entry_id
stringlengths
0
35
text
stringlengths
0
311k
wodeham
## 1. Life Adam Wodeham [Goddam/Woodham] (c. 1295-1358) was born near Southampton. He entered the Franciscan order at a young age. Wodeham's earliest philosophical education was at the Franciscan *studium* in London where he first studied under Walter Chatton (c. 1317-1321) and then William of Ockham (1320-1324). During this period of intense study, Wodeham collaborated with Ockham on his massive *Summa logicae*, editing it and preparing it for publication. After Ockham departed for Avignon in the summer of 1324, Wodeham was sent to Oxford to complete his studies. At Oxford he attended the sentential lectures of Richard FitzRalph (1328-1329), and subsequently qualified to read the *Sentences*. Wodeham lectured on the *Sentences* of Peter Lombard at the London convent sometime in the 1320s, although his earliest lecture notes have not survived. He later lectured at the provincial school in Norwich sometime in the late 1320s, a work that is now referred to as the *Lectura secunda* [LS]. Finally, Wodeham delivered the Oxford lectures (referred to as the *Ordinatio Oxoniensis* [OO]) between 1332 and 1334 (Streveler and Tachau 1995, 22-23, n. 61). According to Thomas de Eccleston (Eccleston 1951, 57), Wodeham was the 61st lector at Oxford, Greyfriars. As is the case with many medieval philosophers, little is known about his latter life after he completed is education. He apparently traveled to Basel in 1339, survived the plague in 1348-49, and died at the Franciscan convent at Babwell in 1358 (Courtenay 1978, 181). ## 2. Writings The extant writings of Adam Wodeham include: his two commentaries on the *Sentences* of Peter Lombard (the *Lectura* and the *Ordinatio*); a prologue to William of Ockham's *Summa logicae*; a short *quaestio* on the *continuum*; a longer *Tractatus de indivisibilibus*; the *Tractatus alphabeticus*, and perhaps the 51st chapter of part I of Ockham's *Summa logicae* and the last question of book IV of the same author's *Reportatio*. Adam Wodeham's most significant philosophical and theological works are his two commentaries on the *Sentences*. The *Lectura* (c. 1320s) is the earlier of the two works and is a loose commentary on the first 26 distinctions of the first book of the Lombard's *Sentences*. The single manuscript of the *Lectura* (Cambridge, Gonville and Caius, Ms 281 (674), ff. 105-250) has been published in a modern critical edition (Gal and Wood 1990). The *Ordinatio* (1332-34), Wodeham's most mature extant work, is a more expansive commentary, treating all four books of the Lombard's *Sentences* and extensively re-writing and re-organizing the first 26 distinctions of the first book. A critical edition of the *Ordinatio* is available at the Scholastic Commentaries and Texts Archive. The shorter works of Wodeham comprise several collaborations with his teacher William of Ockham. These include Wodeham's brief introduction to Ockham's *Summa logicae*, which has been edited in the critical edition. Further, Courtenay argues that Wodeham is probably the disciple who wrote the 51st chapter of part I of Ockham's *Summa logicae* (Courtenay 1978, 34). Both of these short works were written between 1320 and 1324, as Wodeham collaborated with the Venerable Inceptor. Finally, Gedeon Gal also noted that in one of the manuscripts of Ockham's *Reportatio* (Milan, Ambros. 281 inf., fol. 69rb) on book IV of the *Sentences*, a marginal notation attributes the final question of the work to Wodeham (Courtenay 1978, 34, fn. 61). Wodeham's shorter works also include two tracts on the *continuum* written against the indivisibilists or atomists and the *Tractatus alphabeticus*. The shorter work on the *continuum* (Murdoch and Synan 1966, 212-288), consisting of a single *quaestio*, is an early redaction of the longer work, the *Tractatus de indivisibilibus* (Wood 1988). Both of the works were probably written between 1323 and 1331 (Wood 1998, 16). The *Tractatus alphabeticus* considers the latitude of forms and was written around 1333 (Wood 374). Finally, the lost works of Adam Wodeham include Biblical commentaries on the *Canticum canticorum* and the first book of *Ecclesiasticus*. And, based on historical and textual evidence, it is generally held that Wodeham wrote a set of *Determinationes*, some of which were probably included in the *Tractatus de indivisibilibus*. ## 3. Position in the History of Philosophy Adam Wodeham's place in the history of philosophy remains difficult to appreciate because of two related problems, here referred to as: (1) the historiographical problem; and (2) the textual problem. Historiographically, the field of medieval philosophy has been plagued by various narrative accounts of the twelfth through fifteenth centuries that characterize the period in which Wodeham flourished as an age in which fideism, skepticism and scholastic decadence ruled the day (Inglis, 1998). This basic historiographical approach to the late medieval period has recently come under serious attack and scrutiny by specialists working in the field, but a balanced picture of the philosophers and theologians working during this period remains in its infancy. Second, an accurate understanding of Adam Wodeham's place within the history of philosophy is handicapped by the lack of critical editions for Adam Wodeham, his immediate contemporaries, and numerous medieval philosophers and theologians working in the late fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. Regarding Wodeham, it is important to recognize that a critical edition of any complete text of Wodeham was not available until recently (Wood 1988; Gal and Wood 1990). Further, as already noted, an edition of Wodeham's most mature and complete work, the *Ordinatio*, is only now underway. As such, the place of Adam Wodeham within the history of medieval thought is difficult to trace at present, and William Courtenay's important study remains the most relevant point of reference (Courtenay, 1978). Based on the work of Courtenay, the first references to Wodeham's place within medieval thought must begin by considering his *socii* (or contemporary *sententiarii*). Wodeham lectured on the *Sentences* at Oxford in 1332-1334, and contemporaneous with his lectures there were other bachelors lecturing on the *Sentences* (*baccalarius sententiarius*) in the various other convents or theological schools (Courtenay 1978, 89). Understanding who these bachelors are is important because they often engaged with each other's work. In the case of Adam Wodeham the list of *socii* includes: Monachus Niger (Benedictine), Robert Holcot OP, William Crathorn OP, Roger Gosford OP, Edmund Grafton OFM, Hugh Grafton OESA, William Chiterne OFM, William Skelton: Mertonian, Richard of Radford, and an unnamed Carmelite (Courtenay 1978, 89-111). Beyond his immediate *socii*, Wodeham's influence between 1334 and 1346 is evident in England, Paris and Cologne. English theologians, between 1334 and 1350, often do not cite contemporaries by name. That said, there is substantial evidence that Wodeham's contemporaries took his thought seriously. During these decades, Courtenay lists the following English theologians as making either implicit or explicit reference to Adam Wodeham's *lecturae*: Thomas Bradwardine (Mertonian), Robert of Halifax OFM, Roger Roseth OFM and Thomas Buckingham (Mertonian) (Courtenay 1978, 116-123). In contrast to the English authors discussed above, the Parisian authors between 1342 and 1345 were much more willing to cite a contemporary author (Courtenay 1978, 123). Thus, in this period almost all of the Parisian theologians commenting on the *Sentences* cite Wodeham: Gregory of Rimini OESA, Alphonsus Vargas OESA and John of Mirecourt (Cistercian). These authors exhibit a strong knowledge of Wodeham and all had some access to the Oxford (*Ordinatio*) redaction of Wodeham's work (Courtenay 1978, 132). In particular one should note Gregory of Rimini's extensive knowledge of the thought of Wodeham. The spread of Ockham's philosophical and theological thought into Germany (both directly and indirectly through the study of Wodeham) took place between 1335 and 1350 and is evident in Cologne. This is perhaps due to the fact that Wodeham traveled to Basel in the summer of 1339 bringing with him a copy of his *Ordinatio* (Courtenay 1978, 133 and 181). How long Wodeham remained in Germany, or where he traveled, remains unknown. But, it is significant that in Cologne, sometime before 1348, one theologian lectured on the *Sentences secundum Adam* (Courtenay 1978, 133). This and other evidence suggest that Wodeham was being studied seriously in Cologne before 1348. In the aftermath of the Parisian condemnations of Nicholas of Autrecourt in 1346 and John of Mirecourt in 1347, one may expect that the influence of Wodeham would have waned in subsequent years. But, Courtenay argues that the citations of Wodeham throughout this turbulent period demonstrate that this was not the case (Courtenay 1978, 135). Evidence of Parisian masters engaging the thought of Wodeham in the years after 1347 is evident in the works of: Peter Ceffons O.Cist. and Hugolino Malabrancha of Oriveto OESA. In the final four decades of the fourteenth century there is an increase in the citations of the *moderni* as evidenced in the extant commentaries. The list of commentaries that cite Wodeham includes: the anonymous author of ms. Vat. Lat. 986, John Hiltalingen of Basel OESA, James of Eltville O.Cist, Conrad of Ebrach O.Cist., Pierre d'Ailly, Henry Totting of Oyta, John of Wasia, Henry of Langenstein, Nicholas of Dinkelsbuhl, Peter of Candia, John Brammart O.C., Peter Plaoul, and Marsilius of Inghen. This period of medieval philosophy remains understudied, but it is clear that there was a strong interest in Wodeham at the close of the fourteenth century. Further evidence of this is found in Henry Totting of Oyta's *Abbreviato* of Adam Wodeham's *Ordinatio* produced between 1373 and 1378 (Courtenay 1978, 147). Oyta's *Abbreviato* of Wodeham was influential in the fifteenth century, as is clear from the number of extant manuscripts spread throughout Europe. The influence of Wodeham's thought in the fifteenth and early sixteenth centuries is a chapter of medieval philosophy and theology that has yet to be written. There are citations of Wodeham in the works of Arnold of Sehnsen O.C., Peter Reicher/Pirchenward, John Capreolus, Gabriel Biel and John Mair (Major), although the evidence at this point has yet to be analyzed in detail (Courtenay 1978, 150-156). What is certain is that Wodeham remained important for philosophers and theologians in the long fifteenth century, and John Mair eventually, in the sixteenth century, published an edition of Oyta's *Abbreviato*. This has been both positive and negative for Wodeham studies: positive, as Wodeham has remained available to those who do not have access to the manuscript tradition; and negative as it has meant that scholars often read and cite an inferior text that significantly abbreviates the original work. More attention should be given to the influence of Wodeham in this period. ## 4. Psychology and Cognition To the present day a significant part of Wodeham scholarship has been focused on his philosophy of mind and the sequence of events from sense impression to complex scientific judgment. Modern scholarship's focus here is partly due to the fact that this was a clear area of interest for Wodeham, to which he devoted significant energy. But it is also a reflection of the availability of texts; the contracted nature of the *Lectura secunda* has focused the efforts of scholarship on book I and issues of cognition. In the following section, we will try to give an overview of the general consensus and debates of modern scholarship on the process of cognition as it is currently found in the *Lectura secunda*. ### 4.1 Intuitive and Abstractive Cognition Wodeham turns first to the question of intuitive and abstractive cognition: two concepts developed by John Duns Scotus and William of Ockham. But while they identify the parallel notions of intuitive and abstractive cognition proper to the sensitive and intellective souls respectively, Wodeham distinguishes himself from his predecessors by insisting that this parallel reduplication is redundant and violates the principle of parsimony. Regarding intuitive cognition Wodeham begins by stating that: "every act of science naturally caused presupposes evidence of some proposition or of the thing signified through the proposition. Science (or a scientific act of assent) is caused by the mediation of this evidence" (LS I:9, ll. 44-46). The question is: what is the source of this evidence? The assumption is that an evident proposition arises from, or is formulated from, certain types of simple evident apprehensions, namely, intuitive apprehensions. Wodeham, then asks: does the intellect require an intuitive apprehension distinct from the act of sensation? The definition of intuitive apprehension states that such an apprehension must be sufficient for the intellect to make a judgment about the existence of the object. Given this definition Wodeham wonders why a second act of intuitive apprehension, beyond the apprehension of sensation, is necessary in order for the intellect to make this judgment. The fact that the present object in question has been "sensed" ought to be sufficient for the intellect to feel confident that such an object exists. Wodeham's position is distinctive because he denies what was a traditional distinction for Scotus and Ockham, namely, a distinction between the sensitive and intellective soul (a real distinction in the case of Ockham and a formal distinction in the case of Scotus). For Wodeham, the assumption of two separate acts of intuition mandates that a human being have either two souls or that the human has one soul and also another vital power, separate from that soul. But, drawing on the authority of Augustine, Wodeham identifies the notion of two souls as a heresy to be avoided. Another option is to think that the sensitive soul is not really a soul at all, but rather a power distinct and separate from the one human soul. But this too is unacceptable. To be a true sensitive potency, Wodeham insists that it must be a living form (*viva forma*); if it were not, it would not be able to receive "living" or vital acts, among which apprehensive and appetitive acts are numbered. But if one admits that the sensitive power remains a "living form", then two souls are once more introduced into the single human being. This, at least, is the case for Wodeham, who holds that to be a "soul" is to be a "living form" (LS I:11, ll. 44-55). Thus, Wodeham is adamant that there can only be one soul in the single human being, and the intuitive act of sensation alone is sufficient for the simple apprehension "presupposed" by an "evident assent" (LS I:9, ll. 44-48). However, by denying this distinction, Wodeham must be willing to say that, strictly speaking, the "intellect senses" because it is the same intellectual soul that both senses and thinks. This was an unsavory consequence for a thinker like Ockham, but one that Wodeham was fully willing to accept (Wood 1990, 21\*; LS I:14-15, ll.1-49). Despite disagreeing with Scotus and Ockham on the nature of the intellective and the sensitive soul, Wodeham affirms the formal definition of intuition originally given by Scotus. This definition is formulated in the third conclusion of the second question of the prologue to the *Lectura Secunda*: "the incomplex act, which is able to cause evident assent about a contingent truth of a present object, and which naturally requires the existence and presence of that object, is intuitive knowledge" (LS I, 37, ll. 69-72). The presence of the object is required and not just its existence because intuitive cognition requires the object to function as an efficient cause. The object, however, cannot function as an efficient cause unless it is also present to the knower (LS I:45-46, ll. 40-44). With this definition Wodeham is also rejecting an important and controversial part of Ockham's definition of intuitive knowledge. For Ockham, not only was an intuitive knowledge able to produce an affirmative judgment of the existence of an extant object, but it was also able to affirm the non-existence of a non-extant object. By insisting on the criteria of a present object for any kind of intuitive knowledge, Wodeham denies that an intuition of a non-extant, non-present object is possible. Here Wodeham offers an illustrative example. He remarks that sometimes we can judge that something does not exist as a consequence of having a positive intuition. He gives the example of intuitively seeing the dead body of Socrates and knowing that Socrates *does not exist.* While acknowledging that such an example might be the inspiration behind Ockham's controversial claim about an intuitive knowledge of non-existents, he points out that in this example, we do not have an intuitive knowledge of the same thing about which we are making a judgment. Rather we are making an inference from our intuitive knowledge of (and a judgment about) the existence of the dead body of Socrates (LS I:38-39, ll. 4-15). The difference, then, between intuitive knowledge and abstractive knowledge is again taken from Scotus. Here, in Wodeham's sixth conclusion, of the second question, the difference is attributable, not to diverse objects of knowledge, but to the attitude that one can take towards that object with respect to existence (LS I:45, ll. 22-26). Unlike intuitive knowledge, abstractive knowledge does not require the existence or presence of the object to be known. However, in this case "what is known" is indifferent to the existence of that object and no judgment about that object's existence can be made. ### 4.2 Skepticism and Aureoli Wodeham's decision to identify the difference between intuitive and abstractive knowledge with the presence or absence of an object, as Scotus and Ockham did, meant that he shared with these two thinkers a common opponent, namely Peter Aureoli. In response to Scotus's definition of intuitive knowledge Aureoli identified several experiences wherein a person appears to have a sensitive intuition of a non-present object. Such experiences, according to Aureoli, were the consequence of lingering sensitive images that remain even after an object is no longer present. Such lingering images (sometimes called *esse perspectivum* or *esse apparens*) were used to explain all sorts of visual anomalies that do not correspond to reality. Such experiences were enough for Aureoli to define intuitive knowledge, not as the direct grasp of a present object, but as *direct* knowledge (as opposed to knowledge arrived at through a discursive reasoning process). Rega Wood explains: > > > Abstract and intuitive cognition were distinguished by the manner in > which their objects were presented. The objects of abstract cognition > appeared in a quasi-imaginary mode (*quasi modo imaginario et > absente*); intuitive cognition was direct rather than discursive, > and it conveyed the impression that its objects existed and were > actually present (Wood 1982, 216). > > > In short, this meant that a direct grasp of a lingering appearance or *esse apparens*, even after the object was no longer present, could count as intuitive knowledge. For those who came after Aureoli, his definition and his notion of *esse apparens* raised a host of skeptical concerns. If sensation produces an *esse apparens*, the intellect must also produce a similar object, something Peter Aureoli called *esse intentionale*. And if intuitive knowledge is a direct knowledge of either the *esse apparens* or the *esse intentionale*, and not of the object itself, from where does the certainty come by which one can firmly and confidently state that "this thing exists"? Aureoli's *esse apparens* opened up the possibility of an experience, wherein what appears to be present, might actually not be present or even in existence. Ockham's answer to Aureoli's insistence on the need for an *esse apparens* to explain certain strange and misleading phenomena was to relocate the source of the error. The error does not come from the impression of some non-existent object. On the contrary, the naturally produced intuitive cognition does not lie. Instead, as Wood paraphrases Ockham, "error arises when the observer infers a proposition which does not follow formally from his perceptions" (Wood 1982, 224). Ockham calls the intuition of those appearances that cause apparitions "imperfect intuitive cognition". In such cases, the immediate judgment of the intellect is not "that the object represented exists", but "that the object was impressed" (and, it would seem, that this impression exists). The intellect errs, then, when it assents to what the "imperfect" intuition does not warrant. A central concern with Ockham's account, raised by Walter Chatton and responded to by Wodeham, was the character of these apparition causing "after-images". For Ockham, the after images were not caused by the object, but by a lingering impression distinct from the object or impression-causing species. For Chatton, it could not be overlooked that these after-images appeared *as if* they were the object, not *as if* they were some left-over impression caused by the object. Thus, he argued that the after-images are caused by the lingering of the representative species of the object, even after the object is no longer present. Chatton was therefore willing to admit that intuition of a non-present object was possible, as long as its representative species lingered. On this issue Wodeham takes sides with Ockham against Chatton. He expressly attacks Chatton's description of the lingering species as having a likeness sufficient to cause the observer to believe in the existence of the original object. Wood writes of Wodeham's position: > > > In after-images only the remains of the form or species caused by the > first act of perception are seen. But the belief that the principal > object is seen when after-images are present is not caused by the > first vision or even by the remains of the species imprinted during > vision. It is caused by strong imagination which leads the observer to > judge falsely that what he sees in an after-image is the same as what > he saw when the principal object was presented (Wood 1982, 228). > > > In short, against Chatton, Wodeham defends an Ockham-like position, suggesting that the source of error is not the intuitive cognition of something not actually there, but the fact that the intellect chooses to make a judgment about the existence of something other than what was intuited. In many ways, the case is similar to that inference made about Socrates' non-existence, when Socrates' dead body is intuitively grasped. The inference made from one intuitive cognition is not always correct, even if the intuition itself remains reliable. ### 4.3 Three Degrees of Evidence What then does all this mean for the question of certitude and the possibility of building a genuine and trustworthy science based on these foundational impressions received from the natural world? Wodeham defended the reliability of our immediate simple apprehensions, but he also admitted the possibility that the imagination can severely distort these impressions such that we are inclined to assent to what the simple apprehension itself does not warrant. Wodeham discusses the question of evidence for a proposition which can be built from these initial apprehensions in the sixth question of the prologue. He says that the idea of "complex evidence" can be understood in two ways: either as referring to the apprehension of an evident proposition itself or to the so-called "evident judgment" which has been caused by this evident proposition. What Wodeham means by an evident proposition is complicated and requires that we have a clear sense of the distinction between apprehension and judgment, which are for Wodeham two distinct and separate acts. An evident proposition for Wodeham can be of three kinds. The first and lowest degree of evidence is identified with the apprehension of the proposition (or what it signifies). Wodeham uses as his example the proposition, "a stick submerged in water is broken". The apprehension of this state of affairs has all the trappings of an evident proposition, to such an extent that it inclines us to perform the separate act of producing an affirmative judgment. Nevertheless, this type of proposition is one that can still be false, despite the fact that it has all the appearance of truth. This lingering possibility, however, allows the intellect to suspend its judgment on the basis of other experiences or reasons. Distinctive of such propositions is their contingent nature. Though they can appear true, it remains possible that they are false. The second degree of certainty associated with evident propositions is exemplified by a proposition that not only appears certain and inclines the judgment to assent, but is also a proposition that cannot fail to signify correctly. According to Wodeham all propositions of this type are categorical and necessary. And, he distinguishes them from those contingent types of propositions which may have every appearance of being true but yet may turn out to be false (LS II:163, ll.17-20). Finally, Wodeham distinguishes this second type of evident proposition from a third type of proposition which is also categorical and necessary. This third type of proposition is the highest degree of evidence, because, not only can it not fail to appear *and be* true, but it also cannot be doubted. That is, it not only inclines to assent, but necessitates the intellect to assent. For Wodeham, this is distinct from the second and less-evident type of proposition. While this second type cannot fail to be true, it nevertheless can still be doubted owing to the fact that other conflicting propositions also appear to be true. The third type cannot be doubted in this way, no matter what other propositions appear to be true. If other evident propositions are genuinely in conflict with (i.e., are inconsistent with) the proposition in question, those propositions cannot be evident in the highest degree. But nor can these conflicting propositions be evident in the second highest degree since the second and third types are both supposed to be necessary. Therefore they cannot actually be in conflict, though it is still possible that they may appear to be in conflict. For Wodeham, propositions of the third and highest type can be known in themselves and are necessarily *per se nota* (LS I:164, 36). ### 4.4 Evident Judgments If this is how we can understand an evident proposition, what then constitutes an evident judgment? Again, a judgment, for Wodeham, is sharply distinguished from the distinct act of apprehension or the mental proposition. It amounts to a mental nod of approval to the correspondence between the apprehended proposition and the reality signified. (See LS I, prol., d. 6, SS 20, I:176-178.) Clearly, the first two types of propositions do not provide us with absolute certainty. These propositions have all the appearance of truth, but the judgment that follows from them cannot be called evident as long as doubt remains, even if the judgment in question is correct. When it comes then to a truly evident judgment, propositions which are *per se nota* can cause evident judgments because the truth of those propositions can in no way be doubted. However, besides propositions *per se nota* there are certain mechanisms through which originally dubitable propositions can come to be evident in the third degree, thereby necessitating assent and causing a truly evident judgment. The most obvious mechanism is the demonstrative syllogism, which leads us finally to Wodeham's conception of a science and the immediate object of this act of assent. In article two of question one, he discusses whether a scientific act of knowing (the evident assent given to the conclusion of a syllogism) has as its immediate object "that which is signified by only one proposition, i.e., the conclusion" or "that which is signified by the conclusion and the premises joined together at the same time through a syllogism" (LS I:199, ll. 5-11). Wodeham's conclusion is decidedly in favor of the latter; namely, in order for a previously dubitable proposition to be elevated to the third degree of evidence, whereby the intellect is necessitated to assent, it must acquire that evidence from the force of the syllogism as whole. The conclusion by itself is not *per se nota*. Thus, for a truly evident judgment to take place, a single evident proposition cannot be its cause, rather all three propositions of the syllogism must be taken together in order for the concluding proposition to have the evidence it needs to not only appear true, but to compel the mind's assent (LS I:199-208). This requirement that scientific assent be given to the syllogism as a whole (and cannot be sustained if one of the premises is forgotten) is a position that will be explicitly opposed by the later Parisian reader of Wodeham, Gregory of Rimini (*Lectura*, I, Prol., q. 3, a. 1, Trapp I:107ff). ### 4.5 The Complexe Significabile If there is a topic that has dominated Wodeham scholarship, it is the *complexe significabile* or alternatively, that which is signifiable in a complex way, i.e., through a proposition. This mysterious entity was intended by Wodeham to function both as the immediate object of propositional knowledge and as a genuine *via media* between two extreme theories regarding the object of knowledge offered by his contemporaries. Representing one extreme was William of Ockham, who was thought by Wodeham to identify the terms of a proposition as the actual object. This is sometimes referred to as the anti-realist position. On the other hand there was Walter Chatton, who argued that the object of propositional knowledge was the actual entity signified by the subject term of the proposition. Wodeham, in turn, rejected both these positions and stated that the object of science was an actual state of affairs which could only be signified through a complex or a proposition. Questions and puzzles have continued to linger regarding the exact ontological status of these states-of-affairs. While insisting that they have some real ontological weight, they do not fit nicely under either of the Aristotelian categories of real being, substance or accident. Thus, within an Aristotelian framework, it is difficult to articulate exactly how or in what way the *complexe significabile* is actually real. The legacy of the *complexe significabile* has a somewhat involved history. We can find several examples of its use and discussion throughout the fourteenth, fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. However, for many years the idea was thought to originate with Gregory of Rimini. Modern scholarship slowly discovered, albeit not immediately, that this particular terminology was original to Wodeham and only later adopted by Rimini. (The idea, however, has many precursors evident in earlier debates over terms like *dicta* or *enuntiabilia*. See Klima 1993; Nuchelmans 1973; Bermon 2007.) The most frequently cited misattribution in modern scholarship has been Hubert Elie's "Le complexe significabile" (Elie 1936). In the following generation, Gedeon Gal (Gal 1977) discovered that Wodeham was actually the author of this idea. Gal edited the first modern edition of the *Lectura Secunda* dist. 1, q. 1, the traditional point of entry into Wodeham's thought on the matter. Since Gal's article, several studies have followed: Nuchelmans (1980), Tachau (1987), Grassi (1990), Zupko (1994-1997), Karger (1995), and Brower-Toland (2007). A frequent part of the contemporary discussion involves distinguishing the genuine doctrine of Adam Wodeham from later versions. Gal's initial characterization of Rimini's position as a "mutilation" of Wodeham's position has exerted its influence over the subsequent scholarship (cf. Nuchelmans, and esp. Zupko). Most complaints stem from the idea that Rimini gives too much ontological weight to this mysterious entity or at least lacks the nuance of Wodeham, exposing the doctrine to objections that could not be addressed to Wodeham himself (cf. Zupko 1994-1997). Brower-Toland has recently challenged this traditional reading. She suggests the "radical nature of Wodeham's claims" have largely gone unrecognized, and that his *complexe significabile* represents a significant "ontological addition" to the Aristotelian substance-accident framework (Brower-Toland 2007:600n7, 638-640). ## 5. Philosophical Theology ### 5.1 Proofs of God's Existence Wodeham's approach to philosophical theology begins with a traditional attempt to determine whether or not God's existence can be philosophically and demonstratively proved. In both the *Lectura secunda* and the *Ordinatio* his strategy is structured by two proofs. The first is taken from and explicitly attributed to Scotus. Of the Scotist proof, Wodeham remarks that it seems very persuasive and more evident than any reason that can be brought against it. The second argument appears to be original to Wodeham. The first proof taken from John Duns Scotus is found both in his *Ordinatio* and *De Primo Principio*. The argument follows from an initial disjunctive premise: there is either some first uncaused cause or there is not. If the former, Scotus and Wodeham argue that it is obvious that this is God. If the latter is chosen then unacceptable consequences follow. The most notable is that there would be an infinite series of caused causes without a terminating point. Two reasons are offered for why such an infinite series is impossible. The first is that, the whole of all "essentially ordered" causes must have a cause, but if the cause of this multitude comes from the totality of caused causes, then this cause will be the cause of itself, which is impossible. The second reason that an infinite series of causes will not work is this would require that there are an infinite amount of causes acting at the same time. This requirement is built into Wodeham's (and Scotus's) conception of essentially ordered causes--which Wodeham later sharply distinguishes from a series of accidentally ordered causes. Wodeham offers a second proof for the existence of God. Regarding this proof he states that it is sufficient to incline the intellect to assent, but he also acknowledges that it is still able to be doubted by "shameful adversaries" (LS II:121; OO I, d. 2, a. 1). According to Wodeham's description of different types of evidence, it is clear that this "proof" is not able to compel a truly evident judgment because the proof remains open to doubt and thus only reaches the second degree of evidence. The proof begins from another disjunctive proposition inspired by Anselm's *Proslogion*. Either there is some most noble being about which no more noble thing is able to be thought, or there is no such most noble thing. Wodeham remarks that one possible consequence that might follow is that there would be an infinite succession of more noble things, thus permitting an infinity of beings. This conclusion, he says, is unpleasant to the mind; that is, the intellect is not able to admit an infinity of beings without "grumbling" (*murmere*). For this option at least, it is clear that the intellect can incline us to assent that God exists, but it is still possible to doubt it, which is the distinguishing mark of the second degree of evidence. The other alternative is that there must be some most noble thing actually existing (*in actu existens*), even though this is not the most noble thing possible. Wodeham finds this alternative opposed by the most evident of reasons--something akin to Anselm's ontological argument: whatever is actually existing (*existens in actu*) is *de facto* more noble than what is not in existence. Thus, it is nonsensical to speak of something more noble, which is only potentially existing (LS II:121, ll.13-15). ### 5.2 Proof of God's Unicity From the philosophical proof of the existence of the highest being, not always demonstrative, but evident in at least the second degree, Wodeham turns to the question of whether there is one highest being or many. The question found in *Lectura*, I, q. 1, a. 3, and the *Ordinatio* I, d. 2, a. 2 is posed in an ambiguous way. It asks whether it is *evidently probable* that something absolutely uncausable is only one in number. The question is ambiguous because it is not immediately clear whether Wodeham's intention is to show that there is only one God or if he intends to evaluate the relative degrees of evidence of the existing proofs of God's unicity or multiplicity. As the question progresses, it appears that Wodeham is primarily interested in evaluating the evidence of both pro and con arguments. Wodeham juxtaposes arguments of Scotus against counter arguments of Ockham in order to argue that the unicity of God cannot be demonstrably proven. Ultimately, he argues that its seems that natural reason is not able to prove evidently the numerical unity of God (LS II:144). He argues for the inconclusiveness of several arguments including: the argument that proceeds from the belief that there cannot be several total causes of the same effect (LS II:144); that there cannot be more than one necessary being (LS II:159); and that there cannot be more than one final cause (OO I, q. 2, a. 2, dubium 5). In the end, Wodeham is not interested in denying that there is only one God, but he simply wants to show that the relatively strong arguments for God's unicity do not reach the third and highest degree of evidence. Even when it comes to the specific unity of God, which is granted only a brief discussion in the *Lectura secunda* and is left out of the *Ordinatio* altogether, Wodeham shows some hesitation. He writes: "I say that the argument of Scotus given above is probably able to be persuasive" (LS II: 171). Thus he again shows that even though it is his own opinion that God is specifically one, it is possible for doubt to continue to linger. ### 5.3 Philosophy and the Trinity Adam Wodeham's trinitarian theology is developed in the *Lectura* (d. 2, d. 3 q. 5; d. 7; dd. 9-16; dd. 18-21; dd. 23-26) and the *Ordinatio* I, d. 3; d. 33 qq. 1-9. The two accounts, despite their various formal placements in the two works, are often identical (e.g., LS d. 11, q. un. and OO d. 33, q. 6). Wodeham, however, did substantially re-work his discussion of the *imago Trinitatis* (LS d. 3, q. 5; OO I, d. 3), focusing in the latter work on the writings of Richard FitzRalph instead of Richard Campsall. Further, in the closing discussion of distinction 2 of the *Ordinatio*, Wodeham tells his readers that the discussion of the Trinity will be collected into the numerous questions of distinction 33. Wodeham's trinitarian theology has received little attention from scholars. However, there are several notable exceptions. Hester Gelber offers an analysis of *Ordinatio* I, dd. 33, qq. 1-3, concerning the formal distinction and formal non-identity (q. 1) and the complex problem of trinitarian paralogisms (qq. 2-3) (Gelber 1974, 235-264, 629-648). Russell Friedman treats the relationship between Peter Auriol and Adam Wodeham in the *Lectura secunda*, d. 7 on the question: *utrum potentia generandi possit communicari Filio* (whether the power to generate can be communicated to the Son) (1997, 342-349). Olli Hallamaa considers Wodeham's discussion of trinitarian paralogisms within the context of other fourteenth-century Franciscans (Hallamaa 2003). For our purposes Gelber's and Hallamaa's analyses of trinitarian paralogisms are the most relevant philosophically, as Wodeham debates the universality of Aristotelian logic with respect to the doctrine of the Trinity. Like many of his Oxford contemporaries, Adam Wodeham was particularly concerned with solving the tension between Aristotelian logic and trinitarian theology. In the *Lectura secunda*, Wodeham did not address the problem in a substantial way (see LS III, 446-448), although in the *Ordinatio* he devotes a specific question to the problem of whether there is a "certain rule or art" through which one can solve trinitarian paralogisms (OO I, d. 33, q. 3). The problem of trinitarian paralogisms arises when one considers certain syllogisms regarding the Trinity. God, according to Church teaching, is one simple divine essence and three distinct divine persons (Father, Son and Holy Spirit). And, when some valid syllogisms are formulated according to Aristotelian rules, paradoxes arise in which both premises are true and the conclusion is false. For example: | | | | --- | --- | | This divine essence is the Father | *Haec essentia divina est Pater* | | This divine essence is the Son | *Haec essentia divina est Filius* | | Therefore, the Son is the Father | *Ergo Filius est Pater.* | In this valid expository syllogism, both of the premises are true according to Church teaching, but the conclusion is false. The theologians of the first half of the fourteenth century developed two strategies when confronting such syllogisms. First, some theologians denied the universality of Aristotelian logic outside of the natural order. This approach, which remained in the minority, can be found in the author of the *Centiloquium theologicum* (*OPh* VII, SS 56-59, 469-472) and in Robert Holcot's commentary on the *Sentences* (Holcot 1518, q. 5) (albeit Holcot's position changes in other parts of his corpus, cf. Gelber 1974). In his commentary, Holcot remains ambiguous about his eventual solution, although he writes that there are two logics: the logic of faith (*logica fidei*) and the logic of the natural order (*logica naturalis*). Second, and more moderately, most theologians insisted that Aristotelian logic is universal--thus, valid in both the natural and supernatural realms--but that the trinitarian syllogisms in question are not valid syllogisms, despite their seemingly valid form. This approach was shared by William of Ockham and Adam Wodeham. Adam Wodeham, in the first two questions of distinction 33, surveys the traditional methods of solving the problem of trinitarian paralogisms (Gelber 1974, 235-253), and in the third question finally offers his own response. It is not possible to recount all of Wodeham's methods for addressing such paralogisms, but it is useful to consider the following syllogism: | | | | --- | --- | | Every divine essence is the Father | *Omnis essentia divina est Pater* | | Every divine essence is the Son | *Omnis essentia divina est Filius* | | Therefore, the Son is the Father | *Ergo Filius est Pater.* | In the above case, the two premises are universal. As such, the syllogism should be governed by "all or none": meaning that, with respect to a given subject and predicate, what is said of all (*dici de omni*) of the subject (essence) must also be said of the predicate (Father) (OO I, d. 33, q. 3, a. 2). In the above argument, there is a fallacy of the figure of speech because not everything said of the divine essence is predicable to the Father, because the term *divine essence* (subject) supposits for the Son and Holy Spirit while the term *Father* (predicate) does not. Thus, the premise is not sufficiently universal and violates the rules of a valid expository syllogism (Gelber 1974, 255-256). This is one of Wodeham's methods for addressing trinitarian paralogisms, and effectively captures his basic method and approach to such problems. Further, it helps elucidate Wodeham's broader approach to the role of Aristotelian logic within theology and his characteristically "analytic" approach to questions of philosophical theology. ## 6. Natural Philosophy Adam Wodeham's *Tractatus de indivisibilibus* and *Tractatus alphabeticus* establish him as one of the leading representatives of the *theologia Anglicana*. This group of thinkers, including the Oxford Calculators, was heavily influenced by natural philosophy and its implications for a range of philosophical and theological problems. Wodeham's discussion of the *continuum* and the latitude of forms demonstrates his place within this philosophical tradition. ### 6.1 The *Continuum* Adam Wodeham, like many of his English contemporaries in the first decades of the fourteenth century, was embroiled in the debate over divisibilism and indivisibilism (atomism). Following William of Ockham, Adam Wodeham was a divisibilist who argued in his *Tractatus de indivisibilibus* against philosophical atomism (indivisibilism). Wodeham cites extensively from the writings of divisibilists and indivisibilists, such that his *Tractatus de indivisibilibus* is a rich source for tracing the history of this long and complex debate (Wood 1988, 14). Aristotle, in the sixth book of the *Physics*, develops several arguments against the idea that *continua* are composed of atoms or indivisibles. The majority of medieval philosophers accepted Aristotle's position, but by the end of the thirteenth century there developed a minority opinion that supported indivisibilism. The most famous proponents of indivisibilism were Robert Grosseteste (d. 1253), Henry Harclay (d. 1317), Walter Chatton (d. 1343), Gerard Odon (d. 1349), William Crathorn (fl. 1330s) and Nicholas Bonet (d. 1360). The divisibilists/indivisibilist debate in the fourteenth century was concerned with the philosophical status of space and time. Spacial-temporal reality, according to the traditional Aristotelian view, was infinitely divisible. Thus, authors like Thomas Bradwardine and Adam Wodeham follow Aristotle and Averroes in defending the view that the *continuum* is composed of divisible parts without end, and not of atoms. This view (divisibilism) is the one defended by Adam Wodeham in his magisterial *Tractatus de indivisibilibus*. In response to the classical divisibilist position supported by Aristotle, the indivisibilists held that there were "indivisibles" which constituted the composition of temporal and spatial *continua*, e.g., temporal instants and lines respectively. Such "indivisibles", in the early 14th century, were understood to be an extended and simple ontological unit, but not physical atoms *per se*. It is helpful here to consider briefly an indivisibilist account, before turning to the divisibilism of Wodeham. Henry Harclay and Walter Chatton are two relatively well known medieval philosophers who supported indivisibilism. Thinkers such as Harclay and Chatton argued, in response to Aristotle, for the possibility that a *continuum* is composed of indivisibles. The individual components, or indivisibles, were generally held to be extensionless regardless of whether or not the individual thinker understood there to be an infinite (Harclay) or finite (Chatton) number of indivisibles in a given *continuum*. But, as is well know, such indivisibilists accounts were generally so defensive in their posture--arguing for the mere possibility of indivisibles--that it is difficult to ascertain the broader philosophical motivations which grounded such arguments. John Murdoch argues that there are perhaps two motives that can be gleamed for the texts: (1) indivisibles may have been useful as a method of accounting for the motion of angels; or (2) indivisibles may have been useful when addressing the inequality of infinites (Murdoch 1982, 576-577). Although, he notes that such motivations are mentioned only in passing and that a broader motivation could have simply been that "the analysis of Aristotle's arguments against indivisibilism uncovered loopholes in them" (Murdoch 1982, 577). The *Tractatus de indivisibilibus* consists of five questions and it is instructive to consider the content briefly. 1. In the first question, containing three articles, Wodeham considers whether or not forms, or extended *continua*, are composed of indivisibles. In the first article Wodeham develops twelve arguments against the indivisibilists, anticipates responses to those arguments, and rejects them (TI 35-93). In the second article, he considers twelve arguments, from Henry Harclay and Walter Chatton, in support of the thesis that forms are composed of indivisibles (TI 93-101). And, in the third article, Wodeham responds to the arguments of Harclay and Chatton (TI 103-121). This first article comprises about a third of the work, and the first article in particular contains many of Wodeham's most significant arguments. 2. In the second question, Wodeham treats the problem of whether or not extended forms or objects are composed of indivisibles. In response, Wodeham (following Ockham) argues in the first article against the existence of points, lines or surfaces (TI 123-139). And, as with the previous question, the second and third articles consider arguments in defense of indivisibles and responses to those arguments (TI 139-163). 3. The third question entertains seven doubts relating to the divisibilist position. In the first four doubts Wodeham treats Zeno's famous paradoxes (as reported by Aristotle in his *Physics* VI) (TI 165-183), and in the last three doubts he treats more contemporary arguments (TI 183-211). 4. The fourth question considers whether or not a *continuum* is infinitely divisible. Thus, if a *continuum* can be divided, why cannot it be infinitely divided? To this question Wodeham provides an argument that a *continuum* cannot be divided (a. 1) (TI 213-225) and an argument to the contrary (a. 2) (TI 225-235). 5. The final question considers whether or not there are more parts, of the same proportion, in a larger *continuum* than in a smaller one. In three articles, Wodeham considers an argument for the claim that there are more respective parts in a larger *continuum* (a. 1) (TI 239-247), objections to this argument (a. 2) (TI 247-261), and finally replies to the objections (a. 3) (TI 261-273). In the second doubt of question 3 (LT 171-175; P13-20), as noted above, Wodeham considers the argument of Zeno (recorded in Aristotle's *Physics*) against those who argue that motion is compatible with the divisibility of a *continuum*. This particular argument, familiar to all students of ancient philosophy, is exemplary both of Wodeham's historical approach to the questions posed by the *continuum* and his own method of argumentation. Thus, it is instructive to consider the argument in some detail. Wodeham records Zeno's argument as: > > > If every continuum is infinitely divisible, then every movable object > traversing any space will reach the middle of that [space] before the > end, and consequently it will reach the middle of the second half > before reading [the end] of the completing [part] of that half, and > then [it will reach] the middle of that next fourth [before] its > completing [part]. Therefore if such halves are infinite proportional > [parts], and if it does not happen that [a moveable object] traverses > infinitely many [parts] in a finite time, then it is impossible that > any space be traversed in a finite time. And consequently, it is > impossible that anything move locally (LT 172-173; > P14). > > > Wodeham, who is a divisibilist, offers a response to Zeno's "paradox" because it is necessary to avoid the *reductio ad absurdum* (i.e., there is no motion) posed by the claim that an infinitely divisible finite space is not traversable. Wodeham begins by considering Averroes's argument that Aristotle, in the *Physics* VI, contradicts the "words, not the substance, of Zeno's discourse" (LT 173; P15). But, Wodeham does not agree with Averroes's interpretation of Aristotle, and he defends Aristotle's argument. Wodeham argues that Aristotle recognizes that Zeno's argument "supposes falsely" that it is "not possible to traverse something infinite ... in a finite time" (LT 173; P16), although he also correctly recognizes that there is more to be said in response to Zeno. Further, Wodeham argues that Aristotle recognized that there is an equivocation with respect to the term "infinite" as applied to a *continuum* of space or time: infinite can be understood with respect to "division", or with respect to "infinite ends". That is, the term infinite can refer to the infinite divisibility of a given finite *continuum* of space or time, or the term can refer to the fact that space or time extends without end or termination (LT 173; P17). Because of this equivocation, the phrase "a moveable object may traverse infinitely many things in a finite time" can be understood in two ways: either (1) as stating that a moveable object traverses infinitely many things that are extensively never terminated in a finite time; or (2) as stating that a moveable object traverse infinitely many non-equal things (that a given *continuum* is divided into) in a finite time (LT 173-175; P18). In the former sense the claim is false, in the latter sense it is true. And, in this way, Aristotle solves Zeno's "paradox" to Wodeham's satisfaction. Finally, Wodeham analyzes William of Ockham's interpretation--in the *Expositio Physicorum* (OP V, ll. 49-56)--of Averroes's argument that Aristotle addresses the words and not the substance of Zeno's argument. Wodeham, recording Ockham's argument, implies that Ockham's reading of Averroes is too "charitable", concluding that "if [Averroes] did understand [the matter] in the manner expounded here, both his exposition and what he expounds are false" (LT 175; P175). As demonstrated by this brief example, in the *Tractatus de indivisibilibus* Adam Wodeham engages at length with the ancient and medieval philosophical tradition. Further, throughout the work he quotes extensively from William of Ockham's *Exposition Physicorum* and his *Tractatus de quantitate*. Wodeham also considers in detail the arguments of Henry Harclay and Walter Chatton, all of which provides a useful historical record of this heated debate. But, ultimately, the work remains a barrage of arguments against the indivisibilist, or atomist, position as defended in the early fourteenth century. ### 6.2 The Latitude of Forms In his minor work, the *Tractatus alphabeticus*, Wodeham takes up the question of qualitative change and offers a position that is consistent with his overall opposition to atomism (cf. Wood 1990). According to Sylla, there were three dominant views of qualitative change that shaped the context of the discussion: the succession theory, the addition theory, and the admixture theory (Sylla 1973, 230-232). The succession and addition theory distinguish themselves from the admixture theory in that they are both committed to the fact that qualitative forms themselves do not change in degree. Rather it is the subject that changes in degree through the acquisition of a new qualitative form (cf. Sylla 1973, 232; Wood 1990, 375). Wodeham, in relative concord with the views of Ockham and FitzRalph and against the Mertonian Campsall and his usual nemesis Walter Chatton, argues against the admixture theory. He claims that it is impossible for one and the same quality to be changed while retaining its identity. As Wood says: > > > Addition and succession of forms theorists agree on this issue; in no > sense is it true that the same form undergoes remission or > intension...strictly speaking it is the subject, not the form, > which becomes more white, more hot or more charitable. (Wood 1990, > 375) > > > A helpful analog can be found in the case of numbers. When the number 9 is increased to 10, Wodeham understands the admixture theorist to be claiming that the same form has been intensified, but he wonders how this numerically identical form can really be said to retain its old identity now that it has been increased to 10 and is no longer 9. While the succession and addition theorist are united in their opposition to any admixture, and while both believe that intension and remission occur in the subject and not in the qualitative form, they disagree about just how this intension and remission occurs. In the *Tractatus alphabeticus*, Wodeham shows himself to be numbered among the addition theorists. The key difference here is that the succession theorist believes that when a quality increases a new form of a given quality destroys and then replaces the old form. Wodeham and the addition theorist disagree. They hold that when qualitative change happens, a new form is indeed acquired, but it does not destroy the proceeding form. On the contrary, the new form takes in the preceding form as one of its parts. And here, the analogy of quantitative change is again helpful. When 9 increases to 10, the succession theorist argues that the old form of 9 is completely destroyed and replaced by an entirely new form, where no part of the old form of 9 contributes to the new form of 10. In opposition, the addition theorist argues that when a quality increases, this is analogous to the number 1 being added to 9, and through this addition, the new form of 10 is created. In this case, the old form of 9 has not been destroyed, but rather becomes a part of the new whole. A critical underlying difference between the succession and addition theorists is the question over whether forms are indivisible or can be perpetually broken down into smaller parts. The succession theorist thinks forms are indivisible and do not contain parts (Sylla 1973, 231). But Adam Wodeham, in harmony with his general anti-atomists position, argues that forms can be infinitely divided. In this way, there is no trouble in saying that, through addition, a new form is created, which contains the old form as one of its parts. ## 7. Ethics ### 7.1 Moral Goodness Since the *Lectura secunda* does not extend beyond book I, the moral philosophy of Adam Wodeham found in book IV of the *Ordinatio* has remained relatively unexamined. However, in 1981 Marilyn Adams and Rega Wood edited the tenth question of Book IV of the *Ordinatio*, providing us with a glimpse into Wodeham's moral philosophy. Question ten concentrates on the moral worth or goodness of an action. Here the philosophical debate is about whether the moral worth of action resides in the choice of the will alone (in the manner of Kant) or whether moral goodness can be ascribed to the performance of actions themselves, independent of the intention of the agent. Wodeham's discussion is embedded in a larger Franciscan discussion, whose main players are Scotus and Walter Chatton on the one hand, and Ockham and Wodeham on the other. The discussion is grounded in the distinction between purely internal acts (or volitional acts, acts within the power of the will) and external acts (or acts that can only be indirectly controlled by the will). In the case of the latter (an external act), the power of the will is not sufficient, and another source of power is needed. Scotus's position, as understood by Wodeham, states that while an external act can only be good if it falls under the control of the will (cf. Adams and Wood 1981, 9), the external and indirectly controlled act can nevertheless contribute *an additional* moral goodness beyond the moral value accrued through the act of volition. The result is that while willing to do the right thing or bad thing is in itself praiseworthy or blameworthy, executing and performing that act can impute to the agent further praise or blame, depending on how well one performs the willed act (cf. Adams and Wood 1981, 9). Wodeham, like Ockham, finds this position rather confusing. If someone performs a morally praiseworthy volition, but this volition is not able to be executed, the only reason for this failure of performance is some impotency within the agent. But Wodeham insists that no one should be damned for not doing what is not in their power to do (OO IV, 57-59, ll. 11-30; cf. Adams and Wood 1981, 14). Thus, no one can earn more merit for simply having the potency to perform the action that they willed meritoriously. Having or not having the potency to execute that volition does not fall under the free power of the agent, and, even for Scotus, only those acts that "are under the free power of the agent" are imputable acts (Adams and Wood 1981, 9 and 14). ### 7.2 Morality, the Will, and the Nature of Faith For Walter Chatton, Ockham and Wodeham's position on the amoral status of external acts leads to unsavory consequences. Among other things, Chatton is concerned about the implications of Wodeham's position for the necessity of faith. Wodeham's reply not only gives us a nice illustration of how his moral theory plays out in concrete instances, but also provides us with a helpful introduction to his position on the nature of belief and its connection to the will. Chatton is concerned that if one holds a position similar to the one of Wodeham there will no longer be any need for faith or belief, but only the desire to believe. Chatton has this concern because, for him, the act of belief is not directly under the control of the will (cf; OO IV 36, ll. 20-23). Wodeham responds by starkly distinguishing between two kinds of faith. Infused faith, which appears to be a pure act of the will and acquired faith which is not a direct act of the will and is not required for salvation (OO IV 58, ll.13-14). Presumably, this act of acquired belief is an act of the intellect and a response to the relative evidence of a given proposition or an entire syllogism taken together (see above *An Evident Judgment*). With this distinction in place, Wodeham uses his moral theory to show that the act of acquired belief, described as the act of believing calmly (*quiete*) and presumably without intellectual hesitation or doubt, does not add any moral worth. This is the case since, as we have already seen, if one wishes to believe, but is prevented from doing so *by a lack of power*, the agent should not be held responsible for this lack of power. Reasons for such a lack of power include a melancholic disturbance, a passion, or sophism (OO IV 58, ll. 15-18). He further concludes, it is quite possible that the person who wishes to believe, but is not able to do so calmly (*quiete*), may be more morally praiseworthy than the person who intellectually believes "quietly" and is not beset by doubt. Intriguingly, he critiques Lombard at this point, saying: > > > If the Master means to say that in order to achieve salvation one must > believe with something more than a perfect will, but must also have > belief calmly (*quiete*), then he does think > correctly ... . (OO IV 58, ll. 26-29) > > >
wolff-christian
## 1. Biographical Sketch Christian Wolff was born 24 January 1679 in Breslau in the province of Silesia (now part of Poland) to parents of modest means.[1] Wolff was educated at the Lutheran-humanist Maria-Magdelena-Gymansium, where his teachers included Christian Gryphius (1649-1706), a baroque poet and dramatist, and Caspar Neumann (1648-1715), the latter of whom Wolff credited with introducing him to the Cartesian philosophy. In 1699, Wolff enrolled at the University of Jena, where he pursued a course of study in theology, physics, and mathematics, moving from there to Leipzig in 1702 where he would sit the *Magisterexamen* and then complete his *Habilitationsschrift* in 1703 entitled: *Philosophia practica universalis, methodo mathematica conscripta* (On Universal Practical Philosophy, composed according to the Mathematical Method). Otto Mencke (1644-1707), the founder of the learned journal *Acta eruditorum*, served as an examiner for the dissertation and, impressed, sent it to Leibniz, with whom Wolff subsequently struck up a correspondence that continued until Leibniz's death in 1716. Due in part to Leibniz's support, Wolff was soon offered, and accepted, a position in Giessen (though he had also been offered positions at Danzig and Wismar) which he intended to take up after visiting his family in Breslau. However, on his homeward journey the occupation of Saxony by Charles XII of Sweden required Wolff to take a detour through nearby Halle in Prussia, whose recently founded university also happened to be in need of a professor of mathematics. Wolff was offered the position and, again with Leibniz's assistance, was able to extricate himself from his commitment to Giessen, delivering his inaugural lecture at Halle in early 1707. During the next 15 years he enjoyed a prolific period, publishing and lecturing at first primarily in mathematics and natural science, though he began to lecture in philosophy proper around 1710.[2] Wolff's first major philosophical textbook was published in 1713, the *Vernunfftige Gedancken von den Krafften des menschlichen Verstandes und ihrem richtigen Gebrauche in Erkantnis der Wahrheit* (Rational Thoughts on the Powers of the Human Understanding and its Propert Use in the Cognition of Truth) [the *German Logic*, hereafter GL]. In 1720, Wolff published his German textbook on metaphysics, the *Vernunftige Gedanken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen uberhaupt* (Rational Thoughts on God, the World and the Soul of Man, and on All Things in General) [the *German Metaphysics*, hereafter GM]. These were followed by further German textbooks on ethics (1720), politics (1721), and physics (1723). Wolff's expanding philosophical activity, especially concerning topics in natural theology, as well as his popularity as a lecturer and growing influence within the university drew the ire of his Pietist colleagues in the faculty of theology, including August Hermann Francke (1663-1723), the founder of the famous *Waisenhaus* (orphanage), and Joachim Lange (1670-1744). They took exception to a number of doctrines expressed in Wolff's *German Metaphysics*, including its privileging of the intellect to the will, its apparent demotion of freedom to mere spontaneity, and the diminished role played by revelation in matters of theological interest. While the Pietists were at first content to wage a behind-the-scenes campaign, Wolff's address as outgoing rector of the university on 12 July 1721, in which he defended the reasonableness of Confucian moral philosophy, led to a significant escalation of the dispute. Wolff, asserting the independence of the philosophical faculty, refused to submit the text of his lecture for subsequent examination by the faculty of theology, a conflict that came to involve the university senate and even king Frederick Wilhelm I (the "soldier king") himself. While Wolff enjoyed the support of officials within the royal court, the Pietists exploited their personal connections with the king, who was ultimately persuaded that Wolff's endorsement of the pre-established harmony represented a threat to military discipline (as the acts of deserters would be pre-established and so not subject to sanction). On 8 November 1723, the king issued an edict removing Wolff from his university position and ordering him to leave Prussia within 48 hours on pain of hanging. The edict was received in Halle four days later, and Wolff immediately left Prussian lands on 12 November 1723. While Wolff's Pietist colleagues celebrated Wolff's exile (reportedly even from the pulpit), it ultimately served only to enhance Wolff's reputation, bringing him to the attention of luminaries of the Enlightenment, including Voltaire. He was immediately offered positions in Leipzig and Marburg, the latter of which he accepted though a special exemption had to be granted to allow a Lutheran to teach at a Reformed university. And even as the dispute with his critics continued, generating a substantial literature in its own right, Wolff managed during his Marburg years to complete a reworked Latin presentation of his theoretical philosophy intended to make his ideas available to a pan-European audience. These texts include: *Philosophia rationalis sive Logica* (*Rational Philosophy, or Logic*) of 1728 [the *Latin Logic*, hereafter LL], the first part of which is the *Discursus praeliminaris de philosophia in genere* (*Preliminary Discourse on Philosophy in General*) [DP]; the *Philosophia prima sive Ontologia* (*First Philosophy, or Ontology*) of 1730 [Ont.]; *Cosmologia generalis* (*General Cosmology*) of 1731 [Cosm.]; *Psychologia empirica* (*Empirical Psychology*) of 1732 [EP]; the *Psychologia rationalis* (*Rational Psychology*) of 1734 [RP]; and the two-volume *Theologia naturalis* (*Natural Theology*) of 1736-37 [NT]. Friedrich Wilhelm I eventually thought better of his precipitous action against Wolff, as he attempted in 1733 to entice him (unsuccessfully) back to Halle and in 1736 lifted a prohibition he had enacted against the teaching of Wolffian texts. However, Wolff remained in Marburg, collecting tributes and memberships in learned societies, until the ascension of Friedrich Wilhelm I's son, Friedrich II (the Great), himself an enlightened monarch and admirer of Wolff. Wolff accepted the new king's offer of a professorship and vice-chancellorship at his previous institution in Halle and returned to the city on 6 December 1740 to take up his new position. Wolff continued to lecture and publish actively, with his later efforts devoted particularly to works on the law of peoples, natural law, and ethics. He died in Halle on 9 April 1754. ## 2. Philosophical Sources and Relationship with Leibniz Wolff's wide intellectual interests saw him exposed to a diverse set of influences. Neumann not only acquainted Wolff during his time at Gymansium with the Cartesian philosophy but impressed on him the need for "mathematical" treatments of philosophical topics (including natural theology and practical philosophy). Wolff also familiarized himself with late Scholastic philosophy, through a textbook by Johannes Scharf (1595-1660), a follower of Suarez; indeed, Wolff's mastery of Scholastic thinking was displayed in his successful disputations with students at the rival (Catholic) St.-Elizabeth-Gymnasium. While Wolff's own later philosophy would likewise be branded a form of scholasticism, or *Schulphilosophie*, the extent of the influence of Scholastic philosophers, such as Suarez, upon his thought is debated (Ecole 2001, Leduc 2018). Wolff's interest in mathematics was encouraged by his teachers, which interest ultimately brought him to Jena where he attended classes from G. A. Hamberger (1662-1716), the successor of Erhard Weigel (1625-99); he also studied a Euclidean textbook by J. C. Sturm (1635-1703), though his reflection on its obscurities reportedly brought him his "first light concerning the ancient method of demonstration" (Wuttke 1841: 122-3). A rather important if under-appreciated early influence on Wolff's thinking, particularly concerning scientific method, was Ehrenfried Walther von Tschirnhaus (1651-1708). Tschirnhaus, a Saxon nobleman, studied at the University of Leiden where the Cartesian Geulincx was active,[3] and was an important member of Spinoza's circle of friends (among whom he circulated the *Ethics*). Yet, Tschirnhaus was also an active scientist, mathematician, and inventor, who among other things played a (perhaps *the*) key role in the discovery of the secret for making porcelain. Tschirnhaus' principal philosophical work is his *Medicina mentis* (1687, 2nd ed. 1695), and he characterizes his aim there as outlining a "certain and constant method" for the discovery of all unknown truths. Wolff first gained an interest in reading the *Medicina mentis* while at Gymnasium, but it was only after taking up his mathematical studies in Jena in 1699 that he found himself able to profit from reading it. Wolff evidently read the text with great interest and care, marking his own copy with comments and queries and later preparing an excerpted text for use in lectures for students without the requisite mathematical background. Wolff even sought out Tschirnhaus himself during an Easter book fair in Leipzig to press him with his concerns relating to his method. (After Tschirnhaus' death in 1708 Wolff inquired as to the status of his manuscripts but was disappointed to learn that, like Spinoza, he had ordered them destroyed). It was G. W. Leibniz, however, who would exercise the most consequential influence on Wolff, both professionally (as seen above) and philosophically. Wolff is often described as a disciple or follower of Leibniz, a characterization for which there is some justification. So, central tenets of Wolff's philosophical system closely resemble those advanced by Leibniz. The commitment to metaphysics, the extensive use of the principle of sufficient reason, and the (qualified) endorsement of the pre-established harmony are among many striking points of agreement. Indeed, Wolff appears not only to accept the principles and methods of analysis posed by Leibniz, but he also identifies opponents to his system, such as Descartes, Spinoza, and the Atomists, that Leibniz opposed in his own. To describe Wolff as merely a disciple of Leibniz, however, is misleading in several respects. First and foremost, this characterization undercuts the important philosophical differences that existed between the two men. Second it misconstrues the nature of their relationship and the type of intellectual exchange that transpired between them. During the early part of Wolff's career, and the period when he corresponded with Leibniz, Wolff's primary focus was in the field of mathematics. It is maintained that Wolff was the first to teach calculus formally in Germany (Beck 1969: 257). According to Wolff's own report (Wuttke 1841: 146), when he arrived at Halle in 1707, mathematics was "entirely neglected, nay quite unknown, in that place". With the exception of his *German Logic*, Wolff's energy early in his career was directed at producing a four-volume *Elements of All the Mathematical Sciences* [German edition 1710, and Latin edition 1713] as well as a *Mathematical Lexicon* [1716]. In this light, it is perhaps not surprising to find the bulk of the Wolff-Leibniz correspondence dedicated to issues in mathematics. Although they also exchanged ideas on philosophical topics (for discussion, see Rutherford 2004), their philosophical correspondence centered primarily on ethics and philosophical theology. Leibniz published his *Theodicy* in 1710, and this work remained the only extended presentation of his philosophical ideas published in his lifetime. Apart from a handful of other smaller articles written on philosophical topics, most notably, *Meditations on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas* [1684], *A Specimen of Dynamics* [1695], and *On Nature Itself* [1698], there were relatively few texts available, and hardly any from what is regarded today as the core of Leibniz's *corpus*, from which Wolff could have extracted a definitive statement of Leibniz's philosophy. Consider a remark by Leibniz to Nicolas Remond, in a letter dated July 1714: > > > Mr. Wolff has adopted some of my opinions, but since he is very busy > with teaching, especially in mathematics, and we have not had much > correspondence together on philosophy, he can know very little about > my opinions beyond those which I have published. (Leibniz 1989b: > 657) > > > The philosophical works by Leibniz that we typically consider today to represent his mature philosophical views were published posthumously. *The Principles of Nature and Grace* appeared in 1718, *The Monadology* in 1720, and the *New Essays Concerning Human Understanding* as late as 1765. Although the early Kant and later German thinkers had the benefit of these texts, Wolff had no such luxury when writing his *German Metaphysics* in 1719. What is significant about considering the relationship between Wolff and Leibniz is that although there is clear evidence that Leibniz was a direct influence on Wolff, there is also equal evidence that testifies to Wolff's independence from Leibniz, particularly when Wolff was formulating and first presenting his philosophical views (cf. Corr 1975 for an influential discussion). Recognizing Wolff's independence is perhaps important for understanding what Kant and his contemporaries understood by the expression "Leibnizian-Wolffian philosophy". Instead of taking this expression to mean "the philosophy of Leibniz, interpreted and presented by Wolff and his followers", as it commonly is, it is perhaps preferable to understand the expression to mean "Wolff's philosophical system, variously corrected and improved through the posthumously discovered views of Leibniz". ## 3. Wolff on Philosophy, Science, and Method Early in his career, until shortly after his expulsion from Halle, Wolff primarily presented his work in the German vernacular. His reasons for choosing German, rather than Latin, the standard languages for academic texts in Germany at the time, were both tactical and theoretical. Before Wolff, there were very few philosophical works written in German. By providing treatises on logic and metaphysics, Wolff was able to service a noticeable gap in the German university curriculum while at the same time promoting his own philosophical agenda. Prior to Wolff's contributions, the standard text books in philosophy were largely outdated Lutheran-scholastic treatises modeled after the treatises of Philipp Melanchthon (1497-1560) (cf. Beck 1969: 189-94, 101-10). Unlike English and French universities, which had set aside hidebound scholasticism and embraced modern ideas and systems, German universities (often under the direct jurisdiction of local theological authorities) were slow to make such a change. But Wolff also had deep-seated theoretical reasons for writing a German-language philosophy. He believed that the goal and purpose of philosophy should not only be rooted in what he calls "the pursuit of the knowledge of the truth" but also in its utility and the practical value it has for humans in their everyday life. In the preface to his *German Logic*, he writes: > > > a person should learn philosophy ...[not with] a view to the > vicious taste of the schools for idle disputation and wrangling, but > in order to [enjoy its] usefulness in future life.... (GL: > lxxvii; cf. also Corr 1970) > > > By writing a German-language philosophy, Wolff sought to transform philosophy from a discipline that had become mired in formalism and centered around traditionally defined topics to a discipline that had genuine utility for German students. Among the practical aims of Wolff's philosophy is outfitting the mind with the tools it needs to pursue and attain properly scientific knowledge, in contrast with "common" or "vulgar" knowledge, or as Wolff sometimes says "the natural way of thinking". If certain groups of facts can be shown to follow from "well-grounded" assumptions according to strict requirements of demonstration, the class of facts is deemed by Wolff to constitute a "science". Wolff gives several definitions of the term science: > > > By science, I understand, that habit of the understanding, whereby, in > a manner not to be refuted, we establish our assertions on > irrefragable grounds or principles (GL: c. 1, SS2). > > > > By science here I mean the habit of demonstrating propositions, i.e., > the habit of inferring conclusions by legitimate sequence from certain > and immutable principles (DP: SS30). > > > > Science is the capacity to prove from indisputable grounds everything > one asserts or, in a word, the capacity to demonstrate; and in > demonstration truths are connected together; therefore through science > one knows the connection of truths, and thus science comes from reason > (GM: SS383). > > > While Wolff emphasizes that science is a "habit of the understanding", this should be taken to also involve the human capacity of *reason*, inasmuch as it is the faculty for perceiving the connection between truths. When properly employed, then, human reason can discern groups of facts, establish a certain order and interconnectedness between these facts, and ultimately justify them as being certain parts of human knowledge. Put slightly differently, science is a disposition or ability of the human mind to conceive the facts of reality in an ordered and structured way. Individual sciences, therefore, such as theology, cosmology, or psychology, are simply the various sets, or subsets of demonstrable cognitions and the principles (including axioms, definitions, and empirical facts) from which they are derived. Wolff's system is also structured according to a notion of rational order. The "order of science" pertains to the relationship not only between individual sciences but also between the sets of discoverable facts within each given discipline (cf. DP: SSSS132-5). The central idea here is that certain truths are known prior to, and serve as a basis for discovering, other truths. And just as there are certain facts that are more fundamental and serve as a basis for discovering other facts, there are, Wolff believes, certain sciences whose subject matter is more basic and which ultimately stand as the foundation for other sciences that have a more specialized focus. For example, in the "order of demonstration", physics follows general cosmology which, in turn, follows ontology (or first philosophy) (DP: SSSS94-5). It appears, at first glance, that Wolff's insistence on the rational order of science simply follows from a dogmatic metaphysical claim about the structure of reality. A reasonable objection to Wolff might be that his conception of the rational order of science is based on an unwarranted assumption about the harmonious order he believes to be present in all facets of reality. This harmonious order (the objection continues) illicitly presupposes that a divine architect has created everything according to a plan and thus the rational order of human science is simply an upshot of God's creative power. There are certainly passages of Wolff's works that lend support to such an objection (see for instance GL: c. 16, SS3). However, to reduce Wolff's view of the rational order of science to simply a dogmatic metaphysical claim really ignores the practical and common sense dimensions to his thought. An important part of the reason why Wolff believes that there is a rational order to science is because of the progress he believes he has witnessed in such sciences as astronomy and optics, which he believes have utilized such an order when establishing various scientific truths (DP: SS139). By virtue of the very interconnectedness of the different disciplines (most notably, mathematics with physics and physics with astronomy) the claim for an intrinsic rational order among the sciences is seen by Wolff to be a pragmatic explanation for what is already largely observed and accepted as the *status quo* among many natural philosophers (GL: c. 1, SS39). Unlike Leibniz, Wolff was much more willing to embrace the advances brought in the name of Newtonian natural philosophy (on this, see the next section). Wolff gives the following definition of philosophy in his *German Logic*: "[p]hilosophy is the *science* of all possible things, together with the manner and reason of their possibility" (Preface, SS1). Now because of its subject matter, philosophy is considered by Wolff to be the broadest and most fundamental science. In the classification of sciences given in his *Preliminary Discourse*, Wolff first divides philosophy into two branches: practical philosophy, on one hand, and theoretical philosophy, on the other. Practical philosophy deals (in general) with human actions and includes morality, politics, jurisprudence, and economics. Theoretical philosophy, by contrast, deals with sets of possible and actual objects and is (itself) divided into three separate branches: (1) ontology, or metaphysics *proper*, (2) "special" metaphysics, which includes general cosmology, psychology and natural theology, and (3) physics (DP: SS92). Whereas ontology and general cosmology are considered by Wolff to be completely "pure" (or *a priori*) sciences, psychology, natural theology, and physics are considered to be based upon empirical (i.e., historical) principles. As a brief aside, Wolff and the Critical Kant hold very different views on the relationship between practical and theoretical philosophy. Whereas Wolff believes that all of practical philosophy is subordinated to metaphysics (i.e., ontology as well as the three sub-disciplines that comprise special metaphysics), the Critical Kant argues for the independence of practical from theoretical principles. Wolff, in stark contrast, maintains that discoveries and conclusions made in practical philosophy are necessarily based upon prior conclusions drawn from ontology or metaphysics. Before turning to an examination of Wolff's theoretical philosophy, and metaphysics in particular, it will be helpful to first consider Wolff's distinctive, and often misunderstood, rationalism. ## 4. Wolffian Rationalism Philosophical rationalism can be understood to involve any or all of the following: commitment to the existence of innate ideas or principles, the privileging of *a priori* cognition to cognition known *a posteriori*, and endorsement of the principle of sufficient reason (*PSR*). Even though Wolff is officially agnostic regarding innate ideas, *a priori* cognition (at least in the traditional sense of a cognition *from grounds*) enjoys a privileged place in his system, and to be sure, *PSR* is central to Wolff's entire exposition of metaphysics and figures prominently in all levels of his philosophical system. Wolff is, accordingly, correctly identified as a philosophical rationalist; yet, this label has often inspired misleading characterizations of Wolff's thought as abjuring all reliance upon experience in the aim of constructing a pure intellectual system founded solely on the principle of contradiction. Such a caricature, however persistent, is to be firmly rejected on both historical and philosophical grounds. Historically, this misrepresentation of Wolff as an arch-rationalist ignores his liberal borrowings from, and deep engagement with, empiricistic and scientifically-minded thinkers, most notably Locke and Newton. In his capacity as reviewer for the *Acta eruditorum*, Wolff was intimately familiar with intellectual developments in England--indeed he was brought on by Mencke specifically in order to comment on the mathematical and scientific developments there (for which task Wolff taught himself English over a Summer)--and he wrote approving early reviews of Newton's *Optics* and Locke's *Opera posthuma*. In general, Wolff took Locke's "historical, plain method" as a model for his own empirical psychology, and admired the blending of reason and experiment that characterized Newton's method, even if Wolff was deeply skeptical of Newton's speculative and metaphysical excursions in the Queries in the Latin edition of the *Optics* and in the General Scholium of the second edition of the *Principia* (not to mention the metaphysical views explicitly defended by Samuel Clarke in the correspondence with Leibniz, for the German edition of which Wolff wrote the preface). Even so, Wolff's importance for the reception of Locke in Germany is currently under-appreciated (*vide* Fischer 1975), and his contributions to the reception of Newton have only recently been explored in some detail (see Dunlop 2013, Stan 2012). It might nonetheless be thought that Wolff's philosophy itself does not reflect this engagement with empiricism. Indeed, Wolff himself gives this impression when he states in the *German Metaphysics* that experience is opposed to reason such that they constitute "two paths to truth" (GM: SS372), and while the path of experience might suffice for the concerns of ordinary life, Wolff makes clear that the philosopher cannot rest content with it but must use reason to press beyond what experience offers. That this is so is reflected in Wolff's distinction between "common knowledge or cognition [*gemeine Erkantniss*]" and "the cognition of a philosopher [*Erkanntniss eines Welt-Weisen*]" which he first offers in the *German Logic*: > > > It can now be seen how common cognition is distinguished from the > cognition of a philosopher, namely, one who has no understanding of > philosophy can learn many things about what is possible from > experience, yet, he will not know how to indicate the reason why it > [i.e., that which he learns from experience] can be. For instance, he > learns from experience that it can rain, but cannot say how it happens > [...] nor indicate the causes why it rains. (GL: Preface, > SS6) > > > This would suggest, then, that for Wolff the path to genuinely philosophical truth is ultimately that of reason pursued independently of experience. Yet, a more careful look at Wolff's texts reveals that, rather than representing completely divergent paths, reason and experience are envisioned as forming a complementary whole, where experience provides an indispensable basis for properly philosophical cognition and even serves to confirm the latter's results. Indeed, the important *dependence* of philosophical cognition upon experiential cognition is emphasized in Wolff's later discussion in the *Preliminary Discourse*. There, Wolff labels the cognition of that which is and which happens *historical* cognition (DP: SS3), and contends that cognition of the reason of that which is or occurs, that is, philosophical cognition (DP: SS6), frequently relies on historical cognition as its foundation (*fundamenta*). This is the case, for instance, when we discover by means of experience something that can serve as the ground for something else that is or occurs (DP: SS10). Since that which is known directly through experience is, for Wolff, "firm and unshakeable" (DP: SS11), it follows that anyone who strives for philosophical cognition should not neglect the historical, or as Wolff claims, that > > > historical cognition should precede philosophical cognition and be > constantly conjoined with it so that it does not lack a firm > foundation. (DP: SS11; cf. Kreimendahl 2007) > > > Unsurprisingly, Wolff sets up his distinctive emphasis on experience and introduces his innovations in philosophical method in conscious opposition to his rationalist predecessors. He faults Descartes, for instance, for attempting to posit universal metaphysical principles "from which one will deduce through the mere understanding everything that is possible in nature" (Wolff 1723 [Preface]). Instead, Wolff recommends near the end of the *German Logic* that the philosopher should be trained > > > to draw determinate propositions from experience and with the help of > some to find the ground of others, consequently, to unite reason with > experience (GL: c. 16, SS11) > > > and later, in his oft-used metaphor, Wolff characterizes philosophical cognition itself as a "marriage of reason and experience [*connubium rationis et experientiae*]" (LL: SS1232; cf. Cataldi Madonna 2001). Ideally, then, Wolff construes reason and experience as converging toward a common end rather than constituting divergent paths, and the philosopher is warned against pursuing one at the expense of the other (DP: SS11). In this way, Wolff's rationalism clearly separates itself from the spirit of classical rationalism. ## 5. Metaphysics Philosophy is a science of possible and actual reality. According to Wolff's own taxonomy, theoretical philosophy is divided into three separate branches: ontology (or metaphysics *proper*), special metaphysics, and physics. Cosmology, as a branch of metaphysics, is a special or restricted science insofar as its subject matter deals with the "world-whole" rather than "being in general" (the subject matter of ontology). Although there is an important sense for Wolff in which ontology is relevant for, and even necessarily grounds cosmology and the other special sciences, cosmology (itself) stands in a grounding relationship to physics that is, yet again, a more narrow and specialized discipline (Cosm. SS121). Just as there are certain principles and certain truths established in ontology that are relevant for cosmology, there are certain principles and certain truths established in cosmology that are relevant for the more specialized science of physics. In fact, within Wolff's system there is complete uniformity from the top-down (so to speak), so that even principles of ontology are relevant for the discipline of physics. ### 5.1 Ontology Wolff's ontology is constructed on two foundational principles, namely, the principle of contradiction [*PC* hereafter] and the principle of sufficient reason. According to Wolff, *PC* is the fundamental principle of human thought, the very first principle of "all metaphysical first principles", and the "font [or source] of all certitude" (Ont. SSSS54-5). It is regarded by him to be a self-evident first principle, its truth made manifest through our inability to think in a manner contrary to it. In the *Ontologia*, he writes: > > > SS27. We experience...[*PC*]... in the nature of > our mind, in that, while it judges something to be, it is impossible > at the same time to judge the same not to be.... > > > > SS28....[I]t cannot happen that the same thing simultaneously > is and is not.... > > > > SS30....