was no
more need of them. Or they have said that there was a danger
that it would sink into a cult. Others that it was the corruption of
the Israelites by the Babylonians, who were by this time as omenridden from the cradle to the grave as any nation could be. A l l of
these are partly true, but the plainer fact to me is that the decline
of prophecy is part of that much larger phenomenon going on
elsewhere in the world, the loss of the bicameral mind.
Once one has read through the Old Testament from this point
of view, the entire succession of works becomes majestically and
wonderfully the birth pangs of our subjective consciousness. No
other literature has recorded this absolutely important event at
8 The date of Zechariah is around 520 b.C., but scholars are agreed that the final
chapters of the book ascribed to him are later additions from some other source. The
date of this injunction is probably the fourth or third century B.C.
MORAL
CONSCIOUSNESS
OF
THE
KHABIRU
313
such length or with such fullness. Chinese literature jumps into
subjectivity in the teaching of Confucius with little before it.
Indian hurtles from the bicameral Veda into the ultra subjective
Upanishads, neither of which are as authentic to their times.
Greek literature, like a series of steppingstones from the Iliad to
the Odyssey and across the broken fragments of Sappho and
Solon toward Plato, is the next best record, but is still too incomplete. And Egypt is relatively silent. While the Old Testament,
even as it is hedged with great historical problems of accuracy,
still remains the richest source for our knowledge of what the
transition period was like. It is essentially the story of the loss of
the bicameral mind, the slow retreat into silence of the remaining
elohim, the confusion and tragic violence which ensue, and the
search for them again in vain among its prophets until a substitute is found in right action.
But the mind is still haunted with its old unconscious waysj it
broods on lost authorities; and the yearning, the deep and hollowing yearning for divine volition and service is with us still.
As the stag pants after the waterbrooks,
So pants my mind a f t e r y o u , O g o d s !
M y mind thirsts for g o d s !
for living g o d s !
W h e n shall I come face to face with gods?
— P s a l m 42
BOOK T H R E E
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind
in the Modern World
CHAPTER 1
The Quest for Authorization
W
E ARE NOW at last in a position where we can look back and
see the history of mankind on this planet in its proper values
for the first time and understand some of the chief features of the
last three millennia as vestiges of a previous mentality. Our view
of human history here must be that of a furthest grandeur. We
must try to see man against his entire evolutionary background,
where his civilizations, including our own, are but as mountain
peaks in a particular range against the sky, and from which we
must force ourselves into an intellectual distance so that we see
its contours aright. And from this prospect, a millennium is an
exceedingly short period of time for so fundamental a change as
from bicamerality to consciousness.
We, at the end of the second millennium A.D., are still in a
sense deep in this transition to a new mentality. And all about us
lie the remnants of our recent bicameral past. We have our
houses of gods which record our births, define us, marry us, and
bury us, receive our confessions and intercede with the gods to
forgive us our trespasses. Our laws are based upon values which
without their divine pendancy would be empty and unenforceable. Our national mottoes and hymns of state are usually divine
invocations. Our kings, presidents, judges, and officers begin
their tenures with oaths to the now silent deities taken upon the
writings of those who have last heard them.
The most obvious and important carry-over from the previous
318
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
mentality is thus our religious heritage in all its labyrinthine
beauty and variety of forms. The overwhelming importance of
religion both in general world history and in the history of the
average world individual is of course very clear from any objective standpoint, even though a scientific view of man often
seems embarrassed at acknowledging this most obvious fact. For
in spite of all that rationalist materialist science has implied since
the Scientific Revolution, mankind as a whole has not, does not,
and perhaps cannot relinquish his fascination with some human
type of relationship to a greater and wholly other, some mysterium tremendum with powers and intelligences beyond all left
hemispheric categories, something necessarily indefinite and unclear, to be approached and felt in awe and wonder and almost
speechless worship, rather than in clear conception, something
that for modern religious people communicates in truths of feeling, rather than in what can be verbalized by the left hemisphere,
and so what in our time can be more truly felt when least named,
a patterning of self and numinous other from which, in times of
our darkest distress, none of us can escape — even as the infinitely
milder distress of decision-making brought out that relationship
three millennia ago.
There are many things that could be said at this point — many.
A full discussion here would specify how the attempted reformation of Judaism by Jesus can be construed as a necessarily new
religion for conscious men rather than bicameral men. Behavior
now must be changed from within the new consciousness rather
than from Mosaic laws carving behavior from without. Sin and
penance are now within conscious desire and conscious contrition,
rather than in the external behaviors of the decalogue and the
penances of temple sacrifice and community punishment. The
divine kingdom to be regained is psychological not physical. It is
metaphorical not literal. It is 'within' not in extenso.
But even the history of Christianity does not and cannot remain true to its originator. The development of the Christian
Church returns again and again to this same longing for bicam-
THE
QUEST
FOR
AUTHORIZATION
319
eral absolutes, away from the difficult inner kingdoms of agape to
an external hierarchy reaching through a cloud of miracle and
infallibility to an archaic authorization in an extended heaven. In
previous chapters I have often paused to point out various parallels between ancient bicameral practices and modern religious
ones, and I shall not labor such comparisons here.
Also beyond the purview of the present book is a full exploration of the way that the more secular developments of the last
three millennia are related to their emergence from a different
mentality. I am thinking here of the history of logic and conscious reasoning from the Greek development of Logos to modern
computers, and of the spectacular historical pageant of philosophy, with its efforts to find a metaphor of all existence in which
we may find some conscious familiarity and so feel at home in
the universe. I am thinking too of our struggles toward systems
of ethics, of attempting with rational consciousness to find substitutes for our previous divine volition which could carry with them
that obligation which at least could simulate our earlier obedience
to hallucinated voices. And too of the cyclic history of politics,
the gyres of our wavering attempts to make governments out of
men instead of gods, secular systems of laws to perform that
formerly divine function of binding us together into an order, a
stability, and a commonweal.
These larger questions are the important ones. But here, in
this chapter, I wish to introduce the issues of Book III by considering a handful of more ancient topics of lesser importance
that are precise and clear carry-overs from the earlier mentality.
My reason for doing so here is that these historical phenomena
shed a needed and clarifying light back into some of the darker
problems of Books I and II.
One distinguishing characteristic of such vestiges is that they
are more obvious against the complexity of history the closer we
are to the breakdown of the bicameral mind. The reason for this
320
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
is quite clear. While the universal characteristics of the new
consciousness, such as self-reference, mind-space, and narratization, can develop swiftly on the heels of new language construction, the larger contours of civilization, the huge landscape of
culture against which this happens, can only change with geological slowness. The matter and technic of earlier ages of civilizations survive into the new eras uneroded, dragging with them
the older outworn forms in which the new mentality must live.
But living also in these forms is a fervent search for what I
shall call archaic authorization. After the collapse of the bicameral mind, the world is still in a sense governed by gods, by
statements and laws and prescriptions carved on stelae or written
on papyrus or remembered by old men, and dating back to bicameral times. But the dissonance is there. Why are the gods no
longer heard and seen? The Psalms cry out for answers. And
more assurances are needed than the relics of history or the paid
insistences of priests. Something palpable, something direct,
something immediate! Some sensible assurance that we are not
alone, that the gods are just silent, not dead, that behind all this
hesitant subjective groping about for signs of certainty, there is a
certainty to be had.
Thus, as the slow withdrawing tide of divine voices and presences strands more and more of each population on the sands of
subjective uncertainties, the variety of technique by which man
attempts to make contact with his lost ocean of authority
becomes extended. Prophets, poets, oracles, diviners, statue
cults, mediums, astrologers, inspired saints, demon possession,
tarot cards, Ouija boards, popes, and peyote all are the residue of
bicamerality that was progressively narrowed down as uncertainties piled upon uncertainties. In this chapter and the next we
shall examine some of these more archaic vestiges of the bicameral mind.
THE
QUEST
FOR
AUTHORIZATION
321
ORACLES
The most immediate carry-over of bicamerality is simply its perpetuation in certain persons, particularly itinerant prophets,
which I have discussed in 11.6, or those institutionalized as
oracles, which I shall describe here. While there is a series of
cuneiform tablets describing Assyrian oracles1 dating from the
seventh century B.C., and the even earlier oracle of Amon of
Thebes in Egypt, it is really in Greece that we know this institution best. Greek oracles were the central method of making
important decisions for over a thousand years after the breakdown of the bicameral mind. This fact is usually obscured by the
strident rationalism of modern historians. Oracles were subjectivity's umbilical cord reaching back into the sustaining unsubjective past.
The Oracle at Delphi
Coincidental with my metaphor is the fact that at the most
famous oracle, that of Apollo at Delphi, there was a queer conelike stone structure called the omphalos or navel. It stood at the
reputed center of the earth. Here presided on certain days, or in
some centuries every day throughout the year, a supreme priestess, or sometimes two or three in rotation, selected so far as we
know on no particular basis (in Plutarch's day, in the first century B.C., she was the daughter of a poor farmer). 2 She first
bathed and drank from a sacred brook, and then established
contact with the god through his sacred tree, the laurel, much as
conscious Assyrian kings are depicted being smeared by treecones in the hands of genii. She did this either by holding a
1 Alfred Guillaume, Prophecy and Divination among the Hebrews and Other
Semites (New York, Harper, 1938), p. 42ff.
2 Plutarch, Pyth. rac. 22, 405C.
322
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
laurel branch, or by inhaling and fumigating herself with burnt
laurel leaves (as Plutarch said), or perhaps by chewing the
leaves (as Lucian insisted).
The replies to questions were given at once, without any reflection, and uninterruptedly. The exact manner of her announcements is still debated,3 whether she was seated on a tripod,
regarded as Apollo's ritual seat, or simply stood at an entrance to
a cave. But the archaic references to her, from the fifth century
on, all agree with the statement of Heraclitus that she spoke
"from her frenzied mouth and with various contortions of her
body." She was entheos, plena deo. Speaking through his priestess, but always in the first person, answering king or freeman,
'Apollo' commanded sites for new colonies (as he did for presentday Istanbul), decreed which nations were friends, which rulers
best, which laws to enact, the causes of plagues or famines, the
best trade routes, which of the proliferation of new cults, or
music, or art should be recognized as agreeable to Apollo — all
decided by these girls with their frenzied mouths.
Truly, this is astonishing! We have known of the Delphic
Oracle so long from school texts that we coat it over with a
shrugging usualness when we should not. How is it conceivable
that simple rural girls could be trained to put themselves into a
psychological state such that they could make decisions at once
that ruled the world?
The obdurate rationalist simply scoffs plena deo indeed! Just
as the mediums of our own times have always been exposed as
frauds, so these so-called oracles were really performances
manipulated by others in front of an illiterate peasantry for
political or monetary ends.
But such a realpolitik attitude is doctrinaire at best. Possibly
there was some chicanery in the oracle's last days, perhaps some
bribery of the prophetes, those subsidiary priests or priestesses
3 See E. R. Dodds, The Greeks and, the Irrational (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1968), which I have used as a handbook in these matters.
THE
QUEST
FOR
AUTHORIZATION
323
who interpreted what the oracle meant. But earlier, to sustain so
massive a fraud for an entire millennium through the most brilliant intellectual civilization the world had yet known is impossible, just impossible. Nor can it gibe with the complete absence
of criticism of the oracle until the Roman period. Nor with the
politically wise and often cynical Plato reverently calling Delphi
"the interpreter of religion to all mankind."4
Another kind of explanation, really a quasi-explanation, still
busied about with in the popular and sometimes professional
literature, is biochemical. The trances were real, it says, but
caused by vapors of some sort rising from a casium beneath the
floor of the cave. But the French excavations of 1903 and more
recent ones have shown distinctly that no such casium existed.5
Or else there might be a drug in the laurel that could have
produced such an Apollonian effect. To test this, I have crushed
laurel leaves and smoked quantities of them in a pipe and felt
somewhat sick but no more inspired than usual. And chewed
them as well for over an hour, and very distinctly felt more and
more Jaynesian, alas, than Apollonian.6 The glee with which
external explanations are sought out for such phenomena simply
indicates the resistance in some quarters to admitting that psychological phenomena of this type exist at all.
Rather, I suggest a quite different explanation. And for that
purpose, I shall introduce here the notion of
The General Bicameral Paradigm
By this phrase, I mean an hypothesized structure behind a
4 Plato,
Republic, 4, 427B. We should also remember that Socrates derived some
of what I am about to call his 'archaic authorization* from the oracle. See Apology,
20E.
5 A. P. Oppe, "The Chasm at Delphi," Journal of Historical Studies, 1904, 24:
214f.
6 I am grateful to EveLynn McGuinness for much in my life and here for acting
as an observer, although her role was somewhat compromised both by her participation and a certain minimal reverence. Our negative result agrees with T. K.
Oesterreich. See his Possession, Demoniacal and Other, English translation, 1930,
p. 319, note 3.
324
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
large class of phenomena of diminished consciousness which I
am interpreting as partial holdovers from our earlier mentality.
The paradigm has four aspects:
the collective cognitive imperative, or belief system, a culturally agreed-on expectancy or prescription which defines the
particular form of a phenomenon and the roles to be acted out
within that form;
an induction or formally ritualized procedure whose function
is the narrowing of consciousness by focusing attention on a
small range of preoccupations;
the trance itself, a response to both the preceding, characterized by a lessening of consciousness or its loss, the diminishing
of the analog
or its loss, resulting in a role that is accepted,
tolerated, or encouraged by the group; and
the archaic authorization to which the trance is directed or related to, usually a god, but sometimes a person who is accepted
by the individual and his culture as an authority over the individual, and who by the collective cognitive imperative is prescribed to be responsible for controlling the trance state.
Now, I do not mean these four aspects of the general bicameral paradigm to be considered as a temporal succession necessarily, although the induction and trance usually do follow each
other. But the cognitive imperative and the archaic authorization
pervade the whole thing. Moreover, there is a kind of balance or
summation among these elements, such that when one of them is
weak the others must be strong for the phenomena to occur.
Thus, as through time, particularly in the millennium following
the beginning of consciousness, the collective cognitive imperative becomes weaker (that is, the general population tends
toward skepticism about the archaic authorization), we find a
rising emphasis on and complication of the induction procedures,
as well as the trance state itself becoming more profound.
By calling the general bicameral paradigm a structure, I not
THE
QUEST
FOR
AUTHORIZATION
325
only mean a logical structure into which these phenomena can be
analyzed, but also some presently unspecified neurological structure or relationships between areas of the brain, perhaps something like the model for the bicameral mind presented in 1.5. We
might thus expect that all of the phenomena mentioned in Book
III in some way involve right hemispheric function in a way that
is different from ordinary conscious life. It is even possible that
in some of these phenomena we have a partial periodic right
hemisphere dominance that can be considered as the neurological residue of nine millennia of selection for the bicameral mind.
The application of this general bicameral paradigm to the
oracle at Delphi is obvious: the elaborate induction procedures,
the trance in which consciousness is lost, the ardently pursued
authorization of Apollo. But it is the collective cognitive" imperative or group belief or cultural prescription or expectancy (all of
these terms indicating my meaning) which I wish to emphasize.
The immensity of the cultural demand upon the entranced priestess cannot be overemphasized. The whole Greek world believed,
and had for almost a millennium. As many as thirty-five thousand people a day from every part of the Mediterranean world
might struggle by sea through the tiny port of Itea that snuggles
the receptive coast just below Delphi. And they, too, went through
induction procedures, purifying themselves in the Castalian
spring, making offerings to Apollo and other gods as they persisted
up the Sacred Way. In the latter centuries of the oracle, more
than four thousand votive statues crowded this 220-yard-long
climb up the side of Mount Parnassus to the temple of the oracle.
It was, I suggest, this confluence of huge social prescription and
expectancy, closer to definition than mere belief, which can account for the psychology of the oracle, for the at-once-ness of her
answers. It was something before which any skepticism would be
as impossible as for us to doubt that the speech of a radio originates in a studio that we cannot see. And it is something before
which modern psychology must stand in awe.
326
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
To this causative expectancy should be added something about
the natural scene itself. Oracles begin in localities with a specific
awesomeness, natural formations of mountain or gorge, of hallucinogenic wind or waves, of symbolic gleamings and vistas,
which I suggest are more conducive to occasioning right hemisphere activity than the analytic planes of everyday life. Perhaps
we can say that the geography of the bicameral mind in the first
part of the first millennium B.C. was shrinking down into sites of
awe and beauty where the voices of gods could still be heard.
Certainly the vast cliffs of Delphi move into such a suggestion
and fill it fully: a towering caldron of blasted rock over which
the sea winds howl and the salt mists cling, as if dreaming nature
were twisting herself awake at awkward angles, falling away into
a blue surf of shimmering olive leaves and the gray immortal
sea.
(It is, however, difficult for us to appreciate such scenic awe
today, so clouded is the purity of our response to landscape with
our conscious 'inner' worlds and our experience with swift geographical change. Moreover, Delphi today is not quite as it was.
Its five acres of broken columns, cheerful graffiti, camera-clicking tourists, and stumps of white marble over which heedless
ants crawl indecisively, are not exactly the stuff of divine inspiration.)
Other Oracles
Particularly recommending such a cultural explanation of
Delphi is the fact that there were similar if less important oracles
throughout the civilized world at the time. Apollo had others: at
Ptoa in Boeotia and at Branchidae and Patara in Asia Minor. At
the latter, the Prophetess, as part of the induction, was locked
into the temple at night for connubial union with her hallucinated god that she might better be his medium.7 The great
7 Herodotus,
1 :I82.
THE
QUEST
FOR
AUTHORIZATION
327
oracle at Claros had priests as mediums whose frenzies were
visited by Tacitus in the first century A.D.8 Pan had an oracle at
Acacesium, but it became defunct early.9 The golden oracle at
Ephesus, famous for its enormous wealth, had tranced eunuchs
as the mouthpieces of the goddess Artemis.10 (The style of their
vestments, incidentally, is still used today by the Greek Orthodox
Church.) And the abnormal dancing on the tips of the toes of
modern ballerinas is thought to derive from the dances before the
altar of the goddess.11 Anything opposite to the everyday can
serve as a cue for the engagement of the general bicameral
paradigm.
The voice of Zeus at Dodona must have been one of the oldest
oracles, since Odysseus visited it to hear whether to return to
Ithaca openly or by stealth.12 It was at that time probably just a
huge sacred oak tree and the Olympian voice was hallucinated
from the wind trembling in its leaves, making one wonder if
something similar took place among the Druids who held the oak
holy. It is only in the fifth century B.C. that Zeus is no longer
heard directly, and Dodona has a temple and a priestess who
speaks for him in unconscious trances,13 again conforming to
the temporal sequence the bicameral theory would predict.
Not only the voices of gods, but also of dead kings, could still
be heard bicamerally, as we have earlier suggested was the origin
of gods themselves. Amphiaraus had been the heroic prince of
Argos who had plunged to his death in a chasm in Boeotia,
supposedly at the nudge of an angry Zeus. His voice was 'heard'
from the chasm for centuries after, answering the problems of
8 Tacitus, Annates, 2 15 4.
9 Pausanias, Description of Greece, J. E. Fraser, trans.
(London: Macmillan, 1898),
37:8.
Charles Picard, Ephese et Claros (Paris: de Bocard, 1922).
Louis Sechan, La Dance Greque Antique (Paris: de Bocard, 1930)} and also
Lincoln Kirstein, The Book of the Dance (Garden City: Garden City Publishing Co.,
1942).
12 Odyssey, 14:327 ;19:296.
13 Aelius Aristides, Orationes, 45 : n .
10
11
328
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
his petitioners. But again as centuries passed, the Voice' came to
be hallucinated only by certain entranced priestesses who lived
there. At that later time they did not so much answer questions
as interpret the dreams of those who consulted the voice.14
In some ways the most interesting, however, from the hypothesis of the bicameral mind is the hallucinated voice of Trophonius at Lebadea, twenty miles east of Delphi. For it is the longest
lasting of the direct Voices' without intermediary priests or priestesses. The locale of the oracle even today bears some remnants
of its ancient awesomeness, a meeting of three soaring precipices, of murmuring springs easing strongly out of the solemn
ground and crawling submissively away into stony ravines. And
up a little, where one ravine begins to wind into the heart of the
mountain, there was once a carved-out cell-like pit in the rock
that squeezed down into an ovenlike shrine over an underground
flume.
When the collective imperative of the general bicameral paradigm is less, when belief and trust in such phenomena are
waning with rationalism, and particularly when it is being applied not to a trained priestess but to any suppliant, the induction
is longer and more intricate to compensate. And this is what
occurred at Lebadea. Pausanias, the Roman traveler, described
the elaborate induction procedure that he found there in A.D.
150.15 After days of waiting and purification and omens and
expectancy, he tells us how he was abruptly taken one night and
bathed and anointed by two holy boys, then drank from Lethe's
spring to forget who he was (the loss of the analog ' I ' ) , then
made to sip at the spring of Mnemosyne so as to remember later
what was to be revealed (like a post-hypnotic suggestion). Then
he was made to worship a secret image, then was dressed in holy
linen, girded with sacred ribbons, and shod with special boots,
and then only after more omens, if favorable, was finally inserted
14
15
Pausanias, Description of Greece, 1, 34:5.
Ibid., 9, 39:11.
THE
QUEST
FOR
AUTHORIZATION
334
down an impassive ladder into the devout pit with its dark torrent
where the divine message grew swiftly articulate.
The Six Oracular Terms
As the Greek mind moves from the universally bicameral to
the universally conscious, these oracular vestiges of the bicameral world and their authority change until they become more
and more precarious and difficult to obtain. There is, I suggest, a
loose pattern in all this, and that over the thousand years of their
existence, oracles were in a continuing decadence which can be
understood as six terms. These can be regarded as six steps
down from the bicameral mind as its collective cognitive imperative grew weaker and weaker.
1. T h e locality oracle.
Oracles began simply as specific lo-
cations where, because of some awesomeness of the surroundings, or some important incident or some hallucinogenic sound,
waves, waters, or wind, suppliants, any suppliants, could still
'hear' a bicameral voice directly.
Lebadea remained at this
term, probably because of its remarkable induction.
2. T h e prophet oracle. Usually there then occurred a term
where only certain persons, priests, or priestesses, could 'hear'
the voice of the god at the locality.
3. T h e trained prophet oracle, when such persons, priests,
or priestesses, could 'hear' only after long training and elaborate inductions. Up to this term, the person was still himself
and relayed the god's voice to others.
4. T h e possessed oracle. Then, from at least the fifth century B.C., came the term of possession, of the frenzied mouth
and contorted body after even more training and more elaborate
inductions.
330
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
5. T h e interpreted possessed oracle.
As the cognitive impera-
tive weakened, the words became garbled and had to be interpreted by auxiliary priests or priestesses who themselves had
gone through induction procedures.
6. T h e erratic oracle.
A n d then even this became difficult.
T h e voices became fitful, the possessed prophet erratic, the
interpretations impossible, and the oracle ended.
The oracle of Delphi endured longest. It is striking evidence
for its supreme importance to the god-nostalgic subjectivity of
Greece in its golden age that it lasted so long, particularly when it
is recalled that in almost every invasion it sided with the invader: with Xerxes I in the early fifth century B.C., with Philip II
in the fourth century B.C., and even in the Peloponnesian Wars, it
spoke on the side of Sparta. Such the strength of bicameral
phenomena in the forces of history. It even lived out its sad,
hilarious, patriotic mocking by Euripides in the amphitheaters.
But by the first century A.D., Delphi had come to its sixth term.
Bicamerality having receded further and further into the unremembered past, skepticism had overgrown belief. The mighty
cultural cognitive imperative of the oracular was played out and
shattered, and the thing with increasing frequency would not
work. One such instance at Delphi is told by Plutarch in A.D. 60.
The prophetess reluctantly attempted a trance, the omens being
dreadful. She began to speak in a hoarse voice as if distressed,
then appeared filled with a "dumb and evil spirit," and then ran
screaming toward the entrance and fell down. Everyone else,
including her prophetes, fled in terror. The report goes on that
they found her partly recovered when they returned, but that she
died within a few days.16 As this was probably observed by a
prophetes who was a personal friend of Plutarch's, we have no
reason to doubt its authenticity.17
16
17
Plutarch, Def. Orac., 51, 438C.
Dodds, Greeks and the Irrational, p. 72.
THE
QUEST
FOR
AUTHORIZATION
331
Yet even with these neurotic failures, Delphi was still consulted by the tradition-hungry Greece-haunted Romans. The last
to do so was my namesake, the Emperor Julian who, following
his namesake Julianus (who had written down from hallucinated
gods his Chaldaean Oracles), was attempting to revive the ancient
gods. As part of this personal quest for authorization, he tried to
rehabilitate Delphi in A.D. 363, three years after it had been
ransacked by Constantine. Through his remaining priestess,
Apollo prophesied that he would never prophesy again. And the
prophecy came true. The bicameral mind had come to one of its
many ends.
Sibyls
The Age of Oracles occupies the entire millennium after the
breakdown of the bicameral mind. And as it slowly dies away,
there appear here and there what might be called amateur oracles, untrained and uninstitutionalized persons who spontaneously felt themselves possessed by gods. Of course some simply
spoke schizophrenic nonsense. Probably most. But others had
an authenticity that could command belief. Among such were
those few but unknown number of weird and wonderful women
known as the Sibyls (from the Aeolic sios = god + boule =
advice). In the first century B.C., Varro could count at least ten
at one time around the Mediterranean world. But there were
certainly others in more remote regions. They lived in solitude,
sometimes in reverenced mountain shrines that were built for
them, or in tufaceous subterranean caverns near the groan of the
ocean, as did the great Cumaean Sibyl. Virgil had probably personally visited the latter around 40 B.C., when he described her
frenzied laboring with a possessing Apollo in Book VI of the
Aeneid.
Like oracles, the Sibyls were asked to make decisions on matters high and low up to the third century A.D. So gristled with
332
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
moral fervor were their replies that even the early Christian
Fathers and Hellenistic Jews bowed to them as prophets on a
level with those of the Old Testament. The early Christian
Church, in particular, used their prophecies (often forged) to
buttress its own divine authenticity. Even a thousand years later,
at the Vatican, four of the Sibyls were painted into prominent
niches on the ceiling of the Sistine Chapel by Michelangelo. And
even centuries later, copies of these muscular ladies with their
oracular books open used to look down on the wondering present
writer in a Unitarian Sunday school in New England. Such is the
thirst of our institutions after authorization.
And when they too had ceased, when the gods no longer would
inhabit living human forms in prophecy and oracle, mankind
searches for other ways of taking up the slack, as it were, between
heaven and earth. There are new religions, Christianity, Gnosticism, and Neo-Platonism. There are new orders of conduct to
relate god-shorn men to the enormous conscious landscape of a
now spatialized time, as in Stoicism and Epicureanism. There is
an institutionalization and elaboration of divination beyond anything in Assyria, divination built into the political state officially
to generate decisions on important matters. As the Greek civilizations had been anchored into the divine by oracles, so the Roman
now is by auspices and augurers.
A Revival of Idols
But even these cannot fill the need of the common man for
transcendence. Following the failure of oracles and prophets as
if to replace them is an attempted revival of idols similar to those
of bicameral times.
The great bicameral civilizations had, as we have seen, used a
wide variety of effigies to help hallucinate bicameral voices. But
when those voices ceased in the adjustment to subjective consciousness, all this was darkened. Most idols were destroyed.
THE
QUEST
FOR
AUTHORIZATION
333
Late bicameral kingdoms at the behest of their jealous gods had
always smashed and burned the idols of opposing gods or kings.
And the practice accelerated when the idols were no longer
heard and worshiped. King Josiah, in the seventh century B.C.,
ordered all idols in his domain destroyed. The Old Testament is
full of the destruction of idols, as well as imprecations on the
heads of those who make new ones. By the middle of the first
millennium B.C., idolatry is only here and there, fitful and unimportant.
Curiously, there is at this time a very minor cult of hallucinating from severed heads. Herodotus (4:26) speaks of the practice
in the obscure Issedones of gilding a head and sacrificing to it.
Cleomenes of Sparta is said to have preserved the head of
Archonides in honey and consulted it before undertaking any
important task. Several vases of the fourth century B.C. in Etruria depict scenes of persons interrogating oracular heads.18 And
the severed head of the rustic Carians which continues to 'speak'
is mentioned derisively by Aristotle. 19 And this is about all. Thus,
after subjective consciousness is firmly established, the practice of
hallucinating from idols is only sporadically present.
But as we approach the beginning of the Christian era, with
the oracles mocked into silence, we have a very true revival of
idolatry. The temples that whitened the hills and cities of decadent Greece and ascendant Rome were now crammed with more
and more statues of gods. By the first century A.D., the Apostle
Paul despairingly found Athens full of idols (Acts 17), and Pausanias, whom we met a few pages ago at Lebadea, described
them as being simply everywhere on his travels and of every
conceivable sort: marble and ivory, gilded and painted, life-sized
and some two or three stories high.
Did such idols 'speak' to their worshipers? There is no doubt
18
See John Cohen, "Human Robots and Computer Art," History Today, 1970,
8:562.
19
De Partibus Animalium, III, 10:9-12.
334
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
that this sometimes occurred, just as in bicameral times. But in
general in the subjective era, it seems very doubtful that this
happened spontaneously very often. For otherwise there would
not have been the rising attention to artificial means, magical and
chemical, for obtaining hallucinated messages from stone and
ivory gods. And here again we see the entrance into history of
the general bicameral paradigm: collective cognitive imperative,
induction, trance, and archaic authorization.
In Egypt, where the breaking point between bicamerality and
subjectivity is far less sharp than in more volatile nations, there
was the development of the so-called Hermetic literature. This is
a series of papyri describing various induction procedures that
came into being at the edge of bicameral certainty and spread
over the conscious world. In one of them, there is a dialogue
called the Asclepus (after the Greek god of healing) that describes the art of imprisoning the souls of demons or of angels in
statues with the help of herbs, gems, and odors, such that the
statue could speak and prophesy.20 In other papyri, there are
still other recipes for constructing such images and animating
them, such as when images are to be hollow so as to enclose a
magic name inscribed on gold leaf.
By the first century A.D., this practice had spread over most of
the civilized world. In Greece, rumors broke into legends over the
miraculous behavior of public cult statues. In Rome, Nero prized
a statue which warned him of conspiracies.21 Apuleius was
accused of possessing one.22 So common were hallucinogenic
idols by the second century A.D. that Lucian in his Philopseudes
satirized the belief in them. And Iamblichus, the Neo-Platonist
apostle of theurgy, as it was called in his Peri agalmaton, tried to
20 The records of the various temples to the medical god Asclepius are full of reported diagnoses and therapeutic directives told to the sick as they slept there. These
have been collected and translated by E. J. and L. Edelstein, Asclepus: A Collection
and Interpretation of the Testimonies, 2 vols., 1945.
21 Suetonius, Nero, 56.
22 Apuleius, Apol., 63.
THE
QUEST
FOR
AUTHORIZATION
335
prove “that idols are divine and filled with the divine presence,”
establishing a vogue for such idols against the fuming execration
of Christian critics. His disciples obtained omens of every sort
and distinction from idols. One hallucinator boasted he could
make a statue of Hecate laugh and cause the torches in her hand
to light up. And another feels he can tell whether a statue is
animate or inanimate by the sensation it gives him. Even Cyprian, the good gray Bishop of Carthage, complained in the third
century of the “spirits that lurk under statues and consecrated
images.”23 The whole civilized world, in this effort to recall the
bicameral mind after the failure of oracles and prophecy, was
filled with epiphanies of statues of every sort and description in
this remarkable revival of idolatry.
How was all this believable? Since this is well into the subjective era, when men prided themselves on reason and common
sense, and at last knew there were such experiences as false
hallucinations, how was it possible that they could actually believe that statues embodied real gods? And really spoke?
Let us recall the almost universal belief of these centuries in
an absolute dualism of mind and matter. Mind or soul or spirit or
consciousness (all these were confused together) was a thing
imposed from heaven on the bodily matter to give it life. All the
newer religions of this era were allied about this point. And if a
soul can be imposed on so fragile a thing as flesh to make it live,
on a hurtable carcass that has to have vegetable and animal
matter stuffed in one end and stenchfully excreted at another, a
sense-pocked sinful vessel that the years wrinkle and the winds
chafe and diseases cruelly hound, and that can be sliced off in a
trice from the soul it holds by the same act that stabs an onion,
how much more possible for life, divine life, to be imposed by
heaven upon a statue of unbleeding beauty with a faultless and
immaculate body of unwrinkling marble or diseaseless gold!
23 Other instances are mentioned by E. R. Dodds, Greeks and the Irrational.
336
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
Here is Callistratus, for example, in the fourth century A.D.,
writing about an ivory and gold statue of the god Asclepius:
Shall we admit that the divine spirit descends into human
bodies, there to be even defiled by passions, and nevertheless
not believe it in a case where there is no attendant engendering
of evil?
. . . for see how an image, after A r t has portrayed
in it a god, even passes over into the god himself!
Matter
though it is, it gives forth divine intelligence. 24
And he and most of the world believed it.
The evidence for all this would be much more obvious today,
had not Constantine in the fourth century, even like King Josiah
in Israel one millennium earlier, sent his armies of Christian
converts out with sledge hammers through the once bicameral
world to smash all its physical vestiges in sight. Every god is a
jealous god after the breakdown of the bicameral mind.
But even this destruction could not abolish idolatrous practice,
so vital is it to have some kind of authorization for our behavior.
Medieval Italy and Byzantium believed in enchanted idols who
had power to avert disaster. The notorious Knights Templars
were at least accused of taking orders from a gold head called
Baphomet. So common had hallucinogenic idols become in the
late Middle Ages that a bull of Pope John X X I I in 1326 denounced those who by magic imprison demons in images or other
objects, interrogate them, and obtain answers. Even up to the
Reformation, monasteries and churches vied with each other to
attract pilgrims (and their offerings) by miracle-producing
statuary.
In some epochs, perhaps when the cognitive imperatives for
such neo-bicameral experiences began to wither under the sunlight of rationalism, the belief in statue animation was occasion24 Callistratus, Descriptions, 10, A. Fairbanks, trans. (Loeb Classical Library,
1902).
THE
QUEST
FOR
AUTHORIZATION
337
ally sustained by the use of fraudulent contrivances.25 In one
instance of many, a life-sized medieval rood of the crucified Jesus
at Boxley, which rolled its eyes at penitents, shed tears, and
foamed at the mouth, was found in the sixteenth century to have
“certain engines and old wires with old rotten sticks in the back of
the same.”26 But we shouldn’t cynicize too deeply here. While
such artificial animation often functioned as chicanery to fool the
miracle-hungry pilgrim, it may also have been meant as an enticement to the god to body itself in a more lifelike statue. As a
fourteenth-century tract on the matter explained, “God’s power in
working of his miracles loweth down in one image more than in
another.”27 Animated idols in some contemporary tribes are
explained by their worshipers in the same way.
Idolatry is still a socially cohesive force — its original function.
Our parks and public gardens are still the beflowered homes of
heroic effigies of past leaders. While few of us can hallucinate
their speech, we still on appropriate occasions might give them
gifts of wreaths, even as greater gifts were given in the gigunus
of Ur. In churches, temples, and shrines the world over, religious
statues are still being carved, painted, and prayed to. Figurines
of a Queen of Heaven dangle protectively from the mirrors of
American windshields. Teen-age girls I have interviewed, living
in deeply religious convents, often sneak down to the chapel in
the dead of night and have mentioned to me their excitement at
being able to ‘hear‘ the statue of the Virgin Mary speak, and ‘see’
her lips move or her head bow or — sometimes — her eyes weep.
Gentle idols of Jesus, Mary, and the saints throughout much of
the Catholic world are still being bathed, dressed, incensed,
25 See F. Poulsen, “Talking, weeping-, and bleeding- sculptures.” Ada Archeologica,
1945, 16 : 178f.
26 See Jonathan Sumption’s Pilgrimage: An Image of Medieval Religion (Totawa,
N.J.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1975), p. 56; also Julia Holloway’s forthcoming The
Pilgrim. I am grateful to her for bringing this to my attention.
27 Quoted from the Lollard manuscript Lanterne of Lights by Sumption, p. 270.
338
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
flowered, jeweled, and launched shoulder-high and glorious out
of bell-bellowing churches on outings through towns and countrysides on feast days. Placing special foods in front of them or
dancing and bowing before them still generates its numinous
excitement.28 Such devotions differ from similar divine outings
in bicameral Mesopotamia 4000 years ago mostly in the idol's
relative silence.
28 As in Flaubert's beautiful story Un Coeur Simple.
CHAPTER 2
Of Prophets and Possession
I
N T H E F O R E G O I N G theory of oracles,
I am sure that the reader
has seen the profound gap that I have jumped over in my argument. I have called the general bicameral paradigm a vestige of
the bicameral mind. And yet the trance state of narrowed or
absent consciousness is not, at least from the fourth oracular
term and thereafter, a duplicate of the bicameral mind. Instead
we have for the rest of the oracle's existence a complete domination of the person and his speech by the god-side, a domination
which speaks through the person but does not allow him to
remember what has happened afterwards. This phenomenon is
known as possession.
The problem it presents is not confined to far-off ancient oracles. It occurs today. It has occurred through history. It has a
negatory form that seems to have been one of the most common
maladies in the Galilee of the New Testament. And a good case
could be made that at least some of the wandering prophets of
Mesopotamia, Israel, Greece, and elsewhere did not simply relay
to listeners something they were hearing in hallucination, rather
that the divine message was coming directly from the prophet's
vocal apparatus without any cognition on 'his' part during the
speech or memory of it after. And if we call this a loss of
consciousness, and I shall, such a statement is quite problematic.
Is it not also possible to say that it is not the loss of consciousness
so much as its replacement by a new and different conscious-
340 Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
ness? But what can that mean? Or is that linguistic organization
which speaks from the supposed possessed person not conscious
at all in the sense of narratizing in a mind-space as described in
I.2?
These questions are not solved by simple answers. The fact that
we may regard possession by metaphysical essences as ontological nonsense should not blind us from the psychological and
historical insights that examination of such idiosyncrasies of history and belief can give us. Indeed, any theory of consciousness
and its origin in time must face such obscurities. And I do
suggest that the theory in this book is a better torch for such dark
corners of time and mind than any alternative theory. For if we
still hold to a purely biological evolution of consciousness back
somewhere among the lower vertebrates, how can we approach
such phenomena or begin to understand their historically and
culturally segregated nature? It is only if consciousness is
learned at the mercy of a collective cognitive imperative that we
can take hold of these questions in any way.
Our first step in understanding any mental phenomenon must
be to delimit its existence in historical time. When did it first
occur?
The answer in Greece, at least, is very clear. There is no such
thing as possession or any hint of anything similar throughout
the Iliad or Odyssey or other early poetry. No 'god' speaks
through human lips in the truly bicameral age. Yet by 400 B.C., it
is apparently as common as churches are with us, both in the
many oracles scattered about Greece as well as in private individuals. The bicameral mind has vanished and possession is its
trace.
Plato, in the fourth century B.C., has Socrates casually say in
the midst of a political discussion that "God-possessed men speak
much truth, but know nothing of what they say," 1 as if such
1 Meno, 99C. See also Ttmaeus, 71E-72A, where it is said "no man in his wits
attains prophetic truth and inspirations."
OF
PROPHETS
AND
POSSESSION
341
prophets could be heard every day around the streets of Athens.
And he was very clear about the loss of consciousness in the
oracles of his time:
. . . for prophecy is a madness, and the prophetess at Delphi
and the priestesses at Dodona when out of their senses have conferred great benefits on Hellas, both in public and private life,
but when in their senses few or none. 2
And so in the centuries that follow, supposed possession is the
obliteration of ordinary consciousness. Four hundred years after
Plato, in the first century A.D., Philo Judaeus categorically states,
W h e n he (a prophet) is inspired he becomes unconscious;
thought vanishes away and leaves the fortress of the soul; but
the divine spirit has entered there and taken up its abode; and
this later makes all the organs resound so that the man gives
clear expression to what the spirit gives him to say. 3
And so also in the century after that, as in Aristides5 saying
that the priestesses at the oracle of Dodona
. . . do not know, before being seized by the spirits, what they
are going to say, any more than after having recovered their
natural senses they remember what they have said, so that everyone knows what they say except themselves. 4
And Iamblichus, the leading Neo-Platonist at the beginning of
the third century, insisted that divine possession "participated" in
divinity, had a "common energy" with a god, and "comprehends
indeed everything in us but exterminates our own proper con2 Phaedrus, 244B.
3 Philo, De Special Legibus, 4, 343M, Cohn and Wendland, eds., who in another
place says, "He who is really inspired and filled with god cannot comprehend with his
intelligence what he says; he only repeats what is suggested to him, as if another
prompted him." 222M.
4 Aristides, Opera, 213.
342
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
sciousness and motion."5 Such possession, then, is not a return
to the bicameral mind properly speaking. For when Achilles
heard Athene a millennium earlier, he certainly did know what
was said to him; that was the function of the bicameral mind.
This then is the very core of the problem. The speech of
possessed prophets is not an hallucination proper, not something
heard by a conscious, semi-conscious, or even nonconscious man
as in the bicameral mind proper. It is articulated externally and
heard by others. It occurs only in normally conscious men and is
coincident with a loss of that consciousness. What justification
then do we have for saying that the two phenomena, the hallucinations of the bicameral mind and the speech of the possessed, are
related?
I do not have a truly robust answer. I can only meekly maintain that they are related (1) because they are serving the same
social function, (2) because they yield similar communications
of authorization, and (3) because the little evidence we have on
the early history of oracles indicates that possession in a few
institutionalized persons at certain locations is a gradual outgrowth from the hallucinations of gods by anyone at those locations. We can therefore at least suggest that possession is a
transformation of a particular sort, a derivative of bicamerality in
which the rituals of induction and the different collective cognitive imperatives and trained expectancies result in the ostensive
possession of the particular person by the god-side of the bicameral mind. Perhaps we could say that, to retrieve the older
mentality, developing consciousness more and more had to be
obliterated, inhibiting the man-side with it, leaving the god-side
in control of speech itself.
And what of the neurology of such a mentality? From the
model I have presented in 1.5, we must naturally hypothesize that
5 Iamblichus, De Mysteriis, 3:8, or the English translation by Thomas Taylor
(London: Theosophical Society, 1895), pp. 128-129.
OF
PROPHETS
AND
POSSESSION
343
in possession there is some kind of disturbance of normal hemispheric dominance relations, in which the right hemisphere is
somewhat more active than in the normal state. In other words,
if we could have placed electrodes on the scalp of a Delphic
oracle in her frenzy, would we have found a relatively faster EEG
(and therefore greater activity) over her right hemisphere, correlating with her possession? And particularly over her right
temporal lobe?
I suggest that we would. There is at least a possibility that the
dominance relations of the two hemispheres would be changed,
and that the early training of the oracle was indeed that of
engaging a higher ratio of right hemisphere activity in relation to
the left as a response to the complex stimulus of the induction
procedures. Such a hypothesis might also explain the contorted
features, the appearance of frenzy and the nystagmic eyes, as an
abnormal right hemisphere interference or release from inhibition by the left hemisphere.6
And a comment can be added here about sexual differences. It
is now well known that women are biologically somewhat less
lateralized in brain function than men. This means simply that
psychological functions in women are not localized into one or
the other hemisphere of the brain to the same degree as in men.
Mental abilities in women are more spread over both hemispheres. Even by age six, for example, a boy can recognize objects
in his left hand by feel alone better than in his right hand. In girls
both hands are equal. This shows that haptic recognition (as it is
called) has already been primarily localized in the right hemisphere in boys but not in girls.7 And it is common knowledge that
6 It is likely that it is not the right motor cortex controlling- the facial grimaces,
but that the unusual right temporal-parietal lobe activity distorts the symmetry of
input from the basal ganglia to facial expression.
7 Sandra F. Witelson, "Sex and the Single Hemisphere," Science, 1976, 193:425427. A collation of about thirty other studies on the subject may be found in Richard
A. Harshman and Roger Remington, "Sex, Language, and the Brain, Part I: A Review
of the Literature on Adult Sex Differences in Lateralization," authors' preprint, 19755
see also Stevan Harnad, "On Gender Differences in Language," Contemporary
Anthropology, 197 6, 17:327—328.
344
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
elderly men with a stroke or hemorrhage in the left hemisphere
are more speechless than elderly women with a similar diagnosis.
Accordingly we might expect more residual language function in
the right hemisphere of women, making it easier for women to
learn to be oracles. And indeed the majority of oracles and Sibyls,
at least in European cultures, were women.
Induced Possession
Institutionalized unconscious speaking in the prophets of oracles as if by a god becomes, as we have seen in III.1, erratic and
silent toward the first centuries of the Christian era. It falls to a
siege of rationalism, to volleys of criticism and ramming irreverence in comic drama and literature. Such public (indeed urban)
suppression of a general cultural characteristic often results in
pushing it into private practice, into abstruse sects and esoteric
cults where its cognitive imperative is protected from such criticism. And so with induced possession. With the oracles mocked
into silence, such the quest for authorization that there is a
widespread attempt in private groups to bring back the gods and
have them speak through almost anyone.
The second century A.D. saw a growing number of such cults.
Their seances were sometimes in official shrines, but increasingly more often in private circles. Usually one person called a
felestike or operator tried to incarnate the god temporarily in
another called a katochos, or more specially a docheus, or what in
contemporary lore is called a medium.8 It was soon found that if
the phenomenon was to work, the katochos should come from a
simple unsophisticated background, something that runs through
all the literature on possession. Iamblichus in the early third
century, the real apostle of all this, states that the most suitable
8 In this part of my discussion I am indebted to the wealth of information in E. R.
Dodds, The Greeks and the Irrational (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1968), Appendix II, Theurgy, where many other references may be found.
OF
PROPHETS
AND
POSSESSION
345
mediums are "young and simple persons." And so, we remember,
were the uneducated country girls chosen to train as priestesses
for the oracle at Delphi. Other writings mention adolescents
such as the boy Aedesius, who "had only to put on the garland and
look at the sun, when he immediately produces reliable oracles in
the best inspirational style." Presumptively, this was due to careful training. That such induced bicameral possession has to be
learned is known from the training of oracles as well as a comment of Pythagoras of Rhodes in the third century, that the gods
come at first reluctantly, then more easily when they have
formed the habit of entering the same person.
What was learned, I suggest, was a state approaching the
bicameral mind as a response to the induction. This is important.
We do not ordinarily think of learning a new unconscious mentality, perhaps a whole new relationship between our cerebral
hemispheres, as we think of learning to ride a bicycle.
Since this is the learning of a now difficult neurological state,
so different from ordinary life, it is not surprising that the cues of
the induction had to be wildly distinctive and have an extreme
difference from ordinary life.
And they certainly were different: anything odd, anything
strange: bathing in smoke or sacred water, dressing in enchanted
chitons with magical girdles, wearing weird garlands or mysterious symbols, standing in a charmed magic circle as medieval
magicians did, or upon charakteres as Faust did to hallucinate
Mephistopheles, or smearing the eyes with strychnine to procure
visions as was done in Egypt, or washing in brimstone (sulphur)
and seawater, a very old method which began in Greece, as
Porphyry said in the second century A.D., to prepare the anima
sfiritalis for the reception of a higher being. All these of course
did nothing except as they were believed to do something — just
as we in this latter age have no 'free wil' unless we believe we
have.
346
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
And what was done, this 'reception of the god', was not psychologically different from the other forms of possession we have
examined. Consciousness as well as normal reactivity in the
katochos was usually in complete suspension so that it was necessary to have others look after him. And in such a deep trance,
the 'god' would supposedly reveal past or future, or answer questions and make decisions, as in the older Greek oracles.
How was it to be explained when these gods were incorrect?
Well, evil spirits might have been invoked instead of true gods,
or other intrusive spirits might have occupied the medium. Iamblichus himself claims to have unmasked in his medium an alleged
Apollo who was only the ghost of a gladiator. Such excuses
reverberate throughout the subsequent decadent literature of
spiritualism.
And when the seance did not seem to be working, the operator
as well often went through an induction of purifying rites that
put him into a hallucinatory state, such that he might 'see' more
clearly or 'hear' from the unconscious medium something that
perhaps the medium did not even say. This kind of doubling-up
is similar to the prophetes’ relationship to their oracles, and
explains various reported levitations, elongations, or dilations of
the medium's body.9
By the end of the third century, Christianity had suddenly
flooded the pagan world with its own claims to authorization and
began to dissolve into itself many of the then existing pagan
practices. The idea of possession was one of those. But it was
absorbed in a transcendental way. At almost the same time that
Iamblichus was teaching the induction of gods into statues, or
young illiterate katochoi to "participate" in divinity and have "a
common energy" with a god, Athanasius, the competitive Bishop
of Alexandria, began claiming the same thing for the illiterate
9 It is safe to suggest that many feats of present-day stage magicians have their
origin in duplicating these 'proofs' of divine intervention.
OF
PROPHETS
AND
POSSESSION
347
Jesus. The Christian Messiah had heretofore been regarded as
like Yahweh, a demigod perhaps, half human, half divine, reflecting his supposed parentage. But Athanasius persuaded Constantine, his Council of Nicaea, and most of Christianity thereafter,
that Jesus participated in Yahweh, was the same substance, the
Bicameral Word made Flesh. I think we can say then that the
growing church, in danger of shattering into sects, exaggerated
the subjective phenomenon of possession into an objective theological dogma. It did so to assert an even greater claim to an
absolute authorization. For Athanasian Christians the actual
gods had indeed returned to earth and would return again.
Curiously, neither the oracle at Delphi nor the Sibyls were
doubted as contacting a heavenly reality by this expanding Christian Church. But such pagan seances as induced divine possession in simple boys seemed theologically rowdy, the mischief of
devils and shady spirits. And so as the church arches up into
political authority over the Middle Ages, voluntary induced possession disappears at least from public notice. It goes even further underground into witchcraft and assorted necromancies,
emerging into notice only from time to time.
Its contemporary practice I shall come to in a moment. But
first we should examine a cultural side effect of induced possession, a disturbing phenomenon I shall call
Negatory Possession
There is another side to this vigorously strange vestige of the
bicameral mind. And it is different from other topics in this
chapter. For it is not a response to a ritual induction for the
purpose of retrieving the bicameral mind. It is an illness in
response to stress. In effect, emotional stress takes the place of
the induction in the general bicameral paradigm just as in antiquity. And when it does, the authorization is of a different kind.
The difference presents a fascinating problem. In the New
348
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modem World
Testament, where we first hear of such spontaneous possession,
it is called in Greek daemonizomai, or demonization.10 And from
that time to the present, instances of the phenomenon most often
have that negatory quality connoted by the term. The why of
the negatory quality is at present unclear. In an earlier chapter
(II.4) I have tried to suggest the origin of ‘evil5 in the volitional
emptiness of the silent bicameral voices. And that this took place
in Mesopotamia and particularly in Babylon, to which the Jews
were exiled in the sixth century B.C., might account for the
prevalence of this quality in the world of Jesus at the start of this
syndrome.
But whatever the reasons, they must in the individual be similar to the reasons behind the predominantly negatory quality of
schizophrenic hallucinations. And indeed the relationship of this
type of possession to schizophrenia seems obvious.
Like schizophrenia, negatory possession usually begins with
some kind of an hallucination.11 It is often a castigating ‘voice’
of a ‘demon’ or other being which is ‘heard’ after a considerable
stressful period. But then, unlike schizophrenia, probably because of the strong collective cognitive imperative of a particular
group or religion, the voice develops into a secondary system of
personality, the subject then losing control and periodically entering into trance states in which consciousness is lost, and the
‘demon’ side of the personality takes over.
Always the patients are uneducated, usually illiterate, and all
believe heartily in spirits or demons or similar beings and live in a
society which does. The attacks usually last from several minutes to an hour or two, the patient being relatively normal be10 Moreover, instances of such possession occur most often in the oldest and most
authentic of the Gospels: Mark 1:32, 5:15-18} and Matthew (which scholars are
agreed is based upon Mark as well as some unknown older Gospel) 4:24; 8:16;
8 :2 8—33; 9 :32 ; 12 :22.
11 Here I am summarizing cases in the literature. For fuller discussions of this
topic as well as other case descriptions (not very complete) see Oesterreich, Possession;
as well as J. L. Nevius, Demon Possession and Allied Themes (Chicago: Revell,
1896).
OF
PROPHETS
AND
POSSESSION
349
tween attacks and recalling little of them. Contrary to horror
fiction stories, negatory possession is chiefly a linguistic phenomenon, not one of actual conduct. In all the cases I have studied, it
is rare to find one of criminal behavior against other persons.
The stricken individual does not run off and behave like a
demon j he just talks like one.
Such episodes are usually accompanied by twistings and writhings as in induced possession. The voice is distorted, often guttural, full of cries, groans, and vulgarity, and usually railing
against the institutionalized gods of the period. Almost always,
there is a loss of consciousness as the person seems the opposite
of his or her usual self. 'He' may name himself a god, demon,
spirit, ghost, or animal (in the Orient it is often 'the fox'), may
demand a shrine or to be worshiped, throwing the patient into
convulsions if these are withheld. 'He' commonly describes his
natural self in the third person as a despised stranger, even as
Yahweh sometimes despised his prophets or the Muses sneered at
their poets.12 And 'he' often seems far more intelligent and alert
than the patient in his normal state, even as Yahweh and the
Muses were more intelligent and alert than prophet or poet.
As in schizophrenia, the patient may act out the suggestions of
others, and, even more curiously, may be interested in contracts
or treaties with observers, such as a promise that 'he' will leave
the patient if such and such is done, bargains which are carried
out as faithfully by the 'demon' as the sometimes similar covenants of Yahweh in the Old Testament. Somehow related to this
suggestibility and contract interest is the fact that the cure for
spontaneous stress-produced possession, exorcism, has never
varied from New Testament days to the present. It is simply by
the command of an authoritative person often following an induction ritual, speaking in the name of a more powerful god.
12 I probably should not be making these cross-comparisons. But I am at least
revealing my thinking. Is it possible that what corresponds to Wernicke's area on the
right hemisphere always 'looks down' on Wernicke's area on the left? The references
are to Exodus 4:24 and to Hesiod's Theogony, line 26, respectively.
350
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
The exorcist can be said to fit into the authorization element of
the general bicameral paradigm, replacing the 'demon.' The cognitive imperatives of the belief system that determined the form
of the illness in the first place determine the form of its cure.
The phenomenon does not depend on age, but sex differences,
depending on the historical epoch, are pronounced, demonstrating its cultural expectancy basis. Of those possessed by 'demons'
whom Jesus or his disciples cured in the New Testament, the
overwhelming majority were men. In the Middle Ages and
thereafter, however, the overwhelming majority were women.
Also evidence for its basis in a collective cognitive imperative are
its occasional epidemics, as in convents of nuns during the Middle Ages, in Salem, Massachusetts, in the eighteenth century,
or those reported in the nineteenth century at Savoy in the Alps.
And occasionally today.
Now, again, with any alteration of mentality as striking as this,
we cannot escape the neurological question. What is happening?
Are the speech areas of the right nondominant hemisphere activated in spontaneous possession, as I have suggested they were in
the induced possession of the oracles? And are the contorted
features due to the intrusion of right hemisphere control? The
fact that the majority of instances (as well as most oracles and
Sibyls) were women, and that women are (presently in our culture) less lateralized than men is somewhat suggestive.
At least some instances of possession begin with contortions on
the left side of the body, which may indicate this is true. Here is
one case reported at the beginning of this century. The patient
was a forty-seven-year-old uneducated Japanese woman who
would become possessed by what she called the fox, six or seven
times a day, always with the same laterality phenomena. As it
was then observed by her physicians:
At first there appeared slight twitchings of the mouth and
arm on the left side. As these became stronger she violently
OF
PROPHETS
AND
POSSESSION
351
struck with her fist her left side which was already swollen and
red with similar blows, and said to me: “ A h , sir, here he is
stirring again in my breast.” T h e n a strange and incisive voice
issued from her mouth: “Yes, it is true, I am there. Did you
think, stupid goose, that you could stop
me?”
Thereupon the
woman addressed herself to us: “Oh dear, gentlemen, forgive
me, I cannot help it!”
Continuing to strike her breast and contract the left side of
her face . . . the woman threatened him, adjured him to be
quiet, but after a short time he interrupted her and it was he
alone who thought and spoke. T h e woman was now passive like
an automaton, obviously no longer understanding what was said
to her. It was the fox which answered maliciously instead. At
the end of ten minutes the fox spoke in a more confused manner,
the woman gradually came to herself and assumed back her
normal state.
She remembered the first part of the fit and
begged us with tears to forgive her for the outrageous conduct
of the fox. 1 3
But this is one case. I have not found any other patient in which
such distinct laterality phenomena were in evidence.
In puzzling about the neurology of negatory possession, it can
be helpful, I think, to consider the contemporary illness known as
Gilles de la Tourette’s Syndrome,14 or, occasionally, "foul-mouth
disease." This bizarre group of symptoms usually begins in childhood at age five or sometimes earlier, with perhaps merely a
repeated facial twitch or bad word out of context. This then
develops into an uncontrollable emission of ripe obscenities,
grunts, barks, or profanities in the middle of otherwise normal
13 E. Balz, Ueber Besessenheit (Leipzig, 1907), as translated by Oesterreich, Possession,, p. 227. Physicians attending her were astonished to see the cleverness of
speech, the witty and ironic language, so unlike the patient's own, which the 'fox'
displayed.
14 For recent work on this subject as well as its history, see the references and
data in A. K. Shapiro, E. Shapiro, H. L. Wayne, J. Clarkin, and R. D. Bruun,
"Tourette's Syndrome: summary of data on 34. patients," Psychosomatic Medicine,
973, 35:419-435.
352
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
conversation, as well as various facial tics, sticking out the
tongue, etc. These often continue through adult life, much to the
distress of the patient. Such persons often end up refusing to
leave their homes because of their horror and embarrassment at
their own intermittent uncontrollable vulgarity. In one case I
knew of recently, the man invented a cover of having severe
bladder problems requiring him to urinate often. Actually, every
time he dashed to the Men’s Room while at a restaurant or to the
bathroom in a house, it was the welling up of profanity that he
went to relieve himself of by shouting it at toilet walls.15 To be
profane myself, the linguistic feeling within him may not have
been unlike the prophet Jeremiah’s fire shut up in his bones (see
11:6), although the semantic product was somewhat (but not
altogether) different.
What is of interest here is that Tourette’s Syndrome so clearly
resembles the initial phase of stress-produced possession as to
force upon us the suspicion that they share a common physiological mechanism. And this may indeed be incomplete hemispheric
dominance, in which the speech areas of the right hemisphere
(perhaps stimulated by impulses from the basal ganglia) are
periodically breaking through into language under conditions
which would have produced an hallucination in bicameral man.
Accordingly it is not surprising that almost all sufferers from
Tourette's Syndrome have abnormal brain wave patterns, some
central nervous system damage, and are usually left-handed (in
the majority of left-handed persons there is mixed dominance),
and that the symptoms begin around the age of five when the
neurological development of hemispheric dominance in regard to
language is being completed.
Now all of this says something important but unsettling about
15 Tourette’s Syndrome is often if not usually misdiagnosed as a form of insanity,
which it definitely is not. Fortunately and interestingly, however, one of the new antipsychotic tranquilizers, haloperidol, has been found to abolish the symptoms — which
it did in the above-mentioned cases. I am grateful to Dr. Shapiro for discussion on
these points.
OF
PROPHETS
AND
POSSESSION
353
our nervous systems. For while I believe the neurological model
in I.5 to be in the right direction, we are getting further and
further away from it. It is very improbable that modern spirit
possession is everywhere engaging right hemisphere speech centers for the articulated speech itself. Such an hypothesis is contrary to so many clinical facts as to rule it out except in highly
unusual cases.
A more likely possibility, perhaps, is that the neurological
difference between the bicameral mind and modern possession
states is that in the former, hallucinations were indeed organized
and heard from the right hemisphere; while in possession, the
articulated speech is our normal left hemisphere speech but controlled or under the guidance of the right hemisphere. In other
words, what corresponds to Wernicke's area on the right hemisphere is using Broca's area on the left hemisphere, the result
being the trance state and its depersonalization. Such cross control could be the neurological substrate of the loss of normal
consciousness.
Possession in the Modern World
I wish now to turn to induced possession in our own times to
demonstrate with some conclusiveness that it is a learned phenomenon. The best example I have found is the Umbanda religion, the largest by far of the Afro-Brazilian religions practiced
today by over half the population of Brazil. It is believed in as a
source of decision by persons of all ethnic backgrounds and is
certainly the most extensive occurrence of induced possession
since the third century.
Let us look in on a typical gira or “turn around,” as an Umbanda session is so aptly called.16 It may be taking place at the
present time in a room above a store or in an abandoned garage.
16 This entire section on the Umbanda is based on the extremely rich and definitive
study of Esther Pressel, “Umbanda Trance and Possession in Sao Paulo, Brazil,” in
Felicitas Goodman et al., Trance, Healing, and Hallucination (New York: Wiley,
1974.).
354 Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
Perhaps a dozen or fewer mediums (70 percent are women), all
dressed ceremoniously in white, come out from a tiring room in
front of a white-draped altar crammed with flowers, candles, and
statues and pictures of Christian saints, an audience of a hundred
or so being beyond a railing on the other side of the room. The
drummers beat and the audience sings, as the mediums begin to
sway or dance. This swaying and dancing is always in a counterclockwise motion, that is, beginning with motor impulses from the
right hemisphere. There follows a Christian type of service.
Then drums are once more pounded furiously, everyone sings,
and the mediums begin to call their spirits; some spin to the left
like whirling dervishes, again exciting their right hemispheres.
There is the explicit metaphor here of the medium as a cavalo
or horse. A particular spirit is supposed to lower himself into his
cavalo. As this is happening, the head and chest of the cavalo,
or medium, jerks back and forth in opposing directions like a
bronco being ridden. The hair falls into disarray. Facial expressions become contorted, as in ancient examples I have cited.
Posture changes into the likeness of any of several possessing
spirits. The possession accomplished, the ‘spirits’ may dance for
a few minutes, may greet each other in the possessed state, may
perform other actions suitable to the type of spirit, and then,
when the drumming stops, go to preassigned places, and, curiously, as they wait for members of the audience to come forward
for the consultas, they snap their fingers impatiently as their
hands rest beside their bodies, palms outward. In the consultas
the possessed medium may be asked for, and may give, decisions
on any illness or personal problem, on getting or keeping a job,
on financial business practices, family quarrels, love affairs, or
even, among students, advice about scholastic grades.
Now the evidence that possession is a learned mentality is very
clear in these Brazilian cults. In a bairro playground, one may
occasionally see children in their play imitating the distinctive
back-and-forth jerking of the head and chest that is used for
OF
PROPHETS
AND
POSSESSION
355
inducing and terminating spirit possession. If a child wishes to
become a medium, he is encouraged to do so and given special
training, just as were the young country girls who became the
oracles at Delphi and elsewhere. Indeed, some of the many
Umbanda centers (there are 4000 in Sao Paulo alone) hold regular training sessions, where the procedures include various ways
of making the novice dizzy in order to teach him or her the trance
state, as well as techniques similar to those used in hypnosis.
And in the trance state, the novice is taught how each of several
possible spirits behaves. This fact of a differentiation of possessing
spirits is important, and I wish to comment further on it and its
function in culture.
The vestiges of the bicameral mind do not exist in any empty
psychological space. That is, they should not be considered as
isolated phenomena that simply appear in a culture and loiter
around doing nothing but leaning on their own antique merits.
Instead, they always live at the very heart of a culture or subculture, moving out and filling up the unspoken and the unrationalized. They become indeed the irrational and unquestionable support and structural integrity of the culture. And the culture in
turn is the substrate of its individual consciousnesses, of how the
metaphor ‘me’ is ‘perceived’ by the analog ‘I’, of the nature of
excerption and the constraints on narratization and conciliation.