[For] ... contradiction is simultaneity in > affirming and denying. > > > *PC* is the "font of all certitude" insofar as, if it were called into question, the most evident and secure judgments of human knowledge, such as knowledge of the self (as a thinking thing), could likewise be called into question. We recognize the fact of our own existence by recognizing the psychological impossibility of denying it. But if it were possible both to affirm and also deny our own existence (simultaneously), then the experience of certitude that accompanies this cognition would thereby be undermined. Wolff contends that *PC* is not only for our thinking but, in defining the limits of what is conceivable or not, also serves to distinguish the possible from the impossible. So, impossibility, defined formally, is that which involves a contradiction, whereas that which does not is taken to be possible. Now for Wolff, "possible" and "possible thing" are basically synonymous terms. What is possible as a concept is simply reducible to what is possible as a thing. The realm of concepts and the ontological realm of objects converge in the Wolffian system (Kuehn 1997). A thing or "being" is defined as "that which does not involve a contradiction" (Ont. SS135). A possible concept, consequently, is that which corresponds to a possible object (Ont. SSSS57, 59, 60). This analysis of the concept of the possible typifies Wolff's non-existential and essence-centered approach to ontology. Very briefly, Wolff's understanding of being (or what is) involves regarding being in its most general sense. A being is "something" if and only if it is intrinsically possible, and something is intrinsically possible, if and only if its predicates or "determinations" are not contradictory. "Nothing", in contrast, is simply a term that is empty of all content. In the ontological realm of objects there is literally *no thing* to which "nothing" corresponds (Ont. SS57). Nothing, by definition, is not thinkable or conceivable. One important point to emphasize about Wolff's exposition of ontology is that existence (or the actual reality of being) is regarded exclusively as a determination or "complement" of a possible thing (Ont. SS174). Although existing things are included in his overall description of reality, they are not as a class of objects his primary focus. More accurately, existing objects figure into Wolff's metaphysical account only insofar as existing objects are a subset of possible things. With the notions of "possible thing", "something", and "nothing" firmly in hand, we can now explain the notion of reason (*Grund* or *ratio*) that Wolff includes in his definition of philosophy. Insofar as the subject matter of philosophy concerns the realm of all possible things, Wolff believes that the task of the philosopher is to provide "the manner and reason" of their possibility. Warrant for this claim is grounded in the idea that everything, whether possible or actual, has a "sufficient reason" for why it is rather than not. In SS56 of his *Ontologia*, he writes: "By sufficient reason we understand that from which it is understood why something is [or can be]". Unlike Leibniz who essentially restricts the notion of sufficient reason to "contingent truths of fact", Wolff considers the notion to have a much broader scope of application to include the set of all possible objects and what Leibniz calls "necessary truths of reason". The idea that everything has a sufficient reason is presented formally by Wolff as the principle of sufficient reason. Wolff's most extensive treatment of the *PSR* appears in SSSS56-78 of his *Ontologia*. In this discussion, Wolff appears to give two separate accounts of the theoretical origin of the principle. On the one hand, in SS70, Wolff provides a proof (or derivation) of *PSR* from *PC* and the notions of "something" and "nothing". And, on the other hand, in SS74, Wolff claims *PSR* is a principle of the human mind and a self-evident logical axiom. Although *prima facie*, it is unclear why Wolff attempts to advance both views, it is perhaps worth pointing out the difference between (1) being able to be demonstrate the truth of a proposition and (2) knowing the truth of a proposition because it is self-evident. While demonstrating the truth of a proposition yields knowledge of it, to know a proposition because it is self-evident may or may not mean the proposition is also demonstrable. There is no inconsistency, for example, in holding that one and same proposition is both self-evident and demonstrable. A proposition could be known immediately one way and yet, in another way, follow as a conclusion of a sound deductive argument. Wolff believes that the fact that *PSR* obtains becomes apparent when we consider three specific aspects of our rational/conscious experience. The first is that *PSR* is never contradicted by experience; the second is that we can recognize singular instances, or examples, of it in our experience of the world, and the third is that we have an inquisitive attitude toward our surroundings and future life (Ont. SSSS72-4). For Wolff, these characteristics are not regarded as empirical evidence for *PSR*, but rather that *PSR* is a necessary presupposition for these characteristics to be a part of our conscious experience. Thus by simply reflecting on the nature of our understanding of the world, Wolff believes that we arrive at the manifest truth of *PSR*. Now according to Wolff there are at least four self-evident (axiomatic) principles of human thought: *PC*, the principle of excluded middle, the principle of certitude (or principle of identity), and *PSR* (Ont. SSSS52-55). Of these, only *PC* is indemonstrable in the sense that the truth of the principle cannot be proved to follow from a formal deductive inference. As we have seen, Wolff believes that we gain assurance of the truth of this principle by attending to the psychological experience of not being able to both affirm and deny our own existence in introspection. Thus only in a weak (and non-Wolffian) sense of "demonstration" can Wolff be said to demonstrate the truth of *PC*. The remaining principles, however, are demonstrable in the strict sense and each, he believes, can be derived from *PC*. His demonstration of *PSR* in SS70 of the *Ontologia* is as follows: > > > Nothing exists without a sufficient reason for why it exists rather > than does not exist. That is, if something is posited to exist, > something must also be posited that explains why the first thing > exists rather than does not exist. For either (i) nothing exists > without a sufficient reason for why it exists rather than does not > exist, or else (ii) something can exist without a sufficient reason > for why it exists rather than does not exist (SS53). Let us assume > that some *A* exists without a sufficient reason for why it > exists rather than does not exist. (SS56) *Therefore nothing is > to be posited that explains why A exists. What is more, A is admitted > to exist because nothing is assumed to exist*: since this is > absurd (SS69), nothing exists without a sufficient reason; and if > something is posited to exist, something else must be assumed that > explains why that thing exists. > > > The crucial premise (italicized above) purports to reveal a contradiction that follows from the assumption that something exists without a sufficient reason. Since "nothing" cannot both be something and nothing at the same time (according to *PC*), the conclusion (or *PSR*) is claimed to follow. This proof was the subject of an incisive critique by Wolff's contemporary and critic, Christian August Crusius (1715-75), who (among other things) accuses Wolff of an equivocation with the term "nothing", and once the two different meanings of this term are identified (*viz*. nothing as the opposite of something, on one hand, and nothing as a non-being, on the other), the supposed contradiction, purported to follow from the assumption, cannot be established (Crusius 1741). In any case, for Wolff, the expression "to provide the reason of something" can be taken in two different ways. On the one hand, if the something for which a reason is provided is regarded solely as a possible thing, then "reason" stands to account for why that thing (as a possible thing) is the possible thing that it is. According to Wolff, every being is endowed with an essential nature. Possible things have natures insofar as they as are comprised of a number of non-contradictory determinations or predicates. Different sets of determinations, and the relationships among these determinations, serve as the principle of individualization within the realm of possible things. Hence, to provide the reason for a possible thing is simply to enumerate the determinations that make that thing the kind of possible thing that it is. A reason, in this sense, is regarded by Wolff as *ratio essendi* or the "reason of being". If, on the other hand, the something to which a reason is provided is an actual (i.e., existing) thing, then "reason" stands to explain why that thing as an actual thing comes into existence. Reason, in this sense, is regarded as *ratio fiendi* or the "reason of becoming". Recall that for Wolff existence is simply a predicate or determination of possible things. A familiar expression appearing in Wolff's writings is that existence is "the complement of possibility" (Ont. SS174). The basic idea here is that existence, as a predicate, perfects a possible thing by making it actual and a "real individual". Real individuals differ from nominal beings insofar as the former are "complete and determinate". To be "complete and determinate", in Wolff's sense of the expression, means that every aspect or determination of a thing can be specified and that its determinations are sufficient to individuate it from all other things. Nominal beings, although "complete", are indeterminate (cf. GL: c. 1, SS15). That is to say, although there is a certain set of specifiable determinations that is sufficient to pick out a given possible thing among all possible things, the total set of its determinations is not specifiable. A being, in the most general sense, is comprised of three different types of determinations: *essentialia*, attributes, and modes. Essential determinations define the essential nature of a being and a being's attributes follow from, or are determined by, its *essentialia*. Whereas *essentialia* and attributes are both necessary properties of a thing, modes are contingent or accidental properties. Thus to say a nominal being is indeterminate is to say that there are modes of it that may or may not be present. In the weakest sense, since existence is a mode, and nominal beings do not exist (as such) but are able to come into existence under certain conditions, all nominal beings are indeterminate. Discerning the difference between the "reason of being" and the "reason of becoming" is important for understanding the different ways Wolff employs *PSR* in his exposition of metaphysics. Depending on how exactly "reason" is interpreted, the principle, "nothing is without a sufficient reason for why it is rather than not" may apply either to the realm of possibility or to the realm of actual reality. Toward the end of his *Ontologia*, Wolff makes an attempt to recognize formally two different versions of *PSR* as "the Principle of Being" and "the Principle of Becoming" respectively (Ont. SS866). As a Principle of Being, *PSR* stands as a definition of a thing's essential nature. Yet as a Principle of Becoming, *PSR* serves to furnish the causes, or grounds, for why a real individual comes into actuality. It is on the basis of *PC* and *PSR* that Wolff proceeds to explicate the fundamental concepts of his ontology. Recall that for Wolff a being in the most general sense is any possible thing. Possible things have essential natures insofar as they are composed of a number of non-contradictory determinations or predicates. The essence of any given possible thing is its principle of being, or principle of individualization. Whereas the essence of a simple being is defined by its essential properties, the essence of a composite being is defined by the manner in which its parts are combined together. In SS532 of his *Ontologia*, Wolff explains: > > > A being is called composed which is made up of many parts distinct > from each other. The parts of which a composite being is composed > constitute a composite through the link which makes the many parts > taken together a unit of a definite kind. > > > In one respect, simple beings and composite beings are not simply two different species of beings. It is not the case, for example, that within the realm of all possible things simple beings exist separate from, and in addition to, composite beings. More accurately, at the nominal level of reality simples and composites result from an epistemological distinction imposed by a perceiving mind in its analysis of what "exists" (i.e., exists in a nominal sense). Strictly speaking, the only substantial things to exist at any level of reality are simple substances. Simples are defined by their *essentialia*, and to borrow an expression from Gilson, *essentialia* are both "compatible and prime" (Gilson 1952: 114). That is to say, the essential properties that define a given simple substance do not contradict one another, or cancel each other out, and they are (themselves) not determined by any other thing and/or property. In this light, Wolff's notion of substance is perhaps best regarded as a notion of essence, where each simple substance is a different set of compatible and prime essential properties (see Burns 1966: 26 and Gilson, 1952: 115). Furthermore, essential properties should not be viewed as the accidents of substance because, according to Wolff, they are the substance itself. In Wolff's system, the accidents of substance are the properties that exist by virtue of a thing's *essentialia*. And according to Wolff, there are three basic classes of accidents: proper attributes, common attributes, and modes (Ont. SS148). Proper and common attributes of substance follow from and are determined by a thing's *essentialia*. Proper attributes are the properties of a thing that are determined by all the *essentialia* taken together, and common attributes are the properties of a thing that are determined by only some, but not all, its *essentialia*. Attributes (as such) are perhaps best understood as necessary accidents, since they are determined by and necessarily follow from a thing's *essentialia*. Modes, in contrast, are only contingent accidents of substance. They are the properties of a thing that may or may not be present, and if actually present, they are causally the result of some contingent state of affairs. More precisely, the possible presence of any given mode follows from a substance's *essentialia*, but the actual presence of a given mode is the result of something outside the substance's essence that is causally responsible for its presence in a being. At the nominal level of reality, composite beings exist insofar as the accidents of a certain simple substance, or set of simple substances, are linked and/or arranged together in a certain sort of way. In SS789 of his *Ontologia*, Wolff writes: > > > [t]he essence of a composite being consists only in mere accidents for > the essence of a composite consists in the manner in which its parts > are combined with one another. > > > ### 5.2 Cosmology The notion of "extended-composite" lies at the heart of Wolff's doctrine of the world-whole. Cosmology, as a special metaphysical science, is the study of the world-whole in general. The world, as such, is an extended composite of extended composites. In SS544 of his *German Metaphysics*, Wolff explains: > > > The world is a collection of mutable things that are next to each > other, follow upon one another, but which are overall connected with > one another. > > > In precise terms, Wolff believes the world is an extended whole that is composed of a finite number of interacting physical bodies. To better understand the types of cosmological claims that Wolff defends about the universe, it is perhaps helpful to consider first his conception of physical bodies. Ultimately, the conclusions that Wolff draws at the macroscopic level about the world-whole are simply extrapolated from his analysis of physical bodies. After considering Wolff's analysis of body, this section will conclude with an overview of Wolff's view of space, time and material extension. Wolff's analysis of physical bodies is given from two different perspectives. First is the "bottom-up" metaphysical account of bodies, where bodies are defined as aggregates of simple substances, and second is the "top-down" mechanistic description, where the reality of bodies, given by the testimony of the senses, is explained in terms of interacting primitive *corpusula* (or corpuscles). To facilitate our discussion, we should identify the three levels of description that Wolff employs when giving his two perspective account. Identifying these three different levels is helpful in understanding at what respective point the mechanical and metaphysical accounts each terminate or bottom out. The ground floor (so to speak) is the atomic level that is occupied by a "multitude" of simple substances. Unlike simple substances at the nominal level of reality that lack the "mode of existence", simples at the atomic level are real individuals (i.e., complete and determinate, actually existing beings). In addition to the term "simples", Wolff also refers to these occupants of the atomic level as "elements" and "atoms of nature" (*atomi naturae*). Atomic elements (as such) are conceived by Wolff to be "unextended points of force" that lack internal motion (*motus intestinus*) but yet remain in a constant state of change. Each atomic element is defined, or individuated, by its own distinctive internal state and each is considered to be indivisible in-itself. Although later Wolffians, such as Baumeister, would eventually refer to Wolff's atomic elements as "monads", there is at least one important respect in which Wolff's atomic elements are different from Leibniz's monads (Baumeister 1747: 226). Leibniz conceives monads as simple unextended substances, and hence Leibnizian monads are "windowless" substances that do not interact or influence one another. Wolff's atomic elements, in contrast, do interact and have real dynamic influence over each other.[4] The second level of description that Wolff employs when giving his account of bodies is the microphysical level. The occupants of this level are the primitive parts of bodies which Wolff calls corpuscles or material atoms. In SS186 of his *Cosmologia*, Wolff provides a helpful contrast between atoms of nature, on one hand, and material atoms, on the other: > > > That is called an atom of nature which is indivisible in itself > because it is devoid of parts into which it can be divided. That is > called a material atom which in itself is able to be divided, but for > actually dividing it, existing causes in *rerum natura* are not > adequate.[5] > > > Material atoms or corpuscles are indivisible in the sense that there is nothing within the world that is capable of reducing them into further parts. Corpuscles represent the lowest level of explanation that is possible within a mechanical account of bodies. Similar to the atomic level, the microphysical level lies beyond the boundaries of human perception. Wolff believes that although corpuscles are extended, fill space, and are endowed with the "force of inertia", a precise statement of their size, magnitude, and shape cannot be empirically determined. It is unclear, for example, whether all corpuscles retain homogeneity with respect to their magnitude and shape. Yet because corpuscles are a species of composite beings, Wolff is confident that the essence of a corpuscle consists in the manner in which its parts are joined together. A corpuscle is an aggregate of atomic elements. Its component parts are simply the unextended points of force that occupy the atomic level. The third level of description that Wolff employs when giving his account of bodies is the level of appearance or sensible reality. It is at this level that bodies and their phenomenal properties, such as extension, the force of inertia, and motor force (*vis motrix*), are described in mechanistic terms. In SS793 of his *Ontologia*, Wolff writes: > > > I prefer that aggregates of simple substances, namely, those compound > beings of which the material world is composed, be called bodies > rather than simple substances... > > > In a strict sense, a body is considered by Wolff to be a composite of composites. The interacting atomic elements (conceived as unextended points of force) give rise to primitive corpuscles and from the cohesion of corpuscles, a body is thereby constituted at the level of appearance. Wolff writes, " ... each body has its origin in that which is not extended, although it is itself extended" (*Cosmologia*, SS223). At the level of appearance, bodies display a number of determinate properties. Each body has a specifiable size or magnitude (i.e., it can be measured), it occupies a fixed space or place (insofar as it is extended), it displays a certain shape, and it is divisible to the primitive corpuscles from which it is composed. Yet, according to Wolff, the properties of bodies should not be considered as the accidents of anything substantial because bodies are merely phenomenal manifestations of real, interacting, atomic elements. Even the principal properties of bodies used in the analysis of bodily change and motion (i.e., the properties used in mechanics), such as extension, the force of inertia, and motor force, are deemed by Wolff to be phenomenal properties. Now according to Wolff all sensible properties of bodies should be considered as secondary (or mind-dependent) qualities. In SS144 of his *Cosmologia*, Wolff writes: "...extension is a phenomenon in the same sense in which color is accustomed to be called a phenomenon...". And somewhat later in this same work, he states in SS298: "[t]he force of inertia is called a phenomenon in the same sense in which all sensible qualities are called phenomena". Perhaps the best way to understand Wolff's view of sensible properties is to consider a quick comparison with Locke's corpuscularian view of bodies. For Locke, the primary qualities of bodies, such as extension, solidity, shape, size and texture give rise to the secondary qualities that we perceive in bodies, such as color, sound, taste, smell and temperature. According to Locke, secondary qualities are nothing in the objects themselves but are the result of certain "powers" inherent in the primary qualities of things which effect various sensations in us, such as the sensation of a certain color or temperature. Thus it is by virtue of a body's micro-structure that we are able to perceive its secondary qualities. Wolff, for the most part, accepts this causal-corpuscularian theory of secondary qualities. However, unlike Locke, Wolff believes that all sensible properties are secondary qualities that result from a body's atomic structure. In very simplistic terms, sensible properties are for Wolff what color, sound, taste, smell and temperature are for Locke. For both philosophers, secondary qualities are phenomenal and mind-dependent properties having their causal origin in some objective (i.e., mind-independent) reality. For Locke, this reality is the independently existing corpuscles that comprise the material world; and for Wolff, this reality is the unextended points of force, or simple substances, that occupy his atomic level cf. Cosm. SS191). Before explaining Wolff's view of how extended composites come into being (i.e., the causal process that allows us to form our ideas of extended objects), it is necessary to say a few prefatory words about his view of space and time. The notions of "place" and "space", on one hand, and the notion of "time", on the other, figure in at different stages of Wolff's exposition of extended reality. First and foremost, there is an important distinction in Wolff's cosmology between "general space" and "particular space". Particular space (or a given place) is what an extended body "fills" or "occupies" by virtue of its corpuscular parts (Cosm. SSSS122-4). Its reality is derivative of the interacting atomic elements that give rise to individual corpuscles. For Wolff, a corpuscle's place simply results from a corpuscle's extension. A given place is conceived as an imaginary immobile container that has the same dimensions as the extended thing that occupies it (Ont. SSSS676-9). General space, in contrast, is conceived as the perceived order of coexisting bodies. As explained above, the existence of bodies is established by Wolff experientially and amounts to an instance of historical cognition. In SS45 and SS46 of his *German Metaphysics*, Wolff explains: > > > If we pay attention to ourselves [as thinking things], we will find > that we are conscious of many things outside ourselves. However, we > set them apart from us in that we recognize that they are > distinguishable from us, just in the same way as they are set beside > each other, we recognize they are distinguishable from each > other.... In that there are many things now which exist at the > same time and which are presented apart (and yet at the same time > different) from each other, such things come into being under a > certain order. And as soon as we perceive this order we perceive > space. Therefore, if we do not want to examine the matter differently > than we recognize it, we must assume space is the order of such things > which are simultaneous. > > > Wolff's derivation of general space essentially involves three steps. First, knowledge of the self, as a thinking thing, affords a distinction between consciousness, on one hand, and consciousness of external things, on the other. Second, since that which is conscious (*viz.* the self) is different from that of which it is conscious (*viz.* the world), the self can recognize the historical and mathematical fact that it is conscious of many external things at one time (i.e., the world as a plurality). And third, since this empirical fact affords knowledge of real existences, the order or way the self represents these things is what becomes known as space. To borrow Kant's terminology, Wolffian space lacks "objective reality" because it is simply abstracted from the coexistence of things in the world, and therefore takes on purely a subjective character (cf. Beck 1969: 270). In contrast to his theories of place and general space, Wolff holds a much more realistic theory of time. In a strict sense, place and space serve an explanatory role for Wolff at two distinct levels of description (*viz*. the micro-physical level and the level of appearance). Since atomic elements are unextended, the concepts of place and space are considered by Wolff to be extraneous at the atomic level. Time, however, is not. Atomic elements are in time insofar as each element is in a constant state of change. In his most general description of time, Wolff writes: "[t]ime is the order of successive things in a continuous series" (Ont. SS572). Since each atomic element produces in-itself a constant and continuous series of changes, time is regarded by Wolff as the objective measure of such changes. One clear statement of the Wolffian view of the relationship between time and change can be found in a letter to Kant (dated 13 October 1770) from Johann Heinrich Lambert. Lambert (1728-77) writes: > > > All changes are bound to time and are inconceivable without time. If > changes are real, then time is real, whatever it may be. If time is > unreal, then no change can be real. I think, though, that even an > idealist must grant at least that changes really exist and occur in > his representations, for example, their beginning and ending. Thus > time cannot be regarded as something unreal. It is not a substance, > and so on, but a finite determination of duration, and like duration, > it is somehow real in whatever this reality may consists (AA > 10:107\*\*\*AA?\*). > > > For Wolff, Lambert, and Moses Mendelssohn, time is real insofar as it is an objective measure of change (cf. Falkenstein 1991 for discussion). Change is a constant feature of existing reality in that real individuals are finite and created beings with a determinate duration. Real individuals come into and go out of existence. Time, therefore, is applicable to the series of changes that occur within a given individual and, in the same respect, it is applicable to the totality of all the individuals that compose the world-whole. Thus for Wolff there is a meaningful sense in which real individuals and the world-whole (itself) are "in time". This is not to say, however, that time is granted its own ontological existence. In Lambert's words, time is not a substance (i.e., something real in-and-of itself). More precisely, time is the measure of the objective order of change that real things undergo. Understanding the sense in which atomic elements are "in time" is important for grasping the manner in which Wolff's atomic elements interact. Since atomic elements lack extension, the nature of atomic interaction is not spatial. It is not the case, for example, that Wolff's simple substances influence one another by physical contact and repulsion. Instead, atomic elements as unextended points of force affect, and are responsive to, degrees of change by communicating with each other in time. The series of changes internal to a given atomic element are the result of its own power (or motor force) as well as the motor forces of other elements to which it is connected. Ultimately Wolff believes that it is the interacting forces of a multitude of simple substances that gives rise to our idea of an extended object. In particular, we perceive extended objects at the level of appearance insofar as there are unextended points of force interacting in time at the atomic level. Our confused perception of this temporal interaction results in the idea of an extended object. Similarly to Locke, Wolff believes that it is the primitive qualities of a composite that produce, or effect in us, the various ideas we have of its secondary qualities. Since all sensible properties are considered by Wolff to be secondary qualities, extension, or a composite's extendedness, results from the primitive forces of a composite at the atomic level. The analogy that Wolff presents to help explain the phenomenal manifestation of extension involves a rapidly ringing bell (Cosm. SS789; cf. Burns 1966: 52). According to Wolff, just as the impression we gain from a rapidly ringing bell is the sound of one prolonged peal, where the successive strikes of a bell's clacker are perceived as one monomial sound, our impression of extension is likewise the result of many successively acting atomic forces that give rise to our confused perception of one continuous extended object. The notion of "extended-composite", as already mentioned, is what ultimately stands at the heart of Wolff's doctrine of the world-whole. Insofar as the world is a composite being, it follows from the principles of Wolff's ontology that the world's essence consists in the manner in which its parts are linked together. The world's parts, as described from the standpoint of appearance, are simply the multitude of interacting physical bodies that are perceived in everyday life. And, if described from a metaphysical standpoint, the world's parts are conceived by Wolff to be the interacting unextended points of force that occupy his atomic level. Yet regardless of what standpoint or level of description is employed, it is clear that a necessary condition of the world's existence is that its parts need to be interconnected. According to Wolff, the world is conceived as a substantial whole (*totum substantiale*) by virtue of the fact that all of its parts form real reciprocal connections with one another. On the basis of this "interconnection-thesis" the world is defined formally by Wolff as "a whole which is not also a part". ### 5.3 Psychology (Empirical and Rational) While the soul, as a simple substance, is understood to be a part of the world, and so is implicated in the treatment of cosmology, this does not exhaust what can be known of it, a fact that leads Wolff to treat it as a separate topic of metaphysics. Indeed, Wolff's psychology constitutes one of his signal and most historically influential innovations. Most generally, insofar as Wolff seeks to offer a scientific account of the *human* soul specifically, and indeed with a focus on its cognitive and conative functions, his psychology represents a significant, and distinctly modern, departure from both the treatment of the soul in the context of a generic science of living things, still prevalent among Aristotelian natural philosophers in seventeenth century Germany, and from the metaphysical treatment of the soul in the context of a pneumatology, or doctrine of finite *and* infinite spirit (Stiening 2003, Vidal 2011). More narrowly, Wolff's principal, and best-known innovation in psychology consists in his clear separation between two distinct investigations of the soul, the first based on the observation of one's own mind, identified as *empirical psychology*, and the second which seeks to use reasoning to uncover truths about the soul that are not readily disclosed by experience, identified as *rational psychology*. Wolff's distinction between empirical and rational psychology proved to be enormously consequential, but no less important (if less well attended to) is the fact that these disciplines remain intrinsically connected. For Wolff, the observations catalogued in the course of empirical psychology serve as principles for the inferences of rational psychology, and the resulting findings on the part of rational psychology serve to guide our empirical observation in search of confirmation. Thus, Wolff writes, that which everyone can experience of themselves will serve "as a principle for deriving something else that not everyone can immediately see for themselves" (GM: SS191), and that which is known of the soul from experience "is the touchstone [*Probier-Stein*] of that which is taught [in rational psychology] of its nature and essence" (GM: SS727). Rather than constituting distinct disciplines, empirical and rational psychology amount to complementary parts of a *single* science, working together in the same way in which observation and theory co-operate in astronomy (EP: SS5). Consequently, Wolff's rational psychology is not to be identified as a narrowly *rationalistic* psychology, insofar as the latter is taken to intend a science of the soul that proceeds *completely* independently of experience. Nor is this interdependence of the two parts of psychology an aberration as Wolff takes their union as exemplifying his ideal for science of a *connubium rationis et experientiae* (EP: SS497; cf., Dyck 2014, Rumore 2018). Turning first to empirical psychology, Wolff's treatment can be divided into four parts: (1) the initial consideration of the human soul in an attempt to arrive at an initial definition; the consideration of the soul's (2) cognitive faculty and (3) appetitive faculty; and (4) a consideration of what can be known of the soul's relation to the body through experience. In the first part, Wolff begins, in Cartesian fashion, by first considering the grounds for our certainty in the existence of the soul (EP: SS11-14). Wolff begins by asserting that we are conscious of ourselves and other things, which he takes to be confirmed by our own indubitable experience (for to doubt it would presuppose such consciousness), and inasmuch as anything that is so conscious must exist, a claim Wolff identifies as an identical proposition or axiom (cf. GL: c. 3, SS13), it follows that we can be certain that we exist. Wolff conveniently reconstructs this as a syllogism: > > * Whatever being is conscious of its self and of other things > outside of it, exists. > * We are actually conscious of ourselves and of things outside of > us. > * Therefore, we exist. (EP: SS16) > > > In addition to assuring ourselves of the indubitability of the knowledge of our own existence (cf. Euler 2003), this initial consideration supplies a touchstone for what will count as demonstratively certain, but also provides the elements for a nominal definition of the soul. Thus, the soul is identified just as "that being in us which is conscious of itself and other things outside of it" (EP: SS20) which, as an existing thing, can serve as the object of empirical psychology. The next task for empirical psychology consists in cataloguing the various capacities that the soul has, which Wolff brings under two general headings: the cognitive faculty (*facultas cognoscendi*) and the appetitive faculty (*facultas appetendi*). Relevant to the distinction between (sub-)faculties in both cases is the distinction, borrowed from Leibniz, between obscure and clear perception (where the latter but not the former suffices for recognition of the perceived thing), and (clear but) confused and (clear and) distinct perception (where the latter but not the former involves the ability to explicate what serves to distinguish the perceived thing from others). Accordingly, both the cognitive and appetitive faculty are distinguished into lower and higher parts, where the lower includes capacities relating to ideas and notions that are obscure or clear but confused, and the higher those relating to ideas and notions that are distinct (EP: SSSS54-5, 584). (It bears noting that Wolff also distinguishes between obscure and clear perceptions inasmuch as the former are not *apperceived* but the latter are; cf. EP: SSSS25, 35; RP: SS20, and for discussion see Wunderlich 2005 and Thiel 2011). Among the faculties Wolff considers within the lower cognitive faculty are the faculty of sense, imagination, the fictive faculty, and memory. Sense, which includes the five sensory modalities, is understood as the capacity for sensations, where these are perceptions the reason for which is contained in the organs of our bodies, given the presence of an external thing (EP: SSSS67, 65). Imagination, by contrast, is the faculty for producing perceptions in the absence of sensible things. Wolff further claims that the imagination's activity is guided by a general (associative) law that, when we have perceived things together (as parts of a whole, for instance, or as contiguous in space), if the perception of one is produced, then the imagination supplies the perception of the other (EP: SS117). It is the imagination that is likewise responsible for the order of ideas in dreams. The fictive faculty (*facultas fingendi*) is our capacity to combine or divide the products of the imagination to create new representations (SS144), and memory is defined as the faculty through which we *recognize* reproduced ideas as previously had (SS175). Where the lower cognitive faculty handles the generation and (re)production of obscure and confused ideas, the higher cognitive faculty encompasses the capacities and operations through which we introduce clarity and distinctness into those ideas. Accordingly, Wolff first considers the faculties of attention, whereby we introduce more clarity into a part of a composite perception (EP: SS237), and reflection, through which we successively direct attention to what we perceive (as well as, in a Lockian vein, to the soul and its operations--SS261) and thereby make distinct perception possible (SS266). The capacity for distinct representation in general is identified as the understanding, which can be pure or non-pure depending on whether it admits confused representations, though since these are unavoidable in the case of the human being, our understanding is never pure (EP: SSSS313-4; for general discussion see Chance 2018). With an eye to his discussion of logic, Wolff further distinguishes three operations of the intellect with respect to its cognitions: simple apprehension (through which notions or representations of what is common to multiple things are formed), judgment (through which agreement or disagreement between representations is asserted), and discursion or reasoning (where judgments are formed on the basis of previous judgments) (EP: SSSS325, 366-7; cf. Dyck 2016, Rumore 2018). This latter operation informs Wolff's definition of the *faculty* of reason as the capacity to perceive the interconnection among universal truths (SS483), though Wolff again emphasizes that our reason is never pure but is always to some extent reliant upon *experience* (SSSS495-7). Where the discussion of the cognitive faculty is relevant to Wolff's aims in logic and metaphysics, the treatment of the appetitive faculty in empirical psychology is significant for Wolff's practical philosophy. Wolff likewise distinguishes the appetitive faculty into lower and higher parts, where the distinction turns on whether there is an obscure or confused cognition of the good or evil (grounding a sensory desire or aversion), or a distinct cognition of the good or evil (grounding our act of willing or not willing). In connection with the latter, Wolff takes up the issue of freedom. He rejects the conception of freedom in terms of a capacity to act contrary to determining motives as counter to our experience and to the principle of sufficient reason (EP: SS944), and instead defends a (Leibnizian) compatibilist conception, in accordance with which a freely willed act involves a distinct cognition of the perfection of some thing (which generates a motive to act in its favor); is spontaneous, or has its reason within the agent (insofar as the agent chooses it because it is pleasing); and is contingent, or the agent is not determined to choose it through its essence (EP: SSSS933-41; cf. Kawamura 1996; Dyck forthcoming[a]). Lastly, but importantly, empirical psychology takes up the distinctively early modern problem of what can be experienced of the soul's relation to the body. Here Wolff notes that we experience that some states of the soul depend upon the body (such as sensations), and some states of the body depend upon the soul (such as voluntary actions), such that the body and soul stand in a union or *commercium*. Nonetheless, Wolff contends (following Malebranche and in anticipation of Hume) that we have no experience of the causal power through which the soul influences the body and vice versa, but rather that our experience only confirms the general agreement between the states of each without penetrating to its ground (EP: SSSS961-2). In turning to the rational consideration of the soul, Wolff's aim is not to determine what can be known completely independently of experience but rather to employ what has been discerned in empirical psychology as principles from which its demonstrations proceed and as cognitions for which reasons are to be given (RP: SSSS3-4; Richards 1980). Conforming to this, the topics of rational psychology proceed from those which are closest to and draw most heavily from empirical psychology, such as the account of our soul's nature and essence, to the increasingly more speculative topics, such as the defense of the pre-established harmony to the demonstration of the soul's immortality and consideration of its state after death. The determination of the soul's nature and essence sets out from the definition of the soul given in empirical psychology as that in us which is conscious of itself and other things. Wolff argues that this consciousness is the result of a complex activity that involves reflection on and comparison of parts of a given perception as well as attention and memory (RP: SSSS22-3, 25). Given this, Wolff contends, the soul must be distinct from body since such an act cannot be explained in terms of a change in figure, magnitude, or the location of parts, through which alone changes in body are possible. Similar considerations serve to show that no composite can think, and thus that the soul, as conscious, must not be composite and is therefore simple, and indeed, a simple substance, since it perdures through changes in its thoughts (RP: SSSS44, 47-8). That the soul is a substance further implies for Wolff (as it did for Leibniz) that it is endowed with a power, understood as a sufficient reason for the actuality of the states that are possible for it through its faculties (RP: SSSS54-5; cf. Blackwell 1961, Hessbruggen-Walter 2004). Wolff proceeds to determine the character of this power (which must be a single one given the soul's simplicity), and he concludes that, because sensations are representations of the world in accordance with the position of the organic body, and because all of the representations the soul is capable of are derived from sensations, it follows that the soul's power is just a power of representing the world in accordance with the position of the body, which power Wolff finally identifies as the essence and nature of the soul (RP: SSSS64-9). Rational psychology also takes up the question of what best explains the agreement between the states of the soul and the body. Wolff considers three possible systems that purport to explain this agreement: (i) the system of physical influx, according to which one substance produces a state in another directly through its own activity (RP: SSSS558-60), (ii) the (Cartesian) system of occasional causes, according to which God modifies one substance on the occasion of some state arising in another (SSSS589-91); and (iii) the (Leibnizian) system of pre-established harmony, where the agreement between states of substances is the result of God's initial activity in actualizing this world of substances (SSSS612-13). Wolff provides a number of familiar objections to the first two systems, claiming for instance, that physical influx conflicts with the laws of physics (cf. SSSS578-9), and that occasionalism relies on what amounts to a perpetual miracle (cf. SS603), while defending the pre-established harmony from similar criticisms (cf. Watkins 2005: 45-51). Even so, given that any possible explanation cannot be confirmed or rejected by experience (as was disclosed at the conclusion of empirical psychology), each of these systems amounts to a mere *hypothesis*, and Wolff's conclusion is only that the pre-established harmony is a more *probable* hypothesis than the other two (RP: SSSS503, 685; cf. Dyck 2014: 34-6), though he thinks that nothing significant turns on settling this contentious issue. The last major topic Wolff turns to is the most speculative, namely, the demonstration of the soul's immortality of the soul and its state after death. Immortality is taken to presuppose the incorruptibility of the soul, that is, that the soul does not naturally pass away after the death of the body, but (contrary to the Cartesians) Wolff does not think that this is all that is involved as any immortality worth having (and that would be consistent with Scripture) must also extend to the preservation of the soul's capacity for distinct perception (that is, its spirituality) and its consciousness that it is the same being in the afterlife as it was before the body's death (or its *personality*). The soul's incorruptibility follows straightforwardly from the fact that it is simple (and so incapable of decomposition); inductive grounds are offered in favor of the soul's preservation of its spirituality (namely, that the clarity of the soul's perceptions is enhanced in all "great changes"--RP: SS745); and the soul's maintenance of its personality is shown by reference to the law of imagination in accordance with which its subsequent perceptions will lead it to recall previous ones. The relative merits of these arguments were hotly debated, with especially notable contributions by Wolff's colleague in Halle, G. F. Meier, and later by Mendelssohn (in his famous *Phaedo*), and ultimately Kant (for discussion, see Sassen 2008; Dyck 2014: 141-72). ### 5.4 Natural Theology Wolff's treatment of metaphysics concludes with a consideration of natural theology defined as "the science of those things that are possible through God" (NT: I, SS1, see Corr 1973). Yet, at the same time, natural theology also provides a bottom-up justification for metaphysics insofar as metaphysics is concerned with actual existing beings of a contingent, and so created, reality. Wolff indicates that natural theology has two principle aims: (1) to prove the existence of God and (2) to determine what pertains to the essence and attributes of God, and what follows from these. Concerning the demonstration of God's existence, Wolff had offered criticisms (much to the chagrin of his Pietist opponents) of a variety of traditional proofs early in his career (cf. Theis 2018: 221-3). In his *Natural Theology*, however, Wolff presents and defends two proofs: an *a posteriori* proof presented at the outset of the first volume, and an *a priori* proof provided at the beginning of the second. Wolff's *a posteriori* proof sets out from the fact (elaborated at the outset of empirical psychology) that we exist, and proceeds to argue that the reason for our existence must be found in a necessary being: > > > The human soul exists or we exist. Since nothing is without a > sufficient reason why it is rather than is not, a sufficient reason > must be given why our soul exists, or why we exist. Now this reason is > contained in ourselves or in some other being diverse from us. But if > you maintain that we have the reason of our existence in a being > which, in turn, has the reason of its existence in another, you will > not arrive at the sufficient reason unless you come to a halt at some > being which does have the sufficient reason of its own existence in > itself. Therefore, either we ourselves are the necessary being, or > there is given a necessary being other and diverse from us. > Consequently, a necessary being exists (NT: I, SS24). > > > From there, Wolff argues that the necessary being must also be independent, or have its sufficient reason in itself, and cannot have a beginning or end in time or is eternal. As such, the necessary being cannot be identified with the world (which is composite) or anything within it (since these have a beginning and end); moreover, it cannot be identified with the soul since unlike the soul it does not depend on the world. Therefore, the necessary being is identified as God, understood as an independent being in which the reason for the actuality of the world and the soul is found (NT: I, SS67, see Corr 1973). By contrast, Wolff's *a priori* proof for God's existence proceeds from the identification of God as the most perfect being (*ens perfectissimum*): > > > God contains all compossible realities in the absolutely highest > degree. But He is possible. Wherefore, since the possible can exist, > existence can belong to it. Consequently, since existence is a > reality, and since realities are compossible which can belong to a > being, existence is in the class of compossible realities. Moreover, > necessary existence is the absolutely highest degree. Therefore, > necessary existence belongs to God or, what is the same, God > necessarily exists (NT: II, SS21, see Corr 1973). > > > From the notion of a most perfect being, Wolff purports to prove God is an *ens realissimum* (or most real existing being). However, like Leibniz before him commenting on the Cartesian ontological proof, Wolff believes God must first be shown to be possible in order to be shown to exist. According to Wolff, arriving at the knowledge of God as an *ens perfectissimum* involves first contemplating the attributes that are present in the human soul, to a limited degree, and then extrapolating those attributes as unlimited qualities to God. Things are compossible insofar as they can coexist in the same subject. Since existence is a mode or reality for Wolff, existence is considered to fall within the class of compossible realities. And just as it is better to exist than not to exist, it is better to exist necessarily than just to exist contingently, therefore Wolff concludes that God's existence is necessary. With God's existence assured, Wolff considers what can be known of Him. God is taken to have an understanding, consisting in His distinct representation of all possible worlds and which representation itself originates from the divine essence (NT: II, SSSS81, 84). God is also shown to have a will, through which He chooses one possible world to make actual, and since God's choice in doing so finds its sufficient reason in his distinct cognition of the supreme perfection of that world, Wolff identifies God's will as *free* (in the same sense of freedom presented in the empirical psychology, albeit in the highest possible degree--NT: II, SS277). Wolff additionally considers God's *wisdom*, which consists in His choice of the appropriate means to realize His end in creation, namely, the manifestation of His own glory and perfection (NT: I, SS629), and *goodness*, which consists in His conferring of as much goodness on creatures as is consistent with His wisdom (NT: I, SSSS697-9). While these discussions conclude the proper subject matter of natural theology, in the second half of the second volume Wolff additionally turns to critically examining various systems of atheism and radical thought. Significantly, among the views discussed is *Spinozism*, and indeed his treatment is considerably detailed (spanning SSSS671-716 of the second volume), likely reflecting the fact that Wolff had himself faced a persistent accusation of supporting Spinoza on the part of his Pietist critics. In contrast, however, with other discussions of Spinoza by philosophers of this period, Wolff's does not trade in convenient caricatures or speculation concerning the real (immoral) motives behind Spinoza's thought but hews closely, if critically, to the text of the *Ethics*. Wolff scrutinizes Spinoza's definitions, particularly of God, substance, attribute, mode, and finite thing (which he contrasts with their proper definitions in the Leibnizian-Wolffian philosophy), and proceeds to show how these figure into Spinoza's account of extension (NT: II, SSSS688-93), doctrine of bodies (SSSS694-6), claims of the uniqueness and necessary existence of substance (SSSS697-706), and his faulty account of infinite thought as composed of an infinite number of finite thinking things (SSSS707-8). Wolff's discussion proved rather influential, with Mendelssohn echoing and developing it, and the accuracy of Wolff's characterization of Spinoza was also a point of discussion in the famous *Pantheismusstreit* (cf. Beiser 1987: 103). ## 6. Practical Philosophy The subject matter of Wolff's practical philosophy is restricted to those things that have to do with human action. In Wolff's Latin texts, practical philosophy is divided into four main disciplines: universal practical philosophy, natural law, politics, and moral philosophy. And just as ontology purportedly provides the foundational underpinnings for the disciplines of "special metaphysics" in the theoretical realm, universal practical philosophy plays an analogous role for the disciplines of natural law, politics, and moral philosophy in the practical realm. A central and perhaps unifying concept in Wolff's practical writings is the concept of "perfection". In an early letter to Leibniz, dated 4 May 1715, Wolff explains the importance that the concept serves in his ethics: > > > I need the notion of perfection for dealing with morals. For, when I > see that some actions tend toward our perfection and that of others, > while others tend toward our imperfection and that of others, the > sensation of perfection excites a certain pleasure [*voluptas*] > and the sensation of imperfection a certain displeasure > [*nausea*]. And the emotions [*affectus*], by virtue of > which the mind is, in the end, inclined or disinclined, are > modifications of this pleasure and displeasure; I explain the origin > of natural obligation in this way... From this also comes the > general rule or law of nature that our actions ought to be directed > toward the highest perfection of ourselves and others. (Leibniz 1989a: > 231-232) > > > According to Wolff, the ultimate goal of human action is to attain, or at least approximate, the highest degree of perfection that is possible. Humans, as individuals or groups, should strive for perfection insofar as moral worth and goodness reside in the objective essence of humankind. In a strict sense, each person is obligated by the law of nature to instantiate perfection in his/her own life. Actions that tend toward perfection produce pleasure and actions that tend toward imperfection produce displeasure (or pain). In many respects, this consequentialist feature of Wolff's ethical theory resembles various forms of utilitarianism that were emerging in England during the mid-to-late eighteenth century. Also central to Wolff's practical philosophy is its autonomy from theological doctrine. Although maintaining that a universal ethics is certainly compatible with the teachings of Sacred Scripture, Wolff is adamant that morality does not depend on revelation or God's divine commands. Advocating the separation of philosophy and religion is a theme that Wolff developed and defended throughout his entire career and it is a feature of his thought that secures him a place among other philosophers of Europe's Enlightenment. ## 7. Other Philosophical Contributions Wolff's prominence in eighteenth-century Germany, and his wide-ranging interests, have meant that he is an important figure in the history of a number of established fields in the eighteenth century, including mathematics, physics, political theory, and even economics. Wolff also made notable, even pioneering contributions to disciplines that were not as yet recognized as distinct areas of philosophical inquiry. Wolff had, for instance, an early interest in the philosophy of language, having devoted a dissertation to the topic in 1703 (*Disquisitio philosophica de loquela*), an interest he continued to pursue in subsequent discussions in his logical writings, relating to semiotics and hermeneutics, and in his psychological texts, concerning the relation between mental and linguistic entities (see Favaretti Camposampiero 2018 for details). Wolff is also widely recognized as a founding figure in the discipline of aesthetics--while his only text devoted to the topic is a treatise on civil architecture (a volume in a mathematical textbook), Wolff's account of aesthetic pleasure in terms of the intuitive cognition of perfection (EP: SS511), and identification of that perfection as consisting in a unity in multiplicity, were taken up and discussed by later aesthetic theorists, including A. G. Baumgarten (the father of modern aesthetics), J. C. Gottsched, J. G. Sulzer (1720-79), and Mendelssohn (see Beiser 2009; Buchenau 2013).
wollstonecraft
## 1. Biography The second of seven children, Mary Wollstonecraft was born in Spitalfields, London, on 27 April 1759, in a house on Primrose Street. Her paternal grandfather was a successful master weaver who left a sizeable legacy, but her father, Edward John, mismanaged his share of the inheritance. He tried to establish himself as a gentleman farmer in Epping. This was the first of the family's several moves, each of which marked its financial and social decline. Only Mary's brother, Edward (Ned), was to receive a formal education; he became a lawyer. He had also inherited directly from his grandfather a substantial part of the latter's legacy. Wollstonecraft's own somewhat haphazard education was, however, not entirely unusual for someone of her sex and position, nor was it particularly deficient. Her published writings show her to have acquired a true command of the Bible and a good knowledge of the works of several of the most famous Ancient philosophers. The latter is partly explained through her personal acquaintance with Thomas Taylor, famed for his translations of Plato (Tomaselli 2019). She also drew on a variety of early modern sources, such as Shakespeare and Milton's works. Through her own writing for the *Analytical Review* she was to become widely read in the literature of her period. Initially, the nature and extent of her reading was partly owed to the friendship shown to her in her youth by a retired clergyman and his wife. Nevertheless, as a woman from an impecunious family, her prospects were very limited. In relatively rapid succession, she was to enter the most likely occupations for someone of her sex and circumstances: a lady's companion, a schoolteacher, and a governess. In 1778, she was engaged as a companion to a Mrs Dawson and lived at Bath. She returned home to nurse her ailing mother in the latter part of 1781. After Mrs Wollstonecraft's death, in the spring of 1782, Mary lived with the Bloods, the impoverished family of her dearest friend, Fanny. In the winter of 1783, Mary left them in order to attend to her sister Eliza and her newly born daughter. There followed the first of the emotionally very difficult episodes in Mary's life. What prompted Mary to intervene as decisively as she did in her sister's marriage remains somewhat of a mystery; but in the course of January 1784, Mary took her sister away, and the two women went into hiding, leaving Eliza's infant daughter behind; the baby died the following August. By February of that year, the two sisters had already been planning to establish a school with Fanny Blood. Mary's other sister, Everina, joined in the project a little later. They first set their sights on Islington, then moved to Newington Green, where Mary met the moral and political thinker, the Reverend Richard Price, head of Newington's thriving Dissenting community, and heard him preach. This was a crucial encounter for Mary. Several years later, she was to rise to his defence in a *Vindication of* *the Rights of Men* (1790), and it was through her connections to members of this community that she was to gain an introduction to her future publisher, friend, and one might even say, patron, Joseph Johnson. In November 1785, Wollstonecraft set off on a trip to Lisbon, where her friend Fanny, who had married that February, was expecting her first child. On board the ship, Mary met a man suffering from consumption; she nursed him for a fortnight, the length of the journey. This experience is related in her first novel, *Mary, a Fiction* (1788). She gained a very unfavourable opinion of Portuguese life and society, which seemed to her ruled by irrationality and superstitions. Mary's brief stay in Portugal was, furthermore, to be a profoundly unhappy one, for both Fanny and her baby died shortly after the delivery. On her return to England, Wollstonecraft found her school in a dire state. Far from providing her with a reliable income and some stability, it was to be a source of endless worries and a financial drain. Only Joseph Johnson's advance on her first book, *Thoughts on the Education of Daughters: with Reflections on Female Conduct in the more important Duties of Life* (1787) helped ease her considerable financial difficulties. It consists of brief discussions on such topics as 'Moral Discipline', 'Artificial Manners', 'Boardings-Schools', 'The Benefits Which Arise From Disappointments', 'The Observance of Sunday', and 'On the Treatment of Servants'. Although it might seem somewhat cursory, this book served as the groundwork for many of the topics to which she would return in her more famous works of the 1790s. Following the collapse of her school, Wollstonecraft became a governess to the family of Lord Kingsborough for a brief and unsatisfactory period. The position took her to Ireland, where she completed *Mary, A Fiction*. On her return to London, Joseph Johnson came to the rescue once again by giving her some literary employment. In 1787, she also began, but never completed, *The Cave of Fancy. A Tale*. The same year, she wrote *Original Stories from Real Life; with Conversations, calculated to Regulate the Affections, and Form the Mind to Truth and Goodness* (1788); it appeared in two other London editions in her life time (1791 and 1796), the last of which illustrated by William Blake. Wollstonecraft's anthology, *The Female Reader; Miscellaneous Pieces in Prose and Verse; Selected from the Best Writers and Disposed under Proper Heads; for the Improvement of Young Women* (1789), was compiled in the same period and published under the name of 'Mr. Cresswick, teacher of Elocution'; it pursues themes to be found in her previous works and contains excerpts mostly from the Bible and Shakespeare's plays, as well as many by various eighteenth-century authors, such as Voltaire, Hume, Steele, Charlotte Smith, and Madame de Genlis. To understand the extent to which Wollstonecraft made up for the lack of a formal education, it is essential to appreciate fully that her talents were to extend to translating and reviewing, and that these two activities, quite apart from her own intellectual curiosity, acquainted her with a great many authors, including Leibniz and Kant. She translated into English Jacques Necker's *Of the Importance of Religious Opinions* (1788) from French, Rev. C. G. Salzmann's *Elements of Morality, for the Use of Children; with an Introductory Address to Parents* (1790) from German, and Madame de Cambon's *Young Grandison* (1790) from Dutch. In each case, the texts she produced were almost as if her own, not just because she was in agreement with their original authors, but because she more or less re-wrote them. The Reverend Salzmann is unlikely to have resented her for this, as he was to translate into German both *A Vindication of the Rights of Woman* and William Godwin's *Memoirs of the Author of a Vindication of the Rights of Woman* (1798). Throughout the period covered by these translations Wollstonecraft wrote for the *Analytical Review*, which her publisher, Joseph Johnson, together with Thomas Christie, started in May 1788. She was involved with this publication either as a reviewer or as editorial assistant for most of its relatively short life. Despite her own practice of the genre, her many reviews reveal the degree to which, she, like many other moralists in the eighteenth century, feared the moral consequences of reading novels. She believed that even those of a relatively superior quality encouraged vanity and selfishness. She was to concede, however, that reading such works might nonetheless be better than not reading at all. Besides novels, Wollstonecraft reviewed poetry, travel accounts, educational works, collected sermons, biographies, natural histories, and essays and treatises on subjects such as Shakespeare, happiness, theology, music, architecture and the awfulness of solitary confinement; the authors whose works she commented on included Madame de Stael, Emanuel Swedenborg, Lord Kames, Rousseau, and William Smellie. Until the end of 1789, her articles were mostly of a moral and aesthetic nature. However, in December 1789, she reviewed a speech by her old friend, Richard Price, entitled *A Discourse on the Love of our Country, delivered on Nov. 4, 1789, at the Meeting-House in the Old Jewry, to the Society for Commemorating the Revolution of Great Britain. With an Appendix, containing the report of the Committee of the Society; and Account of the Population of France; and the Declarations of the Rights by the National Assembly of France* (1789). This address to the Revolution Society in commemoration of the events of 1688 partly prompted Burke to compose his famous *Reflections on the Revolution in France, and on the Proceedings in Certain Societies in London Relative to that Event* (1790). Burke's attack on Price in that work in turn led Wollstonecraft, egged on by her publisher, Johnson, to take up her pen in the aged Reverend's defence. *A Vindication of the Rights of Men* (1790) was almost certainly the first of many responses Burke's *Reflections* elicited*.* Initially published anonymously at the end of November, the second edition that quickly followed in mid-December bore its author's name and marked a turning point in her career; it established her as a political writer. In September 1791, Wollstonecraft began *A Vindication of the Rights of Woman: with Strictures on Political and Moral Subjects,* which elaborated a number of points made in the previous *Vindication*, namely, that in most cases, marriage was nothing but a property relation, and that the education women received ensured that they could not meet the expectations society had of them and almost certainly guaranteed them an unhappy life. Following the publication of her second *Vindication*, Wollstonecraft was introduced to the French statesman and diplomat, Charles Talleyrand, on his mission to London on the part of the Constituent Assembly in February 1792. She dedicated the second edition of the *A Vindication of the Rights of Woman* to him. In December 1792, she travelled to France where she met Gilbert Imlay, an American merchant and author of *A Topographical Descriptions of the Western Territory of North America* (1792) and *The Emigrants* (1793). As British subjects were increasingly at risk under the Terror, Wollstonecraft passed as Imlay's wife so as to benefit from the security enjoyed at the time by American citizens. They never married. Imlay was probably the source of Wollstonecraft's greatest unhappiness, first through his lack of ardour for her, then because of his infidelity, and finally because of his complete rejection of her. Most of all, her love of Imlay brought Wollstonecraft to the realisation that the passions are not so easily brought to heel by reason. Wollstonecraft had a girl by Imlay. She was born at Le Havre in May 1794 and named Fanny, after Wollstonecraft's friend, Fanny Blood. A year after Fanny's birth, Wollstonecraft twice attempted suicide, first in May, then in October 1795. She broke with Imlay finally in March 1796. In April of the same year, she renewed her acquaintance with William Godwin and they became lovers that summer. They were married at St Pancras church in March 1797. On the 30th August, Mary Wollstonecraft Godwin, future author of *Frankenstein* and wife of Shelley, was born. ## 2. Pedagogical Writings Apart from *Mary, a Fiction* and *The Cave of Fancy* Wollstonecraft's early writings were of a pedagogical nature (Jones 2020). These reveal the profound influence John Locke had on Wollstonecraft's thought, and several of the arguments of his *Some Thoughts Concerning Education* (1693) are echoed in Wollstonecraft's conception of morality and the best manner to inculcate it in individuals at the earliest possible age. The opening paragraph of her *Thoughts on the Education of Daughters* speaks of the duty parents have to ensure that 'reason should cultivate and govern those instincts which are implanted in us to render the path of duty pleasant--for if they are not governed they will run wild; and strengthen the passions which are ever endeavouring to obtain dominion--I mean vanity and self-love.' Similarly, the beginning of her *Original Stories from Real Life* stated its author's intent, namely to seek 'to cure those faults by reason, which ought never to have taken root in the infant mind. Good habits, imperceptibly fixed, are however far preferable to the precepts of reason; but as this task requires more judgement than generally falls to the lot of parents, substitutes must be sought for, and medicines given, when regimen would have answered the purpose better'. Wollstonecraft's prescriptions to counter the deplorable education she thought her contemporaries were inflicting on their children takes the form of a tale about two girls, Mary and Caroline. At the beginning of the story, the reader finds the girls left to the management of ignorant servants (one of Locke's great bugbears), but they are eventually placed under the tuition of a woman of tenderness and discernment. The book shows how the latter succeeds in teaching contemptuous Mary and vain Caroline to avoid anger, exercise compassion, love truth and virtue, and respect the whole of God's creation. It is important to note however that whilst Locke advocated home education to shield boys from the bad influences to which they might be subject at school, Wollstonecraft was mostly inclined to think the opposite on the grounds that children needed to be with persons of their own age. In an ideal world, boys and girls would be educated together in schools. Many of these concerns would appear again in her *Vindication of the Rights of Woman* (1792): indeed Sandrine Berges reads this work primarily as a treatise on education (Berges 2013). That reason must rule supreme could easily appear to be a running theme of Wollstonecraft's works written prior to her sojourn in Revolutionary France and, all the more, prior to her travels through Scandinavia. It is stressed in her *Vindication of the Rights of Woman*. Other continuities between her *Thoughts on the Education of Daughters* and the *Vindication* include her insistence that girls and young women be made to acquire 'inner resources' so as to make them as psychologically independent as possible. The *Thoughts* also reveals Wollstonecraft's conviction that universal benevolence is the first virtue, as well as her faith in a providentially ordained universe. She enjoined her readers to prepare their children for 'the main business of our lives', that is, the acquisition of virtue, and, unsurprisingly given her own history, she urged parents to strengthen their children's characters so as to enhance their capacity to survive personal tragedies. Self-mastery was thus the aim of education and it was the duty of parents to ensure that their children received it. However, she insisted that there was a time for everything, including for the development of each of the mind's faculties, not least the imagination. Ultimately, she wanted children and young people to educated in such a way as to have well balanced minds in strong and healthy bodies. That mind and body needed to be exercised and prepared to face the inevitable hardships of life is the fundamental point of her of her pedagogical works (Tomaselli 2020). ## 3. Moral and Political Writings When Wollstonecraft began to engage in political commentary in reviewing Price's *A Discourse on the Love of our Country*, she praised him for his account of true patriotism as 'the result of reason, not the undirected impulse of nature, ever tending to selfish extremes' as well as his defence of Christianity's prescription of universal benevolence against those who argued that such sentiments were incompatible with the love of one's country. She endorsed his view of liberty of conscience as a sacred right and wrote sympathetically about his plea for the repeal of the Test and Corporation Acts, which imposed civil disabilities on Dissenters. She also seemed to support his claim that the political Settlement of 1689 was wanting in that it did not make for full representation of the people and hence made only for partial liberty. Finally, Wollstonecraft reproduced the passage in which Price linked the American and French revolutions and clamoured for the end of despotism throughout Europe. When not so long thereafter she came to write her *Vindication of the Rights of Men* (1790), Wollstonecraft attacked Edmund Burke for having set upon an harmless elderly preacher in his *Reflections*; yet her own review justifies Burke's depiction of Price's sermon as inflammatory. Far from thinking that the events taking place in France gave grounds for rejoicing, Burke feared their consequences from the very start. The National Assembly's confiscation of the Church's property, he predicted, would lead to further confiscations, undermine the fundamental right to property, and result in anarchy, which only the rise of a charismatic, authoritarian figure could bring to an end. Of the disagreements between Price and Wollstonecraft, on the one hand, and Burke, on the other, one of the deepest was over their respective view of the nature of civil society and of political power in general. The two friends believed that government, the rule of law, and all human relations could be simplified, explicated, and rendered transparent, and both were convinced that this was the task ahead for all lovers of liberty. For Burke, on the contrary, civil society consisted of countless ineffable links between individuals. The latter's relationship to authority was for the most part no less ineffable; moreover, he believed sound political judgement to be the product of experience, and he cautioned prudence. To sweep away established practices and institutions and think of politics as a mere matter of administrating in accordance with a set of abstract rules or rights uninformed by the customs and culture, and hence the national character, of a people was, in his view, to demonstrate a crass disregard for the most obvious facts of human nature and history (Conniff 1999). Burke's argument led him to dwell on France's financial position in some detail, and he defended its royal family and its Church; he insisted, moreover, that it was already benefiting from a policy of gradual reform. The overall effect Burke sought to achieve was to depict his opponent as theoretically confused, politically naive, generally misinformed; and to show, most damnably of all, that Price's sermon on the *Love of our Country*, with all its affirmation of feelings for humanity, proved him to be unpatriotic. Wollstonecraft's *Vindication* was the first of many replies. Amongst those that followed was one by Catharine Macaulay, who had influenced Wollstonecraft's pedagogy and was much admired by her (Gunther-Canada 1998; Coffee, 2019). Wollstonecraft's riposte is an interesting and rhetorically powerful work in its own right as well as a necessary introduction to the *Vindication of the Rights of Woman*. It consists mostly of a sustained attack on Burke rather than a defence of the rights of man. This is partly because Wollstonecraft took for granted a Lockean conception of God-given rights discoverable by reason, except when the latter was warped by self-love. Wollstonecraft further believed that God made all things right and that the cause of all evil was man. In her view, Burke's *Reflections* showed its author to be blind to man-made poverty and injustice; this she attributed to his infatuation with rank, Queen Marie-Antoinette, and the English Constitution. Demonstrating her familiarity with Burke's other works and speeches, especially *A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful* (1757) and the *Speech on Conciliation with America* (1775), she also argued that he was inconsistent, if only because of the impossibility, as she saw it, of reconciling his sympathy for the American cause with his reaction to events in France. In this, Wollstonecraft was far from alone and many who had followed Burke's parliamentary career and heard his Speeches to the House of Commons were astonished by what they thought was a radical and inexplicable change of position. As she was to do in her next and more famous *Vindication*, Wollstonecraft did not simply clamour for rights, but emphasised that these entail duties; but she also insisted that none could be expected to perform duties whose natural rights were not respected. Furthermore she used David Hume's *History of England* (1754-62) to contend that England's laws were the product of historical contingency and insisted that only those institutions that could withstand the scrutiny of reason and be shown to be in conformity with natural rights and God's justice merited respect and obedience. There was no question of blanket reverence for the past and its juridical legacy. As for civilization, she thought its progress very uneven and dismissed the culture of politeness and polish as nothing but a screen behind which hypocrisy, egotism and greed festered unchecked. Finally, opposing nature and reason to artifice and politeness, she made herself the true patriot and Burke the fickle Francophile. She was the clear-headed independent thinker, he the emotive creature of a system of patronage. She exhibited manly virtues, he effeminacy; although Mary Fairclough argues that, in truth, there was much in common between each thinker's treatment of feelings and instincts (Fairclough 2020). In the midst of her tirade she turned, rather unexpectedly, to the subject of family life and the limits of parental authority, especially in relation to arranged marriages (Tomaselli 2001). She condemned marriages of convenience together with late marriages: both fostered immorality in her view. Indeed, from her perspective, nearly every aspect of the prevailing culture had that consequence, for, in bringing girls up to be nothing but empty headed playthings, parents made for a morally bankrupt society. Such beings could never make dutiful mothers, as they took the horizon to be the eyes of the men they flirted with. The moral depravity of a society devoted to the acquisition of property and its conspicuous display rather than to the pursuit of reason and the protection of natural rights found the means of its reproduction in the family, she contended. Here her dispute was not just with Burke, but implicitly also with Price (Jones, 2005). In his sermon, he had deplored the sexual depravity of the times that he saw embodied even in those he considered patriots. But to seek only to vindicate the rights of men, as Price had done, was insufficient and misconceived, according to Wollstonecraft. If one sought a truly moral society, the family had to change, and this, in turn, required a complete transformation in the nature of the relationship between men and women before, and within, marriage (Botting 2006). Only a sound upbringing of both the sexes could secure that. This was the nub of her attack on political theorists and educationalists alike. When Wollstonecraft came to write *The Vindication of the Rights of Woman*, which she did within a matter of months following the publication of her first overtly political work, the moral rejuvenation of society and the happiness of individual women were woven together. Women were ill-prepared for their duties as social beings and imprisoned in a web of false expectations that would inevitably make them miserable. She wanted women to become rational and independent beings whose sense of worth came, not from their appearance, but from their inner perception of self-command and knowledge. Women had to be educated; their minds and bodies had to be trained. This would make them good companions, wives, mothers and citizens (Brace 2000). Above all it would make them fully human, that is, beings ruled by reason and characterised by self-command. Besides criticisms of existing pedagogical practices and theories, most notably Rousseau's *Emile* (1762), the *Vindication* contains many social and political proposals which range from a detailed outline of necessary changes in school curriculum to the suggestion that women be granted not only civil and political rights, but have elected representatives of their own. It argues that women should be taught skills so as to be able to support themselves and their children in widowhood, and never have to marry or remarry out of financial necessity. It seeks to reclaim midwifery for women, against the encroachment of men into this profession, and contends that women could be physicians just as well as nurses. It urges women to extend their interests to encompass politics and the concerns of the whole of humanity. It also contains advice on how to make marriages last. In Wollstonecraft's view, marriages ought to have friendship rather than physical attraction as their basis (Kendrick 2019). Husbands and wives ought not, moreover, to be overly intimate and should maintain a degree of reserve towards each other. This said, she thought sex should be based on genuine mutual physical desire. Wollstonecraft wanted women to aspire to full citizenship, to be worthy of it, and this necessitated the development of reason. Rational women would perceive their real duties. They would forgo the world of mere appearances, the world of insatiable needs on which eighteenth-century society was based, as Adam Smith had explained more lucidly than anyone, and of which France was the embodiment, in Wollstonecraft's conception (Leddy 2016). That she embraced the social and economic consequences of her vision of happy marriages, based on friendship and producing the next moral generation was spelled out further in her subsequent work, *An Historical and Moral View of the Origin and Progress of the French Revolution; and the Effect It Has Produced in Europe* (1794). In that work, she endeavoured, amongst other things, to assess the merits and demerits of the progress of humanity and establish the causes of French despotism. The picture she drew of *ancien* *regime* France was of a country ruled by superstition, and morally and politically degenerate. Borrowing from Smith, whose *Theory of Moral Sentiments* (1759) and *Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations* (1776) she had drawn on previously, she sketched a possible future society in which the division of labour would be kept to a minimum and the sexes would be not only educated together but encouraged to work in family units. Single sex institutions and, for instance, all-male workshops encouraged lasciviousness in her view. She thus looked forward to a society in which small businesses and farms would provide basic, instead of superfluous, needs. The combination of her experience of her unrequited love for Imlay, the dictates of her own emotions, and the tribulations of a trip in Northern Europe led her to reconsider her view of the power of reason. Indeed, she was also to review her opinion of France, polite culture and manners, even Catholicism which she had abhorred, a loathing that her stay in Portugal had done much to strengthen. The *Letters Written During A Short Residence in Sweden, Norway and Denmark* (1796), whose influence on travel literature as well as the Romantic movement is by no means negligible, show Wollstonecraft to have begun to espouse an increasingly nuanced view of the world, and to have sought to develop an even more fluid account of the relationship between reason, the imagination, and the passions, as well as of modernity. Thus she grew a little closer to Burke in that she came to think that the tyranny of commercial wealth might be worse than that of rank and privilege. Whilst in France, she had already begun to write less critically of the English system of government. She had witnessed the Terror, fallen in love, born a child out of wedlock, been rejected, and attempted suicide. A second suicide attempt lay ahead. So did the prospect of happiness with William Godwin, a prospect cut short by her death in childbirth. Posthumous notoriety was to follow as Wollstonecraft became identified only with the *Vindication of the Rights of Woman* and that work was ironically, in turn, equated with a flouting of social conventions, principally in relation to marriage. ## 4. Reputation Although she was very much encouraged by her publisher, Joseph Johnson, she received little support from fellow intellectuals in her lifetime. Even Godwin did not take to her on their first meeting. Relatively few of the foremost women writers gave Wollstonecraft their wholehearted support in the eighteenth century. She received some encouragement for her first publications from Catharine Macaulay, but the latter unfortunately died in 1791, before Wollstonecraft's career reached its peak. Some mocked her, but rarely were her ideas genuinely assessed in the way they have come to be since the second half of the twentieth century. The leading poet, Anna Barbauld (1743-1825) was one of the few members of the radical intelligentsia of the time whose opposition to Wollstonecraft was the product of a real engagement with her views on women. By the end of the 1790s and for most of the nineteenth century, Wollstonecraft was derided by many, if only because of what was deemed to have been a scandalous personal life. There were, to be sure, important exceptions, especially in America (Botting and Carey 2004). But such praise as she did receive on both sides of the Atlantic came from arguably limited acquaintance with her ideas or her intellectual persona. Thus it seemed that from the end of the eighteenth century and throughout the next, she, who had endeavoured to place marriage on a solid foundation by providing an account of the education that would prepare spouses for it, would be thought of as someone who had sought to pass as married when she wasn't and as the mother of an illegitimate child. Much of this reputation was owed to Godwin's frank, arguably unnecessarily frank, account of Wollstonecraft's life, in *Memoirs of the Author of a 'Vindication of the Rights of Woman'* (1798). It revealed, amongst other personal details, her relationship with Imlay and thereby cast a deep shadow over her reputation. In any event, John Stuart Mill's *Subjection of Women* (1869) was to eclipse most other contributions to feminist debates of the period. In the twentieth century, and especially following the growth of feminism in the Anglo-Saxon world in the 1960s, scholars disregarded the vicissitudes of Wollstonecraft's private life and heralded her as the first English feminist. She came to be read principally within the context of the history of the women's movement. Since the last decades of the twentieth century, however, a growing number of commentators have looked at *A Vindication of the Rights of Woman* in its historical and intellectual context rather than in isolation or in relation to subsequent feminist theories. This has led to renewed interest in her other political writings, including her *Letters Written During A Short Residence in Sweden, Norway and Denmark*. Wollstonecraft has now long ceased to be seen as just a scandalous literary figure, or just the embodiment of a nascent feminism which only reached maturity two hundred years later, but as an Enlightenment moral and political thinker whose works present a self-contained argument about the kind of change society would need to undergo for men and women to be virtuous in both the private and the public sphere and thereby secure the chance of a measure of happiness. What is more, with growing interest in reception history, the extent of her influence in Europe and beyond as been the subject of reassessments. It is becoming increasingly evident that Wollstonecraft was widely read and respected as a pioneer of woman's rights around the world, especially in America, continental Europe, and Brazil (Botting 2013). She was translated into several languages, in the 1790s and throughout the nineteenth century (Johns 2020). Efforts to place Wollstonecraft's thought within an international, and specifically an imperial, context have focused on her use of abolitionist discourses, or what Laura Brace (2016) calls the 'social imaginary' of anti-slavery, to criticize British society. Moira Ferguson (1994) places Wollstonecraft in dialogue with nineteenth-century representations of sexual exploitation within the colonial context by such women authors as Jane Austen and Jamaica Kincaid. Wollstonecraft's reference to slavery and the slave trade as "an atrocious insult to humanity" in *Vindication of the Rights of Men*, and her call for social justice more generally, has been noted by Amartya Sen in his *The Idea of Justice* (2009). Often seen as a proponent of liberal values (Sapiro 1992), Wollstonecraft continues also to placed within a republican tradition, most recently by Sandrine Berges (2013), Alan Coffee (2014), and Lena Halldenius (2015), who have analysed her view of freedom in terms of independence and the absence of subordination to the arbitrary power of others. In recent years, scholars have also made use of Wollstonecraft to inform modern feminist discussions, especially those regarding autonomy, education, and nature. Catriona Mackenzie (2016) argues that Wollstonecraft's understanding of freedom as independence is a forebear to feminist theories that emphasise female autonomy. Sandrine Berges has compared Wollstonecraft's model of education to modern 'capabilities' approaches that favour grassroots educational programmes. Barbara Seeber (2016) places Wollstonecraft within the tradition of ecofeminism: she argues that Wollstonecraft linked social hierarchies with the domination of nature by human beings. Sandrine Berges (2016) identifies a contradiction in her position on feminist motherhood that remains relevant for feminism today. Twenty-first century studies have displayed new interest in the philosophical and theological underpinnings of Wollstonecraft's work. Isabelle Bour (2019) has charted her engagement with competing epistemological models in the 1790s, while Sylvana Tomaselli (2016; 2019) asserts that Wollstonecraft engaged closely with the aesthetic theories of Immanuel Kant and Edmund Burke, as well as Plato's theory of knowledge, Emily Dumler-Winckler (2019) argues that Wollstonecraft appropriated and sometimes subverted a set of conceptual tools from theology in order to make her arguments for women's equality. Wollstonecraft's complex relationship with the works of Jean-Jacques Rousseau has been investigated by Christopher Brooke (2019). Whether Wollstonecraft is best seen as belonging to one tradition or any other will remain a matter of dispute. What is important to remember is that she responded to a fast changing political situation and that she continued to engage critically with public opinion, the leading intellectual and political figures of her age, and most remarkably, her own views in the light of her experiences in France, Northern Europe and Great Britain. Her critique of Burke, the English political system, even the aristocracy, became more muted as she found the continued expansion of commerce and growth of the luxury economy to lead to even greater inequities than the world it was replacing.