Such vestiges of the bicameral mind as we are here considering
are no exception. A possession religion such as the Umbanda
functions as a powerful psychological support to the heterogeneous masses of its poor and uneducated and needy. It is
pervaded with a feeling of caridade, or charity, which consoles and
binds together this motley of political impotents, whose urbanization and ethnic diversity has stranded them without roots. And
look at the pattern of particular neurological organizations that
emerge as possessing divinities. They remind us of the presenting
personal gods of Sumer and Babylon, interceders with those
356
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
above them. Each medium on any particular night may be possessed by an individual spirit from any of four main groups.
They are, in order of frequency:
the caboclos, spirits of Brazilian-Indian warriors, who advise
in situations requiring quick and decisive action, such as obtaining or maintaining a job;
the pretos velhos, spirits of old Afro-Brazilian slaves, adept
at handling long drawn-out personal problems;
the crianças, spirits of dead children, whose mediums make
playful suggestions;
the exus
(demons)
or, if female,
pombagiras
(turning
pigeons), spirits of wicked foreigners, whose mediums make
vulgar and aggressive suggestions.
Each of these four main types of possessor spirits represents a
different ethnic group corresponding to the ethnic hybridism of
the worshipers: Indian, African, Brazilian (the criangas are “like
us”), and European, respectively. Each represents a different
familial relationship to the petitioner: father, grandfather, sibling, and stranger respectively. And each represents a different
area of decision: quick decisions for choices of action, comforting
advice on personal problems, playful suggestions, and decisions in
matters of aggression respectively. Even as the Greek gods were
originally distinguished as areas of decision, so the spirits of the
Umbanda. And the whole is like a network or metaphor matrix
of four-way inner-related distinctiveness that binds the individuals together and holds them in a culture.
And all this, I suggest, is a vestige of the bicameral mind, as we
go through these millennia of adjusting to a new mentality.
True possession, as described by Plato and others, has always
been held to go on without consciousness, thus differentiating it
from acting. But the training of the persons of oracles must have
admitted of degrees and stages toward such a state. In the Brazilian possession religions, apparently, this is exactly what happens.
OF
PROPHETS
AND
POSSESSION
357
The young novice may begin by acting out possession in play,
then proceed with his training until eventually he can separate
what a spirit would say from what he himself would normally
talk about. Then there occurs a stage of passing back and forth
between consciousness and unconsciousness. And then with full
possession, perhaps the connecting up of Wernicke’s area on the
right hemisphere with Broca's on the left, the much-desired state
of unconsciousness, with no remembrance of what happens.
This, however, is true of only some mediums. And in any
pseudobicameral practice as extensive as this, it is to be expected
that there will be many different qualities and degrees of acting
and trance even within the same individual.
Glossolalia
A final phenomenon that is weakly similar to induced possession
is glossolalia, or what the apostle Paul called “speaking in
tongues.” It consists of fluent speech in what sounds like a
strange language which the speaker himself does not understand
and usually does not remember saying. It seems to have begun
with the early Christian Church17 in the asserted descent of the
ghost of God into the assembled apostles. This event was regarded as the birthday of the Christian Church and is commemorated in the festival of Pentecost, the fiftieth day after Easter.18
Acts 2 describes what is probably its first instance in history as a
great rushing wind roaring with cloven tongues of fire, in which
all the apostles begin to speak as if drunk in languages they had
never learned.
17 Old Testament references to Yahweh’s pouring out his spirit are sometimes put
forth as references to glossolalia, but I find this utterly unconvincing. The phenomenon can be regarded as peculiarly of Christian origin, particularly in the writings of, or influenced by, Paul.
18 Today at Vatican celebrations of Pentecost, red is worn to symbolize the tongues
of fire; and in Protestant churches, white, to symbolize the Holy Ghost, hence the
English term Whitsuntide, around white Sunday.
358
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
This alteration of mentality happening to the likes of the
apostles became its own authorization. The practice spread.
Soon early Christians were doing it everywhere. Paul even put it
on a level with prophecy (I Corinthians 14:27, 29). From time
to time in the centuries since Paul, glossolalia as a search for
authorization after the breakdown of the bicameral mind has had
its periods of fashion.
Its recent practice, not just by the sects that are theologically
extremely conservative, but also by members of mainline Protestant churches, has pushed it into some scientific scrutiny with
some interesting results. Glossolalia first happens always in groups
and always in the context of religious services. I am stressing the
group factor, since I think this strengthening of the collective
cognitive imperative is necessary for a particularly deep type of
trance. Often there will be what corresponds to an induction,
particularly hymn singing of a rousing sort, followed by the
exhortations of a charismatic leader: “If you feel your language
change, don’t resist it, let it happen.”19
The worshiper, through repeated attendance at such meetings,
watching others in glossolalia, first learns to enter into a deeptrance state of diminished or absent consciousness in which he is
not responsive to exteroceptive stimuli. The trance in this case is
almost an autonomic one: shakes, shivers, sweat, twitches, and
tears. Then he or she may somehow learn to "let it happen."
And it does, loud and clear, each phrase ending in a groan: aria
ariari isa, vena amiria as aria!20 The rhythm pounds, the way
epic dactyls probably did to the hearers of the aoidoi. And this
quality of regular alternation of accented and unaccented syllables, so similar to that of the Homeric epics, as well as the rising
and then downward intonation at the end of each phrase, does
not — and this is astonishing — does not vary with the native
19 Felicitas D. Goodman, "Disturbances in the Apostolic Church: A Trance-Based
Upheaval in Yucatan," in Goodman et al., Trance, Healing, and Hallucination,
pp. 227-364.
20 From a tape of Dr. Goodman's of a male glossolalist of Mayan descent in Yucatan. Ibid., pp. 262-263.
OF
PROPHETS
AND
POSSESSION
359
language of the speaker. If the subject is English, Portuguese,
Spanish, Indonesian, African, or Mayan, or wherever he is, the
pattern of glossolalia is the same.21
After the glossolalia, the subject opens his eyes and slowly
returns from these unconscious heights to dusty reality, remembering little of what happened. But he is told. He has been
possessed by the Holy Spirit. He has been chosen by God as his
puppet. His problems are stopped in hope and his sorrows torn
with joy. It is the ultimate in authorization since the Holy Spirit
is one with the highest source of all being. God has chosen to
enter the lowly subject and has articulated his speech with the
subject's own tongue. The individual has become a god —
briefly.
The cruel daylight of it all is less inspiring. While the phenomenon is not simply gibberish, nor can the average person
duplicate the fluency and structure of what is spoken, it has no
semantic meaning whatever. Tapes of glossolalia played before
others in the same religious group are given utterly inconsistent
interpretations.22 That the metered vocalizations are similar
across the cultures and language of the speakers, probably indicates that rhythmical discharges from subcortical structures are
coming into play, released by the trance state of lesser cortical
control.23
The ability does not last. It attenuates. The more it is prac21 The important result of Dr. Goodman's earlier study., Speaking in Tongues: A
Cross-Cultural Study of Glossolalia (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1972).
22 This is a generalization from the careful work of John P. Kildahl on twentysix American glossolalists all belonging to major Protestant denominations. See his
The Psychology of Speaking in Tongues (New York: Harper & Row, 1972). He
also gives a very complete bibliography on the matter.
23 "The surface structure of a non-linguistic deep structure," as Dr. Goodman says
in structuralist terms (p. 151-152). But the idea of an energy discharge from subcortical structures under diminished consciousness has been sharply criticized, particularly by the linguist W. J. Samarin in his review of Goodman in Language,
1974, 50:207-212. See also his Tongues of Men and Angels: The Religious Language of Pentecostalism (New York: Macmillan, 1972). I am grateful to Ronald
Baker of the University of Prince Edward Island for bringing this to my attention.
360
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
ticed, the more it becomes conscious, which destroys the trance.
An essential ingredient of the phenomenon, at least in more
educated groups where the cognitive imperative would be weaker,
is the presence of a charismatic leader who first teaches the
phenomenon. And if tongue speaking is to be continued at all,
and the resulting euphoria makes it a devoutly wished state of
mind, the relationship with the authoritative leader must be continued. It is really this ability to abandon the conscious direction
of one's speech controls in the presence of an authority figure
regarded as benevolent that is the essential thing. As we might
expect, glossolalists by the Thematic Apperception Test reveal
themselves as more submissive, suggestible, and dependent in the
presence of authority figures than those who cannot exhibit the
phenomenon.24
It is, then, this pattern of essential ingredients, the strong
cognitive imperative of religious belief in a cohesive group, the
induction procedures of prayer and ritual, the narrowing of consciousness into a trance state, and the archaic authorization in
the divine spirit and in the charismatic leader, which denotes this
phenomenon as another instance of the general bicameral paradigm and therefore a vestige of the bicameral mind.
Aria ariari isa, vena amiria asaria
Menin aeide thea Peleiadeo Achilleos
My comparison of the sound of speaking in tongues with the
sound of the Greek epics to their hearers (the second line above
is the first line of the Iliad) is not just an ornature of my style. It
is a very deliberate comparison. And one that I intend now as a
lead-in to the next chapter. For we should not leave our inquiry
into these cultural antiques without at least noting the oddity, the
difference, the true profundity, and — ultimately — the question
of and for poetry.
24 John P. Kildahl, The Final Progress Report: Glossolalia and Mental Health
(for NIMH), privately circulated.
CHAPTER 3
Of Poetry and Music
W
HY HAS so much of the textual material we have used as
evidence in earlier chapters been poetry? And why, particularly in times of stress, have a huge proportion of the readers of
this page written poems? What unseen light leads us to such
dark practice? And why does poetry flash with recognitions of
thoughts we did not know we had, finding its unsure way to
something in us that knows and has known all the time, something, I think, older than the present organization of our nature?
To charter a discussion down this optional and deserted topic
at this point in what has hitherto been a fairly linear argument
may seem an unwarranted indirection. But the chapters of Book
III, in contrast to the previous two books, are not a consecutive
procession. They are rather a selection of divergent trajectories
out of our bicameral past into present times. And I think it will
become obvious that the earlier argument, particularly as relating
to the Greek epics, needs to be rounded out with the present
chapter.
I shall state my thesis plain. The first poets were gods. Poetry
began with the bicameral mind. The god-side of our ancient
mentality, at least in a certain period of history, usually or perhaps always spoke in verse. This means that most men at one
time, throughout the day, were hearing poetry (of a sort) composed and spoken within their own minds.
362
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
The evidence is, of course, only inferential. It is that all of
those individuals who remained bicameral into the conscious age,
when speaking of or from the divine side of their minds, spoke in
poetry. The great epics of Greece were of course heard and
spoken by the aoidoi as poetry. The ancient writings of Mesopotamia and Egypt are darkened with our ignorance of how such
languages were pronounced; but with such assurances in transliteration as we can muster, such writings when spoken were also
poetry. In India, the oldest literature is the Veda, which were
dictated by gods to the rishi or prophets; these too were poetry.
Oracles spoke poetry. From time to time, their utterances from
Delphi and elsewhere were written down, and every one of them
that survives as more than a simple phrase is in dactylic hexameter, just as were the epics. The Hebrew prophets also, when
relaying the hallucinated utterance of Yahweh, were often poets,
though their scribes did not in every case preserve such speech in
verse.
As the bicameral mind recedes further into history, and the
oracles reach their fifth term, there are exceptions. Poetic utterance by the oracles breaks down here and there. The oracle at
Delphi, for example, in the first century A.D. evidently spoke in
both verse and prose, the latter to be put into verse by poets in the
service of the temples.1 But the very impulse to transpose oracular prose back into dactylic hexameters is, I suggest, a part of the
nostalgia for the divine in this late period; it demonstrates again
that metered verse had been the rule previously. Even later,
some oracles still spoke exclusively in dactylic hexameters. Tacitus, for example, visited the oracle of Apollo at Claros about A.D.
1 Strabo,
Geography, 9.3.5, or as translated by H. L. Jones in the Loeb edition,
p. 353. This observation was made about A.D. 30. Plutarch's offhand suggestion in
the second century a.d. that the raw prophetic outpouring of the oracle always had to
be versified by inspired prophetes is contrary to all the earlier writings and evidence
from the oracles themselves. See his The Oracles of Delphi in Vol. 5 of The Moralia,
Loeb edition. I am not sure how seriously we should take Plutarch's rambling
after-dinner conversation piece.
OF
POETRY
AND
MUSIC
363
100 and described how the entranced priest listened to his decision-seeking petitioners; he then
. . . swallows a draught of water from a mysterious spring
and — though ignorant generally of writing and of meters —
delivers his response in set verses.2
Poetry then was divine knowledge. And after the breakdown
of the bicameral mind, poetry was the sound and tenor of authorization. Poetry commanded where prose could only ask. It felt
good. In the wanderings of the Hebrews after the exodus from
Egypt, it was the sacred shrine that was carried before the multitude and followed by the people, but it was the poetry of Moses
that determined when they would start and when stop, where
they would go and where stay.3
The association of rhythmical or repetitively patterned utterance with supernatural knowledge endures well into the later
conscious period. Among the early Arabic peoples the word for
poet was sha’ir, ‘the knower’, or a person endowed with knowledge by the spirits; his metered speech in recitation was the mark
of its divine origin. The poet and divine seer have a long tradition
of association in the ancient world, and several Indo-European
languages have a common term for them. Rhyme and alliteration too were always the linguistic province of the gods and their
prophets.4 In at least some instances of spontaneous possession,
the demonic utterances are in meter.5 Even glossolalia today, as
2 Tacitus, Annals, 2:54, or as translated by John Jackson in the Loeb edition,
p. 471.
3 Numbers 10:35, 36. My authority that these lines in Hebrew come under the
rubric of poetry is Alfred Guillaume, Prophecy and Divination among the Hebrew
and Other Semites (New York: Harper, 1938), p. 244.
4 Guillaume, p. 245.
5 A possessed woman in China at the beginning of this century, for example, would
extemporize verses by the hour. "Everything she said was in measure verse, and was
chanted to an unvarying tune . . . the rapid, perfectly uniform, and long continued
utterances seemed to us such as could not possibly be counterfeited or premeditated."
J. L. Nevius, Demon Possession and Allied Themes, p. 3 7f.
364
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
we have seen in III.2, wherever it is practiced, tends to fall into
metrical patterns, particularly dactyls.
Poetry then was the language of gods.
Poetry and Song
A l l the above discussion is mere literary tradition and sounds
more plea than proof. We should, therefore, ask if there is
another way of approaching the matter to show the relationship
of poetry to the bicameral mind more scientifically. There is, I
think, if we look at the relation of poetry to music.
First of all, early poetry was song. The difference between
song and speech is a matter of discontinuities of pitch. In ordinary speech, we are constantly changing pitch, even in the pronunciation of a single syllable. But in song, the change of pitch is
discrete and discontinuous. Speech reels around all over a certain portion of an octave (in relaxed speech about a fifth). Song
steps from note to note on strict and delimited feet over a more
extended range.
Modern poetry is a hybrid. It has the metrical feet of song with
the pitch glissandos of speech. But ancient poetry is much closer
to song. Accents were not by intensity stress as in our ordinary
speech, but by pitch.6 In ancient Greece, this pitch is thought to
have been precisely the interval of a fifth above the ground note of
the poem, so that on the notes of our scale, dactyls would go G C C ,
G C C , with no extra emphasis on the G. Moreover, the three extra
accents, acute, circumflex, and grave, were, as their notations
´,ˆ,` imply, a rising pitch within the syllable, a rising and falling
on the same syllable, and a falling pitch respectively. The result
was a poetry sung like plainsong with various auditory ornamentation that gave it beautiful variety.
6 It was Thomas Day, whose new and syntactically vigorous translation of the
Iliad is eagerly awaited, who first recited or rather sang epic Greek to me as it should
be done. For the theory here, see W. B. Stanford, The Sound of Greek (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1967), and play the record inserted in the back cover.
OF
POETRY
AND
MUSIC
365
Now how does all this relate to the bicameral mind? Speech, as
has long been known, is a function primarily of the left cerebral
hemisphere. But song, as we are presently discovering, is primarily a function of the right cerebral hemisphere. The evidence
is various but consistent:
• It is common medical knowledge that many elderly patients
who have suffered cerebral hemorrhages on the left hemisphere
such that they cannot speak can still sing.
• The so-called Wada Test is sometimes performed in hospitals to find out a person’s cerebral dominance. Sodium amytal is
injected into the carotid artery on one side, putting the corresponding hemisphere under heavy sedation but leaving the other
awake and alert. When the injection is made on the left side so
that the left hemisphere is sedated and only the right hemisphere
is active, the person is unable to speak, but can still sing. When
the injection is on the right so that only the left hemisphere is
active, the person can speak but cannot sing.7
• Patients in whom the entire left hemisphere has been removed because of glioma can only manage a few words, if any,
postoperatively. But at least some can sing.8 One such patient
with only a speechless right hemisphere to his name “was able to
sing ‘America’ and ‘Home on the Range,’ rarely missing a word
and with nearly perfect enunciation.”9
• Electrical stimulation on the right hemisphere in regions
adjacent to the posterior temporal lobe, particularly the anterior
temporal lobe, often produces hallucinations of singing and music.
I have already described some of these patients in 1.5. And this
in general is the area, corresponding to Wernicke’s area on the
7 H. W. Gordon and J. E. Bogen, “Hemispheric Lateralization of Singing after
Intracarotid Sodium Ammo-barbitol,” Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery and
Psychiatry, 1974, 37: 727-739.
8 H. W. Gordon, “Auditory Specialization of Right and Left Hemispheres,” in
M. Kinsbourne and W. Lynn Smith, eds. Hemispheric Disconnections and Cerebral
Function (Springfield: Thomas, 1974), pp. 126-136.
9 Charles W. Burklund, “Cerebral Hemisphere Function in the Human,” in
W. L. Smith ed., Drug, Development and Cerebral Function (Springfield: Thomas,
1972), p. 22.
366
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
left hemisphere, which I have hypothesized was where the auditory hallucinations of the bicameral mind were organized.
Singing and melody then are primarily right hemisphere activities. And since poetry in antiquity was sung rather than spoken,
it was perhaps largely a right hemisphere function, as the theory
of the bicameral mind in I.5 would predict. More specifically,
ancient poetry involved the posterior part of the right temporal
lobe, which I have suggested was responsible for organizing
divine hallucinations, together with adjacent areas which even
today are involved in music.
For those who are still skeptical, I have devised an experiment
where they may even feel for themselves right now the truth of
these matters. First, think of two topics, anything, personal or
general, on which you would like to talk for a couple of paragraphs. Now, imagining you are with a friend, speak out loud on
one of the topics. Next, imagining you are with a friend, sing out
loud on the other topic. Do each for one full minute, demanding
of yourself that you keep going. Compare introspectively. Why
is the second so much more difficult? Why does the singing
crumble into cliches? Or the melody erode into recitative? Why
does the topic desert you in midmelody? What is the nature of
your efforts to get your song back on the topic? Or rather — and
I think this is more the feeling — to get your topic back to the
song?
The answer is that your topic is ‘in’ Wernicke’s area on your left
hemisphere, while your song is ‘in’ what corresponds to Wernicke’s area on your right hemisphere. Let me hasten to add that
such a statement is an approximation neurologically. And by
‘topic’ and ‘song’ I am meaning their neural substrates. But such
an approximation is true enough to make my point. It is as if
volitional speech is jealous of the right hemisphere and wants
you to itself, just as your song is jealous of the left hemisphere
and wants you to leave your left hemisphere topic behind. To
OF
POETRY
AND
MUSIC
367
accomplish the improvised singing of a pre-decided topic feels as
if we were jumping back and forth between hemispheres. And so
in a sense 'we' are, deciding on the words in the left and then
trying to get back to song with them on the right before some
other words have got there first. And usually the latter happens,
the words are not on the topic, careering off on their own, or not
consecutively coherent or not there at all, and so we stop singing.
Of course we can learn to sing our verbal thoughts to a certain
extent and musicians often do. And women, since they are less
lateralized, may find it easier. If you practice it as an exercise
twice a day for a month or a year or a lifetime, sincerely avoiding
cliche and memorized material on the lyric side, and mere recitative on the melody side, I expect you will be more proficient at it.
If you are ten years old, such learning will probably be much
easier and might even make a poet out of you. And if you should
be unlucky enough to have some left hemisphere accident at
some future time, your thought-singing might come in handy.
What is learned here is very probably a new relationship between the hemispheres, not entirely different from some of the
learned phenomena in the previous chapter.
The Nature of Music
I wish to expand a little upon the role of instrumental music in
all this. For we also hear and appreciate music with our right
hemispheres.
Such lateralization of music can be seen even in very young
infants. Six-month-old babies can be given EEG's while being
held in the laps of their mothers. If the recording electrodes are
placed directly over Wernicke's area on the left hemisphere and
over what corresponds to Wernicke's area on the right, then
when tape recordings of speech are played, the left hemisphere
will show the greatest activity. But when a tape of a music box is
played or of someone singing, the activity will be greater over the
368
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
right hemisphere. In the experiment I am describing, not only
did the children who were fidgeting or crying stop doing so at the
sound of music, but also they smiled and looked straight ahead,
turning away from the mother’s gaze,10 even acting as we do when
we are trying to avoid distraction. This finding has an immense
significance for the possibility that the brain is organized at birth
to ‘obey’ stimulation in what corresponds to Wernicke's area on
the right hemisphere, namely the music, and not be distracted
from it, even as earlier I have said that bicameral men neurologically had to obey hallucinations from the same area. It also
points to the great significance of lullabies in development, perhaps influencing a child's later creativity.
Or you can prove this laterality of music yourself. Try hearing
different musics on two earphones at the same intensity. You
will perceive and remember the music on the left earphone better.11 This is because the left ear has greater neural representation on the right hemisphere. The specific location here is
probably the right anterior temporal lobe, for patients in which it
has been removed from the right hemisphere find it very difficult
to distinguish one melody from another. And, conversely, with
left temporal lobectomies, patients postoperatively have no
trouble with such tests.12
10 This is the interesting recent work of Martin Gardiner of the Boston Children's
Hospital, personal communication. It is to be published as "EEG Indicators of
Lateralization in Human Infants" in S. Hamad, R. Doty, L. Goldstein, J. Jaynes,
and G. Krauthammer, eds., Lateralization in the Nervous System (New York: Academic Press, 1976).
11 The experiment was done with Vivaldi concertos by Doreen Kimura, “Functional Asymmetry of the Brain in Dichotic Listening,” Cortex, 1967, 3: 163—178.
But there is evidence that this is not true of musicians whose training has resulted
in music’s being represented on both hemispheres. This was first discovered by R. C.
Oldfield, “Handedness and the Nature of Dominance,” Talk at Educational Testing
Service, Princeton, September 1969. See also Thomas G. Bever and R. J. Chiarello,
"Cerebral Dominance in Musicians and Non-Musicians," Science (1974), Vol. 185,
pp. 137-139.
12 D. Shankweiler, “Effects of Temporal-Lobe Damage on Perception of Dichotically Presented Melodies,” Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology,
1966, 62 : 115—119.
OF
POETRY
AND
MUSIC
369
Now we know neurologically that there can be a spread of
excitation from one point of the cortex to adjacent points. Thus it
becomes likely that a buildup of excitation in those areas on the
right hemisphere serving instrumental music should spread to
those adjacent serving divine auditory hallucinations — or vice
versa. And hence this close relationship between instrumental
music and poetry, and both with the voices of gods. I am suggesting here that the invention of music may have been as a neural
excitant to the hallucinations of gods for decision-making in the
absence of consciousness.
It is thus no idle happenstance of history that the very name of
music comes from the sacred goddesses called Muses. For music
too begins in the bicameral mind.
We thus have some ground for saying that the use of the lyre
among early poets was to spread excitation to the divine speech
area, the posterior part of the right temporal lobe, from immediately adjacent areas. So also the function of flutes that accompanied the lyric and elegiac poets of the eighth and seventh
centuries B.C. And when such musical accompaniment is no
longer used, as it is not in later Greek poetry, it is, I suggest,
because the poem is no longer being sung from the right hemisphere where such spreading excitation would help. It is instead
being recited from left hemispheric memory alone, rather than
being recreated in the true prophetic trance.
This change in musical accompaniment is also reflected in the
way poetry is referred to, although a large amount of historical
overlap makes the case not quite so clear. But more early poetry
is referred to as song (as in the Iliad and the Theogony, for
example), while later poetry is often referred to as spoken or
told. This change perhaps corresponds roughly to the change
from the aoidoi with their lyres to the rhapsodes with their
rhapdoi (light sticks, perhaps to beat the meter) that took place
perhaps in the eighth or seventh centuries B.C. And behind these
370
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
particulars is the more profound psychological change from bicameral composition to conscious recitation, and from oral to
written remembering. In much later poetry, however, the poet as
singer and his poem as song are brought back metaphorically as a
conscious archaism, yielding its own authorization to the now
conscious poet.13
Poesy and Possession
A third way to examine this transformation of poetry during
the rise and spread of consciousness is to look at the poet himself
and his mentality. Specifically, were the relations of poets to the
Muses the same as the relationship of the oracles to the greater
gods?
For Plato at least, the matter was quite clear. Poetry was a
divine madness. It was katokoche or possession by the Muses;
. . . all good poets, epic as well as lyric, composed their beautiful poems not by art, but because they are inspired and
possessed . . . there is no invention in him until he has been
inspired and is out of his senses and the mind is no longer in
him. 1 4
Poets then, around 400 B.C., were comparable in mentality to the
oracles of the same period, and went through similar psychological transformation when they performed.
Now we might be tempted to think with Plato that such possession characterized poetry all the way back into the epic tradition.
But the evidence does not warrant such a generalization. In the
Iliad itself, so many centuries before the existence of katokoche is
ever mentioned or observed, a good argument could be made that
the primitive aoidos was not "out of his senses and the mind no
13 On this matter see T. B. L. Webster, From Mycenae to Homer (London:
Methuen, 1958), p. 271f.
14 Plato, Io. 534.
OF
POETRY
AND
MUSIC
371
longer in him.” For in several places, the poem breaks off as the
poet gets stuck and has to beg the Muses to go on (2:483,
11:218,14:508,16:112).
Let it be stressed parenthetically here that the Muses were not
figments of anyone’s imagination. I would ask the reader to
peruse the first pages of Hesiod’s Theogony and realize that all of
it was probably seen and heard in hallucination, just as can
happen today in schizophrenia or under certain drugs. Bicameral
men did not imagine; they experienced. The beautiful Muses
with their unison “lily-like” voice, dancing out of the thick mists
of evening, thumping on soft and vigorous feet about the lonely
enraptured shepherd, these arrogances of delicacy were the hallucinatory sources of memory in late bicameral men, men who
did not live in a frame of past happenings, who did not have
‘lifetimes’ in our sense, and who could not reminisce because they
were not fully conscious. Indeed, this is put into mythology by
their chosen medium, the shepherd of Helicon himself: the
Muses who, he tells us, always sing together with the same
phrenes15 and in “unwearying flows” of song, this special group
of divinities who, instead of telling men what to do, specialized in
telling certain men what had been done, are the daughters of
Mnemosyne, the Titaness whose name later comes to mean
memory — the first word with that meaning in the world.
Such appeals to the Muses then are identical in function with
our appeals to memory, like tip-of-the-tongue struggles with
recollection. They do not sound like a man out of his senses who
doesn’t know what he is doing. In one instance in the Iliad, the
poet begins to have difficulty and so begs the Muses,
Say now to me, Muses, having Olympian homes, for you are
goddesses, and are present and know all; but we hear report
15 The Greek
for singing together is homophronas, in Hesiod, Theogony, line 60.
I know of no records of contemporary hallucinations that sound like a group of
people in unison. Just why the Muses are plural is an interesting problem. See II. 4,
note 2.
372
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
alone, neither do we know anything: tell me who were the
leaders and rulers of the Greeks? ( 2 : 4 8 3 - 4 8 7 )
and then goes on to plead in his own person that he, the poet,
cannot name them, though he had "ten tongues and ten mouths
and an unbreakable voice," unless the Muses start singing the
material to him. I have italicized a phrase in the quotation to
underline their actuality to the poet.
Nor does possession seem to be occurring in Hesiod in his first
meeting with them on the holy flanks of Mount Helicon while he
was keeping watch over his sheep. He describes how the Muses
. . . breathed into me a divine voice to celebrate things that
shall be and things that were aforetime; and they begged me
sing of the race of the blessed gods that are eternally, but ever to
sing of themselves both first and last. 16
Again, I think this should be believed literally as someone’s experience in exactly the same way that we believe in the experience of Hesiod's contemporary, Amos, in his meeting with
Yahweh in the meadows of Tekoa while he too was keeping
watch over his flock.17 Nor does it seem possession when the
Muses’ Theogony stops (line 104) and Hesiod cries out again in
his own voice, praising the Muses and pleading with them again
to go on with the poem: “Tell me these things from the beginning, you Muses,” having just given a long list of the topics which
the poet wants the poem to be about (line 114).
Nor does the stately and careful description of Demodocus in
the Odyssey permit an interpretation of the poet as possessed.
Evidently Demodocus, if he was real, may have gone through
16 Hesiod, Theogony, translated by H. G. Evelyn-White, Loeb Classical Library.
Another reason for thinking that this Hesiod is not the author of Works and Days,
as I suggested in II.5, is the last phrase above. Certainly the work I have ascribed
to Perses is not true to this promise to sing only about the gods "both first and last."
17 Amos, too, was not in a state of possession since he too had dialogue with his
god. See Amos 7: 5-8; 8: 1-2. In some of my phrasing I am trying to remind the
reader of Luke 2: 8-14.
OF
POETRY
AND
MUSIC
373
some kind of cerebral accident which left him blind, but with the
power to hear the Muses sing such enchanting poetry as could
make an Odysseus drape his head and moan with tears (8:6392). Indeed Odysseus himself understands that Demodocus of
the disabled vision, who could not have witnessed the Trojan
War, could sing about it only because the Muse, or Apollo, was
actually telling it to him. His chant was hormetheis theou, constantly given by the god himself (81499).
The evidence, therefore, suggests that up to the eighth and
probably the seventh century B.C., the poet was not out of his
mind as he was later in Plato’s day. Rather, his creativity was
perhaps much closer to what we have come to call bicameral.
The fact that such poets were “wretched things of shame, mere
bellies,” as the Muses scornfully mocked their human adoring
mediums,18 unskilled roughs who came from the more primitive
and lonely levels of the social structure, such as shepherds, is in
accord with such a suggestion. Mere bellies out in the fields had
less opportunity to be changed by the new mentality. And loneliness can lead to hallucination.
But by the time of Solon in the sixth century B.C., something
different is happening. The poet is no longer simply given his
gifts j he has to have “learning in the gift of the Muses” (Fragment 13:51). And then, in the fifth century B.C., we hear the
very first hint of poets’ being peculiar with poetic ecstasy. What a
contrast to the calm and stately manner of the earlier aoidoi,
Demodocus, for example! It is Democritus who insists that no
one can be a great poet without being frenzied up into a state of
fury (Fragment 18). And then in the fourth century B.C., the
mad possessed poet “out of his senses” that Plato and I have
already described. Just as the oracles had changed from the
prophet who heard his hallucinations to the possessed person in a
wild trance, so also had the poet.
Was this dramatic change because the collective cognitive im18 Hesiod,
Theogony, 1. 26.
374 Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
perative had made the Muses less believable as real external
entities? Or was it because the neurological reorganization of
hemispheric relations brought on by developing consciousness
prohibited such givenness; so that consciousness had to be out of
the way to let poetry happen? Or was it Wernicke's area on the
right hemisphere using Broca's area on the left, thus shortcircuiting (as it were) normal consciousness? Or are these three
hypotheses the same (as of course I presently think they are) ?
For whatever reasons, decline continues decline in the ensuing
centuries. Just as the oracles sputtered out through their latter
terms until possession was partial and erratic, so, I suggest, poets
slowly changed until the fury and possession by the Muses was
also partial and erratic. And then the Muses hush and freeze into
myths. Nymphs and shepherds, dance no more. Consciousness is a
witch beneath whose charms pure inspiration gasps and dies into
invention. The oral becomes written by the poet himself, and
written, it should be added, by his right hand, worked by his left
hemisphere. The Muses have become imaginary and invoked in
their silence as a part of man's nostalgia for the bicameral mind.
In summary, then, the theory of poetry I am trying to state in
this scraggly collation of passages is similar to the theory I presented for oracles. Poetry begins as the divine speech of the
bicameral mind. Then, as the bicameral mind breaks down,
there remain prophets. Some become institutionalized as oracles
making decisions for the future. While others become specialized
into poets, relating from the gods statements about the past.
Then, as the bicameral mind shrinks back from its impulsiveness, and as perhaps a certain reticence falls upon the right
hemisphere, poets who are to obtain this same state must learn to
do it. As this becomes more difficult, the state becomes a fury,
and then ecstatic possession, just as happened in the oracles.
And then indeed toward the end of the first millennium B.C., just
as the oracles began to become prosaic and their statements
OF
POETRY
AND
MUSIC
375
versified consciously, so poetry also. Its givenness by the unison
Muses has vanished. And conscious men now wrote and crossed
out and careted and rewrote their compositions in laborious
mimesis of the older divine utterances.
Why as the gods retreated even further into their silent
heavens or, in another linguistic mode, as auditory hallucinations
shrank back from access by left hemisphere monitoring mechanisms, why did not the dialect of the gods simply disappear?
Why did not poets simply cease their rhapsodic practices as did
the priests and priestesses of the great oracles? The answer is
very clear. The continuance of poetry, its change from a divine
given to a human craft is part of that nostalgia for the absolute.
The search for the relationship with the lost otherness of divine
directives would not allow it to lapse. And hence the frequency
even today with which poems are apostrophes to often unbelievedin entities, prayers to unknown imaginings. And hence the opening
paragraph of this treatise. The forms are still there, to be worked
with now by the analog ‘I’ of a conscious poet. His task now is an
imitation or mimesis19 of the former type of poetic utterance and
the reality which it expressed. Mimesis in the bicameral sense of
mimicking what was heard in hallucination has moved through
the mimesis of Plato as representation of reality to mimesis as
imitation with invention in its sullen service.
There have been some latter-day poets who have been very
specific about actual auditory hallucinations. Milton referred to
his "Celestial Patroness, who . . . unimplor'd . . . dictates to
me my unpremeditated Verse," even as he, in his blindness, dictated it to his daughters.20 And Blake's extraordinary visions and
auditory hallucinations — sometimes going on for days and
sometimes against his will — as the source of his painting and
19 On the history of this word, see Eric A. Havelock, Preface to Plato (New York:
Grosset & Dunlap, 1967), p. 57, n. 22, as well as Ch. 2.
20 Paradise Lost, 9: 21-24.
376
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
poetry are well known. And Rilke is said to have feverishly
copied down a long sonnet sequence that he heard in hallucination.
But most of us are more ordinary, more with and of our time.
We no longer hear our poems directly in hallucination. It is
instead the feeling of something being given and then nourished
into being, of the poem happening to the poet, as well and as
much as being created by him. Snatches of lines would “bubble
up” for Housman after a beer and a walk “with sudden and
unaccountable emotions” which then “had to be taken in hand
and completed by the brain.” “The songs made me, not I them,”
said Goethe. “It is not I who think,” said Lamartine, “it is my
ideas that think for me.” And dear Shelley said it plain:
A man cannot say, “I will compose poetry.”
T h e greatest
poet even cannot say it; for the mind in creation is as a fading
coal, which some invisible influence, like an inconstant wind,
awakens to transitory brightness . . . and the conscious portions of our natures are unprophetic either of its approach or
its departure. 21
Is the fading coal the left hemisphere and the inconstant wind
the right, mapping vestigially the ancient relationship of men to
gods?
Of course there is no universal rule in this matter. The nervous systems of poets come like shoes, in all types and sizes,
though with a certain irreducible topology. We know that the
relations of the hemispheres are not the same in everyone. Indeed, poetry can be written without even a nervous system. A
vocabulary, some syntax, and a few rules of lexical fit and measure can be punched into a computer, which can then proceed to
write quite inspired’ if surrealist verse. But that is simply a copy
of what we, with two cerebral hemispheres and nervous systems,
21 Percy Bysshe Shelley, “A Defense of Poetry” in The Portable Romantic Reader,
H. E. Hugo, ed. (New York: Viking Press, 1957), p. 536.
OF
POETRY
AND
MUSIC
377
already do. Computers or men can indeed write poetry without
any vestigial bicameral inspiration. But when they do, they are
imitating an older and a truer poesy out there in history. Poetry,
once started in mankind, needs not the same means for its production. It began as the divine speech of the bicameral mind.
And even today, through its infinite mimeses, great poetry to the
listener, however it is made, still retains that quality of the wholly
other, of a diction and a message, a consolation and an inspiration, that was once our relationship to gods.
A Homily on Thamyris
I would like to end these rather clumsy suggestions on the
biology of poetry with some homiletic sentiments on the true
tragedy of Thamyris. He was a poet in the Iliad (2:594-600)
who boasted he would conquer and control the Muses in his
poetry. Gods, as they die away in the transition to consciousness,
are jealous gods, as I have said earlier. And the Sacred Nine are
no exception. They were enraged at the beautiful ambition of
Thamyris. They crippled him (probably a paralysis on his left
side), and deprived him forever of poetic expression, and made
him forget his ability at harping.
Of course, we do not know if there even was a Thamyris, or
exactly what reality is being pointed at by this story. But I
suggest it was among the later accretions to the Iliad, and that its
insertion may point to the difficulties in hemisphere cooperation
in artistic expression at the breakdown of the bicameral mind.
The parable of Thamyris may be narratizing what is to us the
feeling of losing consciousness in our inspiration and then losing
that inspiration in our consciousness of that loss. Consciousness
imitates the gods and is a jealous consciousness and will have no
other executives of action before it.
I remember when I was younger, at least through my twenties,
while walking in woods or along a beach, or climbing hills or
378
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
almost anything lonely, I would quite often suddenly become
conscious that I was hearing in my head improvised symphonies
of unambiguous beauty. But at the very moment of my becoming
conscious of the fact, not loitering even for a measure! the music
vanished. I would strain to call it back. But there would be
nothing there. Nothing but a deepening silence. Since the music
was undoubtedly being composed in my right hemisphere and
heard somehow as a semi-hallucination, and since my analog ‘I’
with its verbalizations was probably, at that moment at least, a
more left hemispheric function, I suggest that this opposition was
very loosely like what is behind the story of Thamyris. ‘I’ strained
too much. I have no left hemiplegia. But I do not hear my music
anymore. I do not expect ever to hear it again.
The modern poet is in a similar quandary. Once, literary
languages and archaic speech came somehow to his bold assistance in that otherness and grandeur of which true poetry is
meant to speak. But the grinding tides of irreversible naturalism
have swept the Muses even farther out into the night of the right
hemisphere. Yet somehow, even helplessly in our search for
authorization, we remain “the hierophants of an unapprehended
inspiration.” And inspiration flees in attempted apprehension,
until perhaps it was never there at all. We do not believe enough.
The cognitive imperative dissolves. History lays her finger carefully on the lips of the Muses. The bicameral mind, silent. And
since
T h e god approached dissolves into the air,
Imagine then, by miracle, with me,
(Ambiguous gifts, as what gods give must be)
What could not possibly be there,
And learn a style from a despair.
CHAPTER 4
Hypnosis
I
F I ASK YOU to taste vinegar as champagne, to feel pleasure
when I jab a pin in your arm, or to stare into darkness and contract the pupils of your eyes to an imagined light, or to willfully
and really believe something you do not ordinarily believe, just
anything, you would find these tasks difficult if not impossible.
But if I first put you through the induction procedures of hypnosis, you could accomplish all these things at my asking without
any effort whatever.
Why? How can such supererogatory enabling even exist?
It seems a very different company we enter when we go from
the familiarity of poetry to the strangeness of hypnosis. For
hypnosis is the black sheep of the family of problems which
constitute psychology. It wanders in and out of laboratories and
carnivals and clinics and village halls like an unwanted anomaly.
It never seems to straighten up and resolve itself into the firmer
proprieties of scientific theory. Indeed, its very possibility seems
a denial of our immediate ideas about conscious self-control on
the one hand, and our scientific idea about personality on the
other. Yet it should be conspicuous that any theory of consciousness and its origin, if it is to be responsible, must face the difficulty of this deviant type of behavioral control.
I think my answer to the opening question is obvious: hypnosis
can cause this extra enabling because it engages the general
bicameral paradigm which allows a more absolute control over
behavior than is possible with consciousness.
380
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
In this chapter, I shall even go so far as to maintain that no
theory other than the present one makes sense of the basic
problem. For if our contemporary mentality is, as most people
suppose, an immutable genetically determined characteristic
evolved back somewhere in mammalian evolution or before, how
can it be so altered as in hypnosis? And that alteration merely at
some rather ridiculous ministrations of another person? It is
only by rejecting the genetic hypothesis and treating consciousness as a learned cultural ability over the vestigial substrate of an
earlier more authoritarian type of behavioral control that such
alterations of mind can begin to seem orderly.
The central structure of this chapter, obviously, will be to show
how well hypnosis fits the four aspects of the bicameral paradigm. But before I do so, I wish to bring out clearly a most
important feature of how hypnosis began in the first place. This
is what I have emphasized in I.2 and II.5, the generative force of
metaphor in creating new mentality.
The Paraphrands of Newtonian Forces
Hypnosis, like consciousness, begins at a particular point in
history in the paraphrands of a few new metaphors. The first of
these metaphors followed Sir Isaac Newton’s discovery of the
laws of universal gravitation and his use of them to explain the
ocean tides under the attraction of the moon. The mysterious
attractions and influences and controls between people were then
compared to Newtonian gravitational influences. And the comparison resulted in a new (and ridiculous) hypothesis, that there
are tides of attraction between all bodies, living and material, that
can be called animal gravitation, of which Newton’s gravitation is
a special case.1
1 A full history of hypnosis is yet to be written. But see F. A. Pattie, “Brief History of Hypnotism,” in J. E. Gordon, ed., Handbook of Clinical and Experimental
Hypnosis (New York: Macmillan, 1967). See also an historical paper by one of
HYPNOSIS
381
This is all very explicit in the romantic and turbid writings of a
wanton admirer of Newton‘s called Anton Mesmer, who began it
all. And then came another metaphor, or rather two. Gravitational attraction is similar to magnetic attraction. Therefore,
since (in Mesmer‘s rhetorical thought) two things similar to a
third thing are similar to each other, animal gravitation is like
magnetic attraction, and so changes its name to animal magnetism.
Now at last the theory was testable in a scientific way. To
demonstrate the existence of these vibrant magnetic tides in and
through living things similar to celestial gravitation, Mesmer applied magnets to various hysterical patients, even prefeeding the
patients with medicines containing iron so that the magnetism
might work better. And it did! The result could not be doubted
with the knowledge of his day. Convulsive attacks were produced
by the magnets, creating in Mesmer‘s words “an artificial ebb and
flow” in the body and correcting with its magnetic attraction “the
unequal distribution of the nervous fluids confused movement,”
thus producing a “harmony of the nerves.” He had ‘proved’ that
there are flows of forces between persons as mighty as those that
hold the planets in their orbits.
Of course he hadn‘t proved anything about any kind of magnetism whatever. He had discovered what Sir James Braid on the
metaphier of sleep later called hypnosis. The cures were effective because he had explained his exotic theory to his patients
with vigorous conviction. The violent seizures and peculiar twists
of sensations at the application of magnets were all due to a cognitive imperative that these things would happen, which they
did, constituting a kind of self-perpetuating escalating ‘proof’ that
the magnets were working and could effect a cure. We should
remember here that just as in ancient Assyria there was no
concept of chance and so the casting of lots ‘had’ to be controlled
the important experimenters in hypnosis, Theodore Sarbin‘s “Attempts to Understand Hypnotic Phenomena,” in Leo Postman, ed., Psychology in the Making (New
York: Knopf, 1964), pp. 745-784.
382
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
by the gods, so in the eighteenth century there was no concept of
suggestion and the result had to be due to the magnets.
Then when it was found that not only magnets, but cups,
bread, wood, human beings, and animals to which a magnet had
been touched were also efficacious (how false beliefs breed upon
each other!), the whole matter jumped over into another metaphor (this is the fourth), that of static electricity, which — Benjamin Franklin's kite and all — was being so much studied at the
time. Thus Mesmer thought there was a "magnetic material"
that could be transferred to a countless array of objects, just as
static electricity can. Human beings in particular could store up
and absorb magnetism, particularly Mesmer himself. Just as a
carbon rod stroked with fur produces static electricity, so patients
were to be stroked by Mesmer. He could now dispense with
actual magnets and use his own animal magnetism. By stroking
or making passes over the bodies of his patients, as if they were
carbon rods, he produced the same results: convulsions, coiling
twists of peculiar sensations, and the cure of what later were
called hysterical illnesses.
Now it is critical here to realize and to understand what we
might call the paraphrandic changes which were going on in the
people involved, due to these metaphors. A paraphrand, you will
remember, is the projection into a metaphrand of the associations
or paraphiers of a metaphier. The metaphrand here is the influences between people. The metaphiers, or what these influences
are being compared to, are the inexorable forces of gravitation,
magnetism, and electricity. And their paraphiers of absolute
compulsions between heavenly bodies, of unstoppable currents
from masses of Ley den jars, or of irresistible oceanic tides of
magnetism, all these projected back into the metaphrand of
interpersonal relationships, actually changing them, changing
the psychological nature of the persons involved, immersing
them in a sea of uncontrollable control that emanated from the
HYPNOSIS
383
'magnetic fluids’ in the doctor's body, or in objects which had
'absorbed' such from him.
It is at least conceivable that what Mesmer was discovering
was a different kind of mentality that, given a proper locale, a
special education in childhood, a surrounding belief system, and
isolation from the rest of us, possibly could have sustained itself
as a society not based on ordinary consciousness, where metaphors of energy and irresistible control would assume some of the
functions of consciousness.
How is this even possible? As I have mentioned already, I
think Mesmer was clumsily stumbling into a new way of engaging
that neurological patterning I have called the general bicameral
paradigm with its four aspects: collective cognitive imperative,
induction, trance, and archaic authorization. I shall take up each
in turn.
The Changing Nature of Hypnotic Man
That the phenomenon of hypnosis is under the control of a
collective cognitive imperative or group belief system is clearly
demonstrated by its continual changing in history. As beliefs
about hypnosis changed, so also its very nature. A few decades
after Mesmer, subjects no longer twisted with strange sensations
and convulsions. Instead they began spontaneously to speak and
reply to questions during their trance state. Nothing like this had
happened before. Then, early in the nineteenth century, patients
spontaneously began to forget what had happened during the
trance,2 something never reported previously. Around 1825, for
some unknown reason, persons under hypnosis started to spontaneously diagnose their own illnesses. In the middle of the
century, phrenology, the mistaken idea that conformations of the
skull indicate mental faculties, became so popular that it actually
2 As revealed in the important writings of A.-M.-J. Chastenet, Marquis de
Puyseg-ur, "Memoires four Servir a L’Histoire et a L’Establissement du Magnetism
Animate>" 2nd ed. (Paris, 1809).
384
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
engulfed hypnosis for a time. Pressure on the scalp over a phrenological area during hypnosis caused the subject to express the
faculty controlled by that area (yes, this actually happened), a
phenomenon never seen before or since. When the scalp area
over the part of the brain supposedly responsible for "veneration"
was pressed, the hypnotized subject sunk to his knees in prayer! 3
This was so because it was believed to be so.
A little later, Charcot, the greatest psychiatrist of his time,
demonstrated to large professional audiences at the Salpetriere
that hypnosis was again quite different! Now it had three successive stages: catalepsy, lethargy, and somnambulism. These
"physical states" could be changed from one to another by
manipulating muscles, or various pressures, or friction on the top
of the head. Even rubbing the head over Broca's area produced
aphasia! And then Binet, arriving at the Salpetriere to check on
the findings of Charcot, promptly compounded the problem by
returning to Mesmer's magnets and discovering even more bizarre behavior.4 Placing magnets on one side or the other of the
body of a hypnotized person, he could flip-flop perceptions, hysterical paralyses, supposed hallucinations, and movements from
one side to the other, as if such phenomena were so many iron
filings. None of these absurd results was ever found before or
since.
It is not simply that the operator, Mesmer or Charcot or whoever, was suggesting to the pliant patient what the operator
believed hypnosis to be. Rather, there had been developed within
3 These
demonstrations by Sir James Braid, otherwise the first cautions student of
the subject, later embarrassed him. He never referred to such results after 1845 -— and
probably never understood them. A detailed account of Braid's pivotal position in
the history of hypnosis may be found in J. M. Bramwell, Hypnotism: Its History,
Practice, and Theory (London: 19035 New York: Julian Press, 1956).
4 See Alfred Binet and C. Fere, Le Magnetisme Animate (Paris: Alcan, 1897).
This self-deluding work and the dispute with Delboeuf and the more correct Nancy
School that followed, as well as Binet's later acknowledgment of his foolish error,
are described in Theta Wolf's excellent biography Alfred Binet (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1973), pp. 40-78.
HYPNOSIS
385
the group in which he worked a cognitive imperative as to what
the phenomenon was 'known' to be. Such historical changes then
clearly show that hypnosis is not a stable response to given
stimuli, but changes as do the expectations and preconceptions of
a particular age.
What is obvious in history can be shown in a more experimentally controlled way. Previously unheard-of manifestations
of hypnosis can be found by simply informing subjects beforehand that such manifestations are expected in hypnosis, that is,
are a part of the collective cognitive imperative about the matter.
For example, an introductory psychology class was casually told
that under hypnosis a subject's dominant hand cannot be moved.
This had never occurred in hypnosis in any era. It was a lie.
Nevertheless, when members of the class at a later time were
hypnotized, the majority, without any coaching or further suggestion, were unable to move their dominant hand. Out of such
studies has come the notion of the "demand characteristics" of
the hypnotic situation, that the hypnotized subject exhibits the
phenomena which he thinks the hypnotist expects.5 But that
expresses it too personally. It is rather what he thinks hypnosis
is. And such "demand characteristics," taken in this way, are of
precisely the same nature as what I am calling the collective
cognitive imperative.
Another way of seeing the force of the collective imperative is
to note its strengthening by crowds. Just as religious feeling and
belief is enhanced by crowds in churches, or in oracles by the
throngs that attended them, so hypnosis in theaters. It is well
known that stage hypnotists with an audience packed to the
5 This is one of the important ideas in the history of hypnosis research. See the
papers of Martin Orne, particularly, "Nature of Hypnosis: Artifact and Essence,"
Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 1959, 58: 277-299; in this connection
David Rosenhan's important and sobering, "On the Social Psychology of Hypnosis
Research" in J. E. Gordon, ed., Handbook of Clinical and Experimental Psychology.
386
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
rafters, reinforcing the collective imperative or expectancy of
hypnosis, can produce far more exotic hypnotic phenomena than are
found in the isolation of laboratory or clinic.
The Induction
Secondly, the place of an induction procedure in hypnosis is
obvious.6 And needs little comment. The variety of techniques
in contemporary practice is enormous, but they all share the
same narrowing of consciousness, similar to the induction procedures for oracles, or the relationship between a pelestike and a
katochos which we looked at in the previous chapters. The subject may be seated or standing or lying down, may be stroked or
not, stared at or not, asked to look at a small light or flame or
gem, or perhaps a thumbtack on the wall, or at the thumbnail of
his own clasped hands, or not — there are hundreds of variations. But always the operator is trying to confine the subject';
attention to his own voice. " A l l you hear is my voice and you are
getting sleepier and sleepier, etc." is a common pattern, repeated
until the subject, if hypnotized, is unable to open his clasped
hands if the operator says he can't, for example, or cannot move
his relaxed arm if the operator so suggests, or cannot remember
his name if that is suggested. Such simple suggestions are often
used as indications of the success of the hypnosis in its beginning
stages.
If the subject is not able to narrow his consciousness in this
fashion, if he cannot forget the situation as a whole, if he remains in a state of consciousness of other considerations, such as
the room and his relationship to the operator, if he is still narra6 The best discussion of induction procedures is that of Perry London, "Hie Induction of Hypnosis," in J. E. Gordon, pp. 44-79. And for discussions of hypnosis
in general that I have found helpful, see the papers of Ronald Shor, particularly his
"Hypnosis and the Concept of the Generalized Reality-Orientation," American Journal of Psychotherapy, 1959, 13: 582-602, and "Three Dimensions of Hypnotic
Depth," International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, 1962, 10:
23-38.
HYPNOSIS
387
tizing with his analog ‘I’ or 'seeing' his metaphor 'me' being hypnotized, hypnosis will be unsuccessful. But repeated attempts
with such subjects often succeed, showing that the "narrowing"
of consciousness in hypnotic induction is partly a learned ability,
learned, I should add, on the basis of the aptic structure I have
called the general bicameral paradigm. As we saw earlier that
the ease with which a katochos can enter an hallucinatory trance
improves with practice, so also in hypnosis: even in the most
susceptible, the length of the induction and its substances can be
radically reduced with repeated sessions.
Trance and Paralogic Compliance
Thirdly, the hypnotic trance is called just that. It is of course
usually different from the kind of trance that goes on in other
vestiges of the bicameral mind. Individuals do not have true
auditory hallucinations, as in the trances of oracles or mediums.
That place in the paradigm is taken over by the operator. But
there is the same diminution and then absence of normal consciousness. Narratization is severely restricted. The analog 'P is
more or less effaced. The hypnotized subject is not living in a
subjective world. He does not introspect as we do, does not know
he is hypnotized, and is not constantly monitoring himself as, in
an unhypnotized state, he does.
In recent times, the metaphor of submersion in water is almost invariably used to talk about the trance. Thus there are
references to "going under" and to "deep" or "shallow" trances.
The hypnotist often tells a subject he is going "deeper and
deeper." It is indeed possible that without the submersion metaphier, the whole phenomenon would be different, particularly in
regard to post-hypnotic amnesia. The paraphiers of above and
below the surface of water, with its different visual and tactual
fields, could be creating a kind of two-world-ness resulting in
something similar to state-dependent memory. And the sudden
388
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
appearance of spontaneous post-hypnotic amnesia in the early
nineteenth century may be due to this change from gravitational
to submersion metaphors. In other words, spontaneous posthypnotic amnesia may have been a paraphrand of the submersion metaphor. (It is interesting to note that such spontaneous
amnesia is presently disappearing from hypnotic phenomena.
Possibly, hypnosis has become so familiar as to become a thing
in itself, its metaphorical basis wearing away with use, reducing
the power of its paraphrands.)
It is in the "deeper" stages of the trance that the most interesting phenomena can be elicited. These are extremely important
for any theory of mind to explain. Unless otherwise suggested,
the subject is 'deaf' to all but the operator's voice; he does not
'hear' other people. Pain can be 'blocked' off, or enhanced above
normal. So can sensory experience. Emotions can be totally
structured by suggestion: told he is about to hear a funny joke,
the subject will laugh uproariously at "grass is green." The subject can somehow control certain automatic responses better than
in the normal state at the suggestion of the operator. His sense
of identity can be radically changed. He can be made to act as if
he were an animal, or an old man, or a child.
But it is an as-if with a suppression of an it-isn't. Some extremists in hypnosis have sometimes claimed that when a subject in a
trance is told he is now only five or six years old, that an actual
regression to that age of childhood occurs. This is clearly untrue.
Let me cite one example. The subject had been born in Germany, and emigrated with his family to an English-speaking
country at about age eight, at which time he learned English,
forgetting most of his German. When the operator suggested to
him under 'deep' hypnosis that he was only six years old, he
displayed all kinds of childish mannerisms, even writing in childish print on a blackboard. Asked in English if he understood
English, he childishly explained in English that he could not
understand or speak English but only German! He even printed
HYPNOSIS
389
on the blackboard in English that he could not understand a word
of English! 7 The phenomenon is thus like play acting, not a true
regression. It is an uncritical and illogical obedience to the operator and his expectations that is similar to the obedience of a
bicameral man to a god.
Another common error made about hypnosis, even in the best
modern textbooks, is to suppose that the operator can induce true
hallucinations. Some unpublished observations of my own bear
to the contrary. After a subject was in deep hypnosis, I went
through the motions of giving him a nonexistent vase and asked
him to place nonexistent flowers from a table into the vase, saying
out loud the color of each one. This was easily done. It was playacting. But giving him a nonexistent book, and asking him to
hold it in his hands, to turn to page one and begin reading was a
different matter. It could not be play-acted without more creativity than most of us can muster. The subject would readily go
through the suggested motions of holding such a book, might
stumble through some cliche first phrase or possibly a sentence,
but then would complain that the print was blurry, or too difficult
to read, or some similar rationalization. Or when asked to describe a picture (nonexistent) on a blank piece of paper, the
subject would reply in a halting way if at all, giving only short
answers when prodded by questions as to what he saw. If this
had been a true hallucination, his eyes would have roamed over
the paper and a full description would have been a simple matter — as it is when schizophrenics describe their visual hallucinations. There were great individual differences here, as might be
expected, but the behavior is much more consistent with an as-if
hesitant role-taking than with the effortless givenness with which
true hallucinations are experienced.
This point is brought out by another experiment. If a hypnotized person is told to walk across the room, and a chair has been
placed in his path, and he is told that there is no chair there, he
7 I am grateful to Martin Orne for this example.
390
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
does not hallucinate the chair out of existence. He simply walks
around it. He behaves as if he did not notice it — which of
course he did, since he walked around it. It is interesting here
that if unhypnotized subjects are asked to simulate hypnosis in
this particular situation, they promptly crash into the chair,8
since they are trying to be consistent with the erroneous view that
hypnosis actually changes perceptions.
Hence the important concept of trance logic which has been
brought forward to denote this difference.9 This is simply the
bland response to absurd logical contradictions. But it is not any
kind of logic really, nor simply a trance phenomenon. It is rather
what I would prefer to dress up as paralogical compliance to
verbally mediated reality. It is paralogic because the rules of
logic (which we remember are an external standard of truth, not
the way the mind works) are put aside to comply with assertions
about reality that are not concretely true. It is a type of behavior
found everywhere in the human condition from contemporary
religious litanies to various superstitions of tribal societies. But
it is particularly pronounced in and centrally characteristic of the
mental state of hypnosis.
It is paralogic compliance that a subject walks around a chair
he has been told is not there, rather than crashing into it (logical
compliance), and finds nothing illogical in his actions. It is paralogical compliance when a subject says in English that he knows
no English and finds nothing amiss in saying so. If our German
subject had been simulating hypnosis, he would have shown
logical compliance by talking only in what German he could
remember or being mute.
It is paralogic compliance when a subject can accept that the
same person is in two locations at the same time. If a hypnotized
subject is told that person X is person Y, he will behave accord8 The basic work in comparing hypnotized subjects with control subjects asked to
simulate the hypnotic state has been done by Martin Orne. This ingeniously simple
example is due to him.
9 Martin Orne, "The Nature of Hypnosis: Artifact and Essence."
HYPNOSIS
391
ingly. Then if the real person Y walks into the room, the subject
finds it perfectly acceptable that both are person Y. This is
similar to the paralogic compliance found today in another vestige of the bicameral mind, schizophrenia. Two patients in a
ward may both believe themselves to be the same important or
divine person without any feelings of illogicality.10 I suggest
that a similar paralogic compliance was also evident in the bicameral era itself, as in treating unmoving idols as living and
eating, or the same god as being in several places at one time, or
in the multiples of jewel-eyed effigies of the same god-king found
side-by-side in the pyramids. Like a bicameral man, the hypnotized subject does not recognize any peculiarities and inconsistencies in his behavior. He cannot ‘see’ contradictions because he
cannot introspect in a completely conscious way.
The sense of time in a trance is also diminished, as we have
seen it was in the bicameral mind. This is particularly evident in
post-hypnotic amnesia. We, in our normal states, use the spatialized succession of conscious time as a substrate for successions of
memories. Asked what we have done since breakfast, we commonly narratize a row of happenings that are what we can call
"time-tagged." But the subject in a hypnotic trance, like the
schizophrenic patient or the bicameral man, has not such a
schema of time in which events can be time-tagged. The beforeand afterness of spatialized time is missing. Such events as can
be remembered from the trance by a subject in post-hypnotic
amnesia are vague isolated fragments, cuing off the self, rather
than spatialized time as in normal remembering. Amnesic subjects can only report, if anything, "I clasped my hands, I sat in a
chair," with no detail or sequencing, in a way that to me is
reminiscent of Hammurabi or Achilles.11 What is significantly
10 For an extensive description of one example, see Milton Rokeach, The Three
Christs of Ypsilanti (New York: Knopf, 1960).
11 I am grateful to John Kihlstrom of Harvard for discussions on these points. The
distinct contrast between the language of amnesics and that of rememberers is from
his study, soon to be published.
392
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
different about the contemporary hypnotic subject, however, is
the fact that at the suggestion of the operator, the narratized
sequential memories can often be brought back to the subject,
showing that there has been some kind of parallel processing by
consciousness outside of the trance.
Such facts make the hypnotic trance a fascinating complexity.
Parallel processing! While a subject is doing and saying one
thing, his brain is processing his situation in at least two different
ways, one more inclusive than the other. This conclusion can be
demonstrated even more dramatically by the recent discovery
that has been dubbed "the hidden observer." A hypnotized subject, after the suggestion that he will feel nothing when keeping
his hand in a bucket of ice-cold water for a minute (a really
painful, but benign experience!), may show no discomfort and
say he felt nothing; but if it has previously been suggested that
when and only when the operator touches his shoulder, he will
say in another voice exactly what he really felt, that is what
happens. At such a touch, the subject, often in a low guttural
voice, may give full expression to his discomfiture, yet return
immediately to his ordinary voice and to the anesthetized state
when the operator's hand is lifted. 12
Such evidence returns us to a once rejected notion of hypnosis
known as dissociation that emerged from studies of multiple
personality at the beginning of this century.13 The idea is that in
hypnosis the totality of mind or reactivity is being separated into
concurrent streams which can function independently of each
other. What this means for the theory of consciousness and its
origin as described in Book I is not immediately apparent. But
12 Ernest Hilgard, "A Neodissociation Interpretation of Pain Reduction in Hypnosis," Psychological Review, 1973, 80: 396-411. I would like to record here my
gratitude to Ernest Hilgard for a critical reading of the earlier chapters. His encouraging criticisms were extremely helpful.
13 The classics in this field are Pierre Janet, The Major Symptoms of Hysteria,
1907 (2nd ed., New York: Holt, 1920) and Morton Prince, The Unconscious (New
York: Macmillan, 1914). For an excellent discussion see Ernest Hilgard's "Dissociation Revisited" in M. Henle, J. Jaynes, and J. J. Sullivan, eds., Historical Conceptions of Psychology (New York: Springer, 1973).
HYPNOSIS
393
such dissociated processing is certainly reminiscent of the bicameral organization of mind itself, as well as the kind of nonconscious problem solving discussed in I.1.
Perhaps the least discussed aspect of hypnosis is the difference
in the nature of the trance among persons who have never seen
or known much about hypnosis before. Usually, of course, the
trance is in our time a passive and suggestible state. But some
subjects really do go to sleep. Others are always partly conscious
and yet peculiarly suggestible until who can judge between acting
and reality? Others tremble so severely that the subject has to be
'awakened'. And so on.
That such individual differences are due to differences in the
belief or collective cognitive imperative of the individual is suggested by a recent study. Subjects were asked to describe in
writing what happens in hypnosis. They were later hypnotized,
and the results compared with their expectation. One 'awoke'
from the trance each time she was given a task for which she had
to see. A later perusal of her paper showed she had written, "A
person's eyes must be closed in order to be in a hypnotic trance."