word-meaning
## 1. Basics The notions of *word* and *word meaning* are problematic to pin down, and this is reflected in the difficulties one encounters in defining the basic terminology of lexical semantics. In part, this depends on the fact that the term 'word' itself is highly polysemous (see, e.g., Matthews 1991; Booij 2007; Lieber 2010). For example, in ordinary parlance 'word' is ambiguous between a type-level reading (as in "*Color* and *colour* are spellings of the same word"), an occurrence-level reading (as in "there are thirteen words in the tongue-twister *How much wood would a woodchuck chuck if a woodchuck could chuck wood?*"), and a token-level reading (as in "John erased the last two words on the blackboard"). Before proceeding further, let us then elucidate the notion of word in more detail (Section 1.1), and lay out the key questions that will guide our discussion of word meaning in the rest of the entry (Section 1.2). ### 1.1 The Notion of Word We can distinguish two fundamental approaches to the notion of word. On one side, we have *linguistic* approaches, which characterize the notion of word by reflecting on its explanatory role in linguistic research (for a survey on explanation in linguistics, see Egre 2015). These approaches often end up splitting the notion of word into a number of more fine-grained and theoretically manageable notions, but still tend to regard 'word' as a term that zeroes in on a scientifically respectable concept (e.g., Di Sciullo & Williams 1987). For example, words are the primary locus of stress and tone assignment, the basic domain of morphological conditions on affixation, clitization, compounding, and the theme of phonological and morphological processes of assimilation, vowel shift, metathesis, and reduplication (Bromberger 2011). On the other side, we have *metaphysical* approaches, which attempt to pin down the notion of word by inquiring into the metaphysical nature of words. These approaches typically deal with such questions as "what are words?", "how should words be individuated?", and "on what conditions two utterances count as utterances of the same word?". For example, Kaplan (1990, 2011) has proposed to replace the orthodox type-token account of the relation between words and word tokens with a "common currency" view on which words relate to their tokens as continuants relate to stages in four-dimensionalist metaphysics (see the entries on types and tokens and identity over time). Other contributions to this debate can be found, a.o., in McCulloch (1991), Cappelen (1999), Alward (2005), Hawthorne & Lepore (2011), Sainsbury & Tye (2012), Gasparri (2016), and Irmak (forthcoming). For the purposes of this entry, we can rely on the following stipulation. Every natural language has a *lexicon* organized into *lexical entries*, which contain information about word types or *lexemes*. These are the smallest linguistic expressions that are conventionally associated with a non-compositional meaning and can be articulated in isolation to convey semantic content. Word types relate to word tokens and occurrences just like phonemes relate to phones in phonological theory. To understand the parallelism, think of the variations in the place of articulation of the phoneme /n/, which is pronounced as the voiced bilabial nasal [m] in "ten bags" and as the voiced velar nasal [NG] in "ten gates". Just as phonemes are abstract representations of sets of phones (each defining one way the phoneme can be instantiated in speech), lexemes can be defined as abstract representations of sets of words (each defining one way the lexeme can be instantiated in sentences). Thus, 'do', 'does', 'done' and 'doing' are morphologically and graphically marked realizations of the same abstract word type *do*. To wrap everything into a single formula, we can say that the *lexical entries* listed in a *lexicon* set the parameters defining the instantiation potential of word types in sentences, utterances and inscriptions (cf. Murphy 2010). In what follows, unless otherwise indicated, our talk of "word meaning" should be understood as talk of "word type meaning" or "lexeme meaning", in the sense we just illustrated. ### 1.2 Theories of Word Meaning As with general theories of meaning (see the entry on theories of meaning), two kinds of theory of word meaning can be distinguished. The first kind, which we can label a *semantic* theory of word meaning, is a theory interested in clarifying what meaning-determining information is encoded by the words of a natural language. A framework establishing that the word 'bachelor' encodes the lexical concept adult unmarried male would be an example of a semantic theory of word meaning. The second kind, which we can label a *foundational* theory of word meaning, is a theory interested in elucidating the facts in virtue of which words come to have the semantic properties they have for their users. A framework investigating the dynamics of semantic change and social coordination in virtue of which the word 'bachelor' is assigned the function of expressing the lexical concept adult unmarried male would be an example of a foundational theory of word meaning. Likewise, it would be the job of a foundational theory of word meaning to determine whether words have the semantic properties they have in virtue of social conventions, or whether social conventions do not provide explanatory purchase on the facts that ground word meaning (see the entry on convention). Obviously, the endorsement of a given semantic theory is bound to place important constraints on the claims one might propose about the foundational attributes of word meaning, and *vice versa*. Semantic and foundational concerns are often interdependent, and it is difficult to find theories of word meaning which are either purely semantic or purely foundational. According to Ludlow (2014), for example, the fact that word meaning is systematically underdetermined (a semantic matter) can be explained in part by looking at the processes of linguistic negotiation whereby discourse partners converge on the assignment of shared meanings to the words of their language (a foundational matter). However, semantic and foundational theories remain in principle different and designed to answer partly non-overlapping sets of questions. Our focus in this entry will be on *semantic* theories of word meaning, i.e., on theories that try to provide an answer to such questions as "what is the nature of word meaning?", "what do we know when we know the meaning of a word?", and "what (kind of) information must a speaker associate to the words of a language in order to be a competent user of its lexicon?". However, we will engage in foundational considerations whenever necessary to clarify how a given framework addresses issues in the domain of a semantic theory of word meaning. ## 2. Historical Background The study of word meaning became a mature academic enterprise in the 19th century, with the birth of historical-philological semantics (Section 2.2). Yet, matters related to word meaning had been the subject of much debate in earlier times. We can distinguish three major classical approaches to word meaning: speculative etymology, rhetoric, and classical lexicography (Meier-Oeser 2011; Geeraerts 2013). We describe them briefly in Section 2.1. ### 2.1 Classical Traditions The prototypical example of speculative etymology is perhaps the *Cratylus* (383a-d), where Plato presents his well-known naturalist thesis about word meaning. According to Plato, natural kind terms express the essence of the objects they denote and words are appropriate to their referents insofar as they implicitly describe the properties of their referents (see the entry on Plato's *Cratylus*). For example, the Greek word '*anthropos*' can be broken down into *anathron ha opope*, which translates as "one who reflects on what he has seen": the word used to denote humans reflects their being the only animal species which possesses the combination of vision and intelligence. For speculative etymology, there is a natural or non-arbitrary relation between words and their meaning, and the task of the theorist is to make this relation explicit through an analysis of the descriptive, often phonoiconic mechanisms underlying the genesis of words. More on speculative etymology in Malkiel (1993), Fumaroli (1999), and Del Bello (2007). The primary aim of the *rhetorical tradition* was the study of figures of speech. Some of these concern sentence-level variables such as the linear order of the words occurring in a sentence (e.g., parallelism, climax, anastrophe); others are lexical in nature and depend on using words in a way not intended by their normal or literal meaning (e.g., metaphor, metonymy, synecdoche). Although originated for stylistic and literary purposes, the identification of regular patterns in the figurative use of words initiated by the rhetorical tradition provided a first organized framework to investigate the semantic flexibility of words, and laid the groundwork for further inquiry into our ability to use lexical expressions beyond the boundaries of their literal meaning. More on the rhetorical tradition in Kennedy (1994), Herrick (2004), and Toye (2013). Finally, *classical lexicography* and the practice of writing dictionaries played an important role in systematizing the descriptive data on which later inquiry would rely to illuminate the relationship between words and their meaning. Putnam's (1970) claim that it was the phenomenon of writing (and needing) dictionaries that gave rise to the idea of a semantic theory is probably an overstatement. But the inception of lexicography certainly had an impact on the development of modern theories of word meaning. The practice of separating dictionary entries via lemmatization and defining them through a combination of semantically simpler elements provided a stylistic and methodological paradigm for much subsequent research on lexical phenomena, such as decompositional theories of word meaning. More on classical lexicography in Bejoint (2000), Jackson (2002), and Hanks (2013). ### 2.2 Historical-Philological Semantics Historical-philological semantics incorporated elements from all the above classical traditions and dominated the linguistic scene roughly from 1870 to 1930, with the work of scholars such as Michel Breal, Hermann Paul, and Arsene Darmesteter (Gordon 1982). In particular, it absorbed from speculative etymology an interest in the conceptual mechanisms underlying the formation of word meaning, it acquired from rhetorical analysis a taxonomic toolkit for the classification of lexical phenomena, and it assimilated from lexicography and textual philology the empirical basis of descriptive data that subsequent theories of word meaning would have to account for (Geeraerts 2013). On the methodological side, the key features of the approach to word meaning introduced by historical-philological semantics can be summarized as follows. First, it had a diachronic and pragmatic orientation. That is, it was primarily concerned with the historical evolution of word meaning rather than with word meaning statically understood, and attributed great importance to the contextual flexibility of word meaning. Witness Paul's (1920 [1880]) distinction between *usuelle Bedeutung* and *okkasionelle Bedeutung*, or Breal's (1924 [1897]) account of polysemy as a byproduct of semantic change. Second, it looked at word meaning primarily as a psychological phenomenon. It assumed that the semantic properties of words should be defined in mentalistic terms (i.e., words signify "concepts" or "ideas" in a broad sense), and that the dynamics of sense modulation, extension, and contraction that underlie lexical change correspond to broader patterns of conceptual activity in the human mind. Interestingly, while the classical rhetorical tradition had conceived of tropes as marginal linguistic phenomena whose investigation, albeit important, was primarily motivated by stylistic concerns, for historical-philological semantics the psychological mechanisms underlying the production and the comprehension of figures of speech were part of the ordinary life of languages, and engines of the evolution of all aspects of lexical systems (Nerlich 1992). The contribution made by historical-philological semantics to the study of word meaning had a long-lasting influence. First, with its emphasis on the principles of semantic change, historical-philological semantics was the first systematic framework to focus on the dynamic nature of word meaning, and established contextual flexibility as the primary explanandum for a theory of word meaning (Nerlich & Clarke 1996, 2007). This feature of historical-philological semantics is a clear precursor of the emphasis placed on context-sensitivity by many subsequent approaches to word meaning, both in philosophy (see Section 3) and in linguistics (see Section 4). Second, the psychologistic approach to word meaning fostered by historical philological-semantics added to the agenda of linguistic research the question of how word meaning relates to cognition at large. If word meaning is essentially a psychological phenomenon, what psychological categories should be used to characterize it? What is the dividing line separating the aspects of our mental life that constitute knowledge of word meaning from those that do not? As we shall see, this question will constitute a central concern for cognitive theories of word meaning (see Section 5). ## 3. Philosophy of Language In this section we shall review some semantic and metasemantic theories in analytic philosophy that bear on how lexical meaning should be conceived and described. We shall follow a roughly chronological order. Some of these theories, such as Carnap's theory of meaning postulates and Putnam's theory of stereotypes, have a strong focus on lexical meaning, whereas others, such as Montague semantics, regard it as a side issue. However, such negative views form an equally integral part of the philosophical debate on word meaning. ### 3.1 Early Contemporary Views By taking the connection of thoughts and truth as the basic issue of semantics and regarding sentences as "the proper means of expression for a thought" (Frege 1979a [1897]), Frege paved the way for the 20th century priority of sentential meaning over lexical meaning: the semantic properties of subsentential expressions such as individual words were regarded as derivative, and identified with their contribution to sentential meaning. Sentential meaning was in turn identified with truth conditions, most explicitly in Wittgenstein's *Tractatus logico-philosophicus* (1922). However, Frege never lost interest in the "building blocks of thoughts" (Frege 1979b [1914]), i.e., in the semantic properties of subsentential expressions. Indeed, his theory of sense and reference for names and predicates may be counted as the inaugural contribution to lexical semantics within the analytic tradition (see the entry on Gottlob Frege). It should be noted that Frege did not attribute semantic properties to lexical units as such, but to what he regarded as a sentence's logical constituents: e.g., not to the word 'dog' but to the predicate 'is a dog'. In later work this distinction was obliterated and Frege's semantic notions came to be applied to lexical units. Possibly because of lack of clarity affecting the notion of sense, and surely because of Russell's (1905) authoritative criticism of Fregean semantics, word meaning disappeared from the philosophical scene during the 1920s and 1930s. In Wittgenstein's *Tractatus* the "real" lexical units, i.e., the constituents of a completely analyzed sentence, are just names, whose semantic properties are exhausted by their reference. In Tarski's (1933) work on formal languages, which was taken as definitional of the very field of semantics for some time, lexical units are semantically categorized into different classes (individual constants, predicative constants, functional constants) depending on the logical type of their reference, i.e., according to whether they designate individuals in a domain of interpretation, classes of individuals (or of *n*-tuples of individuals), or functions defined over the domain. However, Tarski made no attempt nor felt any need to represent semantic differences among expressions belonging to the same logical type (e.g., between one-place predicates such as 'dog' and 'run', or between two-place predicates such as 'love' and 'left of'). See the entry on Alfred Tarski. Quine (1943) and Church (1951) rehabilitated Frege's distinction of sense and reference. Non-designating words such as 'Pegasus' cannot be meaningless: it is precisely the meaning of 'Pegasus' that allows speakers to establish that the word lacks reference. Moreover, as Frege (1892) had argued, true factual identities such as "Morning Star = Evening Star" do not state synonymies; if they did, any competent speaker of the language would be aware of their truth. Along these lines, Carnap (1947) proposed a new formulation of the sense/reference dichotomy, which was translated into the distinction between *intension* and *extension*. The notion of intension was intended to be an *explicatum* of Frege's "obscure" notion of sense: two expressions have the same intension if and only if they have the same extension in every possible world or, in Carnap's terminology, in every *state description* (i.e., in every maximal consistent set of atomic sentences and negations of atomic sentences). Thus, 'round' and 'spherical' have the same intension (i.e., they express the same function from possible worlds to extensions) because they apply to the same objects in every possible world. Carnap later suggested that intensions could be regarded as the content of lexical semantic competence: to know the meaning of a word is to know its intension, "the general conditions which an object must fulfill in order to be denoted by [that] word" (Carnap 1955). However, such general conditions were not spelled out by Carnap (1947). Consequently, his system did not account, any more than Tarski's, for semantic differences and relations among words belonging to the same semantic category: there were possible worlds in which the same individual *a* could be both a married man and a bachelor, as no constraints were placed on either word's intension. One consequence, as Quine (1951) pointed out, was that Carnap's system, which was supposed to single out analytic truths as true in every possible world, "Bachelors are unmarried"--intuitively, a paradigmatic analytic truth--turned out to be synthetic rather than analytic. To remedy what he agreed was an unsatisfactory feature of his system, Carnap (1952) introduced *meaning postulates*, i.e., stipulations on the relations among the extensions of lexical items. For example, the meaning postulate * (MP)\(\forall x (\mbox{bachelor}(x) \supset \mathord{\sim}\mbox{married} (x))\) stipulates that any individual that is in the extension of 'bachelor' is not in the extension of 'married'. Meaning postulates can be seen either as restrictions on possible worlds or as relativizing analyticity to possible worlds. On the former option we shall say that "If Paul is a bachelor then Paul is unmarried" holds in every *admissible* possible world, while on the latter we shall say that it holds in every possible world *in which (MP) holds*. Carnap regarded the two options as equivalent; nowadays, the former is usually preferred. Carnap (1952) also thought that meaning postulates expressed the semanticist's "intentions" with respect to the meanings of the descriptive constants, which may or may not reflect linguistic usage; again, today postulates are usually understood as expressing semantic relations (synonymy, analytic entailment, etc.) among lexical items as currently used by competent speakers. In the late 1960s and early 1970s, Montague (1974) and other philosophers and linguists (Kaplan, Kamp, Partee, and D. Lewis among others) set out to apply to the analysis of natural language the notions and techniques that had been introduced by Tarski and Carnap and further developed in Kripke's possible worlds semantics (see the entry on Montague semantics). Montague semantics can be represented as aiming to capture the inferential structure of a natural language: every inference that a competent speaker would regard as valid should be derivable in the theory. Some such inferences depend for their validity on syntactic structure and on the logical properties of logical words, like the inference from "Every man is mortal and Socrates is a man" to "Socrates is mortal". Other inferences depend on properties of non-logical words that are usually regarded as semantic, like the inference from "Kim is pregnant" to "Kim is not a man". In Montague semantics, such inferences are taken care of by supplementing the theory with suitable Carnapian meaning postulates. Yet, some followers of Montague regarded such additions as spurious: the aims of semantics, they said, should be distinguished from those of lexicography. The description of the meaning of non-logical words requires considerable world knowledge: for example, the inference from "Kim is pregnant" to "Kim is not a man" is based on a "biological" rather than on a "logical" generalization. Hence, we should not expect a semantic theory to furnish an account of how any two expressions belonging to the same syntactic category differ in meaning (Thomason 1974). From such a viewpoint, Montague semantics would not differ significantly from Tarskian semantics in its account of lexical meaning. But not all later work within Montague's program shared such a skepticism about representing aspects of lexical meaning within a semantic theory, using either componential analysis (Dowty 1979) or meaning postulates (Chierchia & McConnell-Ginet 2000). For those who believe that meaning postulates can exhaust lexical meaning, the issue arises of how to choose them, i.e., of how--and whether--to delimit the set of meaning-relevant truths with respect to the set of all true statements in which a given word occurs. As we just saw, Carnap himself thought that the choice could only be the expression of the semanticist's intentions. However, we seem to share intuitions of *analyticity*, i.e., we seem to regard some, but not all sentences of a natural language as true by virtue of the meaning of the occurring words. Such intuitions are taken to reflect objective semantic properties of the language, that the semanticist should describe rather than impose at will. Quine (1951) did not challenge the existence of such intuitions, but he argued that they could not be cashed out in the form of a scientifically respectable criterion separating analytic truths ("Bachelors are unmarried") from synthetic truths ("Aldo's uncle is a bachelor"), whose truth does not depend on meaning alone. Though Quine's arguments were often criticized (for recent criticisms, see Williamson 2007), and in spite of Chomsky's constant endorsement of analyticity (see e.g. 2000: 47, 61-2), within philosophy the analytic/synthetic distinction was never fully vindicated (for an exception, see Russell 2008). Hence, it was widely believed that lexical meaning could not be adequately described by meaning postulates. Fodor and Lepore (1992) argued that this left semantics with two options: lexical meanings were either *atomic* (i.e., they could not be specified by descriptions involving other meanings) or they were *holistic*, i.e., only the set of all true sentences of the language could count as fixing them. Neither alternative looked promising. Holism incurred in objections connected with the acquisition and the understanding of language: how could individual words be acquired by children, if grasping their meaning involved, somehow, semantic competence on the whole language? And how could individual sentences be understood if the information required to understand them exceeded the capacity of human working memory? (For an influential criticism of several varieties of holism, see Dummett 1991; for a review, Pagin 2006). Atomism, in turn, ran against strong intuitions of (at least some) relations among words being part of a language's semantics: it is because of what 'bachelor' means that it doesn't make sense to suppose we could discover that some bachelors are married. Fodor (1998) countered this objection by reinterpreting allegedly semantic relations as metaphysically necessary connections among extensions of words. However, sentences that are usually regarded as analytic, such as "Bachelors are unmarried", are not easily seen as just metaphysically necessary truths like "Water is H2O". If water is H2O, then its metaphysical essence consists in being H2O (whether we know it or not); but there is no such thing as a metaphysical essence that all bachelors share--an essence that could be hidden to us, even though we use the word 'bachelor' competently. On the contrary, on acquiring the word 'bachelor' we acquire the belief that bachelors are unmarried (Quine 1986); by contrast, many speakers that have 'water' in their lexical repertoire do not know that water is H2O. The difficulties of atomism and holism opened the way to vindications of molecularism (e.g., Perry 1994; Marconi 1997), the view on which only some relations among words matter for acquisition and understanding (see the entry on meaning holism). While mainstream formal semantics went with Carnap and Montague, supplementing the Tarskian apparatus with the possible worlds machinery and defining meanings as intensions, Davidson (1967, 1984) put forth an alternative suggestion. Tarski had shown how to provide a definition of the truth predicate for a (formal) language *L*: such a definition is materially adequate (i.e., it is a definition of *truth*, rather than of some other property of sentences of *L*) if and only if it entails every biconditional of the form * (T) *S* is true in *L* iff *p*, where *S* is a sentence of *L* and *p* is its translation into the metalanguage of *L* in which the definition is formulated. Thus, Tarski's account of truth presupposes that the semantics of both *L* and its metalanguage is fixed (otherwise it would be undetermined whether *S* translates into *p*). On Tarski's view, each biconditional of form (T) counts as a "partial definition" of the truth predicate for sentences of *L* (see the entry on Tarski's truth definitions). By contrast, Davidson suggested that if one took the notion of truth for granted, then T-biconditionals could be read as collectively constituting a theory of meaning for *L*, i.e., as stating truth conditions for the sentences of *L*. For example, * (W) "If the weather is bad then Sharon is sad" is true in English iff either the weather is not bad or Sharon is sad states the truth conditions of the English sentence "If the weather is bad then Sharon is sad". Of course, (W) is intelligible only if one understands the language in which it is phrased, including the predicate 'true in English'. Davidson thought that the recursive machinery of Tarski's definition of truth could be transferred to the suggested semantic reading, with extensions to take care of the forms of natural language composition that Tarski had neglected because they had no analogue in the formal languages he was dealing with. Unfortunately, few of such extensions were ever spelled out by Davidson or his followers. Moreover, it is difficult to see how, giving up possible worlds and intensions in favor of a purely extensional theory, the Davidsonian program could account for the semantics of propositional attitude ascriptions of the form "A believes (hopes, imagines, etc.) that *p*". Construed as theorems of a semantic theory, T-biconditionals were often accused of being uninformative (Putnam 1975; Dummett 1976): to understand them, one has to already possess the information they are supposed to provide. This is particularly striking in the case of *lexical axioms* such as the following: * (V1) Val(*x*, 'man') iff *x* is a man; * (V2) Val(\(\langle x,y\rangle\), 'knows') iff *x* knows *y*. (To be read, respectively, as "the predicate 'man' applies to *x* if and only if *x* is a man" and "the predicate 'know' applies to the pair \(\langle x, y\rangle\) if and only if *x* knows *y*"). Here it is apparent that in order to understand (V1) one must know what 'man' means, which is just the information that (V1) is supposed to convey (as the theory, being purely extensional, identifies meaning with reference). Some Davidsonians, though admitting that statements such as (V1) and (V2) are in a sense "uninformative", insist that what (V1) and (V2) state is no less "substantive" (Larson & Segal 1995). To prove their point, they appeal to non-homophonic versions of lexical axioms, i.e., to the axioms of a semantic theory for a language that does not coincide with the (meta)language in which the theory itself is phrased. Such would be, e.g., * (V3) *Val*(*x*, 'man') *si et seulement si *x* est un homme.* (V3), they argue, is clearly substantive, yet what it says is exactly what (V1) says, namely, that the word 'man' applies to a certain category of objects. Therefore, if (V3) is substantive, so is (V1). But this is beside the point. The issue is not whether (V1) expresses a proposition; it clearly does, and it is, in this sense, "substantive". But what is relevant here is informative power: to one who understands the metalanguage of (V3), i.e., French, (V3) may communicate new information, whereas there is no circumstance in which (V1) would communicate new information to one who understands English. ### 3.2 Grounding and Lexical Competence In the mid-1970s, Dummett raised the issue of the proper place of lexical meaning in a semantic theory. If the job of a theory of meaning is to make the content of semantic competence explicit--so that one could acquire semantic competence in a language *L* by learning an adequate theory of meaning for *L*--then the theory ought to reflect a competent speaker's knowledge of circumstances in which she would assert a sentence of *L*, such as "The horse is in the barn", as distinct from circumstances in which she would assert "The cat is on the mat". This, in turn, appears to require that the theory yields explicit information about the use of 'horse', 'barn', etc., or, in other words, that it includes information which goes beyond the logical type of lexical units. Dummett identified such information with a word's Fregean sense. However, he did not specify the format in which word senses should be expressed in a semantic theory, except for words that could be defined (e.g., 'aunt' = "sister of a parent"): in such cases, the *definiens* specifies what a speaker must understand in order to understand the word (Dummett 1991). But of course, not all words are of this kind. For other words, the theory should specify what it is for a speaker to know them, though we are not told how exactly this should be done. Similarly, Grandy (1974) pointed out that by identifying the meaning of a word such as 'wise' as a function from possible worlds to the sets of wise people in those worlds, Montague semantics only specifies a formal structure and eludes the question of whether there is some possible description for the functions which are claimed to be the meanings of words. Lacking such descriptions, possible worlds semantics is not really a theory of meaning but a theory of logical form or logical validity. Again, aside from suggesting that "one would like the functions to be given in terms of computation procedures, in some sense", Grandy had little to say about the form of lexical descriptions. In a similar vein, Partee (1981) argued that Montague semantics, like every compositional or *structural* semantics, does not uniquely fix the intensional interpretation of words. The addition of meaning postulates does rule out some interpretations (e.g., interpretations on which the extension of 'bachelor' and the extension of 'married' may intersect in some possible world). However, it does not reduce them to the unique, "intended" or, in Montague's words, "actual" interpretation (Montague 1974). Hence, standard model-theoretic semantics does not capture the whole content of a speaker's semantic competence, but only its structural aspects. Fixing "the actual interpretation function" requires more than language-to-language connections as encoded by, e.g., meaning postulates: it requires some "language-to-world *grounding*". Arguments to the same effect were developed by Bonomi (1983) and Harnad (1990). In particular, Harnad had in mind the simulation of human semantic competence in artificial systems: he suggested that symbol grounding could be implemented, in part, by "feature detectors" picking out "invariant features of objects and event categories from their sensory projections" (for recent developments see, e.g., Steels & Hild 2012). Such a cognitively oriented conception of grounding differs from Partee's Putnam-inspired view, on which the semantic grounding of lexical items depends on the speakers' objective interactions with the external world in addition to their narrow psychological properties. A resolutely cognitive approach characterizes Marconi's (1997) account of lexical semantic competence. In his view, lexical competence has two aspects: an *inferential* aspect, underlying performances such as semantically based inference and the command of synonymy, hyponymy and other semantic relations; and a *referential* aspect, which is in charge of performances such as naming (e.g., calling a horse 'horse') and application (e.g., answering the question "Are there any spoons in the drawer?"). Language users typically possess both aspects of lexical competence, though in different degrees for different words: a zoologist's inferential competence on 'manatee' is usually richer than a layman's, though a layman who spent her life among manatees may be more competent, referentially, than a "bookish" scientist. However, the two aspects are independent of each another, and neuropsychological evidence appears to show that they can be dissociated: there are patients whose referential competence is impaired or lost while their inferential competence is intact, and *vice versa* (see Section 5.3). Being a theory of individual competence, Marconi's account does not deal directly with lexical meanings in a public language: communication depends both on the uniformity of cognitive interactions with the external world and on communal norms concerning the use of language, together with speakers' deferential attitude toward semantic authorities. ### 3.3 The Externalist Turn Since the early 1970s, views on lexical meaning were revolutionized by semantic externalism. Initially, externalism was limited to proper names and natural kind words such as 'gold' or 'lemon'. In slightly different ways, both Kripke (1972) and Putnam (1970, 1975) argued that the reference of such words was not determined by any description that a competent speaker associated with the word; more generally, and contrary to what Frege may have thought, it was not determined by any cognitive content associated with it in a speaker's mind (for arguments to that effect, see the entry on names). Instead, reference is determined, at least in part, by objective ("causal") relations between a speaker and the external world. For example, a speaker refers to Aristotle when she utters the sentence "Aristotle was a great warrior"--so that her assertion expresses a false proposition about Aristotle, not a true proposition about some great warrior she may "have in mind"--thanks to her connection with Aristotle himself. In this case, the connection is constituted by a historical chain of speakers going back to the initial users of the name 'Aristotle', or its Greek equivalent, in baptism-like circumstances. To belong to the chain, speakers (including present-day speakers) are not required to possess any precise knowledge of Aristotle's life and deeds; they are, however, required to intend to use the name as it is used by the speakers they are picking up the name from, i.e., to refer to the individual those speakers intend to refer to. In the case of most natural kind names, it may be argued, baptisms are hard to identify or even conjecture. In Putnam's view, for such words reference is determined by speakers' causal interaction with portions of matter or biological individuals in their environment: 'water', for example, refers to *this* liquid stuff, stuff that is normally found in *our* rivers, lakes, etc. The indexical component (*this* liquid, *our* rivers) is crucial to reference determination: it wouldn't do to identify the referent of 'water' by way of some description ("liquid, transparent, quenches thirst, boils at 100degC, etc."), for something might fit the description yet fail to be water, as in Putnam's (1973, 1975) famous Twin Earth thought experiment (see the entry on reference). It might be remarked that, thanks to modern chemistry, we now possess a description that is sure to apply to water and only to water: "being H2O" (Millikan 2005). However, even if our chemistry were badly mistaken (as in principle it could turn out to be) and water were not, in fact, H2O, 'water' would still refer to whatever has the same nature as *this* liquid. Something belongs to the extension of 'water' if and only if it is the same substance as this liquid, which we identify--correctly, as we believe--as being H2O. Let it be noted that in Putnam's original proposal, reference determination is utterly independent of speakers' cognition: 'water' on Twin Earth refers to XYZ (not to H2O) even though the difference between the two substances is cognitively inert, so that before chemistry was created nobody on either Earth or Twin Earth could have told them apart. However, the label 'externalism' has been occasionally used for weaker views: a semantic account may be regarded as externalist if it takes semantic content to depend in one way or another on relations a computational system bears to things outside itself (Rey 2005; Borg 2012), irrespective of whether such relations affect the system's cognitive state. Weak externalism is hard to distinguish from forms of internalism on which a word's reference is determined by information stored in a speaker's cognitive system--information of which the speaker may or may not be aware (Evans 1982). Be that as it may, in what follows 'externalism' will be used to mean strong, or Putnamian, externalism. Does externalism apply to other lexical categories besides proper names and natural kind words? Putnam (1975) extended it to artifactual words, claiming that 'pencil' would refer to pencils--*those* objects--even if they turned out not to fit the description by which we normally identify them (e.g., if they were discovered to be organisms, not artifacts). Schwartz (1978, 1980) pointed out, among many objections, that even in such a case we could *make* objects fitting the original description; we would then regard the pencil-like organisms as impostors, not as "genuine" pencils. Others sided with Putnam and the externalist account: for example, Kornblith (1980) pointed out that artifactual kinds from an ancient civilization could be re-baptized in total ignorance of their function. The new artifactual word would then refer to the kind *those* objects belong to independently of any beliefs about them, true or false. Against such externalist accounts, Thomasson (2007) argued that artifactual terms cannot refer to artifactual kinds independently of all beliefs and concepts about the nature of the kind, for the concept of the kind's creator(s) is constitutive of the nature of the kind. Whether artifactual words are liable to an externalist account is still an open issue (for recent discussions see Marconi 2013; Bahr, Carrara & Jansen 2019; see also the entry on artifacts), as is, more generally, the scope of application of externalist semantics. There is another form of externalism that does apply to all or most words of a language: *social* externalism (Burge 1979), the view on which the meaning of a word as used by an individual speaker depends on the semantic standards of the linguistic community the speaker belongs to. In our community the word 'arthritis' refers to arthritis--an affliction of the joints--even when used by a speaker who believes that it can afflict the muscles as well and uses the word accordingly. If the community the speaker belongs to applied 'arthritis' to rheumatoids ailments in general, whether or not they afflict the joints, the same word form would not mean arthritis and would not refer to arthritis. Hence, a speaker's mental contents, such as the meanings associated with the words she uses, depend on something external to her, namely the uses and the standards of use of the linguistic community she belongs to. Thus, social externalism eliminates the notion of idiolect: words only have the meanings conferred upon them by the linguistic community ("public" meanings); discounting radical incompetence, there is no such thing as individual semantic deviance, there are only false beliefs (for criticisms, see Bilgrami 1992, Marconi 1997; see also the entry on idiolects). Though both forms of externalism focus on reference, neither is a complete reduction of lexical meaning to reference. Both Putnam and Burge make it a necessary condition of semantic competence on a word that a speaker commands information that other semantic views would regard as part of the word's sense. For example, if a speaker believes that manatees are a kind of household appliance, she would not count as competent on the word 'manatee', nor would she refer to manatees by using it (Putnam 1975; Burge 1993). Beyond that, it is not easy for externalists to provide a satisfactory account of lexical semantic competence, as they are committed to regarding speakers' beliefs and abilities (e.g., recognitional abilities) as essentially irrelevant to reference determination, hence to meaning. Two main solutions have been proposed. Putnam (1970, 1975) suggested that a speaker's semantic competence consists in her knowledge of *stereotypes* associated with words. A stereotype is an oversimplified theory of a word's extension: the stereotype associated with 'tiger' describes tigers as cat-like, striped, carnivorous, fierce, living in the jungle, etc. Stereotypes are not meanings, as they do not determine reference in the right way: there are albino tigers and tigers that live in zoos. What the 'tiger'-stereotype describes is (what the community takes to be) the *typical* tiger. Knowledge of stereotypes is necessary to be regarded as a competent speaker, and--one surmises--it can also be considered sufficient for the purposes of ordinary communication. Thus, Putnam's account does provide some content for semantic competence, though it dissociates it from knowledge of meaning. On an alternative view (Devitt 1983), competence on 'tiger' does not consist in entertaining propositional beliefs such as "tigers are striped", but rather in being appropriately linked to a network of causal chains for 'tiger' involving other people's abilities, groundings, and reference borrowings. In order to understand the English word 'tiger' and use it in a competent fashion, a subject must be able to combine 'tiger' appropriately with other words to form sentences, to have thoughts which those sentences express, and to ground these thoughts in tigers. Devitt's account appears to make some room for a speaker's ability to, e.g., recognize a tiger when she sees one; however, the respective weights of individual abilities (and beliefs) and objective grounding are not clearly specified. Suppose a speaker *A* belongs to a community *C* that is familiar with tigers; unfortunately, *A* has no knowledge of the typical appearance of a tiger and is unable to tell a tiger from a leopard. Should *A* be regarded as a competent user 'tiger' on account of her being "part of *C*" and therefore linked to a network of causal chains for 'tiger'? ### 3.4 Internalism Some philosophers (e.g., Loar 1981; McGinn 1982; Block 1986) objected to the reduction of lexical meaning to reference, or to non-psychological factors that are alleged to determine reference. In their view, there are two aspects of meaning (more generally, of content): the *narrow* aspect, that captures the intuition that 'water' has the same meaning in both Earthian and Twin-Earthian English, and the *wide* aspect, that captures the externalist intuition that 'water' picks out different substances in the two worlds. The wide notion is required to account for the difference in reference between English and Twin-English 'water'; the narrow notion is needed, first and foremost, to account for the relation between a subject's beliefs and her behavior. The idea is that *how* an object of reference is described (not just which object one refers to) can make a difference in determining behavior. Oedipus married Jocasta because he thought he was marrying the queen of Thebes, not his mother, though as a matter of fact Jocasta *was* his mother. This applies to words of all categories: someone may believe that water quenches thirst without believing that H2O does; Lois Lane believed that Superman was a superhero but she definitely did not believe the same of her colleague Clark Kent, so she behaved one way to the man she identified as Superman and another way to the man she identified as Clark Kent (though they were the same man). Theorists that countenance these two components of meaning and content usually identify the narrow aspect with the *inferential* or *conceptual role* of an expression *e*, i.e., with the aspect of *e* that contributes to determine the inferential relations between sentences containing an occurrence of *e* and other sentences. Crucially, the two aspects are independent: neither determines the other. The stress on the independence of the two factors also characterizes more recent versions of so-called "dual aspect" theories, such as Chalmers (1996, 2002). While dual theorists agree with Putnam's claim that some aspects of meaning are not "in the head", others have opted for plain internalism. For example, Segal (2000) rejected the intuitions that are usually associated with the Twin-Earth cases by arguing that meaning (and content in general) "locally supervenes" on a subject's intrinsic physical properties. But the most influential critic of externalism has undoubtedly been Chomsky (2000). First, he argued that much of the alleged support for externalism comes in fact from "intuitions" about words' reference in this or that circumstance. But 'reference' (and the verb 'refer' as used by philosophers) is a technical term, not an ordinary word, hence we have no more intuitions about reference than we have about tensors or c-command. Second, if we look at how words such as 'water' are applied in ordinary circumstances, we find that speakers may call 'water' liquids that contain a smaller proportion of H2O than other liquids they do not call 'water' (e.g., tea): our use of 'water' does not appear to be governed by hypotheses about microstructure. According to Chomsky, it may well be that progress in the scientific study of the language faculty will allow us to understand in what respects one's picture of the world is framed in terms of things selected and individuated by properties of the lexicon, or involves entities and relationships describable by the resources of the language faculty. *Some* semantic properties do appear to be integrated with other aspects of language. However, so-called "natural kind words" (which in fact have little to do with kinds in nature, Chomsky claims) may do little more than indicating "positions in belief systems": studying them may be of some interest for "ethnoscience", surely not for a science of language. Along similar lines, others have maintained that the genuine semantic properties of linguistic expressions should be regarded as part of syntax, and that they constrain but do not determine truth conditions (e.g., Pietroski 2005, 2010). Hence, the connection between meaning and truth conditions (and reference) may be significantly looser than assumed by many philosophers. ### 3.5 Contextualism, Minimalism, and the Lexicon "Ordinary language" philosophers of the 1950s and 1960s regarded work in formal semantics as essentially irrelevant to issues of meaning in natural language. Following Austin and the later Wittgenstein, they identified meaning with use and were prone to consider the different patterns of use of individual expressions as originating different meanings of the word. Grice (1975) argued that such a proliferation of meanings could be avoided by distinguishing between what is asserted by a sentence (to be identified with its truth conditions) and what is communicated by it in a given context (or in every "normal" context). For example, consider the following exchange: * A: Will Kim be hungry at 11am? * B: Kim had breakfast. Although B does not literally assert that Kim had breakfast on that particular day (see, however, Partee 1973), she does communicate as much. More precisely, A could infer the communicated content by noticing that the asserted sentence, taken literally ("Kim had breakfast at least once in her life"), would be less informative than required in the context: thus, it would violate one or more principles of conversation ("maxims") whereas there is no reason to suppose that the speaker intended to opt out of conversational cooperation (see the entries on Paul Grice and pragmatics). If the interlocutor assumes that the speaker intended him to infer the communicated content--i.e., that Kim had breakfast *that morning*, so presumably she would not be hungry at 11--cooperation is preserved. Such non-asserted content, called 'implicature', need not be an addition to the overtly asserted content: e.g., in irony asserted content is negated rather than expanded by the implicature (think of a speaker uttering "Paul is a fine friend" to implicate that Paul has wickedly betrayed her). Grice's theory of conversation and implicatures was interpreted by many (including Grice himself) as a convincing way of accounting for the variety of contextually specific communicative contents while preserving the uniqueness of a sentence's "literal" meaning, which was identified with truth conditions and regarded as determined by syntax and the conventional meanings of the occurring words, as in formal semantics. The only semantic role context was allowed to play was in determining the content of indexical words (such as 'I', 'now', 'here', etc.) and the effect of context-sensitive structures (such as tense) on a sentence's truth conditions. However, in about the same years Travis (1975) and Searle (1979, 1980) pointed out that the semantic relevance of context might be much more pervasive, if not universal: intuitively, the same sentence type could have very different truth conditions in different contexts, though no indexical expression or structure appeared to be involved. Take the sentence "There is milk in the fridge": in the context of morning breakfast it will be considered true if there is a carton of milk in the fridge and false if there is a patch of milk on a tray in the fridge, whereas in the context of cleaning up the kitchen truth conditions are reversed. Examples can be multiplied indefinitely, as indefinitely many factors can turn out to be relevant to the truth or falsity of a sentence as uttered in a particular context. Such variety cannot be plausibly reduced to traditional polysemy such as the polysemy of 'property' (meaning quality or real estate), nor can it be described in terms of Gricean implicatures: implicatures are supposed not to affect a sentence's truth conditions, whereas here it is precisely the sentence's truth conditions that are seen as varying with context. The traditionalist could object by challenging the contextualist's intuitions about truth conditions. "There is milk in the fridge", she could argue, is true if and only if there is a certain amount (a few molecules will do) of a certain organic substance in the relevant fridge (for versions of this objection, Cappelen & Lepore 2005). So the sentence is true both in the carton case and in the patch case; it would be false only if the fridge did not contain any amount of any kind of milk (whether cow milk or goat milk or elephant milk). The contextualist's reply is that, in fact, neither the speaker nor the interpreter is aware of such alleged literal content (the point is challenged by Fodor 1983, Carston 2002); but "what is said" must be intuitively accessible to the conversational participants (*Availability Principle*, Recanati 1989). If truth conditions are associated with what is said--as the traditionalist would agree they are--then in many cases a sentence's literal content, if there is such a thing, does not determine a complete, evaluable proposition. For a genuine proposition to arise, a sentence type's literal content (as determined by syntax and conventional word meaning) must be enriched or otherwise modified by *primary pragmatic processes* based on the speakers' background knowledge relative to each particular context of use of the sentence. Such processes differ from Gricean implicature-generating processes in that they come into play at the sub-propositional level; moreover, they are not limited to *saturation* of indexicals but may include the replacement of a constituent with another. These tenets define contextualism (Recanati 1993; Bezuidenhout 2002; Carston 2002; relevance theory (Sperber & Wilson 1986) is in some respects a precursor of such views). Contextualists take different stands on nature of the semantic contribution made by words to sentences, though they typically agree that it is insufficient to fix truth conditions (Stojanovic 2008). See Del Pinal (2018) for an argument that radical contextualism (in particular, truth-conditional pragmatics) should instead commit to rich lexical items which, in certain conditions, do suffice to fix truth conditions. Even if sentence types have no definite truth conditions, it does not follow that lexical types do not make definite or predictable contributions to the truth conditions of sentences (think of indexical words). It does follow, however, that conventional word meanings are not the final constituents of complete propositions (see Allot & Textor 2012). Does this imply that there are no such things as lexical meanings understood as features of a language? If so, how should we account for word acquisition and lexical competence in general? Recanati (2004) does not think that contextualism as such is committed to meaning eliminativism, the view on which words as types have no meaning; nevertheless, he regards it as defensible. Words could be said to have, rather than "meaning", a *semantic potential*, defined as the collection of past uses of a word *w* on the basis of which similarities can be established between source situations (i.e., the circumstances in which a speaker has used *w*) and target situations (i.e., candidate occasions of application of *w*). It is natural to object that even admitting that long-term memory could encompass such an immense amount of information (think of the number of times 'table' or 'woman' are used by an average speaker in the course of her life), surely working memory could not review such information to make sense of new uses. On the other hand, if words were associated with "more abstract schemata corresponding to types of situations", as Recanati suggests as a less radical alternative to meaning eliminativism, one wonders what the difference would be with respect to traditional accounts in terms of polysemy. Other conceptions of "what is said" make more room for the semantic contribution of conventional word meanings. Bach (1994) agrees with contextualists that the linguistic meaning of words (plus syntax and after saturation) does not always determine complete, truth-evaluable propositions; however, he maintains that they do provide some minimal semantic information, a so-called 'propositional radical', that allows pragmatic processes to issue in one or more propositions. Bach identifies "what is said" with this minimal information. However, many have objected that minimal content is extremely hard to isolate (Recanati 2004; Stanley 2007). Suppose it is identified with the content that all the utterances of a sentence type share; unfortunately, no such content can be attributed to a sentence such as "Every bottle is in the fridge", for there is no proposition that is stably asserted by every utterance of it (surely not the proposition that every bottle in the universe is in the fridge, which is *never* asserted). Stanley's (2007) *indexicalism* rejects the notion of minimal proposition and any distinction between semantic content and communicated content: communicated content can be entirely captured by means of consciously accessible, linguistically controlled content (content that results from semantic value together with the provision of values to free variables in syntax, or semantic value together with the provision of arguments to functions from semantic types to propositions) together with general conversational norms. Accordingly, Stanley generalizes contextual saturation processes that are usually regarded as characteristic of indexicals, tense, and a few other structures; moreover, he requires that the relevant variables be linguistically encoded, either syntactically or lexically. It remains to be seen whether such solutions apply (in a non-*ad hoc* way) to all the examples of content modulation that have been presented in the literature. Finally, *minimalism* (Borg 2004, 2012; Cappelen & Lepore 2005) is the view that appears (and intends) to be closest to the Frege-Montague tradition. The task of a semantic theory is said to be minimal in that it is supposed to account only for the literal meaning of sentences: context does not affect literal semantic content but "what the speaker says" as opposed to "what the sentence means" (Borg 2012). In this sense, semantics is not another name for the theory of meaning, because not all meaning-related properties are semantic properties (Borg 2004). Contrary to contextualism and Bach's theory, minimalism holds that lexicon and syntax together determine complete truth-evaluable propositions. Indeed, this is definitional for lexical meaning: word meanings are the kind of things which, if one puts enough of them together in the right sort of way, then what one gets is propositional content (Borg 2012). Borg believes that, in order to be truth-evaluable, propositional contents must be "about the world", and that this entails some form of semantic externalism. However, the identification of lexical meaning with reference makes it hard to account for semantic relations such as synonymy, analytic entailment or the difference between ambiguity and polysemy, and syntactically relevant properties: the difference between "John is easy to please" and "John is eager to please" cannot be explained by the fact that 'easy' means the property easy (see the entry on ambiguity). To account for semantically based syntactic properties, words may come with "instructions" that are not, however, constitutive of a word's meaning like meaning postulates (which Borg rejects), though awareness of them is part of a speaker's competence. Once more, lexical semantic competence is divorced from grasp of word meaning. In conclusion, some information counts as lexical if it is either perceived as such in "firm, type-level lexical intuitions" or capable of affecting the word's syntactic behavior. Borg concedes that even such an extended conception of lexical content will not capture, e.g., analytic entailments such as the relation between 'bachelor' and 'unmarried'. ## 4. Linguistics The emergence of modern linguistic theories of word meaning is usually placed at the transition from historical-philological semantics (Section 2.2) to structuralist semantics, the linguistics movement started at the break of the 20th century by Ferdinand de Saussure with his *Cours de Linguistique Generale* (1995 [1916]). ### 4.1 Structuralist Semantics The advances introduced by the structuralist conception of word meaning are best appreciated by contrasting its basic assumptions with those of historical-philological semantics. Let us recall the three most important differences (Lepschy 1970; Matthews 2001). * *Anti-psychologism*. Structuralist semantics views language as a symbolic system whose properties and internal dynamics can be analyzed without taking into account their implementation in the mind/brain of language users. Just as the rules of chess can be stated and analyzed without making reference to the mental properties of chess players, so a theory of word meaning can, and should, proceed simply by examining the formal role played by words within the system of the language. * *Anti-historicism*. Since the primary explanandum of structuralist semantics is the role played by lexical expressions within structured linguistic systems, structuralist semantics privileges the synchronic description of word meaning. Diachronic accounts of word meaning are logically posterior to the analysis of the relational properties statically exemplified by words at different stages of the evolution of the language. * *Anti-localism*. Because the semantic properties of words depend on the relations they entertain with other expressions in the same lexical system, word meanings cannot be studied in isolation. This is both an epistemological and a foundational claim, i.e., a claim about how matters related to word meaning should be addressed in the context of a semantic theory of word meaning, and a claim about the dynamics whereby the elements of a system of signs acquire the meaning they have for their users. The account of lexical phenomena popularized by structuralism gave rise to a variety of descriptive approaches to word meaning. We can group them in three categories (Lipka 1992; Murphy 2003; Geeraerts 2006). * *Lexical Field Theory*. Introduced by Trier (1931), it argues that word meaning should be studied by looking at the relations holding between words in the same lexical field. A lexical field is a set of semantically related words whose meanings are mutually interdependent and which together spell out the conceptual structure of a given domain of reality. Lexical Field Theory assumes that lexical fields are closed sets with no overlapping meanings or semantic gaps. Whenever a word undergoes a change in meaning (e.g., its range of application is extended or contracted), the whole arrangement of its lexical field is affected (Lehrer 1974). * *Componential Analysis*. Developed in the second half of the 1950s by European and American linguists (e.g., Pattier, Coseriu, Bloomfield, Nida), this framework argues that word meaning can be described on the basis of a finite set of conceptual building blocks called semantic *components* or *features*. For example, 'man' can be analyzed as [+ male], [+ mature], 'woman' as [[?] male], [+ mature], 'child' as [+/[?] male] [[?] mature] (Leech 1974). * *Relational Semantics*. Prominent in the work of linguists such as Lyons (1963), this approach shares with Lexical Field Theory the commitment to a style of analysis that privileges the description of lexical relations, but departs from it in two important respects. First, it postulates no direct correspondence between sets of related words and domains of reality, thereby dropping the assumption that the organization of lexical fields should be understood to reflect the organization of the non-linguistic world. Second, instead of deriving statements about the meaning relations entertained by a lexical item (e.g., synonymy, hyponymy) from an independent account of its meaning, for relational semantics word meanings are constituted by the set of semantic relations words participate in (Evens et al. 1980; Cruse 1986). ### 4.2 Generativist Semantics The componential current of structuralism was the first to produce an important innovation in theories of word meaning: Katzian semantics (Katz & Fodor 1963; Katz 1972, 1987). Katzian semantics combined componential analysis with a mentalistic conception of word meaning and developed a method for the description of lexical phenomena in the context of a formal grammar. The mentalistic component of Katzian semantics is twofold. First, word meanings are defined as aggregates of simpler conceptual features inherited from our general categorization abilities. Second, the proper subject matter of the theory is no longer identified with the "structure of the language" but, following Chomsky (1957, 1965), with speakers' ability to competently interpret the words and sentences of their language. In Katzian semantics, word meanings are structured entities whose representations are called *semantic markers*. A semantic marker is a hierarchical tree with labeled nodes whose structure reproduces the structure of the represented meaning, and whose labels identify the word's conceptual components. For example, the figure below illustrates the sense of 'chase' (simplified from Katz 1987). ![a tree of the form [.((Activity)_{[NP,S]}) [.(Physical) [.(Movement) (Fast) [.((Direction of)_{[NP,VP,S]}) ((Toward Location of) _{[NP,VP,S]}) ] ] ] [.(Purpose) ((Catching) _{[NP,VP,S]}) ] ]](word-meaning-tree.png) Katz (1987) claimed that this approach was superior in both transparency and richness to the analysis of word meaning that could be provided via meaning postulates. For example, in Katzian semantics the validation of conditionals such as \(\forall x\forall y (\textrm{chase}(x, y) \to \textrm{follow}(x,y))\) could be reduced to a matter of inspection: one had simply to check whether the semantic marker of 'follow' was a subtree of the semantic marker of 'chase'. Furthermore, the method incorporated syntagmatic relations in the representation of word meanings (witness the grammatical tags 'NP', 'VP' and 'S' attached to the conceptual components above). Katzian semantics was favorably received by the Generative Semantics movement (Fodor 1977; Newmeyer 1980) and boosted an interest in the formal representation of word meaning that would dominate the linguistic scene for decades to come (Harris 1993). Nonetheless, it was eventually abandoned. As subsequent commentators noted, Katzian semantics suffered from three important drawbacks. First, the theory did not provide any clear model of how the complex conceptual information represented by semantic markers contributed to the truth conditions of sentences (Lewis 1972). Second, some aspects of word meaning that could be easily represented with meaning postulates could not be expressed through semantic markers, such as the symmetry and the transitivity of predicates (e.g., \(\forall x\forall y (\textrm{sibling}(x, y) \to \textrm{sibling}(y, x))\) or \(\forall x\forall y\forall z (\textrm{louder}(x, y) \mathbin{\&} \textrm{louder}(y, z) \to \textrm{louder}(x, z))\); see Dowty 1979). Third, Katz's arguments for the view that word meanings are intrinsically structured turned out to be vulnerable to objections from proponents of atomistic views of word meaning (see, most notably, Fodor & Lepore 1992). After Katzian semantics, the landscape of linguistic theories of word meaning bifurcated. On one side, we find a group of theories advancing the *decompositional* agenda established by Katz. On the other side, we find a group of theories fostering the *relational* approach originated by Lexical Field Theory and relational semantics. Following Geeraerts (2010), we will briefly characterize the following ones. | *Decompositional Frameworks* | *Relational Frameworks* | | --- | --- | | Natural Semantic Metalanguage | Symbolic Networks | | Conceptual Semantics | Statistical Analysis | | Two-Level Semantics | | | Generative Lexicon Theory | | ### 4.3 Decompositional Approaches The basic idea of the Natural Semantic Metalanguage approach (henceforth, NSM; Wierzbicka 1972, 1996; Goddard & Wierzbicka 2002) is that word meaning is best described through the combination of a small set of elementary conceptual particles, known as *semantic primes*. Semantic primes are primitive (i.e., not decomposable into further conceptual parts), innate (i.e., not learned), and universal (i.e., explicitly lexicalized in all natural languages, whether in the form of a word, a morpheme, a phraseme, and so forth). According to NSM, the meaning of any word in any natural language can be defined by appropriately combining these fundamental conceptual particles. Wierzbicka (1996) proposed a catalogue of about 60 semantic primes, designed to analyze word meanings within so-called reductive paraphrases. For example, the reductive paraphrase for 'top' is a part of something; this part is above all the other parts of this something. NSM has produced interesting applications in comparative linguistics (Peeters 2006), language teaching (Goddard & Wierzbicka 2007), and lexical typology (Goddard 2012). However, the approach has been criticized on various grounds. First, it has been argued that the method followed by NSM in the identification of semantic primes is insufficiently clear (e.g., Matthewson 2003). Second, some have observed that reductive paraphrases are too vague to be considered adequate representations of word meanings, since they fail to account for fine-grained differences between semantically neighboring words. For example, the reductive paraphrase provided by Wierzbicka for 'sad' (i.e., *x* feels something; sometimes a person thinks something like this: something bad happened; if i didn't know that it happened i would say: i don't want it to happen; i don't say this now because i know: i can't do anything; because of this, this person feels something bad; *x* feels something like this) seems to apply equally well to 'unhappy', 'distressed', 'frustrated', 'upset', and 'annoyed' (e.g., Aitchison 2012). Third, there is no consensus on what items should ultimately feature in the list of semantic primes available to reductive paraphrases: the content of the list is debated and varies considerably between versions of NSM. Fourth, some purported semantic primes appear to fail to comply with the universality requirement and are not explicitly lexicalized in all known languages (Bohnemeyer 2003; Von Fintel & Matthewson 2008). See Goddard (1998) for some replies and Riemer (2006) for further objections. For NSM, word meanings can be exhaustively represented with a metalanguage appealing exclusively to the combination of primitive linguistic particles. Conceptual Semantics (Jackendoff 1983, 1990, 2002) proposes a more open-ended approach. According to Conceptual Semantics, word meanings are essentially an interface phenomenon between a specialized body of linguistic knowledge (e.g., morphosyntactic knowledge) and core non-linguistic cognition. Word meanings are thus modeled as hybrid semantic representations combining linguistic features (e.g., syntactic tags) and conceptual elements grounded in perceptual knowledge and motor schemas. For example, here is the semantic representation of 'drink' according to Jackendoff. \[\left[ \begin{align\*} &\text{drink} \\ &\mathrm{V} \\ &\underline{\phantom{xxxi}}\langle \text{NP}\_j \rangle \\ &[\_{\text{Event}} \text{CAUSE} ([\_{\text{Thing}}\quad]\_i, [\_{\text{Event}} \text{GO} ([\_{\text{Thing}} \text{LIQUID}]\_j, \\ &\quad [\_{\text{Path}} \text{TO} ([\_{\text{Place}} \text{IN} ([\_{\text{Thing}} \text{MOUTH OF} ([\_{\text{Thing}}\quad]\_i)])])])])] \end{align\*} \right]\] Syntactic tags represent the grammatical properties of the word under analysis, while the items in subscript are picked from a core set of perceptually grounded primitives (e.g., event, state, thing, path, place, property, amount) which are assumed to be innate, cross-modal and universal categories of the human mind. The decompositional machinery of Conceptual Semantics has a number of attractive features. Most notably, its representations take into account grammatical class and word-level syntax, which are plausibly an integral aspect of our knowledge of the meaning of words. However, some of its claims about the interplay between language and conceptual structure appear more problematic. To begin with, it has been observed that speakers tend to use causative predicates (e.g., 'drink') and the paraphrases expressing their decompositional structure (e.g., "cause a liquid to go into someone or something's mouth") in different and sometimes non-interchangeable ways (e.g., Wolff 2003), which raises concerns about the hypothesis that decompositional analyses a la Jackendoff may be regarded as faithful representations of word meanings. In addition, Conceptual Semantics is somewhat unclear as to what exact method should be followed in the identification of the motor-perceptual primitives that can feed descriptions of word meanings (Pulman 2005). Finally, the restriction placed by Conceptual Semantics on the type of conceptual material that can inform definitions of word meaning (low-level primitives grounded in perceptual knowledge and motor schemas) appears to affect the explanatory power of the framework. For example, how can one account for the difference in meaning between 'jog' and 'run' without ut taking into account higher-level, arguably non-perceptual knowledge about the social characteristics of jogging, which typically implies a certain leisure setting, the intention to contribute to physical wellbeing, and so on? See Taylor (1996), Deane (1996). The neat dividing line drawn between word meanings and general world knowledge by Conceptual Semantics does not tell us much about the dynamic interaction of the two in language use. The Two-Level Semantics of Bierwisch (1983a,b) and Lang (Bierwisch & Lang 1989; Lang 1993) aims to provide such a dynamic account. Two-Level Semantics views word meaning as the result of the interaction between two systems: *semantic form* (SF) and *conceptual structure* (CS). SF is a formalized representation of the basic features of a word. It contains grammatical information that specifies, e.g., the admissible syntactic distribution of the word, plus a set of variables and semantic parameters whose value is determined by the interaction with CS. By contrast, CS consists of language-independent systems of knowledge (including general world knowledge) that mediate between language and the world (Lang & Maienborn 2011). According to Two-Level Semantics, for example, polysemous words can express variable meanings by virtue of having a stable underspecified SF which can be flexibly manipulated by CS. By way of example, consider the word 'university', which can be read as referring either to an institution (as in "the university selected John's application") or to a building (as in "the university is located on the North side of the river"). Simplifying a bit, Two-Level Semantics explains the dynamics governing the selection of these readings as follows. 1. Because 'university' belongs to the category of words denoting objects primarily characterized by their purpose, the general lexical entry for 'university' is \(\lambda x [\textrm{purpose} [x w]]\). 2. Based on our knowledge that the primary purpose of universities is to provide advanced education, the SF of 'university' is specified as \(\lambda x [\textrm{purpose} [x w] \mathbin{\&} \textit{advanced study and teaching} [w]]\). 3. The alternative readings of 'university' are a function of the two ways CS can set the value of the variable x in its SF, such ways being \(\lambda x [\textrm{institution} [x] \mathbin{\&} \textrm{purpose} [x w]]\) and \(\lambda x [\textrm{building} [x] \mathbin{\&} \textrm{purpose} [x w]]\). Two-Level Semantics shares Jackendoff's and Wierzbicka's commitment to a descriptive paradigm that anchors word meaning to a stable decompositional template, all the while avoiding the immediate complications arising from a restrictive characterization of the type of conceptual factors that can modulate such stable decompositional templates in contexts. But there are, once again, a few significant issues. A first problem is definitional accuracy: defining the SF of 'university' as \(\lambda x [\textrm{purpose} [x w] \mathbin{\&} \textit{advanced study and teaching} [w]]\) seems too loose to reflect the subtle differences in meaning among 'university' and related terms designating institutions for higher education, such as 'college' or 'academy'. Furthermore, the apparatus of Two-Level Semantics relies heavily on lambda expressions, which, as some commentators have noted (e.g., Taylor 1994, 1995), appears ill-suited to represent the complex forms of world knowledge we often rely on to fix the meaning of highly polysemous words. See also Wunderlich (1991, 1993). The Generative Lexicon theory (GL; Pustejovsky 1995) takes a different approach. Instead of explaining the contextual flexibility of word meaning by appealing to rich conceptual operations applied on semantically thin lexical entries, this approach postulates lexical entries rich in conceptual information and knowledge of worldly facts. According to classical GL, the informational resources encoded in the lexical entry for a typical word *w* consist of the following four levels. * A *lexical typing structure*, specifying the semantic type of *w* within the type system of the language; * An *argument structure*, representing the number and nature of the arguments supported by *w*; * An *event structure*, defining the event type denoted by *w* (e.g., state, process, transition); * A *qualia structure*, specifying the predicative force of *w*. In particular, qualia structure specifies the conceptual relations that speakers associate to the real-world referents of a word and impact on the way the word is used in the language (Pustejovsky 1998). For example, our knowledge that bread is something that is brought about through baking is considered a Quale of the word 'bread', and this knowledge is responsible for our understanding that, e.g., "fresh bread" means "bread which has been baked recently". GL distinguishes four types of qualia: * constitutive: the relation between an object *x* and its constituent parts; * formal: the basic ontological category of *x*; * telic: the purpose and the function of *x*; * agentive: the factors involved in the origin of *x*. Take together, these qualia form the "qualia structure" of a word. For example, the qualia structure of the noun 'sandwich' will feature information about the composition of sandwiches, their nature of physical artifacts, their being intended to be eaten, and our knowledge about the operations typically involved in the preparation of sandwiches. The notation is as follows. *sandwich*(*x*) const = {bread, ...} form = physobj(*x*) tel = eat(P, *g*, *x*) agent = artifact(*x*) Qualia structure is the primary explanatory device by which GL accounts for polysemy. The sentence "Mary finished the sandwich" receives the default interpretation "Mary finished *eating* the sandwich" because the argument structure of 'finish' requires an action as direct object, and the qualia structure of 'sandwich' allows the generation of the appropriate sense via type coercion (Pustejovsky 2006). GL is an ongoing research program (Pustejovsky et al. 2012) that has led to significant applications in computational linguistics (e.g., Pustejovsky & Jezek 2008; Pustejovsky & Rumshisky 2008). But like the theories mentioned so far, it has been subject to criticisms. A first general criticism is that the decompositional assumptions underlying GL are unwarranted and should be replaced by an atomist view of word meaning (Fodor & Lepore 1998; see Pustejovsky 1998 for a reply). A second criticism is that GL's focus on variations in word meaning which depend on sentential context and qualia structure is too narrow, since since contextual variations in word meaning often depend on more complex factors, such as the ability to keep track of coherence relations in a discourse (e.g., Asher & Lascarides 1995; Lascarides & Copestake 1998; Kehler 2002; Asher 2011). Finally, the empirical adequacy of the framework has been called into question. It has been argued that the formal apparatus of GL leads to incorrect predictions, that qualia structure sometimes overgenerates or undergenerates interpretations, and that the rich lexical entries postulated by GL are psychologically implausible (e.g., Jayez 2001; Blutner 2002). ### 4.4 Relational Approaches To conclude this section, we will briefly mention some contemporary approaches to word meaning that, in different ways, pursue the theoretical agenda of the relational current of the structuralist paradigm. For pedagogical convenience, we can group them into two categories. On the one hand, we have *network* approaches, which formalize knowledge of word meaning within models where the lexicon is seen as a structured system of entries interconnected by sense relations such as synonymy, antonymy, and meronymy. On the other, we have *statistical* approaches, whose primary aim is to investigate the patterns of co-occurrence among words in linguistic corpora. The main example of network approaches is perhaps Collins and Quillian's (1969) hierarchical network model, in which words are represented as entries in a network of nodes, each comprising a set of conceptual features defining the conventional meaning of the word in question, and connected to other nodes in the network through semantic relations (more in Lehman 1992). Subsequent developments of the hierarchical network model include the Semantic Feature Model (Smith, Shoben & Rips 1974), the Spreading Activation Model (Collins & Loftus 1975; Bock & Levelt 1994), the WordNet database (Fellbaum 1998), as well as the connectionist models of Seidenberg & McClelland (1989), Hinton & Shallice (1991), and Plaut & Shallice (1993). More on this in the entry on connectionism. Finally, statistical analysis investigates word meaning by examining through computational means the distribution of words in linguistic corpora. The main idea is to use quantitative data about the frequency of co-occurrence of sets of lexical items to identify their semantic properties and differentiate their different senses (for overviews, see Atkins & Zampolli 1994; Manning & Schutze 1999; Stubbs 2002; Sinclair 2004). Notice that while symbolic networks are models of the architecture of the lexicon that seek to be psychologically adequate (i.e., to reveal how knowledge of word meaning is stored and organized in the mind/brain of human speakers), statistical approaches to word meaning are not necessarily interested in psychological adequacy, and may have completely different goals, such as building a machine translation service able to mimic human performance (a goal that can obviously be achieved without reproducing the cognitive mechanisms underlying translation in humans). More on this in the entry on computational linguistics. ## 5. Cognitive Science As we have seen, most theories of word meaning in linguistics face, at some point, the difficulties involved in drawing a plausible dividing line between word knowledge and world knowledge, and the various ways they attempt to meet this challenge display some recurrent features. For example, they assume that the lexicon, though richly interfaced with world knowledge and non-linguistic cognition, remains an autonomous representational system encoding a specialized body of linguistic knowledge. In this section, we survey a group of empirical approaches that adopt a different stance on word meaning. The focus is once again psychological, which means that the overall goal of these approaches is to provide a cognitively realistic account of the representational repertoire underlying knowledge of word meaning. Unlike the approaches surveyed in Section 4, however, these theories tend to encourage a view on which the distinction between the semantic and pragmatic aspects of word meaning is highly unstable (or even impossible to draw), where lexical knowledge and knowledge of worldly facts are aspects of a continuum, and where the lexicon is permeated by our general inferential abilities (Evans 2010). Section 5.1 will briefly illustrate the central assumptions underlying the study of word meaning in cognitive linguistics. Section 5.2 will turn to the study of word meaning in psycholinguistics. Section 5.3 will conclude with some references to neurolinguistics. ### 5.1 Cognitive Linguistics At the beginning of the 1970s, Eleanor Rosch put forth a new theory of the mental representation of categories. Concepts such as furniture or bird, she claimed, are not represented just as sets of criterial features with clear-cut boundaries, so that an item can be conceived as falling or not falling under the concept based on whether or not it meets the relevant criteria. Rather, items within categories can be considered more or less representative of the category itself (Rosch 1975; Rosch & Mervis 1975; Mervis & Rosch 1981). Several experiments seemed to show that the application of concepts is no simple yes-or-no business: some items (the "good examples") are more easily identified as falling under a concept than others (the "poor examples"). An automobile is perceived as a better example of vehicle than a rowboat, and much better than an elevator; a carrot is more readily identified as an example of the concept vegetable than a pumpkin. If the concepts speakers associate to category words (such as 'vehicle' and 'vegetable') were mere bundles of criterial features, these preferences would be inexplicable, since they rank items that meet the criteria equally well. It is thus plausible to assume that the concepts associated to category words are have a center-periphery architecture centered on the most representative examples of the category: a robin is perceived as a more "birdish" bird than an ostrich or, as people would say, closer to the *prototype* of a bird or to the *prototypical* bird (see the entry on concepts). Although nothing in Rosch's experiments licensed the conclusion that prototypical rankings should be reified and treated as the content of concepts (what her experiments did support was merely that a theory of the mental representation of categories should be consistent with the existence of prototype *effects*), the study of prototypes revolutionized the existing approaches to category concepts (Murphy 2002) and was a leading force behind the birth of cognitive linguistics. Prototypes were central to the development of the Radial Network Theory of Brugman (1988 [1981]) and Lakoff (Brugman & Lakoff 1988), which proposed to model the sense network of words by introducing in the architecture of word meanings the center-periphery relation at the heart of Rosch's seminal work. According to Brugman, word meanings can typically be modeled as radial complexes where a dominant sense is related to less typical senses by means of semantic relations such as metaphor and metonymy. For example, the sense network of 'fruit' features product of plant growth at its center and a more abstract outcome at its periphery, and the two are connected by a metaphorical relation). On a similar note, the Conceptual Metaphor Theory of Lakoff & Johnson (1980; Lakoff 1987) and the Mental Spaces Approach of Fauconnier (1994; Fauconnier & Turner 1998) combined the assumption that word meanings typically have an internal structure arranging multiple related senses in a radial fashion, with the further claim that our use of words is governed by hard-wired mapping mechanisms that catalyze the integration of word meanings across conceptual domains. For example, it is in virtue of these mechanisms that the expressions "love is war", "life is a journey") are so widespread across cultures and sound so natural to our ears. On the proposed view, these associations are creative, perceptually grounded, systematic, cross-culturally uniform, and grounded on pre-linguistic patterns of conceptual activity which correlate with core elements of human embodied experience (see the entries on metaphor and embodied cognition). More in Kovecses (2002), Gibbs (2008), and Dancygier & Sweetser (2014). Another major innovation introduced by cognitive linguistics is the development of a resolutely "encyclopedic" approach to word meaning, best exemplified by Frame Semantics (Fillmore 1975, 1982) and by the Theory of Domains (Langacker 1987). Approximating a bit, an approach to word meaning can be defined "encyclopedic" insofar as it characterizes knowledge of worldly facts as the primary constitutive force of word meaning. While the Mental Spaces Approach and Conceptual Metaphor Theory regarded word meaning mainly as the product of associative patterns between concepts, Fillmore and Langacker turned their attention to the relation between word meaning and the body of encyclopedic knowledge possessed by typical speakers. Our ability to use and interpret the verb 'buy', for example, is closely intertwined with our background knowledge of the social nature of commercial transfer, which involves a seller, a buyer, goods, money, the relation between the money and the goods, and so forth. However, knowledge structures of this kind cannot be modeled as standard concept-like representations. Here is how Frame Semantics attempts to meet the challenge. First, words are construed as pairs of phonographic forms with highly schematic concepts which are internally organized as radial categories and function as access sites to encyclopedic knowledge. Second, an account of the representational organization of encyclopedic knowledge is provided. According to Fillmore, encyclopedic knowledge is represented in long-term memory in the form of *frames*, i.e., schematic conceptual scenarios that specify the prototypical features and functions of a denotatum, along with its interactions with the objects and the events typically associated with it. Frames provide thus a schematic representation of the elements and entities associated with a particular domain of experience and convey the information required to use and interpret the words employed to talk about it. For example, according to Fillmore & Atkins (1992) the use of the verb 'bet' is governed by the risk frame, which is as follows: | | | | --- | --- | | *Protagonist*: | The central agent in the frame. | | *Bad*: | The possible bad outcome. | | *Decision*: | The decision that could trigger the bad outcome. | | *Goal*: | The desired outcome. | | *Setting*: | The situation within which the risk exists. | | *Possession*: | Something valued by the protagonist and endangered in the situation. | | *Source*: | Something or someone which could cause the harm. | In the same vein as Frame Semantics (more on the parallels in Clausner & Croft 1999), Langacker's Theory of Domains argues that our understanding of word meaning depends on our access to larger knowledge structures called *domains*. To illustrate the notion of a domain, consider the word 'diameter'. The meaning of this word cannot be grasped independently of a prior understanding of the notion of a circle. According to Langacker, word meaning is precisely a matter of "profile-domain" organization: the profile corresponds to a substructural element designated within a relevant macrostructure, whereas the domain corresponds to the macrostructure providing the background information against which the profile can be interpreted (Taylor 2002). In the diameter/circle example, 'diameter' designates a profile in the circle domain. Similarly, expressions like 'hot', 'cold', and 'warm' designate properties in the temperature domain. Langacker argues that domains are typically structured into hierarchies that reflect meronymic relations and provide a basic conceptual ontology for language use. For example, the meaning of 'elbow' is understood with respect to the arm domain, while the meaning of 'arm' is situated within the body domain. Importantly, individual profiles typically inhere to different domains, and this is one of the factors responsible for the ubiquity of polysemy in natural language. For example, the profile associated to the word 'love' inheres both to the domains of embodied experience and to the abstract domains of social activities such as marriage ceremonies. Developments of the approach to word meaning fostered by cognitive linguistics include Construction Grammar (Goldberg 1995), Embodied Construction Grammar (Bergen & Chang 2005), Invited Inferencing Theory (Traugott & Dasher 2001), and LCCM Theory (Evans 2009). The notion of a frame has become popular in cognitive psychology to model the dynamics of *ad hoc* categorization (e.g., Barsalou 1983, 1992, 1999; more in Section 5.2). General information about the study of word meaning in cognitive linguistics can be found in Talmy (2000a,b), Croft & Cruse (2004), and Evans & Green (2006). ### 5.2 Psycholinguistics In psycholinguistics, the study of word meaning is understood as the investigation of the *mental lexicon*, the cognitive system that underlies the capacity for conscious and unconscious lexical activity (Jarema & Libben 2007). Simply put, the mental lexicon is the long-term representational inventory storing the body of linguistic knowledge speakers are required to master in order to make competent use of the lexical elements of a language; as such, it can be equated with the lexical component of an individual's language capacity. Research on the mental lexicon is concerned with a variety of problems (for surveys, see, e.g., Traxler & Gernsbacher 2006, Spivey, McRae & Joanisse 2012, Harley 2014), that center around the following tasks: * Define the overall organization of the mental lexicon, specify its components and clarify the role played by such components in lexical production and comprehension; * Determine the internal makeup of single components and the way the information they store is brought to bear on lexical performance; * Describe the interface mechanisms connecting the mental lexicon to other domains in the human cognitive architecture (e.g., declarative memory); * Illustrate the learning processes responsible for the acquisition and the development of lexical abilities. From a functional point of view, the mental lexicon is usually understood as a system of *lexical entries*, each containing the information related to a word mastered by a speaker (Rapp 2001). A lexical entry for a word *w* is typically modeled as a complex representation made up of the following components (Levelt 1989, 2001): * A *semantic form*, determining the semantic contribution made by *w* to the meaning of sentences containing *w*; * A *grammatical form*, assigning *w* to a grammatical category (noun, verb, adjective) and regulating the behavior of *w* in syntactic environments; * A *morphological form*, representing the morphemic substructure of *w* and the morphological operations that can be applied on *w*; * A *phonological form*, specifying the set of phonological properties of *w*; * An *orthographic form*, specifying the graphic structure of *w*. From this standpoint, a theory of word meaning translates into an account of the information stored in the semantic form of lexical entries. A crucial part of the task consists in determining exactly what kind of information is stored in lexical semantic forms as opposed to, e.g., bits of information that fall under the scope of episodic memory or general factual knowledge. Recall the example we made in Section 3.3: how much of the information that a competent zoologist can associate to tigers is part of her knowledge of the meaning of the word 'tiger'? Not surprisingly, even in psycholinguistics tracing a neat functional separation between word processing and general-purpose cognition has proven a problematic task. The general consensus among psycholinguists seems to be that lexical representations and conceptual representations are richly interfaced, though functionally distinct (e.g., Gleitman & Papafragou 2013). For example, in clinical research it is standard practice to distinguish between *amodal* deficits involving an inability to process information at both the conceptual and the lexical level, and *modal* deficits specifically restricted to one of the two spheres (Saffran & Schwartz 1994; Rapp & Goldrick 2006; Jefferies & Lambon Ralph 2006; more in more in Section 5.3). On the resulting view, lexical activity in humans is the output of the interaction between two functionally neighboring systems, one broadly in charge of the storage and processing of conceptual-encyclopedic knowledge, the other coinciding with the mental lexicon. The role of lexical entries is essentially to make these two systems communicate with one another through semantic forms (see Denes 2009). Contrary to the folk notion of a mental lexicon where words are associated to fully specified meanings or senses which are simply retrieved from the lexicon for the purpose of language processing, in these models lexical semantic forms are seen as highly schematic representations whose primary function is to supervise the recruitment of the extra-linguistic information required to interpret word occurrences in language use. In recent years, appeals to "ultra-thin" lexical entries have taken an eliminativist turn. It has been suggested that psycholinguistic accounts of the representational underpinnigs of lexical competence should dispose of the largely metaphorical notion of an "internal word store", and there is no such thing as a mental lexicon in the human mind (e.g., Elman 2004, 2009; Dilkina, McClelland & Plaut 2010). In addition to these approaches, in a number of prominent psychological accounts emerged over the last two decades, the study of word meaning is essentially considered a chapter of theories of the mental realization of concepts (see the entry on concepts). Lexical units are seen either as ingredients of conceptual networks or as (auditory or visual) stimuli providing access to conceptual networks. A flow of neuroscientific results has shown that understanding of (certain categories of) words correlates with neural activations corresponding to the semantic content of the processed words. For example, it has been shown that listening to sentences that describe actions performed with the mouth, hand, or leg activates the visuomotor circuits which subserve execution and observation of such actions (Tettamanti et al. 2005); that reading words denoting specific actions of the tongue ('lick'), fingers ('pick'), and leg ('kick') differentially activate areas of the premotor cortex that are active when the corresponding movements are actually performed (Hauk et al. 2004); that reading odor-related words ('jasmine', 'garlic', 'cinnamon') differentially activates the primary olfactory cortex (Gonzales et al. 2006); and that color words (such as 'red') activate areas in the fusiform gyrus that have been associated with color perception (Chao et al. 1999, Simmons et al. 2007; for a survey of results on visual activations in language processing, see Martin 2007). This body of research originated so-called *simulationist* (or *enactivist*) accounts of conceptual competence, on which "understanding is imagination" and "imagining is a form of simulation" (Gallese & Lakoff 2005). In these accounts, conceptual (often called "semantic") competence is seen as the ability to simulate or re-enact perceptual (including proprioceptive and introspective) experiences of the states of affairs that language describes, by manipulating memory traces of such experiences or fragments of them. In Barsalou's theory of perceptual symbol systems (1999), language understanding (and cognition in general) is based on perceptual experience and memory of it. The central claim is that "sensory-motor systems represent not only perceived entities but also conceptualizations of them in their absence". Perception generates mostly unconscious "neural representations in sensory-motor areas of the brain", which represent schematic components of perceptual experience. Such perceptual symbols are not holistic copies of experiences but selections of information isolated by attention. Related perceptual symbols are integrated into a *simulator* that produces limitless simulations of a perceptual component, such as *red* or *lift*. Simulators are located in long-term memory and play the roles traditionally attributed to concepts: they generate inferences and can be combined recursively to implement productivity. A concept is not "a static amodal structure" as in traditional, computationally-oriented cognitive science, but "the ability to simulate a kind of thing perceptually". Linguistic symbols (i.e., auditory or visual memories of words) get to be associated with simulators; perceptual recognition of a word activates the relevant simulator, which simulates a referent for the word; syntax provides instructions for building integrated perceptual simulations, which "constitute semantic interpretations". Though popular among researchers interested in the conceptual underpinnings of semantic competence, the simulationist paradigm faces important challenges. Three are worth mentioning. First, it appears that imulations do not always capture the intuitive truth conditions of sentences: listeners may enact the same simulation upon exposure to sentences that have different truth conditions (e.g., "The man stood on the corner" vs. "The man waited on the corner"; see Weiskopf 2010). Moreover, simulations may overconstrain truth conditions. For example, even though in the simulations listeners typically associate to the sentence "There are three pencils and four pens in Anna's mug", the pens and the pencils are in vertical position, the sentence would be true even if they were lying horizontally in the mug. Second, the framework does not sit well with pathological data. For example, no general impairment with auditory-related words is reported in patients with lesions in the auditory association cortex (e.g., auditory agnosia patients); analogously, patients with damage to the motor cortex seem to have no difficulties in linguistic performance, and specifically in inferential processing with motor-related words (for a survey of these results, see Calzavarini, to appear; for a defense of the embodied paradigm, Pulvermuller 2013). Finally, the theory has difficulties accounting for the meaning of abstract words (e.g., 'beauty', 'pride', 'kindness'), which does not appear to hinge on sensory-motor simulation (see Dove 2016 for a discussion). ### 5.3 Neurolinguistics Beginning in the mid-1970s, neuropsychological research on cognitive deficits related to brain lesions has produced a considerable amount of findings related to the neural correlates of lexical semantic information and processing. More recently, the development of neuroimaging techniques such as PET, fMRI and ERP has provided further means to adjudicate hypotheses about lexical semantic processes in the brain (Vigneau et al. 2006). Here we do not intend to provide a complete overview of such results (for a survey, see Faust 2012). We shall just mention three topics of neurolinguistic research that appear to bear on issues in the study of word meaning: the partition of the lexicon into categories, the representation of common nouns vs. proper names, and the distinction between the inferential and the referential aspects of lexical competence. Two preliminary considerations should be kept in mind. First, a distinction must be drawn between the neural realization of word forms, i.e., traces of acoustic, articulatory, graphic, and motor configurations ('peripheral lexicons'), and the neural correlates of lexical meanings ('concepts'). A patient can understand what is the object represented by a picture shown to her (and give evidence of her understanding, e.g., by miming the object's function) while being unable to retrieve the relevant phonological form from her output lexicon (Warrington 1985; Shallice 1988). Second, there appears to be wide consensus about the irrelevance to brain processing of any distinction between strictly semantic and factual or encyclopedic information (e.g., Tulving 1972; Sartori et al. 1994). Whatever information is relevant to such processes as object recognition or confrontation naming is standardly characterized as 'semantic'. This may be taken as a stipulation--it is just how neuroscientists use the word 'semantic'--or as deriving from lack of evidence for any segregation between the domains of semantic and encyclopedic information (see Binder et al. 2009). Be that as it may, in present-day neuroscience there seems to be no room for a correlate of the analytic/synthetic distinction. Moreover, in the literature 'semantic' and 'conceptual' are often used synonymously; hence, no distinction is drawn between lexical semantic and conceptual knowledge. Finally, the focus of neuroscientific research on "semantics" is on information structures roughly corresponding to word-level meanings, not to sentence-level meanings: hence, so far neuroscientific research has had little to say about the compositional mechanisms that have been the focus (and, often, the entire content) of theories of meaning as pursued within formal semantics and philosophy of language. Let us start with the partition of the semantic lexicon into categories. Neuropsychological research indicates that the ability to name objects or to answer simple questions involving such nouns can be selectively lost or preserved: subjects can perform much better in naming living entities than in naming artifacts, or in naming animate living entities than in naming fruits and vegetables (Shallice 1988). Different patterns of brain activation may correspond to such dissociations between performances: e.g., Damasio et al. (1996) found that retrieval of names of animals and of tools activate different regions in the left temporal lobe. However, the details of this partition have been interpreted in different ways. Warrington & McCarthy (1983) and Warrington & Shallice (1984) explained the living vs. artifactual dissociation by taking the category distinction to be an effect of the difference among features that are crucial in the identification of living entities and artifacts: while living entities are identified mainly on the basis of perceptual features, artifacts are identified by their function. A later theory (Caramazza & Shelton 1998) claimed that animate and inanimate objects are treated by different knowledge systems separated by evolutionary pressure: domains of features pertaining to the recognition of living things, human faces, and perhaps tools may have been singled out as recognition of such entities had survival value for humans. Finally, Devlin et al. (1998) proposed to view the partition as the consequence of a difference in how recognition-relevant features are connected with one another: in the case of artifactual kinds, an object is recognized thanks to a characteristic coupling of form and function, whereas no such coupling individuates kinds of living things (e.g., eyes go with seeing in many animal species). For non-neutral surveys, see Caramazza & Mahon (2006) and Shallice & Cooper (2011). On the other hand, it is also known that "semantic" (i.e., conceptual) competence may be lost in its entirety (though often gradually). This is what typically happens in semantic dementia. Empirical evidence has motivated theories of the neural realization of conceptual competence that are meant to account for both modality-specific deficits and pathologies that involve impairment across all modalities. The former may involve a difficulty or impossibility to categorize a visually exhibited object which, however, can be correctly categorized in other modalities (e.g., if the object is touched) or verbally described on the basis of the object's name (i.e., on the basis of the lexical item supposedly associated with the category). The original "hub and spokes" model of the brain representation of concepts (Rogers et al. 2004, Patterson et al. 2007) accounted for both sets of findings by postulating that the semantic network is composed of a series of "spokes", i.e., cortical areas distributed across the brain processing modality-specific (visual, auditory, motor, as well as verbal) sources of information, and that the spokes are two-ways connected to a transmodal "hub". While damage to the spokes accounts for modality-specific deficits, damage to the hub and its connections explains the overall impairment of semantic competence. On this model, the hub is supposed to be located in the anterior temporal lobe (ATL), since semantic dementia had been found to be associated with degeneration of the anterior ventral and polar regions of both temporal poles (Guo et al. 2013). According to more recent, "graded" versions of the model (Lambon Ralph et al. 2017), the contribution of the hub units may vary depending on different patterns of connectivity to the spokes, to account for evidence of graded variation of function across subregions of ATL. It should be noted that while many researchers converge on a distributed view of semantic representation and on the role of domain-specific parts of the neural network (depending on differential patterns of functional connectivity), not everybody agrees on the need to postulate a transmodal hub (see, e.g., Mahon & Caramazza 2011). Let us now turn to common nouns and proper names. As we have seen, in the philosophy of language of the last decades, proper names (of people, landmarks, countries, etc.) have being regarded as semantically different from common nouns. Neuroscientific research on the processing of proper names and common nouns concurs, to some extent. To begin with, the retrieval of proper names is doubly dissociated from the retrieval of common nouns. Some patients proved competent with common nouns but unable to associate names to pictures of famous people, or buildings, or brands (Ellis, Young & Critchley 1989); in other cases, people's names were specifically affected (McKenna & Warrington 1980). Other patients had the complementary deficit. The patient described in Semenza & Sgaramella (1993) could name no objects at all (with or without phonemic cues) but he was able to name 10 out of 10 familiar people, and 18 out of 22 famous people with a phonemic cue. Martins & Farrayota's (2007) patient ACB also presented impaired object naming but spared retrieval of proper names. Such findings suggest distinct neural pathways for the retrieval of proper names and common nouns (Semenza 2006). The study of lesions and neuroimaging research both initially converged in identifying the left temporal pole as playing a crucial role in the retrieval of proper names, from both visual stimuli (Damasio et al. 1996) and the presentation of speaker voices (Waldron et al. 2014) (though in at least one case damage to the left temporal pole was associated with selective sparing of proper names; see Martins & Farrajota 2007). In addition, recent research has found a role for the uncinate fasciculus (UF). In patients undergoing surgical removal of UF, retrieval of common nouns was recovered while retrieval of proper names remained impaired (Papagno et al. 2016). The present consensus appears to be that "the production of proper names recruits a network that involves at least the left anterior temporal lobe and the left orbitofrontal cortex connected together by the UF" (Bredart 2017). Furthermore, a few neuropsychological studies have described patients whose competence on geographical names was preserved while names of people were lost: one patient had preserved country names, though he had lost virtually every other linguistic ability (McKenna & Warrington 1978; see Semenza 2006 for other cases of selective preservation of geographical names). Other behavioral experiments seem to show that country names are closer to common nouns than to other proper names such as people and landmark names in that the connectivity between the word and the conceptual system is likely to require diffuse multiple connections, as with common nouns (Hollis & Valentine 2001). If these results were confirmed, it would turn out that the linguistic category of proper names is not homogeneous in terms of neural processing. Studies have also demonstrated that the retrieval of proper names from memory is typically a more difficult cognitive task than the retrieval of common nouns. For example, it is harder to name faces (of famous people) than to name objects; moreover, it is easier to remember a person's occupation than her or his name. Interestingly, the same difference does not materialize in definition naming, i.e., in tasks where names and common nouns are to be retrieved from definitions (Hanley 2011). Though several hypotheses about the source of this difference have been proposed (see Bredart 2017 for a survey), no consensus has been reached on how to explain this phenomenon. Finally, a few words on the distinction between the inferential and the referential component of lexical competence. As we have seen in Section 3.2, Marconi (1997) suggested that processing of lexical meaning might be distributed between two subsystems, an inferential and a referential one. Beginning with Warrington (1975), many patients had been described that were more or less severely impaired in referential tasks such as naming from vision (and other perceptual modalities as well), while their inferential competence was more or less intact. The complementary pattern (i.e., the preservation of referential abilities with loss of inferential competence) is definitely less common. Still, a number of cases have been reported, beginning with a stroke patient of Heilman et al. (1976), who, while unable to perform any task requiring inferential processing, performed well in referential naming tasks with visually presented objects (he could name 23 of 25 common objects). In subsequent years, further cases were described. For example, in a study of 61 patients with lesions affecting linguistic abilities, Kemmerer et al. (2012) found 14 cases in which referential abilities were better preserved than inferential abilities. More recently, Pandey & Heilman (2014), while describing one more case of preserved (referential) naming from vision with severely impaired (inferential) naming from definition, hypothesized that "these two naming tasks may, at least in part, be mediated by two independent neuronal networks". Thus, while double dissociation between inferential processes and naming from vision is well attested, it is not equally clear that it involves referential processes in general. On the other hand, evidence from neuroimaging is, so far, limited and overall inconclusive. Some neuroimaging studies (e.g., Tomaszewski-Farias et al. 2005, Marconi et al. 2013), as well as TMS mapping experiments (Hamberger et al. 2001, Hamberger & Seidel 2009) did find different patterns of activation for inferential vs. referential performances. However, the results are not entirely consistent and are liable to different interpretations. For example, the selective activation of the anterior left temporal lobe in inferential performances may well reflect additional syntactic demands involved in definition naming, rather than be due to inferential processing as such (see Calzavarini 2017 for a discussion).
work-labor
## 1. Conceptual Distinctions: Work, Labor, Employment, Leisure It is not difficult to enumerate examples of work. Hence, Samuel Clark: > > by *work* I mean the familiar things we do in fields, > factories, offices, schools, shops, building sites, call centres, > homes, and so on, to make a life and a living. Examples of work in our > commercial society include driving a taxi, selling washing machines, > managing a group of software developers, running a till in a > supermarket, attaching screens to smartphones on an assembly line, > fielding customer complaints in a call centre, and teaching in a > school (Clark 2017: 62). > Some contemporary commentators have observed that human life is increasingly understood in work-like terms: parenthood is often described as a job, those with romantic difficulties are invited to 'work on' their relationships, those suffering from the deaths of others are advised to undertake 'grief work,' and what was once exercise is now 'working out' (Malesic 2017). The diversity of undertakings we designate as 'work', and the apparent dissimilarities among them, have led some philosophers to conclude that work resists any definition (Muirhead 2007: 4, Svendsen 2015) or is at best a loose concept in which different instances of work share a 'family resemblance' (Pence 2001: 96-97). The porousness of the notion of work notwithstanding, some progress in defining work seems possible by first considering the variety of ways in which work is organized. For one, although many contemporary discussions of work focus primarily on *employment*, not all work takes the form of employment. It is therefore important not to assimilate work to employment, because not every philosophically interesting claim that is true of employment is true of work as such, and vice versa. In an employment relationship, an individual worker sells their labor to another in exchange for compensation (usually money), with the purchaser of their labor serving as a kind of intermediary between the worker and those who ultimately enjoy the goods that the worker helps to produce (consumers). The intermediary, the *employer*, typically serves to manage (or appoints those who manage) the hired workers -- the employees--, setting most of the terms of what goods are thereby to be produced, how the process of production will be organized, etc. Such an arrangement is what we typically understand as having a *job*. But a worker can produce goods without their production being mediated in this way. In some cases, a worker is a *proprietor*, someone who owns the enterprise as well as participating in the production of the goods produced by that enterprise (for example, a restaurant owner who is also its head chef). This arrangement may also be termed *self-employment*, and differs from arrangements in which proprietors are not workers in the enterprise but merely capitalize it or invest in it. And some proprietors are also employers, that is, they hire other workers to contribute their labor to the process of production. Arguably, entrepreneurship or self-employment, rather than having a job, has been the predominant form of work throughout human history, and it continues to be prevalent. Over half of all workers are self-employed in parts of the world such as Africa and South Asia, and the number of self-employed individuals has been rising in many regions of the globe (International Labor Organization 2019). In contrast, jobs -- more or less permanent employment relationships -- are more a byproduct of industrial modernity than we realise (Suzman 2021). Employees and proprietors are most often in a transactional relationship with consumers; they produce goods that consumers buy using their income. But this need not be the case. Physicians at a 'free clinic' are not paid by their patients but by a government agency, charity, etc. Nevertheless, such employees expect to earn income from their work from some source. But some instances of work go unpaid or uncompensated altogether. Slaves work, as do prisoners in some cases, but their work is often not compensated. So too for those who volunteer for charities or who provide unpaid *care work*, attending to the needs of children, the aged, or the ill. Thus, work need not involve working *for* others, nor need it be materially compensated. These observations are useful inasmuch as they indicate that certain conditions we might presume to be essential to work (being employed, being monetarily compensated) are not in fact essential to it. Still, these observations only inform as to what work is not. Can we say more exactly what work *is*? Part of the difficulty in defining work is that whether a person's actions constitute work seems to depend both on how her actions shape the world as well on the person's attitudes concerning those actions. On the one hand, the activity of work is causal in that it modifies the world in some non-accidental way. As Bertrand Russell (1932) remarked, "work is of two kinds: first, altering the position of matter at or near the earth's surface relatively to other such matter; second, telling other people to do so." But work involves altering the world in presumptively worthwhile ways. In this respect, work is closely tied to the production of what Raymond Geuss (2021:5) has called 'objective' value, value residing in "external" products that can be "measured and valued independently of anything one might know about the process through which that product came to be or the people who made it." By working, we generate goods (material objects but also experiences, states of mind, etc.) that others can value and enjoy in their own right. In most cases of work (for example, when employed), a person is compensated not for the performance of labor as such but because their labor contributes to the production of goods that have such 'objective' value. Note, however, that although work involves producing what others *can* enjoy or consume, sometimes the objective value resulting from work is not in fact enjoyed by others or by anyone at all. A self-sufficient farmer works by producing food solely for their own use, in which case the worker (rather than others) ends up consuming the objective value of their work. Likewise, the farmer who works to produce vegetables for market that ultimately go unsold has produced something whose objective value goes unconsumed. Geuss has suggested a further characteristic of work, that it is "necessary" for individuals and for "societies as a whole" (2021:18). Given current and historical patterns of human life, work has been necessary to meet human needs. However, if some prognostications about automation and artificial intelligence prove true (see section 4 on 'The Future of Work'), then the scarcity that has defined the human condition up to now may be eliminated, obviating the necessity of work at both the individual and societal level. Moreover, as Geuss observes, some work aims to produce goods that answer to human wants rather than human needs or necessities (that is, to produce luxuries), and some individuals manage to escape the necessity of work thanks to their antecedent wealth. Still, work appears to have as one of its essential features that it be an activity that increases the objective (or perhaps intersubjective) value in the world. Some human activities are therefore arguably not work because they generate value for the actor instead of for others. For instance, work stands in contrast to *leisure*. Leisure is not simply idleness or the absence of work, nor is it the absence of activity altogether (Pieper 1952, Walzer 1983: 184-87, Adorno 2001, Haney and Kline 2010). When at leisure, individuals engage in activities that produce goods for their own enjoyment largely indifferent to the objective value that these activities might generate for others. The goods resulting from a person's leisure are bound up with the fact that she generates them through her activity. We cannot hire others to sunbathe for us or enjoy a musical performance for us because the value of such leisure activities is contingent upon our performing the activities. Leisure thus produces subjective value that we 'make' for ourselves, value that (unlike the objective value generated from work) cannot be transferred to or exchanged with others. It might also be possible to create the objective value associated with working despite being at leisure. A professional athlete, for instance, might be motivated to play her sport as a form of leisure but produce (and be monetarily compensated for the production of) objective value for others (spectators who enjoy the sport). Perhaps such examples are instances of work *and* leisure or working *by way of* leisure. Some accounts of work emphasize not the nature of the value work produces but the individual's attitudes concerning work. For instance, many definitions of work emphasize that work is experienced as exertion or strain (Budd 2011:2, Veltman 2016:24-25, Geuss 2021: 9-13). Work, on this view, is inevitably *laborious.* No doubt work is often strenuous. But defining work in this way seems to rule out work that is sufficiently pleasurable to the worker as to hardly feel like a burden. An actor may so enjoy performing that it hardly feels like a strain at all. Nevertheless, the performance is work inasmuch as the actor must deliberately orient their activities to realize the objective value the performance may have for others. Her acting will not succeed in producing this objective value unless she is guided by a concern to produce the value by recalling and delivering her lines, etc. In fact, the actor may find performing pleasurable rather than a burden because she takes great satisfaction in producing this objective value for others. Other work involves little exertion of strain because it is nearly entirely passive; those who are paid subjects in medical research are compensated less for their active contribution to the research effort but simply "to endure" the investigative process and submit to the wills of others (Malmqvist 2019). Still, the research subject must also be deliberate in their participation, making sure to abide by protocols that ensure the validity of the research. Examples such as these suggest that a neglected dimension of work is that, in working, we are paradigmatically guided by the wills of others, for we are aiming in our work activities to generate goods that others could enjoy. ## 2. The Value of Work The proposed definition of work as the deliberate attempt to produce goods that others can enjoy or consume indicates where work's value to those besides the worker resides. And the value that work has to others need not be narrowly defined in terms of specific individuals enjoying or consuming the goods we produce. Within some religious traditions, work is way to serve God and or one's community. But these considerations do not shed much light on the first-personal value of work: What value does one's work have *to* workers? How do we benefit when we produce goods that others could enjoy? ### 2.1 The Goods of Work On perhaps the narrowest conception of work's value, it only has *exchange* value. On this conception, work's value is measured purely in terms of the material goods it generates for the worker, either in monetary terms or in terms of work's products (growing one's own vegetables, for instance). To view work as having exchange value is to see its value as wholly extrinsic; there is no value to work as such, only value to be gained from what one's work concretely produces. If work only has exchange value, then work is solely a cost or a burden, never worth doing for its own sake. Echoing the Biblical tale of humanity's fall, this conception of work's value casts it as a curse foisted upon us due to human limitations or inadequacies. But work is often valued for other reasons. One powerful bit of evidence in favour of work's being valued for reasons unrelated to its exchange value comes from studies of (involuntary) unemployment. Unemployment usually adverse economic effects on workers, inasmuch as it deprives them, at least temporarily, of income. But prolonged unemployment also has measurable negative effects on individuals' health, both physical and mental (Calvo et al 2015, Margerison-Zilko et al. 2016, Helliwell et al 2017), as well as being among the most stressful of live events. (Holmes and Rahe 1967). That being deprived of work is evidently so detrimental to individual well-being indicates that work matters for many beyond a paycheck. Many of the goods of work are linked to the fact that work is nearly always a social endeavour. As Cynthia Estlund (2003:7) observes, "the workplace is the single most important site of cooperative interaction and sociability among adult citizens outside the family." Individuals thus seek out many social goods through work. Gheaus and Herzog (2016) propose that in addition to providing us wages, work fulfills various social roles. For example, work is a primary means by which individuals can achieve a sense of community. In working with others, we can establish bonds that contribute to our sense of belonging and that enable us to contribute to a distinctive workplace culture. In a similar vein, communitarian theorists often argue that work, by embedding us in shared practices or traditions, is essential to social life (Walzer 1983, Breen 2007). MacIntyre (1984:187) defines a practice as a "any coherent and complex form of socially established cooperative activity through which goods internal to that form of activity are realised in the course of trying to achieve those standards of excellence which are appropriate to, and partially definitive of, that form of activity." Those working together in (say) a bakery are cooperating to produce the goods internal to that activity (bread), with the result that they extend their capacities and enrich their appreciation of the goods they cooperatively produce. Many philosophers have closely linked work's value to different aspects of human rationality. For instance, philosophers inspired by thinkers such as Aristotle have underscored work's ability to allow us to perfect ourselves by developing and exercising our rational potential in worthwhile ways. On this picture, work is a central arena for the realization of our natures across our lifetimes (Clark 2017). Marxists typically agree that work allows us to develop and exercise our rational powers, but add that work's value also resides in how it enables us to make those powers visible by imparting human form to a natural world that would otherwise remain alien to us. Hence, for Marxists, work is an expression of our active nature, a pathway to self-realization inasmuch as work creates products that "objectify" the human will. Work thus represents a counterweight to the passive consumption characteristic of modern societies (Elster 1989, Sayers 2005). Another value associated with work is *meaningfulness*. Philosophical inquiry into meaningful work often parallels philosophical inquiry into the meaning of life. One central dispute about meaningful work is whether it is fundamentally subjective (a matter of how a worker feels about her work), fundamentally objective (a matter of the qualities of one's work or of the products one makes), or both (Yeoman 2014, Michaelson 2021). Some accounts of meaningful work are broadly Kantian, seeing meaningful work as grounded in the value of autonomy (Schwartz 1982, Bowie 1998, Roessler 2012). Such accounts judge work as meaningful to the extent that it is freely entered into, affords workers opportunities to exercise their own independent judgment, and allows them to pursue ends of their own that are to some extent distinct from the ends mandated by their employers. Other accounts locate the meaningfulness of work in its potential to enhance our capabilities, to manifest virtues such as pride or self-discipline, or to emotionally engage our sense of purpose (Beadle and Knight 2012, Svendsen 2015, Yeoman 2014, Veltman 2016). At the same time, some argue that meaningful work is in turn a precondition of other important goods. John Rawls, for example, proposed that a lack of opportunity for meaningful work undermines self-respect, where self-respect is the belief that our plan for our lives is both worth pursuing and attainable through our intentional efforts. Meaningful work, as Rawls understood it, involves enjoying the exercise of our capacities, particularly our more complex capacities. Given that meaningful work is a "social basis" for self-respect, a just and stable society may have to offer meaningful work by serving as an "employer of last resort" if such work is otherwise unavailable (Rawls 1996, Moriarty 2009). Recent years have witnessed a resurgence of interest in the *dignity* of work. Christian thought, and Catholicism in particular (John Paul II 1981), has long advocated that work manifests the dignity inherent in human beings. The claim that "all work has dignity," regardless of its nature or of how much social esteem it enjoys, rests on egalitarian ideals about labor, ideals articulated by Black American thinkers such as Booker T. Washington and Martin Luther King, Jr. As Washington expressed it, "there is as much dignity in tilling a field as in writing a poem" (Washington 1901:220). At the same time however, this tradition has also deployed the notion of dignity as a critical concept, to highlight labor injustice and to decry exploitative forms of work (including slavery) that fail to serve or uplift humanity (Washington 1901: 148, King 2011: 171-72, Veltman 2016: 29-31). This position thus seems to assert that work as such has dignity but that work can also vary in its dignity depending on workers' economic conditions or social status. More recent philosophical scholarship on the dignity of work has investigated its relationship to human rights. For instance, Paolo Gilabert (2018) distinguishes between dignity as a status and dignity as a condition. Status dignity is grounded in certain valuable capacities that individuals have, capacities that in turn that require workers be treated with respect and concern. Condition dignity is achieved when individuals are treated in accordance with the 'dignitarian' norms mandated by such respect or concern. Gilabert's distinction may allow the affirmation both of the inherent dignity of work, inasmuch as work gives evidence of human capacities worthy of respect, and of the claim that failing to provide decent working conditions is at odds with (but does not undermine) dignity. ### 2.2 Opposition to Work and Work-centred Culture That work is a potential source of income, social and personal goods, meaning, or dignity, does not entail that work *in fact* provides these goods or that work is good for us *on balance*. Since the Industrial Revolution in particular, many philosophers and social theorists have been sceptical about the value of work and of the work-centred cultures typical of contemporary affluent societies (Deranty 2015). Crucially, much of the scepticism surrounding the value of work is not scepticism about the value of work *per se* but scepticism about the value of work in present day social conditions or scepticism about the veneration of work found in the "Protestant work ethic" (Weber 1904-05) or in work-centred societies. Sceptics about work-centred culture question whether popular enthusiasm for work is rational or well-informed or whether it gives adequate credence to alternatives to work-centred culture (Cholbi 2018b, Sage 2019). Indeed, many critics of contemporary work arrangements essentially argue that good or desirable work is possible but rarer than we suppose. In "Useful Work versus Useful Toil," (1884), for example, the socialist activist William Morris rejects "the creed of modern morality that all labor is good in itself" and argues for a distinction between work that is "a blessing, a lightening of life" and work that is "a mere curse, a burden to life," offering us no hope of rest, no hope of producing anything genuinely useful, and no hope of pleasure in its performance. Similarly, the anarchist Bob Black opens his essay "The Abolition of Work" (1985) as follows: > > No one should ever work. Work is the source of nearly all the misery > in the world. Almost any evil you'd care to name comes from > working or from living in a world designed for work. In order to stop > suffering, we have to stop working. > But Black proceeds to define work as "forced labor, that is, compulsory production." His 'abolition' of work is thus compatible with individuals *voluntarily* engaging in economically productive activities, which (as we have seen) can resemble work in its essentials. Danaher (2019:54) allows that work can contribute to human well-being, but as presently organized, the world of work is "structurally bad" and unlikely to change in these respects: > > The labor market in most developed countries has settled into an > equilibrium pattern that makes work very bad for many people, that is > getting worse as a result of technical and institutional changes, and > that is very difficult to reform or improve in such a way as to remove > its bad-making properties. > Thus, even those espousing stridently 'anti-work' positions usually target not work as such, but work as it has been organized or understood in the contemporary world. Indeed, much of their ire is directed at current conditions of employment, which (as noted earlier) is only one prominent species work can take. The sceptical case against work or work culture has many dimensions, but can be fruitfully analysed as having four strands: 1. *Goods not realized:* While work can be a source of various goods, many people's working lives fail to provide them these goods. Popular enthusiasm for work thus seems misplaced, according to work sceptics, for "the moral sanctity of work is painfully out of step with the way that a vast proportion of people actually experience their jobs" (Frayne 2015: 62-63). With respect to the exchange value of work, work is often poorly compensated or insecure. Contemporary economies are increasingly characterized by a 'hollowing out' of middle class labor, wherein wages continue to increase for those at the upper end of the wage scale, wages stagnate at the bottom end of the scale, and the number of workers in the middle strata shrinks. This has resulted in the emergence of a class of 'working poor,' individuals who lack sufficient income to pay for basic needs such as housing or food *despite* being employed. Many of the other potential goods of work are enjoyed by some workers, but many receive little social recognition or do not achieve a greater sense of community through their work. A good deal of socially valuable or 'essential' work is largely invisible to its beneficiaries. Many jobs are dull or unchallenging, contributing little to the development or exercise of our more sophisticated human capacities. It is difficult to envision, for instance, that toll booth workers find their jobs or stimulating or challenging (aside from testing their ability to withstand repetition or boredom). Modern work has been oriented around the *division of labor*, i.e., the increasing separation of productive processes into ever smaller tasks. (The factory assembly line provides the model here.) The division of labor results in workers becoming hyper-specialists, who repetitively perform narrow or simple tasks. Although the division of labor increases overall economic productivity, critics such as the classical economist Adam Smith worried that it eventually makes workers "as stupid and ignorant as it is possible for a human creature to become." (Smith 1776 [1976]: V.1.178) As to meaning or dignity, a wide swath of human work neither engages workers nor allows them to exercise their autonomous judgment, and many work in oppressive or exploitative conditions seemingly at odds with the dignity of the work they perform. 2. *Internal tensions among work goods:* A characteristic of work-centred societies is that their members look to work to provide them with many different goods. But work (and employment in particular) may be ill-suited to provide this package of goods, i.e., work may be capable of providing some of these goods but only at the expense of others. For instance, many of the professions that individuals view as offering the greatest opportunities for meaningful work (such as education, counseling, or care for the sick, young, or disabled) are among the poorest paid professions. Contemporary labor markets thus seem to offer a workers the opportunity for an inadequate income or meaningful work, but rarely both. The psychologist Barry Schwartz argues (2015) that our non-material motivations for work, such as seeking meaningfulness, social engagement, and opportunities for autonomy, are in motivational competition with the monetary incentives associated with work. The monetary incentives distort workplace attitudes and behaviours so that the non-material goods we seek in work are crowded out by a focus on productivity and the economic goods work makes available. That labor markets are competitive may also undermine the social benefits of work, for even those who succeed in the labor market do so by being 'pitted against' other workers in ways that reduce solidarity among them, turning fellow citizens into rivals who are indifferent (or even hostile to) each other's interests (Hussain 2020). 3. *Unrecognized bads or costs:* Sceptics also point to 'bads' or costs associated with work that tend to go unrecognized. The most obvious of these is the opportunity costs resulting from the amount of time spent working. Typically, full-time workers spend 1,500-2,500 hours per year on the job, equivalent to around nine to fifteen weeks annually. These are hours that, were they not allocated to working, could be devoted to leisure, sleep, exercise, family life, civic and community engagement, and so on (Rose 2016). These hours do not include the considerable amount of time that workers expend on training or educating themselves for work or on commuting to and from workplaces. Nor does it include the hours that many salaried workers are expected to be 'connected' or 'on call' by their employers. Formal employment also tends to preclude workers from work other than that performed for their employers, with the result that workers often end up paying other workers for that labor. Such costs include the hiring of housekeepers, child care providers, maintenance experts and landscapers, etc. And while unemployment seems to have adverse effects on our physical and mental well-being, working is not free of adverse health effects either, including stress, emotional frustration, and physical ailments from repetitive work tasks or ergonomic deficiencies in workplace design. Sceptics also argue that when work fails to deliver certain kinds of goods, workers suffer certain psychological bads. Three such classes of bads merit particular attention: * Marx's critique of work under capitalism rests on the notion that work often lacks goods whose absence gives rise to the further bad of *alienation*. Marx (1844) proposed that work under capitalism alienates workers from what they produce, inasmuch as workers have little if any say over what is produced and how; from the act of work itself, inasmuch as workers are compelled by economic necessity to work and so do not take intrinsic satisfaction in working; from their own human nature or "species-essence," inasmuch as workers do not witness their own agency or intentions "objectified" in the products of their work; and from other workers, inasmuch as capitalism treats workers as interchangeable inputs of production and pits worker against worker. In terms of our earlier enumeration of the goods of work, Marx's appeal to alienation suggests that the absence of these goods is not merely a lack or a deprivation but is a positive bad of work in its own right (Elster 1989, Brudney 1998, Kandiyali 2020). * Many work sceptics emphasize how work may distort our priorities or values. The value of work, in their eyes, has come to be an unquestioned ethical dogma. "The economists and the moralists have cast a sacred halo over work," according to Paul LaFargue (1883), instilling us in the "delusion" of the "love of work." (See also Frayne 2015.) Bertrand Russell (1932) argued that the veneration of work has eroded our appreciation of the value of leisure and idleness. (See also O'Connor 2018.) Economists such as Keynes (1930) observed that the dramatic increases in economic productivity have often not led to reductions in work time, a development he attributes to a work ethic that stymies our capacity to enjoy leisure and abundance. * The social cachet of work may end up warping our moral relationship to ourselves, treating ourselves not as intrinsically valuable but as mere instruments of production. Hannah Arendt (1958) argued that conceiving of ourselves primarily as workers leads to a sort of instrumental stance on ourselves and other human agents, in which we come to view ourselves purely as resources for production or sites of consumption. More recent critics have proposed that work-centred cultures encourage us to view the self as a commodity to be 'branded' or marketed to prospective employers (Davis 2003). Lastly, work can have costs to others besides workers themselves. The aforementioned opportunity costs deriving from time devoted to work may worsen workers' relationships with others or bar their communities from making use of those workers' skills for socially worthwhile purposes. Some work arguably makes workers complicit in harmful or unjust practices, such as the sale of tobacco or unhealthy foods. Workers may also impose *negative externalities* through their work. For example, working outside the home typically results in a greater environmental impact, including contributions to the carbon outputs responsible for global climate change (James 2018). 4. *Alternatives sources of work-related goods:* A last thread in 'anti-work' thinking is that, even to the degree that work is good, it is not obviously uniquely situated to provide the goods it provides. A sense of social recognition or identity can be rooted in domains of human life besides employment, such as volunteer work, family life, religion, or friendship. "Ludic" activities, i.e., play, can offer opportunities to exercise and hone our rational capacities (Black 1985, Nguyen 2019). Some have proposed that virtual reality will provide us simulacra of work-like activities that could thereby substitute for work itself. Contrary to Gheaus and Herzog (2016) then, work may not be a "a privileged context" for realizing the goods we associate with work. Anti-work theorists typically call for work to be re-valued such that individuals will 'work to live, not live to work,' as well as policies (such as reductions in the mandated weekly working time) to minimize the influence of work on our quality of life. That work is both unavoidable and seemingly necessary but frustrating might suggest the wisdom of an ironic stance toward work (de Botton 2010). ## 3. Justice and the Politics of Work Human societies can be seen as cooperative endeavours aimed at securing their members' interests. If so, then social justice will be centrally concerned with those practices within societies by which individuals cooperate to produce goods for one another's use. Work is therefore a central concern of social justice. Questions of work and justice arise both with respect to the design of institutions and the choices of individuals. ### 3.1 Distributive Justice Most accounts of justice assume that a large number of individuals within a given society will engage in paid work. A crucial moral question, then, is what individuals are entitled to with respect to both the benefits and the harms of work. How, in other words, are the goods and bads of work justly distributed? One possible answer to this question is that each worker is entitled to whatever benefits their talents and abilities enable them to secure in a labor market governed purely by supply and demand. This answer entails that those whose talents or abilities are in high demand and/or short supply will command greater benefits from prospective employers than those whose talents or abilities are in low demand and/or generously supplied (Boatright 2010). (This same logic would apply to those who use their labor to produce goods for sale rather than those in employment arrangements.) After the early decades of the twentieth century, many nations implemented policies at odds with this 'pure market' vision of work and labor. Most have wage regulations, for example, mandating a minimum level of pay. But the justice of minimum levels of pay is disputed, with some theorists arguing that disallowing a person to sell her labor at a price she judges adequate infringes on her personal liberty. According to many libertarian thinkers, our labor is an exercise of our bodies or our talents, each of which we own in a way akin to our ownership of private property. To disallow someone the right to sell their labor even at a very low cost thus infringes on their rights of self-ownership. (Mack 2002) The fairness of wage differentials is also disputed. Should wages track the economic value of a worker's contributions or their effort, or are wages primarily an incentive to encourage worker commitment and motivation? (Heath 2018, Moriarty 2020) Some theorists have proposed that inequalities in pay ought to be eliminated altogether (Ortenblad 2021), while some supporters of an unconditional basic income, in which individuals receive regular payments regardless of their working status, see it an alternative way to ensure a sufficient minimum income, one immune to workers becoming unemployed (van Parijs and Vanderbroght 2017). Distributive justice also pertains to various *protections against harms* *or wrongs* associated with work. Again, most societies place legal limitations on various conditions of work. These include protections against overwork via limitations on the length of the workday or workweek; bans on discrimination in hiring or promotion based on race, gender, religion, or other social categories; assurances that workplace risks and dangers are mitigated; and, at a wider societal level, prohibitions aimed at ensuring that individuals lives are not dominated by work at particular life stages (bans on child labor and provisions to make retirement possible). One important moral question about these protections is whether workers should have the right to bargain away some of these protections either for increased pay (as when employees negotiate higher wages in exchange for performing more dangerous jobs) or for enhancements in other protections. ### 3.2 Contributive and Productive Justice The questions of distributive justice addressed in the previous section concern what goods workers receive from work *if* they work at all. But critical questions about justice also pertain to whether workers are entitled to work and whether they are obligated to do so. Work thus raises questions of *contributive* and *productive* justice respectively. For one, do workers have a right to work in the first place? The Universal Declaration of Human Rights states as much, assuring each individual "the right to work, to free employment, to just and favorable conditions of work and to protection against unemployment." (United Nations 1948, Article 23) A right to work would presumably be more than a negative liberty, i.e., not simply a right that others not interfere with one's attempts to work, secure employment, etc., but a *claim* to be provided work if one wishes (Schaff 2017). The right to work has been defended both for specific populations (such as the disabled; see Kavka 1992) or for the populace writ large (Tcherneva 2020). If there is such a right, it will presumably be because work is an essential (or at least the prevailing) means for the acquisition of vital goods. Elster (1988) proposes a job guarantee on the grounds that work is essential to self-realization. Gomberg (2007) argues that work is a key social good because it is the primary path by which to make a socially validated contribution to one's wider community, a contribution that can provide us recognition and a sense of meaning. Two crucial questions that arise in connection with the putative right to work are (a) against whom is this right held, i.e., who must provide work if workers have a right to it, or (b) whether work provided so as to honour this right will in fact provide the goods on which the right to work is based (e.g., the work provided under a government-provided job guarantee could prove unfulfilling). A right to work would mean that any person (or at least any adult) who wished to work would be able to do so. But do individuals have a right *not* to work, or is work in any sense morally obligatory? The most obvious basis for such an obligation appeals to notions of *fair play or reciprocity*: Individuals act wrongly when they fail to contribute to social enterprises from which they benefit, and since the productive economy benefits most everyone in a society, individuals have an obligation to contribute to the productive economy by working. (Becker 1980, White 2003) Opponents of this fair play rationale argue that the conditions for just reciprocal relations between societies and particular groups (e.g., the ghetto poor; see Shelby 2012) do not obtain, thereby exempting members of such groups from the obligation to work, or that contemporary economic developments fail to provide the background conditions for the obligation to apply (Cholbi 2018a). Other opponents of an obligation to work argue that it represents a violation of the state's duty to treat citizens equally; citizens who are compelled to work are made to pursue a conception of the good life with which they may not agree, and a just state should treat citizens as equals by remaining neutral among rival conceptions of the good life (van Parijs 1991, Levine 1995). An obligation to work would in effect amount to the state's endorsement of the 'work ethic' and the rejection of ways of life (e.g., being a beachcomber) that themselves oppose the work ethic. Other opponents of a duty to work argue that requiring individuals to work is likely to stand in the way of self-realization for particular people (Maskivker 2012). Another possibility is that even if there is not a general obligation to work, we might be subject to limitations on our work-related liberties in order to satisfy demands of distributive justice. Many of the goods provided by a just society, including education and health care, are labor-intensive. But societies often face shortfalls of workers in the very occupations that provide these goods. Some philosophers have argued that the demands of distributive justice may permissibly constrain our work choices, and in fact, may license governments conscripting labor in order to secure workers to provide these goods, on the model of the military draft during wartime. (Fabre 2008, Stanczyk 2012). Similar concerns arise concerning socially necessary but undesirable 'dirty' work.(Walzer 1983, Schmode 2019). Conversely, if justice can require individuals to perform certain kinds of work, this might speak against a right to strike (Borman, 2017, Gourevitch 2018), particularly on the part of essential workers (Munoz 2014). How one's choice of work contributes to justice and the overall good is a moral question that individuals face as well. Some jobs (hired assassin, for example) seem immoral as such. But to what extent, if any, are we obligated to choose careers or jobs that promote justice or the welfare of others? On the one hand, choice of jobs and careers does not appear exempt from moral considerations, inasmuch as the work one performs affects others and society at large, and given the often dismal state of the world, perhaps we are obligated to choose jobs and careers for moral reasons rather than solely on the basis of self-interest. Norman Care (1984:285) proposes "that in today's world morality requires that service to others be put before self-realization in the matter of career choice." In contrast, some philosophers who believe that individuals (and not merely institutions) within a society are subject to demands of justice nevertheless accord individuals discretion in their choices of occupation. G.A. Cohen, for instance, asserts that we should each enjoy a "personal prerogative" that allows us to be something more than an "engine for the welfare of other people" or "slaves to social justice." (2008:10) We might likewise worry that requiring that our job or career choices be optimal from the standpoint of justice or social welfare is excessively demanding in light of how such choices both reflect and shape our identities (Cholbi 2020). ### 3.3 Equality and Workplace Governance In recent years, egalitarian philosophers have begun to critique typical workplace arrangements as antagonistic to requirements of equal relations among individuals in society. Particularly influential here is Anderson's suggestion that many workplaces amount to a form of "private government," at least as authoritarian as many forms of state government. > > Imagine a government that assigns almost everyone a superior whom they > must obey. Although superiors give most inferiors a routine to follow, > there is no rule of law. Orders may be arbitrary and can change at any > time, without prior notice or opportunity to appeal. Superiors are > unaccountable to those they order around. They are neither elected nor > removable by their inferiors. ...The government does not > recognize a personal or private sphere or autonomy free from sanction. > It may prescribe a dress code and forbid certain hairstyles. Everyone > lives under surveillance, to ensure that they are complying with > orders. ...The economic system of the society run by this > government is communist. The government owns all the nonlabor means of > production in the society it governs. It organizes production by means > of central planning. The form of the government is a dictatorship > (Anderson 2017: 37-38). > The 'society' Anderson invites us to imagine is of course the contemporary workplace, at least as it stands in the United States and many other nations. Anderson and other *relational* egalitarians view the relationships defined by the powers that employers usually have over their employees as oppressive and unjust. Workers are subject to employers' 'governance,' but this governance consists in employees being arbitrarily and unaccountably subject to the wills of employers. The relational egalitarian thus concludes that workplaces, as presently constituted, do not involve employees and employers relating as genuine equals. And while employees will generally have the right to exit employment relationships, this may be little protection against oppression if most workplaces are organized in the way Anderson illustrates. To some degree, the inequalities to which Anderson points are products of labor law and policies specific to different nations. There are, however, ways of altering the relationships between employers and workers so as to potentially prevent or address these (and other) inequalities. Perhaps the most familiar such method is *unionization* or collective bargaining. Worker unions amplify the power of individual workers in relation to their employers by compelling employers to negotiate contracts with workers as a body. Unions may organize workers within a particular profession, within many professions, or within a single workplace or firm. Societies vary considerably in the degrees to which their workers are unionized and their labor laws friendly to union formation and power. Unions are presumptively justified on the grounds that workers who consensually form or join unions are exercising their right to freely associate with others with whom they share interests in order to promote those interests (Lindblom 2019), though if union membership is required in order to be employed in a particular workplace or industry, unionization may violate individuals right *not* to associate with others or to associate with (in this instance, to enter into an employment relationship) any party of their choosing (White 1998).Appealing to "republican liberty," Mark Reiff (2020) has argued that unions should be viewed as a basic institution of society that protects workers' liberty from exploitation by employers. On Reiff's view, unionization should therefore be universal and *compulsory*. Other methods for redressing the seemingly unequal and oppressive relations between employers and employees involve breaking the monopoly on decision making that management typically has within a given firm or employment arrangement. Typical workplaces are hierarchical rather than democratic. Many egalitarian critics of work call for the workplace to be more democratized, with workers having a greater say not only concerning their own working conditions but also concerning decisions usually reserved for management. Advocates for workplace democracy often argue that it is likely to be the most effective workplace organization in protecting workers' interests. (Gonzalez-Ricoy 2014). Others emphasize that the workplace is a microcosm of larger society and hence serves as a training ground for the development of virtues needed to live in a larger democratic society (Pateman 1970, Estlund 2003). But perhaps the most basic argument for workplace democracy is that firms are analogous to states, and so if the state ought to be governed democratically, so too should firms and other workplaces (Dahl 1986, Mayer 2000, Landemore & Ferreras 2016). Workplace democracy would seem to render the workplace more just inasmuch as it makes workers' conditions a partial byproduct of their consent and a reflection of their autonomy (Schaff 2012). ### 3.4 Gender, Care, And Emotional Labor Work's role in justice is further complicated by the fact that work is a highly gendered phenomenon in many societies. For one, women typically perform much of the housekeeping and child care that traditionally have not been recognized with monetary compensation. Within the formal labor market, many societies have a wage gap wherein women are paid less than men for similar work, and there are significant differences in gender representations in different professions (traditionally, women highly represented in fields such as primary school teaching, nursing, and social work, men highly represented in fields such as engineering and finance). Feminist philosophers have detected in these differentials an undervaluation of the kinds of work, particularly care work, that women have often performed (Gurtler and Smith 2005) as well as a blind spot in philosophical theorizing about justice wherein 'relational' goods that matter to our life prospects but are usually not provided via market exchange are ignored (Gheaus 2009). One intricate set of issues here is understanding the underlying relations of cause and effect: Are women in societies with sexist norms pushed toward low pay or low prestige jobs because they are women, or are these low pay or low prestige jobs because women tend to perform them (or both)? In a similar vein, we may wonder how norms of gender intersect with the gendered division of labor (whether, for example, the stereotype that women are more eager to care for children feeds the gendered division of labor or whether the gendered division of labor reinforces that stereotype, or both). The gendered division of labor is open to objections of different kinds: On the one hand, it appears to result in distributions of work-related goods (such as income, free time, etc.) in which women are systematically shortchanged. In addition, the gendered division of labor may be unjust because it contributes to hierarchies between the genders that render them unequal. (Hartley and Watson 2018) Schouten (2019) argues that, although many individuals embrace traditional gender norms and the gendered division of labor these entail, those who instead favour gender-egalitarian ways of life have a reasonable ground to complain when societies create institutions and policies that support expectations -- the gendered division of labor chief among these -- that serve as impediments to such ways of life. According to Schouten then, a just society will regulate work time, family leave, and dependent care so as to foster gender-egalitarian ways of life and a non-gendered division of labor. (See also Wright and Brighouse 2008, Gheaus 2012.) A further strand in feminist thought about work arises from Hochschild's scholarship (2012) on *emotional labor*. Some work involves intensive monitoring or management of one's own emotions in order to engage or manipulate the emotions of others. Although Hochschild offers examples of such emotional labor undertaken both by women and men, some professions in which women predominate are saturated with emotional labor. Hochschild notes that female flight attendants, for instance, are subject to a wide array of emotional expectations vis-a-vis air travellers (smiling, friendly banter, interest in travellers' destinations or professions, etc.). Scholars have highlighted a number of ethically salient features of emotional labor (see Barry, Olekalns, and Rees 2019 for a useful overview), but the phenomenon has been subject to little systematic philosophical analysis. Hochschild primarily emphasizes the detrimental effects of emotional labor on workers themselves, arguing that it can estrange workers from their own emotions and lead to struggles to identify or express authentic emotion both within and outside the workplace. Furthermore, when emotional labor results in employees' "surface acting," that is, displaying emotions at odds with their own internal feelings, employees' health suffers. Other ethical concerns are more interpersonal -- for example, that emotional labor is deceptive or lacks integrity. Barry, Olekalns, and Rees (2019) offer a useful starting point by noting that emotional labor raises the prospect of conflicts between workers' rights and the rights of their employers, between workers' rights and workers' duties, and between employer rights and employer duties. ## 4. Work and its Future A number of social commentators have predicted that economic and technological trends will soon culminate in societies become increasingly 'post-work,' that is, far fewer individuals will engage in paid work, work hours will dramatically decrease, and work will have a far smaller role among individuals' values or concerns.(Frey and Osborne 2013, Thompson 2015, Brynjolofsson and McAfee 2014). Whether this prospect should be welcomed or avoided depends to a large extent on issues addressed earlier in this article: how good work in fact is, whether there are other avenues for attaining the goods associated with work, etc. Some welcome a post-work future as liberating (Livingston 2016, Chamberlain 2018, James 2018, Danaher 2019), arguing that diminutions in the centrality of work will afford us greater leisure, freedom, or community, especially if activities such as play or the appreciation of the natural worlds supplant work. Others worry that the decline of work will deprive us of a central arena in which to realize goods central to our natures (Deranty 2015) or will instigate high levels of inequality or economic distress (Frase 2016). Others express concern about individuals' ability to psychologically transition from a work-centred to a work-optional society (Cholbi 2018b). ## 5. Conclusion Work and labor bear intrinsic philosophical interest. But their centrality to the human condition also entail that work and labor intersect with still broader philosophical questions about the human good and the just organization of human societies. Ongoing and anticipated changes to the world of work should provide rich fodder for philosophical inquiry in coming decades. Philosophy is likely to have a special role to play in addressing what Appiah (2021:7) has called the "hard problem," to determine "how to produce the goods and services we need, while providing people with income, sociability, and significance."