Another could only be hypnotized on a second attempt. He had
written, "Most people cannot be hypnotized the first time." And
another could not perform tasks under hypnosis when standing.
She had written, "The subject has to be reclining or sitting."14
But the more hypnosis is talked about, even as on these pages,
the more standardized the cognitive imperative and hence the
trance becomes.
The Hypnotist as Authorization
And so, fourthly, a very particular kind of archaic authorization which also determines in part the different nature of the
trance. For here, instead of the authorization being an hallucinated or possessing god, it is the operator himself. He is mani14 T. R. Sarbin, "Contribution to Role-Taking Theory: I. Hypnotic Behavior,"
Psychology Review, 1943, 57: 255-270.
394
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
festly an authority figure to the subject. And if he is not, the subject will be less hypnotizable, or will require a much longer induction or a much greater belief in the phenomenon to begin with (a
stronger cognitive imperative).
Indeed, most students of the subject insist that there must be
developed a special kind of trust relationship between the subject
and the operator.15 One common test of the susceptibility to
hypnosis is to stand behind the prospective subject and ask him to
permit himself to fall voluntarily to see what it feels like to ‘let
go’. If the subject steps back to break his fall, some part of him
lacking confidence that he will be caught, he almost invariably
turns out to be a poor hypnotic subject for that particular
operator.16
Such trust explains the difference between hypnosis in the
clinic and in the laboratory. The hypnotic phenomena found in a
medical psychiatric setting are commonly more profound, because, I suggest, a psychiatrist is a more godlike figure to his
patient than is an investigator to his subject. And a similar
explanation can be made for the age at which hypnosis is most
easily done. Hypnotic susceptibility is at its peak between the
ages of eight and ten.17 Children look up to adults with a vastly
15 Even Clark Hull, a strident behaviorist, the first to perform really controlled
experiments in hypnosis, and who scorned introspective data, was compelled to look
on hypnosis as "prestige suggestion," perhaps with "a quantitative shift in the upward
direction which may result from the hypnotic procedure." Hypnosis and Suggestibility: An Experimental Approach (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1933),
p. 392.
16 See Ernest Hilgard, Hypnotic Susceptibility (New York: Harcourt, Brace and
World, 1965), p. 101. Those investigating glossolalia, discussed in III.2, have
remarked that the person able to "speak in tongues" must have a very similar kind
of trust in his charismatic leader. When such trust in such a leader diminishes, so
does the phenomenon. It would be a simple matter, using cassette recordings for
hypnotic induction procedures, to manipulate the variable of prestige and really
demonstrate the importance of this factor in hypnosis.
17 From the data of Theodore X. Barber and D. S. Calverley, "Hypnotic-Like
Suggestibility in Children and Adults," Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology,
1963, 66: 5S9-597. In a forthcoming book, I shall be discussing the development of
consciousness in the child, suggesting that this age of greatest hypnotic susceptibility
is just after the full development of consciousness.
HYPNOSIS
395
greater sense of adult omnipotence and omniscience, and this
thus increases the potentiality of the operator in fulfilling the
fourth element of the paradigm. The more godlike the operator
is to the subject, the more easily is the bicameral paradigm
activated.
Evidence for the Bicameral Theory of Hypnosis
If it is true that the relationship of subject to operator in
hypnosis is a vestige of an earlier relationship to a bicameral
voice, several interesting questions arise. If the neurological
model outlined in I.5 is in the right direction, then we might
expect some kind of laterality phenomenon in hypnosis. Our
theory predicts that in E E G ’ s of a subject under hypnosis, the
ratio of brain activity in the right hemisphere would be increased
over that of the left, although this is complicated by the fact that
it is the left hemisphere that to some extent must understand the
operator. But at least we would expect proportionally more right
hemisphere involvement than in ordinary consciousness.
At the present time we have no clear idea about even a usual
E E G under hypnosis, such the conflicting findings of researchers.
But there are other lines of evidence, even if they are unfortunately more correlational and indirect. They are:
Individuals can be categorized by whether they use the right
or left hemisphere relatively more than others. A simple way of
doing this is to face a person and ask questions and note which
way his eyes move as he thinks of an answer. (As in 1.5, we are
speaking only of right-handed people.) If to his right, he is using
his left hemisphere relatively more, and if to the left, his right
hemisphere — since activation of the frontal eye fields of either
hemisphere turns the eyes to the contralateral side. It has been
recently reported that people who, in answering questions face to
face, turn their eyes to the left, who are thus using their right
hemisphere more than most others, are much more susceptible to
396
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
hypnosis.18 This can be interpreted as indicating that hypnosis
may involve the right hemisphere in very special ways, that the
more easily hypnotized person is the one who can ‘listen to* and
‘rely on’ the right hemisphere more than others.
As we saw in I.5, the right hemisphere, which we have
presumed to have been the source of divine hallucinations in
earlier millennia, is presently considered to be the more creative,
spatial, and responsible for vivid imagery. Several recent studies
have found that individuals who manifest these characteristics
more than others are indeed more susceptible to hypnosis.19
These findings are consistent with the hypothesis that hypnosis
is a reliance on right hemisphere categories, just as a bicameral
man relied on his divine guidance.
If calling hypnosis a vestige of the bicameral mind is valid,
we might also expect that those most susceptible to being hypnotized would be those most susceptible to other instances of the
general bicameral paradigm. In regard to religious involvement,
this appears to be true. Persons who have attended church regularly since childhood are more susceptible to hypnosis, while
those who have had less religious involvement tend to be less
susceptible. At least some investigators of hypnosis that I know
seek their subjects in theological colleges because they have
found such students to be more susceptible.
The phenomenon of imaginary companions in childhood is
something I shall have more to say about in a future work. But it
too can be regarded as another vestige of the bicameral mind. At
least half of those whom I have interviewed remembered distinctly that hearing their companions speak was the same quality
of experience as hearing the question as I asked it. True halluci18 R. C. Gur and R. E. Gur, “Handedness, Sex, and Eyedness as Moderating Variables in the Relation between Hypnotic Susceptibility and Functional Brain Assymetry,” Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 1974, 83: 635-643.
19 Josephine R. Hilgard, Personality and Hypnosis (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), Ch. 7. The data on which the next three paragraphs are based
also come from her important book, Chs. 5, 8, and 14 respectively.
HYPNOSIS
397
nation. The incidence of imaginary companions occurs mostly
between the ages of three and seven, just preceding what I would
regard as the full development of consciousness in children. My
thinking here is that, either by some innate or environmental
predisposition to have imaginary companions, the neurological
structure of the general bicameral paradigm is (to use a metaphor) exercised. If the hypothesis of this chapter is correct, we
might then expect such persons to be more susceptible to the
engagement of that paradigm later in life — as in hypnosis. And
they are. Those who have had imaginary companions in childhood are easier to hypnotize than those who have not. Again it is
a case where hypnotizability is correlated with another vestige of
the bicameral mind.
If we can regard punishment in childhood as a way of
instilling an enhanced relationship to authority, hence training
some of those neurological relationships that were once the bicameral mind, we might expect this to increase hypnotic susceptibility. And this is true. Careful studies show that those who
have experienced severe punishment in childhood and come from
a disciplined home are more easily hypnotized, while those who
were rarely punished or not punished at all tend to be less susceptible to hypnosis.
These laboratory findings are only suggestive, and there are
quite different ways of understanding them, for which I refer the
reader to the original reports. But together they do form a pattern which lends support to the hypothesis that hypnosis is in
part a vestige of a preconscious mentality. Placing the phenomena of hypnosis against the broad historical background of mankind in this way gives them certain contours that they would not
otherwise have. If one has a very definite biological notion of
consciousness and that its origin is back in the evolution of mammalian nervous systems, I cannot see how the phenomenon of
hypnosis can be understood at all, not one speck of it. But if we
398
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
fully realize that consciousness is a culturally learned event,
balanced over the suppressed vestiges of an earlier mentality,
then we can see that consciousness, in part, can be culturally
unlearned or arrested. Learned features, such as analog ‘I,’ can
under the proper cultural imperative be taken over by a different
initiative, and one such instance is what we call hypnosis. The
reason that that different initiative works in conjunction with the
other factors of the diminishing consciousness of the induction
and trance is that in some way it engages a paradigm of an older
mentality than subjective consciousness.
Objection: Does Hypnosis Exist?
Finally, I should briefly refer to possible alternative interpretations. But presently there are not so much theories of hypnosis
as points of view, each correct as far as it goes. One view insists
that imagination and concentration on what the hypnotist suggests, and the tendency of such an imagination to result in conforming action, are important.20 They are. Another, that it is
condition of monomotivation that counts.21 Of course, that is a
description. Another states that the basic phenomenon is simply
the ability to enact different roles, the as-if nature of most hypnotic
performances.22 This certainly is true. Another correctly
stresses the dissociation.23 Another that hypnosis is a regression
to a childlike relation to a parent.24 And indeed this is often how
20 Magda Arnold, "On the Mechanism of Suggestion and Hypnosis," Journal of
Abnormal and Social Psychology, 1946, 41 : 107-128.
21 Robert White, "A Preface to the Theory of Hypnotism," Journal of Abnormal
and Social Psychology, 1941, 16:477-505.
22 T. R. Sarbin, "Contributions to Role-Taking Theory." But see also his more
recent paper with Milton Anderson "Role-Theoretical Analysis of Hypnotic Behavior,"
in J. E. Gordon.
23 Ernest Hilgard, "A Neodissociation Interpretation."
24 One of two psychoanalytic interpretations of hypnosis. See for example Merton M. Gill and Margaret Brenman, Hypnosis and Related States (New York: International Universities Press, 1959). The other, that hypnosis is a love relationship between operator and subject, is no longer taken seriously.
HYPNOSIS
399
any vestige of the bicameral mind appears, since the bicameral
mind itself is based on such admonitory experience.
But the main theoretical controversy — and it is a continuing
one, and the one that is most important for us here — is whether
or not hypnosis is really anything different from what happens
every day in the normal state. For if this view is final, my
interpretation in this chapter of a different mentality is utterly
wrong. Hypnosis cannot be a vestige of anything since it does not
really exist. All the manifestations of hypnosis, this position
insists, can be shown to be simply exaggerations of normal phenomena. We can tick them off:
As for the kind of obedience to the operator, all of us do the
same thing without thinking in situations that are so definedy as
with a teacher or a traffic policeman, or perhaps the caller at a
square dance.
As to such phenomena as suggested deafness, everyone has
had the experience of 'listening' carefully to another person and
yet not hearing a word. And so the mother who sleeps through a
thunderstorm and yet hears and wakes to the cry of her baby is
not engaging a different mechanism from that of the hypnotized
subject who hears only the hypnotist's voice and is asleep to all
else.
As for the induced amnesia which so astonishes an observer,
who can remember what he was thinking five minutes ago? You
must suggest to yourself a set or struction to remember at the
time. And this the operator of the present day can do or not do,
negating or enhancing the paraphrand of submersion, so that the
subject does or does not remember.
As for the suggested paralysis under hypnosis, who has not
been in discussion with a friend during a walk until, becoming
more and more absorbed, both walk more slowly until you are
standing still? Concentrated attention has meant arrest of
movement.
As for hypnotic anesthesia, that most remarkable of hypnotic
phenomena, who has not seen a hurt child distracted by a toy
400
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
until the crying stops and the pain is forgotten? Or known of
victims of accidents bleeding from unfelt wounds? And acupuncture may indeed be a related phenomenon.
And as for the "hidden observer," this kind of parallel processing goes on all the time. In ordinary conversation, we listen to
someone and plan what we are going to say at the same time.
And actors do this constantly, always acting as their own hidden
observers; Stanislavski to the contrary, they are always able to
criticize their performances. And many of the examples of nonconscious thought in I.1, or my description of driving a car and
conversing which opened I.4, are further instances.
And as for the startling success of post-hypnotic suggestion, we
all sometimes decide to react to some event in a certain way and
then do so, even forgetting our prior reason. It is really not
different from 'pre-hypnotic suggestion', as in the supposed paralysis of the dominant hand a few pages ago. It is a structuring of
the collective cognitive imperative that can predetermine our
reactions in very specific ways.
And so for other remarkable feats performed under hypnosis j
all are exaggerations of everyday phenomena. Hypnosis, the
argument runs, just seems different to an observer. The trance
behavior is simply intense concentration as in the proverbial
"absent-minded professor." Indeed a host of recent experiments
have been aimed at showing that all hypnotic phenomena can be
duplicated in waking subjects by simple suggestion.25
My reply, and it is the reply of others as well, is that this is not
explaining hypnosis. It is explaining it away. Even though all of
the phenomena of hypnosis can be duplicated in ordinary life
(and I do not think they can), hypnosis can still be defined by
distinct procedures, distinct susceptibilities which correlate with
25 The most prominent and untiring researcher with this view is Theodore X.
Barber. For Barber, "hypnosis" just does not exist as a state different from waking
life, and the term should therefore always be written with quotation marks. Among
his numerous papers, see his "Experimental Analysis of 'Hypnotic' Behavior: Review
of Recent Empirical Findings," Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 1965, 70: 132-154.
HYPNOSIS
401
other experiences as well as other vestiges of the bicameral mind,
and by huge differences in the ease with which hypnotic phenomena can be reproduced with and without hypnotic induction. In
any speculation about possible future changes in our mentality,
this latter difference is extremely important. That is why I began
this chapter as I did. If we are asked to be animals, five-year-olds,
painless when pricked, color-blind, cataleptic, or show nystagmus
to imagined whirlings of the visual field,26 or to taste vinegar as
champagne — it is enormously more difficult to do in our normal
state of consciousness than when ordinary consciousness is absent under hypnosis. Such feats without rapport with an operator require grotesque efforts of persuasion and massive burdens
of concentration. The full consciousness of the waking state
seems itself like a huge wilderness of distracting closenesses that
cannot easily be crossed to catch into such immediate control.
Try looking out the window and pretending to be red-green colorblind to such an extent that those colors really do look like shades
of gray.27 It can be done to a certain extent, but it is much easier
under hypnosis. Or get up now from where you are sitting and
act like a bird, flapping your arms and emitting strange calls for
for the next fifteen minutes, something easy to do under hypnosis. But there is not one reader of that last sentence who can
do it — if he is alone. Whatever those sweaty feelings of foolishness or silliness are, the why-should-I5s and the this-is-absurd's,
they crowd in like careful tyrants jealous as a god of such a
performance; you need the permission of a group, the authoriza26 J. P. Brady and E. Levitt, "Nystagmus as a Criterion of Hypnotically Induced
Visual Hallucinations," Science, 1964, 146: 85-86. But I do not agree with the
authors that this proves the existence of true hallucinations.
27 Normal subjects asked to respond to the Ishihara color-blindness test by trying
not to see the color red and then by trying not to see green read some of the Ishihara
cards in the manner expected from individuals with red or green color-blindness. This
was shown by Theoder X. Barber and D. C. Deeley, "Experimental Evidence for a
Theory of Hypnotic Behavior: I. 'Hypnotic Color-Blindness' without 'Hypnosis',"
International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, 1961, 9: 79-86. But
under hypnosis this pseudo-color-blindness is easier to obtain, as in Milton Erickson's
"The Induction of Color-Blindness by a Technique of Hypnotic Suggestion," Journal
of General Psychology, 1939, 20: 61-89.
402
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
tion of a collective imperative as well as the command of an
operator — or a god — to achieve such obedience. Or put your
hands on the table in front of you and make one of them distinctly redder; possible for you to do now, but much easier under
hypnosis. Or raise both your hands for fifteen minutes without
feeling any discomfort, a simple task under hypnosis but onerous
without it.
What is it then that hypnosis supplies that does this extraordinary enabling, that allows us to do things we cannot ordinarily do
except with great difficulty? Or is it ‘we’ that do them? Indeed,
in hypnosis it is as if someone else were doing things through us.
And why is this so? And why is this easier? Is it that we have to
lose our conscious selves to gain such control, which cannot then
be by us?
On another level, why is it that in our daily lives we cannot get
up above ourselves to authorize ourselves into being what we
really wish to be? If under hypnosis we can be changed in
identity and action, why not in and by ourselves so that behavior
flows from decision with as absolute a connection, so that whatever in us it is that we refer to as will stands master and captain
over action with as sovereign a hand as the operator over a subject?
The answer here is partly in the limitations of our learned
consciousness in this present millennium. We need some vestige
of the bicameral mind, our former method of control, to help us.
With consciousness we have given up those simpler more absolute methods of control of behavior which characterized the
bicameral mind. We live in a buzzing cloud of whys and wherefores, the purposes and reasonings of our narratizations, the
many-routed adventures of our analog ‘I’s. And this constant
spinning out of possibilities is precisely what is necessary to save
us from behavior of too impulsive a sort. The analog ‘I’ and the
metaphor ‘me’ are always resting at the confluence of many
collective cognitive imperatives. We know too much to command
ourselves very far.
HYPNOSIS
403
Those who through what theologians call the "gift of faith" can
center and surround their lives in religious belief do indeed have
different collective cognitive imperatives. They can indeed
change themselves through prayer and its expectancies much as
in post-hypnotic suggestion. It is a fact that belief, political or
religious, or simply belief in oneself through some earlier cognitive imperative, works in wondrous ways. Anyone who has experienced the sufferings of prisons or detention camps knows
that both mental and physical survival is often held carefully in
such untouchable hands.
But for the rest of us, who must scuttle along on conscious
models and skeptical ethics, we have to accept our lessened control. We are learned in self-doubt, scholars of our very failures,
geniuses at excuse and tomorrowing our resolves. And so we
become practiced in powerless resolution until hope gets undone
and dies in the unattempted. At least that happens to some of us.
And then to rise above this noise of knowings and really change
ourselves, we need an authorization that ‘we’ do not have.
Hypnosis does not work for everyone. There are many reasons
why. But in one particular group who find hypnosis difficult, the
reason is neurological and partly genetic. In such people, I think
that the inherited neurological basis of the general bicameral
paradigm is organized slightly differently. It is as if they cannot
readily accept the external authorization of an operator because
that part of the bicameral paradigm is already occupied. Indeed,
they often seem to the rest of us as if they were already hypnotized, particularly when confined in hospitals as they commonly
are from time to time. Some theorists have even speculated that
that is precisely their condition — a continuous state of self hypnosis. But I think such a position is a dreadful misuse of the term
hypnosis, and that the behavior of schizophrenics, as we call
them, should be looked at in another way — which is what we
shall do in the next chapter.
CHAPTER 5
Schizophrenia
M
OST OF US spontaneously slip back into something approaching the actual bicameral mind at some part of our lives. For
some of us, it is only a few episodes of thought deprivation or
hearing voices. But for others of us, with overactive dopamine
systems, or lacking an enzyme to easily break down the biochemical
products of continued stress into excretable form, it is a much
more harrowing experience — if it can be called an experience at
all. We hear voices of impelling importance that criticize us and
tell us what to do. At the same time, we seem to lose the
boundaries of ourselves. Time crumbles. We behave without
knowing it. Our mental space begins to vanish. We panic, and
yet the panic is not happening to us. There is no us. It is not that
we have nowhere to turn; we have nowhere. And in that nowhere, we are somehow automatons, unknowing what we do,
being manipulated by others or by our voices in strange and
frightening ways in a place we come to recognize as a hospital
with a diagnosis we are told is schizophrenia. In reality, we have
relapsed into the bicameral mind.
At least that is a provocative if oversimplified and exaggerated
way of introducing an hypothesis that has been obvious in earlier
parts of this essay. For it has been quite apparent that the views
presented here suggest a new conception for that most common
and resistant of mental illnesses, schizophrenia. This suggestion
is that, like the phenomena discussed in the preceding chapters,
S C H I Z O P H R E N I A
405
schizophrenia, at least in part, is a vestige of bicamerality, a
partial relapse to the bicameral mind. The present chapter is a
discussion of this possibility.
The Evidence in History
Let us begin with a glance, a mere side-glance, at the earliest
history of this disease. If our hypothesis is correct, there should
first of all be no evidence of individuals set apart as insane prior
to the breakdown of the bicameral mind. And this is true, even
though it makes an extremely weak case, since the evidence is so
indirect. But in the sculptures, literature, murals, and other artifacts of the great bicameral civilizations, there is never any depiction or mention of a kind of behavior which marked an individual
out as different from others in the way in which insanity does.
Idiocy, yes, but madness, no.1 There is, for example, no idea of
insanity in the Iliad.2 I am emphasizing individuals set apart
from others as ill, because, according to our theory, we could say
that before the second millennium B.C., everyone was schizophrenic.
Secondly, we should expect on the basis of the above hypothesis that when insanity is first referred to in the conscious period,
it is referred to in definitely bicameral terms. And this makes a
much stronger case. In the Phaedrus, Plato calls insanity “a
divine gift, and the source of the chiefest blessings granted to
men.”3 And this passage preludes one of the most beautiful and
1 Even the word found in I Samuel 13 that is sometimes brought forward as the
first reference to schizophrenia is the Hebrew halal, which is better translated as
foolish in the sense of an idiot.
2 When E. R. Dodds suggests that a few places in the Odyssey refer to madness, I
find his argument unconvincing. And when he concludes that there was a concept
of mental disease common in Homer’s time, “and probably long before,” this is a
completely unwarranted assertion. See E. R. Dodds, The Greeks and the Irrational
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1968), p. 67.
3 Phaedrus, 244A.
406
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
soaring passages in all the Dialogues in which four types of
insanity are distinguished: prophetic madness due to Apollo,
ritual madness due to Dionysus, the poetic madness “of those
who are possessed by the Muses, which taking hold of the delicate and virgin soul, and there inspiring frenzy, awaken lyrical
and all other numbers,” and, finally, erotic madness due to Eros
and Aphrodite. Even the word for prophetic, mantike, and the
word for psychotically mad, manike, were for the young Plato
the same word, the letter t being for him “only a modern and
tasteless insertion.”4 The point I am trying to make here is that
there is no doubt whatever of the early association of forms of
what we call schizophrenia with the phenomena that we have
come to call bicameral.
This correspondence is also brought out in another ancient
Greek word for insanity, paranoia, which, coming from para +
nous, literally meant having another mind alongside one’s own,
descriptive both of the hallucinatory state of schizophrenia and of
what we have described as the bicameral mind. This, of course,
has nothing whatever to do with the modern and etymologically
incorrect usage of this term, with its quite different meaning of
persecutory delusions, which is of nineteenth-century origin.
Paranoia, as the ancient general term for insanity, lasted along
with the other vestiges of bicamerality described in the previous
chapter, and then linguistically died with them about the second
century A.D.
But even in Plato’s own time, a time of war, famine, and
plague, the four divine insanities were gradually shifting into the
realm of the wise man’s poetry and the plain man’s superstition.
The sickness aspect of schizophrenia comes to the fore. In later
dialogues, the elderly Plato is more skeptical, referring to what
we call schizophrenia as a perpetual dreaming in which some
men believe “that they are gods, and others that they can fly,”5 in
4 Ibid.,
5
244C.
Theaetetus, 158.
SCHIZOPHRENIA
407
which case the family of those so afflicted should keep them at
home under penalty of a fine.6
The insane are now to be shunned. Even in the exotic farces
of Aristophanes, stones are thrown at them to keep them away.
What we now call schizophrenia, then, begins in human history as a relationship to the divine, and only around 400 B.C.
comes to be regarded as the incapacitating illness we know today.
This development is difficult to understand apart from the theory
of a change in mentality which this essay is about.
The Difficulties of the Problem
Before looking at its contemporary symptoms from the same
point of view, I would make a few preliminary observations of a
very general sort. As anyone knows who has worked in the
literature on the subject, there is today a rather vague panorama
of dispute as to what schizophrenia is, whether it is one disease or
many, or the final common path of multiple etiologies, whether
there exist two basic patterns variously called process and reactive, or acute and chronic, or quick-onset and slow-onset schizophrenia. The reason for this disagreement and its vagueness is
because research in the area is as obstinate a tangle of control
difficulties as can be found anywhere. How may we study schizophrenia and at the same time eliminate the effects of hospitalization, of drugs, of prior therapy, of cultural expectancy, of various
learned reactions to bizarre experiences, or of differences in obtaining accurate data about the situational crises of patients who,
through the trauma of hospitalization, find it frightening to
communicate?
It is beyond my effort here to sort out a way through these
difficulties to any definitive position. Rather I intend to step
around them with some simplicities on which there is wide agreement. These are, that there does exist a syndrome that can be
6 Laws, 934.
408
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
called schizophrenia, that at least in the florid state it is easily
recognized in the clinic, and that it is found in all civilized societies the world over.7 Moreover, for the truth of this chapter, it
is not really important whether I am speaking of all patients with
this diagnosis.8 Nor of the illness as it first appears, or as it
develops subsequent to hospitalization. My thesis is something
less, that some of the fundamental, most characteristic, and most
commonly observed symptoms of florid unmedicated schizophrenia are uniquely consistent with the description I have given
on previous pages of the bicameral mind.
These symptoms are primarily the presence of auditory hallucinations as described in I:4, and the deterioration of consciousness as defined in I:2, namely the loss of the analog
the erosion
of mind-space, and an inability to narratize. Let us look at these
symptoms in turn.
Hallucinations
Again, hallucinations. And what I shall say here is merely
adjunctory to my earlier discussion.
If we confine ourselves to florid unmedicated schizophrenics,
we can state that hallucinations are absent only in exceptional
cases. Usually they predominate, crowding in persistently and
massively, making the patient appear confused, particularly
when they are changing rapidly. In very acute cases, visual
hallucinations accompany the voices. But in more ordinary
cases, the patient hears a voice or many voices, a saint or a devil,
7 “The Experiential World Inventory” developed by H. Osmond and A. El. Miligi
at the Princeton Neuro-Psychiatric Institute, has been given to schizophrenics in different countries and cultures with very similar results.
8 Nor of just such patients. There is a growing movement in psychiatry to distinguish diagnostic categories by the drugs specific to them, the schizophrenias by the
phenothiazines and manic-depression by lithium. If this is correct, many patients
formerly diagnosed as having paranoid schizophrenia are really manic-depressive
since they respond only to lithium. In the manic phase, almost half of such patients
have hallucinations.
SCHIZOPHRENIA
409
a band of men under his window who want to catch him, burn
him, behead him. They lie in wait for him, threaten to enter
through the walls, climb up and hide under his bed or above him
in the ventilators. And then there are other voices who want to
help him. Sometimes God is a protector, at other times one of the
persecutors. At the persecuting voices, the patients may flee,
defend themselves, or attack. With helpful consoling hallucinations, the patient may listen intently, enjoy them like a festivity,
even weeping at hearing the voices of heaven. Some patients
may go through all sorts of hallucinated experiences while lying
under the blankets in their beds, while others climb around, talk
loudly or softly to their voices, making all kinds of incomprehensible gestures and motions. Even during conversation or reading,
patients may be constantly answering their hallucinations softly
or whispering asides to their voices every few seconds.
Now one of the most interesting and important aspects of all
this in respect to the parallel with the bicameral mind is the
following: auditory hallucinations in general are not even
slightly under the control of the individual himself, but they are
extremely susceptible to even the most innocuous suggestion
from the total social circumstances of which the individual is a
part. In other words, such schizophrenic symptoms are influenced by a collective cognitive imperative just as in the case of
hypnosis.
A recent study demonstrates this very clearly.9 Forty-five
hallucinating male patients were divided into three groups. One
group wore on their belts a small box with a lever which when
pressed administered a shock. They were instructed to thus
shock themselves whenever they began to hear voices. A second
group wore similar boxes, were given similar instructions, but
®9 Arthur H. Weingaertner, “Self-administered aversive stimulation with hallucinating hospitalized schizophrenics,” Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology,
1971, 36: 422-429-
410
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
pressing the lever did not give the patient a shock. A third group
were given similar interviews and evaluation, but had no boxes.
The boxes, incidentally, contained counters which recorded the
number of lever presses, the frequency ranging from 19 to 2362
times over the fortnight of the experiment. But the important
thing is that all three groups were casually led to expect that the
frequency of hallucinations might diminish.
It was of course predicted on the basis of learning theory that
the shocked group alone would improve. But alas for learning
theory, all three groups heard significantly fewer voices. In some
cases the voices vanished completely. And no group was superior
to another in this respect, showing clearly the huge role of expectation and belief in this aspect of mental organization.
A further observation is a related one, that hallucinations are
dependent on the teachings and expectations of childhood — as
we have postulated was true in bicameral times. In contemporary cultures where an orthodox excessive personal relationship
to God is a part of the child’s education, individuals that become
schizophrenic tend to hear strict religious hallucinations more
than others.
On the British island of Tortola in the West Indies, for example, children are taught that God literally controls each detail
of their life. The name of the Deity is invoked in threats and
punishment. Churchgoing is the major social activity. When the
natives of this island require any psychiatric care whatever, they
invariably describe experiences of hearing commands from God
and Jesus, feelings of burning in hell or hallucinations of loud
praying and hymn-singing, or sometimes a combination of prayer
and profanity.10
When the auditory hallucinations of schizophrenia have no
particular religious basis they are still playing essentially the
10 Edwin A. Weinstein, “Aspects of Hallucinations,” Hallucinations, L. J. West,
ed. (New York: Grune and Stratton, 1962), pp. 233-238.
SCHIZOPHRENIA
411
same role as I have suggested was true for the bicameral mind,
that of initiating and guiding the patient’s behavior. Occasionally
the voices are recognized as authorities even within the hospital.
One woman heard voices that were mainly beneficial which she
believed were created by the Public Health Service to provide
psychotherapy. Would that psychotherapy could always be so
easily accomplished! They constantly gave her advice, including,
incidentally, not to tell the psychiatrist that she heard voices.
They advised her on difficult pronunciations, or gave her hints
on sewing and cooking. As she described it,
W h e n I am making a cake, she gets too impatient with me.
I try to figure it out all by myself.
I am trying to make a
clothspin apron and she is right there with me trying to tell
me what to do. 1 1
Some psychiatric investigators, particularly of a psychoanalytic
persuasion, wish to infer by the associations the patient uses that
the voices can “in all instances . . . be traced to persons who
were formerly significant in the patients’ lives, especially their
parents.”12 It is supposed that because such figures if recognized
would produce anxiety, they are therefore unconsciously distorted
and disguised by the patients. But why should that be so? It is
more parsimonious to think that it is the patient’s experiences
with his parents (or other loved authorities) that become the core
around which the hallucinated voice is structured, even as I have
suggested was the case with the gods in the bicameral era.
I do not mean that parents do not figure in hallucinations.
They often do, particularly in younger patients. But otherwise,
the voice-figures of schizophrenia are not parents in disguise;
they are authority figures created by the nervous system out of
the patient’s admonitory experience and his cultural expectaA. H. Modell, “Hallucinations in schizophrenic patients and their relation to
psychic structure,” in West, pp. 166-1735 the quotation is from p. 169.
12 Modell, in West, p. 168.
II
412
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
tions, his parents of course being an important part of that admonitory experience.
One of the most interesting problems in hallucinations is their
relation to conscious thought. If schizophrenia is partly a return
to the bicameral mind, and if this is antithetical to ordinary
consciousness (which it need not be in all cases), one might
expect hallucinations to be the replacement of ‘thoughts.’
In some patients at least, this is how hallucinations first appear. Sometimes, the voices seem to begin as thoughts which
then transform themselves into vague whispers, which then
gradually become louder and more authoritative. In other cases,
patients feel the beginning of voices “as if their thoughts were
dividing.” In mild cases, the voices may even be under the control
of conscious attention as are ‘thoughts.’ As one nondeluded patient described it:
Here I have been in this ward for two years and a half and
almost every day and every hour of the day I hear voices about
me, sometimes sounding from the wind, sometimes from footsteps, sometimes rattling dishes, from the rustling trees, or from
the wheels of passing trains and vehicles. I hear the voices only
if I attend to them, but hear them I do. T h e voices are words
that tell me one story or another, just as if they were not
thoughts in my head, but were recounting past deeds — yet
only when I think of them. T h e whole day through they keep
on telling truly my daily history of head and heart. 13
Hallucinations often seem to have access to more memories
and knowledge than the patient himself — even as did the gods
of antiquity. It is not uncommon to hear patients at certain
stages of their illness complain that the voices express their
thoughts before they have a chance to think them themselves.