world-government
## 1. Historical Background For I dipt into the future, far as human eye could see, Saw the Vision of the world, and all the wonders that would be; ... Till the war-drum throbb'd no longer, and the battle-flags were furl'd In the Parliament of man, the Federation of the world. There the common sense of most shall hold a fretful realm in awe, And the kindly earth shall slumber, lapt in universal law. --Alfred, Lord Tennyson, "Locksley Hall" (1837) United States President Harry Truman, who oversaw the founding of the United Nations after the Second World War, kept these lines from Tennyson's poem in his wallet (Kennedy 2006: xi). After this brutal global war that claimed over fifty million lives, just like after the previous world war in which almost ten million perished, ordinary people and statespersons alike sought to establish a post-war international order that would be able to prevent another war of global devastation from occurring. In fact, since the problem of war, or large-scale socially organized violence, has been with us throughout human history, the ideal of a universal community of humankind living in perpetual peace was not at all new. Derek Heater's history of ideas of world government and citizenship begins by noting their presence in ancient Chinese and Indian as well as Graeco-Roman thought (1996: ix-x). According to Heater, the concept of human unity produced an ideal that such unity ought to be expressed in political form. The exact nature of that form, however, has changed radically over time. While Stoic ideas about the oneness of the universe were politically inchoate, they inspired medieval Christian proposals for a global political authority; at the same time, the historical model of imperial Rome (or its myths) inspired medieval quests for world empire. The Italian poet, philosopher, and statesperson, Dante (1265-1321), perhaps best articulated the Christian ideal of human unity and its expression through a world governed by a universal monarch. In *The Banquet* [*Convivio*], Dante argued that wars and all their causes would be eliminated if > > > the whole earth and all that humans can possess be a monarchy, that > is, one government under one ruler. Because he possesses everything, > the ruler would not desire to possess anything further, and thus, he > would hold kings contentedly within the borders of their kingdoms, and > keep peace among them. (*Convivio*, bk 4, ch 4 [2000: 169]) > > > In *De Monarchia* (1309-13: 8]), a full political treatise affirming universal monarchy, Dante draws on Aristotle to argue that human unity stems from a shared end, purpose or function, to develop and realize fully and constantly humanity's distinct intellectual potential. In Book I, Dante argues that peace is a vital condition for realizing this end, and peace cannot be maintained if humanity is divided. Just as "[e]very kingdom divided against itself shall be laid waste" (*Monarchia* bk 1, ch. V, quoting Luke 11:17 [1995: 10]), since humankind shares one goal, > > > there must therefore be one person who directs and rules mankind, and > he is properly called "Monarch" or "Emperor". > And thus it is apparent that the well-being of the world requires that > there be a monarchy or empire. (*Monarchia* bk 1, ch. V [1995: > 10]) > > > Most importantly, when conflicts inevitably arise between two rulers who are equals, "there must be a third party of wider jurisdiction who rules over both of them by right"; a universal monarch is necessary as > > > a first and supreme judge, whose judgment resolves all disputes either > directly or indirectly. (*Monarchia* bk 1, ch. X [1995: > 14]) > > > In the absence of a universal monarch, humanity is "transformed into a many-headed beast", striving after "conflicting things" (*Monarchia* bk 1, ch. XVI [1995: 28]); humankind ordered under a universal monarch, however, > > > will most closely resemble God, by mirroring the principle of oneness > or unity of which he is the supreme example. (*Monarchia* bk 1, > ch. VIII [1995: 19]) > > > Dante completes his treatise by extolling the Roman Empire as a part of God's providence (*Monarchia* bks 2 and 3 [1995: 30-94). And while Dante argued for a universal emperor whose temporal power was distinct from the pope's religious power, and not derivative from the latter, he envisioned that God's will must require pope and emperor to forge a cooperative and conciliatory, rather than competitive and antagonistic, relationship. The idea of uniting humanity under one empire or monarch, however, became an ambivalent appeal by the seventeenth century with the entrenchment in Europe of the system of sovereign states after the Peace of Westphalia (1648). At the same time, European encounters with non-European worlds precipitated European ambitions based on the principle of promoting civilization as an organizing framework for legitimizing European imperial and colonial expansion into other parts of the world (Keene 2002). In *Leviathan* (1651), Hobbes (1588-1679) gave the quintessential formulation of sovereignty as supreme legal coercive authority over a particular population and territory. Hobbes argued that although mutual vulnerabilities and interests lead individuals to give up their liberties in the state of nature, in exchange for protection--thereby instituting sovereign states--the miseries that accompany a plurality of sovereign states are not as onerous to individuals, hence there is less rational basis for political organization to move towards a global leviathan: > > > because states uphold the Industry of their Subjects; there does not > follow from the international state of nature, that misery, which > accompanies the Liberty of particular men. (1651: ch. 13 [1986: > 188]) > > > Contrary to realist interpretations of Hobbes in international relations thought, Hobbes did not consider international law or cooperation between sovereign states to be impossible or impractical. Anticipating the development of international law, collective security organizations, the League of Nations and the United Nations, he affirmed the possibility and efficacy of leagues of commonwealths founded on the interests of states in peace and justice: > > > Leagues between Common-wealths, over whom there is no humane Power > established, to keep them all in awe, are not onely lawfull [because > they are allowed by the commonwealth], but also profitable for the > time they last. (1651: ch. 22 [1986: 286]) > > > In Hobbes, we find the first articulation of the argument that a world state is unnecessary, although he envisaged that the development of a lawful interstate order is possible, and potentially desirable. In the eighteenth century, Charles Castel, Abbe de Saint-Pierre (1658-1743), in his *Project for Making Peace Perpetual in Europe* (1713), extended Hobbes's argument that a rational interest in self-preservation necessitated the creation a domestic leviathan to the international realm, asserting that reason should lead the princes of Europe to form a federation of states by social contract. The contracting sovereigns would form a perpetual and irrevocable alliance, establishing a permanent Diet or Congress that would adjudicate all conflicts between the contracting parties. The federation would also proscribe as "a public enemy" (Rousseau 1756 [1917: 63]) any member who breaks the Treaty or disregards the decisions of the congress; in such a situation, all members would "arm and take the offensive, conjointly and at the common expense, against any State put to the ban of Europe" in order to enforce the decisions of the federation (1756 [1917: 61-4]). In other words, perpetual peace can be achieved if the princes of Europe would agree to relinquish their sovereign rights to make war or peace to a superior, federal body that guaranteed protection of their basic interests. In his comments on this proposal, Rousseau (1712-78) acknowledged its perfect rationality: > > > Realize this Commonwealth of Europe for a single day, and you may be > sure it will last forever; so fully would experience convince men that > their own gain is to be found in the good of all. (1756 [1917: > 93]) > > > To Rousseau, however, existing societies had so thoroughly corrupted humans' natural innocence that they were largely incapable of discovering their true or real interests. Thus, the Abbe's proposals were not utopian, but they were not likely to be realized "because men are crazy, and to be sane in a world of madmen is itself a kind of madness" (1756 [1917: 91]). At the same time, Rousseau noted that the sovereigns of Europe were not likely to agree voluntarily to form such a federation: > > > No Federation could ever be established except by a revolution. That > being so, which of us would dare say whether the League of Europe is a > thing more to be desired or feared? It would perhaps do more harm in > the moment than it would guard against for ages. (1756 [1917: > 112]) > > > This *consequentialist* objection to the idea of world government speculates that even if it were desirable, the process of creating a world government may produce more harm than good; the necessary evils committed on the road to establishing a world government would outweigh whatever benefits might result from its achievement. Rousseau viewed war as a product of defectively ordered social institutions; it is states as public entities that make war, and individuals participate in wars only as members or citizens of states. Far from viewing the achievement of a domestic leviathan as moral progress, Rousseau noted that the condition of a world of entangled sovereign states puts human beings in more peril than if no such institutions existed at all. Isn't it the case, he argued, that > > > each one of us being in the civil state as regards our fellow > citizens, but in the state of nature as regards the rest of the world, > we have taken all kinds of precautions against private wars only to > kindle national wars a thousand times more terrible? And that, in > joining a particular group of men, we have really declared ourselves > the enemies of the whole race? (1756 [1917: 56]) > > > In Rousseau's view, the solution to war is to establish well-governed societies, along the lines he established in *The Social Contract* (1762); only in such contexts will human beings realize their full rational and moral potential. To establish perpetual peace, then, we should not pursue world government, but the moral perfection of states. A world of ideal societies would have no cause for war, and no need for world government. Kant tried, in his *Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose* (1784), to refute the claim that the development of the domestic state constituted a moral step backwards for humankind, by placing it and its trials > > > in the history of the entire species, as a steadily advancing but slow > development of man's original [rational] capacities. (1784 > [1991: 41]) > > > Nature employs the "unsociableness of men" to motivate moral progress; thus war is a means by which nature moves states > > > to take the step which reason could have suggested to them even > without so many sad experiences--that of abandoning a lawless > state of savagery and entering a federation of peoples in which every > state, even the smallest, could expect to derive its security and > rights not from its own power or its own legal judgment, but solely > from this great federation (*Foedus Amphictyonum*), from a > united power and the law-governed decisions of a united will. (1784 > [1991: 47]) > > > This is the "inevitable outcome" (1784 [1991: 48]) of human history, a point Kant reiterated in *Perpetual Peace* [1795], when he argued that rationality dictated the formation of > > > an *international state (civitas gentium),* which would > necessarily continue to grow until it embraced all the peoples of the > earth. (1784 [1991: 105]) > > > In present conditions, however, Kant noted that "the positive idea of a *world republic* cannot be realized", thus his treatise on perpetual peace begins with the social fact of a world of distinct but interacting states. What would be required, given such a world, to achieve perpetual peace? Kant makes three arguments. First, every state must have a republican constitution that guarantees the freedom and equality of citizens through the rule of law and representative political institutions. The internally well-ordered republican state is less likely to engage in wars without good reason; > > > under a constitution where the subject is not a citizen, and which is > therefore not republican, it is the simplest thing in the world to go > to war. (1784 [1991: 100]) > > > Second, such internally well-ordered states would need to enter into a "federation of peoples", which is distinct from an "international state" (1784 [1991: 102]). A > > > *pacific federation (foedus pacificum)* ... does not aim > to acquire any power like that of a state, but merely to preserve and > secure the freedom of each state in itself, along with that of the > other confederated states. (1784 [1991: 104]) > > > In this context, a federal union of free and independent states, he argued, > > > is still to be preferred to an amalgamation of the separate nations > under a single power which has overruled the rest and created a > universal monarchy. > > > His reasons against a universal monarchy combine fears of an all-powerful and powerless world government: > > > For the laws progressively lose their impact as the government > increases its range, and a soulless despotism, after crushing the > germs of goodness, will finally lapse into anarchy. (1784 [1991: > 113]) > > > Most forcefully articulating the tyranny objection, Kant argued that a "universal despotism" would end "in the graveyard of freedom" (1784 [1991: 114]). The third condition for perpetual peace in a world of distinct but interacting states is the observance of cosmopolitan right, which Kant limits to universal hospitality. Although the human race shares in common a right to the earth's surface, Kant argued that strangers do not have entitlements to settle on foreign territory without the inhabitants' agreement. Thus, cosmopolitan right justifies visiting a foreign land, but not conquering it, which Kant criticized the commercial states of his day to have done in "America, the negro countries, the Spice Islands, the Cape" and East India (1784 [1991: 106]). Kant's views on the desirability of world government were clearly complex (Kokaz 2005: 87-92; Pogge 2009). On the one hand, Kant provides two of the most trenchant objections to world government. The *tyranny* argument posits that world government would descend into a global tyranny, hindering rather than enhancing the ideal of human autonomy (Kant 1795 [1991]). Instead of delivering impartial global justice and peace, a world government may form an inescapable tyranny that would have the power to make humanity serve its own interests, and opposition against which might engender incessant and intractable civil wars (Waltz 1979; DuFord 2017). In another argument against its desirability, the inevitable remoteness of a global political authority would dilute the laws, making them ineffectual and meaningless. The posited weakness of world government leads to objections based on its potential *inefficiency* and *soullessness* (Kant 1795 [1991]). On the other hand, Kant also provides a republican vision of world government based on universal reason. His endorsement of the ideal of human unity prompted him to see a world republic, under which free and equal individuals, united by one global sovereign, would achieve a "fully juridical condition" (Pogge 2009: 198), as the ideal end of the progress of human history. At the same time, Kant's faith in human unity through reason coexisted with his subscription to a theory of racial hierarchy in human development, and he came to be critical of the dominant modes of European expansionist policies in world politics in the late eighteenth century--through colonial wars, exploitation, and conquests--as undermining the moral progress of Europeans (Valdez 2019). More generally, Kant condemned any move towards a universal monarchy, because a monarchy, in contrast to a republic, does not guarantee, but undermines, the freedom and equality of individuals. Although a world republic is Kant's ultimate political ideal, a universal despotic monarch that exercises power arbitrarily is equivalent to a global anarchic state of nature, which is his ultimate dystopia. In between lies his "realistic utopia" (Rawls 1999: 11-6) consisting of a federation of free (republican) states short of a world state. As Habermas has put it, > > > This weak conception of a voluntary association of states that are > willing to coexist peacefully while nevertheless retaining their > sovereignty seemed to recommend itself as a transitional stage en > route to a world republic. (2010: 268) > > > Kant's work shows that even in the eighteenth century, debates about world government were alive and well, including arguments by radical political cosmopolitans such as Anacharsis Cloots (Jean-Baptiste du Val-de-Grace, baron de Cloots, 1755-1794), who used social contract theory to advocate the abolition of the sovereign states system in favor of a universal republic encompassing all humanity (Kleingeld & Brown 2002). At the same time, philosophical projects for perpetual peace in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries were Eurocentric in adopting Europe as the centre of world order, in failing to recognize non-European peoples in equal standing, and in obscuring the global inequalities and injustices being established by European commercial enterprises and states (Pitts 2018: 6-7). The nineteenth and twentieth centuries witnessed revivals of proposals for world government that were fueled by racialized theories of progress that buttressed European-led colonial and imperial expansion over much of the world, technological developments in travel and communications, the rapid ascent of a global capitalist system, as well as the devastating impact of wars fought with modern technology. Theories of "scientific racism" continued to pervade European thought on world order: > > > White supremacist visions of global governance circulated widely in > the Anglo-American world. (Bell 2018: 871) > > > One of the most prominent proponents of world order, H.G. Wells (1866-1946), envisaged in 1901 a "New Republic" of Anglo-American dominance, and while he repudiated racial theories, his vision of a universal world state included a civilizing mission (Wells 1902; Bell 2018: 870). The construction of racial and civilizational hierarchies, backed by military domination, meant that the inclusion of non-Europeans and non-whites, whether in imperial projects, colonial civilizing missions, or later, in a system of formally independent states embedded in a capitalist global economy, would be marked by deep asymmetries and inequalities in standing, status, rights, burdens, and powers (Anghie 2005; Bell 2019; Getachew 2019). In the Second World War, after the atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki, atomic scientists lobbied for the international control of atomic energy as a main function of world federalist government. Albert Einstein wrote in 1946 that technological developments had shrunk the planet, through increased economic interdependence and mutual vulnerability through weapons of mass destruction. Although his adherence to the idea of a world government to guarantee interstate peace preceded the development of nuclear weapons, Einstein's advocacy gained momentum with the risk of nuclear annihilation: > > > A world government must be created which is able to solve conflicts > between nations by judicial decision. This government must be based on > a clear-cut constitution which is approved by the governments and > nations and which gives it the sole disposition of offensive weapons. > (1946 [1950: 132]; Nathan & Norden 1960) > > > Organizations such as the United World Federalists (UWF), established in 1947, called for the transformation of the United Nations into a universal federation of states with powers to control armaments. World peace required that states should give up their traditional unrestricted sovereign rights to amass weapons and wage war, and that they should submit their disputes to authoritative international institutions of adjudication and enforcement; world peace would only be achieved through the establishment of world law (Clark & Sohn 1958/1960 [1962]). Calls for world government in the post-World War Two era implied a deep suspicion about the sovereign state's potential as a vehicle for moral progress in world politics. Emery Reves' influential *The Anatomy of Peace,* is a condemnation of the nation-state as a political institution: "The modern Bastille is the nation-state, no matter whether the jailers are conservative, liberal or socialist" (1945: 270). Echoing Rousseau, Reves argued that nation-states threaten human peace, justice and freedom, by diverting funds from important needs, prolonging a global climate of mistrust and fear, and creating a war machine that ultimately precipitates actual war. The experience of the world wars thus made it especially difficult to view states as agents of moral progress. David Mitrany, perhaps motivated by such suspicions, bracketed the idea of a world federation or world state, and focused on the role that "a spreading web of international activities and agencies" could play in the pursuit of world integration and peace (1966: 38; Trachtman 2013). Some did not reject the nation-state *per se*, but only authoritarian nondemocratic states as unfit partners for building a peaceful world order. The Atlantic Union Committee (AUC), formed in 1949 by Clarence Streit, for example, called for a federal union of democratic states that would be the genesis of a > > > free world government, as nations are encouraged by example to > practice the principles which would make them eligible for membership, > namely the principles of representative government and protection of > individual liberty by law. (1950, quoted in Baratta 2004: 470; for a > critique see Rosenboim 2017) > > > In the context of the Cold War (1945-89), however, the division of the world into two ideologically opposed camps--led by the United States (US) and the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics (USSR)--produced mutual distrust that pervaded the reception of all proposals for world government. Soviet opposition to all Western proposals as attempts to impose "American monopolistic capitalism" on the world (Goodman 1953: 234) made the world federalist movement's goal of establishing a universal federation infeasible. The Soviet leadership also condemned the AUC's proposal for an exclusive union of democracies as part of the Cold War rivalry--an attempt to strengthen the anti-communist (anti-Soviet) bloc. In a distorted fashion, the Soviet Union became the historical manifestation of socialist or communist thought. Socialist ideas can be traced back to the French Revolution, but developed more fully as a response to negative aspects of the rapid growth of industry in the nineteenth century. At the same time that technological advancements promised great material progress, the changes they wrought in social and economic relations were not all positive. While the many workers, or "proletarians", in new industrial factories worked under terrible conditions for meager wages, the few factory owners, "the bourgeoisie" or "capitalists", amassed great wealth and power. According to Karl Marx (1818-1883), human history is a history of struggles not between nations or states, but between classes, created and destroyed by changing modes of production. The state as a centralized, coercive authority emerges under social modes of production at a certain stage of development, and is only necessary in a class society as the coercive instrument of the ruling class. The capitalist economic system, however, contains within it the seeds of its own destruction: capitalism necessitates the creation of an ever-growing proletarian class, and a global revolution by the proletariat will sweep away "the conditions for the existence of class antagonisms and of classes generally" (Marx & Engels 1848 [1988: 75]). The state will fall along with the fall of classes: > > > The society that will organize production on the basis of a free and > equal association of the producers will put the whole machinery of > state where it will then belong: into the Museum of Antiquities, by > the side of the spinning wheel and the bronze axe. (Engels 1884 [1978: > 755]) > > > In a communist vision, capitalism is a necessary but transitional and ephemeral order of things; the revolutionary overthrow of capitalism by forces it unleashed itself is necessary to attain a new world order, "in which the free development of each is the condition for the free development of all" (Marx & Engels 1848 [1988: 75]). World peace and freedom as nondomination for all (Roberts 2017), including freedom from the "alienated" or "estranged" labor (Marx 1844 [1978: 71-81]) produced under capitalism, will be achieved through the transformation of a capitalist to a communist social order: > > > In proportion as the antagonism between classes within the nation > vanishes, the hostility of one nation to another will come to an end. > (Marx & Engels 1848 [1988: 73]) > > > The Russian revolutionary, V.I. Lenin (1870-1924), drew on Marx to argue that the proletarian class needed to seize the coercive apparatus of the state to oppress the resisters and exploiters, the bourgeoisie, however, Lenin was committed to world revolution, and to the view that the state is "the organ of class rule", and that even the > > > proletarian state will begin to wither away immediately after its > victory because the state is unnecessary and cannot exist in a society > in which there are no class antagonisms. (Lenin 1918: 65) > > > In the context of the post-World War I world that witnessed the collapse of empires as well as the fortification of others, buttressed by the League of Nations, Lenin's vision of a new communist world order entailed an appeal to the colonized to mount anti-imperialist revolutions. This contrasted with U.S. President Woodrow Wilson's less radical interpretation of self-determination as good self-government, a formulation that was consistent with the civilizing narrative based on racial hierarchies, and the continuation and extension of a colonial international order (Pedersen 2015). Later Soviet leaders and elites who rejected Western proposals for world federation somewhat inconsistently envisaged the transcendence of nation-states and world capitalism, and the establishment of a world socialist economy governed by a "Bolshevik World State" (Goodman 1953: 231). In communist ideology, ultimately, balance-of-power politics between states enjoying unrestricted sovereignty did not cause war; the real cause of war was capitalism. In practice, the Soviet Union's internally and externally repressive policies made a mockery of socialist ideals of a classless society, or a world of peaceful socialist republics, and the disintegration of the Soviet Union itself spelled the practical end of one alternative to a capitalist world order. The end of Cold War ideological divisions led some to have great expectations in the 1990s of enhanced global cooperation to rid humanity of the threat of global nuclear annihilation and to increase global commerce and spread prosperity, the material bases for building a truly global moral and political community of humankind. The end of the twentieth century was marked by an unbridled faith and optimism in the inexorable twin triumph of capitalism and liberal democracy as the end of history (Fukuyama 1992). With the collapse of Soviet-style state socialism, the world witnessed neoliberal transformations on a global scale, driven by the "ideology of free markets, trade liberalization, deregulation, and the small state" (Luthi 2020: 596). Quinn Slobodian has described the paradoxical ascendancy of "globalist" neoliberalism, entailing the development of a world state and regulatory laws that privileged the "encasement" of markets from domestic democratic regulation and accountability, leading to an institutional project to redesign "states, laws, and other institutions to protect the market" (2018: 4 and 6). As neoliberalism spread on a global scale, so did the deterioration of conditions for robust democratic politics, precipitating serious backsliding of democratization. The optimism of the 1990s and early 2000s was thus short-lived as a variety of persistent and deepening structural injustices of the modern international system produced conditions ripe for violent conflict and mass atrocities, the global war on terror after 2001, the global financial crisis of 2007-9, growing numbers of displaced people, rising socioeconomic inequality, and the hollowing out of social welfare protections, not to mention the disruptive consequences wrought by climate change, and the Covid-19 global pandemic. The persistence of racial subordination and gender inequalities, as well as the ascendancy of a neoliberal world order, have provoked much critical debate about how these and other dominating hierarchies, backed by powerful international institutions, law, states, and corporations, can be tamed or overthrown, or how the crises they generate may accelerate structural transformations at the global level in a more emancipatory direction. ## 2. Debates in Contemporary Political Theory ### 2.1 International Relations Theory Contemporary international relations theory developed out of the urgent need to explain and predict the causes of war and peace in world politics. International relations theory has also developed in response to globalization, which has wrought "fundamental changes in the spatial and temporal contours of social existence" (Scheuerman 2002 [2018]), characterized by the uneven increase and intensification of social interconnectedness, economic integration, and the "shrinkage of geographic distance on a world scale" (Keohane 2001). While much of international relations theory's approach to world government has remained focused on the problem of overcoming interstate anarchy for the sake of human security in the face of common global threats, a "global politics paradigm" (Zurn 2018) has emerged which understands world government as only one possible institutional development among others in a system of global governance characterized by the co-constitution of transnational, international and domestic realms of politics and political contestation. Contemporary international "realists" or "neorealists" claim not to evaluate the contemporary states system in normative terms. They liken the international order to a Hobbesian state of nature, where notions of justice and injustice have no place, and in which each unit is rationally motivated to pursue every means within its power to assure its own survival, even at the expense of others' basic interests. Some realists have thus held that ideas of world government constitute exercises in utopian thinking, and are utterly impractical as a goal for human political organization. Assuming that world government would lead to desirable outcomes such as perpetual peace, realists are skeptical that world government will ever materialize as an institutional reality, given the problems of egoistic or corrupted human nature, or the logic of international anarchy that characterizes a world of states, all jealously guarding their own sovereignty or claims to supreme authority. World government is thus infeasible as a solution to global problems because of the unsurpassable difficulties of establishing "authoritative hierarchies" at the global or international level (Krasner 1999: 42). Furthermore, Kenneth Waltz, in his seminal account of neorealism, *Theory of International Politics*, clearly favors a system of sovereign states over a world government (1979: 111-2). World government, according to Waltz, would not deliver universal, disinterested, impartial justice, order or security, but like domestic governments, it would be driven by its own particular or exclusive organizational interests, which it would pursue at the expense of the interests and freedom of states. This realist view thus provides a sobering antidote to liberal and other progressive narratives that foretell peace through interdependence. William Scheuerman has argued (2011: 67-97), however, that so-called "classical" realists of the mid-twentieth century were more sympathetic to ideas of global institutional reform than contemporary realists. "Classical" and "progressive" realists such as Reinhold Niebuhr, E.H. Carr, and Hans Morgenthau, as well as John Herz and Frederick Schuman, supported a global reformist agenda, prompted by the advent of economic globalization, technological change, modern total warfare, and the nuclear revolution. Although a desirable end-goal, the feasibility of global political change towards a world government in the form of a global federal system, according to Reinhold Niebuhr, would depend on deeper global social integration and cohesion than was evident in the mid-twentieth century (Scheuerman 2011: 73). In addition, Niebuhr was concerned that absent the required social and cultural basis for global political unity, the achievement of world government would be undesirable, since in such conditions, a world government would require authoritarian devices to rule, raising the specter of a global tyrannical power (72-6). Others, such as James Burnham, posited that a world state could only arise through imperial conquest (Deudney 2019). Despite these caveats, realist prudence-based as well as functional arguments for a Weberian world state have gained traction again (Cabrera 2010; Ulas 2016; Araujo 2018; Craig 2019). "International society" theorists, or the "English school", argue that although there is no central overriding authority above sovereign states, their relations are not wholly lawless or devoid of authoritative and enforceable norms and rules for conduct. The anarchy between states does not preclude the concept of a norm-governed society of states (Bull 1977). Since "international society" theorists do not see the absence of a central global authority as necessitating a state-eat-state world, they regard the idea of world government as unnecessary, and potentially dangerous, since it may serve as a cloak in the struggle for imperial domination between states. Martin Wight has noted that the moral ideals of cosmopolitanism typically translate in practice into political tyranny and imperialism (1991). As an alternative to world government, and echoing both Rousseau and Kant, Chris Brown forwards > > > the ideal of a plurality of morally autonomous, just communities > related to one another in a framework of peace and law. (1995: > 106) > > > Establishing an international society, ideally conceived, would make a supreme world government unnecessary. Andrew Hurrell, however, argues that > > > it is important to recognize the extent to which social, environmental > and, above all, technological change is likely to affect the > *scale* of governance challenges, the *sources* of > control and governance, and the *subjects* of control. (2007: > 293) > > > For these reasons, Hurrell does not consider a retreat to a traditional state-based pluralism to be feasible, but argues that the development of a "stable, effective and legitimate international society" requires redressing global inequality through the significant redistribution of political power to buttress the collective political agency of the weak and marginalized (2007: 318).Liberal internationalist accounts of world order are motivated by more than just the traditional preoccupation with problems of war and peace. This school of international relations thought, more than the preceding two, is explicitly critical of traditional accounts of state sovereignty. Richard Falk has depicted the contemporary world order as one of "inhumane governance", identifying the following ills: global severe poverty affecting more than one billion human beings, denial of human rights to socially and culturally vulnerable groups, the persistent use and threat of war as an instrument of politics, environmental degradation, and the lack of transnational democratic accountability (1995: 1-2). A liberal internationalist agenda is advanced when progress is made on alleviating or correcting these ills. However, Falk is explicit that > > > humane governance can be achieved *without* world government, > and that this is both the more likely and more desirable course of > action. (1995: 8) > > > By world government, Falk means a form of global political organization that has, at minimum, the following features: > > > compulsory peaceful settlement of all disputes by third-party decision > in accordance with law; general and complete disarmament at the state > and regional levels; a global legislative capacity backed up by > enforcement capabilities; and some form of centralized leadership. > (1995: 7) > > > Instead of world government, Falk calls for "transnational democratic initiatives" from global civil society as well as United Nations reform, both of which would challenge and complement the statist and market forces that currently produce our contemporary global ills (1995: 207). Most liberal international theorists thus envision the need for authoritative international and global institutions that modify significantly the powers and prerogatives traditionally attributed to the sovereign state. Anne-Marie Slaughter has also rejected the idea of cosmopolitan democracy and a global parliament as infeasible and unwieldy (2004: 8 and 238). Slaughter is an advocate of "global governance", in the sense of "a much looser and less threatening concept of collective organization and regulation without coercion", to solve common global problems such as transnational crime, terrorism, and environmental destruction (2004: 9). According to Slaughter, states are not unitary, but "disaggregated" and increasingly "networked" through information, enforcement, and harmonization networks (2004: 167)--producing > > > a world of governments, with all the different institutions that > perform the basic functions of governments--legislation, > adjudication, implementation--interacting both with each other > domestically and also with their foreign and supranational > counterparts. (2004: 5) > > > A networked world order, she argues, > > > would be a more effective and potentially more just world order than > either what we have today or a world government in which a set of > global institutions perched above nation-states enforced global rules. > (2004: 6-7) > > > Although Slaughter is keen to highlight the promise of "global governance through government networks" as "good public policy for the world and good national foreign policy" (2004: 261), she acknowledges that in contemporary world conditions of radical social, economic and political inequality between states and peoples, effective and fair global governance will require the networks comprising global governance to abide by the norms of "global deliberative equality", toleration of reasonable and legitimate difference, and "positive comity" in the form of consultation and active assistance between organizations; in addition, global governance networks would need to be made more accountable through a system of checks and balances, and more responsive through the principle of subsidiarity (2004: 244-60). Without movement towards a more equitable world of mutual respect, however, it is difficult to see actually existing global governance networks operating in an impartial and generous spirit to help > > > all nations and their peoples to achieve greater peace, prosperity, > stewardship of the earth, and minimum standards of human dignity. > (2004: 166) > > > In this vein, Thomas Weiss has lamented the intellectual and political shifts in perspective from world government to global governance, arguing that current voluntary associations, organizations and networks at the global level are "so obviously inadequate" to meeting global challenges that we > > > are obliged to ask ourselves whether we can approach anything that > resembles effective governance for the world without institutions with > some supranational characteristics at the global level. (2009: > 264) > > > While many contemporary international relations theorists seem to reject the feasibility, desirability, or necessity of world government, constructivist theorist Alexander Wendt has argued that the "logic of anarchy" contains within it the seeds of transformation towards a "global monopoly on the legitimate use of organized violence--a world state" (2003: 491). Using Aristotelian and Hegelian insights, Wendt offers a teleological account of the development of world order from an anarchic states system to a world state, arguing that > > > the struggle for recognition between states will have the same outcome > as that between individuals, collective identity formation and > eventually a state. (2003: 493) > > > Technological changes, especially those that increase the "costs of war" as well as "the scale on which it is possible to organize a state", affect the struggle for recognition among states, undermining their self-sufficiency and making a world state "inevitable" (2003: 493-4). Wendt draws on the work of Daniel Deudney (1995 and 1999), who argued that the evolution of destructive technology makes states as vulnerable as individuals in a Hobbesian state of nature: > > > Hence nuclear one-worldism--just as the risks of the state of > nature made it functional for individuals to submit to a common power, > changes in the forces of destruction increasingly make it functional > for states to do so as well. (Wendt 2003: 508) > > > Deudney, however, has recently argued that the world state solution, involving a top-down hierarchical mode of government, is impractical and conceptually dead; his proposed alternative is a "negarchic", republican-federalist conception of world order that solves the problems of anarchy through the development of regimes of mutual restraint and obligation, but without the risk of despotism or totalitarianism accompanying hierarchical world government (2019 and 2020). According to Wendt, however, the path of world state formation is inevitable, and would be characterized by the emergence of "a universal security community", in which members expect to resolve conflicts peacefully rather than through force; a "universal collective security" system that ensures the protection of each member should "crimes" occur; and a "universal supranational authority" that can make binding authoritative decisions about the collective use of force (2003: 505). Driving this transformation is the struggle for recognition, and the > > > political development of the system will not end until the > subjectivity of all individuals and groups is recognized and protected > by a global Weberian state. (2003: 506; for a critique of teleological > arguments about institutional forms, see Levy 2020) > > > Wendt recognizes that powerful states enjoying the benefits of asymmetrical recognition may be most resistant to world state formation. He argues, however, that with the diffusion of greater violence potential to smaller powers (such as al-Qaeda and North Korea), > > > the ability of Great Powers to insulate themselves from global demands > for recognition will erode, making it more and more difficult to > sustain a system in which their power and privileges are not tied to > an enforceable rule of law. (2003: 524) > > > Based on the assumption that systems tend to develop toward stable end-states, a world state in which individuals and > > > states alike will have lost the negative freedom to engage in > unilateral violence, but gained the positive freedom of fully > recognized subjectivity. (2003: 525) > > > is the inevitable end-state of the human struggle for recognition. At the same time that Wendt sees world state formation as an inevitable trajectory of the struggle for recognition between individuals and groups, he argues that a world state could take various forms: while collectivizing organized violence, it need not collectivize on a global scale culture, economy or local politics; while requiring a structure that "can command and enforce a collective response to threats", it need not abolish national armies, or require a single UN army; and while it requires a procedure for making binding choices, > > > it would not even require a world "government", if by this > we mean a unitary body with one leader whose decisions are final. > (2003: 506) > > > ### 2.2 The Liberal Rejection of World Government We now turn to debates about world government among contemporary liberal theorists. Since the publication of John Rawls's landmark *A Theory of Justice* in 1971, liberal theorists such as Charles Beitz and Thomas Pogge have sought to formulate a cosmopolitan version of liberalism by extending Rawlsian principles of domestic justice to the international realm. According to Beitz, a cosmopolitan liberal conception of international morality is > > > concerned with the moral relations of members of a universal community > in which state boundaries have a merely derivative significance. (1979 > [1999a: 181-2]) > > > Cosmopolitan liberalism evaluates the morality of domestic and international institutions based on "an impartial consideration of the claims of each person who would be affected" (1999b: 287). A cosmopolitan liberal theory of global justice thus begins with a conception of humanity as a common moral community of free and equal persons. There is debate among contemporary theorists about the relationship and distinction between moral cosmopolitanism and political or institutional cosmopolitanism in the form of a world state or government (Beitz 1994; Dufek 2013; Ypi 2013; Cabrera 2018 and 2019). Contemporary liberal theorists have traditionally argued that world government, in the form of a global leviathan with supreme legislative, executive, adjudicative and enforcement powers, is largely unnecessary to solve problems such as war, global poverty, and environmental catastrophe. World government so conceived is neither necessary nor sufficient to achieve the aims of a liberal agenda (Yack 2012). Even cosmopolitan liberals have not argued that moral cosmopolitanism necessarily entails political cosmopolitanism in the form of a world government. Although Rawls himself rejects cosmopolitan liberalism, disagreeing with his liberal critics on several critical issues related to global distributive justice, they are united in their agreement that a world state is not part of a liberal ideal for world order. In his treatise on global order, *The Law of Peoples*, Rawls forwards the concept of a society of peoples, governed by principles that will accommodate "cooperative associations and federations among peoples, but will not affirm a world-state" (1999: 36). He explicitly states his reason for rejecting the idea of a world state or government: > > > Here I follow Kant's lead in *Perpetual Peace* (1795) in > thinking that a world government--by which I mean a unified > political regime with the legal powers normally exercised by central > governments--would either be a global despotism or else would > rule over a fragile empire torn by frequent civil strife as various > regions and peoples tried to gain their political freedom and > autonomy. (1999: 36) > > > Other liberal thinkers have similarly rejected the desirability of world government in the form of a domestic state writ large to cover the entire globe (Beitz 1999b: 182; Jones 1999: 229; Tan 2000 and 2004; Pogge 1988: 285; Satz 1999: 77-8; Risse 2012). In a related objection, "communitarian" liberals, such as Michael Walzer, argue against a centralized world government as a threat to social pluralism. Walzer thus endorses "sovereign statehood" as "a way of protecting distinct historical cultures, sometimes national, sometimes ethnic/religious in character", and rejects a centralized global order because he does not > > > see how it could accommodate anything like the range of cultural and > religious difference that we see around us today. ... For some > cultures and most orthodox religions can only survive if they are > permitted degrees of separation that are incompatible with globalism. > And so the survival of these groups would be at risk; under the rules > of the global state, they would not be able to sustain and pass on > their way of life. (2004: 172 and 176) > > > At the same time that distinct communities may constitute intrinsic human goods, Walzer also endorses social and political pluralism as an instrumental good: given the diversity of human values, he argues that they > > > are best pursued politically in circumstances where there are many > avenues of pursuit, many agents in pursuit. The dream of a single > agent--the enlightened despot, the civilizing imperium, the > communist vanguard, the global state--is a delusion. (2004: > 188) > > > A world of distinct, autonomous communities may be important to curbing the appetite of a hegemonic or global state to re-make the world in its own image. Liberal nationalists and communitarians thus object to world government due to the *homogeneity* argument--world government may be so strong and pervasive as to create a homogenizing effect, obliterating distinct cultures and communities that are intrinsically valuable. Liberal political pluralists (Muniz-Fraticelli 2014) are concerned that any state, including a world government, could destroy associative groups that constitute legitimate sources of political authority; and by destroying the rich social pluralism that animates human life (Walzer 2004), produce a loss of value (Miller 2007; Valentini 2012). The liberal rejection of world government, however, does not amount to an endorsement of the conventional system of sovereign states or the contemporary international order, "with its extreme injustices, crippling poverty, and inequalities" (Rawls 1999: 117). Rawls's rejection of a world government does not negate the legitimacy and desirability of establishing international or transnational institutions to regulate cooperation between peoples and even to discharge certain common inter-societal duties. Thus, after his rejection of a world state, Rawls goes on to say that in a well-ordered society of peoples, organizations > > > (such as the United Nations ideally conceived) may have the authority > to express for the society of well-ordered peoples their condemnation > of unjust domestic institutions in other countries and clear cases of > the violation of human rights. In grave cases they may try to correct > them by economic sanctions, or even by military intervention. The > scope of these powers covers all peoples and reaches their domestic > affairs. (1999: 36) > > > Rawls's vision of global order clearly rejects a world of atomistic sovereign states with the traditional powers of absolute sovereignty. Instead, his global vision includes "new institutions and practices" to "constrain outlaw states when they appear" (1999: 48), to promote human rights, and to discharge the duty of assistance owed to burdened societies. Thomas Pogge argues that realizing > > > a peaceful and ecologically sound future will ... require > supranational institutions and organizations that limit the > sovereignty rights of states more severely than is the current > practice. (2000: 213) > > > He sees this development to be possible only when a majority of states are stable democracies (2000: 213-4). Pogge thus appears to agree with Rawls that the path to perpetual peace (and environmental safety) lies in promoting the development of well-ordered states, characterized by democratically representative, responsive and responsible domestic governments. As these lines of argument by Rawls and Pogge suggest, liberals have been quick to reject framing the choice of world orders as one between *either* a world of traditional sovereign states *or* a world with a global central government. Pogge has asserted that liberals should > > > dispense with the traditional concept of sovereignty and leave behind > all-or-nothing debates about world government. > > > Instead, he argues for an > > > intermediate solution that provides for some central organs of world > government without, however, investing them with [exclusive] > "ultimate sovereign power and authority". (1988: 285) > > > In this "multi-layered scheme in which ultimate political authority is vertically dispersed", states that retain ultimate political authority in some areas would be juxtaposed with a world government with "central coercive mechanisms of law enforcement" that has ultimate political authority in other areas (Pogge 2009: 205-6). Debra Satz has also argued that framing the choice as one between the current states system and "an all-powerful world-state" poses a false dilemma: > > > the contrast between a system of sovereign states and a centralized > world-state is too crude. There are many other possibilities, > including a state system restrained by international and > intergovernmental institutions, a non-state-based economic system, a > global separation-of-powers scheme, international federalism, and > regional political-economic structures, such as those currently being > developed in western Europe and the Americas (via NAFTA). (Satz 1999: > 77-8) > > > Simon Caney has also endorsed a system of international institutions designed to > > > provide a reliable and effective means of protecting people's > basis interests (and instrumental consideration) and also to provide a > fair forum for determining which rules should govern the global > economy (a procedural component). (2006: 734) > > > As the many liberal proposals for moral improvement of the world order indicate, liberal objections to world government--whether they take the form of tyranny/homogeneity arguments and/or the inefficiency/soullessness objections--are not motivated by a complacent attitude towards the contemporary world order and its resulting conditions (Pogge 2000). As Charles Jones has put it, these valid and plausible objections to world government do not show that "the status quo is preferable to some alternative arrangement" (1999: 229). While liberal theorists acknowledge the tyrannical potential of a world government, they also acknowledge that "sovereign states are themselves often the cause of the rights-violations of their citizens" (1999: 229). Kok-Chor Tan characterizes liberal proposals for world order to involve, therefore, neither world government nor absolute state sovereignty. Instead, liberals have argued consistently for restrictions on the traditional powers of sovereignty, as well as for the vertical dispersion of sovereignty, "upwards towards supranational bodies, and also downwards toward particular communities within states" (2000: 101). In such a world order, states become "another level of appeal, and not the sole and final one" (2000: 101). David Held argues that this dispersion of sovereignty is inevitable given that the nation-state does not exist in an insular world, but a highly interdependent and complex system: the contemporary reality consists of a globalized economy, international organizations, regional and global institutions, international law, and military alliances, all of which operate to shape and constrain individual states. Although national sovereignty still has a place in the contemporary world order, > > > interconnected authority structures ... displace notions of > sovereignty as an illimitable, indivisible and exclusive form of > public power. (1995: 137) > > > In Held's account of cosmopolitan democracy, the universal realization of the liberal ideal of autonomy, derived from Kant, ultimately requires long-term institutional developments such as the creation of a global parliament, an international criminal court, the demilitarization of states, and global distributive justice in the form of a guaranteed annual income for each individual (1995: 279-80). Although cosmopolitan theorists tend to reject the dichotomy posed between a political system of sovereign states and one with a centralized world government, and have tended to eschew the terminology of the world state in their accounts of global democratic institutional reform, William Scheuerman has argued that some of their proposals of supranational institutions mimic core attributes of traditional statehood, thus inadvertently bringing the world state back into liberal cosmopolitan visions of world order (2014). It is thus an open question whether "statist cosmopolitanism" (Ypi 2011), which considers states as viable agents of cosmopolitan justice, is feasible, or whether cosmopolitanism requires transcending the state system (Ulas 2017). ### 2.3 Republican Nondomination and Global Democracy Democratic, republican and critical theorists have become concerned with the global context of order and justice due to its importance for establishing protective external conditions for the moral and political achievements of centuries of domestic democratic political struggle. Traditionally, the main global threat was interstate war, thus the projects for perpetual peace. Today, democratic theorists worry that contemporary processes of globalization are undermining the achievements of democratic societies in the areas of civil and social rights such as access to education and healthcare, and the economic securities provided by the welfare state. From this perspective, economic globalization and the growing power of international and transnational institutions pose a potential threat to democratic ideals of civic equality and self-determination. The task of the democratic theorist is to think about how democracies can respond to these global developments in ways that best help preserve the fragile achievements of domestic democratic justice (Habermas 2004 [2006]; see also Scheuerman 2008). Increasingly, theorists of global democratic reform envisage the need to develop new institutions and practices of representation and accountability rather than merely to extend traditional constitutional models and electoral mechanisms of domestic democratic governance (Archibugi 2008; Macdonald 2008; Marchetti 2008; Tinnevelt 2012; Tanyi 2019; Erman 2019). Key to discussions in democratic, republican and critical theory about global order and justice is the political ideal of nondomination. Neo-republican theorist Philip Pettit understands commitment to this ideal to entail reducing people's vulnerability to alien control or the arbitrary power of others to interfere with their choices and their lives. In the international context, Pettit has outlined a "republican law of peoples" that has the twin goals of ensuring that every people is represented by a non-dominating government in a non-dominating international order (2010). Starting with a world of states, Pettit argues that a state which is "effective and representative of its people" fulfills the republican ideal of nondomination, and "it would be objectionably intrusive of other agents in the international order" to bypass such states and assume responsibility for its members (2010: 71-2). A legitimate international order is one > > > in which effective, representative states avoid > domination--whether by another state, or by a non-state > body--and seek to enable other states to be effective and > representative too. (2010: 73) > > > In an international context, the sources of domination include other states; "non-domestic, private bodies" such as "corporations, churches, terrorist movements, even powerful individuals"; and "non-domestic, public bodies" such as the World Bank, the International Monetary Fund, and the North Atlantic Treaty Organization (2010: 77). While representative states realize nondomination internally for their members, individuals' enjoyment of freedom as nondomination is not secured unless their states are protected in their external relations from dominating strategies, including "intentional obstruction, coercion, deception, and manipulation" as well as "invigilation", and "intimidation" (2010: 74). Pettit's account presupposes the legitimacy of domestic democracies that ensure nondomination as a starting point for thinking about a legitimate international order, and he explicitly rejects the idea of a world state, modeled on a domestic republican regime, as an infeasible remedy for the challenges posed by domination in an international context (2010: 81; but see Koenig-Archibugi 2011). There is no easy solution, but Pettit considers feasible improvements to the current international order can be made by further developing multilateral > > > international agencies and forums by means of which states can work > out their problems and relations in a space of more or less common > reasons > > > as well as fostering greater solidarity among subgroups of weaker states so that they can form rival blocs that can resist domination by more powerful agents (2010: 84). While Pettit is mostly concerned with the dominating potential of powerful states, and considers international agencies to be less threatening (2010: 86), Cecile Laborde adds to Pettit's account not only a concern for agent-relative domination, but also, and more centrally, systemic domination, which entails a greater awareness of the dominating potential of international organizations such as the International Monetary Fund, World Trade Organization and the World Bank (2010). One of the ways that powerful states dominate weak states is by "entrenching and institutionalizing" their dominant position through unfair international social structures in areas such as trade (2010: 57). Indeed, Nancy Kokaz, in a republican interpretation of Rawls's *Law of Peoples*, argues that "a global republic cannot be dismissed by a civic [republican] theory of global justice" (2005: 94). The civic pluralist ideal that is threatened by the advent of global capitalism and ensuing deracination requires "a global state powerful enough to protect local communities" from the homogenizing tendencies and "excesses of global capitalism" (2005: 93). In a further development of republican ideas about global order and justice, James Bohman has argued that a republican ideal of freedom as nondomination in the new global "circumstances of politics" requires political struggle in the direction of transnational democracy (2004 and 2007). According to Bohman, > > > under conditions of globalization, freedom from tyranny and domination > cannot be achieved without extending our political ideals of > democracy, community and membership. (2004: 352) > > > Not only are currently bounded democratic communities ineffective in resisting new global sources and forms of domination, they are also "potentially self-defeating", constituting > > > a thousand tiny fortresses in which the oldest form of domination is > practiced at many different levels: the domination of noncitizens by > citizens, or nonmembers by members, using their ability to command > noninterference much like those who live within gated communities. > (2007: 175 and 180) > > > Daniele Archibugi has termed this > > > democratic schizophrenia: to engage in a certain [democratic] behavior > on the inside and indulge in the opposite [undemocratic] behavior on > the outside. (2008: 6) > > > Such vicious circles of "democratic domination" can only be overcome by making borders, membership and jurisdiction the subjects of democratic deliberation across *demoi* (Bohman 2007: 179). Whether or not democracy serves global justice depends on the possibility of transnational democratization, and Bohman sees two primary agents of such transformation, in democratic states pursuing "broadly federalist and regional projects of political integration", such as the European Union, and in the less institutionalized activities of "participants in transnational public spheres and associations" (2007: 189). While some think that the formal development of regional or global institutions must be democratized in order to realize republican nondomination or democratic agency (Valentini 2012), others argue that global democracy may be justified mainly for its instrumental role in protecting and promoting > > > the fundamental interests of all the world's citizens, rather > than by that of maximizing citizens' democratic agency > > > at the global level (Weinstock 2006: 10). Critical theorist Iris Marion Young similarly calls for a global politics of nondomination, that would support "a vision of local and cultural autonomy in the context of global regulatory regimes" (2002: 237). Her model of global governance--"a post-sovereign alternative to the existing states system" (2000: 238)--entails a "decentred diverse democratic federalism" (2000: 253). While everyday governance would be primarily local, it would take place in the context of global regulatory regimes, built upon existing international institutions, that would be functionally defined to deal with > > > (1) peace and security, (2) environment, (3) trade and finance, (4) > direct investment and capital utilization, (5) communications and > transportation, (6) human rights, including labor standards and > welfare rights, (7) citizenship and migration. (2002: 267) > > > Young envisages these global regulatory regimes to apply not only to states, but also to non-state organizations, such as corporations, and individuals. In terms of feasibility, Young points to the development of a robust "global public sphere" (Habermas 1998) as crucial to bringing about "stronger global regulatory institutions tied to principles of global and local democracy" (Young 2002: 272). Increasingly, then, republican and democratic theorists view transnational and supranational institutions not as intrinsic threats to democratic freedom and justice, but as potentially instrumental institutional developments that are necessary to fortify the capacities of contemporary states to deliver on democratic and republican values. In this sense, supporting the development of transnational democratic institutions is consistent with upholding the values of national identity and belonging, and the proper functioning of states, by providing a robust framework to coordinate and discipline states into solving problems of human rights and global justice in areas such as labor, health, migration, and taxation, in a more fair, equitable, and non-dominating manner (Abizadeh 2008; Ronzoni 2012; Valentini 2012; Dietsch 2015; Fine & Ypi 2016; Cabrera 2018). Paradoxically, it may be that in conditions of globalization, only a world state can provide the essential supporting conditions for all states, including democratic ones, to enjoy effective and legitimate collective self-determination (Lu 2018). Thus, republican cosmopolitanism in the form of a world state may be less of an oxymoron than Pettit suggests. ### 2.4 Critics of Capitalism and a Neoliberal World State An abiding controversy about the contemporary world economy is its potential to enhance or destroy societal goals of securing justice, freedom, and welfare provision, including the protection of human rights and democratic politics (Stiglitz 2002; Kinley 2009). Craig Murphy has worried that globalization would > > > inevitably be accompanied by the anti-democratic government of > "expertise" or by the non-government of marketization at > ever more inclusive levels. (2000: 800) > > > Economists have warned that the relationship between global economic integration, national self-determination, and democratic politics can be fraught (Rodrik 2011), and that capitalism has a tendency to reproduce and intensify inequality (Piketty 2013 [2014]). In the twentieth century, Immanuel Wallerstein (2011) developed the world-systems approach to analyzing the contradictions inherent in a capitalist world-system. Although imperial military competition gave way to a world of sovereign states in the era of decolonization, he noted that a capitalist world order perpetuates systems of domination to maintain capitalist interests, at the expense of the developing world. World-systems theory thus explains how capitalism forms a stable set of exploitative relations between core and peripheral states, resulting in an international division of labor that benefits the core at the expense of the periphery. While world-systems theory posits that "economic exploitation of the periphery does not necessarily require direct political or military domination" (Kohn & Reddy 2006 [2017]), contemporary postcolonial theorists argue that the rise of neoliberal globalization can be marked by the establishment of international economic institutions that have dislocated the power of sovereign states to make economic decisions, and relocated them in international economic institutions--the WTO, IMF and World Bank--with effective enforcement powers. Whereas realist, liberal and republican theorists typically posit that a world state is a possible futuristic institutional development to evolve from anarchy, postcolonial theorists have argued that anarchy does not accurately describe the global historical institutional reality. Some also argue that world government is already here, albeit in a nascent form (Albert et al. 2012; Goodin 2013). Critical and postcolonial theorists argue that the course of capitalist modernity has produced a nascent world state of neoliberal domination (Chimni 2004; Slobodian 2018). In such conditions of structural domination, a world state may be undesirable as a political project due to established and entrenched global hierarchies based on racist, patriarchal, and capitalist domination and exploitation (Robinson 1983; Pateman and Mills 2007). As B.S. Chimni has put it, > > > A network of economic, social and political [International > Institutions] has been established or repositioned, at the initiative > of the first world, and together they constitute a nascent *global > state* whose function is to realize the interests of transnational > capital and powerful states in the international system to the > disadvantage of third world states and peoples. The evolving global > state formation may therefore be described as having an > *imperial* character. (2004: 1-2) > > > Although fragmented in structure, the future global state, according to Chimni, is in the process of congealing to actualize and legitimize a world-view that ultimately serves the transnational capitalist class comprising the owners of transnational capital. This class allies with the networks of international law and institutions to undermine the decision-making powers of states, especially those with weak institutional capacities, and to make decisions without transparency or effective participation of those affected. While increasingly intrusive, the decisions of international economic and financial institutions remain largely unaccountable. According to Slobodian, neoliberal globalists actively sought to construct the institutions of the global economy to evade accountability, "to contain potential disruptions from the democratically empowered masses", so that the global economy could be "protected from the demands of redistributive equality and social justice" (2018: 264). While the Washington Consensus seemed to be based on sound economic principles--that free markets "and competition enable the efficient allocation of scarce resources"--and forecast economic growth based on liberalizing trade, investment, and capital flows, its failure to produce growth or inclusive development in many countries has revealed the importance of empirical analysis to check ideological distortions of economic policy (Rodrik 2015). China's economic transformation illuminates global challenges arising from the decline of "managerial capitalism", or Fordism, which generated the regulatory state-model of governance, and the rise of "neoliberal capitalism", or post-Fordism, defined by the "hollowing out" of the state, reduction of central regulatory capacity, coupled with flexible production processes disaggregated into production chains and networks, and increasing vulnerability of the peripheral workforce (Dowdle 2016: 207-229). In response to these predicaments of contemporary capitalism, critical and postcolonial theorists emphasize that there is no option to return to a mythical world of autarkic or autonomous and insulated states with traditional sovereign prerogatives (Winter & Chambers-Letson 2015). Instead, globalized domination can only be transformed through globalizing transnational labor and social movements that struggle for greater democratization of the decision-making processes of both domestic and international institutions (Chimni 2004). In calling for a revision of the principles that regulate the relationship between the global economy and sovereign states, in order to buttress state power, especially of Third World states, against international economic and financial institutions, critical theorists join contemporary liberal (Isiksel 2020) and republican theorists who view the state as continuing to play an important role in securing equal human freedom. According to Adom Getachew, "postcolonial cosmopolitanism" acknowledges the persistent unequal integration and hierarchy produced by the world politics of empire, and views the reinforcement of the sovereign state, as well as the dispersion of sovereignty in regional federations and a redistributive international economic order, as key to anti-colonial struggles to resist domination and remake the world (2019: 34). Given that the Eurocentric narrative of civilizational progress forwarded the nation-state as a marker of civilization, and fated Indigenous peoples to extinction with the advent of modernity, however, Indigenous political theorists have reason to be ambivalent about a Weberian state at any level of political organization. Some Indigenous political theorists have mounted radical challenges to the settler colonial state as well as the statist international order. Glen Coulthard's critique of the liberal politics of multicultural recognition reveals that the struggle for recognition may not emancipate, but entrench subjects in the settler colonial subjectivity offered by the settler colonial state (2014). Following anti-colonial thinker Frantz Fanon, Coulthard argues that dominated agents need to struggle to create new decolonized frameworks of recognition that they can call their own, and not only seek equal recognition based on structures of settler colonial power, otherwise > > > the colonized will have failed to reestablish themselves as truly > self-determining: as creators of the terms, values, and conditions by > which they are to be recognized. (2014: 139) > > > Coulthard also understands the political project of Indigenous "resurgence" to be inextricably linked to the struggle to construct alternative social and economic systems to capitalism; thus for Indigenous resurgence to be successful, "capitalism must die" (2014: 173). Such Indigenous politics of refusal (Simpson 2014) of both statism and capitalism underscore that the struggle for recognition of Indigenous humanity in conditions of racial capitalist modernity entails radical structural transformations of global order (Lu 2017 and 2019). ## 3. Conclusion The aim of much normative theorizing about global institutions and global justice is to interrogate whether a world government is feasible, desirable, or necessary for realizing human aspirations for just, inclusive, peaceful, and prosperous relations between the diverse individuals and groups that comprise a common moral community of humankind. Some think that the idea of world government involves a paradox: however it is conceived institutionally, when the winning conditions exist for establishing a desirable form of world government--one that will guarantee human security with individual liberty, protect the environment, and advance global social justice--it will no longer be necessary (Nielsen 1988: 276). Once all governments, especially the most powerful ones, are willing to use their power to build government networks that promote global peace, justice and environmental protection, and to cede some traditional rights of sovereignty to supranational institutions in areas such as the use of military force, the management and protection of the environment and natural resources, and the distribution of wealth, the establishment of a global political authority might seem superfluous. As Alexander Wendt has pointed out, however, a stable end-state of world order development requires such ideal conditions, should they ever develop, to become institutionalized into a world state that enacts "a global monopoly on the legitimate use of organized violence" (1988: 491); enforcement mechanisms are not superfluous, since there is always the possibility of violations by outlaw states and groups. In a similar vein, the Swedish philosopher Torbjorn Tannsjo has argued that neither voluntary multilateral cooperation under conditions of anarchy, nor a hybrid arrangement of "*shared* sovereignty between the world government and nation-states", will be effective in resolving contemporary challenges in the realms of human security, global justice and the environment (2008: 122-125). Since sovereignty is indivisible, Tannsjo posits that a world state must have ultimate decision-making authority over nation-states over jurisdictional issues: > > > Unless there are sanctions available to the central authority to back > up a decision as to where a question is to be handled, the system of > states will be thrown back into a state of nature. (2008: > 125-6) > > > From critical and postcolonial perspectives, however, the state of nature reference point of much of international relations theory is a normatively obscuring myth that occludes the hierarchies of structural domination that have pervaded the development of world order (Jahn 2000; Lu 2017: 120). Postcolonial and critical theorists often share the ethical concerns and moral commitments of normative theorists (Kohn 2013)--justice, equality, freedom, nondomination--but their theorizing focuses on the diagnostic task of analyzing the causes and character of contemporary structural and institutional developments, as well as the global processes and conditions that make them possible. They view contemporary global order, marked by radical imbalances and disparities produced by historic and ongoing structural injustices based on class, race, and gender, as serving certain functions and interests, in terms of what they naturalize, enable, suppress, and obscure. In 2020 and 2021, as a world divided by deep political, social and economic structural inequalities faces pandemic conditions, economic recession, and environmentally deleterious developments, the questions of *whose* sense of world community and *whose* global needs will define the global political agenda and order are more salient than ever.
impossible-worlds
## 1. Reasons for Introducing Impossible Worlds Why might one believe in impossible worlds? One argument is the so-called "argument from ways" (Vander Laan 1997), which is related to the first definition of impossible world given above. This draws on the analogy with David Lewis's notorious argument concerning our quantifying over ways things could have been (see Lewis 1973: 84). The world could have been different in so many ways: Hilary Clinton could have won the 2016 US election, I could be dancing on the ceiling, and Fermat's Last Theorem could have remained without proof. Our belief in possible worlds is just a paraphrase of our belief that there are many ways the world could have been. Aren't there also ways the world could *not* have been? Some authors endorse the claim that *anything* is possible (e.g. Mortensen 1989). However, the majority of philosophers believe that not everything is possible, in the sense that some things just *can't* happen. If I tell you that my college has a cupola which is both fully round and fully square, you are likely to reply, "it can't be *that* way!". So it seems that "'ways' talk goes both ways" (Beall and van Fraassen 2003: 86). If quantification on ways the world could have been should be taken at face value as providing evidence for possible worlds, then quantification on ways the world could not have been should be taken at face value as providing evidence for impossible worlds. The argument as such is hardly convincing. Firstly, one author's *modus ponens* is another's *modus tollens*. Some have used similar considerations to argue against Lewis's modal realism (see Skyrms 1976; Naylor 1986): if one believes in possible worlds (of the Lewisian kind) as ways things could have been, then by parity of reasoning one should believe in impossible worlds (ditto) as ways things could not have been. But impossible worlds are too much to swallow, so (by *modus tollens*) one should not believe in Lewis's modal realism. Secondly, taking quantification over any kind of entity whatsoever at face value, just because it is embedded in ordinary language, doesn't look like a promising general strategy. Lewis's case for accepting commitment to possible worlds did not consist just in an argument from *ways*. He also provided independent motivation for taking quantification over possible worlds at face value. A non-reductive account of possible worlds, according to Lewis, brings net theoretical utility. The ontological cost is compensated by a theoretical gain, given the variety of ontological, semantic, and conceptual explanations allowed by our taking the notion of possible world seriously. This is likely to be the main motivation for believing in impossible worlds. As we will see below, defenders of impossible worlds claim that they are are theoretically useful. Another argument on behalf of impossible worlds, quite pervasive in the literature, comes from *counterpossible reasoning* (e.g. Beall and van Fraassen 2003, Chapter 4; Nolan 1997; Restall 1997; Brogaard and Salerno 2013). This is reasoning from suppositions, assumptions, or conditional antecedents which are not only false, but impossible. We can reason non-trivially from impossible suppositions, by asking what *would* be the case, were (say) the Law of Excluded Middle false. To say that we reason *non-trivially* from an assumption means just that we accept some conclusions but reject others on the basis of that assumption. If we hypothetically suppose the Law of Excluded Middle to be false, for example, then we would likely conclude that intuitionistic logic would be preferable to classical logic, given that supposition. We are unlikely to conclude that classical logic would be a satisfactory logic, or that scarlet would be a shade of green, given that supposition. The point readily generalizes to reasoning about entire theories and to serious philosophical and logical debates. We often reason from suppositions about the truth of certain logical, mathematical, or metaphysical theories which, if in fact false, are necessarily false, because of the very nature of their subject matter. This kind of reasoning is related to our assessment of certain conditional statements with impossible antecedents, often called *counterpossible conditionals* or, more simply, *counterpossibles.* These include: (1.1) If Hobbes had squared the circle, then mathematicians would have been amazed. Let's call a conditional like this *trivially true* when it is true and the conditional with the same antecedent and opposite (negated) consequent is also true. (1.1) is intuitively true, and yet (1.2) If Hobbes had squared the circle, then mathematicians would not have been amazed. is intuitively false. If that's correct, then there are non-trivially true counterpossibles. These considerations impact on our preferred semantics for such conditionals, for the possible worlds semantics for conditionals has trouble accommodating this position. Yet the analysis in terms of worlds does a good job for conditionals with possible antecedents. This motivates a semantics for counterpossibles in terms of impossible (as well as possible) worlds. We will get into more detail in section 2.5. These kinds of argument highlight the usefulness of impossible worlds as devices for analyzing particular linguistic, logical, and philosophical issues. The point can be expanded into the general "argument from utility" mentioned above: we should believe in impossible worlds because they are useful tools for logicians and philosophers. Whether that general argument is acceptable depends on how persuasive the specific impossible worlds analyses are. Let's look at some. ## 2. Applications of Impossible Worlds This section briefly describes various applications of impossible worlds, which collectively provide the main motivation for introducing them. ### 2.1 Intentional States Modelling intentional states, such as knowledge and belief, is a prominent motivation for introducing impossible worlds. The intuitive idea is that one gains knowledge or belief by ruling out would-be possibilities (the *epistemic/doxastic possibilities* for that agent). An agent's knowledge is whatever is true according to all epistemically possible worlds accessible to that agent, i.e., the worlds which represent ways things could be, for all the agent knows (and similarly for belief). Impossible worlds are useful within this approach because these would-be possibilities often turn out to be impossible. Our beliefs are often (covertly) inconsistent with one another. Moreover, our knowledge and belief is not closed under (classical) logical consequence: we do not know or believe all consequences of what we know or believe. It is hard to accommodate these features using only possible worlds. Possible worlds models usually generate the problem of *logical omniscience* (see epistemic logic), which we will discuss in section 5.3. One feature of rational agents' intentional states is that they typically reject *obvious* impossibility or absurdity whilst being subject to *subtle* inconsistency (Lewis 2004). One attempt to capture this feature is developed in Jago 2006, 2007, 2009, 2014a. The idea is that only genuine possibilities and non-obvious impossibilities should be epistemically accessible to rational (but imperfect) agents such as us. For some agents, it may be epistemically possible that Fermat's Last Theorem's is false, but 0 being 1 shouldn't be epistemically possible for anyone. That's why we know the latter but may fail to know the former, says Jago. One worry with this approach is that it is partly proof-theoretic (invoking proof rules as relations between worlds), whereas it isn't clear that proof length correlates well with obviousness. Bjerring (2013) presents other objections to the view. A strategy similar to Jago's is adopted in Berto 2014, 2017. A quite different application of impossible worlds to epistemic states has been proposed by JC Beall 2009, in relation to the Church-Fitch knowability paradox. The Church-Fitch reasoning is supposed to show that is contradictory to suppose that any truth can be known (as some anti-realists claim). The reasoning is this. Suppose all truths are knowable but some are not in fact known. Then some truth \(A\), is not known: \(A \wedge \neg KA\). By assumption, it's possible to know this: \(\Diamond K(A \wedge \neg KA)\). Seemingly good reasoning (in classical epistemic logic) implies that it's possible both to know and not know that \(A\): \(\Diamond(KA \wedge \neg KA)\), which of course isn't possible at all. The usual moral to draw is that not all truths are knowable. Beall's idea, by contrast, is that the knowability principle can be maintained (and the corresponding kind of anti-realism along with it). His suggestion is to deny *distribution of knowledge over conjunction*: the principle that knowing that \(A \wedge B\) implies knowing that \(A\) and knowing that \(B\). He achieves this using impossible worlds in which conjunctions may be true even if their conjuncts are not. ### 2.2 Inconsistent Information Closely connected with inconsistent information (e.g., information including or entailing contradictions) is the issue of modelling *inconsistent databases* (see Belnap 1977a,b, Barwise 1997). These may consist, for instance, in sets of data supplied by different sources which are inconsistent with each other, such as incompatible evidence presented by different witnesses in a trial. Intuitively, we are allowed to draw the logical consequences of data fed in by a *single* source, but should not conjoin data from distinct sources which may be inconsistent with each other. The database is "compartmentalized": occasional inconsistencies are placed in separate sectors and should not be asserted conjunctively (see e.g., Belnap 1977a,b, Hyde 1997, Brown and Priest 2004). Impossible worlds are useful in such models--particularly *non-adjunctive* worlds, where a conjunction may be false even if both conjuncts are true. (We discuss such worlds further in section 5.2.) ### 2.3 Fiction Inconsistent information is at issue also in certain works of fiction. Lewis's classic 1978 paper proposed an analysis of the expression "true in such-and-such fiction" in terms of possible worlds. What holds in a certain fictional work is what holds at a set of possible worlds, properly selected via a series of (quite subtle and complex) clauses. But fiction can be occasionally inconsistent. Sometimes, this happens unintentionally: Conan Doyle's *The Sign of the Four* describes Watson as limping because of a war wound at his leg. In *A Study in Scarlet*, however, Watson has no wound at his leg (for his wound is in his shoulder and he doesn't limp). One may claim that the set of worlds that make such stories true has to be split into disjoint subsets, making true consistent fragments of the fiction. This strategy won't always work, however, for inconsistencies in fiction may be intentional (as stressed in Proudfoot 2006). Suppose we write a novel, and in its first chapter we have the Mad Mathematician produce a round square. If the intentional inconsistency is excised, the fact that mathematicians all over the world are amazed by this result in the second chapter becomes unexplainable. A natural treatment of these cases, then, is obtained by admitting (appropriately selected) impossible worlds in the set of situations that realize what is told in the story (see e.g. Priest 1997b; Woods 2003, Chapter 6; Berto 2012, Chapters 7 and 8; Badura and Berto 2019). ### 2.4 Propositional Content Closely connected to belief is the notion of *propositional content*. Within possible worlds semantics, propositions can be defined as functions from worlds to truth values, or as sets of worlds: a proposition is the set of worlds at which it is true. The account is notoriously too coarse-grained (Barwise 1997). Intuitively distinct impossible propositions (that swans are blue and not blue; that Fermat's Last Theorem is false; that Charles is a married bachelor) all hold at precisely no possible worlds. And we have a dual problem with (unrestrictedly) necessary propositions, which are all identified with the set of all possible worlds. Treating propositions as set-theoretic constructions out of possible worlds leads to a very coarse individuation of propositions, and because of this it has been subject to seemingly devastating attacks, for instance, by Scott Soames 1987. However, impossible worlds allow for fine-grained distinctions unavailable in standard possible worlds semantics. An impossible proposition need not be equated with the empty set of worlds, for it may be a set which includes (only) impossible worlds. We can have an impossible world \(w\_1\) with impossibly coloured swans, a distinct impossible world \(w\_2\) at which Fermat's Last Theorem is false, and a further impossible world \(w\_3\) at which bachelors are married (but at which swans and Diophantine equations behave correctly). Ripley (2012) argues that an account along these lines is a better strategy for addressing the coarse-grainedness problem than resorting to structured propositions. One other application of impossible worlds concerns *perceptual* impossibilities. When we see an Escher drawing or a Penrose triangle, our experience has content. But that content is impossible: such structures cannot be realised. The content of our experience in such cases is naturally captured using impossible worlds. Splitting that content into smaller internally consistent parts would lose the essential feature of the whole. This issue is explored in Mortensen 1997. ### 2.5 Counterpossible Reasoning Perhaps the most important application of impossible worlds has to do with counterpossible reasoning, understood as counterfactual reasoning from impossible antecedents. As we saw in section 1, this kind of reasoning is often taken to provide independent motivation for believing in impossible worlds. (For a recent overview of the literature on counterpossibles, see Kocurek 2021.) In Lewis-Stalnaker theories of counterfactuals, a conditional of the form, "if it were the case that \(A\), then it would be the case that \(B\)" is true if and only if, at the closest world (or closest worlds) at which \(A\) is true, \(B\) is also true. (This is a simplification of the truth conditions provided in the full-fledged semantics of Lewis 1973.) While the standard conditional logics based on this idea have been quite successful in the treatment of counterfactuals, the approach entails that any counterfactual whose antecedent is impossible is vacuously true. For if there are no possible worlds at which \(A\) is true, then trivially, all closest \(A\)-worlds (worlds where \(A\) is true) are \(B\)-worlds. This is unsatisfying in many respects, for we often need to reason nontrivially about theories that (perhaps unbeknownst to us) cannot possibly be correct; and we often need to reason from antecedents that may turn out to be not only false, but necessarily so. (Compare the conditionals (1.1) and (1.2) in section 1 for an example.) Recent defences of the view that counterpossibles are not all vacuously true include Sendlak 2021 and McLoone 2021. Three contexts in which theories of this kind show up are discourses on (1) alternative logics, (2) mathematical conjectures, and (3) metaphysical views. We will now say a few words on each of them. (1) A famous Quinean motto has it that "to change the logic is to change the subject": apparently disagreeing logical parties are actually speaking of different things. So when intuitionists deny that the Law of Excluded Middle holds in non-finitary contexts, they are actually changing the meaning of logical operators; when paraconsistentists claim that some formula can be true (in some weird circumstances) together with its negation, they are not talking of *negation* anymore (see e.g., Berto 2008). But this does not make good sense of many disputes between intuitionists, classical logicians, paraconsistentists, quantum logicians, etc. It is more fruitful to assume that each party generally understands the rival logics as intelligible, albeit necessarily false, theories. Even if classical logic actually is the one true logic, one can reason counterpossibly about what would be the case if a certain non-classical logic were the correct one (e.g., "if intuitionistic logic were correct, then the Law of Excluded Middle would fail" is true and "if intuitionistic logic were correct, then the Law of Explosion would fail" is false). One can take into account situations in which the Law of Excluded Middle fails and argue about what would and would not be the case in them. These situations are, by classical standards, just impossible worlds (of the third kind: Classical Logic Violators). (2) Similar claims can be made for mathematical conjectures. Different set theorists have different views on controversial subjects such as non-well-founded sets, the Continuum Hypothesis, the Axiom of Choice, the set/(proper-)class distinction, etc. If one embraces the Platonic view (subscribed to, at least implicitly, by many set theorists) that there is One True Universe of sets, then at most one of the alternative set theories can be correct: the others are wrong, and necessarily so. But people can work under the hypothesis that a necessarily false basic mathematical principle holds, and reason coherently from this: > > It is doubtless true that nothing sensible can be said about how > things would be different if there were no number 17; that is largely > because the antecedent of this counterfactual gives us no hints as to > what alternative mathematics is to be regarded as true in the > counterfactual situation in question. If one changes the example to > "Nothing sensible can be said about how things would be > different if the axiom of choice were false", it seems wrong > ... : if the axiom of choice were false, the cardinals > wouldn't be linearly ordered, the Banach-Tarski theorem would > fail and so forth. (Field 1989: 237-8) > Field takes this as an argument to the effect that mathematical necessity is not coextensive with logical necessity. But we can turn the tables around: mathematical necessity is unrestricted and false mathematical theories are just impossible theories. (3) The third area in which counterpossible reasoning comes into play are metaphysical disputes (and more broadly, any philosophical dispute whose subject matter is necessarily true or necessarily false). Much metaphysical talk is made with our quantifiers "wide open", that is, aiming at stating truths about all that there was, is, or could possibly be. This is evident in modal ontology, when people advance a theory on the totality of worlds and on their nature. But other metaphysical debates easily come to mind. Suppose a philosopher wants to evaluate metaphysical theories which she considers wrong (say, in order to draw unpalatable consequences by way of criticism), such as Spinoza's monism or Hegel's metaphysics of the Absolute. She must envisage situations where such metaphysics are correct and wonder what would be the case according to them: situations at which there is only one substance, or at which the Absolute *Geist* necessarily shapes the teleological development of history. These situations will be, under the hypotheses we have made, impossible worlds. Counterpossible reasoning may also show up in philosophical analyses of various kinds. For example, Boris Kment (2014) has proposed an account of modal notions which grounds them in explanatory reasoning, in particular of the counterfactual kind. To account for non-trivial counterpossibles, Kment uses impossible worlds taken as as collections of structured Russellian propositions. Semantic structures for counterfactual conditionals involving impossible worlds were first introduced by Routley 1989, and have been proposed e.g. by Read 1995, Mares and Fuhrmann 1995, Mares 1997, Nolan 1997, Brogaard and Salerno 2013, Bjerring 2014, Berto et al. 2018. Most of these are natural extensions of Lewis's 1973 semantics for counterfactuals and capture several intuitions about counterpossible reasoning. The main task for such theories consists in accounting for the concepts of closeness and qualitative similarity between worlds once impossible worlds enter the stage. How to fine-tune these notions is not a trivial matter (for an extensive discussion, see Vander Laan 2004; we will say more in section 4.2). Non-trivial treatments of counterpossibles require the failure of several logical principles which hold in the standard Lewis-Stalnaker approach to counterfactuals (Williamson 2007 chapter 5, Brogaard and Salerno 2013). (Williamson uses these failures to argue that counterpossibles are always trivially true.) One important principle that fails is the entailment from a strict conditional, "if \(A\) then-strictly \(B\)", to the corresponding counterfactual, "if it were the case that \(A\) then it would be the case that \(B\)". Normally, the former entails the latter. A strict conditional is true when all the (accessible) possible worlds where the antecedent is true also make the consequent true. If all the possible \(A\)-worlds are \(B\)-worlds, then in particular all the closest possible \(A\)-worlds are \(B\)-worlds. In an account which admits impossible worlds, however, we can have closest impossible worlds where \(A\) obtains and \(B\) fails, making the counterpossible false even though the corresponding strict conditional is true. The ensuing anarchy can be mitigated to some extent, e.g., by assuming what Nolan 1997 calls the *Strangeness of Impossibility Condition* (SIC): any possible world, however weird, should be closer to any possible world \(w\) than any impossible world is to \(w\). Reality will be turned upside down before logical laws or mathematical truths abandon us. Then it is plausible that the Lewis-Stalnaker principles will still hold whenever the relevant antecedent is *possible*. For then we will consider only the closest antecedent-worlds when we evaluate the conditional, all of which will be possible worlds: the impossible ones will be too far away (Berto et al. 2018). ## 3. The Metaphysics of Impossible Worlds Supporters of impossible worlds disagree over their metaphysical nature, just as supporters of possible worlds do. If one accepts ontological commitment to worlds of any kind, then one faces the follow-up question: just what are they, metaphysically speaking? The two main options among *modal realists* (philosophers who accept possible worlds in their ontology) are David Lewis's *extreme* or *genuine modal realism* and *ersatzism* (or *actualism* or *abstractionism*: these terms all have slightly different connotations, which we'll ignore here). It is a common thought among impossible worlds theorists that impossible worlds should just inherit the ontological status of their possible mates: whatever your favorite metaphysics of possible worlds is, impossible worlds are of the same kind. This has been called the *Parity Thesis* (see Rescher and Brandom 1980). As Graham Priest puts it: > > As far as I can see, any of the main theories concerning the nature of > possible worlds can be applied equally to impossible worlds: they are > existent nonactual entities; they are nonexistent objects; they are > constructions out of properties and other universals; they are just > certain sets of sentences. ... There is, as far as I can see, > absolutely no cogent (in particular, non-question-begging) reason to > suppose that there is an *ontological* difference between > merely possible and impossible worlds. (Priest 1997b: 580-1) > Yagisawa's *extended modal realism* proposes a Lewis-inspired realist account of impossible worlds and *impossibilia* (the objects exemplifying absolute impossibilities which inhabit impossible worlds). On this view, impossible worlds are concrete mereological sums of real individuals, which are causally and spatiotemporally interrelated within each world but never across worlds (see Yagisawa 1988). Yagisawa exploits the "argument from ways" we met above: if quantification on ways the world might be or have been commits us to possible worlds, then, by parity of reasoning, quantification on ways the world might not be commits us to impossible worlds. The argument is backed by Yagisawa's considerations on the additional logical and philosophical applications allowed by impossible worlds, which are not available, in his view, to traditional Lewisian modal realism. Extended modal realism is a strong position: concrete impossible worlds represent absolute and logical impossibilities directly, by *instantiating* them. So impossibilities and, in particular, logical inconsistencies, are "out there" in reality. In his 2010 book, Yagisawa is more distant from Lewisian modal realism. He still admits impossible worlds and *impossibilia*, and he rejects ersatz accounts of them. However, he now takes worlds to be points in modal space. Worlds are modal indices for truth, just like times are temporal indices for it; and modal matters are treated in a way similar to how four-dimensionalist philosophers, who believe in temporal parts, treat temporal matters. According to four-dimensionalists, material objects are like temporal worms extended across time: an object has a property at time \(t\) by having a temporal stage at time \(t\) which has that property. Analogously, for Yagisawa an object has a modal property, a property at world \(w\), by having a modal stage at world \(w\) which has that property. More moderate (Yagisawa would say: *too* moderate) realists treat impossible worlds as *ersatz* constructions: abstract entities on a par with ersatz possible worlds (see e.g. Mares 1997, Vander Laan 1997). Modal ersatzism comes in various shapes (Divers 2002, Part III, is by far the best critical evaluation in the literature). If one takes possible worlds as maximally consistent sets of propositions (as per Adams 1974), impossible worlds could be sets of propositions that are inconsistent and/or incomplete. Similarly, Plantingan ersatzism (possible worlds are particular states of affairs) or Stalnakerian ersatzism (possible worlds are world-natures or maximal properties) could be easily extended to accommodate impossible worlds. All hands agree that such worlds come at no great ontological or theoretical cost, once one has accepted ersatz possible worlds. After all, ersatz worlds are abstract: they account for impossibilities, not by instantiating them as Lewisian worlds do, but by representing them in some way or other. Jago (2012) takes both possible and impossible worlds to be constructions out of positive and negative facts, such as Barack Obama's not being French (see the entry on facts). The extension of ersatzism from possible to impossible worlds appears to be particularly straightforward for *linguistic* ersatzism. On this approach, possible worlds are *world-books*: sets of sentences of a special "worldmaking" language. (Carnap's (1947) state-descriptions and Jeffrey's (1983) complete consistent novels are examples of this strategy.) It is easy to admit impossible worlds of the same kind, that is, world-books which are locally inconsistent or incomplete, which fail to comply with some logical law or to be closed under some notion or other of logical consequence. However, there may be reasons to reject the Parity Thesis. If Lewis's criticisms of ersatzism in *On the Plurality of Worlds* are right, then each ersatz account of impossible worlds inherits the limits of ersatz theories of possible worlds: each of these theories has to resort to intensional entities taken as primitive (such as propositions or states of affairs) in its explanation of what ersatz worlds are, or to primitive modal notions (most often, to both). Suppose that, instead, one wants to retain the advantages of both worlds (no pun intended), ersatz and genuine, when it comes to impossibilities. Suppose, that is, that (a) one wants to employ a modal framework including both possible and impossible worlds to retain the theoretical benefits provided by the latter; and (b) one wants to stick to Lewis's project of a reductive account of intensional and modal notions to fully extensional ones (*contra* ersatzism); but also (c) one wants to avoid the unwelcome consequences of concrete impossible worlds instantiating impossibilities, such as having true contradictions "out there" in reality (*contra* Yagisawa's extended modal realism). One could then try the following hybrid solution: (1) go realist about possible worlds, and (2) exploit the set-theoretic machinery of modal realism to represent different impossible worlds as distinct ersatz, abstract constructions. To fulfil these desiderata, Berto 2010 sketches an intermediate account, labeled as *Hybrid Modal Realism* (HMR), which dispenses with the Parity Thesis. The account follows suggestions from Divers 2002, Chapter 5, and is similar to a strategy pursued in Kiourti 2010, Chapter 3. On this view, genuine, concrete possible worlds are the basic stuff. Atomic propositions are taken as sets of possible worlds. Distinct impossible situations can then be represented by distinct world-books, taken as set-theoretic constructions from atomic propositions. Krakauer 2013 gives a similar account in terms of structured propositions built out of ordinary possible worlds. Jago 2012 and Sendlak 2015 criticise Berto's approach on the basis that it cannot distinguish the proposition *that Hesperus is the second planet from the sun* from the proposition *that Phosphorus is the second planet from the sun*. Reinert 2018 attempts to do better by combining Lewisian possible worlds with an ersatz situation-based account of impossible worlds. Fouche 2022 develops Berto's hybrid account into a full-fledged hyperintensional theory of content. A metaphysical account of impossible worlds, alternative both to ersatzism and to Lewisian realism, has been proposed in Zalta 1997. Zalta's powerful theory of abstract objects is based upon his logic of *encoding*, whose core idea consists in postulating an ambiguity in the copula of predication: "\(x\) is \(P\)" can mean that object \(x\) exemplifies property \(P\), as per ordinary predication; but it may also mean that \(x\) *encodes* \(P\), encoding being a special mode of predication. Abstract objects encode properties, besides exemplifying them; in particular, they can encode properties they do not exemplify (see Zalta 1983). Within this theory, *situations* are defined as abstract objects that encode states of affairs (taken as 0-ary properties); and impossible worlds are taken as maximal situations that are not possible, that is, such that it is not possible that all the states of affairs encoded by them simultaneously obtain. Zalta claims that, despite treating worlds as abstract objects, this is not an ersatz conception of worlds. A given state of affairs \(p\)'s obtaining at world \(w\) (no matter whether \(w\) is possible or impossible) is analyzed as: * (Z) \(w\) encodes the property *being-such-that-p*, and so *being-such-that-p* is ascribed, in the encoding sense, to \(w\). As such, \(w\) *is* (in the encoding sense of the copula, at least) such that \(p\). Thus, according to Zalta's theory of encoding, worlds are in some sense metaphysically characterized or determined by such states of affairs. And according to Zalta nothing of the sort can be claimed of ersatz conceptions of worlds. All the ontological accounts of impossible worlds presented so far are in a broad sense realist. They all accept that sentences referring to or quantifying over impossible worlds can be literally true, and take the entailed ontological commitment at face value, although they disagree with each other about the metaphysical status of worlds. A deeply anti-realist alternative to modal metaphysics has also been developed: modal fictionalism. The view is fictionalist (or anti-realist) about *worlds*. Its key claim is that talk of and quantification over worlds ought to be understood as literally false: it is only true within a "worlds fiction". We make-believe in the fiction because it delivers useful results in the explanation of modal notions. Modal fictionalism promises the theoretical benefits of modal realism without the ontological costs. We should not include worlds (other than the actual world) in our ontological catalogue. But talking *as if* there were worlds is useful. Gideon Rosen (1990), a major proponent of the view, takes Lewisian modal realism to be the relevant fiction. But it is relatively easy to extend such modal fictionalist accounts into fictional treatments of possible *and* impossible worlds, taking e.g. Yagisawa's extended modal realism as the fiction which we make-believe. JC Beall (2008) proposes an approach to impossible worlds (see section 5.1), which can be motivated by the idea that these are worlds where "logical fictions" take place. ## 4. The Structure of Impossible Worlds Another issue which theories of impossible worlds disagree on concerns the amount of logical *structure* such worlds have. This issue affects impossible worlds specifically: there is no correlative issue concerning possible worlds (beyond our choice of logic). Various classes of impossible worlds display different degrees of anarchic logical behavior: as we shall see, non-normal worlds for non-normal modal logics (section 5.1), for instance, are such that only modal sentences behave in a non-standard fashion at them, whereas sentences that include just the Boolean operators of classical logic get the standard treatment. Such worlds appear to be logically more structured than fully anarchic "open" worlds (section 5.3). For, we shall see, even principles of classical logic involving only the extensional, truth-functional connectives can fail at open worlds: their openness consists in their not being closed under any non-trivial logical consequence principle. Should we require impossible worlds to comply with *any* logical rules? And if we allow different classes of impossible worlds, each exhibiting different degrees of logical structure, can these classes be ordered in a meaningful way? This section focuses on these two issues. ### 4.1 The Granularity Issue Are there any logical principles which impossible worlds must obey? More precisely, is there any logical inference such that, for any (impossible) world \(w\), if the premises are all true according to \(w\), then so is the conclusion? There is at least one such inference: the trivial inference from \(A\) to \(A\). (For if \(A\) is true at world \(w\), then \(A\) is true at world \(w\)! An impossible world may represent *that it is not the case that A entails A*; but unless there are true contradictions, it cannot both represent and not represent that *A.*) Are there any others? This is the *granularity issue*. In addressing the issue, a good starting place is the *Nolan-Zalta Principle* (Nolan 1997: 542; Zalta 1997: 647): * (NZ) If it is impossible that \(A\), then there's an impossible world which represents that \(A\). (This is not an 'if and only if', since the converse is clearly false: some impossible world represents your reading this article, yet that's not at all impossible. Impossible worlds represent possible *and* impossible situations. The things they represent make for an impossible bunch, but might each be possible when taken individually.) The principle has some intuitive force. Nolan thinks of it as a kind of unrestricted 'comprehension principle' for impossibilities. It tells something about which impossible worlds there are. There will be worlds which represent that water is not H\(\_2\)O, that \(2+2=5\), and that snow both is and is not white. One might think that (NZ) entails that 'anything goes' with regard to impossible worlds: that any logical principle (except \(A \vDash A)\) will be broken by some impossible world. If so, then (NZ) delivers the open worlds mentioned above. However, to apply (NZ), we need a single object-language sentence \(A\) which describes an impossibility. Logical laws, by contrast, are stated as relationships between *multiple* object-language sentences. So it is not clear that (NZ) does its intended work. Priest (2016) adopts two principles that are similar to, but stronger than, (NZ): 'everything holds at some worlds, and everything fails at some worlds' (Priest 2016, 5) and, for any distinct \(A\), \(B\), 'there are worlds where \(A\) holds and \(B\) fails' (Priest 2016, 7). More specifically, in our terminology: * (4.1) For any \(A\), there is a world which represents that \(A\) and a world which does not represent that \(A\). * (4.2) For any distinct \(A\) and \(B\), there is a world which represents that \(A\) but does not represent that \(B\). Priest calls these the 'primary directive' and 'secondary directive' on impossible worlds, respectively. The latter implies the former, which in turn implies (NZ), but neither converse holds. To illustrate the extra power (4.2) gives us (over (4.1) and (NZ)), consider *Simplification*, the inference from \(A \wedge B\) to \(A\), or *Disjunction Introduction*, from \(A\) to \(A \vee B\). (4.2) directly entails that there are worlds where these rules fail. So, if we find (4.2) plausible, we can infer that impossible worlds are not, in general, governed by standard paraconsistent logics. A *paraconsistent logic* is any one in which cont radictory premises \(A\), \(\neg A\) do not entail arbitrary conclusions. But standardly, paraconsistent logics maintain the principle that conjunctions are true just in case both conjuncts are; disjunctions are true just in case at least one disjunct is; and double negations \(\neg \neg A\) are true just in case \(A\) is. If we accept (4.2), then these relationships will break down in some impossible worlds. Yet even with (4.2) in play, it doesn't follow that 'anything goes' with impossible worlds. No principle so far entails that some impossible world breaks the Adjunction rule, from \(A\) and \(B\) to \(A \wedge B\), simply because 4.2 doesn't apply to inferences with multiple premises. (We discuss Adjunction-violating worlds further in section 5.2 below.) To infer the 'anything goes' conclusion, that for any logically valid inference there is some impossible world that breaks it, we'll need this principle: * (NZ\(^+\)) If it is impossible that \(A\_1, A\_2,\ldots\) but not \(B\), then there's an impossible world which represents that \(A\_1, A\_2,\ldots\) but not \(B\). However, we can hardly claim that we've derived the 'anything goes' picture of impossible worlds from this principle, for it is, in effect, an explicit statement of that very view. Whilst the original (NZ) has a good deal of intuitive force, it's much harder to feel that way about (NZ\(^+)\). There may be no completely general, intuitively motivated principle (along the lines of (NZ)) from which we can ascertain just how fine-grained impossible worlds should be. Nevertheless, there are arguments which support the 'anything goes' picture, on which there exist open worlds (those closed under no valid inferences except \(A \vDash A)\). We'll briefly consider three such arguments. The first is simple. If impossible worlds can break some logical rule, then why can't they break all of them? Suppose we fix on standard proof rules for the connectives. Each such rule is as closely tied to the meaning of the associated connective as the others are (to their associated connectives). Yet, as each logically impossible world breaks at least one of those rules, what's to stop some other impossible world from breaking any of the other rules? This argument has some intuitive force, but is clearly far from conclusive. The second argument is from epistemic states. When we consider real-world finite and fallible epistemic agents, there seem to be no rules of the form: if someone believes \(A\_1, A\_2,\ldots\), then they must believe (distinct) \(B\) (that's why the logical omniscience problem discussed in 2.3 is hard!). If we model their epistemic states in terms of worlds, then at least one of the worlds must break the inference from \(A\_1, A\_2,\ldots\) to \(B.\) So each logical inference (except \(A \vDash A)\) is broken by some world (Jago 2014a; Priest 2016). The third argument is from counterpossible reasoning. Suppose, in a class on alternative logics, we consider what would happen if Excluded Middle \((\vDash A \vee \neg A)\), Double-Negation Elimination \((\neg \neg A \vDash A)\), or the Law of Explosion \((A, \neg A \vDash B)\) were to fail. If classical logic is the one true logic, and logical necessity is absolute, we're then reasoning counterpossibly. If we want to analyse counterpossibles in general using impossible worlds, then we'll need worlds where these principles fail. But we seem to be able to reason this way, non-trivially, for any kind of logical principle, and so our analysis will require open worlds (Priest 2016). Why have we spared \(A \vDash A\) so far? Well, it seems that in order to break this, an impossible world would simultaneously have to represent that \(A\) and not represent that \(A\). Such a world would itself be an impossible object, one with inconsistent features. Since most impossible worlds theorists maintain that impossible worlds (actually) exist and that actuality is not inconsistent, this position is ruled out. It is available to *dialetheists* and others who allow reality to have inconsistent features. There seems to be no theoretical cost in requiring \(A \vDash A\) to hold at all worlds (impossible or otherwise). Going back to epistemic states, for example, we want to represent inconsistent beliefs, such as someone's believing both that \(A\) and that \(\neg A\) at the same time; but it would be a mistake to infer that she both believes and does not believe that \(A\). ### 4.2 The Closeness of Impossible Worlds If impossible worlds display different degrees of logical structure (or lack thereof), it may make sense to order them. A natural way to do this is via an extension of the traditional "closeness" relations between possible worlds. How to spell out the ordering in detail, though, is far from straightforward. Within standard conditional logics, and in the treatment of counterfactual conditionals in terms of possible worlds due to Robert Stalnaker (1968) and David Lewis (1973), worlds stand in similarity relations; and similarity comes in degrees. This is usually represented by having each possible world, \(w\), come with a system of "spheres". If \(W\) is the set of all worlds, let \(\$\) be a function from worlds to sets of subsets of \(W\), so that \(\$w = \{S\_1, S\_2 , \ldots \}\), with \(w \in S\_1 \subseteq S\_2 \subseteq \ldots = W\). Worlds within a given sphere \(S\_i\) are more similar to \(w\) than worlds outside it. If we take the special case in which \(w =\) the actual world (call it "@"), we get a natural arrangement of possible worlds in a system of spheres that mirrors their degree of (dis)similarity with respect to @, according to the different kinds of possibilities and (relative) impossibilities they represent. For instance, a world which is exactly like @, except that Franz wears a white t-shirt instead of the black one he's actually wearing while writing these lines, is, intuitively, closer to @ than a world at which the laws of physics are turned upside down. Some people have a general, intuitive depiction of such closeness relations, and set out a hierarchy of modalities accordingly: possible worlds where the laws of physics are different from ours are naturally seen as more eccentric than worlds where only biological, but not physical, laws are different; and these are more eccentric than possible worlds with minimal factual changes with respect to @, such as the white t-shirt world. Can such a natural view be extended to impossible worlds? First, it is intuitive to claim that some impossible worlds are more similar to the actual world @ than others. For instance, the "explosion" world (call it \(e)\) at which everything is the case (every sentence is true) seems to be as far from @ as one can imagine, if one can actually imagine or conceive such an extremely absurd situation. Now, pick the impossible world, \(t\), at which everything is as in @, except that Franz wears an impossible t-shirt which is white all over and black all over. Intuitively, \(t\) is closer to @ than \(e\). Next, some authors (e.g. Mares 1997) favor Nolan's SIC principle (introduced in section 2.5). This implies that any possible world is closer to @ than any impossible world is to @. A system of spheres for impossible worlds centered on @ will just extend the intuitive possible worlds spheres described above, by adding further, larger spheres where worlds outside (logical, or more generally unrestricted) possibility stand. But how are these latter to be internally ordered? One very general option is the following. Even though we subscribe to some unrestricted comprehension principle for impossible worlds, we may admit that worlds where only the intensional operators, e.g., the box and diamond of necessity and possibility, behave in a non-standard fashion are less deviant than worlds where also the extensional operators, like classical conjunction and disjunction, do. Let us call worlds of the former kind *intensionally* impossible and worlds of the latter kind *extensionally* impossible. This picture (inspired by Priest 2005, Chapter 1) has some intuitive force to recommend it. Kripkean non-normal worlds, where only the behaviour of the modal operators is non-standard (see section 5.1), are intuitively less deviant than open worlds, where all formulas may behave arbitrarily. Generalizing, the view would entail arranging the respective spheres in such a way that any intensionally impossible world is closer to @ than any extensionally impossible one. This very general ordering of impossibilities, albeit intuitive, may not be fully satisfying. A general qualm concerns the SIC principle itself. For one may claim that, intuitively, some slightly deviant impossible worlds may be *more* similar to the actual world @ than some possible but very weird worlds. For instance, the impossible world \(t\) above, which is like @ except for Franz's wearing an inconsistent T-shirt, may look more familiar than a world which is logically possible, but where the laws of physics are turned upside down. Several authors (Nolan 1997, Vander Laan 2004, Bernstein 2016) have proposed putative counterexamples to SIC along these lines. Although we cannot pursue this topic further within the limits of this entry, the discussion developed so far should show that the issue of the structure, closeness, and ordering of impossible worlds is quite open. ## 5. The Logic(s) of Impossible Worlds This section is a bit more technical than the others. None of the other sections presuppose this material. ### 5.1 Impossible Worlds in Non-Normal Modal Logics Possible worlds semantics is celebrated for providing suitable interpretations for different axiomatic systems of modal logic, such as C.I. Lewis's systems \(\mathbf{S4}\) and \(\mathbf{S5}\) (Lewis and Langford 1931). In each model, sentences are evaluated as true or false relative to a possible world. Modal sentences \(\Box A\) and \(\Diamond A\) (usually read as 'it is necessary that \(A\)' and 'it is possible that \(A\)', respectively) are evaluated in terms of \(A\)'s truth at all or some of the *accessible* worlds. By placing various conditions on the accessibility relation between worlds, different modal logics can be accommodated. (Readers unfamiliar with modal logic are advised again to read the entities on possible worlds and modal logic before going further in this section.) This approach validates the *Necessitation* inference rule: If \(A\) is valid, then so is \(\Box A\). (In symbols: if \(\vDash A\) then \(\vDash \Box A\).) To see why, suppose \(A\) is a logical truth. Then in any model, it is true at all possible worlds. So given any world \(w\) in an arbitrary model, \(A\) is true at all worlds accessible from \(w\), hence \(\Box A\) is true at \(w\), and so \(\Box A\) too is valid. Logics in which the Necessitation rule is valid are called *normal modal logics*. But historically, not all of the modal logics of interest are normal logics. C.I. Lewis's systems \(\mathbf{S2}\) and \(\mathbf{S3}\) (Lewis and Langford 1931) are non-normal logics, for example. These logics are *weaker* than normal modal logics, in the sense that they support fewer valid inferences. To give a worlds-based semantics for such logics, we need to look beyond possible worlds. In 1965, Saul Kripke introduced a special kind of world, the *non-normal worlds*, in order to provide semantics for non-normal modal logics. Let us introduce some simple semantic machinery for propositional modal logic. Take a non-normal interpretation of a propositional modal language, \(\langle W, N, R, v\rangle\), where \(W\) is a set of worlds; \(N\) is a proper subset of \(W\), the set of *normal* worlds; \(R\) is a binary accessibility relation between worlds; and \(v\) is a valuation function assigning truth values to formulas at worlds: "\(v\_w(A)\)" denotes the truth value of \(A\) at world \(w\). Worlds in \(W - N\) are the non-normal worlds. The truth conditions for the extensional logical vocabulary (negation, conjunction, disjunction, the material conditional) are given the usual way. The same holds for the modal operators of necessity \(\Box\) and possibility \(\Diamond\), but only at *normal* worlds. If \(w\) is non-normal, the truth conditions for the modalizers go as follows: \[\begin{align} v\_w (\Box A) &= 0 \\ v\_w (\Diamond A) &= 1 \end{align}\] where 1 stands for *true*, 0 for *false*. At non-normal worlds, formulas of the form PS\(A\), with PS a modal, are not evaluated depending on the truth value of \(A\) at other (accessible) worlds, but get assigned their truth value directly: all box-formulas are false and all diamond-formulas are true. In a sense, at non-normal worlds nothing is necessary, and anything is possible. These worlds, however, are deviant only in this respect: their behavior, as far as the extensional connectives are concerned, is quite regular. In some (though not all) worlds semantics, logical validity and consequence are defined relative to just the *normal* worlds. The idea is that the normal worlds behave 'appropriately' with respect to the logic in question, whereas the non-normal worlds do not. For example, \(\Box(A \vee \neg A)\) is valid in \(\mathbf{S2}\) and \(\mathbf{S3}\), but (by definition) it is false at the non-normal worlds. So we need to ignore the non-normal worlds when defining validity and consequence, which we do as follows: \(A\) is *valid* \((\vDash A)\) if and only if, for all *normal* worlds \(w\) in all models, \(v\_w (A) = 1\). Premises \(S\) entail \(A (S \vDash A)\) if and only if, for all *normal* worlds \(w\) in all models: if \(v\_w (B) = 1\) for all premises \(B \in\) S, then \(v\_w (A) = 1\). Even though we have ignored the non-normal worlds in this definition, they still play a role in invalidating Necessitation. For take any classical propositional tautology, say \(A \vee \neg A\). This holds at all worlds of all models, so \(\Box(A \vee \neg A)\) holds at all normal worlds and hence is valid. But \(\Box(A \vee \neg A)\) holds at no non-normal world. Now suppose \(w\) is a normal world that has access to any non-normal world. Then \(\Box \Box(A \vee \neg A)\) is false at \(w\) and so (since \(w\) is normal) \(\Box \Box(A \vee \neg A)\) is not valid. That's a counterexample to Necessitation. In these semantics for non-normal modal logics such as \(\mathbf{S2}\) and \(\mathbf{S3}\), the valuation function assigns the same truth value to all box formulas (false) and all diamond formulas (true) at non-normal worlds. But we can do things differently. In Cresswell's (1966) semantics for the modal system **S0.5** (due to E.J. Lemmon 1957), sentences beginning with a modality are assigned *arbitrary* truth values. The valuation function \(v\) treats modal sentences as if they were atomic sentences. (Interpretations for \(\mathbf{S2}\) or \(\mathbf{S3}\) are thus special cases of the interpretations for **S0.5**.) The idea of considering impossible (non-normal) worlds as worlds at which complex formulas are treated as atomic one is a popular one, as we will see below. Kripke introduced non-normal worlds as a technical device in order to treat C.I. Lewis' non-normal modal logics; the question of the *interpretation* of such structures (particularly, of the ontological status of impossible worlds), then, makes perfect sense -- and the answer is not straightforward, as have seen in section 3. ### 5.2 Nonadjunctive and Nonprime Impossible Worlds In 1980, Nicholas Rescher and Robert Brandom published *The Logic of Inconsistency. A Study in Non-Standard Possible-Worlds Semantics and Ontology*. They introduced a modal semantics including, besides ordinary possible worlds (taken as maximally consistent collections of states of affairs), also non-standard worlds that are locally inconsistent (such that, for some \(A\), both \(A\) and \(\neg A\) hold at them), and incomplete (such that for some \(A\), neither \(A\) nor \(\neg A\) hold at them). These are obtained combinatorially, via two recursive operations having standard worlds as their base, and called *schematization* \((\cap)\) and *superposition* \((\cup)\). Given two worlds \(w\_1\) and \(w\_2\), a schematic world \(w\_1 \cap w\_2\) is one at which all and only the states of affairs obtain, which obtain both at \(w\_1\) and at \(w\_2\). Dually, a "superposed" or inconsistent world \(w\_1 \cup w\_2\) is one at which all and only the states of affairs obtain, which obtain at \(w\_1\) or at \(w\_2\). Rescher and Brandom's inconsistent-superposed worlds are, therefore, impossible worlds of the fourth kind: Contradiction Realizers making both \(A\) and its negation true, for some \(A\) (just superpose, for instance, a possible world, \(w\_1\), at which I am 1.70m tall, and another possible world, \(w\_2\), at which I am 1.90m tall). The assignment of truth values at such worlds is not (obviously) compositional with respect to conjunction. The standard semantic clause interprets the '\(\wedge\)' symbol using our world 'and': * (S\(\wedge\)) \(v\_w (A \wedge B) = 1\) if and only if \(v\_w (A) = 1\) and \(v\_w (B) = 1\) But the right-to-left direction will have to go, if \(w\) is one of Rescher and Brandom's impossible worlds. These worlds are *nonadjunctive*: they allow two sentences to be true even though their conjunction is not true. (*Adjunction* is the principle that the truth of a conjunction follows from the truth of its conjuncts.) Rescher and Brandom's worlds can also be *nonprime*: a disjunction may hold at them even though neither disjunct does. They may also make some \(A\) and its negation \(\neg A\) both true. But the corresponding conjunction, \(A \wedge \neg A\), doesn't follow. These impossible worlds retain a certain amount of logical structure. They are closed under any classically valid, essentially single-premised inference (such as *Disjunction Introduction*); but they are not closed under essentially multiple-premised inferences (such as *Adjunction*). Rescher and Brandom's approach falls in the nonadjunctive tradition (see Berto 2007, Chapter 6) of paraconsistent logics: a tradition started by Jaskowksi's *discussive logic* \(\mathbf{D}\_2\) (also labeled as \(\mathbf{J}\) in the literature, Jaskowski 1948), and based on the idea of rejecting or limiting the Adjunction principle. Such an approach has been revived in works by Hyde (1997), and Varzi (1997 and 2004). ### 5.3 Impossible Worlds in Epistemic Logic To model a concept such as knowledge, we can use a modality '\(K\)' for 'knows that', with semantics along the lines of '\(\Box\)', quantifying over all epistemically possible worlds: worlds which are ways things could be, for all one knows, or given the information or evidence one has available. This is *epistemic modal logic*. (See the entry on epistemic logic for background material.) This approach has proved to be very useful. However, when epistemically possible worlds confirm to the rules of logically possible worlds, the following principle is valid: (Closure) If \(KA\) and \(A\) entails \(B\), then \(KB\) This principle says that one knows all the logical consequences of the things one knows. A special case of this principle says that all valid formulas are known: (Validity) If \(A\) is valid, then so is \(KA\) But these principles seem false. You don't know all the logical and mathematical truths, and there are truths which follow from what you know which you don't know. (You might be indifferent to those truths; you might even disbelieve them.) This is the problem of *logical omniscience* (see epistemic logic again). There is a rich literature on the problem (Alechina et al. 2004, Duc 1997, Hintikka 1975, Jago 2014a,b, Rantala 1982a), including some who defend these seemingly false principles (Stalnaker 1991, 1999). Exactly the same holds for belief (treated with a modality '\(B\)' along the lines of '\(K\)'). The modal epistemic approach tells us that, as well as believing all consequences of what we believe, we must hold a perfectly consistent set of beliefs: (Consistency) \(\vDash \neg(BA \wedge B\neg A)\). This is a hard principle to defend, as anyone who has reflected on their own beliefs will appreciate. A popular method of avoiding these principles (beginning with Cresswell 1973 and Hintikka 1975) is to allow impossible worlds into the account. Consider again Rescher and Brandom's nonadjunctive and nonprime worlds, at which conjunction and disjunction behave anarchically. Rantala (1982a) takes the idea further, introducing worlds at which *any* connective may behave anarchically. Rantala's approach divides the worlds into *normal* and *non-normal* ones. Normal worlds behave like possible worlds whereas at non-normal worlds, *every* sentence is assigned an arbitrary truth value. In effect, complex sentences \(\neg A, A \vee B\), and so on, are treated as if they were atomic sentences. The truth value of \(\neg A\) is independent of \(A\); the value of \(A \vee B\) is independent of the values of \(A\) and \(B\) at a non-normal world; and so on for the other complex sentences. These non-normal worlds are thus a very anarchic form of impossible world. Priest (2005, 2016) calls them *open* worlds, since they are not closed under any rule of inference (other than the trivial rule allowing one to infer \(A\) from \(A\); see also Jago 2014a). Logical consequence and validity are defined with respect to possible (normal) worlds only. Impossible worlds come into play only when evaluating knowledge claims, \(KA\). So, ignoring \(K\)-sentences, the logic is classical. But the logic of \(K\)-sentences is not closed under any non-trivial rule of inference, thereby dispensing with Closure, Validity, and (in the case of belief) Consistency. An agent is modelled as having inconsistent beliefs, for example, simply by treating an impossible world where both \(A\) and \(\neg A\) are true as being epistemically accessible (from the actual world) for that agent. The approach has been generalized to quantified modal logics (Rantala 1982b) and developed into a unified framework for epistemic logics (Wansing 1989, 1990). Wansing has shown that various logics for knowledge and belief developed in Artificial Intelligence can find equivalent models in structures including impossible worlds. Further equivalence results in this area have been obtained in Sillari 2008, where it is shown that impossible worlds structures using binary epistemic accessibility relations are equivalent to structures using Montague-Scott neighborhood semantics. This kind of approach faces problems, however. If there's no logical structure to impossible worlds, then we might do as well to model an agent's knowledge using an arbitrary set of sentences, as in Konolige 1986. The worry is that unconstrained impossible worlds semantics makes no real progress over this purely syntactic approach (Jago 2007, 2009). One may instead adopt impossible worlds that retain *some* logical structure, e.g., worlds closed under some weaker-than-classical logical consequence. One approach of this kind is found in Levesque 1984 (see also Cresswell 1973). This employs impossible worlds of the kind used in paraconsistent relevant logics, which can be locally inconsistent and incomplete but are well-behaved with respect to conjunction and disjunction, that is, they are adjunctive and prime. Laws of classical logic fail at them, and by accessing them a cognitive agent can have inconsistent beliefs. However, we still have a weakened form of logical omniscience: the beliefs of an agent are closed under the weaker paraconsistent-relevant logic at issue. This seems incorrect as an attempt to model finite agents. Rasmussen (2015) and Bjerring and Skipper (2019) present a *dynamic* impossible worlds solution to the logical omniscience problem. Agents' beliefs evolve over time due to *epistemic actions*, on this approach (see the entry on dynamic epistemic logic for background). Bjerring and Skipper focus on *deductive* actions. Agents count as competent insofar as they unfold the consequences of their beliefs, up to a certain depth of reasoning. Their operator "\(\langle n\rangle KA\)", says: "After some \(n\)-step chain of logical reasoning, the agent comes to know that \(A\)". The agent can update its epistemic state by kicking out choices of impossible worlds which were epistemic possibilities before the deduction took place. One can show that if a formula \(A\) follows from formulas \(A\_1, \ldots, A\_n\) in \(n\) steps of reasoning, then \(KA\_1, \ldots, KA\_n\) together entail \(\langle n\rangle KA\). Impossible worlds are starting to be used not only in formal, but also in mainstream and Bayesian epistemology. Modal accounts of knowledge invoking possible worlds, whether based on the notion of safety or on that of sensitivity, make all necessary or logical truths trivially sensitive and safe. Melchior 2021 proposes to address the issue by using impossible worlds. Probabilistic-Bayesian accounts of credences or degrees of belief can be formulated using logically possible worlds and sets thereof, to which probabilities are assigned by credence functions obeying the Kolmogorov axioms of probability. As noted by Pettigrew 2021, this models logically omniscient, idealised agents who assign probability 1 to all logical truths and never have higher credences in any given premises than in their logical consequences. To model rational but more realistic agents, Pettigrew introduces a setting similar to that Berto and Jago 2019 had for all-or-nothing beliefs. He resorts to "personally possible worlds" which make true what a rational but cognitively limited agent believes and has not (yet) ruled out using its bounded cognitive resources. Such worlds are in fact impossible worlds of the open kind. ### 5.4 Impossible Worlds in Relevance Logic Relevance logic (or relevant logic) is an attempt to capture the idea that good reasoning requires a genuine condition between premises and conclusions. This should go beyond a mere guarantee of truth preservation. For when a conclusion \(A\) is guaranteed to be true (for example, when it is a logical truth), *any* argument concluding in \(A\) will preserve truth from premises to conclusions. But those premises may have no genuine connection whatsoever to what \(A\) is about. The same consideration applies when taking a conditional \(A \rightarrow B\) to be valid: there should be a genuine connection between \(A\) and \(B\). With this in mind, relevance logic attempts to avoid the 'fallacies of relevance' (also called 'paradoxes of the material conditional'). These are conditionals that are valid in classical and modal logic, simply because the antecedent is a necessary falsehood or the consequent is a necessary truth, but without a guarantee of any real connection between them. Examples include \(A \wedge \neg A \rightarrow B\) (*ex contradictione quodlibet*, or the Law of Explosion), \(A \rightarrow B \vee \neg B\), and \(A \rightarrow (B \rightarrow B)\) (*verum ex quolibet*). Contradiction-realizing impossible worlds can help us avoid *ex contradictione quodlibet*, if they are worlds where some contradiction \(A \wedge \neg A\) is true but some other \(B\) is not true. For that reason, various systems of relevant logic have been given semantics which include (things naturally thought of as) impossible worlds. A *Routley-Meyer* interpretation (see Routley and Routley 1972; Routley and Meyer 1973, 1976; Routley 1979) for relevant (propositional) logics is a structure \(\langle W, N, R, {}^\*, v\rangle\), where \(W\) is a set of worlds; \(N\) is a proper subset of \(W\) including the normal or possible worlds (the remaining worlds are the non-normal or impossible worlds); \(R\) is a *ternary* accessibility relation between worlds, and \({}^\*\) (the *Routley star*) is a function from worlds to worlds. \({}^\*\) and \(R\) figure prominently in the truth conditions for negation and the (relevant) conditional. Their task is precisely to provide a semantics for negation that allows for the truth of \(A\) and \(\neg A\) at some worlds, and a semantics for the conditional that frees it from the fallacies of relevance. #### 5.4.1 The Relevant Conditional In order to get rid of such entailments as \(A \rightarrow (B \rightarrow B)\), we need some world at which \(A\) holds but \(B \rightarrow B\) fails. One way to achieve this may be to admit "partial" or incomplete situations of the kind studied in situation semantics, at which \(A\) holds but \(B \rightarrow B\) fails to hold, just because they carry no information about \(B\). Another way is via impossible worlds: an understanding of such worlds, as we have seen, is as scenarios where logical laws may fail, and the Law of (propositional) Identity, stating that any formula entails itself, is one of them. At possible worlds, we still require for the truth of conditionals \(A \rightarrow B\) that at every accessible world where \(A\) holds, \(B\) holds, too. Consequently, \(A \rightarrow(B \rightarrow B)\) is not logically valid. Technically, when \(w\) is an impossible world, we state the truth conditions for the conditional, by means of the ternary \(R\), as follows: * (\(\rightarrow\)) \(v\_w (A \rightarrow B) =\) *true* if and only if, for all worlds \(w\_1\) and \(w\_2\) such that \(Rww\_1 w\_2\), if \(v\_{w1}(A) =\) *true*, then \(v\_{w2}(B) =\) *true*. The key difference between \((\rightarrow)\) and the standard modal clause for the strict conditional (which is true at a world if and only if, at all accessible worlds where the antecedent is true, the consequent is true), is that the worlds of the antecedent and the consequent have been "split". Specifically, \(B \rightarrow B\) fails at impossible worlds \(w\) when there are worlds \(w\_1\) and \(w\_2\) such that R\(ww\_1 w\_2, B\) holds at the former, but fails at the latter. Since we do not want \(B \rightarrow B\) to fail at normal/possible worlds, we can add a *Normality Condition*, saying that the accessible worlds \(w\_1\) and \(w\_2\) are one and the same: * (NC) For normal worlds \(w, Rww\_1 w\_2\) only if \(w\_1 = w\_2\). Using the ternary relation \(R\), one can build models for different relevant logics. Starting with the basic relevant system \(\mathbf{B}\), one obtains models for stronger logics such as \(\mathbf{R}\), the system of relevant implication, by adding additional conditions on \(R\). (This is similar to the way we may move on from basic modal logic \(\mathbf{K}\) to the systems \(\mathbf{T}, \mathbf{S4}\), and \(\mathbf{S5}\), by adding extra conditions on the accessibility relation.) The constraints to be added to the ternary \(R\) are more complex than those of standard modal logic and some involve the star operator \({}^\*\) (which we'll address shortly). It isn't easy to provide an intuitive reading for the ternary relation \(R\). The basic idea is that the truth of an entailment \(A \rightarrow B\) at a world \(w\) depends on \(w\)'s "seeing an accessibility" (Bremer 2005: 67) between two other worlds \(w\_1\) and \(w\_2\), such that if \(A\) is true at the former, \(B\) is true at the latter. But what does this mean? This is perhaps the most important philosophical issue facing semantics for relevant logics. One approach is the information-based account of Mares (2004, 2009, 2010) and Restall (1995), based on situation semantics. Another approach draws on various interpretations of *conditionality*, such as those found in the literature on conditional logics (Beall et al. 2012). (See the entry on relevance logic or Jago 2013c for further discussion.) #### 5.4.2 The Routley Star Given a world \(w\), the Routley star function outputs a world \(w^\*\) which is, in a sense, its "reverse twin". The truth conditions for negation within the Routley-Meyer semantics are: * (\(\neg\)) \(v\_w (\neg A) =\) *true* if and only if \(v\_{w^\*}(A) =\) *false*. So \(\neg A\) is true at a world \(w\) if and only if \(A\) is false, not at \(w\) itself (as it happens with standard negation), but at its twin \(w^\*\). Relevant negation is therefore an *intensional* operator: in order to evaluate negated sentences at \(w\), we may need to check the goings on at some other world. Adding appropriate constraints provides this negation with many intuitive inferential features. If \(w^{\*\*} = w\) for all worlds \(w\), for example, Double Negation introduction and elimination is valid. This is often called *De Morgan* negation, for De Morgan's Laws hold of it. But it does not validate the Law of Explosion (that a contradiction entails any sentence). For a counterexample, take a model where \(A\) holds at \(w, B\) doesn't hold at \(w\), and \(A\) doesn't hold at \(w^\*\). Then, both \(A\) and \(\neg A\) hold at \(w\), whereas \(B\) doesn't: \(w\) is an inconsistent but non-trivial world. What is the intuitive connection between \(w\) and \(w^\*\)? The idea is that the twins are "mirror images one of the other reversing 'in' and 'out'" (Dunn 1986: 191). If \(w\) is \(A\)-inconsistent (both \(A\) and \(\neg A\) hold), then \(w^\*\) is \(A\)-incomplete (neither \(A\) nor \(\neg A\) hold), and vice versa. The \({}^\*\) takes local inconsistency into local incompleteness and vice versa. It may also be the case that \(w = w^\*\): the twins are in fact one. In that case, \(w\) must be a maximal and consistent world, where negation behaves classically: \(\neg A\) is true if and only if \(A\) is false *there*. ## 6. Objections to Impossible Worlds This last section discusses some difficulties for impossible worlds theories. ### 6.1 The Exportation Principle Suppose that the expression 'at world \(w\)' works as a restricting modifier: its main task consists in restricting the quantifiers within its scope to parts of \(w\) (Lewis 1986). If so, then it should distribute through the truth-functional connectives. This means in particular that \[ \text{At } w: (A \wedge \neg A) \] will entail the contradiction \[ (\text{At } w: A) \wedge \neg (\text{at } w: A). \] This is the *exportation principle*. It is disastrous for any theory of impossible worlds. It implies that an inconsistency at some impossible world will spill over into an overt inconsistency. A true contradiction at some \(w\) implies that there are true contradictions, full stop. This is hard to swallow, unless one is a dialetheist. (And even dialethists may want to reject the exportation principle for impossible worlds: see Jago 2013b.) Avoiding the exportation principle is not difficult, however (Kiourti 2010, Chapter 4; Jago 2013b). For it to be valid, it seems to require genuine worlds, as in Lewis's (1986) genuine modal realism or Yagisawa's (1988, 2010) extended modal realism. Adopting an ersatz conception of worlds blocks the principle. If a world represents that \(A\) (say, by containing a sentence or proposition expressing *that A*), but is not in itself such that \(A\), then the principle is blocked. 'At \(w: (A \wedge \neg A)\)' will be interpreted as: \(w\) contains the sentence (or proposition) *that A* \(\wedge \neg A\), whereas 'at \(w: A\)' will mean that \(w\) contains the sentence (or proposition) *that A*, and 'not at \(w: A\)' will mean that \(w\) does not contain the sentence (or proposition) *that A.* But an impossible world may contain both, or neither, of \(A\) and \(\neg A\), so that containing one implies nothing about containing the other. An impossible world may (depending on how fine-grained we take them to be) also contain the conjunction \(A \wedge \neg A\) independently of whether it contains both \(A\) and \(\neg A.\) So the inference from 'at \(w: (A \wedge \neg A)\)' to '(at \(w: A) \wedge \neg\)(at \(w: A)\)' is blocked (possibly twice over). It is controversial whether any genuine account of worlds can block the exportation principle. Jago 2013a,b argues not; Yagisawa 2015 responds in defence of genuine impossible worlds. ### 6.2 Defining Possibility If there are impossible worlds, then we cannot accept the simple clause for possibility: * (P) It is possible that \(A\) if and only if there's a world \(w\) such that, at \(w\), \(A\). Once impossible worlds enter the stage, (P) becomes false from right to left. We therefore need a principle that restricts the quantification in the right half of the biconditional to *possible* worlds. How to do that, without appealing to modal notions, is not straightforward. A hybrid account (Berto 2010) can answer the objection, by taking possible worlds to be all and only the genuine ones, with impossible worlds as ersatz constructions of some kind. We can then capture the intent of (P) as: * (P\({}^\*\)) It is possible that \(A\) if and only if there's a genuine world \(w\) such that, at \(w\), \(A\). Note that it doesn't matter if the hybrid account accepts the existence of ersatz possible worlds in addition to her genuine possible worlds: (P\({}^\*\)) will still give the right result. The ersatzist may respond by biting the bullet. Even without admitting impossible worlds, most possible worlds accounts do not aim at providing a reductive and complete analysis of modality. (Lewis's modal realism does. But it may not succeed, when so-called 'alien' properties, not instantiated by anything at the actual world nor obtainable as constructions out of actually instantiated properties, enter the stage. See Divers 2002, Chapter 7; Divers and Melia 2002.) ### 6.3 The Usefulness of Impossible Worlds Stalnaker (1996) argues that, whilst there is nothing wrong in admitting impossible worlds, not much explanatory work can be expected from them. For instance, if one takes worlds as sets of propositions, one cannot then analyze propositions as sets of worlds. But an advocate of impossible worlds may respond that the same point can be made against any account of possible worlds (such as Adams's) that takes them to be maximally consistent sets of propositions. And, just as ersatz possible worlds needn't be constructed in this way, nor need ersatz impossible worlds. Impossible worlds have found many uses in the recent literature, as we have abundantly seen. So we don't find Stalnaker's worry convincing. ### 6.4 The Semantics of Negation The standard semantic clause for negation has it that \(\neg A\) is true if and only if \(A\) is not true. So there could not be worlds at which both or neither of \(A\) and \(\neg A\) are true, unless we revise the semantics of negation. Stalnaker (1996) argues that negation is such a basic operator, whose semantics is 'learned in a first logic class' that it had better be left alone. To this, the impossible world theorist can reply that it is in fact the case that \(\neg A\) is true if and only if \(A\) is not true; for this concerns truth *simpliciter*, that is, truth at the actual world. She may also agree that the same holds for any possible world. But it is precisely *im*possible worlds that we are talking about here; how negation works at any possible world need not be affected by the fact that, at some impossible world or other, some sentence can hold together with its negation: this is one of the things that makes them impossible, after all. ### 6.5 Counterpossible Reasoning Timothy Williamson (2007, Chapter 5) has objected to non-trivial treatments of counterpossibles, in particular (though not perforce) when they resort to impossible worlds. Consider the claim: 1. If \(5 + 7\) were 13, then \(5 + 6\) would be 12. *Prima facie*, this is a non-trivially true counterpossible. However, Williamson argues, other non-trivial consequences of the supposition would then be that \(5 + 5 = 11\), and \(5 + 4 = 10\), and ... , and \(0 = 1\). Therefore, 2. If the number of answers I gave to a given question were 0, then the number of answers I gave would be 1. But (2) is clearly false. Brogaard and Salerno (2007) pose a dilemma for Williamson: either we hold the context fixed in this kind of counterpossible reasoning, or we don't. If we don't, then (2) does not follow from (1). In particular, the context at which (2) comes out false is one at which the closest antecedent worlds are possible and, to be sure, at those worlds, 0 is not 1. But if we hold the context fixed, then what does follow is just the following counterpossible: 3. If 0 were 1 and the number of right answers I gave were 0, then the number of right answers I gave would be 1. Now this is intuitively true, and non-trivially so. Williamson (2007) also argues that non-trivial treatments of counterpossibles create opaque contexts, in which the substitutivity of co-referential terms fails. Supporters of non-trivial counterpossibles will take the following conditional as false: 4. If Hesperus had not been Phosphorus, then Phosphorus would not have been Phosphorus. Given the necessity of identity, (4) is a counterpossible: as Hesperus is Phosphorus, its antecedent can only be true at impossible worlds. That's false, supposedly, because even if Hesperus and Phosphorus had been distinct, Phosphorus would have remained self-identical. However, all accept that 5. If Hesperus had not been Phosphorus, then Hesperus would not have been Phosphorus since it is an instance of 'if it had been that \(A\), then it would have been that \(A\)'. Yet substituting 'Phosphorus' for the first occurrence of 'Hesperus' in the consequent of (5) gives (4). Since (5) is true and (4) is (supposedly) false, substitution of identicals has failed. This failure of substitutivity, Williamson claims, is a bad result, for counterfactuals should *not* create opaque contexts. Brogaard and Salerno (2013) accept that counterpossibles do create opaque contexts. They argue that the impossible worlds similarity semantics for counterpossibles should be "partially epistemic" (Brogaard and Salerno 2013: 654), and this epistemic component explains the failure of substitution. An alternative reply to Williamson is that the objection is question-begging. It is clearly false that counterfactuals allow substitution of identical terms (of arbitrary type). 'Had Aristotle never taught, Aristotle would still have been Aristotle' is true, and Aristotle is the teacher of Alexander, yet 'had Aristotle never taught, Aristotle would still have been the teacher of Alexander' is clearly false. The substitution principle must (at the least) be restricted to *rigid designators*: terms that denote the same entity in all *metaphysically possible* worlds. But if the definition of 'rigid designator' is to be restricted to *possible* worlds, then the application of the corresponding substitution principle should likewise be restricted to contexts which do not invoke impossible worlds. Viewed from this perspective, it is question-begging to insist at the outset that the substitution principle (for rigid designators) is valid for all counterfactuals (including counterpossibles). Berto et al. 2018 is an extensive discussion of a number of Williamsonian objections to non-trivial treatments of counterpossibles. ### 6.6 Compositionality *Compositionality* is the principle that the meaning or content of a complex expression is a function of the meanings of its constituent expressions. It's commonly taken to be a mandatory feature of any adequate theory of meaning and content. The argument is that, as competent speakers of a language, we are in principle capable of grasping the meanings of a potentially infinite number of sentences. And since we've learnt the meanings of a limited number of words, this is possible only if the meanings of complex sentences are obtainable recursively from the meanings of their constituent parts (Davidson 1965). The worry is that a theory of meaning or content which includes impossible worlds will not be compositional. Consider what we said above about the exportation principle (Section 6.1) and the semantics of negation (Section 6.4). An impossible world may represent that \(\neg A\) independently of whether it represents that \(A\). But then, for such worlds, the truth-value of \(\neg A\) is not a function of the truth-value of \(A\). So, the worry goes, the content or proposition that \(\neg A\), understood as a set of possible and impossible worlds, will not be a function of the proposition that \(A\). Certainly, the latter is not the set-theoretic complement of the former, as it is on the possible worlds account. The same goes for all the other logically complex sentences. This is perhaps the most serious objection to the impossible worlds approach. If it can't be met, it may well be fatal. To address the worry, defenders of impossible worlds must show that their notion of content is compositional, even if it does not provide uniform truth-conditions across all worlds. In other words, they must specify a way to calculate complex contents from constituent contents, but which does not go via the usual truth-at-a-world clauses for connectives. As far as we know, the only attempt to achieve this is in Berto and Jago 2019, Chapter 8. They view contents as sets of (possible and impossible) worlds, which are themselves sets of sentences of some 'worldmaking' language. They argue that grammatical structures can thus be recovered from semantic contents, via the syntactic structure of the worldmaking sentences involved. This provides a functional map between grammatical structure and semantic content which in turn, they argue, provides a means for calculating complex contents from their constituents. Whether this provides an acceptable notion of compositionality (as they claim) remains to be seen. The compositionally objection also appears in Williamson 2020, a book mostly devoted to a defense of the extensional material conditional as giving the meaning of the indicative "if", but also dealing with counterfactuals. Williamson accuses hyperintensional approaches to conditionals and to content in general -- whether based on impossible worlds, or of other kinds, e.g., based on truthmakers -- of "overfitting": complicating the semantics in order to account for the variability and systematic inconsistencies of speakers' judgments, with the result of incorporating "noise" in their models. At the extreme of fine-graining, open impossible worlds approaches "must individuate meanings so finely as to restrict synonymy to self-synonymy, and thereby render the conception of meaning theoretically useless, because it filters nothing out" (249). Of course, hyperintensionalists (with impossible worlds sympathies, or of other kind) may equally accuse extensional or merely intensional semantics of "underfitting": conflating contents we may have good reasons to keep distinct. We seem to need some principled way to mark the proper boundaries of semantics. Williamson proposes one: we should pay more attention to a cognitive or epistemic level, intermediate between semantics and pragmatics. Many intuitive distinctions hyperintensionalists try to force into the semantics are better explained as belonging to competent speakers' cognitive-epistemic heuristics. He grants, for instance, that the view that counterpossibles are not all trivially true speaks to our intuitions; but objects that "sometimes, the robustly shared verdicts of native speakers on a sample sentence will simply be false, the predictable output of a fallible human heuristic." (265). Some authors, e.g. Rothschild (2021), argue that the Williamsonian stance is at odds with standard practice in semantics. The early chapters of any textbook introduction to semantics (e.g., Chierchia and McConnell-Ginet 1990; Heim and Kratzer 1997) tell us that one key task of semantics is to account for (rather than explain away) competent speakers' intuitions and judgments of synonymy, antonymy, entailment, etc. Williamson's endorsement of the extensional material conditional gives, of course, a very simple semantics for the indicative "if"; but, says Rothschild, "the simplicity comes at the cost of failing to integrate conditionals with the compositional semantics of natural language" (22). And once the heuristic procedures are developed in order to carry out the aforementioned key task, "it is not clear that Williamson's overall system will still look simple". (Ibid.) The compositionally objection is also raised by Fine 2021, who proposes his truthmaker semantics as a hyperintensional account of content in place of possible and impossible worlds-based accounts. Fine's semantics (2017a,b) uses *states* in place of worlds, where states are things that may fail to be maximal (making some sentences neither true nor false), and they may be inconsistent. Inconsistent states may be formed as mereological sums of consistent states, e.g., summing the state in which the table is round with one in which it is square gives an impossible situation in which there is a round square table. (To handle conjunction, Fine requires each set of states to have a mereological sum, so he is committed to inconsistent states like this.) Impossible worlds, too, may be inconsistent and incomplete. One live issue is thus whether truthmaker semantics is a notational variant of a kind of impossible worlds semantics, rather than an alternative to it. Ontologically, they seem on a par and, in this sense, truthmaker semantics can be seen as a form of impossible worlds semantics. However, it is probably more appropriate to view truthmaker semantics as a rival to standard impossible worlds accounts. Central to truthmaker semantics is the notion of *exact truthmaking*, whereby the state in question is wholly relevant to the sentence's truth. Truthmaker semantics stakes its reputation on the utility of this notion, whereas standard impossible worlds semantics does not. Fine's approach is appealing with respect to the compositionally worry: it provides uniform clauses for the Boolean connectives at a state, irrespective of whether the state is consistent. But the same can be said of some impossible worlds semantics, e.g. the worlds semantics for First Degree Entailment (FDE), a simple four-valued, paraconsistent logic (Dunn 1976, Belnap 1977a-b) which has been provided with a worlds semantics including worlds where formulas can be both true and false, or neither true nor false. But whether uniform clauses can be given for all operators is unclear. In Fine's 2012 semantics for counterfactuals, for instance, counterfactuals may be evaluated only with respect to possible worlds (which are, in effect, maximal possible states), with the consequence that embedded counterfactuals are not permitted. It is currently unclear whether evaluation of counterfactuals at impossible states would require non-uniform clauses. Another compositionally-based worry concerns negation: are the negations of equivalent sentences themselves equivalent? This will not be the case in general within impossible worlds semantics. The situation with truthmaker semantics is not straightforward: it holds in some but not all systems (e.g. not in Fine and Jago 2019). Fine's response is not to banish those weaker systems, but to prefer certain systems for certain purposes. That response is also open to friends of impossible worlds. Undoubtedly, other objections to impossible worlds can and are likely to be raised. The current debate on impossible worlds appears to be at the same stage as the one on *possible* worlds was, some forty years ago. At that time, people struggled to make sense of the concept of a possible world. Many declared it meaningless. Nowadays, the variety of its applications has placed the notion firmly at the core of much philosophical and logical practice (see e.g., Divers 2002, Chapter 4). Impossible worlds may undergo the same fate, should they prove as useful as they appear to be in the treatment of impossibilities of various kinds.