This process of having one’s thoughts anticipated and expressed
13 Gustav
Storring, Mental Pathology (Berlin: Swan Sonnenschein, 1907), p. 27.
SCHIZOPHRENIA
413
aloud to one is called in the clinical literature Gedankenlautwerden and is approaching closely the bicameral mind. Some say
they never get a chance to think for themselves; it is always done
for them and the thought is given to them. As they try to read,
the voices read in advance to them. Trying to speak, they hear
their thoughts spoken in advance to them. Another patient told
his physician that: “Thinking hurts him, for he can not think for
himself. Whenever he begins to think, all his thoughts are dictated to him. He is at pains to change the train of thought, but
again his thinking is done for him . . . In church he not infrequently hears a voice singing, anticipating what the choir sings
. . . If he walks down the street and sees, say, a sign, the voice
reads out to him whatever is on it . . . If he sees an acquaintance in the distance, the voice calls out to him, ‘Look, there goes
so and so,’ usually before he begins to think of the person. Occasionally, though he has not the least intention of noticing
passersby, the voice compels him to attend to them by its remarks
about them.” 14
It is the very central and unique place of these auditory hallucinations in the syndrome of many schizophrenics which it is
important to consider. W h y are they present? And why is “hearing voices” universal throughout all cultures, unless there is some
usually suppressed structure of the brain which is activated in the
stress of this illness?
And why do these hallucinations of schizophrenics so often
have a dramatic authority, particularly religious? I find that the
only notion which provides even a working hypothesis about this
matter is that of the bicameral mind, that the neurological structure responsible for these hallucinations is neurologically bound
to substrates for religious feelings, and this is because the source
of religion and of gods themselves is in the bicameral mind.
Religious hallucinations are particularly common in the so14 Ibid.,
p. 30.
414
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
called twilight states, which are a kind of waking dream in many
patients, varying in time from a few minutes to a few years, six
months’ duration being quite common. Invariably such states are
characterized by religious visions, posturing, ceremony, and worship, a patient living with hallucinations just as in the bicameral
state, except that the environment itself may be hallucinated and
the hospital surroundings blotted out. The patient may be in
contact with the saints in heaven. Or he may recognize doctors
or nurses around him for what they are, but believe that they will
prove to be gods or angels in disguise. Such patients may even cry
with joy at talking directly with the inhabitants of heaven, may
continually cross themselves as they converse with the divine
voices or even with the stars, calling to them out of the night.
Often the paranoid, after a lengthy period of difficulties in
getting on with people, may begin the schizophrenic aspect of his
illness with an hallucinated religious experience in which an
angel, Christ, or God speaks to the patient bicamerally, showing
him some new way. 15 He becomes convinced therefore of his
own special relationship to the powers of the universe, and the
pathological self-reference of all the occurrences around him
then becomes elaborated into delusional ideas which may be
pursued for years without the patient’s being able to discuss it.
Particularly illustrative of the tendency toward religious hallucinations is the famous case of Schreber, a brilliant German jurist
around the close of the nineteenth century.16 His own extremely
literate retrospective account of his hallucinations while ill with
schizophrenia is remarkable from the point of view of their similarity to the relationships of ancient men to their gods. His
disease began with a severe anxiety attack during which he hallucinated a crackling in the walls of his house. Then one night,
15 Eugen Bleuler, Dementia Praecox or The Grouf of Schizophrenias, Joseph
Zinkin, trans. (New York: International Universities Press, 1950), p. 229.
16 D. P. Schreber, Memoirs of My Nervous Illness, I. MacAlpine and R. A.
Hunter, trans, and eds. (London: Dawson, 1955).
SCHIZOPHRENIA
415
the cracklings suddenly became voices which he immediately
recognized as divine communications and “which since then have
spoken to me incessantly.” The voices were continuous “for a
period of seven years, except during sleep, and would persist
undeterred even when I was speaking with other people.” 17 He
saw rays of light like “long-drawn-out filaments approaching my
head from some vast distant spot on the horizon . . . Or from
the sun or other distant stars that do not come towards me in a
straight line, but in a kind of circle or parabola.”18 And these
were the carriers of the divine voices, and could form into the
physical beings of gods themselves.
As his illness progressed, it is of particular interest how the
divine voices soon organized themselves into a hierarchy of upper
and lower gods, as may be supposed to have occurred in bicameral times. And then, streaming down their rays from the gods,
the voices seemed to be trying to “suffocate me and eventually to
rob me of my reason.” They were committing “soul-murder,“ and
were progressively “unmanning” him, that is, taking away his own
initiative or eroding his analog
Later in his illness, during
more conscious periods, he narratized this into the delusion of
being bodily turned into a woman. Freud, I think, overemphasized this particular narratization in his famous analysis of these
memoirs, making the entire illness the result of repressed homosexuality that was erupting from the unconscious.19 But such
an interpretation, while possibly related to the original etiology of
the stress that began the illness, is not very powerful in explaining the case as a whole.
Now, can we have the temerity to draw a parallel with such
phenomena of mental illness and the organization of gods in
antiquity? That Schreber also had voice-visions of “little men” is
suggestive of the figurines found in so many early civilizations.
Ibid., p. 225.
Ibid., pp. 227-228.
19 Sigmund Freud, “Psycho-analytic notes on an autobiographical account of a
case of paranoia,” in Complete Psychological Works, Vol. 12, James Strachey, trans.
and ed. (London: Hogarth Press, 1958).
17
18
416
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
And the fact that, as he slowly recuperated, the tempo of speech
of his gods slowed down and then degenerated into an indistinct
hissing20 is reminiscent of how idols sounded to the Incas after
the conquest.
A further suggestive parallel is the fact that the sun as the
world’s brightest light takes on a particular significance in many
unmedicated patients, as it did in the theocracies of bicameral
civilizations. Schreber, for example, after hearing his “upper God
(Ormuzd)” for some time, finally saw him as “the sun . . . surrounded by a silver sea of rays . . .21 And a more contemporary patient wrote:
T h e sun came to have an extraordinary effect on me.
It
seemed to be charged with all power; not merely to symbolize
G o d but actually to be God.
Phrases like: “ L i g h t of the
W o r l d , ” “ T h e Sun of Righteousness that Setteth Nevermore,”
etc., ran through my head without ceasing, and the mere sight
of the sun was sufficient greatly to intensify this manic excitement under which I was laboring. I was impelled to address the
sun as a personal god, and to evolve from it a ritual sun worship. 22
In no sense am I thinking here that there is innate sun-worship
or innate gods in the nervous system that are released under the
mental reorganization of psychosis. The reasons that hallucinations take the -particular form they do lie partly in the physical
nature of the world, but mostly in education and a familiarity
with gods and religious history.
But I do mean to suggest
(1)
that there are in the brain aptic structures for the very existence of such hallucinations,
20 Schreber, pp. 226,
332.
Ibid., p. 269.
22 J. Custance, Wisdom, Madness and Folly (New York: Pellegrini and Cudahy,
1952), p. 18.
21
SCHIZOPHRENIA
417
(2) that these structures develop in civilized societies such
that they determine the general religious quality and authority of such hallucinated voices, and perhaps organize
them into hierarchies,
(3) that the paradigms behind these aptic structures were
evolved into the brain by natural and human selection during the early civilizing of mankind, and
(4) are released from their normal inhibition by abnormal
biochemistry in many cases of schizophrenia and particularized into experience.
There is a great deal more to say about these very real phenomena of hallucination in schizophrenia. And the need for
more research here cannot be overstressed. We would like to
know the life history of hallucinations and how this relates to the
life history of the patient’s illness, of this hardly anything is
known. We would like to know more of how the particular
hallucinatory experiences relate to the individuals upbringing.
Why do some patients have benevolent voices, while others have
voices so relentlessly persecuting that they flee or defend themselves or attack someone or something in an attempt to end
them? And why do still others have voices so ecstatically religious and inspiring that the patient enjoys them like a festivity?
And what are the language characteristics of the voices? Do
they use the same syntax and lexicon as the patient’s own
speech? Or are they more patterned as we might expect from
III.3? A l l these are problems that can be resolved empirically.
When they are, they may indeed give us more insight into the
bicameral beginnings of civilization.
The Erosion of the Analog ‘I’
Of what transcending importance is this analog we have of
ourselves in our metaphored mind-space, the very thing with
which we narratize out solutions to problems of personal action,
418
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
and see where we are going, and who we are! And when in
schizophrenia it begins to diminish, and the space in which it
exists begins to collapse, how terrifying the experience must be!
Florid schizophrenic patients all have this symptom in some
degree:
W h e n I am ill I lose the sense of where I am. I feel ‘I’ can
sit in the chair, and yet my body is hurtling out and somersaulting about 3 feet in front of me.
It is really very hard to keep conversations with others because I can’t be sure if others are really talking or not and if I
am really talking back. 23
Gradually I can no longer distinguish how much of myself
is in me, and how much is already in others. I am a conglomeration, a monstrosity, modeled anew each day. 24
My ability to think and decide and will to do, is torn apart by
itself.
Finally, it is thrown out where it mingles with every
other part of the day and judges what it has left behind.
In-
stead of wishing to do things, they are done by something that
seems mechanical and frightening . . . the feeling that should
dwell within a person is outside longing to come back and yet
having taken with it the power to return. 26
Many are the ways in which this loss of ego is described by
patients who are able to describe it at all. Another patient has to
sit still for hours at a time “in order to find her thoughts again.”
Another feels as if “he died away.” Schreber, as we have seen,
talked of “soul-murder.” One very intelligent patient needs
23 Both quotations from patients of Dr. C. C. Pfeiffer of the Brain-Bio Center of
Princeton, New Jersey, where schizophrenia is regarded as several biochemical illnesses
primarily treatable by brain nutrients.
24 Storch as quoted by H. Werner, Comparative Psychology of Mental Development (New York: International Universities Press, 1957), p. 467.
25 From E. Meyer and L. Covi, “The experience of depersonalization: A written
report by a patient,” Psychiatry, i960, 23: 215-217.
SCHIZOPHRENIA
419
hours of strenuous effort “to find her own ego for a few brief
moments.” Or the self feels it is being absorbed by all that is
around it by cosmic powers, forces of evil or of good, or by God
himself. Indeed, the very term schizophrenia was coined by
Bleuler to point to this central experience as the identifying
mark of schizophrenia. It is the feeling of ‘losing one’s mind5, of
the self ‘breaking off’ until it ceases to exist or seems to be
unconnected with action or life in the usual way, resulting in
many of the more obvious descriptive symptoms, such as “lack of
affect” or abulia.
Another way in which this erosion of the analog ‘I’ shows itself
is in the relative inability of schizophrenics to draw a person. It
is, of course, a somewhat tenuous assumption to say that when
we draw a person on paper, that drawing is dependent upon an
intact metaphor of the self that we have called the analog ‘I’ But
so consistent has this result been that it has become what is
called the Draw-A-Person Test ( D A P ) , now routinely administered as an indicator of schizophrenia.26 Not all schizophrenic
patients find such drawings difficult. But when they do, it is
extremely diagnostic. They leave out obvious anatomical parts,
like hands or eyes; they use blurred and unconnected lines; sexuality is often undifferentiated; the figure itself is often distorted
and befuddled.
But the generalization that this inability to draw a person is a
reflecting of the erosion of the analog ‘I’ should be taken with
some circumspection. It has been found that older people sometimes show the same fragmented and primitive drawings as do
these schizophrenics, and it should also be noticed that there is a
considerable inconsistency with this result and the hypothesis
being examined in this chapter. We have stated in an earlier
26 The first several years of research with the DAP have been reported in L. W.
Jones and C. B. Thomas, “Studies on figure drawings,” Psychiatric Quarterly Sufflementy 1961, 35: 212-216.
420
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
chapter that the analog ‘I’ came into being toward the end of the
second millennium B.C. If the ability to draw a person is dependent upon the drawer having an analog ‘I’, then we would expect
no coherent pictures of humans before that time. And this most
definitely is not the case. It is obvious that there are ways of
explaining this discrepancy, but I prefer to simply record the
anomaly at this time.
We should not leave this discussion of the erosion of the
analog ‘I’ without mentioning the tremendous anxiety in our own
culture that accompanies it, and the attempt, sometimes successful, sometimes unsuccessful, to arrest this terrifying fading-off of
that most important part of our interior selves, the almost sacramental center of conscious decision. In fact, much of the behavior that has nothing to do with any reversion to a bicameral mind
can be construed as an effort to combat this loss of the analog
‘I’.
Sometimes, for example, there is what is called the “I am”
symptom. The patient in trying to keep some control over his
behavior repeats over and over to himself “I am,” or “I am the one
present in everything,” or “I am the mind, not the body.” Another
patient may use only single words like “strength” or “life” to try
to anchor himself against the dissolution of his consciousness.27
The Dissolution of Mind-Space
A schizophrenic not only begins to lose his ‘I’ but also his mindspace, the pure paraphrand that we have of the world and its
objects that is made to seem like a space when we introspect. To
the patient it feels like losing his thoughts, or “thought deprivation,” a phrase which elicits immediate recognition from the
schizophrenic. The effect of this is so bound up with the erosion
27 Carney Landis, Varieties of Psychopathological Experience (New York: Holt,
Rinehart and Winston, 1964).
SCHIZOPHRENIA
421
of the analog ‘I’ as to be inseparable from it. Patients cannot
easily think of themselves in the places that they are in and so
they are unable to utilize information to prepare in advance for
things that may happen to them.
One way this can be experimentally observed is in reactiontime studies. A l l schizophrenics of every type are much less
capable than normally conscious people when they attempt to
respond to stimuli presented to them at intervals of varying
lengths. The schizophrenic, lacking an intact analog ‘I’ and a
mind-space in which to picture himself doing something, is unable to “get ready” to respond, and, once responding, is unable to
vary the response as the task demands.28 A patient who has
been sorting blocks on the basis of form may be unable to shift to
sorting them for color when instructed to sort in a different
way.
Similarly, the loss of the analog ‘I’ and its mind-space results in
the loss of as-if behaviors. Because he cannot imagine in the usual
conscious way, he cannot play-act, or engage in make-believe
actions, or speak of make-believe events. He cannot, for example, pretend to drink water out of a glass if there is no water
in it. Or asked what he would do if he were the doctor, he might
reply that he is not a doctor. Or if an unmarried patient is asked
what he would do if he were married, he might answer that he is
not married. And hence his difficulty with the as-if behavior of
hypnosis, as I mentioned at the end of the previous chapter.
Another way the dissolving of mind-space shows itself is in the
disorientation in respect to time so common in the schizophrenic.
We can only be conscious of time as we can arrange it into a
spatial succession, and the diminishing of mind-space in schizophrenia makes this difficult or impossible. For example, patients
may complain that “time has stopped,” or that everything seems
to be “slowed down” or “suspended,” or more simply that they
28 This is an interpretation of a widely held theory of David Shakow, “Segrnental
Set,” Archives of General Psychiatry, 1962, 6: 1-17.
422
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
have “trouble with time.” As one former patient remembered it
after he was well:
For a long time no days seemed to me like a day and no night
seemed like a night.
But this in particular has no shape in my
memory. I used to tell time by my meals, but as I believed we
were served sets of meals in each real day — about half a dozen
sets of breakfast, lunch, tea, and dinner in each twelve hours —
this was not much help. 28
On the face of it, this may seem inconsistent with the hypothesis that schizophrenia is a partial relapse to the bicameral mind.
For bicameral man certainly knew the hours of the day and the
seasons of the year. But this knowing was, I suggest, a very
different knowing from the narratization in a spatially successive
time which we who are conscious are constantly doing. Bicameral man had behavioral knowing, responding to the cues for
rising and sleeping, for planting and harvesting, cues so important that they were worshiped, as at Stonehenge, and were probably hallucinogenic in themselves. For someone coming from
a culture where attention to such cues has been superseded by a
different sense of time, the loss of that spatial successiveness
leaves the patient in a relatively timeless world. It is interesting
in this connection that when it is suggested to normal hypnotic
subjects that time does not exist, a schizophrenic form reaction
results.30
The Failure of Narratization
With the erosion of the analog
and its mind-space, narratization becomes impossible. It is as if all that was narratized in the
normal state shatters into associations subordinated to some genM. Harrison, Spinners Lake (London: Lane, 1941), p. 32.
S. Aaronson, “Hypnosis, responsibility, and the boundaries of self,”
American Journal of Clinical Hypnosisy 1967, 9: 229-246.
29
30 Bernard
SCHIZOPHRENIA
423
eral thing perhaps, but unrelated to any unifying conceptive purpose or goal, as occurs in normal narratization. Logical reasons
cannot be given for behaviors, and verbal answers to questions do
not originate in any interior mind-space, but in simple associations or in the external circumstances of a conversation. The
whole idea that a person can explain himself, something which in
the bicameral era was distinctly the function of gods, can no
longer occur.
With the loss of the analog ‘I’, its mind-space, and the ability to
narratize, behavior is either responding to hallucinated directions, or continues on by habit. The remnant of the self feels like
a commanded automaton, as if someone else were moving the
body about. Even without hallucinated orders, a patient may
have the feeling of being commanded in ways in which he must
obey. He may shake hands normally with a visitor, but, asked
about this, reply, “I don’t do it, the hand proffers itself.” Or a
patient may feel that somebody else is moving his tongue in
speech, particularly as in coprolalia, when scatalogical or obscene
words are substituted for others. Even in early stages of schizophrenia, the patient feels memories, music, or emotions, either
pleasant or unpleasant, which seem to be forced upon him from
some alien source, and, therefore, over which ‘he‘ has no control.
This symptom is extremely common and diagnostic. And these
alien influences often then develop into the full-blown hallucinations I have discussed earlier.
According to Bleuler, “conscious feelings rarely accompany the
automatisms which are psychic manifestations split off from the
personality. The patients can dance and laugh without feeling
happy; can commit murder without hating; do away with themselves without being disappointed with life . . . the patients
realize that they are not their own masters.”31
Many patients simply allow such automatisms to take place.
Others, still able to narratize marginally, invent protective de31 Bleuler, p.
204.
424
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
vices against such foreign control of their actions. Negativism
itself, even, I think, in neurotics, is such. One of Bleuler’s patients, for example, who was inwardly driven to sing, managed to
get hold of a small block of wood which he would cram into his
mouth in order to stop his mouth from singing. At present we do
not know whether such automatisms and inner commands are
always the result of articulate voices directing the patient in his
actions, as a relapse to the bicameral mind would suggest. It may
indeed be impossible to know, since the split-off fragment of the
personality that is still responding to the physician may have
suppressed the bicameral commands which are being ‘heard’ by
other parts of the nervous system.
In many patients this appears as the symptom called Command Automatism. The patient obeys any and every suggestion
and command coming from the outside. He is incapable of not
obeying authoritative short orders, even when otherwise negativistic. Such orders must deal with simple activities and cannot
apply to a long complicated task. The well-known waxy flexibility of catatonics may fall under this heading; the patient is really
obeying the physician by remaining in any position in which he is
placed. While not all such phenomena are, of course, characteristic of what we have called the bicameral mind, the underlying
principle is. An interesting hypothesis would be that patients
with such Command Automatism are those in whom auditory
hallucinations are absent, and the external voice of the physician
is taking its place.
Consistent with such an hypothesis is the symptom known as
echolalia. When no hallucinations are present, the patient repeats back the speech, cries, or expressions of others. But when
hallucinations are present, this becomes hallucinatory echolalia,
where the patient must repeat out loud all that his voices say to
him, rather than those of his environmental surroundings. Hallucinatory echolalia is, I suggest, essentially the same mental
organization that we have seen in the prophets of the Old Testament, as well as the aoidoi of the Homeric poems.
425
SCHIZOPHRENIA
Body Image Boundary Disturbance
It is possible that the erosion of the analog ‘I’ and its mindspace also results in what is called Boundary Loss in Rorschach
studies of schizophrenia. This is a score for the proportion of
images seen in the ink blots that have poorly defined, fuzzy, or
inexistent boundaries or edges. Most interesting from our point
of view here is that this measure is strongly correlated with the
presence of vivid hallucinatory experiences. A patient high in
Boundary Loss often describes it as a feeling of disintegration.
W h e n I am melting I have no hands, I go into a doorway
in order not to be trampled on. Everything is flying away from
me.
In the doorway I can gather together the pieces of my
body. It is as if something is thrown in me, bursts me asunder.
W h y do I divide myself in different pieces?
I feel that I am
without poise, that my personality is melting and that my ego
disappears and that I do not exist anymore. Everything pulls me
apart . . . T h e skin is the only possible means of keeping the
different pieces together. T h e r e is no connection between the
different parts of my body . . , 3 2
In one study on Boundary Loss, the Rorschach was given to 80
schizophrenic patients. Boundary definiteness scores were significantly lower than in the group of normals and neurotics
matched for age and socio-economic status. Such patients would
commonly see in the ink blots mutilated bodies, animal or human.33 This mirrors the breaking up of the analog self, or the
metaphor picture that we have of ourselves in consciousness. In
another study of 604 patients in Worcester State Hospital, it was
specifically found that Boundary Loss, including, we may presume, the loss of the analog ‘I’, is a factor in the development of
hallucinations. Patients who had more hallucinations were those
32 P. Schilder, The Image and Appearance of the Human Body (London: Kegan
Paul, Trench, Trubner, and Co., 1935), p. 159.
33 S. Fisher and S. E. Cleveland, “The Role of Body Image in Psychosomatic
Symptom Choice,” Psychological Monographs, 1955, 69, No. 17, whole no. 402.
426
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
who were less successful in establishing “boundaries between the
self and the world.” 34
Along the same line of thought, chronic schizophrenic patients
are sometimes unable to identify themselves in a photograph, or
may misidentify themselves, whether they are photographed individually or in a group.
The Advantages of Schizophrenia
A curious heading, certainly, for how can we say there are
advantages of so terrifying an illness? But I mean such advantages
in the light of all human history. Very clearly, there is a genetic
inherited basis to the biochemistry underlying this radically different reaction to stress. And a question that must be asked of
such a genetic disposition to something occurring so early in our
reproductive years is, what biological advantage did it once have?
W h y , in the slang of the evolutionist, was it selected for? And
at what period long, long ago, since such genetic disposition is
present all over the world?
The answer, of course, is one of the themes I have stated so
often before in this essay. The selective advantage of such genes
was the bicameral mind evolved by natural and human selection
over the millennia of our early civilizations. The genes involved,
whether causing what to conscious men is an enzyme deficiency or
other, are the genes that were in the background of the prophets
and the ‘sons of the nabiim’ and bicameral man before them.
Another advantage of schizophrenia, perhaps evolutionary, is
tirelessness. While a few schizophrenics complain of generalized
fatigue, particularly in the early stages of the illness, most patients do not. In fact, they show less fatigue than normal persons
and are capable of tremendous feats of endurance. They are not
fatigued by examinations lasting many hours. They may move
about day and night, or work endlessly without any sign of being
tired. Catatonics may hold an awkward position for days that the
34 L. Phillips and M. S. Rabinovitch, Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology,
1958, 57: 181.
SCHIZOPHRENIA
427
reader could not hold for more than a few minutes. This suggests
that much fatigue is a product of the subjective conscious mind,
and that bicameral man, building the pyramids of Egypt, the
ziggurats of Sumer, or the gigantic temples at Teotihuacan with
only hand labor, could do so far more easily than could conscious
self-reflective men.
A further thing that schizophrenics do ‘better’ than the rest
of us — although it certainly is no advantage in our abstractly
complicated world — is simple sensory perception. They are more
alert to visual stimuli, as might be expected if we think of them
as not having to strain such stimuli through a buffer of consciousness. This is seen in their ability to block E E G alpha waves more
quickly than normal persons following an abrupt stimulus, and to
recognize projected visual scenes coming into focus considerably
better than the normal.35 Indeed, schizophrenics are almost
drowning in sensory data. Unable to narratize or conciliate, they
see every tree and never the forest. They seem to have a more
immediate and absolute involvement with their physical environment, a greater in-the-world-ness. Such an interpretation, at least,
could be put on the fact that schizophrenics fitted with prism
glasses that deform visual perception learn to adjust more easily
than the rest of us, since they do not overcompensate as much.36
The Neurology of Schizophrenia
If schizophrenia is in part a relapse to the bicameral mind, and
if our earlier analyses have any merit, then we should find some
kind of neurological changes that are consistent with the neurological model suggested in I.5. There I proposed that the halluci35 See R. L. Cromwell and J. M. Held, “Alpha blocking latency and reaction time
in schizophrenics and normals,” Perceptual and Motor Skills, 1969, 29: 195-201;
E. Ebner and B. Ritzier, “Perceptual recognition in chronic and acute schizophrenics,”
Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 1969, 33: 200-206.
36 See E. Ebner, V. Broekma, and B. Ritzier, “Adaptation to awkward visual
proprioceptive input in normals and schizophrenics,” Archives of General Psychiatry,
1971, 24: 367-371-
428
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
nated voices of the bicameral mind were amalgams of stored
admonitory experiences that were somehow organized in the
right temporal lobe and conveyed to the left or dominant hemisphere over the anterior commissures and perhaps the corpus
callosum.
Further, I have suggested that the advent of consciousness
necessitated an inhibition of these auditory hallucinations originating in the right temporal cortex. But what precisely this
means in a neuro-anatomical sense is far from clear. We definitely know that there are specific areas of the brain that are
inhibitory to others, that the brain in a very general way is always
in a kind of complicated tension (or balance) between excitation
and inhibition, and also that inhibition can occur in a number of
different ways. One way is an inhibition of an area in one hemisphere by excitation of an area in the other. The frontal eye
fields, for example, are mutually inhibitory, such that stimulation
of the frontal eye field on one hemisphere inhibits the other.37
And we may suppose that some proportion of the fibers of the
corpus callosum which connects the frontal eye fields are inhibitory themselves, or else excite inhibitory centers on the opposite
hemisphere. In behavior, this means that looking in any direction is programmed as the vector resultant of the opposing excitation of the two frontal eye fields.38 And this mutual inhibition of
the hemispheres can be presumed to operate in various other
bilateral functions.
But to generalize this reciprocal inhibition to asymmetrical
unilateral functions is a more daring matter. Can we suppose,
for example, that some mental process on the left hemisphere is
paired in reciprocal inhibition with some different function on the
37 A. S. F. Layton and C. S. Sherrington, “Observation on the excitable cortex of
chimpanzees, orangutan, and gorilla,” Quarterly Journal of Experimental Physiology,
1917, 11: 135.
38 The phrasing here is that of Marcel Kinsbourne in “The control of attention by
interaction between the cerebral hemispheres,” Fourth International Symposium on
Attention and Performance, Boulder, Colorado, August 1971.
SCHIZOPHRENIA
429
right, so that some of the so-called higher mental processes could
be the resultants of the two opposing hemispheres?
At any rate, the first step in bringing some credence to these
ideas about the relationship of schizophrenia to the bicameral
mind and its neurological model is to look for some kind of laterality differences in schizophrenics. Do such patients have different
right-hemispheric activity from the rest of us? Research on this
hypothesis is only beginning, but the following very recent studies
are at least suggestive:
• In most of us, the total E E G over a long time period shows
slightly greater activity in the dominant left hemisphere than
in the right hemisphere. But the reverse tends to occur in schizophrenia: slightly more activity in the right.39
• This increased right hemisphere activity in schizophrenia is
much more pronounced after several minutes of sensory deprivation, the same condition that causes hallucinations in normal
persons.
• If we arrange our E E G machine so that we can tell which
hemisphere is more active every few seconds, we find that in most
of us this measure switches back and forth between the hemispheres
about once a minute. But in those schizophrenics so far tested, the
switching occurs only about every four minutes, an astonishing lag.
This may be part of the explanation of the “segmental set” I have
previously referred to, that schizophrenics tend to “get stuck” on
one hemisphere or the other and so cannot shift from one mode of
information processing to another as fast as the rest of us. Hence
their confusion and often illogical speech and behavior in interaction with us, who switch back and forth at a faster rate.40
39 Arthur Sugarman, L. Goldstein, G. Marjerrison, and N. Stoltyfus, “Recent
Research in EEG Amplitude Analysis,” Diseases of the Nervous System, 1973, 34:
162-181.
40 This is the preliminary work on a few subjects of Leonide E. Goldstein, “Time
Domain Analysis of the EEG: the Integrated Method,” Rutgers Medical School preprint, 1975. I am grateful to him for discussing these suggestions with me.
430
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
• It is possible that the explanation of this slower switching in
schizophrenia is anatomical. A series of autopsies of long-term
schizophrenics have, surprisingly, shown that the corpus callosum
which connects the two hemispheres is i mm. thicker than in normal brains. This is a statistically reliable result. Such a difference
may mean more mutual inhibition of the hemispheres in schizophrenics.41 The anterior commissures in this study were not measured.
• If our theory is true, any extensive dysfunction of the left
temporal cortex due to disease, circulatory changes, or stressinduced alteration of its neurochemistry should release the right
temporal cortex from its normal inhibitory control. When temporal lobe epilepsy is caused by a lesion on the left temporal lobe
(or on both the left and right), thus (presumably) releasing the
right from its normal inhibition, a full 90 percent of the patients
develop paranoid schizophrenia with massive auditory hallucinations. When the lesion is on the right temporal lobe alone, fewer
than 10 percent develop such symptoms. In fact this latter group
tend to develop a manic-depressive psychosis.42
These findings need to be confirmed and explored further. But
together they indicate without doubt and for the first time significant laterality effects in schizophrenia. And the direction of these
effects can be interpreted as partial evidence that schizophrenia
may be related to an earlier organization of the human brain which
I have called the bicameral mind.
In Conclusion
Schizophrenia is one of our most morally prominent problems
of research, such the agony of heart that it spreads both in those
Randall Rosenthal and L. B. Bigelow, “Quantitative Brain Measurements in
Chronic Schizophrenia,” British Journal of Psychiatry, 1972, 121: 259-264.
42 P. Flor-Henry, “Schizophrenic-like Reactions and Affective Psychoses Associated
with Temporal Lohe Epilepsy: Etiological Factors,” American Journal of Psychiatry,
1969, 126: 400—404.
41
SCHIZOPHRENIA
431
afflicted and in those who love them. Recent decades have
watched with gratitude a strong and accelerating improvement in
the way this illness is treated. But this has come about not under
the banners of new and sometimes flamboyant theories such as
mine, but rather in the down-to-earth practical aspects of day-today therapy.
Indeed, theories of schizophrenia — and they are legion — because they have too often been the hobbyhorses of competing
perspectives, have largely defeated themselves. Each discipline
construes the findings of others as secondary to the factors in its
own area. The socio-environmental researcher sees the schizophrenic as the product of a stressful environment. The biochemist insists that the stressful environment has its effect only
because of an abnormal biochemistry in the patient. Those who
speak in terms of information processing say that a deficit in this
area leads directly to stress and counterstress defenses. The
defense-mechanism psychologist views the impaired information
processing as a self-motivated withdrawal from contact with reality. The geneticist makes hereditary interpretations from family
history data. While others might develop interpretations about
the role of schizophrenogenic parental influence from the same
data. And so on. As one critic has expressed it, “Like riding the
merry-go-round, one chooses his horse. One can make believe his
horse leads the rest. Then when a particular ride is finished, one
must step off only to observe that the horse has really gone
nowhere.43
It is thus with some presumption that I add yet one more
loading to this heavy roster. But I have felt impelled to do so, if
only out of responsibility in completing and clarifying the suggestiveness of earlier parts of this book. For schizophrenia, whether
one illness or many, is in its florid stage practically defined by
certain characteristics which we have stated earlier were the
salient characteristics of the bicameral mind. The presence of
43 R. L. Cromwell, “Strategies for Studying Schizophrenic Behavior” (prepublication copy), p. 6.
432
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
auditory hallucinations, their often religious and always authoritative quality, the dissolution of the ego or analog
and of the
mind-space in which it once could narratize out what to do and
where it was in time and action, these are the large resemblances.