possible-worlds
## 1. Possible Worlds and Modal Logic Although 'possible world' has been part of the philosophical lexicon at least since Leibniz, the notion became firmly entrenched in contemporary philosophy with the development of *possible world semantics* for the languages of propositional and first-order modal logic. In addition to the usual sentence operators of classical logic such as 'and' ('[?]'), 'or' ('[?]'), 'not' ('!'), 'if...then' ('-'), and, in the first-order case, the quantifiers 'all' ('[?]') and 'some' ('[?]'), these languages contain operators intended to represent the modal adverbs 'necessarily' ('#') and 'possibly' ('*'). Although a prominent aspect of logic in both Aristotle's work and the work of many medieval philosophers, modal logic was largely ignored from the modern period to the mid-20th century. And even though a variety of modal deductive systems had in fact been rigorously developed in the early 20th century, notably by Lewis and Langford (1932), there was for the languages of those systems nothing comparable to the elegant semantics that Tarski had provided for the languages of classical first-order logic. Consequently, there was no rigorous account of what it means for a sentence in those languages to be *true* and, hence, no account of the critical semantic notions of validity and logical consequence to underwrite the corresponding deductive notions of theoremhood and provability. A concomitant philosophical consequence of this void in modal logic was a deep skepticism, voiced most prominently by Quine, toward any appeal to modal notions in metaphysics generally, notably, the notion of an essential property. (See Quine 1953 and 1956, and the appendix to Plantinga 1974.) The purpose of the following two subsections is to provide a simple and largely ahistorical overview of how possible world semantics fills this void; the final subsection presents two important applications of the semantics. (Readers familiar with basic possible world semantics can skip to SS2 with no significant loss of continuity.) ### 1.1 Extensionality Lost Since the middle ages at least, philosophers have recognized a semantical distinction between *extension* and *intension*. The extension of a denoting expression, or *term*, such as a name or a definite description is its referent, the thing that it refers to; the extension of a predicate is the set of things it applies to; and the extension of a sentence is its truth value. By contrast, the intension of an expression is something rather less definite -- its *sense*, or *meaning*, the semantical aspect of the expression that determines its extension. For purposes here, let us say that a *logic* is a formal language together with a semantic theory for the language, that is, a theory that provides rigorous definitions of truth, validity, and logical consequence for the language.[2] A logic is *extensional* if the truth value of every sentence of the logic is determined entirely by its form and the extensions of its component sentences, predicates, and terms. An extensional logic will thus typically feature a variety of valid *substitutivity principles*. A substitutivity principle says that, if two expressions are coextensional, that is, if they have the same extension, then (subject perhaps to some reasonable conditions) either can be substituted for the other in any sentence *salva veritate*, that is, without altering the original sentence's truth value. In an *intensional* logic, the truth values of some sentences are determined by something over and above their forms and the extensions of their components and, as a consequence, at least one classical substitutivity principle is typically rendered invalid. Extensionality is a well known and generally cherished feature of classical propositional and predicate logic. Modal logic, by contrast, is intensional. To illustrate: the substitutivity principle for sentences tells us that sentences with the same truth value can be substituted for one another *salva veritate*. So suppose that John's only pets are two dogs, Algol and BASIC, say, and consider two simple sentences and their formalizations (the predicates in question indicating the obvious English counterparts): | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | All John's dogs are mammals: [?]*x*(*Dx* - *Mx*). | | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | All John's pets are mammals: [?]*x*(*Px* - *Mx*) | As both sentences are true, they have the same extension. Hence, in accordance with the classical substitutivity principle for sentences, we can replace the occurrence of (1) with (2) in the false sentence | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | Not all John's dogs are mammals: ![?]*x*(*Dx* - *Mx*) | and the result is the equally false sentence | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | Not all John's pets are mammals: ![?]*x*(*Px* - *Mx*). | However, when we make the same substitution in the true sentence | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | Necessarily, all John's dogs are mammals: #[?]*x*(*Dx* - *Mx*), | the result is the sentence | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | Necessarily, all John's pets are mammals: #[?]*x*(*Px* - *Mx*), | which is intuitively false, as John surely could have had a non-mammalian pet. In a modal logic that accurately represents the logic of the necessity operator, therefore, the substitutivity principle for sentences will have to fail. The same example illustrates that the substitutivity principle for predicates will have to fail in modal logic as well. For, according to our example, the predicates '*D*' and '*P*' that are true of John's dogs and of John's pets, respectively, are coextensional, i.e., [?]*x*(*Dx* - *Px*). However, while substituting the latter predicate for the former in (3) results in a sentence with the same truth value, the same substitution in (5) does not. Modal logic, therefore, is intensional: in general, the truth value of a sentence is determined by something over and above its form and the extensions of its components. Absent a rigorous semantic theory to identify the source of its intensionality and to systematize intuitions about modal truth, validity, and logical consequence, there was little hope for the widespread acceptance of modal logic. ### 1.2 Extensionality Regained The idea of possible worlds raised the prospect of extensional respectability for modal logic, not by rendering modal logic itself extensional, but by endowing it with an extensional semantic theory -- one whose own logical foundation is that of classical predicate logic and, hence, one on which possibility and necessity can ultimately be understood along classical Tarskian lines. Specifically, in *possible world semantics*, the modal operators are interpreted as *quantifiers* over possible worlds, as expressed informally in the following two general principles: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **Nec** | | A sentence of the form [?]Necessarily, ph[?] ([?][?]ph[?]) is true if and only if ph is true in every possible world.[3] | | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **Poss** | | A sentence of the form [?]Possibly, ph[?] ([?]*ph[?]) is true if and only if ph is true in some possible world. | Given this, the failures of the classical substitutivity principles can be traced to the fact that modal operators, so interpreted, introduce contexts that require subtler notions of meaning for sentences and their component parts than are provided in classical logic; in particular, a subtler notion (to be clarified shortly) is required for predicates than that of the set of things they happen to apply to. **Tarskian Semantics.** Standard model theoretic semantics for the languages of predicate logic deriving from the work of Tarski (1933, 1944) is the paradigmatic semantic theory for extensional logics. Given a standard first-order language L, a Tarskian *interpretation* **I** *for* L specifies a set **D** for the quantifiers of L to range over (typically, some set of things that L has been designed to describe) and assigns, to each term (constant or variable) t of L, a referent **a**t [?] **D** and, to each *n*-place predicate p of L, an appropriate extension **E**p -- a truth value (TRUE or FALSE) if *n* = 0, a subset of **D** if *n* = 1, and a set of *n*-tuples of members of **D** if *n* > 1. Given these assignments, sentences are evaluated as true under the interpretation **I** -- true**I**, for short -- according to a more or less familiar set of clauses. To facilitate the definition, let **I**[n/**a**] be the interpretation that assigns the individual **a** to the variable n and is otherwise exactly like **I**. Then we have: * An atomic sentence [?]pt1...t*n*[?] (of L) is *true***I** if and only if + *n* = 0 (i.e., p is a sentence letter) and the extension of p is the truth value TRUE; or + *n* = 1 and **a**t1 is in the extension of p; or + *n* > 1 and <**a**t1, ..., **a**t*n*> is in the extension of p. * A negation [?]!ps[?] is true**I** if and only if ps is not true**I**. * A material conditional[?]ps - th[?] is true**I** iff, if ps is true**I**, then th is true**I**. * A universally quantified sentence [?][?]nps[?] is true**I** if and only if, for all individuals **a** [?] **D**, ps is true**I**[n/**a**].[4] Clauses for the other standard Boolean operators and the existential quantifier under their usual definitions follow straightaway from these clauses. In particular, where | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | [?]nph =*def* ![?]n!ph | it follows that: * An existentially quantified sentence [?][?]nps[?] is is true**I** if and only if, for some individual **a** [?] **D**, ps is true**I**[n/**a**]. It is easy to verify that, in each of the above cases, replacing one coextensional term, predicate, or sentence for another has no effect on the truth values rendered by the above clauses, thus guaranteeing the validity of the classical substitutivity principles and, hence, the extensionality of first-order logic with a Tarskian semantics. **From Tarskian to Possible World Semantics.** The truth conditional clauses for the three logical operators directly reflect the meanings of the natural language expressions they symbolize: '!' means *not*; '-' means *if...then*; '[?]' means *all*. It is easy to see, however, that we cannot expect to add an equally simple clause for sentences containing an operator that symbolizes necessity. For a Tarskian interpretation *fixes* the domain of quantification and the extensions of all the predicates. Pretty clearly, however, to capture necessity and possibility, one must be able to consider alternative "possible" domains of quantification and alternative "possible" extensions for predicates as well. For, intuitively, under different circumstances, fewer, more, or other things might have existed and things that actually exist might, in those circumstances, have had very different properties. (6), for example, is false because John could have had non-mammalian pets: a canary, say, or a turtle, or, under *very* different circumstances, a dragon. A bit more formally put: Both the domain of quantification and the extension of the predicate '*P*' could, in some sense or other, have been different. Possible world semantics, of course, uses the concept of a possible world to give substance to the idea of alternative extensions and alternative domains of quantification. (Possible world semantics can be traced most clearly back to the work of Carnap (1947), its basic development culminating in the work of Hintikka (1957, 1961), Bayart (1958, 1959), and Kripke (1959, 1963a, 1963b).[5]) Similar to Tarskian semantics, a possible world interpretation **M** of a modal language L specifies a nonempty set **D**, although thought of now as the set of "possible individuals" of **M**. Also as in Tarskian semantics, **M** assigns each term t of L a referent **a**t in **D**.[6] Additionally however, **M** specifies a set **W**, the set of "possible worlds" of **M**, one of which is designated its "actual world", and each world **w** in **W** is assigned its own domain of quantification, **d**(**w**) [?] **D**, intuitively, the set of individuals that exist in **w**.[7] To capture the idea of both the actual and possible extensions of a predicate, **M** assigns to each *n*-place predicate p a function **M**p -- the *intension* of p -- that, for each possible world **w**, returns the *ex*tension **M**p(**w**) of p *at* **w**: a truth value, if *n* = 0; a set of individuals, if *n* = 1; and a set of *n*-tuples of individuals, if *n* > 1.[8] We can thus rigorously define a "possible extension" of a predicate p to be any of its ***w**-extensions* **M**p(**w**), for any world **w**. The Tarskian truth conditions above are now generalized by relativizing them to worlds as follows: for any possible world **w** (the *world of evaluation*): * An atomic sentence [?]pt1...t*n*[?] (of L) is *true***M** *at* **w** if and only if: + *n* = 0 and the **w**-extension of p is the truth value TRUE; or + *n* = 1 and *a*t1 is in the **w**-extension of p; or + *n* > 1 and <**a**t1,..., **a**t*n*> is in the **w**-extension of p. * A negation [?]!ps[?] is true**M** at **w** if and only ps is not true**M** in **w**. * A material conditional[?]ps-th[?] is true**M** at **w** iff, if ps is true**M** at **w**, then th is true**M** at **w**. * A quantified sentence [?][?]nps[?] is true**M** at **w** if and only if, for all individuals **a** that exist in **w**, ps is true**M**[n/**a**]. And to these, of course, is added the critical modal case that explicitly interprets the modal operator to be a quantifier over worlds, as we'd initially anticipated informally in our principle **Nec**: * A necessitation [?][?]ps[?] is true**M** at **w** if and only if, for all possible worlds **u** of **M**, ps is true**M** at **u**.[9] A sentence ph is *false***M** at **w** just in case it is not true**M** at **w**, and ph is said to be *true***M** just in case ph is true**M** at the actual world of **M**. On the assumption that there is a (nonempty) set of all possible worlds and a set of all possible individuals, we can define "objective" notions of truth at a world and of truth *simpliciter*, that is, notions that are not simply relative to formal, mathematical interpretations but, rather, correspond to objective reality in all its modal glory. Let L be a modal language whose names and predicates represent those in some fragment of ordinary language (as in our examples (5) and (6) above). Say that **M** is the "intended" interpretation of L if (i) its set **W** of "possible worlds" is in fact the set of all possible worlds, (ii) its designated "actual world" is in fact the actual world, (iii) its set **D** of "possible individuals" is in fact the set of all possible individuals, and (iv) the referents assigned to the names of L and the intensions assigned to the predicates of L are the ones they in fact have. Then, where **M** is the intended interpretation of L, we can say that a sentence ph of L is *true at* a possible world **w** just in case ph is true**M** at **w**, and that ph is *true* just in case it is true**M** at the actual world. (Falsity at **w** and falsity, *simpliciter*, are defined accordingly.) Under the assumption in question, then, the modal clause above takes on pretty much the exact form of our informal principle **Nec**. Call the above *basic* possible world semantics. Spelling out the truth conditions for (6) (relative to the intended interpretation of its language), basic possible world semantics tells us that (6) is true if and only if | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | For all possible worlds **w**, '[?]*x*(*Px* - *Mx*)' is true at **w**. | And by unpacking (8) in terms of the quantificational, material conditional, and atomic clauses above we have that (6) is true if and only if | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | For all possible worlds **w**, and for all possible individuals **a** that exist in **w**, if **a** is in the **w**-extension of '*P*' then **a** is in the **w**-extension of '*M*'. | Since we are evaluating (6) with regard to the intended interpretation of its language, the **w**-extension of '*P*' that is returned by its intension, for any world **w**, is the (perhaps empty) set of John's pets in **w** and that of '*M*' is the set of mammals in **w**. Hence, if **w** is a world where John has a pet canary -- COBOL, say -- COBOL is in the **w**-extension of '*P*' but not that of '*M*' , i.e., '[?]*x*(*Px* - *Mx*)' is false at **w** and, hence, by the truth condition (9), (6) is false at the actual world -- that is, (6) is false *simpliciter*, as it should be. Note that interpreting modal operators as quantifiers over possible worlds provides a nice theoretical justification for the usual definition of the possibility operator in terms of necessity, specifically: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | [?]*ph[?] =*def* [?]![?]!ph[?]. | That is, a sentence is possible just in case its negation isn't necessary. Since, semantically speaking, the necessity operator is *literally* a universal quantifier, the definition corresponds exactly to the definition (7) of the existential quantifier. For, unpacking the right side of definition (10) according to the negation and necessitation clauses above (and invoking the definitions of truth and truth at a world *simpliciter*), we have: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | [?]*ph[?] is true iff it is not the case that, for all possible worlds **w**, ph is not true at **w**. | Clearly, however, if it is not the case that ph fails to be true at all possible worlds, then it must be true at some world; hence: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | [?]*ph[?] is true iff, for some possible world **w**, ph is true at **w**. | And that corresponds exactly to our intuitive truth condition **Poss** above. Thus, spelling out the negation '!#[?]*x*(*Px* - *Mx*)' of our false sentence (6) above in accordance with definition (10) (and the standard definition of conjunction [?]), we have: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | Possibly, one of John's pets is not a mammal: *[?]*x*(*Px* [?] !*Mx*), | for which (12) and the possible world truth conditions for quantified, Boolean, and atomic sentences yield the correct truth condition: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | There is a possible world **w** and an individual **a** existing in **w** that is in the **w**-extension of '*P*' but not that of '*M*', | that is, less stuffily, there is a possible world in which, among John's pets, at least one is not a mammal. **Summary: Intensionality and Possible Worlds.** Analyzed in terms of possible world semantics, then, the general failure of classical substitutivity principles in modal logic is due, not to an irreducibly intensional element in the meanings of the modal operators, but rather to a sort of mismatch between the surface syntax of those operators and their semantics: syntactically, they are unary sentence operators like negation; but semantically, they are, quite literally, quantifiers. Their syntactic similarity to negation suggests that, like negation, the truth values of [?]#ph[?] and [?]*ph[?], insofar as they are determinable at all, must be determined by the truth value of ph. That they are not (in general) so determined leads to the distinctive substitutivity failures noted above. The possible worlds analysis of the modal operators as quantifiers over worlds reveals that the unary syntactic form of the modal operators obscures a semantically relevant parameter. When the modal operators are interpreted as quantifiers, this parameter becomes explicit and the reason underlying the failure of extensionality in modal logic becomes clear: That the truth values of [?]#ph[?] and [?]*ph[?] are not in general determined by the truth value of ph at the world of evaluation is, semantically speaking, nothing more than the fact that the truth values of '[?]*xFx*' and '[?]*xFx*' are not in general determined by the truth value of '*Fx*', for any particular value of '*x*'. Possible world semantics, therefore, *explains* the intensionality of modal logic by revealing that the syntax of the modal operators prevents an adequate expression of the meanings of the sentences in which they occur. Spelled out as possible world truth conditions, those meanings can be expressed in a wholly extensional fashion. (For a more formal exposition of this point, see the supplemental article The Extensionality of Possible World Semantics.) ### 1.3 Two Applications: The Analysis of Intensions and the *De Re* / *De Dicto* Distinction As noted, the focus of the present article is on the metaphysics of possible worlds rather than applications. Of course, the semantics of modal languages is itself an application, but one that is of singular importance, both for historical reasons and because most applications are in fact themselves applications of (often extended or modified versions of) the semantical apparatus. Two particularly important examples are the analysis of intensions and a concomitant explication of the *de re*/*de dicto* distinction.[10] **The Analysis of Intensions.** As much a barrier to the acceptance of modal logic as intensionality itself was the need to appeal to intensions *per se* -- properties, relations, propositions, and the like -- in semantical explanations. Intensional entities have of course featured prominently in the history of philosophy since Plato and, in particular, have played natural explanatory roles in the analysis of intentional attitudes like belief and mental content. For all their prominence and importance, however, the nature of these entities has often been obscure and controversial and, indeed, as a consequence, they were easily dismissed as ill-understood and metaphysically suspect "creatures of darkness" (Quine 1956, 180) by the naturalistically oriented philosophers of the early- to mid-20th century. It is a virtue of possible world semantics that it yields rigorous *definitions* for intensional entities. More specifically, as described above, possible world semantics assigns to each *n*-place predicate p a certain function **I**p -- p's intension -- that, for each possible world **w**, returns the extension **I**p(**w**) of p at **w**. We can define an intension *per se*, independent of any language, to be any such function on worlds. More specifically: * A *proposition* is any function from worlds to truth values. * A *property* is any function from worlds to sets of individuals. * An **n*-place relation* (*n* > 1) is any function from worlds to sets of *n*-tuples of individuals. The adequacy of this analysis is a matter of lively debate that focuses chiefly upon whether or not intensions, so defined, are too "coarse-grained" to serve their intended purposes. (See, e.g., Stalnaker 1987 and 2012 for a strong defense of the analysis.) However, Lewis (1986, SS1.5) argues that, even if the above analysis fails for certain purposes, it does not follow that intensions cannot be analyzed in terms of possible worlds, but only that more subtle constructions might be required. This reply appears to side-step the objections from granularity while preserving the great advantage of the possible worlds analysis of intensions, viz., the rigorous definability of these philosophically significant notions. **The *De Re* / *De Dicto* Distinction.** A particularly rich application of the possible world analysis of intensions concerns the analysis of the venerable distinction between *de re* and *de dicto* modality.[11] Among the strongest modal intuitions is that the possession of a property has a modal character -- that things exemplify, or fail to exemplify, some properties *necessarily*, or *essentially*, and others only *accidentally*. Thus, for example, intuitively, John's dog Algol is a pet accidentally; under less fortunate circumstances, she might have been, say, a stray that no one ever adopted. But she is a dog essentially; she couldn't have been a flower, a musical performance, a crocodile or any other kind of thing. Spelling out this understanding in terms of worlds and the preceding analysis of intensions, we can say that an individual **a** has a property **F** essentially if **a** has **F** in every world in which it exists, that is, if, for all worlds **w** in which **a** exists, **a** [?] **F**(**w**). Likewise, **a** has **F** accidentally if **a** has **F** in the actual world @ but lacks it in some other world, that is, if **a** [?] **F**(@) but, for some world **w** in which **a** exists, **a** [?] **F**(**w**). Thus, let '*G*' and '*T*' symbolize 'is a dog' and 'is someone's pet', respectively; then, where '*E!x*' is short for '[?]*y*(*x*=*y*)' (and, hence, expresses that *x* exists), we have: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | Algol is a dog essentially: #(*E!a* - *Ga*) | | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | Algol is a pet accidentally: *Ta* [?] *(*E!a* [?] !*Ta*) | More generally, sentences like (15) and (16) in which properties are ascribed to a specific individual in a modal context -- signaled formally by the occurrence of a name or the free occurrence of a variable in the scope of a modal operator -- are said to exhibit modality *de re*[12] (modality *of the thing*). Modal sentences that do not, like | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | Necessarily, all dogs are mammals: #[?]*x*(*Gx* - *Mx*) | are said to exhibit modality *de dicto* (roughly, modality *of the* *proposition*). Possible world semantics provides an illuminating analysis of the key difference between the two: The truth conditions for both modalities involve a commitment to possible worlds; however, the truth conditions for sentences exhibiting modality *de re* involve in addition a commitment to the meaningfulness of *transworld identity*, the thesis that, necessarily, every individual (typically, at any rate) exists and exemplifies (often very different) properties in many different possible worlds. More specifically, basic possible world semantics yields intuitively correct truth values for sentences of the latter sort by (i) permitting world domains to overlap and (ii) assigning intensions to predicates, thereby, in effect, relativizing predicate extensions to worlds. In this way, one and the same individual can be in the extension of a given predicate at all worlds in which they exist, at some such worlds only, or at none at all. (For further discussion, see the entry on essential vs. accidental properties.) ## 2. Three Philosophical Conceptions of Possible Worlds The power and appeal of basic possible world semantics is undeniable. In addition to providing a clear, extensional formal semantics for a formerly somewhat opaque, intensional notion, cashing possibility as truth in some possible world and necessity as truth in every such world seems to tap into very deep intuitions about the nature of modality and the meaning of our modal discourse. Unfortunately, the semantics leaves the most interesting -- and difficult -- philosophical questions largely unanswered. Two arise with particular force: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **QW** | | What, exactly, is a possible world? | And, given **QW**: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **QE** | | What is it for something to exist in a possible world? | In this section we will concern ourselves with, broadly speaking, the three most prominent philosophical approaches to these questions.[13] ### 2.1 Concretism Recall the informal picture that we began with: a world is, so to say, the "limit" of a series of increasingly more inclusive situations. Fleshed out philosophical accounts of this informal idea generally spring from rather different intuitions about what one takes the "situations" in the informal picture to be. A particularly powerful intuition is that situations are simply structured collections of physical objects: the immediate situation of our initial example above, for instance, consists of, among other things, the objects in Anne's office -- notably Anne herself, her desk and her computer, with her seated at the former and typing on the latter -- and at least some of the things in the next room -- notably, her husband and the phone he is talking on. On this view, for one situation **s** to include another **r** is simply for **r** to be a (perhaps rather complex and distributed) physical part of **s**. The actual world, then, as the limit of a series of increasingly more inclusive situations in this sense, is simply the entire physical universe: all the things that are some spatiotemporal distance from the objects in some arbitrary initial situation, structured as they in fact are; and other possible worlds are things of exactly the same sort. Call this the *concretist* intuition, as possible worlds are understood to be concrete physical situations of a special sort. #### 2.1.1 Concrete Worlds and Existence Therein The originator and, by far, the best known proponent of concretism is David Lewis. For Lewis and, as noted, concretists generally, the actual world is the concrete physical universe as it is, stretched out in space-time. As he rather poetically expresses it (1986, 1): > > The world we live in is a very inclusive thing....There is nothing so > far away from us as not to be part of our world. Anything at any > distance is to be included. Likewise the world is inclusive in time. > No long-gone ancient Romans, no long-gone pterodactyls, no long-gone > primordial clouds of plasma are too far in the past, nor are the dead > dark stars too far in the future, to be part of this same > world....[N]othing is so alien in kind as not to be part of our world, > provided only that it does exist at some distance and direction from > here, or at some time before or after or simultaneous with now. > The actual world provides us with our most salient example of what a possible world is. But, for the concretist, other possible worlds are no different in kind from the actual world (*ibid.*, 2): > > There are countless other worlds, other very inclusive things. Our > world consists of us and all our surroundings, however, remote in time > and space; just as it is one big thing having lesser things as parts, > so likewise do other worlds have lesser other-worldly things as parts. > It is clear that spatiotemporal relations play a critical role in Lewis's conception. However, it is important to note that Lewis understands such relations in a very broad and flexible way so as to allow, in particular, for the possibility of spirits and other entities that are typically thought of as non-spatial; so long as they are located in time, Lewis writes, "that is good enough" (*ibid.*, 73). So with this caveat, let us say that that an object **a** is *connected* if any two of its parts bear some spatiotemporal relation to each other,[14] and that **a** is *maximal* if none of its parts is spatiotemporally related to anything that is not also one of its parts. Then we have the following concretist answers to our questions: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **AW1** | | **w** is a possible world =*def* **w** is a maximal connected object.[15] | And, hence, to exist in a world is simply to be a part of it: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **AE1** | | Individual **a** exists in world **w** =*def* **a** is a part of **w**. | It follows from **AW1** (and reasonable assumptions) that distinct worlds do not overlap, spatiotemporally; that no spatiotemporal part of one world is part of another.[16] Moreover, given Lewis's counterfactual analysis of causation, it follows from this that objects in distinct worlds bear no causal relations to one another; nothing that occurs in one world has any causal impact on anything that occurs in any other world. #### 2.1.2 Actuality Critically, for Lewis, worlds and their denizens do not differ in the *manner* in which they exist. The actual world does not enjoy a kind of privileged existence that sets it apart from other worlds. Rather, what makes the actual world actual is simply that it is *our* world, the world that we happen to inhabit. Other worlds and their inhabitants exist just as robustly as we do, and in precisely the same sense; all worlds and all of their denizens are equally *real*.[17] A significant semantic corollary of this thesis for Lewis is that the word 'actual' in the phrase 'the actual world' does not indicate any special *property* of the actual world that distinguishes it from all other worlds; likewise, an assertion of the form '**a** is actual' does not indicate any special property of the individual **a** that distinguishes it from the objects existing in other worlds. Rather, 'actual' is simply an *indexical* whose extension is determined by the context of utterance. Thus, the referent of 'the actual world' in a given utterance is simply the world of the speaker, just as the referent of an utterance of 'the present moment' is the moment of the utterance; likewise, an utterance of the form '**a** is actual' indicates only that **a** shares the same world as the speaker. The speaker thereby ascribes no special property to **a** but, essentially, expresses no more than when she utters '**a** is *here*', understood in the broadest possible sense. By the same token, when we speak of non-actual *possibilia* -- Lewis's preferred label for the denizens of possible worlds -- we simply pick out those objects that are *not* here in the broadest sense. In the mouth of an other-worldly metaphysician, we here are all among the non-actual *possibilia* of which she speaks in her lectures on *de re* modality. #### 2.1.3 Modal Reductionism, Counterparts, and the Analysis of Intensions **Modal Reductionism and Counterparts.** Lewis parted ways dramatically with his mentor W. V. O. Quine on modality. Quine (1960, SS41) stands in a long line of philosophers dating back at least to David Hume who are skeptical, at best, of the idea that modality is an objective feature of reality and, consequently, who question whether modal assertions in general can be objectively true or false, or even coherent. Lewis, by contrast, wholly embraces the objectivity of modality and the coherence of our modal discourse. What he denies, however, is that modality is a fundamentally *irreducible* feature of the world. Lewis, that is, is a *modal reductionist*. For Lewis, modal notions are not primitive. Rather, truth conditions for modal sentences can be given in terms of worlds and their parts; and worlds themselves, Lewis claims, are defined entirely in non-modal terms. The earliest presentation of Lewis's theory of modality (Lewis 1968) -- reflecting Quine's method of regimentation -- offers, rather than a possible world semantics, a scheme for *translating* sentences in the language of modal predicate logic into sentences of ordinary first-order logic in which the modal operators are replaced by explicit quantifiers over worlds.[18] The mature account of Lewis 1986 is much more semantic in orientation: it avoids any talk of translation and offers instead a (somewhat informal) account of concretist possible world truth conditions for a variety of modal assertions. Nonetheless, it is useful to express the logical forms of these truth conditions explicitly in terms of worlds, existence in a world (in the sense of **AE1**, of course), and the *counterpart* relation, which will be discussed shortly: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | *Wx*: | | *x* is a *world* | | *Ixy*: | | *x* *exists in* world *y* | | *Cxy*: | | *x* is a *counterpart* of *y* | For sentences like (17) involving only *de dicto* modalities, Lewis's truth conditions are similar in form to the truth conditions generated by the modal clauses of basic possible world semantics; specifically, for (17): | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | For every world **w**, every individual **x** in **w** that is a dog is a mammal: [?]*w*(*Ww* - [?]*x*(*Ixw* - (*Gx* - *Mx*))). | As in possible world semantics, the modal operators '#' and '*' "turn into" quantifiers over worlds in concretist truth conditions (1986, 5). Also as in possible world semantics, a quantifier (in effect) ranging over individuals that occurs in the scope of a quantifier (in effect) ranging over worlds -- '[?]*x*' and '[?]*w*', respectively, in (18) -- is, for each value **w** of the bound world variable, restricted to the objects existing in **w**. However, unlike possible world semantics, predicates are not to be thought of as having different extensions at different worlds. Rather, for Lewis, each (*n*-place) predicate has a single extension that can contain (*n*-tuples of) objects across many different worlds -- intuitively, all of the objects that have the property (or *n*-tuples of objects that stand in the relation) expressed by the predicate across all possible worlds. Thus, in particular, the predicate '*G*' picks out, not just this-worldly dogs but other-worldly canines as well. Likewise, the pet predicate '*T*' picks out both actual and other-worldly pets. Such a move is not feasible in basic possible world semantics, which is designed for a metaphysics in which one and the same individual can exemplify a given property in some worlds in which they exist but not others. Hence, a typical predicate will be true of an individual with respect to some worlds and false of it with respect to others. But, for Lewis, as we've seen, distinct possible worlds do not overlap and, hence, objects are worldbound, thereby eliminating the need to relativize predicate extensions to worlds. However, this very feature of Lewis's account -- worldboundedness -- might appear to threaten its coherence. For example, since Algol is in fact a pet, given worldboundedness and the definition **AE1** of existence in a world **w**, we have: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | There is no world **w** such that Algol exists in **w** and fails to be someone's pet: ![?]*w*(*Iaw* [?] !*Ta*), | But, according to Lewis's analysis, the modal operators '#' and '*', semantically, are quantifiers over worlds. Hence, (19) might appear to be exactly the concretist truth condition for the denial of (the right conjunct of) (16), i.e., it might appear that, on Lewis's analysis, Algol is not a pet accidentally but essentially; likewise, more generally, any individual and any intuitively accidental property of that individual. In fact, Lewis whole-heartedly accepts that things have accidental properties and, indeed, would accept that (16) is robustly true. His explanation involves one of the most interesting and provocative elements of his theory: the doctrine of *counterparts*. Roughly, an object **y** in a world **w**2 is a counterpart of an object **x** in **w**1 if **y** resembles **x** and nothing else in **w**2 resembles **x** more than **y**.[19] Each object is thus its own (not necessarily unique) counterpart in the world it inhabits but will typically differ in important ways from its other-wordly counterparts. A typical other-worldly counterpart of Algol, for example, might resemble her very closely up to some point in her history -- a point, say, after which she continued to live out her life as a stray instead of being brought home by our kindly dog-lover John. Hence, sentences making *de re* assertions about what *Algol* might have done or what *she* could or could not have been are unpacked, semantically, as sentences about her *counterparts* in other possible worlds. Thus, when we analyze (16) accordingly, we have the entirely unproblematic concretist truth condition: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | Algol is a pet, but there is a world in which exists a counterpart of hers that is not: *Ta* [?] [?]*w*(*Ww* [?] [?]*x*(*Ixw* [?] *Cxa* [?] !*Tx*)). | Ascriptions of essential properties, as in (15), are likewise unpacked in terms of counterparts: to say that Algol is a dog essentially is to say that | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | All of Algol's counterparts in any world are dogs: [?]*w*(*Ww* - [?]*x*((*Ixw* [?] *Cxa*) - *Gx*)). | **The Analysis of Intensions.** Lewis's possible world truth conditions are expressed in classical non-modal logic and, hence, they are to be interpreted by means of standard Tarskian semantics. Thus, *n*-place predicates p are assigned extensions **E**p -- in particular, for 1-place predicates, sets of individuals -- as their semantic values, as described in the exposition in SS1.2 above. However, given worldboundedness and the fact that predicate extensions are drawn not simply from the actual world but from all possible worlds, these extensions are able to serve as *in*tensions in Lewis's theory. As in basic possible world semantics, intensional entities in general can be defined in terms of the basic ontology of the theory independent of the linguistic roles they can play as the intensions of predicates. And because individuals are worldbound, Lewis is able to simplify the definitions given in SS1.3 by defining intensions as sets rather than functions: * A *proposition* is any set of worlds. * A *property* is any set of individuals. * An **n*-place relation* (*n* > 1) is any set of *n*-tuples of individuals.[20] Thus, on this analysis, a proposition **p** is *true in* a world **w** just in case **w** [?] **p** and an individual **a** has a property **P** just in case **a** [?] **P**. (Note that propositions are thus simply properties of worlds on these definitions.) **a** has **P** *accidentally* just in case **a** [?] **P** but **b** [?] **P** for some other-worldly counterpart of **b** of **a**; and **a** has **P** *essentially* if **b** [?] **P** for every counterpart **b** of **a**. In Lewis's theory of modality, then, modal operators are understood semantically to be quantifiers over concrete worlds, predicates denote intensions understood as sets of (*n*-tuples of) parts of those worlds, and sentences involving *de re* modalities are understood in terms of counterparts. To the extent that these notions are free of modality, Lewis has arguably reduced modal notions to non-modal. #### 2.1.4 Plenitude and Recombination That Lewis's truth conditions for modal statements are themselves free of modality and, hence, that his theory counts as a genuine reduction of modal notions to non-modal is not terribly controversial (albeit not undisputed -- see Lycan 1991, 224-27; Divers and Melia 2002, 22-24). Significantly more controversial, and perhaps far more critical to the project, is whether or not his account is *complete*, that is, whether or not, for all modal statements ph, (i) if ph is intuitively true, then its Lewisian truth condition holds (ii) if ph is intuitively false, then its Lewisian truth condition fails.[21] The challenge to Lewis, then, is that his account can be considered *successful* only if it is complete in this sense. The chief question Lewis faces in this regard is whether there are *enough* worlds to do the job. The truth condition (20) for the intuitively true (16) says that there exists a possible world in which a counterpart of Algol is no one's pet. By virtue of what in Lewis's theory does such a world exist? The ideal answer for Lewis would be that some principle in his theory guarantees a *plenitude* of worlds, a maximally abundant array of worlds that leaves "no gaps in logical space; no vacancies where a world might have been, but isn't" (Lewis 1986, 86). From this it would follow that the worlds required by the concretist truth condition for any intuitive modal truth exist. Toward this end, Lewis initially considers the evocative principle: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **Ways** | | Absolutely every way that a world could be is a way that some world is. | Since, in particular, a world satisfying (20) seems quite obviously to be a way a world could be, by **Ways** such a world exists. But there is a fatal flaw here: Lewis himself (1973, 84) identifies *ways* that a world could be with worlds themselves. So understood, **Ways** collapses into the triviality that every world is identical to some world.[22] Lewis finds a replacement for **Ways** in a principle of *recombination* whereby "patching together parts of different possible worlds yields another possible world" (1986, 87-88). The principle has two aspects. The first is the principle that "anything can coexist with anything". For "if there could be a dragon, and there could be a unicorn," Lewis writes, "but there couldn't be a dragon and a unicorn side by side, that would be ... a failure of plenitude" (*ibid*., 88). Given that individuals are worldbound, however, the principle is expressed more rigorously (and more generally) in terms of other-worldly *duplicates*: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **R1** | | For any (finite or infinite) number of objects **a**1, **a**2, ..., there is a world containing any number of duplicates of each of those objects in any spatiotemporal arrangement (size and shape permitting). | The second aspect of the principle expresses "the Humean denial of necessary connections" (*ibid*., 87), that is, the idea that anything can *fail* to coexist with anything else. For "if there could be a talking head contiguous to the rest of a living human body, but there couldn't be a talking head separate from the rest of a human body, that too would be a failure of plenitude" (*ibid*). To express this a bit more rigorously, say that objects **a**1, **a**2, ..., are *independent of* objects **b**1, **b**2, ..., if no sum of any parts of the former are parts or duplicates of any sum of any parts of the latter and vice versa; then we have: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **R2** | | For any world **w** any (finite or infinite number of) objects **a**1, **a**2, ..., in **w** and any objects **b**1, **b**2, ..., in **w** that are independent of **a**1, **a**2, ..., there is a world containing duplicates of **a**1, **a**2, ..., and no duplicates of **b**1, **b**2, ... . | Worlds that satisfy the concretist truth conditions for workaday possibilities like (16) are easily conceived as consisting of duplicates of relevant parts of the actual world -- suitably organized to retain their actual properties, or not, as needed. Hence, the existence of such worlds does indeed appear to follow from the existence of the actual world by recombination. Worlds containing talking donkeys, exotic species resulting from a wholly different evolutionary history, worlds with silicon-based life forms, and so on present a bigger challenge to the view. Nonetheless, it is not entirely implausible to think such worlds exist given suitable duplication and reorganization of microphysical objects.[23] Whether recombination completely captures our modal intuitions regarding plenitude is still a matter of some dispute.[24] However, even if it doesn't, it is less than clear whether this counts against the success of Lewis's reductionist project. For, as a realist about worlds, Lewis does not seem to be under any obligation to "derive" plenitude from more fundamental principles. Hence, there is no obvious reason why he cannot respond to charges of incompleteness by saying that it is simply a presupposition of his theory that logical space has no gaps, that there are always enough worlds to satisfy the concretist truth condition for any intuitive modal truth.[25] So understood, the role of recombination for a realist about worlds like Lewis is something like the role of such axioms as powerset and replacement for a realist about sets: given some sets, these principles provide us with a detailed -- but always less than complete -- characterization of what further sets there are. Their role, therefore, is to give us insight into the richness and diversity of set theoretic space, not a complete mechanism for proving which particular sets do or do not exist. Likewise recombination vis-a-vis worlds and logical space. #### 2.1.5 A Brief Assessment of Concretism Lewis's theory is particularly commendable for its striking originality and ingenuity and for the simple and straightforward answers **AW1** and **AE1** that it provides to our two questions **QW** and **QE** above. Furthermore, because worlds are (plausibly) defined entirely in nonmodal terms, the truth conditions provided by Lewis's translation scheme themselves appear to be free of any implicit modality. Hence, unlike many other popular accounts of possible worlds (notably, the abstractionist accounts discussed in the following section), Lewis's promises to provide a genuine *analysis* of the modal operators. Perhaps the biggest -- if not the most philosophically sophisticated -- challenge to Lewis's theory is "the incredulous stare", i.e., less colorfully put, the fact that its ontology is wildly at variance with common sense. Lewis faces this objection head on: His theory of worlds, he acknowledges, "*does* disagree, to an extreme extent, with firm common sense opinion about what there is" (1986, 133). However, Lewis argues that no other theory explains so much so economically. With worlds in one's philosophical toolkit, one is able to provide elegant explanations of a wide variety of metaphysical, semantical, and intentional phenomena. As high as the intuitive cost is, Lewis (135) concludes, the existence of worlds "ought to be accepted as true. The theoretical benefits are worth it." Additional discussion of, and objections to, concretism can be found in the supplemental document Further Problems for Concretism. ### 2.2 Abstractionism A rather different set of intuitions about situations is that they are *abstract* entities of a certain sort: They are *states* or *conditions*, of varying detail and complexity, that a concrete world could be in -- they are *ways* that things, as a whole, could be.[26] Thus, returning to our original example, one very simple way things could be is for our philosopher Anne to be in her office. We can now imagine, as in our example, further detail being successively added to that description to yield more complex ways things could be: Anne working at her desk in her office; music being in the background; her husband being on the phone in the next room; her neighbor mowing the lawn next door; and so on. Roughly speaking, then, a possible world for an abstractionist is the *limit* of such a "process" of consistently extending and adding detail to some initial state of the world; it is a *total* way things could be, a consistent state of the world that settles every possibility; a consistent state to which no further detail could be added without rendering it inconsistent. #### 2.2.1 Abstract Possible Worlds and Existence Therein To give the notion of a state, or condition, of the world a little more metaphysical substance, abstractionists typically appeal to more traditional ontological categories. Thus, for example, that things could be in the simple state described above might be spelled out in one of the following ways: * The *proposition* **that Anne is in her office and at her desk** is possibly true. * The *set of propositions* {**that Anne is in her office**, **that Anne is at her desk**} is such that, possibly, all of its members are true. * The *property* **being such that Anne is in her office and at her desk** is possibly exemplified (by "things as a whole"). Possible worlds are then defined as special cases of the type of entity in question that are in some relevant sense *total*. Adams (1974), for example, defines possible worlds to be consistent sets of propositions that are total in the sense of containing, for every proposition **p**, either **p** or its negation; Fine (1977), fleshing out ideas of Prior, defines a possible world to be a consistent proposition **w** that is total in the sense that, for every proposition **p**, **w** entails either **p** or its negation. For purposes here, however, we will sketch the fundamentals of the abstractionist view in terms of *states of affairs*, following the basic features of the account developed by Plantinga (1974, 1976), an account that, in the literature, frequently serves as a particularly trenchant abstractionist counterpoint to Lewis's concretism.[27] States of affairs (SOAs) are abstract, intensional entities typically signified by sentential gerundives like "Algol's being John's pet" and "There being more than ten solar planets". Importantly, SOAs constitute a primitive ontological category for the abstractionist; they are not defined in terms of possible worlds in the manner that propositions are in SS1.3. Just as some propositions are true and others are not, some SOAs are *actual* and others are not.[28] Note, then, that to say an SOA is non-actual is *not* to say that it does not actually *exist*. It is simply to say that it is not, in fact, a condition, or state, that the concrete world is actually in. However, because '\_\_\_\_ is actual' is often used simply to mean '\_\_\_\_ exists', there is considerable potential for confusion here. So, henceforth, to express that an SOA is actual we will usually say that it *obtains*. An SOA is said to be *possible* (*necessary*, *impossible*) insofar as it is possible (necessary, impossible) that it obtain. One SOA **s** is said to *include* another **t** if, necessarily, **s** obtains only if **t** does; **s** *precludes* **t** if, necessarily, **s** obtains only if **t** doesn't. So, for example, **Algol's being John's pet** includes **Algol's being someone's pet** and precludes **there being no pets**. Thus, on the abstractionist's understanding of a situation as a state or condition of the physical world rather than a concrete, structured piece of it, the inclusion of one situation in another is a purely *logical* relation, not a mereological one. Finally, say that an SOA **s** is *total* if, for every SOA **t**, **s** either includes or precludes **t**. (Abstractionists often use 'maximal' instead of 'total', but we have already introduced this term in the context of concretism.) Abstractionist possible worlds are now definable straightaway: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **AW2** | | **w** is a possible world =*def* **w** is an SOA that is both possible and total.[29] | It is easy to see that this definition covers the more intuitive characterizations of abstract possible worlds above: they are consistent -- i.e., possible -- states of the world that settle every possibility, consistent states to which no further detail could be added without rendering them inconsistent. Note also that, for the abstractionist, as for the concretist, the actual world is no different in kind from any other possible world; all possible worlds exist, and in precisely the same sense as the actual world. The actual world is simply the total possible SOA that, in fact, obtains. And non-actual worlds are simply those total possible SOAs that do not. What of existence in such worlds? As we've seen, on Lewis's account, to exist in a concrete world **w** is literally to exist *in **w***, that is, within the spatiotemporal boundaries of **w**. Clearly, because SOAs are abstract, individuals cannot exist in abstractionist worlds in anything like the same literal, mereological sense. Accordingly, the abstractionist defines existence in a world simply to be a special case of the inclusion relation: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **AE2** | | Individual **a** *exists in* possible world **w** =*def* **w** includes ****a**'s existing**. | Unlike concretism, then, abstractionism does not entail that individuals are worldbound; there is no inconsistency whatever in the idea that many distinct worlds can include the existence of one and the same individual. Indeed, typically, abstractionists are staunchly committed to transworld identity and hold that most any given individual exists in many possible worlds and, moreover, that contingent individuals, at least, can exemplify very different properties from world to world. Abstractionists, therefore, have no need to appeal to counterparts to understand *de re* modalities and can therefore accept the truth conditions for such modalities given by basic possible world semantics (spelled out, of course, in terms of their definitions **AW2** and **AE2**). In particular, they can take the standard possible world truth condition for, e.g., the right conjunct of (16) at face value: '*(*E!a* [?] !*Ta*)' is true on the abstractionist's approach if and only if there is is a world in which Algol herself, rather than some counterpart of hers, exists but fails to be anyone's pet. #### 2.2.2 Irreducible Modality and Intensional Entities It is important to note that the possible worlds of abstractionism do not yield a reductive analysis of modality. The reason for this is clear: abstract possible worlds are defined in irreducibly modal terms -- a possible world is an SOA that (among other things) *possibly* obtains; or a set of propositions such that it is *possible* that all of its members are true; or a property that is *possibly* exemplified; and so on. Hence, unpacked in terms of the abstractionist's definitions, the possible world truth conditions for modal propositions are themselves irreducibly modal. For example, when we unpack Plantinga's definition of a possible world in the semantic clause for sentences of the form [?][?]ps[?] in order to derive the truth condition for (17), '#[?]*x*(*Gx* - *Mx*)', we end up with this: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | For all SOAs **w**, if (i) *possibly*, **w** obtains and (ii) for all SOAs **s**, either (a) *necessarily*, **w** obtains only if **s** does or (b) *necessarily*, **w** obtains only if **s** doesn't, then, '[?]*x*(*Gx* - *Mx*)' is true at **w**. | If we now unpack the modal operators in (22) using the corresponding truth conditional clauses of standard possible world semantics, the result will contain further world quantifiers. And spelling out those world quantifiers in turn using Plantinga's definition will re-introduce those same modal operators yet again. More generally, and a bit more exactly, put: As noted above, the logical framework of basic possible world semantics is classical predicate logic. The logical framework of abstractionism is modal predicate logic. Hence, if possible world semantics is supplemented with abstractionist definitions of possible worlds, then the logical framework of possible world semantics becomes modal predicate logic as well and, as a consequence, the extensionality of the semantics is lost once again. (This point is expressed somewhat more formally in the supplemental document The Intensionality of Abstractionist Possible World Semantics.) Since, as noted above, the central motivation for possible world semantics was to deliver an extensional semantics for modal languages, any motivation for abstractionism as a semantic theory is arguably undermined.[30] However, it is not entirely clear that this observation constitutes an objection to abstractionism. For abstractionists can argue that the goal of their analysis is the converse of the reductionist's goal: The reductionist wants to understand modality in terms of worlds; the abstractionist, by contrast, wants to understand worlds in terms of modality. That is, abstractionists can argue that we begin with a primitive notion of modality and, typically upon a certain amount of philosophical reflection, we subsequently discover an intimate connection to the notion of a possible world, as revealed in the principles **Nec** and **Poss**. The analysis that abstractionists provide is designed to make this connection explicit, ideally, in such a way that **Nec** and **Poss** fall out as theorems of their theory (see, e.g., Plantinga 1985 and Menzel and Zalta 2014). Hand in glove with the irreducible nature of modality is the nature of intensional entities. Concretists define intensional entities in terms of worlds, as described in SS2.1.3. Abstractionists, by contrast, define worlds in terms of intensional entities. This divergence in their choice of ontological primitives reflects, not only their differing stances toward modality, but also an important methodological difference with regard to metaphysical inquiry. The concretist is far more pragmatic; notions of *property*, *relation*, *proposition*, and the like play certain roles in our theorizing and are subject to a "jumble of conflicting *desiderata*" (Lewis 1986, 54). Within a given theory, any entities that can play those roles fruitfully for the purposes at hand are justifiably identified with those notions -- regardless of how well they comport with pre-theoretic intuitions. Thus, Lewis finds it to be a strength of his position that he is able to adopt the set theoretic definitions in SS2.1.3. By contrast, at least some abstractionists -- Plantinga (1987) perhaps most notably -- believe that we have intuitive, pre-theoretic knowledge of intensional entities that precludes their being identified with set theoretic constructions of any sort.[31] (See Stalnaker 1976 for a particularly illuminating discussion of the contrast between concretism and abstractionism with respect to the treatment intensional entities.) #### 2.2.3 Actuality and Actualism As was noted in SS2.1.2, for the concretist, there is no special property of the actual world -- *actuality* -- that distinguishes it, in any absolute sense, from all of the others; it is simply the world that *we* inhabit. For abstractionists, however, actuality *is* a special property that distinguishes exactly one possible world from all others -- the actual world is the only world that happens to *obtain*; it is the one and only way things could be that is the way things as a whole, in fact, *are*. However, for most abstractionists, the distinctiveness of the actual world does not lie simply in its actuality but in its ontological comprehensiveness: the actual world encompasses all that there is. In a word: most abstractionists are *actualists*. Actualism is the thesis that everything that there is, everything that has *being* in any sense, is actual. In terms of possible worlds: Everything that exists in any world exists in the actual world.[32] Possibilism, by contrast, is the denial of actualism; it is the thesis that there are *mere possibilia*, i.e., things that are not actual, things that exist in other possible worlds but fail to exist in the actual world. Concretists are obviously not actualists (on their understanding of 'actual', at any rate).[33] Indeed, for the concretist, since individuals are worldbound, everything that exists in any nonactual possible world is distinct from everything in the actual world. However, although possibilism and abstractionism are entirely compatible -- Zalta (1983), for example, embraces both positions -- abstractionists *tend* to be actualists. The reason for this is clear: Basic possible world semantics appears to be committed to possibilism and abstractionism promises a way of avoiding that commitment. The specter of possibilism first arises with regard to *non-actual* possible worlds, which would seem by definition to be prime examples of mere *possibilia*. However, we have just seen that the abstractionist can avoid this apparent commitment to possibilism by defining possible worlds to be SOAs of a certain sort. So defined, non-actual worlds, i.e., worlds that fail to obtain, can still actually exist. Hence, the commitment of basic possible world semantics to non-actual worlds does not in itself threaten the actualist's ontological scruples. However, the specter of possibilism is not so easily exorcised. For non-actual worlds are not the only, or even the most compelling, examples of mere *possibilia* that seem to emerge out of basic possible world semantics. For instance, it is quite reasonable to think that evolution could have taken a very different course (or, if you like, that God could have made very different creative choices) and that there could have been individuals -- call them *Exotics* -- that are biologically very different from all actually existing individuals; so different, in fact, that no actually existing thing could possibly have been an Exotic. According to basic possible world semantics, the sentence 'There could have been Exotics' or, more formally, | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | *[?]*xEx* | is true just in case there is a world in which '[?]*xEx*' is true, i.e., when all is said and done, just in case: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | There is a possible world **w** and an individual **a** in **w** such that **a** is an Exotic in **w**, | which, a bit less formally, is simply to say that | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | Some individual is an Exotic in some possible world. | However, since no actually existing thing could have been an Exotic, anything that is an Exotic in some possible world cannot be among the things that exist in the actual world. Thus, the truth conditions that basic possible world semantics assigns to some of our intuitive modal beliefs appear to entail that there are non-actual individuals as well as non-actual possible worlds. Defining possible worlds as SOAs provided a way for the actualist to embrace non-actual worlds without compromising her actualism. But how is the actualist to understand the apparent commitment to non-actual *individuals* in such truth conditions as (25)? Answers that have been given to this question represent a rather deep divide between actualist abstractionists. On the one hand, "trace" actualists introduce actually existing entities into their ontologies that can play the role of mere *possibilia* in (25) and its like. Trace actualists come in two varieties: *new* actualists and *haecceitists*. New actualists like Linsky and Zalta (1996) and Williamson (1998, 2000, 2013) argue that, in fact, all individuals are actually existing, necessary beings but not all of them are necessarily *concrete*. Some concrete individuals -- those traditionally (mis-)categorized as contingent beings -- are only contingently concrete. Likewise, some non-concrete individuals -- those, like possible Exotics, traditionally (mis-)categorized as contingently non-actual mere *possibilia* -- are only contingently non-concrete.[34] This novel take on modal metaphysics allows the new actualist to reinterpret possible world semantics so as to avoid possibilism. Notably, the domain **d**(**w**) of a world **w** is understood not as the set of things that exist in **w** -- for all individuals exist in all worlds -- but the set of things that are *concrete* in **w**.[35] Hence, for the new actualist, the correct truth condition for (23) is: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | There is a possible world **w** and an individual **a** that is (i) concrete in **w** and (ii) an Exotic in **w**. | On the other hand, haecceitists like Plantinga introduce special properties -- haecceities -- to similar ends. The haecceity of an individual **a** is the property of being *that very individual*, the property **being **a****. A property is a *haecceity*, then, just in case it is possible that it is the haecceity of some individual.[36] It is a necessary truth that everything has a haecceity. More importantly, for haecceitists, haecceities are necessary beings. Thus, not only is it the case that, had any particular individual **a** failed to exist, its haecceity **ha** would still have existed, it is also the case that, for any "merely possible" individual **a**, there is an actually existing haecceity that would have been **a**'s haecceity had **a** existed. More generally (and more carefully) put: Necessarily, for any individual **a**, (i) **a** has a haecceity **h** and (ii) necessarily, **h** exists. Like the new actualists, then, the metaphysics of the haecceitists enables them to systematically reinterpret possible world semantics in such a way that the truth conditions of modal discourse are expressed solely in term of actually existing entities of some sort rather than actual and non-actual individuals. More specifically, for the haecceitist, the domain **d**(**w**) of a world **w** is taken to be the set of haecceities that are *exemplified* in **w**, that is, the set of haecceities **h** such that **w** includes ****h**'s being exemplified**. Likewise, the **w**-extension of a (1-place) predicate p is taken to be a *set* of haecceities -- intuitively, those haecceities that are coexemplified in **w** with the property expressed by p. So reinterpreted, the truth condition for (23) is: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | There is a possible world **w** and a haecceity **h** that is (i) exemplified in **w** and (ii) coexemplified with the property **being an Exotic** in **w**. | By contrast, "no-trace", or *strict*, actualists like Prior (1957), Adams (1981), and Fitch (1996) hew closely to the intuition that, had a contingent individual **a** failed to exist, there would have been absolutely no trace, no metaphysical vestige, of **a** -- neither **a** itself in some non-concrete state nor any abstract proxy for **a**. Hence, unlike trace actualism, there are no such vestiges in the actual world of objects that are not actual but only could have been. The logical consequences for no-trace actualists, however, appear to be severe; at the least they cannot provide a standard compositional semantics for modal languages, according to which (roughly) the meaning of a sentence is determined by its logical form and the meanings of its semantically significant constituents. In particular, if there is nothing to play the role of a "possible Exotic", nothing that is, or represents, an Exotic in some other possible world -- a mere *possibile*, a contingently non-concrete individual, an unexemplified haecceity -- then the strict actualist cannot provide standard, compositional truth conditions for quantified propositions like (23) that yield the intuitively correct truth value. For, understood compositionally, (23) is true if and only if '[?]*xEx*' is true at some world **w**. And that, in turn, is true at **w** if and only if '*Ex*' is true at **w** for some value of '*x*'. But, as just noted, for the strict actualist, there is no such value of '*x*'. Hence, for the strict actualist, '*Ex*' is false at **w** for all values of '*x*' and, hence, (23) is false as well. (These issues are explored in much greater detail in the entry on the possibilism-actualism debate.) #### 2.2.4 A Brief Assessment of Abstractionism Like concretism, abstractionism provides a reasonably clear and intuitive account of what worlds are and what it is to exist in them, albeit from a decidedly different perspective. Although, as noted in SS2.2.2, the fact that modality is a primitive in abstractionist definitions of possible worlds arguably compromises its ability to provide semantically illuminating truth conditions for the modal operators, those definitions can be taken to illuminate the connection between our basic modality concepts and the evocative notion of a possible world that serves as such a powerful conceptual tool for constructing philosophical arguments and for analyzing and developing solutions to philosophical problems. In this regard, particularly noteworthy are: Plantinga's (1974) influential work on the ontological argument and the free will defense against the problem of evil; Adams' (1974, 1981) work on actualism and actuality; and Stalnaker's (1968, 1987) work on counterfactual conditionals and mental content. A number of important objections have been voiced in regard to abstractionism. Some of these are addressed in the document Problems with Abstractionism. ### 2.3 Combinatorialism As its name might suggest, our third approach -- *combinatorialism* -- takes possible worlds to be recombinations, or rearrangements, of certain metaphysical simples. Both the nature of simples and the nature of recombination vary from theory to theory. Quine (1968) and Cresswell (1972), for example, suggest taking simples to be space-time points (modeled, perhaps, as triples of real numbers) and worlds themselves to be arbitrary sets of such points, each set thought of intuitively as a way that matter could be distributed throughout space-time. (A world *w*, so construed, then, is *actual* just in case a space-time point *p* is a member of *w* if and only if *p* is occupied by matter.) Alternatively, some philosophers define states a world could be in, and possible worlds themselves, simply to be maximally consistent sets of sentences[37] in an expressively rich language -- "recombinations", certainly, of the sentences of the language. (Lewis refers to this view as *linguistic ersatzism*.[38]) However, the predominant version of combinatorialism finds its origins in Russell's (1918/1919) theory of logical atomism and Wittgenstein's (1921, 1922, 1974) short but enormously influential *Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus*. A suggestive paper by Skyrms (1981) spelling out some of the ideas in the *Tractatus*, in turn, inspired a rich and sophisticated account that is developed and defended in great detail in an important series of books and articles by D. M. Armstrong (1978a, 1978b, 1986a, 1989, 1997, 2004b, 2004c). In this section, we present a somewhat simplified version of combinatorialism that draws primarily upon Armstrong's work. Unless otherwise noted, this is what we shall mean by 'combinatorialism' for the remainder. #### 2.3.1 The Basic Ontology of Combinatorialism Wittgenstein famously asserted that the world is the totality of *facts*, not of things (*ibid.*, SS1.1). The combinatorialist spells out Wittgenstein's aphorism explicitly in terms of an ontology of objects (a.k.a., particulars), universals (a.k.a., properties and relations), and facts. Facts are either atomic or molecular. Every atomic fact -- *Sachverhalt*, in the language of the *Tractatus* -- is "constituted" by an *n*-place relation (= property, for *n*=1) and *n* objects that *stand in*, or *exemplify*, that relation. Thus, for example, suppose that John is 1.8 meters tall. Then, in addition to John and the property **being 1.8 meters tall**, there is for the combinatorialist the atomic fact of John's exemplifying that property. More generally, atomic facts exist according to the following principle: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **AF** | | Objects **a**1, ..., **a***n* exemplify *n*-place relation **R** iff there is the fact **a1, ..., a*n*'s exemplifying R** ([**R**,**a**1,...,**a***n*], for short). | Say that the **a***i* are the *constituent objects* of the fact in question and **R** its *constituent universal*, and that **R** and the **a***i* all *exist in* [**R**,**a**1,...,**a***n*]. A fact is *monadic* if its constituent universal is a property. A *molecular* fact **f** is a conjunction of atomic facts. Its constituent objects and universals are exactly those of its conjuncts and an entity exists in **f** just in case it exists in one of its conjuncts. (For simplicity, we stipulate that an atomic fact has (only) itself as a conjunct and, hence, is "trivially" molecular.) One fact **f** *includes* another **g** if every conjunct of **g** is a conjunct of **f**. (Note, importantly, that inclusion, so defined, is quite different from the homonymous notion defined in the discussion of abstractionism above -- most notably, combinatorial inclusion is not a *modal* notion.) For purposes below, say that an object **a** is a *bare particular in* a molecular fact **f** if there is no monadic conjunct of **f** of which **a** is the constituent object, no conjunct of the form **a exemplifies F**, for some property **F**. **a** is a *bare particular* if it is bare in every molecular fact. Intuitively, of course, a bare particular is an unpropertied object. There is no upper bound on the "size" of a molecular fact and no restriction on which atomic facts can form a conjunction; for any atomic facts at all, there is a molecular fact whose conjuncts are exactly those facts. As a first cut, then, we can spell out Wittgenstein's characterization of the (actual) world as the totality of facts by defining the world to be the largest molecular fact, the molecular fact that includes all of the atomic facts.[39] Although objects and universals are typically included along with facts in the basic ontology of combinatorialism, facts are typically considered more fundamental. Indeed, taking his queue from the Tractarian thesis that the world consists of facts, not things, Armstrong (1986a, 577) argues that facts alone are ontologically basic and that objects and universals are simply "aspects of, abstractions from" facts. Accordingly, he calls the object constituent of a fact of the form [**P**,**a**] a "thin" particular, an object "considered in abstraction from all its [intrinsic] properties" (1993, 433); and where **N** is the conjunction of "all the non-relational properties of that particular (which would presumably include **P**), the atomic fact **a's exemplifying N** itself is the corresponding "thick" particular " (*ibid*., 434 -- we will occasionally use italics to distinguish a thin particular *a* from the corresponding thick particular **a**). Though not all combinatorialists of every stripe buy into Armstrong's "factualist" metaphysics (Bricker 2006), they do generally agree that facts are more fundamental, at least to the extent that both the notion of a bare particular, i.e., an object exemplifying no properties, and that of an unexemplified property are considered incoherent; insofar as they exist at all, the existence of both particulars and universals depends on their "occurring" in some fact or other. Whatever their exact ontological status, it is an important combinatorialist thesis that exactly *what* objects and universals exist is ultimately a matter for natural science, not metaphysics, to decide. Objects can be either simple or complex. An object is *simple* if it has no proper parts, and *complex* otherwise. Like objects, universals too divide into simple and complex. A universal is simple if it has no other universal as a constituent, and complex otherwise. Complex universals accordingly come in two varieties: conjunctive -- the constituents of which are simply its conjuncts -- and structural. A structural universal **U** is one that is exemplified by a complex object **O**, and its constituents are universals (distinct from **U**) exemplified by simple parts of **O** that are relevant to **O**'s being an instance of **U**.[40] It is important to note that, for Armstrong, the constituency relation is not the mereological parthood relation. Rather, complex universals (hence also complex facts of which they are constituents) enjoy a "non-mereological mode of composition" (1997, 119-123) that, in particular, allows for a richer conception of their structure.[41] (An assumption of our simplified account here will be that both the *proper part of* relation and the constituency relation are well-founded. It follows that (i) there is no *gunk*, i.e., that every complex object is composed, ultimately, entirely of simples and (ii) complex universals -- hence the complex facts in which they are exemplified -- are ultimately "grounded" in simple facts, i.e., that they cannot be infinitely decomposed into further complex universals/facts.[42]) To illustrate the basic idea: in Figure 1, the left-hand diagram depicts a water molecule **W** comprising an oxygen atom **o** and two hydrogen atoms **h1** and **h2**. For the combinatorialist, "thick" particulars like the molecule itself as well as its constituent atoms are themselves facts: **o** is the fact [**O**,*o*] in which the universal **oxygen** (**O**) is exemplified by a thin particular *o*;[43] likewise **h1** and **h2**. **W** in turn comprises those monadic facts and the relational facts [**B**,**o**,**h**1], [**B**,**o**,**h**2] wherein the covalent bonding relation **B** holds between the oxygen atom and the two hydrogen atoms. The structural universal **Water** itself, then, shares this structure -- it is, so to say, an *isomorph* consisting of the monadic universals **O** and **H** and the binary relation **B**, structured as indicated in the right-hand diagram of Figure 1.[44] ![diagram of structure of water](Water.png) Figure 1: A Water Molecule **W** and the Structural Universal **Water** #### 2.3.2 States of Affairs and Recombination It should be clear from principle **AF** that all atomic facts *hold*; that is, all of them reflect actual exemplification relations. Obviously, however, possibility encompasses more than what is actual, that is, there are *possible* facts as well as actual facts; the world's universals might have been exemplified by its objects very differently. If they had -- if the world's objects and universals had combined in a very different way -- there would have been a very different set of atomic facts and, hence, a very different world. To spell out the idea of a possible fact, the combinatorialist introduces the more general notion of an atomic *(combinatorial) state of affairs*, that is, an entity that simply has the *form* of an atomic fact -- *n* objects exemplifying an *n*-place relation -- but without any requirement that the exemplification relation in question actually holds between them. More exactly: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **AS** | | For any objects **a**1, ..., **a***n* and any *n*-place relation **R**, there is an atomic (combinatorial) state of affairs **a**1, ..., **a***n*'s exemplifying **R** (again, [**R**,**a**1,...,**a***n*], for short). | Thus, even if the two hydrogen atoms **h**1 and **h**2 in a water molecule do not in fact stand in the covalent bonding relation **B**, there is nonetheless the (non-factual) state of affairs [**B**,**h**1,**h**2]. Combinatorialism takes facts to be literal, structured parts of the physical world. This suggests that a non-factual state of affairs -- a merely *possible* fact -- must be part of a merely possible physical world. This idea is at odds with the strong, scientifically-grounded form of actualism that typically motivates combinatorialism. Two options are available: The combinatorialist can follow the (actualist) abstractionists and define states of affairs to be philosophical or mathematical constructs consisting only of actual objects, properties, relations, and facts. For example, the state of affairs [**R**,**a**1,...,**a***n*] can simply be identified with the ordered *n*-tuple <**R**,**a**1,...,**a***n*> . So long as the combinatorialist is willing to adopt the additional metaphysical or set theoretic machinery, this sort of approach offers a way of introducing non-factual states of affairs that does not involve any untoward ontological commitments to merely possible entities. Alternatively, following Armstrong (1989, 46-51; 1997, 172-4), the combinatorialist can refuse to grant non-factual states of affairs any genuine ontological status and adopt a form of modal fictionalism that nonetheless permits one to speak *as if* such states of affairs exist. The exposition to follow will remain largely neutral between these options. Constituency for states of affairs is understood as for facts. Additionally, analogous to molecular facts, there are molecular states of affairs -- conjunctions of atomic states of affairs. Inclusion between states of affairs is understood exactly as it is between facts and being a *bare particular* in a molecular state of affairs **s** is understood as for facts: **a** is a bare particular in **s** if there is no monadic conjunct of **s** of the form ****a** exemplifies F**. The notion of recombination is now definable straightaway: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | **s** is a *recombination* of a molecular state of affairs **f** =*def* **s** is a molecular state of affairs whose constituent objects and constituent universals are exactly those of **f**. **s** is a *non-trivial* recombination of **f** if it does not include the same states of affairs as **f**. | Very roughly then, a *possible world* will be a certain sort of recombination of (some portion of) the *actual* world, the molecular fact that includes all of the atomic facts. This idea will be refined in the following sections. #### 2.3.3 Structural States of Affairs and Supervenience Say that a state of affairs is *structural* if it is atomic and its constituent universal is structural or it is molecular and includes a structural state of affairs; and say that it is *simple* otherwise. The difference between structural and simple universals and states of affairs is particularly significant with regard to the important concept of *supervenience* (Armstrong 1989, Ch 8).