But there are great differences as well. If there is any truth to
this hypothesis, the relapse is only partial. The learnings that
make up a subjective consciousness are powerful and never
totally suppressed. And thus the terror and the fury, the agony
and the despair. The anxiety attendant upon so cataclysmic a
change, the dissonance with the habitual structure of interpersonal
relations, and the lack of cultural support and definition for the
voices, making them inadequate guides for everyday living, the
need to defend against a broken dam of environmental sensory
stimulation that is flooding all before it — produce a social withdrawal that is a far different thing from the behavior of the
absolutely social individual of bicameral societies. The conscious
man is constantly using his introspection to find ‘himself’ and to
know where he is, relevant to his purposes and situation. And
without this source of security, deprived of narratization, living
with hallucinations that are unacceptable and denied as unreal
by those around him, the florid schizophrenic is in an opposite
world to that of the god-owned laborers of Marduk or of the idols
of Ur.
The modern schizophrenic is an individual in search of such a
culture. But he retains usually some part of the subjective consciousness that struggles against this more primitive mental organization, that tries to establish some kind of control in the middle
of a mental organization in which the hallucination ought to do
the controlling. In effect, he is a mind bared to his environment,
waiting on gods in a godless world.
CHAPTER 6
The Auguries of Science
I
H A V E T R I E D in these few heterogeneous chapters of Book III to
explain as well as I could how certain features of our recent
world, namely, the social institutions of oracles and religions, and
the psychological phenomena of possession, hypnosis, and
schizophrenia, as well as artistic practices such as poetry and
music, how all these can be interpreted in part as vestiges of an
earlier organization of human nature. These are not in any sense
a complete catalogue of the present possible projections from our
earlier mentality. They are simply some of the most obvious.
And the study of their interaction with the developing consciousness continually laying siege to them allows us an understanding that we would not otherwise have.
In this final chapter, I wish to turn to science itself and point
out that it too, and even my entire essay, can be read as a
response to the breakdown of the bicameral mind. For what is
the nature of this blessing of certainty that science so devoutly
demands in its very Jacob-like wrestling with nature? Why
should we demand that the universe make itself clear to us?
Why do we care?
To be sure, a part of the impulse to science is simple curiosity,
to hold the unheld and watch the unwatched. We are all children
in the unknown. It is no reaction to the loss of an earlier mentality to delight in the revelations of the electron miscroscope or in
quarks or in negative gravity in black holes among the stars.
434
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
Technology is a second and even more sustaining source of the
scientific ritual, carrying its scientific basis forward on its own
increasing and uncontrollable momentum through history. And
perhaps a deep aptic structure for hunting, for bringing a problem to bay, adds its motivational effluence to the pursuit of
truth.
But over and behind these and other causes of science has
been something more universal, something in this age of specialization often unspoken. It is something about understanding the
totality of existence, the essential defining reality of things, the
entire universe and man’s place in it. It is a groping among stars
for final answers, a wandering the infinitesimal for the infinitely
general, a deeper and deeper pilgrimage into the unknown. It is
a direction whose far beginning in the mists of history can be
distantly seen in the search for lost directives in the breakdown of
the bicameral mind.
It is a search that is obvious in the omen literature of Assyria
where, as we saw in II.4, science begins. It is also obvious a mere
half millennium later when Pythagoras in Greece is seeking the
lost invariants of life in a theology of divine numbers and their
relationships, thus beginning the science of mathematics. And so
through two millennia, until, with a motivation not different,
Galileo calls mathematics the speech of God, or Pascal and Leibnitz echo him, saying they hear God in the awesome rectitudes of
mathematics.
We sometimes think, and even like to think, that the two
greatest exertions that have influenced mankind, religion and
science, have always been historical enemies, intriguing us in
opposite directions. But this effort .at special identity is loudly
false. It is not religion but the church and science that were
hostile to each other. And it was rivalry, not contravention. Both
were religious. They were two giants fuming at each other over
the same ground. Both proclaimed to be the only way to divine
revelation.
THE
AUGURIES
OF
SCIENCE
435
It was a competition that first came into absolute focus with
the late Renaissance, particularly in the imprisonment of Galileo
in 1633. The stated and superficial reason was that his publications had not been first stamped with papal approval. But the
true argument, I am sure, was no such trivial surface event. For
the writings in question were simply the Copernican heliocentric
theory of the solar system which had been published a century
earlier by a churchman without any fuss whatever. The real
division was more profound and can, I think, only be understood
as a part of the urgency behind mankind’s yearning for divine
certainties. The real chasm was between the political authority
of the church and the individual authority of experience. And the
real question was whether we are to find our lost authorization
through an apostolic succession from ancient prophets who heard
divine voices, or through searching the heavens of our own experience right now in the objective world without any priestly
intercession. As we all know, the latter became Protestantism
and, in its rationalist aspect, what we have come to call the
Scientific Revolution.
If we would understand the Scientific Revolution correctly, we
should always remember that its most powerful impetus was the
unremitting search for hidden divinity. As such, it is a direct
descendant of the breakdown of the bicameral mind. In the late
seventeenth century, to choose an obvious example, it is three
English Protestants, all amateur theologians and fervently devout, who build the foundations for physics, psychology, and
biology: the paranoiac Isaac Newton writing down God’s speech
in the great universal laws of celestial gravitation j the gaunt and
literal John Locke knowing his Most Knowing Being in the riches
of knowing experience; and the peripatetic John Ray, an unkempt ecclesiastic out of a pulpit, joyfully limning the Word of
his Creator in the perfection of the design of animal and plant
life. Without this religious motivation, science would have been
mere technology, limping along on economic necessity.
The next century is complicated by the rationalism of the
436
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
Enlightenment, whose main force I shall come to in a moment.
But in the great shadow of the Enlightenment, science continued
to be bound up in this spell of the search for divine authorship.
Its most explicit statement came in what was called Deism, or in
Germany, Vernunftreligion. It threw away the church’s “Word,’’
despised its priests, mocked altar and sacrament, and earnestly
preached the reaching of God through reason and science. The
whole universe is an epiphany! God is right out here in Nature
under the stars to be talked with and heard brilliantly in all the
grandeur of reason, rather than behind the rood screens of ignorance in the murky mutterings of costumed priests.
Not that such scientific deists were in universal agreement.
For some, like the apostle-hating Reimarus, the modern founder
of the science of animal behavior, animal triebe or drives were
actually the thoughts of God and their perfect variety his very
mind. Whereas for others, like the physicist. Maupertuis, God
cared little about any such meaningless variety of phenomena; he
lived only in pure abstractions, in the great general laws of
Nature which human reason, with the fine devotions of mathematics, could discern behind such variety.1 Indeed, the toughminded materialist scientist today will feel uncomfortable with
the fact that science in such divergent and various directions only
two centuries ago was a religious endeavor, sharing the same
striving as the ancient psalms, the effort to once again see the
elohim “face to face.”
This drama, this immense scenario in which humanity has
been performing on this planet over the last 4000 years, is clear
when we take the large view of the central intellectual tendency
of world history. In the second millennium B.C., we stopped
hearing the voices of gods. In the first millennium B.C., those of
us who still heard the voices, our oracles and prophets, they too
1 I discuss this more fully in my paper with William Woodward, “In the Shadow
of the Enlightenment,” Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 1974, 10:
3-15, 144-159.
THE
AUGURIES
OF
SCIENCE
437
died away. In the first millennium A.D., it is their sayings and
hearings preserved in sacred texts through which we obeyed our
lost divinities. And in the second millennium A.D., these writings
lose their authority. The Scientific Revolution turns us away
from the older sayings to discover the lost authorization in
Nature. What we have been through in these last four millennia
is the slow inexorable profaning of our species. And in the last
part of the second millennium A.D., that process is apparently
becoming complete. It is the Great Human Irony of our noblest
and greatest endeavor on this planet that in the quest for authorization, in our reading of the language of God in Nature, we should
read there so clearly that we have been so mistaken.
This secularization of science, which is now a plain fact, is
certainly rooted in the French Enlightenment which I have just
alluded to. But it became rough and earnest in 1842 in Germany
in a famous manifesto by four brilliant young physiologists.
They signed it like pirates, actually in their own blood. Fed up
with Hegelian idealism and its pseudoreligious interpretations of
material matters, they angrily resolved that no forces other than
common physicochemical ones would be considered in their scientific activity. No spiritual entities. No divine substances. No
vital forces. This was the most coherent and shrill statement of
scientific materialism up to that time. And enormously influential.
Five years later, one of their group, the famous physicist and
psychologist Hermann von Helmholtz, proclaimed his Principle
of the Conservation of Energy. Joule had said it more kindly,
that “the Great Agents of Nature are indestructible,” that sea and
sun and coal and thunder and heat and wind are one energy and
eternal. But Helmholtz abhorred the mush of the Romantic. His
mathematical treatment of the principle coldly placed the emphasis where it has been ever since: there are no outside forces
in our closed world of energy transformations. There is no corner
438
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
in the stars for any god, no crack in this closed universe of matter
for any divine influence to seep through, none whatever.
All this might have respectfully stayed back simply as a mere
working tenet for Science, had it not been for an even more
stunning profaning of the idea of the holy in human affairs that
followed immediately. It was particularly stunning because it
came from within the very ranks of religiously motivated science.
In Britain since the seventeenth century, the study of what was
called “natural history” was commonly the consoling joy of finding the perfections of a benevolent Creator in nature. What more
devastation could be heaped upon these tender motivations and
consolations than the twin announcement by two of their own
midst, Darwin and Wallace, both amateur naturalists in the
grand manner, that it was evolution, not a divine intelligence,
that has created all nature. This too had been put earlier in a
kindlier way by others, such as Darwin’s grandfather, Erasmus
Darwin, or Lamarck, or Robert Chambers, or even in the exaltations of an Emerson or a Goethe. But the new emphasis was
dazzling strong and unrelieving. Cold Uncalculating Chance, by
making some able to survive better in this wrestle for life, and so
to reproduce more, generation after generation, has blindly, even
cruelly, carved this human species out of matter, mere matter.
When combined with German materialism, as it was in the
wantonly abrasive Huxley, as we saw in the Introduction to this
essay, the theory of evolution by natural selection was the hollowing knell of all that ennobling tradition of man as the purposed
creation of Majestic Greatnesses, the elohim, tnat goes straight
back into the unconscious depths of the Bicameral Age. It said in
a word that there is no authorization from outside. Behold! there
is nothing there. What we must do must come from ourselves.
The king at Eynan can stop staring at Mount Hermon; the dead
king can die at last. We, we fragile human species at the end of
the second millennium A.D., we must become our own authorization. And here at the end of the second millennium and about
to enter the third, we are surrounded with this problem. It is one
THE
AUGURIES
OF
SCIENCE
439
that the new millennium will be working out, perhaps slowly,
perhaps swiftly, perhaps even with some further changes in our
mentality.
The erosion of the religious view of man in these last years of
the second millennium is still a part of the breakdown of the
bicameral mind. It is slowly working serious changes in every
fold and field of life. In the competition for membership among
religious bodies today, it is the older orthodox positions, ritually
closer to the long apostolic succession into the bicameral past,
that are most diminished by conscious logic. The changes in the
Catholic Church since Vatican II can certainly be scanned in
terms of this long retreat from the sacred which has followed the
inception of consciousness into the human species. The decay of
religious collective cognitive imperatives under the pressures of
rationalist science, provoking, as it does, revision after revision of
traditional theological concepts, cannot sustain the metaphoric
meaning behind ritual. Rituals are behavioral metaphors, belief
acted, divination foretold, exopsychic thinking. Rituals are
mnemonic devices for the great narratizations at the heart of
church life. And when they are emptied out into cults of spontaneity and drained of their high seriousness, when they are acted
unfelt and reasoned at with irresponsible objectivity, the center is
gone and the widening gyres begin. The result in this age of
communications has been worldwide: liturgy loosened into the
casual, awe softening in relevance, and the washing out of that
identity-giving historical definition that told man what he was
and what he should be. These sad temporizings, often begun by a
bewildered clergy,2 do but encourage the great historical tide
they are designed to deflect. Our paralogical compliance to verb2 Theologians are well aware of these problems. To enter into their discussions,
one might start with Harvey Cox’s The Secular City and then Mary Douglas’
Natural Symbolsy and then Charles Davis’ “Ghetto or Desert: Liturgy in a Cultural
Dilemma,” in Worship and Secularization, ed. Wiebe (Vos, Holland: Bussum, 1970),
pp. 10-27, and follow that with James Hitchcock’s The Recovery of the Sacred
(New York: Seabury Press, 1974).
440 Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
ally mediated reality is diminished: we crash into chairs in our
way, not go around them; we will be mute rather than say we do
not understand our speech ; we will insist on simple location. It is
the divine tragedy or the profane comedy depending on whether
we would be purged of the past or quickened into the future.
What happens in this modern dissolution of ecclesiastical
authorization reminds us a little of what happened long ago after
the breakdown of the bicameral mind itself. Everywhere in the
contemporary world there are substitutes, other methods of authorization. Some are revivals of ancient ones: the popularity of
possession religions in South America, where the church had
once been so strong; extreme religious absolutism ego-based on
“the Spirit,” which is really the ascension of Paul over Jesus;
an alarming rise in the serious acceptance of astrology, that
direct heritage from the period of the breakdown of the bicameral
mind in the Near East; or the more minor divination of the I
Ching, also a direct heritage from the period just after the breakdown in China. There are also the huge commercial and sometimes psychological successes of various meditation procedures,
sensitivity training groups, mind control, and group encounter
practices. Other persuasions often seem like escapes from a new
boredom of unbelief, but are also characterized by this search
for authorization: faiths in various pseudosciences, as in Scientology, or in unidentified flying objects bringing authority
from other parts of our universe, or that gods were at one time
actually such visitors; or the stubborn muddled fascination with
extrasensory perception as a supposed demonstration of a spiritual surround of our lives whence some authorization might
come; or the use of psychotropic drugs as ways of contacting
profounder realities, as they were for most of the American
native Indian civilizations in the breakdown of their bicameral
mind. Just as we saw in III.2 that the collapse of the institutionalized oracles resulted in smaller cults of induced possession,
so the waning of institutional religions is resulting in these
THE
AUGURIES
OF
SCIENCE
441
smaller, more private religions of every description. And this
historical process can be expected to increase the rest of this
century.
Nor can we say that modern science itself is exempt from a
similar patterning. For the modern intellectual landscape is informed with the same needs, and often in its larger contours goes
through the same quasi-religious gestures, though in a slightly
disguised form. These scientisms, as I shall call them, are
clusters of scientific ideas which come together and almost surprise themselves into creeds of belief, scientific mythologies
which fill the very felt void left by the divorce of science and
religion in our time.3 They differ from classical science and its
common debates in the way they evoke the same response as did
the religions which they seek to supplant. And they share with
religions many of their most obvious characteristics: a rational
splendor that explains everything, a charismatic leader or succession of leaders who are highly visible and beyond criticism, a
series of canonical texts which are somehow outside the usual
arena of scientific criticism, certain gestures of idea and rituals
of interpretation, and a requirement of total commitment. In
return the adherent receives what the religions had once given
him more universally: a world view, a hierarchy of importances,
and an auguring place where he may find out what to do and
think, in short, a total explanation of man. And this totality is
obtained not by actually explaining everything, but by an encasement of its activity, a severe and absolute restriction of attention,
such that everything that is not explained is not in view.
The materialism I have just mentioned was one of the first
such scientisms. Scientists in the middle of the nineteenth century were almost numbed with excitement by dramatic discoveries of how nutrition could change the bodies and minds of
3 George Steiner in his articulate Massey Lectures of 1974 called these “mythologies” and discussed the point at greater length. I have borrowed some of his phrasing.
442
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
men. And so it became a movement called Medical Materialism,
identified with relieving poverty and pain, taking to itself some of
the forms and all of the fervor of the religions eroding around it.
It captured the most exciting minds of its generation, and its
program sounds distantly familiar: education, not prayers; nutrition, not communion; medicine, not love; and politics, not
preaching.
Distantly familiar because Medical Materialism, still haunted
with Hegel, matured in Marx and Engels into dialectical materialism, gathering to itself even more of the ecclesiastical forms of
the outworn faiths around it. Its central superstition then, as
now, is that of the class struggle, a kind of divination which gives
a total explanation of the past and predecides what to do in every
office and alarm of life. And even though ethnicism, nationalism,
and unionism, those collective identity markers of modern man,
have long ago showed the mythical character of the class struggle,
still Marxism today is joining armies of millions into battle to
erect the most authoritarian states the world has ever seen.
In the medical sciences, the most prominent scientism, I think,
has been psychoanalysis. Its central superstition is repressed
childhood sexuality. The handful of early cases of hysteria which
could be so interpreted become the metaphiers by which to
understand all personality and art, all civilization and its discontents. And it too, like Marxism, demands total commitment,
initiation procedures, a worshipful relation to its canonical texts,
and gives in return that same assistance in decision and direction
in life which a few centuries ago was the province of religion.
And, to take an example closer to my own tradition, I will add
behaviorism. For it too has its central auguring place in a handful of rat and pigeon experiments, making them the metaphiers
of all behavior and history. It too gives to the individual adherent
the talisman of control by reinforcement contingencies by which
he is to meet his world and understand its vagaries. And even
though the radical environmentalism behind it, of belief in a
tabula rasa organism that can be built up into anything by rein-
THE
AUGURIES
OF
SCIENCE
443
forcement has long been known to be questionable, given the
biologically evolved aptic structuring of each organism, these principles still draw adherents into the hope of a new society based
upon such control.
Of course these scientisms about man begin with something
that is true. That nutrition can improve health both of mind and
body is true. The class struggle as Marx studied it in the France
of Louis Napoleon was a fact. The relief of hysterical symptoms
in a few patients by analysis of sexual memories probably happened. And hungry animals or anxious men certainly will learn
instrumental responses for food or approbation. These are true
facts. But so is the shape of a liver of a sacrificed animal a true
fact. And so the Ascendants and Midheavens of astrologers, or
the shape of oil on water. Applied to the world as representative
of all the world, facts become superstitions. A superstition is after
all only a metaphier grown wild to serve a need to know. Like the
entrails of animals or the flights of birds, such scientistic superstitions become the preserved ritualized places where we may
read out the past and future of man, and hear the answers that
can authorize our actions.
Science then, for all its pomp of factness, is not unlike some of
the more easily disparaged outbreaks of pseudoreligions. In this
period of transition from its religious basis, science often shares
with the celestial maps of astrology, or a hundred other irrationalisms, the same nostalgia for the Final Answer, the One Truth, the
Single Cause. In the frustrations and sweat of laboratories, it
feels the same temptations to swarm into sects, even as did the
Khabiru refugees, and set out here and there through the dry
Sinais of parched fact for some rich and brave significance flowing with truth and exaltation. And all of this, my metaphor and
all, is a part of this transitional period after the breakdown of
the bicameral mind.
And this essay is no exception.
*
*
*
444
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
Curiously, none of these contemporary movements tells us anything about what we are supposed to be like after the wrinkles in
our nutrition have been ironed smooth, or “the withering away of
the state” has occurred, or our libidos have been properly
cathected, or the chaos of reinforcements has been made
straight. Instead their allusion is mostly backward, telling us
what has gone wrong, hinting of some cosmic disgrace, some
earlier stunting of our potential. It is, I think, yet another characteristic of the religious form which such movements have taken
over in the emptiness caused by the retreat of ecclesiastical certainty — that of a supposed fall of man.
This strange and, I think, spurious idea of a lost innocence
takes its mark precisely in the breakdown of the bicameral mind
as the first great conscious narratization of mankind. It is the
song of the Assyrian psalms, the wail of the Hebrew hymns, the
myth of Eden, the fundamental fall from divine favor that is the
source and first premise of the world’s great religions. I interpret
this hypothetical fall of man to be the groping of newly conscious
men to narratize what has happened to them, the loss of divine
voices and assurances in a chaos of human directive and selfish
privacies.
We see this theme of lost certainty and splendor not only
stated by all the religions of man throughout history, but also
again and again even in nonreligious intellectual history. It is
there from the reminiscence theory of the Platonic Dialogues,
that everything new is really a recalling of a lost better world, all
the way to Rousseau’s complaint of the corruption of natural man
by the artificialities of civilization. And we see it also in the
modern scientisms I have mentioned: in Marx’s assumption of a
lost “social childhood of mankind where mankind unfolds in
complete beauty,” so clearly stated in his earlier writings, an
innocence corrupted by money, a paradise to be regained. Or in
the Freudian emphasis on the deep-seatedness of neurosis in
civilization and of dreadful primordial acts and wishes in both
THE
AUGURIES
OF
SCIENCE
445
our racial and individual pasts; and by inference a previous innocence, quite unspecified, to which we return through psychoanalysis. Or in behaviorism, if less distinctly, in the undocumented
faith that it is the chaotic reinforcements of development and the
social process that must be controlled and ordered to return man
to a quite unspecified ideal before these reinforcements had
twisted his true nature awry.
I therefore believe that these and many other movements of
our time are in the great long picture of our civilizations related
to the loss of an earlier organization of human natures. They are
attempts to return to what is no longer there, like poets to their
inexistent Muses, and as such they are characteristic of these transitional millennia in which we are imbedded.
I do not mean that the individual thinker, the reader of this
page or its writer, or Galileo or Marx, is so abject a creature as to
have any conscious articulate willing to reach either the absolutes
of gods or to return to a preconscious innocence. Such terms are
meaningless applied to individual lives and removed from the
larger context of history. It is only if we make generations our
persons and centuries hours that the pattern is clear.
As individuals we are at the mercies of our own collective
imperatives. We see over our everyday attentions, our gardens
and politics, and children, into the forms of our culture darkly.
And our culture is our history. In our attempts to communicate
or to persuade or simply interest others, we are using and moving
about through cultural models among whose differences we may
select, but from whose totality we cannot escape. And it is in this
sense of the forms of appeal, of begetting hope or interest or
appreciation or praise for ourselves or for our ideas, that our
communications are shaped into these historical patterns, these
grooves of persuasion which are even in the act of communication an inherent part of what is communicated. And this essay is
no exception.
446
Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World
No exception at all. It began in what seemed in my personal
narratizations as an individual choice of a problem with which I
have had an intense involvement for most of my life: the problem of the nature and origin of all this invisible country of
touchless rememberings and unshowable reveries, this introcosm
that is more myself than anything I can find in any mirror. But
was this impulse to discover the source of consciousness what it appeared to me? The very notion of truth is a culturally given
direction, a part of the pervasive nostalgia for an earlier certainty. The very idea of a universal stability, an eternal firmness
of principle out there that can be sought for through the world as
might an Arthurian knight for the Grail, is, in the morphology of
history, a direct outgrowth of the search for lost gods in the first
two millennia after the decline of the bicameral mind. What was
then an augury for direction of action among the ruins of an archaic mentality is now the search for an innocence of certainty
among the mythologies of facts.
AFTERWORD
I
T IS NOW more than a decade since this essay first appeared in
book form, and my publishers have encouraged me to add a postscript in which I might discuss the general reaction to this book as
well as changes I might make if I were to rewrite it.
A favorite practice of some professional intellectuals when at first
faced with a theory as large as the one I have presented is to search
for that loose thread which, when pulled, will unravel all the rest.
And rightly so. It is part of the discipline of scientific thinking. In
any work covering so much of the terrain of human nature and
history, hustling into territories jealously guarded by myriad
aggressive specialists, there are bound to be such errancies, sometimes of fact but I fear more often of tone. But that the knitting of
this book is such that a tug on such a bad stitch will unravel all the
rest is more of a hope on the part of the orthodox than a fact in the
scientific pursuit of truth. The book is not a single hypothesis.
There are four main hypotheses in Books I and II. I welcome
this opportunity to add some comments to each of them.
1. Consciousness is based on language. Such a statement is of
course contradictory to the usual and I think superficial views of
consciousness that are embedded both in popular belief and in language. But there can be no progress in the science of consciousness
until careful distinctions have been made between what is introspectable and all the hosts of other neural abilities we have come
to call cognition. Consciousness is not the same as cognition and
should be sharply distinguished from it.
The most common error which I did not emphasize sufficiently
is to confuse consciousness with perception. Recently, at a meeting
of the Society for Philosophy and Psychology, a well-known and
448
Afterword
prestigious philosopher stood up to object vociferously on this
point. Looking at me directly, he exclaimed, “I am perceiving you
at this moment. Are you trying to say that I am not conscious of
you at this moment?” A collective cognitive imperative in him
was proclaiming in the affirmative. But actually he was being conscious of the rhetorical argument he was making. He could have
better been conscious of me if he had turned away from me or had
closed his eyes.
This type of confusion was at least encouraged back in 1921 by
Bertrand Russell: “ W e are conscious of anything that we perceive.” 1 And as his logical atomism became fashionable in philosophy, it became difficult to see it any other way. And in a later book
Russell uses as an example of consciousness “I see a table.” 2 But
Descartes, who gave us the modern idea of consciousness, would
never have agreed. Nor would a radical behaviorist like Watson,
who in denying consciousness existed certainly did not mean sense
perception.
Just as in the case I mentioned above, I suggest Russell was not
being conscious of the table, but of the argument he was writing
about. In my own notation, I would diagram the situation as
Russell thought his consciousness was the second term, but in
reality it was the entire expression. He should have found a more
ethologically valid example that was really true of his consciousness, that had really happened, such as, “I think I will rewrite the
Principa now that Whitehead’s dead” or “How can I afford the
alimony for another Lady Russell?” He would then have come
to other conclusions. Such examples are consciousness in action.
“I see a table” is not.
Perception is sensing a stimulus and responding appropriately.
And this can happen on a nonconscious level, as I have tried to
describe in driving a car. Another way to look at the problem is to
1 Bertrand Russell, Analysts of Mind
2 Bertrand Russell, Philosophy
(London: Allen and Unwin, 192-1).
(New York: Norton, 1927).
Afterword
449
remember the behavior of white blood cells, which certainly perceive bacteria and respond appropriately by devouring them. To
equate consciousness with perception is thus tantamount to saying
that we have six thousand conscious entities per cubic millimeter of
blood whirling around in our circulatory system — which I think is
a reductio ad absurdum.
Consciousness is not all language, but it is generated by it and
accessed by it. And when we begin to untease the fine reticulation
of how language generates consciousness we are on a very difficult
level of theorizing. The primordial mechanisms by which this
happens in history I have outlined briefly and then in II:5 tried
to show how this worked out in the development of consciousness
in Greece. Consciousness then becomes embedded in language
and so is learned easily by children. The general rule is: there is
no operation in consciousness that did not occur in behavior first.
To briefly review, if we refer to the circle triangle problem on
page 40, in solving this struction we say, “I ‘see’ it’s a triangle,”
though of course we are not actually seeing anything. In the struction of finding how to express this solving of the problem, the
metaphor of actual seeing pops into our minds. Perhaps there
could be other metaphiers3 leading to a different texture of consciousness, but in Western culture ‘seeing’ and the other words
with which we try to anchor mental events are indeed visual. And
by using this word ‘see’, we bring with it its paraphiers, or associates of actual seeing.
In this way the spatial quality of the world around us is being
driven into the psychological fact of solving a problem (which as
we remember needs no consciousness). And it is this associated
spatial quality that, as a result of the language we use to describe
such psychological events, becomes with constant repetitions this
3 My friend W. V. Quine strenuously objects to my metaphrand-metaphier coinage
because they are hybrids of Latin and Greek. I have opted to keep them however for
their connotative association with multiplicand and multiplier. He has made the interesting suggestion that perhaps this distinction is related to the latent-manifest distinction of psychoanalysis. Are dreams metaphors? Is what Freud called the unconscious
actually the latent metaphrand operated on by the manifest metaphier?
450
Afterword
functional space of our consciousness, or mind-space. Mind-space
I regard as the primary feature of consciousness. It is the space
which you preoptively are ‘introspecting on’ or ‘seeing’ at this very
moment.
But who does the ‘seeing’? Who does the introspecting? Here
we introduce analogy, which differs from metaphor in that the
similarity is between relationships rather than between things or
actions. As the body with its sense organs (referred to as I) is to
physical seeing, so there develops automatically an analog ‘I’ to
relate to this mental kind of ‘seeing’ in mind-space. The analog
‘I’ is the second most important feature of consciousness. It is not
to be confused with the self, which is an object of consciousness in
later development. The analog ‘I’ is contentless, related I think
to Kant’s transcendental ego. As the bodily I can move about in
its environment looking at this or that, so the analog ‘I’ learns to
‘move about’ in mind-space, ‘attending to’ or concentrating on one
thing or another.
A l l the procedures of consciousness are based on such metaphors
and analogies with behavior, constructing a careful matrix of considerable stability. And so we narratize the analogic simulation of
actual behavior, an obvious aspect of consciousness which seems
to have escaped previous synchronic discussions of consciousness.
Consciousness is constantly fitting things into a story, putting a
before and an after around any event. This feature is an analog
of our physical selves moving about through a physical world with
its spatial successiveness which becomes the successiveness of time
in mind-space. And this results in the conscious conception of time
which is a spatialized time in which we locate events and indeed
our lives. It is impossible to be conscious of time in any other way
than as a space.
T h e basic connotative definition of consciousness is thus an analog ‘I’ narratizing in a functional mind-space. The denotative
definition is, as it was for Descartes, Locke, and Hume, what is
introspectable.
Afterword
451
My list of features is not meant to be exhaustive or exclusive.
Nor are they meant to be universal aspects of consciousness everywhere. Given the great cultural differences in the world today,
just as in the world’s past, it seems to me unreasonable to think
that the features and emphases of consciousness would be everywhere the same.
As it stands, the list I have given is I think incomplete. At least
two other features should be added: concentration, which is the
analog of sensory attention,4 and suppression, by which we stop being conscious of annoying thoughts, the behavioral analog of repugnance, disgust, or simply turning away from annoyances in the
physical world.
I would also take this opportunity of commenting on what is
called in this book conciliation or compatibilization, which have
perplexed some readers. At the risk of even more confusion, I
would change this word to consilience, which is Whewell’s better
term for my intended meaning of mental processes that make
things compatible with each other.5 While this is not so obvious
in waking life, it becomes extremely important in dreams. Originally, I had written two chapters on dreams to go in the present
volume, but my publishers suggested that because of the length of
the book, it seemed more reasonable to save them for the next
volume, which I hope will appear in several years.6
Psychologists are sometimes justly accused of the habit of reinventing the wheel and making it square and then calling it a first
approximation. I would demur from agreement that that is true
in the development that I have just outlined, but I would indeed
like to call it a first approximation. Consciousness is not a simple
4 It would be interesting to see experimentally if training in accurate and fast attention resulted in better concentration in tasks when tested with distraction.
5 William Whewell, Theory of Scientific Method (1858), ed. R. E. Butts (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1968).
6 For readers who would like an abstract of how this theory translates into dreams,
I would suggest that they read my Bauer Symposium lecture in Canadian Psychology,
1986, 27:128-182, particularly pages 146 and 147.
452
Afterword
matter and it should not be spoken of as if it were. Nor have I
mentioned the different modes of conscious narratization such as
verbal (having imaginary conversations — certainly the most common mode in myself), perceptual (imagining scenes), behavioral
(imagining ourselves doing something), physiological (monitoring our fatigue or discomfort or appetite), or musical (imagining
music), all of which seem quite distinct, with properties of their
own. Such modes have obviously different neural substrates, indicating the complexity of any possible neurology of consciousness.
2. The bicameral mind. The second main hypothesis is that
preceding consciousness there was a different mentality based on
verbal hallucinations. For this I think the evidence is overwhelming. Wherever we look in antiquity, there is some kind of evidence
that supports it, either in literary texts or in archeological artifacts.
Apart from this theory, why are there gods? Why religions?
W h y does all ancient literature seem to be about gods and usually
heard from gods?
And why do we have verbal hallucinations at all? Before the
publication of this book, verbal hallucinations were not paid much
attention to, except as the primary indicator of schizophrenia. But
since that time, a flurry of studies have shown that the incidence of
verbal hallucinations is far more widespread than was thought
previously. Roughly one third of normal people hear hallucinated voices at some time. Children hear voices from their imaginary or we should say hallucinated playmates. It has recently
been discovered that congenital quadriplegics who have never in
their lives spoken or moved, and are often regarded as “vegetables,“ not only understand language perfectly but also hear voices
they regard as God.7 The importance I put on these studies taken
together is that they clearly indicate to me that there is a genetic
7 John Hamilton, “Auditory Hallucinations in Nonverbal Quadriplegics,” Psychiatry,
1985, 48’.382-392. For other work on verbal hallucinations, see my “Verbal Hallucinations and Preconscious Mentality,” in Manfred Spitzer and Brendan H. Maher, eds.,
Philosophy and Psychofathology (New York: Springer Verlag, 1990), pp. 157-170.
Afterword
453
basis for such hallucinations in us all, and that it was probably
evolved into the human genome back in the late Pleistocene, and
then became the basis for the bicameral mind.
3. The dating. The third general hypothesis is that consciousness was learned only after the breakdown of the bicameral mind.
I believe this is true, that the anguish of not knowing what to do
in the chaos resulting from the loss of the gods provided the social
conditions that could result in the invention of a new mentality to
replace the old one.
But actually there are two possibilities here. A weak form of
the theory would state that, yes, consciousness is based on language, but instead of its being so recent, it began back at the beginning of language, perhaps even before civilization, say, about
12,000 B.C., at about the time of the beginning of the bicameral
mentality of hearing voices. Both systems of mind then could
have gone on together until the bicameral mind became unwieldy
and was sloughed off, leaving consciousness on its own as the medium of human decisions. This is an extremely weak position
because it could then explain almost anything and is almost
undisprovable.
The strong form is of greater interest and is as I have stated
it in introducing the concept of the bicameral mind. It sets an
astonishingly recent date for the introduction into the world of
this remarkable privacy of covert events which we call consciousness. The date is slightly different in different parts of the world,
but in the Middle East, where bicameral civilization began, the
date is roughly 1000 B.C.
This dating I think can be seen in the evidence from Mesopotamia, where the breakdown of the bicameral mind, beginning
about 1200 B.C., is quite clear. It was due to chaotic social disorganizations, to overpopulation, and probably to the success of
writing in replacing the auditory mode of command. This breakdown resulted in many practices we would now call religious which
were efforts to return to the lost voices of the gods, e.g., prayer,
454
Afterword
religious worship, and particularly the many types of divination I
have described, which are new ways of making decisions by supposedly returning to the directions of gods by simple analogy.
I would not now make as much of the Thera explosion as I did
in II.3. But that it did cause the disruption of theocracy in the
Near East and hence the conditions for the learning of a nonhallucinatory mentality is I think valid. But in the general case, I
would rather emphasize that the success of a theocratic agricultural civilization brings with it overpopulation and thus the seeds
of its own breakdown. This is suggested at least among the civilizations of Mesoamerica, where the relative rapidity of the rise and
fall of civilizations with the consequent desertion of temple complexes contrasts with the millennia-long civilizations in the older
parts of the world.
But is this consciousness or the concept of consciousness? This
is the well-known use-mention criticism which has been applied
to Hobbes and others as well as to the present theory. Are we not
confusing here the concept of consciousness with consciousness
itself? My reply is that we are fusing them, that they are the
same. As Dan Dennett has pointed out in a recent discussion of the
theory,8 there are many instances of mention and use being identical. The concept of baseball and baseball are the same thing. Or
of money, or law, or good and evil. Or the concept of this book.
4. The double brain. When in any discussion or even in our
thinking we can use spatial terms, as in “locating” a problem or
“situating” a difficulty in an argument, as if everything in existence
were spread out like land before us, we seem to get a feeling of
clarity. This pseudo-clarity, as it should be called, is because of
the spatial nature of consciousness. So in locating functions in different parts of the brain we seem to get an extra surge of clarity
about them — justified or not.
At the time I was writing that part of the book in the 1960s,
8 Daniel
Dennett, “Julian Jaynes” Software Archeology,” Canadian Psychology,
1986, 27:149-154.
Afterword
455
there was little interest in the right hemisphere. Even as late as
1964, some leading neuroscientists were saying that the right
hemisphere did nothing, suggesting it was like a spare tire. But
since then we have seen an explosion of findings about right hemisphere function, leading, I am afraid, to a popularization that
verges on some of the shrill excesses of similar discussions of
asymmetrical hemisphere function in the latter part of the nineteenth century9 and also in the twentieth century.10
But the main results, even conservatively treated, are generally
in agreement with what we might expect to find in the right hemisphere on the basis of the bicameral hypothesis. The most significant such finding is that the right hemisphere is the hemisphere
which processes information in a synthetic manner. It is now well
known from even more studies that the right hemisphere is far
superior to the left in fitting together block designs (Kohs Block
Design Test), parts of faces, or musical chords,11 and such synthetic functions were indeed those of the admonitory gods in fitting
together civilizations.
The reader has by now guessed that a somewhat crucial experiment is possible. Since I have supposed that the verbal hallucinations heard by schizophrenics and others are similar to those once
heard by bicameral people, could we not test out this cerebral location in the right temporal lobe of the voices by one of the new
brain imaging techniques, using patients as they are hallucinating?
This has recently been tried using cerebral glucography with positron tomography, a very difficult procedure. Indeed, the results
demonstrated that there was more glucose uptake (showing more
9 Anne
Harrington, “Nineteenth Century Ideas on Hemisphere Differences and
‘Duality of Mind,’ ” Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 1985, 8:517—659, or her excellent enlarged study, Medicine, Mind, and the Double Brain (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1987).
10 S. J. Segalowitz, Two Sides of the Brain (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall,
1983).
11 M. P. Bryden, Laterality: Functional Asymmetry in the Intact Brain (New York:
Academic Press, 1982).
456
Afterword
activity) in the right temporal lobe when the patient was hearing
voices.12
I wish to emphasize that these four hypotheses are separable.
The last, for example, could be mistaken (at least in the simplified
version I have presented) and the others true. The two hemispheres of the brain are not the bicameral mind but its present
neurological model. The bicameral mind is an ancient mentality
demonstrated in the literature and artifacts of antiquity.
The last line of Book III sounds indeed like a ponderous finality
of judgment. It is. But it is also the beginning, the opening up of
human nature as we know it and feel it profoundly because consciously in ourselves, with all its vicissitudes, clarities, and obscurities. Because of the documentation, we can see this most clearly in
Greece in the first half of the first millennium B.C., where the
change can truly be called
The Cognitive Explosion.
With consciousness comes an increased importance of the spatialization of time and new words for that spatialization, like
chronos. But that is to put it too mildly. It is a cognitive explosion
with the interaction of consciousness and the rest of cognition producing new abilities. Whereas bicameral beings knew what followed what and where they were, and had behavioral expectancies
and sensory recognitions just as all mammals do, now conscious,
humans can ‘look’ into an imagined future with all its potential of
terror, joy, hope, or ambition, just as if it were already real, and
into a past moody with what might have been, or savoring what
did, the past emerging through the metaphier of a space through
12 M. S. Buchsbaum, D. H. Ingvar, R. Kessler, R. N. Waters, J. Cappelletti, D. P.
van Kammen, A. C. King, J. L. Johnson, R. G. Manning, R. W. Flynn, L. S. Mann,
W. E. Bunney, and L. Sokoloff, “Cerebral Glucography with Positron Tomography:
Use in Normal Subjects and in Patients with Schizophrenia,” Archives of General Psychiatry, 1982, 39:251-259.
Afterword
457
whose long shadows we may move in a new and magical process
called remembrance or reminiscence.
Reminiscent memory (or episodic memory, as it is sometimes
called), 13 in sharp contrast to habit retention (or semantic memory), is new to the world with consciousness. And because a
physical space in the world can always be returned to, so we feel
irrationally, somehow certain, impossibly certain, that we should
be able to return again to some often unfinished relationship, some
childhood scene or situation or regretted outburst of love or temper
or to undo some tragic chance action back in the imagined inexistent space of the past.
We thus have conscious lives and lifetimes and can peer through
the murk of tomorrow toward our own dying. With the prodding of Heraclitus in the sixth century B.C.,14 we invent new
words or really modifications of old words to name processes or
symbolize actions over time by adding the suffix sis and so be conscious of them, words in Greek like gnosis, a knowing; genesis, a
beginning; emphasis, a showing in; analysis, a loosening up; or
particularly phronesis, which is variously translated as intellection,
thinking, understanding, or consciousness. These words and the
processes they refer to are new in the sixth and seventh centuries B.C. 1 5
The Self
Along this new lifetime, putting together similar occurrences or
excerpts of them — inferences from what others tell us we are and
from what we can tell ourselves on the basis of our own conscious13 Endel Tulving, Elements of Episodic Memory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983).
14 Howard Jones, “-Sis Nouns in Heraclitus,” Museum Africum, 1974, 3:1-13. I
am grateful to Professor Jones for discussion on this point.
15 This has been noted and emphasized by several classical scholars including Bruno
Snell, speaking of “a new ‘mental’ concord that apparently was not possible before the
seventh century when a new dimension of the intellect is opened.” Cited by Joseph
Russo in “The Inner Man in Archilochus and the Odyssey,” Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies, 1974, 25:139, n. 1, who prefers an earlier date for this transformation, as
his title indicates.
458
Afterword
ness of what we have done — we come to construct or invent, on a
continuing basis, in ourselves and in others, a self. The advantage
of an idea of your self is to help you know what you can or can’t do
or should or should not do. Bicameral individuals had stable identities, names to which they or others could attach epithets, but such
verbal identity is a far shallower form of behavior than the consciously constructed although variable, fragile, and defensive self
that shakily pilots us through the alternatives of living consciously.
Particularly with regard to the self, but also in all of the treacherous terminology of mind, we must beware of the perils of polysemy or homonymic or multireferential confusion, as I have called
it elsewhere. This results from the historical growth and inner
alterations of most mental terms; the referrent of a term changes
usually with the addition of new conscious referrents until the term
is really multireferential. “ S e l f “ is a good example. Originally,
the word (or corresponding word in whatever language) probably
was simply used as an identity marker as in all its many compounds: self-employed, self-discipline, etc. Or as when we say a
fly washes itself. But with the fractal-like proliferation and intensification of consciousness through history, particularly since the
twelfth century A.D., a very different referrent of “self“ came into
existence. It is the answer to the question “ W h o am I ? ” Most
social psychologists accept that denotation of self.
Thus, as John Locke somewhere says,16 if we cut off a finger,
we have not diminished the self. The body is not the self. An
early critic of my book pointed to the well-known fact that mirrors
were used far back into antiquity17 and therefore such ancient
But see Locke’s profoundly modern discussion in Essay on the Human Understanding, II:10-29.
17 Exactly the significance of such mirrors is a question. In the archeological museum
in Riyadh, Saudi Arabia, I have seen an ancient tombstone with the outline of a lady
holding such a mirror. Would this be vanity? Were mirrors hand idols which were
common in bicameral Mesopotamia? The mystery of the use of mirrors in Mayan
iconography should also be noted, as it usually represents a god or the brightness of a
god. See Linda Schele and Mary Ellen Miller, The Blood of Kings (Fort Worth:
Kimbell Art Museum, 1986).
16
Afterword
459
peoples were conscious. But we don’t see our selves in mirrors,
although we say so; we see our faces. The face is not the self.
Because of the importance of this confusion and its frequency
in misunderstanding my book, I would like here to describe a few
other studies briefly. When presented with mirrors, most fish,
birds, or mammals react with complete disinterest or else engage
in social or aggressive displays or attack their mirror images. But
humans and chimpanzees are different: they like mirrors. Human
children go through four stages of behavior with respect to their
mirror images. At first there is little reaction, then smiling, touching, vocalizing as if it were another child, then a stage of testing
or repetitive activity while observing the mirror image intently,
and then, when the child is almost two years old, the adult reaction
to the image as if it were its own.18 The test for this final stage
has been to smear rouge on the child’s nose and then have the child
look in a mirror and see if the child touches its nose — which it
readily does by age two.19
But the real interest in this phenomenon began when Gallup
showed that the same effect could be obtained with chimpanzees.20
Chimpanzees after extensive experience with mirrors were put
under deep anesthesia. Then a conspicuous spot of red dye was
daubed on the brow or top half of an ear. Upon awakening, the
chimpanzees paid no attention to the markings, showing that no
local tactile stimulation was present. But when a mirror was provided, the chimpanzees, who by now were very familiar with their
mirror images, immediately reached for the color spot to rub or
pick it off, showing they knew the mirror images of themselves.
Other chimpanzees that had had no experience with mirrors did
not react in this way. Hence it was claimed that chimpanzees have
selves and self-recognition. Or, in the words of one of the major
18 J. C. Dixon, “Development of Self-recognition,” Journal of Genetic Psychology,
1957, 91:251-256.
19 B. K. Amsterdam, “Mirror Self-image Reactions Before Age Two,” Developmental Psychobiology, 1972, 5:297-305.
20 G. G. Gallup, “Chimpanzees: Self-recognition,” Science, 1970, 167-.86-87.
460
Afterword
senior figures in animal behavior, “the results provide clear evidence of self-awareness in chimpanzees.”21
This conclusion is incorrect. Self-awareness usually means the
consciousness of our own persona over time, a sense of who we are,
our hopes and fears, as we daydream about ourselves in relation to
others. We do not see our conscious selves in mirrors, even though
that image may become the emblem of the self in many cases. The
chimpanzees in this experiment and the two-year-old child learned
a point-to-point relation between a mirror image and the body,
wonderful as that is. Rubbing a spot noticed in the mirror is not
essentially different from rubbing a spot noticed on the body without a mirror. The animal is not shown to be imagining himself
anywhere else, or thinking of his life over time, or introspecting
in any sense — all signs of a conscious self.
This less interesting, more primitive interpretation was made
even clearer by an ingenious experiment done in Skinner’s laboratory.22 Essentially the same paradigm was followed with pigeons,
except that it required a series of specific trainings with the mirror,
whereas the chimpanzee or child in the earlier experiments was, of
course, self-trained. But after about fifteen hours of such training
when the contingencies were carefully controlled, it was found
that a pigeon also could use a mirror to locate a blue spot on its
body which it could not see directly, though it had never been
explicitly trained to do so. I do not think that a pigeon because it
can be so trained has a self-concept.
From Affect to Emotion
The new spatialized time in which events and experiences could
be located, remembered, and anticipated results not only in the
21 Donald R. Griffin, “Prospects for a Cognitive Ethology,” Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 1978, 4:52 7-5 3 8.
22 Robert Epstein, R. P. Lanza and B. F. Skinner, “ ‘Self awareness’ in the Pigeon,”
Science, 1981, 212:695-696.
Afterword
461
conscious construction of a self, but also in a dramatic alteration of
our emotions. We share with other mammals a not very orderly
repertoire of affects whose neural substrate was evolved long ago
by natural selection into the limbic system deep in the brain. I
wish here to mention three: fear, shame, and mating. And in
doing so I wish to forewarn the reader that terminology is again
a problem, particularly in this area — even the word affect, which
I do not like to use because it is so often confused with effect and
sounds strange to the nonprofessional. By affect, psychology
means to designate a biologically organized behavior that has a
specific anatomical expression and a specific biochemistry, one that
dissipates with time. But with consciousness, all this is changed.
I shall call this consciousness of a past or future affect an emotion, as that is how we describe it. And what I am proposing here
is a two-tiered theory of emotions for modern human beings as
distinguished from bicameral man and other animals.23 There are
the basic affects of mammalian life and then our emotions, which
are the consciousness of such affects located inside an identity in a
lifetime, past or future, and which, be it noted, have no biologically
evolved mechanisms of stopping.
From Fear to Anxiety
In fear, there are a class of stimuli, usually abrupt and menacing, which stop the animal or person from ongoing behavior,
provoke flight, and in most social mammals produce specific bodily
expressions and internally a rise in the level of catecholamines in
the blood, such as adrenalin and noradrenalin. This is the wellknown emergency response, which dissipates after a few minutes
if the frightening object or situation is removed.
But with consciousness in a modern human being, when we
23 Julian Jaynes, “A Two-tiered Theory of Emotions,” Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 1982, 5:434-435, and also “Sensory Pain and Conscious Pain,” Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 1985,, 8:161-63.
462
Afterword
reminisce about previous fears or imagine future ones, fear becomes
mixed with the feeling of anxiety. If we wish to make echoes here
of the James-Lange theory of the emotions, we would call anxiety
the knowledge of our fear. We see a bear, run away in fear, and
have anxiety. But anxiety as a rehearsal of actual fear partially
occasions the emergency response at least weakly. It is man’s new
capacity for conscious imagery that can keep an analog of the
frightening situation in consciousness with a continuing response
to it. And how to turn off this response with its biochemical basis
was and I think still is a problem for conscious human beings, particularly with the resulting increase in catecholamine levels and
all its long-term effects. I would ask you here to consider what it
was like for an individual back in the first millennium B.C. to have
these anxieties that did not have their own built-in mechanism of
cessation and before human beings learned conscious mechanisms
of thought for doing so.
This is demonstrated in the famous incident described by H e rodotus of the very first tragedy performed in Athens. It was
performed only once. The play was The Fall of Miletus by
Phrynicus, describing the sack of that Ionian city by the Persians
in 494 B.C., a disaster that had happened the previous year. The
reaction of the audience was so extreme that all Athens could not
function for several days. Phrynicus was banished, never to be
heard of again, and his tragedy burnt.
From Shame to Guilt
The second biological affect I wish to consider here is shame.
Because it is a socially evoked affect, it has rarely been studied
experimentally, in either animals or humans. It is a complicated
affect whose occasioning stimuli often have to do with maintaining
hierarchical relationships in highly social animals, and is the submissive response to rejection by the hierarchical group. While
such biological shame is apparent as a controlling mechanism in
Afterword
463
carnivore groups, it is much more obvious among the primates, and
particularly in human beings. We seem to be ashamed to talk
about shame, and, indeed, as adults, we have been so shaped by
shame in the past, so confined to a narrow band of socially acceptable behavior, that it is rarely occasioned.
But when we think back to our childhoods, the piercing, throbbing trauma of being rejected by our peer groups, the fear of
inappropriately crossing over from the private domain into the
public countenance, the agony when we do, particularly in relation
to sexual and excretory functions, toilet accidents of others or ourselves, but also in a milder form, in wanting to be dressed the same
as other children, to receive as many valentines, and to be promoted with the rest, or have parents equal in wealth, health, or
promise to the parents of others, or not to be beaten up or teased
by others, sometimes even to be average in schoolwork when one
is really superior — anything to be sure that one is snugly sunk
deeply into one’s cohort — these are some of the most powerful
and profound influences on our development. We should remember here that as we grow older, our cohort is less and less our
immediate peer group and more and more our family tradition,
race, religion, union, or profession, et cetera.
The physiological expression of shame or humiliation involves
of course blushing, dropping of the eyes and of the head, and the
behavioral one of simply hiding from the group. Unfortunately,
nothing is known about its biochemical or neurological basis.
If you wish to feel shame in its pure form, this stepping outside
what is expected of you, simply stand out in a busy street and
shout out the time in minutes and seconds over the heads of everyone who passes by, and do it for five minutes — or until you are
taken away. This is shame, but not guilt, because you have done
nothing your society has taught you to call wrong.
And now consider what conscious reminiscence and imagery of
the future bring to this affect. And particularly consider this in
the milieu of ethical right and wrong that developed as markers
464
Afterword
for behavior after the breakdown of the bicameral mind with its
certainty of gods’ directives. Wrongs, or by another word, sins,
or indeed anything that would eject us from society if it were
known or seem to eject us from society can be reminisced about
out of the past and worried about for the future. And this we call
guilt. No one before 1ooo B.C. ever felt guilt, even while shame
was the way groups and societies were held together.
To indicate the evidence that guilt as opposed to shame is a new
emotion at this time, I would cite a single bit of evidence, and one
that is well known.24 This is the story of Oedipus. It is referred
to in two lines of the Iliad and two lines in the Odyssey which I
think we can take as indicating the true story, as it came down from
bicameral times. The story seems to be about a man who killed
his father and then unwittingly married his mother and so became
King of Thebes, proceeding to have several children-siblings by
his mother, then discovering what he had done, certainly feeling
shame since incest had always been a taboo, but evidently recovering from that shame, living a happy life thereafter with his wifemother, and dying with royal honors sometime later. This was
written down around 800 B.C., but the story comes from several
centuries before that.
And then, only four hundred years later, we have the great
trilogy of Sophocles on the subject, a play about unknown guilt,
guilt so extreme that a whole city is in famine because of it, so convulsive that the culprit when he discovers his guilt is not worthy to
look upon the world again and stabs his eyes into darkness with
the brooches clutched from his mother-wife’s breasts, and is led
away by his sister-daughters into a mystical death at Colonus.
And again, there is no biological mechanism for getting rid of
guilt. How to get rid of guilt is a problem which a host of learned
social rituals of reacceptance are now developed: scapegoat ceremonies among the Hebrews (the word for sending away translates
24 E. R. Dodds, The Greeks and the Irrational (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1951).
Afterword
465
now as “forgiveness”), the similar pharmakos among the Greeks
(again the word aphesis for sending the pharmakos away becomes
the Greek for “forgiveness”), “purification” ceremonies of many
sorts, baptism, the taurobolium, the haj, confession, the tashlik, the
mass, and of course the Christian cross, which takes away the sins
of the world (note the metaphors and analogies in all this). Even
changing the nature of God to a forgiving father.
And I would also have you note here that while the affects are
usually discrete, and evoked in very specific kinds of situations for
specific kinds of responses, the emotions in consciousness are not
discrete, can meld and evoke each other. Pve just said that in guilt
we can have worry about future shameful experiences, which indeed is anxiety, and we thus have two emotions, anxiety and guilt,
coming together as an even more powerful emotion.
From Mating to “Sex”
The third example I would consider here is the affect of mating.
It is similar in some respects to other affects but in other ways
quite distinct. Animal studies show that mating, contrary to what
the popular mind thinks, is not a necessary drive that builds up
like hunger or thirst (although it seems so because of consciousness), but an elaborate behavior pattern waiting to be triggered
off by very specific stimuli. Mating in most animals is thus confined to certain appropriate times of the year or day as well as to
certain appropriate sets of stimuli as in another’s behavior, or
pheromones, light conditions, privacy, security, and many other
variables. These include the enormous variety of extremely complicated courtship procedures that for rather subtle evolutionary
advantages seem in many animals almost designed to prevent
mating rather than to encourage it, as one might expect from an
oversimplified idea of the workings of natural selection. Among
the anthropoid apes, in contrast to other primates, mating is so
rare in the natural habitat as to have baffled early ethologists as to
466
Afterword
how these most human-like species reproduced at all. So too perhaps with bicameral man.
But when human beings can be conscious about their mating
behavior, can reminisce about it in the past and imagine it in the
future, we are in a very different world, indeed, one that seems
more familiar to us. Try to imagine what your “sexual life” would
be if you could not fantasize about sex.
What is the evidence for this change? Scholars of the ancient
world, I think, would agree that the murals and sculptures of
what I’m calling the bicameral world, that is, before 1ooo B.C.,
are chaste; depictions with sexual references are scarcely existent,
although there are exceptions. The modest, innocent murals from
bicameral Thera now on the second floor of the National Museum
in Athens are good examples.
But with the coming of consciousness, particularly in Greece,
where the evidence is most clear, the remains of these early Greek
societies are anything but chaste.25 Beginning with seventh century B.C. vase paintings, with the depictions of ithyphallic satyrs,
new, semidivine beings, sex seems indeed a prominent concern.
And I mean to use the word concern, for it does not at first seem
to be simply pornographic excitement. For example, on one island
in the Aegean, Delos, is a temple of huge phallic erections.
Boundary stones all over Attica were in the form of what are
called herms: square stone posts about four feet high, topped
with a sculptured head usually of Hermes and, at the appropriate
height, the only other sculptured feature of the post, a penile
erection. Not only were these herms not laughter-producing, as
they certainly would be to children of today, they were regarded
as serious and important, since in Plato’s Symposium “the mutilation of the herms” by the drunken general Alcibiades, in which
he evidently knocked off these protuberances with his sword around
the city of Athens, is regarded as a sacrilege.
25
Most of this information and references can be found in Hans Licht, Sexual Life
in Ancient Greece ( L o n d o n : Routledge, 1 9 3 1 ) , or in G. Rattray T a y l o r , Sex in History ( N e w Y o r k : V a n g u a r d Press, 1 9 5 4 ) .
Afterword
467
Erect phalli of stone or other material have been found in large
numbers in the course of excavations. There were amulets of
phalli. Vase paintings show naked female dancers swinging a
phallus in a Dionysian cult. One inscription describes the measures to be taken even in times of war to make sure that the phallus
procession should be led safely into the city. Colonies were obliged
to send phalli to Athens for the great Dionysian festivals. Even
Aristotle refers to phallic farces or satyr plays which generally
followed the ritual performances of the great tragedies.
If this were all, we might be able to agree with older Victorian
interpretations that this phallicism was merely an objective fertility rite. But the evidence from actual sexual behavior following
the advent of conscious fantasy speaks otherwise. Brothels, supposedly instituted by Solon, were everywhere and of every kind
by the fourth century B.C. Vase paintings depict every possible
sexual behavior from masturbation to bestiality to human threesomes, as well as homosexuality in every possible form.
The latter indeed began only at this time, due, I suggest, in part
to the new human ability to fantasize. Homosexuality is utterly
absent from the Homeric poems. This is contrary to what some
recent Freudian interpretations and even classical references of this
period (particularly after its proscription by Plato in The Laws as
being contrary to physis, or nature), seeking authorization for
homosexuality in Homer, having projected into the strong bonding between Achilles and Patroclus.
And again I would have you consider the problem twenty-five
hundred years ago, when human beings were first conscious and
could first fantasize about sex, of how they learned to control sexual behavior to achieve a stable society. Particularly because erectile tissue in the male is more prominent than in the female, and
that feedback from even partial erections would promote the continuance of sexual fantasy (a process called recruitment), we might
expect that this was much more of a male problem than a female
one. Perhaps the social customs that came into being for such
control resulted in the greater social separation of the sexes (which
468
Afterword
was certainly obvious by the time of Plato) as well as an enhanced
male dominance. We can think of modern orthodox Muslim societies in this respect, in which an exposed female ankle or lock of
hair is punishable by law.
I certainly will admit that there are large vacant places in the
evidence for what I am saying. And of course there are other
affects, like anger becoming our hatred, or more positive ones like
excitement with the magical touch of consciousness becoming joy,
or affiliation consciousized into love. I have chosen anxiety, guilt,
and sex as the most socially important. Readers of a Freudian
persuasion will note that their theorizing could begin here. I hope
that these hypotheses can provide historians more competent than
myself with a new way of looking at this extremely important
period of human history, when so much of what we regard as
modern psychology and personality was being formed for the first
time.
There is so much more to do, so many more bays and inlets of
history and theory to explore. The tracking of ancient mentalities
is an ongoing process that is leading to new insights and discoveries. Since I do not know Chinese, I could not address that part
of the data in the book. But I am pleased that my associate
Michael Carr, an expert in ancient Chinese texts, is making up
for that lack in a series of definitive papers.26 The dating here is
approximately the same as in Greece, which has led some historians to call this period the “axial age.”
Several scholars have explored the ramifications of the theory
in literature, particularly Judith Weissman, whose book with the
working title of Vision, Madness, and Morality, Poetry and the
Theory of the Bicameral Mind is being completed as I am writing.27 Thomas Posey is continuing his studies of verbal halluci26 Michael Carr, “Sidelights on Xin ‘Heart, Mind’ in the Shijingabstract in Proceedings of the 31st CISHAAN, Tokyo and Kyoto, 1983, 824-825, and his “Personation of the Dead in Ancient China,” Computational Analyses of Asian and African
Languages, 1985, 1-107.
27 The title also of one of her papers: “Vision, Madness, and Morality: Poetry and
Afterword
469
nations, Ross Maxwell is doing further historical studies, and
many others, such as D. C. Stove,28 I also thank for their support
and encouragement,
PRINCETON
UNIVERSITY,
1 9 9 0
the Theory of the Bicameral Mind,” Georgia Review, 1979, 35:118-158. See also
her “Somewhere in Earshot: Yeats’ Admonitory Gods,” Pequod, 1982, 74:16-31.
28 D. C. Stove, “The Oracles and Their Cessation: A Tribute to Julian Jaynes,”
Encounter, April 1989, pp. 30-38.
THE DRAWINGS
On pages 40, 1 0 1 , 104, 120 by the author; on page 142 by Christiane
Gillièron after a photograph by J. Perrot; on page 152 from J. Mellaart,
Earliest Civilizations of the Near East
( L o n d o n : T h a m e s and Hudson,
1 9 6 5 ) ; on page 1 5 4 by kind permission of E k r e m A k u r g a l ; on page 168
after Mellaart; on pages 170, 1 7 1 , 224 by Susan Hockaday; on page 199
by Carol Goldenberg; on page 1 7 2 by kind permission of Francis Robicsek;
on page
192 redrawn from Henri Frankfort, Kingship and the Gods
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1 9 4 8 ) .
T h e lines of verse on page 378 are from William Empson’s “Doctrinal
Point” and
“ T h e Last Pain,” in
Collected Poems of
Reprinted by permission of Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
William Empson.
Julian Jaynes was born in West Newton, Massachusetts, in 1920.
He attended Harvard University and received his bachelors degree from McGill University and his master’s and doctoral degrees
in psychology from Yale University. Dr. Jaynes lectured in the
psychology department at Princeton University from 1966 to 1990.
He published articles widely, focusing during the early part of his
career on the study of animal behavior. He later redirected the
scope of his thinking and energy to the study of human consciousness, culminating in his groundbreaking and only published book,
The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind,
which was nominated for the National Book Award in 1978. The
book is considered by many to be one of the most significant and
controversial books of the twentieth century. Dr. Jaynes suffered a
fatal stroke on November 21,1997.
At the heart of this seminal work is the revolutionary idea that human
consciousness did not begin far back in animal evolution but was a learned
process that emerged, through cataclysm and catastrophe, from a hallucinatory mentality only three thousand years ago and that is still developing.
T h e implications of this scientific paradigm extend into virtually every
aspect of our psychology, our history, our culture, our religion — indeed
our future. In the words of one reviewer, it is “a humbling text, the kind
that reminds most of us who make our livings through thinking, how
much thinking there is left to do.”
“ W h e n Julian Jaynes . . . speculates that until late in the second millennium
B.C. men had no consciousness but were automatically obeying the voices
of gods, we are astounded but compelled to follow this remarkable thesis
through all the corroborative evidence.” — John Updike, The New Yorker
“ T h i s b o o k s and this mans ideas may be the most influential, not to say
controversial, of the second half of the twentieth century. It renders whole
shelves of books obsolete.” — William Harrington,
Columbus Dispatch
“Having just finished The Origin of C o n s c i o u s n e s s , I myself feel something
like Keats’ C o r t e z staring at the Pacific, or at least like the early reviewers
of D a r w i n or Freud. I’m not quite sure what to make of this new territory; but its expanse lies before me and I am startled by its power.”
—
Edward Profitt,
Commonweal
“ H e is as startling as Freud was in The Interpretation of D r e a m s , and Jaynes
is e q u a l l y a d e p t at f o r c i n g a n e w v i e w of k n o w n h u m a n b e h a v i o r . ”
—
Raymond
Headlee,
American Journal
of Psychiatry
“ T h e weight of original thought in [this b o o k ] is so great that it makes
me uneasy for the author’s well-being: the human mind is not built to
support such a b u r d e n . ” — D. C. Stove, Encounter
ISBN-13:
978-0-618-05707-8
ISBN-10:
0-618-05707-2
PSYCHOLOGY/SELF-HELP/$18.00
0800/6-82620
www.hmco.com/trade
C o v e r d e s i g n by Erin Hasley
© H o u g h t o n Miff Lin C o m p a n y
780618 057078
Cover illustration by Susan Hockaday |