[45] Entity or entities **S** supervene on entity or entities **R** if and only if the existence of **R** necessitates that of **S** (*ibid.*, 103). (Necessitation here is, of course, ultimately to be spelled out in terms of combinatorial possible worlds.) Non-structural states of affairs supervene directly on their atomic conjuncts.[46] However, things are not in general quite so straightforward for structural states of affairs. For, although structural states of affairs are ultimately constituted entirely by simple states of affairs, unlike non-structural states of affairs, structural states of affairs typically supervene on more than the totality of their constituents. For, in many cases, whether or not a structural fact exists depends not only on the existence of its constituent facts but also on the *absence* of certain others (Armstrong 1997, 34ff). For example, as noted in our example above, our water molecule **W** comprises two further facts in which two hydrogen atoms **h**1 and **h**2 both stand in the covalent binding relation with an oxygen atom **o**. However, if **o** were to bind with a further hydrogen atom **h**3, then, despite the fact that the constituent facts of **W** would still hold, **W** would not be water; there would be no such fact as **W's being water**.[47] Rather, **W** would exist only as a complex part of a hydronium ion; the new binding [**B**,**o**,**h**3] would, so to say, "spoil" the instantiation of **Water**. Thus, more generally, whether or not a structural state of affairs **S** exists in a possible world typically requires something over and above its constituent states of affairs being "welded together" in the right sort of way (Armstrong, 1997, 36); it requires also that there be no relevant "spoilers" for **S**.[48] Armstrong draws directly on the initial passages of the *Tractatus*[49] for the necessary apparatus: a structural state of affairs **S** in any possible world **w**, supervenes, not simply on its constituent atomic states of affairs but on a certain *higher-order* state of affairs **T****w**, namely, the state of affairs that the (first-order) atomic states of affairs of **w** are *all the (first-order) atomic states of affairs* and, hence, that **w** includes no spoilers for **S**. Armstrong (*ibid.*, 35, 134-5, 196-201) calls **Tw** the *totality* state of affairs for the atomic states of affairs of **w**.[50] #### 2.3.4 Combinatorial Possible Worlds and Existence Therein The idea of possibility being rooted in arbitrary recombinations of the actual world, rearrangements of its objects and universals, is intuitively appealing. Clearly, however, not just any such recombination can count as a possible world. Some states of affairs are intuitively impossible -- [**being an elephant**, **e**], where **e** is an individual electron, say -- and some pairs of states of affairs, while individually possible, are not *com*possible -- the states of affairs [**having 1kg mass**, **a**] and [**having 2kg mass**, **a**] for a given object **a**, or, for a given mereological sum **m** of simples, the states of affairs [**being a baboon**, **m**] and [**being a hoolock**, **m**]. But nothing that has been said rules out the existence of recombinations of the actual world -- rearrangements of its objects and universals -- that include such states of affairs. Obviously, however, such recombinations cannot be thought to represent genuinely possible worlds. Of course, like the abstractionist, the combinatorialist could simply stipulate as part of the definition that all legitimate recombinations must be genuinely *possible* states of affairs of a certain sort, genuinely *possible* recombinations. But this will not do. For, like concretism, combinatorialism purports to be a *reductive* account of modality, an account of possible worlds that does not depend ultimately on modal notions (see Armstrong 1989, 33).[51] Here the distinction between simple and structural states of affairs together with the combinatorialist's strong notion of supervenience come to the fore. For, given that structural facts supervene on simple facts and the actual totality fact **T**@, the actual world can be defined more parsimoniously as the molecular fact that includes all the *simple* atomic facts and the totality fact **T**@. And at the level of simples, there are no limitations whatever on recombination (Wittgenstein 1921, 2.062-2.063); hence, any recombination of simple objects and universals is by definition considered possible. Thus Armstrong (1986a, 579): > > The simple individuals, properties, and relations may be combined in > *all* ways to yield possible [simple] atomic states of affairs, > provided only that the form of atomic facts is respected. That is the > combinatorial idea. > Worlds, in particular, can be defined as special cases of such recombinations, together with appropriate totality facts. To state this, we need a condition that ensures the existence of a unique actual world: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | States of affairs **s** and **t** are identical iff they include exactly the same states of affairs. | Given this, we have: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | The (combinatorial) actual world =*def* the fact @ that includes exactly all the simple atomic facts and the totality state of affairs **T**@ for the conjunction of those facts. | | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **AW3** | | **w** is a (combinatorial) possible world =*def* **w** is a recombination of the simple atomic facts of the actual world conjoined with the totality fact **Tw** for that recombination.[52] | Armstrong's ontological commitments are notoriously rather slippery but, given **AW3**, a reasonably complete notion of existence in a world is forthcoming. First, let us note that, for Armstrong, the "combinatorial idea" yields a substantial metaphysical thesis, as well, viz., the *ontological free lunch* (1986, 12ff), i.e., the thesis that "[w]hat supervenes is no addition of being"; that "whatever supervenes ... is not something ontologically additional to the subvenient entity or entities." Hence, for Armstrong, it appears that *simple* states of affairs and their constituents exist most fundamentally and that the existence of more complex entities is in a certain sense *derivative*. Thus: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | | | Entity **a** exists *fundamentally* in (combinatorial) possible world **w** =*def* (i) **a** is a simple state of affairs that **w** includes or (ii) **a** is a constituent or conjunct of an entity that exists fundamentally in **w**. | Given this, existence in a world generally -- both fundamental and derivative -- both for simples and (*first-order*[53]) non-simples alike, is definable as follows: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **AE3** | | Entity **a** exists in (combinatorial) possible world **w** =*def* either (i) **a** exists fundamentally in **w** or (ii) **a** supervenes on entities that exist in **w**. | Semantics receives rather short shrift in Armstrong's version of combinatorialism -- at least, semantics in the model theoretic sense of SS1.2 -- but, as it has played an important role in our discussion of concretism and abstractionism, we note briefly how the ontology of combinatorialism might be taken to populate a possible world interpretation of the language of modal predicate logic. Specifically, we can take the range of the modal operators -- understood, semantically, as quantifiers -- to be all of the combinatorial possible worlds in the sense of **AW3**. The domain **d**(**w**) of each world **w** is the set of all simple and complex objects that exist in **w** according to **AE3** and the **w**-extension **I**p(**w**) of a predicate p expressing a simple or complex universal **R** is the set of all *n*-tuples, <**a**1, ..., **a***n*> such that the atomic fact [**R**,**a**1,...,**a***n*] exists in **w**. #### 2.3.5 Analytic and Emergent Modalities; Essential Properties There are, then, for the combinatorialist no intrinsically modal phenomena; there are just all of the various worlds that exist on unrestricted combinatorial grounds alone. Ultimately, all genuine possibilities, simple or not, are just states of affairs that exist in these combinatorial worlds in the sense of **AE3**. However, it is not immediately as clear how to understand many intuitive *necessities*/*impossibilities* involving complex structural universals, for example, the impossibilities noted in the previous section, viz., that something simultaneously have a mass of both 1kg and 2kg or simultaneously be both a baboon and a hoolock. Likewise, it is not entirely clear how combinatorialism accounts for intuitive facts about essential properties, such as that our water molecule **W** is essentially water or that Algol is essentially a dog. Combinatorialists argue that such modal facts can nevertheless be explained in terms that require no appeal to primitive modal features of the world (Armstrong 2004b, 15). **Analytic Modalities.** Armstrong argues that many intuitive modal facts -- notably, the impossibility of an object exemplifying more than one determinate of the same determinable -- can be understood ultimately as logical, or analytic, modalities that are grounded in meaning rather than any primitive modal features of reality. For example, intuitively it is impossible that an object simultaneously exemplify the structural properties **having 2kg mass** and **having 1kg mass**. The combinatorial reason for this (cf. Armstrong 1989, 79) is that, for an object **a** to exemplify the former property is simply for there to be a division of **a** into two wholly distinct parts, both of which exemplify the latter property. Moreover, this division into parts is entirely arbitrary, that is, for *any* part **a**1 of **a** exemplifying **having 1kg mass**, there is a (unique) part **a**2 of **a** wholly distinct from **a**1 that also exemplifies that property. It follows that, if our 2kg object **a** itself *also* exemplifies **having 1kg mass**, then, as **a** is a part of itself, there must be a 1kg part of **a** that is wholly distinct from **a**. And that is analytically false, false "solely by virtue of the meaning we attach to" the word 'part' (*ibid*., 80).[54] **Emergent Modalities.** Combinatorialism purports to explain a further class of intuitive modal facts as features that simply "emerge" from facts about structural properties.[55] The discussion of structural states of affairs and supervenience above provides an example. Let us suppose the actual world **w**1 includes our water molecule **W** from Figure 1 plus a further hydrogen atom **h**3. In this world, only **h**1 and **h**2 bind to **o**. Hence, this world includes the state of affairs **W's being water** but not the state of affairs **I's being hydronium** in which **o**, **h**1, **h**2, and **h**3 are so bonded as to constitute a hydronium ion **I**. Conversely, however, given the unrestricted nature of recombination, there is a world **w**2 that includes **W** structured as it actually is in **w**1 but which also includes the spoiler [**B**,**o**,**h**3] -- where **o** and **h**3 bond -- and, hence, the structural state of affairs **I's being hydronium**. Thus, the absence of [**B**,**o**,**h**3] in **w**1 enables the emergence of **W's being water** and precludes **I's being hydronium** whilst its presence in **w2** enables the emergence of the latter but precludes the former. As a consequence, it is impossible that the states of affairs **W's being water** and **I's being hydronium** coexist.[56] ![diagram of structure of water](Water-and-Hydronium.png) Figure 2: **W**'s being water and (given a bond between **o** and **h**3) **I**'s being hydronium Although more dramatic, large-scale examples of incompatible states of affairs -- such as a thing's being simultaneously both a baboon and a hoolock -- might be vastly more complex, there is no obvious reason why their impossibility could not have the same sort of combinatorial explanation. **Essential Properties.** It follows from the unrestricted nature of recombination that, for any simple object **a** and simple universal **P**, **a** recombines with **P** in some worlds and fails to recombine with **P** in others. Generalizing from this fact, it follows that no simple or sum of simples has any simple universal or conjunction of simple universals essentially. It also follows that no such object has any structural property essentially. For assume **o** is such an object and that it exemplifies a structural property **P**. Since **P** is structural, it supervenes on some set of simple states of affairs. But by the nature of recombination, there are combinatorial worlds in which those states of affairs do not exist and, hence, in which **P** doesn't but **o** -- being a simple or a sum of simples -- does. Thick particulars like our water molecule **W** don't fare much better because of the possibility of spoilers. For Armstrong (1997, 35), **W** is simply the conjunction of its constituent states of affairs. As we've just seen, however, in the presence of spoilers, that conjunction would exist -- hence, **W** would exist -- without being **Water**. Hence, it would seem that at least some properties that, intuitively, are essential to their bearers turn out not to be for the combinatorialist. The problem is compounded by the fact that some intuitively non-essential properties of some thick particulars are arguably essential for the combinatorialist. The shape properties of a thick particular **A**, for example, would seem to be a function of its constituent states of affairs. Moreover, the exemplification of such properties are not obviously subject to spoilers the way that natural kind properties like **Water** are. Hence, as **A** is identical to the conjunction of its constituent states of affairs, it would seem that it will have the same shape in any world in which it exists, i.e., it will have that shape essentially. That said, combinatorialism can arguably provide a reasonably robust analysis of intuitions about the essential properties of ordinary thick particulars like dogs or persons. Such objects can be taken to be temporal successions of sums of simples and each sum in the succession as its temporal parts. Sums in the same rough temporal neighborhood are composed of roughly the same simples and are structured in roughly the same way. Similarities between such objects across worlds in turn determine counterpart relations. Following Lewis, the essential properties of such objects can then be identified with those properties exemplified by (all of the temporal parts of) all of its counterparts in every world in which it exists (Armstrong 1997, 99-103, 169).[57] #### 2.3.6 Fewer Things and Other Things: Modified Combinatorialism Since a possible world is a recombination of the actual world and every recombination includes states of affairs involving every simple individual and every simple universal, by **AE3**, every simple entity exists in every world. Hence, there could not have been fewer of them; nor could there have been simples other than the ones there actually are. In this section, we address this issue and the issue of contingent existence generally in combinatorialism. **Fewer things.** Combinatorialism as it stands has no problem accounting for the general intuition that there could have been fewer things. We have already noted in SS2.3.3 and again in SS2.3.5 how our water molecule **W**, as such, might not have existed. More generally, given the unrestricted nature of recombination, for any **a** involving a structural fact **S**, there are recombinations of the actual world wherein either (a) some of the relations among **a**'s constituents that are critical to **S**'s structure fail to be exemplified by those constituents, or (b) there are further states of affairs included by those recombinations that act as spoilers for **S**. Consequently, the combinatorialist seems to have no difficulty explaining how there might have been fewer water molecules, humans, etc. Intuitively, however, there isn't anything in the idea of a simple that suggests that simples are necessary beings -- especially if, as combinatorialists generally agree, simples are physical things of some sort and simple universals are properties of, and relations among, those things. For there is nothing in the nature of a simple object to suggest that any given simple had to have existed. Likewise, there is nothing in the nature of a simple universal to suggest it had to have been exemplified and, hence, on the combinatorialist's own conception of universals, that it had to exist. Otherwise put, as simples exist only insofar as they are constituents of facts, there seems no reason why there couldn't have been a very small number of facts, indeed, just a single simple, atomic, monadic fact and, hence, a lone simple object and a lone simple universal. In fact, however, **AW3** can be easily modified to accommodate these intuitions without doing any serious violence to combinatorialist intuitions. Specifically, the combinatorialist can admit "contracted" worlds in which fewer simples exist by allowing any recombination of *any* simple fact -- that is, equivalently, by allowing any state of affairs -- to count as a possible world: | | | | | --- | --- | --- | | **AW3'** | | **w** is a (combinatorial) possible world =*def* **w** is a recombination of some simple fact **f** conjoined with the totality state of affairs **Tw** for that recombination. | **AE3** requires no modification, as it was defined with sufficient generality above. Under **AW3'**, however, **AE3** entails that all entities alike -- objects and universals, simple and structural -- are contingent and, indeed, that every simple object is the sole constituent of some combinatorial possible world. **Other things.** Intuitively, not only could there have been fewer things, there could have been more things or, more generally, things *other* than those that actually exist. As above, combinatorialism as it stands seems able to account for many instances of this intuition: Figure 2 illustrates how a non-actual hydronium ion **I** might exist in another world. Likewise, there seems no reason to deny, e.g., that there are rearrangements **w** of the actual world's simples wherein exist all of the human beings that actually exist (at, say, 0000GMT 1 January 2013) and more besides that are composed of simples that, in fact, constitute things other than human beings (Armstrong 1997, 165).[58] Combinatorialism also seems able to account for the possibility of conjunctive and structural universals that are simply rearrangements of actual simples. It is not implausible to think that such recombinations can give rise to, say, exotic biological kinds that have no actual instances (Armstrong 1989, 55-56). Thus, in particular, combinatorialism seems quite able to provide the truth condition (24) for (23) and, hence, can account for some possibilities involving "missing" universals that, intuitively, ought to be possible. However, it is far from clear that such possibilities exhaust the modal intuition that other things could have existed. Notably, intuitively, there could have been different *simple* universals distinct from any that actually exist -- different fundamental properties of simples, for example. Likewise for simple objects. Either way, there seems to be nothing in the idea of a simple object or simple universal that suggests there couldn't have been simples other than, or in addition to, the simples there are in fact. But **AW3**' does not allow for this; the simples of every possible world are a subset of the actual simples and there is no obvious way of modifying the principle to accommodate the intuition. Nor is there any obvious way of modifying the principle to accommodate the intuition in question.[59] The combinatorialist could of course abandon actualism and include merely possible simples into her ontology. Again, she could follow the new actualists and draw a division between actually concrete and non-actual, possibly concrete simples; or she could introduce Plantinga-style haecceities to go proxy for merely possible simples. But all of these options would be badly out of step with the strong, naturalist motivations for combinatorialism: There is but the one physical world comprising all of the facts; recombinations of (at least some of) those facts -- arbitrary rearrangements of their simple objects and universals -- determine the possible worlds. Mere *possibilia*, merely possible non-*concretia*, and non-qualitative haecceities have no real place in that picture. The "purest" option for the combinatorialist is simply to brazen it out and argue that the actual simples are, in fact, all the simples there could be (Armstrong 1989, 54ff; Driggers 2011, 56-61). A more robust option suggested by Skyrms (1981) makes some headway against the problem by introducing an "outer", or "second-grade" realm of possibility, but at the cost of moving beyond the basic intuitions of combinatorialism (Armstrong 1989, 60; 1997, 165-167). Finally, Sider (2005, 681) suggests that combinatorialists who (like Armstrong) are modal fictionalists can deal with the problem of missing entities simply by appealing to yet more fictionalism: As the combinatorialist fiction *already* includes non-actual states of affairs with actually existing constituents, there seems no reason not to extend the fiction to include non-actual states of affairs whose constituents include non-actual particulars and universals. Fictionalism itself, however, leaves the combinatorialist with the deep problems detailed by Kim (1986), Lycan (1993), and Rosen (1993).[60] #### 2.3.7 A Brief Assessment of Combinatorialism As with concretism and abstractionism, combinatorialism provides reasonably clear definitions of possible worlds and existence in a world and is noteworthy for its attempt to avoid what might be thought of as the metaphysical excesses of the two competing views. In contrast to concretism, combinatorialism is staunchly actualist: instead of an infinity of alternative physical universes, each with its own unique inhabitants existing as robustly as the inhabitants of the actual world, the worlds of combinatorialism are simply rearrangements of the universals and particulars of the actual world; and commitment even to them might be avoided if some version of fictionalism is tenable. Likewise, in contrast to abstractionism's rather rich and unrestrained ontology of SOAs, combinatorialism's states of affairs are comparatively modest. Moreover, in contrast to nearly all versions of abstractionism, combinatorialism shares with concretism the virtue of a reductive theory of modality: Modal statements, ultimately, are true or false in virtue of how things stand with respect to worlds that are themselves defined in non-modal terms. Combinatorialism's ontological modesty, however, is also a weakness. For, unlike, the two competing approaches, there are modal intuitions that the combinatorialist is not easily able to account for, notably, the intuition that there could have been other things. Additional difficulties are discussed in the supplemental document Further Problems for Combinatorialism.
wright
## 1. Biographical Sketch Chauncey Wright was born in Northampton, Massachusetts, in 1830, where his family had lived since colonial times and where his father had been a merchant and deputy-sheriff of the county. In 1848, he entered Harvard College. His education there included two years of advanced study in natural sciences. Graduating in 1852, he took employment with the Nautical Almanac office in Cambridge as a computer. This work constituted his livelihood throughout his life. He concentrated his work for each year into the last three months of the year, devoting the rest of the time to his own studies in the logic of science and metaphysics. The first philosophical influence on Wright was the Scottish realist, Sir William Hamilton, whose works formed the curriculum for Francis Bowen's teaching of philosophy at Harvard. Wright was, however, greatly influenced by John Stuart Mill's criticism of Hamilton, and the influence of Mill is evident in Wright's views on utility in science and ethics. The great conversion of his life came, however, with his reading of Darwin's *Origin of Species*, published in 1859. Wright became an American defender of Darwin against his religious antagonists and also, like Harvard's Asa Gray, against Darwin's scientific critics in America. Wright taught for a short time at Harvard, but was not successful as a lecturer. He was an intellectual conversationalist and through his participation in a succession of study groups in Cambridge, influenced Charles S. Peirce, William James, and Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., among others. In spite of his perspicacity and his dispassionate logical approach to discussion, he also had a gentle, sometimes angelic, temperament. Children liked him and he was willing to spend time entertaining them. He was close to Charles Eliot Norton and his family and exchanged many letters with Norton's sisters. When his friends were away for extended periods, Wright's spirits and health suffered. He endured two bouts of deep depression from which his friends roused him. Among his friends Wright counted both William and Henry James. William James said of Wright, "Never in a human head was contemplation more separated from desire." Wright died of a stroke in Cambridge, Massachusetts, in 1875, at the age of 45.[3] ## 2. Wright's Philosophy of Science ### 2.1 Verification Wright's writings are contained in two volumes, *Philosophical Discussions*, a collection of his articles published in American and British periodicals of the time, and *Letters*, collected shortly after his death by his friend James B. Thayer.[4] Two fundamental epistemological themes are prominent throughout his work: 1) sense perception provides the only *evidence* whose authority all humankind acknowledges, and 2) sense experience alone can produce the *conviction and permanence* that we believe knowledge should have. The first point addresses the problem of the diversity of truth claims, the second the expectation that genuine truth claims not be superseded. He said: > All observers not laboring under hallucinations of the > senses are agreed, or can be made to agree, about facts of sensible > experience, through evidence toward which the intellect is merely > passive, and over which the individual will and character have no > control. Such evidence is not the only kind which produces belief; > though positivism maintains that it is the only kind which > *ought* to produce so high a degree of confidence as all minds > have or can be made to have through their agreements. (*L* > 96) Conviction should be accompanied by consensus, and only sense perception can claim consensus among honest investigators. Wright often acknowledged there were legitimate sources of *belief* besides sense perception -- faith or rational introspection for instance -- but none of them were adequate as sources of *knowledge*. Wright did not analyze sense experience into sense data, preferring to trust the holistic character of ordinary experience and most scientific observation. He introduced no theory of perception nor did he address the possible contamination of sense experience by preconceived notions. He rather placed the weight of conviction upon the employment of verification, which he allied at different times with scientific method, the philosophical doctrine of induction, and Comte's positivism. He said that the ancients did not make more progress in science because "they did not, or could not, verify their theories" (*PD* 45). Furthermore, all that really distinguishes metaphysics from science in the modern era is that metaphysics lacks method and "well-grounded canons of research and criticism" (*PD* 366). Wright, then, regarded the nature of verification as evident and without problems of interpretation. Verification was part of the solution to the problems that beset theory-making and explanation, e.g., the competing claims about what theoretical entities exist, and what factors should militate for or against acceptance of any theory or cosmology. Asserting the priority of verification as the judge of theory, Wright said that discussion of the origin of theories or any claim for their *a priori* character is of no moment in science, "which maintains strict neutrality toward all philosophical systems" (*PD* 47). He said that the only difference between theories and facts is that theories are more complex and less directly testable (*PD* 44). Unlike later logical positivists, however, Wright did not hold that terms or descriptions for theoretical entities were meaningless or to be resolved only into propositions stating their verifiable consequences. The unobservables postulated by science are "for the purpose of giving a material or visual basis to the phenomena and empirical laws of life in general" (*PD* 164-65), and some of them will be proven to exist. In this regard, he likened Darwin's gemmule theory to Newton's corpuscular theory of light and the molecular theory of matter. In alluding to the difficulty of representing the extremely small size of molecules as measured by Thomson, Wright said: > But there is no reason to doubt that in every such molecule > there are still subordinate parts and structures; or that, even in > these parts, a still finer order of parts and structures exists, at > least to the extent of assimilated growth and *simple* division. > Mr. Darwin supposes such growths and divisions in the vital gemmules. > (*PD* 166) The important thing about hypothesized unobservables is that they be related to actual phenomena in such a way as to have verifiable consequences. Even at this, unobservables should not be specialized natures or forces taken to account just for certain phenomena. This was, according to Wright, the problem with scholastic substantial forms (*PD* 166-67). His criticism of metaphysical concepts was that they are empirically poor; they do not link different phenomena and do not generate predictions that can be verified at the level of the tangible and visible. Unlike early modern critics of scholastic metaphysical concepts, Wright did not claim that scientific concepts are by comparison clear and simple. Indeed, theoretical entities in modern science can be hard to represent to ourselves because of the limitations of our conceptions to perceptible forms and properties (*PD* 166). Wright speculated that there were "orders of forces" between the physico-chemical and the vital, just as there are intermediate phenomena between the vegetative functions of an animal and sensibility, i.e., sensation and perception. But since sensibility presents the elements from which conceptions of size and movement must come, our conceptions of forces and hidden elements are limited to the sensible (*PD* 167). There are thus areas of nature we would investigate that are largely inaccessible to us because of empirical limitations. Wright did not resort to reductionism to bridge this gap in our knowledge. He said, "Can sensibility and the movements governed by it be derived directly by chemical synthesis from the forces of inorganic elements? It is probable, both from analogy and direct observation, that they cannot" (*PD* 167). To determine what theoretical entities are real is difficult but is nevertheless the task of science, which always concerns itself with facts.[5] Given the realist tendency of his treatment of unobservables, indirect verification is an important part of Wright's conception of the empirical basis of all knowledge. The theory of gravity, which Wright takes to be proven, "fails to become a fact in the proper sense" because it can never be verified by direct and immediate sensory activity. Its truth must be verified indirectly. He said: > Modern science deals then no less with theories than with > facts, but always as much as possible with the verification of > theories, -- if not to make them facts by simple verification > through experiment and observation, at least to prove their truth by > indirect verification (*PD* 45). Wright did not elaborate upon the difference between direct and indirect verification in actual practice. He had much more to say about differences in method between science and philosophy. He believed that all branches of knowledge had to follow the method of verification belonging to science. The "philosophy of method" is incomplete, however, in that it cannot say what constitutes verification in all the departments of knowledge. Because there is no "complete inventory of our primary sources of knowledge," there can be disagreement as to what constitutes a legitimate appeal to observation or what is a real verification (*PD* 45). Platonists or rationalists claim verification for their theories because they have made an observation of what reason reveals to them. In fact, they have made an induction from rational introspection (*PD* 46). The positivists' claim, which Wright endorsed, is simply that "verification by reason settles nothing" and that only data from sensible experience are reliable enough to admit ideas into the range of what is held to be true. Wright added to this that verification means empirical judgment made upon *deduction* of consequences, not induction either from sense data or examination of self-consciousness (*PD* 47). Nevertheless, even science that aims at a complete empiricism must admit some "ideal or transcendental elements." In every case, however, these elements must yield consequences that are testable, either by themselves or in conjunction with empirically derived notions (*PD* 47). For example, from Wright's standpoint, the cosmological theory that the universe is developing, not just changing, might be a plausible interpretation of the data available to astronomers of his day. But he thought the notion of development relies implicitly on the idea of an end or culmination. So this "development theory," which he calls "transcendental," must still submit to empirical test (*PD* 17, 118). He denied Kant's division of knowledge into "*data* of experience and *conditions* of experience" and so did not admit the transcendental in the sense of the rational a priori (*L* 106). ### 2.2 Induction Despite Wright's distinguishing verification from induction, the latter, nevertheless, played an important role in his philosophy of science. Induction is relevant to his views of what makes for a rigorous science and what constitutes truth in science. Wright did not think it informative to contrast intuition and induction, because they do not refer to different ultimate grounds of belief (*PD* 373). Intuition is "rapid, instinctive judgment, whether in the objective sensible perception of relatively concrete matters, or in the most abstract" (*PD* 372). Intuition is properly contrasted to inference, i.e., reasoning, whether inductive or deductive. 'Inductive,' then, refers to the a posteriori *source* of reasoning, i.e., from evidence. It does not refer to a procedure for generalizing from evidence. He said, "In their primary signification and in this connection the terms 'induction' and 'inductive' refer directly to evidences, and not to any special means and processes of collating and interpreting them" (*PD* 372). So, induction may begin from a variety of sources. What philosophers, either Platonist or Cartesian, usually call intuition he understood to be induction from the data of self-consciousness. Even induction from sense experience is not of one type. It may start with evidence taken from different levels of perceptual and experiential complexity and is at work at different stages of an investigation. This approach to induction is guided by the character of scientific knowledge itself, which Wright understood to be the relating of particular facts to more general ones (*PD* 205-206). But it also follows the character of natural phenomena. In biology in particular, the new science of evolution concerns the "external economy of life" and thus must investigate an accumulation of related facts of observation at the level of secondary causes (*PD* 99-100). Induction may come from ordinary experience, experiment, or the inspections of the field naturalist. He said, "Inductions are still performed for the most part unconsciously and unsystematically.... But when and however ideas are developed science cares nothing, for it is only by subsequent tests of sensible experience that ideas are admitted into the pandects of science" (*PD* 47). For Wright, no axioms of science can be absolute. He said: > But all that is really implied in the name [axiom] is that > truths when *called* axioms are *used* for the deductive > proof of other truths, and that their own proof is not involved in the > process. This does not deny, however, that they may be, as truths, the > conclusions of other processes; to wit, the inductions of experience. > If they are, then the only ultimate truths are the particulars of > concrete experience, and no postulate or general assumption is inherent > in science until its proceedings become systematic, or the truths > already reached give direction to further research (*L* > 109). In this passage, axioms are not foundational in an epistemological sense. We seek simple principles of physical reality but must be wary of taking them as foundations in the sense of ultimate simple facts. The only ultimate in knowledge is recourse to the empirical in verification. Though verification depends on deduction, it does not depend on absolutely true starting points of deduction to yield reliable knowledge. This part of Wright's view reflects his assimilation of the positivist understanding of science as a taxonomy of practical experience with nature. ### 2.3 Positivism Several issues were involved in the view of science as a taxonomy or grammar. The influential French positivist, Auguste Comte, along with scientific positivists like Mach, distrusted theoretical concepts in science because they saw that these concepts rely on elements of practical experience.[6] A prime example was the relation of the concept of gravity to the experience of weight on the surface of the earth. Comte said that gravitation is a "general fact" which is itself "a mere extension of [a fact] which is perfectly familiar to us, and which we therefore say that we know; -- the weight of bodies on the surface of the earth" (*Comte* 28-29). Positivists believed we cannot avoid the anthropomorphic origin of theoretical concepts. It had, however, become clear to positivists who were actually engaged in the practice of science that the structure of a science is what sustains prediction, not the meaning of the theoretical terms of the science. A system of principles constitutes a logical form of explanation, and the ability of the system of principles to link disparate phenomena, more than concepts, is the truth in science. As a result, descriptions of the logical character of a science come to the fore in discussions of theory. Wright's emphasis on verification, his pluralism about induction, and his focus on the logical character of scientific principles together show that he had absorbed important aspects of scientific positivism. He often highlighted scientific theory as classificatory (*PD* 363) and emphasized the relating of higher and lower levels of generality as the hallmark of science. He referred to the positivists often and to Comte in particular. In a passage that parallels Auguste Comte, Wright said that every scientific distinction is of value in classification and "must coincide with and be of use as a sign of other distinctions -- that is, be a mark of the things distinguished by it" (*PD* 370).[7] This passage points to Wright as a link between Comte's positivism and C.S. Peirce, who believed that concepts are indexical signs. Although he had no semiotic theory, Wright's view of scientific discourse as a device substituting for useless thought made him sensitive to the role of signs (*PD* 280). Wright also identified the objective value of science with its use. He meant by this "its relatedness or ulterior value, whether as leading to other and wider ranges of knowledge, or as a discipline of the mind, or even as leading to 'bread and butter'" (*PD* 282). Peirce, as is well-known, insisted that the meaning of a concept *is* its use or effect. In contrast, Wright believed theoretical statements have meaning other than their effects, but the truth of the statements is judged by whether predicted effects or results are verified.[8] His own approach to signs is evident in his speculation, undertaken at the urging of Darwin, about the origin of self-consciousness. Here Wright treated concepts as images. He traced the emergence of self-consciousness in terms of human awareness of different kinds of signs (usually vocal, he said) that recall images in thought. The images themselves act as signs when a human being reasons, but "with reference to the more vivid outward signs, they are, in the animal mind, merged in the things signified, like stars in the light of the sun" (*PD* 209). The conscious awareness of the difference between outward and inward signs is crucial to human awareness, he believed. This awareness may have come with the "consciousness of simultaneous internal and external suggestion" and the recognition of the outward sign as a substitute for the inward sign (*PD* 210). The key to rationality is the outward sign itself, i.e., elements of language, being made the object of attention (*PD* 206).[9] It is worth noting that, in a letter of 1869, Wright used the term consilience to explain the advantages of positivism over the "older philosophy."[10] Positivism, he said, is a system of "universal methods, hypotheses, and principles" founded on the sciences. It is not a universal science itself but must be "coextensive with actual knowledge, and exhibit the consilience of the sciences" (L, 141). Consilience was a term used by William Whewell in 1858 to describe the coherence and mutual consistency of different scientific disciplines as they develop. This coherence, for Whewell, was a test of the truth of the sciences.[11] In summary, Wright's understanding of science and its method are distinguished by (1) his refusal to theorize about sense data and his consequent grounding of empiricism in the type of data available to everyday perceiving, (2) his nuanced treatment of induction, which rejects Cartesian starting points, and (3) his combination of verification with methodological realism about theoretical entities. ## 3. Interpretation of Darwin Wright was in advance of his contemporaries in his understanding of Darwin's change in organisms and species, in part because he applied the foregoing interpretation of science to Darwin's theory. Wright highlighted the overall structure of the theory of evolution, which he believed illustrated the principle of utility. He also characterized evolutionary change in terms of different levels of causative and explanatory principles. Natural selection is a descriptive principle that unifies these other principles in a comprehensive account. It is a template, a form of explanation, by which an investigator may be guided in finding how more basic explanatory principles -- the principles of chemistry and the laws of inheritance, for instance -- issue in features of living things observable by direct perception. Wright said that natural selection is a manifestation of the all-pervasive principle of utility, which governs adaptation. Utility he characterized in this way: "Let the questions of the uses of life, then, be put in this shape: To what ascertainable form or phase of life is this or that other form or phase of life valuable or serviceable?" (*L* 274-75). Features or parts of a living thing are forms or phases of life that serve the organism's more general functions and its survival. Perception of colors, for instance, serves to avoid the effects of dispersion of light in perception and to make possible definition of objects in vision through limits in sensibility (*L* 279). Using teleological language without teleological intent, he said, "Colors were invented by Nature to avoid the confusing effects of dispersion" (*L* 279). The physical laws of optics in this case lend themselves to an adaptation useful to living things. Theorists of evolution are sometimes criticized for offering 'just so' stories of adaptation. How a given serviceable feature might have evolved is taken as tantamount to how it actually did evolve. There is, however, a valuable insight about the nature of evolutionary science to be gleaned from the practice of giving likely stories of evolution. The general form of explanation by utility is more important than which particular explanation by natural selection is advanced to explain a feature or structure. At this very early stage of reception of Darwin's theory, Wright had already realized this. In correspondence with Darwin, Wright said, "The inquiry as to which of several real uses is the *one* through which natural selection has acted for the development of any faculty or organ ... has for several years seemed to me a somewhat less important question than it seemed formerly and still appears to most thinkers on the subject" (*L* 335). Wright thought there might be a plurality of uses for the same feature in the history of an organism. Sometimes these uses are contemporaneous; at other times they succeed one another in the course of evolution. Wright believed that thinking in terms of natural selection would shed light on physiological questions and connect chemical and physical explanations to the more complicated phenomena of life (*PD* 296). He realized that natural selection promised to be a research program for investigation that would unify biological science. Wright strongly criticized Herbert Spencer's philosophy of evolution, both because of its excessive claims for the range of evolution and because of Spencer's understanding of evolution as a force or operative cause. There is no Law of Evolution applicable to nature and civilization. Spencer's examples drawn from the history of civilization are not truly scientific and are "liable to the taint of teleological and cosmological conception." (*PD* 73). Wright said, "To us Mr. Spencer's speculation seems but the abstract statement of the cosmological conceptions, and that kind of orderliness which the human mind spontaneously supplies in the absence of facts sufficiently numerous and precise to justify sound scientific conclusions" (*PD* 73). In a review of a collection of essays by Alfred Wallace, the co-discoverer of the principle of natural selection, Wright said: > Strictly speaking, Natural Selection is not a cause at all, > but is the mode of operation of a certain quite limited class of > causes. Natural Selection never made it come to pass, as a habit of > nature, that an unsupported stone should move downwards rather than > upwards. It applies to no part of inorganic nature, and is very limited > even in the phenomena of organic life (*PD* 108). Wright held that three different "classes of causes" are involved in natural selection. The first has to do with the external conditions of the life of a living thing, its relation to other organisms and the non-organic world. Second are physical laws; he mentions specifically principles of mechanics, optics, and acoustics. These are the best known and most basic of all the principles of science. They are the principles by which means come to be fitted to ends, the fulfilling or supplying of the needs of the organism. They are the laws in accordance with which an arm or wing, an eye or ear, can be of use. Third are the causes introduced by Darwin, "the little known phenomena of variation, and their relations to the laws of inheritance" (*PD* 142). He said there are several divisions within this third class, distinguishing in particular diversities always existing in a population from abnormal or unusual variations. In responding to St. George Mivart's criticism of natural selection, he said that diversities existing normally in a population are the source of evolutionary change more than "unusual and monstrous variations" (*PD* 144). Wright made this point both to highlight the level at which natural selection operates and to drive home the role of natural selection as an alternative to teleological explanations of the usefulness of adaptations. Variations in inherited characteristics in individuals are not themselves the direct causes of changes in species. Natural selection is a complex general fact of which utility is the organizing principle. Wright's study of Mill's utilitarianism undoubtedly influenced his understanding of Darwin. Although he rejected Spencer's application of the principle of evolution to history and civilization, he thought many aspects of human behavior and psychology could be treated by the principle of natural selection. Utilitarian ethics provided a model for him. He used the way humans make moral choices as an analogy for unconscious selection in the change of human language over time. Utility is not the motive of moral decision-makers. In the moral agent thinking rightly according to his principle of virtue, conscience will display the utilitarian principle. Similarly, there may be a variety of motives for adoption of a change in linguistic form or behavior: authority, ease of pronunciation, or distinctness from other utterances. The adoption of the change is what concerns natural selection. Natural selection shows the utility implicit unconsciously in selection by the agency of one of these motives (*L* 244). In commenting on moral behavior itself, Wright in effect based ethics on human nature, because of the importance he accorded to habit in human behavior: > The pains of disconcerted or frustrated habits, and the > inherent pleasure there is in following them, are motives which nature > has put into our wills without generally caring to inform us why; and > she sometimes decrees, indeed, that her reasons shall not be ours. So > that, practically, we find ourselves acting the more reasonably and > more for the real ends of nature, in proportion as these are not our > immediate motives, but give place to more completely devoted, > single-purposed, and therefore effective powers, or to instincts and > habits (*L* 242). We see in this passage the separation of immediate causes of action, namely pleasure and pain, from the pattern of action serving nature's real end, namely utility. Wright thought utilitarianism needed, as a supplement, a developed philosophy of habit. In a way similar to his explanation of natural selection, he separated (1) the conditions militating toward habit, (2) immediate motives for choosing action, and (3) the larger principle governing selection of action.[12] Wright labored in his essays and review articles to make Darwin's theory understandable to the educated American public by countering the questions about what kind of explanation natural selection offered. Realizing that utility as a principle provided the logical form for Darwin's theory, he insisted that natural selection could not submit to requirements of demonstration. It could not serve as an axiom from which deduction starts. Indeed, it should be compared to the principle of gravitation not as this concept figured in celestial mechanics or even in the laboratory but as gravitation is manifest "in the concrete courses of outward nature, in meteorology and physical geology." Natural selection could be compared to the fundamental laws of political economy, as these laws actually emerge in the fixing of value and prices through demand and supply (*PD* 137). Here we see both the influence of utilitarianism and Wright's belief in the interdependence of different levels of explanatory principles. His understanding of induction figures also in his defense of Darwin. In a review essay of 1870, he commented on the almost universal acceptance of Darwin's theory by the scientifically minded and attributed its success to "the skillful combination of inductive and deductive proofs with hypothesis." This combination must rely, however, on a preceding simpler induction, he said. The near simultaneous discovery by Wallace and Darwin of the principle behind biological evolution testifies to their ability as naturalists to appreciate "the force of obscure and previously little studied facts" (*PD* 99). In this context, he also insisted upon the importance to science of investigating principles operating at a level in nature comparable to the level of political economy. He said that to fail to investigate a principle operating at the level of the whole organism or at the level of populations would go against the "Aristotelian" tendency of mind of the scientific culture. The scientific mind cannot regard the intricate system of adaptations in nature as arbitrary and is not satisfied "so long as any explanation, not tantamount to arbitrariness itself, has any probability in the order of nature" (*PD* 100). In responding both to friends and enemies of Darwin's evolution, Wright sought to keep clear the minimal meaning of natural selection in scientific terms. In this way, he did great service to Darwin. Like a good positivist, he was protecting the new theory of evolution from annexation into cosmological speculation or alliance with the final causality that was always a part of natural theology.[13] ## 4. Cosmology and Argument Against Natural Theology Wright had interesting and original views about the origin of the universe and changes in the heavens.[14] He saw no evidence in astronomical data or known scientific law for ascribing purpose or direction to the evolution of the cosmos as a whole. He believed it most likely that the universe is eternal, constituting "an order without beginning and without termination" (*PD* 4). It is governed by the principle of "counter-movements," which he believed was manifest already in biological phenomena in the cycle of life and death, nutrition and decay. Gravitation and heat were the chief forces involved in counter-movements. Geology manifests the principle, in the relation of forces producing elevations, compressions, erosion, and deposits, and it is even more markedly evident in meteorological phenomena. Wright believed that changes in interstellar space constituted, in a way similar to meteorology, "cosmical weather" (*PD* 10). He was concerned that the nebular hypothesis of the origin of solar systems, presented as a plausible scientific hypothesis by Laplace and supported by the observations of Herschel, was too readily taken in support of a "developmental hypothesis" about the universe, namely that the universe was created and had evolved toward an end congenial to supporting human life. For Wright, teleological notions in science were always anathema. He accepted the nebular hypothesis in terms of the physical laws that yielded the developmental hypothesis, both in astronomy and biology. But he called it the "derivative hypothesis" to connote the fact that "in several classes of phenomena hitherto regarded as ultimate and inexplicable, physical explanations are probable and legitimate" (*PD* 17). He meant by this that scientific cosmology need entertain no extra-scientific principles as fundamental: "the constitution of the solar system is not archetypal, as the ancients supposed, but the same corrupt mixture of law and apparent accident that the phenomena of the earth's surface exhibit" (*PD* 9). Wright was aware that the second law of thermodynamics militated against his cosmology of cosmic weather continuing in an endless succession of phenomena in infinite time. But he believed the "tendency to diffuse the mechanical energies of nature" that was characteristic of the laws of heat was considered too narrowly by Thomson and others. There was a "round of actions" in the complex interactions of heat and gravitation through space that set up the counter-movements of continuous change (*L* 177). To the scientific Aristotelian mind that Wright claimed to have, the theory of "wasting" raised more questions than it answered, and so he deferred his own full acceptance of it (*PD* 87). Wright's approach to this issue illustrates his penchant, evident also in his acute and ready understanding of natural selection, to focus on large-scale effects of natural law as making sense of nature. In this, his mind worked against the reductionist tendencies of philosophers who had less experience with and sympathy for science itself. He was interested in the persistent patterns evident to sense perception set up by the operation of natural law at levels inaccessible to perception. A constant theme for Wright is the rejection of natural theology. He did not believe that there could be philosophical arguments, starting from natural phenomena, whether motion or the intelligible forms of living things, that prove the existence of a deity. He also believed it was impossible to identify in nature genuine final causes, ends present naturally that are always prior to the subordinate causes that bring about those ends. He said: > By what criterion ... can we distinguish among the > numberless effects, that are also causes, and among the causes that > may, for aught we can know, be also effects, -- how can we > distinguish which are the means and which are the ends? (*PD* > 36). That the universe has a purpose or that the forms of living things given by nature have an inevitability or natural priority to them can be believed on grounds of faith but can in no way be disclosed or supported by scientific investigation of nature. Perhaps judging from the state of philosophy and theology in the American institutions of higher learning in the mid-nineteenth century, Wright believed that metaphysics had no other purpose than the service of natural theology. He was never precise about what he meant by metaphysics, but he said that the motives for theological and metaphysical speculation come from "the active emotional life of man" (*PD* 49-50). He seemed to equate metaphysics and philosophy. He continued, "The questions of philosophy proper are human desires and fears and aspirations -- human emotions -- taking an intellectual form" (*PD* 50). A spirit of inquiry free of these influences motivates science, but it is "necessarily, at all times, a weak feeling" and could have little effect on civilization until a body of scientific learning had been developed. He said, "And we owe science to the combined energies of individual men of genius, rather than to any tendency to progress inherent in civilization" (*PD* 51). Philosophy belongs with the fine arts and religion. Its attainments are not great but its motives are noble (*PD* 52). This *ad hominen* argument against philosophers -- that their enterprise is not rational and disinterested -- would have found ready reinforcement in Comte's rejection of metaphysics in favor of scientific method. Wright never followed Comte, however, in Comte's recommendation of a religion of humanity to take the place of religion for the masses. Although Wright's own thinking is highly philosophical, the rejection of metaphysics and philosophy together is fundamental for him and lies in the background of all his pronouncements in philosophy of science. ## 5. Consciousness, Evolution, and Philosophy Wright's philosophical position is a type of naturalism, though not a naturalism endorsed by most twentieth century philosophers who have used that term. Given his view of philosophy, he resisted skepticism, idealism, and realism, regarding them all as defects of thought. Nevertheless, compared to twentieth century philosophies of science, his own philosophy of science is decidedly realist. He believed scientists discover structures and features of natural things, and previously unknown hidden entities, as well as phenomenal laws that govern the behavior of natural things. In this respect, his positivism is methodological and precautionary, a preparation for scientific realism. In treating the origin of consciousness, he said that idealism and natural realism are the two philosophical positions to issue from taking sense data and emotions as the primarily real. In idealism, the conscious subject is immediately known through his perceptions, i.e., the phenomena, and the existence of an external world can only be an inference from the phenomena known to belong to the self (*PD* 230). He rejected this but also rejected natural realism, which holds that "both the subject and object are absolutely, immediately, and equally known through their essential attributes in perception." This view, he says, "is more than an unlearned jury are competent to say" (*PD* 231). According to Wright, the immediacy of sensible qualities to consciousness entails that there is no way to separate subject and object in consciousness. But, he continued: > All states of consciousness are, it is true, referred to > one or the other, or partly to each of the two worlds [subject and > object]; and this attribution is, in part at least, instinctive, yet > not independent of all experience, since it comes either from the > direct observation of our progenitors, or, possibly, through the > natural selection of them; that is, possibly through the survival of > those who rightly divided the worlds, and did not often mistake a real > danger for a dream or for an imagined peril, nor often mistake a dream > of security for reality. If. . . we mean by immediacy such an > instinctive attribution, independent of repeated connections of > attributes in their subject through the individual's own experiences, > then "natural realism" is most in accordance with our view. > (*PD* 231) In this quotation, Wright suggests that the division of subject from object may constitute "rightly dividing the world" as indexed by survival value. A division made in these terms, rather than by an individual's experiences of himself and the world, is a reasonable basis for natural realism. Wright's view in this passage is consistent with the position of Hume that human beings by nature make connections between ideas and the world and that skepticism about these connections is useless and idle. In this regard, Wright's position anticipates that of P.F. Strawson, a twentieth-century logical analyst. Strawson said our beliefs, e.g., in the existence of bodies, "are not grounded beliefs and at the same time are not open to serious doubt" (Strawson 1985, 19). Wright here articulates a similar point couched in terms of natural selection of beliefs. Also like Strawson, Wright took for some purposes ordinary experience as what is primarily real, while for other purposes he took the entities and properties given in physical theory as the real. This pluralistic approach came from Wright's acceptance of different levels of experience as equally valid starting points for science. Also evident in this passage, however, is the way Wright made biological evolution the basis for all other accounts of nature and human psychology. In this respect, his approach is a forerunner of John Dewey's philosophy of nature.
wilhelm-wundt
## 1. Biographical Timeline 1832 born at Neckarau/Mannheim, August 16 1845 enters Bruchsal Gymnasium 1851-2 study of medicine at Tubingen 1852-5 study of medicine at Heidelberg 1853 first publication "on the sodium chloride content of urine" 1855 medical assistant at a Heidelberg clinic 1856 semester of study with J. Muller and DuBois-Reymond at Berlin; doctorate in medicine at Heidelberg; habilitation as *Dozent* in physiology; nearly fatal illness 1857-64 *Privatdozent* at the Physiological Institute, Heidelberg 1858 *Beitrage zur Theorie der Sinneswahrnehmung*; Helmholtz becomes director of the Heidelberg Physiological Institute 1862 first lectures in psychology 1863 *Vorlesungen uber die Menschen- und Tier-Seele* 1864 made *ausserordentlicher Professor*; lectures on physiological psychology (published as Wundt 1873-4) 1870-71 fails to be named Helmholtz's successor at Heidelberg; army doctor in Franco-Prussian War 1873-4 publishes *Grundzuge der physiologischen Psychologie*[5] 1874 called to Zurich to the professorship in "inductive philosophy"; 1875 called to Leipzig as professor 1879 founds the *Institut fur Experimentelle Psychologie*, Leipzig; birth of son, Max 1881 *Philosophische Studien* founded 1880-83 *Logik*, 2 vols. 1886 *Ethik*, 3 vols. 1889 *System der Philosophie*, 2 vols. 1889-90 Rector of Leipzig University 1904 *Volkerpsychologie*, 2 vols. 1915 emeritus 1917 retires from teaching; replaced by his student, Felix Krueger (Sluga 1993: 95) 1920 dies at Grossbothen, near Leipzig, at the age of 88, August 31 ## 2. Life & Times Wilhelm Maximilian Wundt was born on August 16, 1832, in the German town of Neckarau, outside of Mannheim, the son of a Lutheran minister (Titchener 1921b: 161). The family moved when Wilhelm was six to the town of Heidenheim, in central Baden (Boring 1950: 316). By all accounts, he was a precocious, peculiar boy, schooled mainly by his father's assistant, the vicar, Friedrich Muller; young Wilhelm was so attached to Muller that he moved in with him when the latter got a post in a neighboring village (Boring 1950: 316). Wundt studied at the *Gymnasien* at Bruchsal and Heidelberg and entered the University of Tubingen at 19, in 1851 (Boring 1950: 317). After one year he transferred to the University of Heidelberg, where he majored in medicine. By his third year, his intense work ethic yielded his first publication (Boring 1950: 318). Nevertheless, doctoring was not Wundt's vocation and he turned instead to physiology, which he studied for a semester under Johannes Muller (the "father of experimental physiology") at Berlin (Boring 1950: 318). In 1856, at the age of 24, Wundt took his doctorate in medicine at Heidelberg, and habilitated as a *Dozent* in physiology. Two years later, the physicist, physiologist, and psychologist, Hermann von Helmholtz,[6] received the call to Heidelberg as a professor of physiology, a decisive moment for Wundt's career, with Wundt working as Helmholtz's assistant from 1858 until 1865 (Boring 1950: 300, 319; Araujo 2014: 55). When Helmholtz moved to Berlin in 1871, Wundt was passed over as Helmholtz's replacement; three years later he took the chair in "inductive philosophy" at the University of Zurich. He remained at Zurich for only one year before receiving an appointment to "a first-class chair of philosophy at Leipzig in 1875" (Ben-David and Collins 1966: 462). Leipzig's philosophy department, dominated by Herbartians, provided the ideal environment for his intellectual flowering, the soil having been prepared by Fechner, Weber, and Lotze (Littman 1979: 74; cf. Kim 2009). Wundt became famous at Leipzig. It was here, in 1879, that the university formally recognized his little room of equipment as a *bona fide* laboratory, the world's first devoted to psychology.[7] Students flocked to Wundt,[8] and while he set the tone and direction of research, it was largely they who constructed apparatus, performed experiments, and published results. > > > Enrollment in his courses doubled about every 15 years, reaching a > peak of 620 students in the summer of 1912. Wundt ended up sponsoring > 186 Ph.D. dissertations, about a third of which apparently involved > purely philosophical topics (Tinker, 1932). (Quote--including > reference to Tinker-from Hearst 1979b: 22) > > > Though Wundt participated actively in labor politics in his early years at Heidelberg, even being elected to the Baden parliament, he steadily drifted rightwards, eventually being persuaded by his "virulently anti-Semitic"[9] son, Max, a historian of philosophy, to join the ultranationalist *Deutsche Philosophische Gesellschaft*, after 1917.[10] It is hard to ignore Wundt's unattractive "application" of his late social and cultural psychology to the tendentious critique of Germany's enemies (Kusch 1995: 220-1). Nevertheless, his drive and unflagging intellectual advocacy will arouse admiration in some: even at age 80, he remained involved in academic controversy.[11] But let us consider the man through his work. To understand Wundt's philosophical importance one must know something of his intellectual context. Early nineteenth-century German psychology labored under the looming shadow of Kant and his arguments that a science of psychology is in principle impossible. This fact by itself illustrates the oddity of the situation, from our point of view: why would a psychologist care what a philosopher thought about his practice? The answer is that since ancient times, psychology had been a basic part of philosophical speculation, though after Kant's criticisms many considered it a dying branch, dangerously close to breaking off. Psychologists were philosophers on the defensive (cf. *L* III: 163). Psychology, as a part of philosophy, had already several times changed the way it defined its object: as "soul", "mental substance", "mind", etc. By the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, many regarded psychology to be the account of consciousness or "inner experience", distinct from the natural scientific accounts of external, sensible reality. After having dealt the *coup de grace* to the speculative, rational, *a priori* psychology of the soul epitomized by Christian Wolff, however, Kant tried to cut off any retreat into the empirical study of consciousness, as well. In the *Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science*, he argued that empirical psychology cannot be an exact science because the phenomena it seeks to explain are not mathematically expressible (Kitcher 1990: 11). Moreover, it can never become an experimental science "because it is not possible to isolate different thoughts" (Kitcher 1990: 11). Finally, and most fatally, the only access to the phenomena of inner experience, introspection, *ipso facto* alters those phenomena: if I try, by introspection, to study what it's like to be tristful, the phenomena of my sadness are now something different, namely, phenomena of my sadness-being-studied-by-me (Kitcher 1990: 11). Thus psychologists found their object declared beyond the limit of possible investigation and their methods vain. While such arguments did not persuade all of Kant's successors of the hopelessness of their enterprise, their attempts were unpromising. On the one hand, the German Idealists' fanciful speculation about *Geist* collapsed upon itself. On the other hand, the efforts of J.F. Herbart to devise a mathematical mental mechanics suggested a possible way forward although in the end it proved equally fruitless. Thus, for those mid-nineteenth-century enthusiasts of mental phenomena, the future of a genuine psychology seemed blocked. At the same time, however, progress was being made in human physiology, especially of the sensory systems. In 1834, the physiologist, E.H. Weber, published a startling discovery in his *De tactu*. His experiments on the sensation of weight had led him to find that there obtains a constant ratio between, on the one hand, a given stimulus and, on the other hand, a second stimulus sufficiently larger for the difference between the two stimuli to be just noticeable, no matter the magnitude of the first stimulus.[12] In other words, if the first stimulus is of intensity \(I\), then \(\Delta I\) is the amount by which it must be increased for the difference to be just noticeable; the ratio of \(I\) and \(\Delta I\) is constant (\(k\)): \(\Delta I / I = k\) (cf. *L* III: 186). This equation, which later came to be known as Weber's Law,[13] was crucial to the development of psychology because it apparently demonstrated that where Herbart had failed in his aprioristic construction of mathematical regularities of mind, experimentation could succeed. The situation nevertheless remained murky as interpretations of Weber's Law multiplied. Fechner, for example, elaborated Weber's experiments but took his results as the basis for an arcane panpsychic monism (Wundt's own "psychological" interpretation is treated in Section 4) (cf., e.g., Boring 1950: 286). In founding the experimental science of psychology, Wundt in effect "triangulated" a *media via* between the available options: he rejected Fechner's mysticism while maintaining his experimental approach; at the same time, Wundt went beyond the purely physical interpretation of physiological experiments a la Helmholtz, arguing that at least in humans experimentation could reveal law-like regularities of *inner* (psychological) reality. Thus, to use the phrase of Ben-David and Collins, he established the "hybrid science" whose dual provenance is expressed in Wundt's name for it, "physiological psychology" (Ben-David and Collins 1966: 459; Kusch 1995: 122, ff.).[14] Wundt's interest, both to scholars of the history of philosophy and to contemporary philosophers of mind, flows ultimately from the definition, methodology, and "metaphysics" of this physiological psychology. Sections 3 and 4 are devoted to a description of its definition, method, and doctrine, while Section 5 is concerned with its theoretical underpinnings. The practical and theoretical limits of experimental psychology will be treated in Section 6, on *Volkerpsychologie*. ## 3. Experimental psychology: object and method ### 3.1 Object "The exact description of consciousness [*Bewusstsein*] is the sole aim of experimental psychology" (cited by Titchener 1921b: 164). Wundt identifies "physiological" with "experimental" psychology.[15] Thus, for Wundt, experimental psychology is the unmediated study of consciousness, *aided* by the experimental protocols of the natural sciences. Yet this definition involves two contestable assumptions: first, that "consciousness" is susceptible to experiment (rejected by Kant); second, that psychology, even if conceived as experimental, has for its object consciousness or "the mental" (later rejected by the Behaviorists) (cf. Hearst 1979b: 10). Let us focus on the first assumption, since it is one Wundt addresses. Wundt defines consciousness as "inner experience;" it is only the "immediately real"[16] phenomena constituting this experience, and nothing behind or beyond it, that is the object of *psychological*, as opposed to physiological or psychophysical investigation (*PP* II: 636). Wundt's project is not only a "psychology without a soul", in F.A. Lange's phrase, but also a science without a substrate *tout court*.[17] Wundt therefore presents himself as a radical empiricist. The subject of psychology "is itself determined wholly and exclusively by its predicates", and these predicates derive solely from direct, internal observation (on which below). The basic domain of inquiry, accordingly, is that of "individual psychology" (cf. e.g. *L* III: 160, ff), i.e. of the concrete mental contents appearing to particular human beings, and not some mental substance or bundle of faculties.[18] In Wundt's declaration that individual psychology must become a science via the experimental manipulation of inner phenomena, we see a pragmatic attitude perhaps peculiar to the working scientist: the future science as *doctrine* takes shape in and through the present *practice* of experimentation, its essays, assays, trials, and errors. Instead of simply submitting to Kant's injunctions against the very possibility of a scientific psychology, Wundt finds that certain aspects of our inner experience can be, and in fact have been, made susceptible to experiment and mathematical representation: Weber and Fechner did this. ### 3.2 Method Nevertheless, Wundt repeatedly addresses the objections raised against the very possibility of psychological, as opposed to physiological or psychophysical, experimentation. How are we to subject the mind-body complex to physiological stimulation such that the reactions may be given a purely psychological interpretation? From the physiological point of view, experimentation with stimulus and response are not experiments of sensation, but of externally observable excitations and reactions of nerve and muscle tissue. For example, a nerve fiber or a skin surface may be given an electric shock or brought into contact with acid, and twitches of muscle fiber are observed to follow. It is obvious, especially when the nerve-tissue in question belongs to a dead frog (Wundt describes such an experiment in *PP*), that these experiments say nothing about the "inner" experience or consciousness of sensation. Wundt's innovation is the attempt to project the experimental rigor of physiology into the domain of inner experience by supplementing these experiments with a *purely* psychological set of procedures. These procedures constitute Wundt's well-known yet misunderstood method of *Selbstbeobachtung*, i.e. "introspection" or, better, "self-observation". Because "inner" distinguishes itself from "external" experience by virtue of its immediacy, all psychology must begin with self-observation, so that physiological experiment is given an ancillary function (Boring 1950: 320-21). Now Wundt is well aware of the common criticism that self-observation seems inescapably to involve the paradoxical identity (described in the previous section) of the observing subject and observed object. Indeed, he takes pains to distinguish his notion of self-observation from that of "most advocates of the so-called empirical psychology", which he calls "a fount of self-delusions [*Selbsttauschungen*]": > > > Since in this case the observing subject coincides with the observed > object, it is obvious that the direction of attention upon these > phenomena alters them. Now since our consciousness has less room for > many simultaneous activities the more intense these activities are, > the alteration in question as a rule consists in this: the phenomena > that one wishes to observe are altogether suppressed [i.e., by the > activity of focused attention upon them]. (*L* III: 162) > > > Wundt believes that one can experimentally correct for this problem by > > > using, as much as possible, unexpected processes, processes not > intentionally adduced, but rather such as involuntarily present > themselves [*sich darbieten*]. (*L* III: > 162)[19] > > > In other words, it is in the controlled conditions of a laboratory that one can, by means of experimenter, experimental subject, and various apparatus, arbitrarily and repeatedly call forth precisely predetermined phenomena of consciousness. The *psychologist* is not then interested in the *psychophysical* connections between the somatic or nervous sense-mechanisms and the elicited "inner" phenomena, but solely in describing, "and where possible measuring", the *psychological* regularities that such experiments can reveal, viz., regular causal links within the domain of the psychic alone (*L* III: 165). According to Wundt, psychological experiments thus conceived accomplish in the realm of consciousness precisely what natural-scientific experiments do in nature: they do not leave consciousness to itself, but force it to answer the experimenter's questions, by placing it under regulated conditions. Only in this way is > > > a [psychological] *observation* [as opposed to a mere > perception {*Wahrnehmung*}] at all possible in the scientific > sense, i.e., the attentive, regulated pursuit of the phenomena. > (*L* III: > 165)[20] > > > A detailed account of these experiments themselves, however, lies far beyond the scope of this article.[21] ## 4. Wundt's "individual psychology" ### 4.1 Sensation Wundt, like most early experimental psychologists,[22] concentrated his investigations upon sensation and perception; of all psychic phenomena, sensation is the most obviously connected to the body and the physical world (Hearst 1979b: 33). For Wundt, sensations and our somatic sensory apparatus are especially important for the project of physiological psychology for the simple reason that sensations are the "contact points" between the physical and the psychological (*PP* I: 1). Sensations (*Empfindungen*), as the medium between the physical and psychic, are uniquely susceptible to a double-sided inquiry,[23] viz. from the "external" physical side of stimulus, and the "internal" psychological side of corresponding mental representation (*Vorstellung*).[24] The Wundtian psychologist therefore controls the external, physiological side experimentally, in order to generate diverse internal representations that can only "appear" to the introspective observer. According to Wundt, the representations (*Vorstellungen*) that constitute the contents (*Inhalt*) of consciousness all have their elemental basis in sensations (*Empfindungen*) (*PP* I: 281).[25] Sensations are never given to us as elemental, however; we never apperceive them "purely", but always already "combined" (*verbunden*) in the representation of a synthesized perception (*PP* I: 281). Yet, the manifestly composite nature of our representations forces us to abstract such elementary components (*PP* I: 281) (cf. *PP* II: 256). Pure sensations, according to Wundt, display three differentiae: quality, intensity, and "feeling-tone" (*Gefuhlston*) (*PP* I: 282-3).[26] His treatment of quality and intensity are especially important for getting a clearer notion of his notion of psychological experimentation. It is a "fact of inner experience" that "every sensation possesses a certain intensity with respect to which it may be compared to other sensations, especially those of similar quality" (*PP* I: 332). The outer sensory stimuli may be measured by physical methods, whereas *psychology* is given the corresponding > > > task of determining to what degree our *immediate estimation* > [*Schatzung*] [of the strength of sensory stimuli] that we > make aided by our sensations--to what degree this estimation > corresponds to or deviates from the stimuli's *real* > strength. (*PP* I: 332-3) > > > There are two possible tasks for psychophysical measurement of sense-stimuli: the "determination of limit-values between which stimulus-changes are accompanied by changes in sensation"; and "the investigation of the lawful relations between stimulus-change and change in sensation" (*PP* I: 333). Sensation can thus be measured with respect to changes in intensity *corresponding* to changes in strength of stimuli (*PP* I: 335-6). Weber's Law (WL) is the most striking example of such a relation, and Wundt's interpretation of WL sheds much light on what he means by "physiological psychology". Wundt writes: > > > We can formulate [this law] as follows: A difference between any two > stimuli is estimated [*geschatzt*] to be equal if the > relationship between the stimuli is equal. Or: If in our apprehension > [*Auffassung*] the intensity of the sensation is to increase by > equal amounts, then the relative stimulus-increase must remain > constant. This latter statement may also be expressed as follows: The > strength of a stimulus must increase geometrically if the strength of > the apperceived sensation is to increase arithmetically. (*PP* > I: 359) > > > Now these various formulations[27] of WL admit, as Wundt says, of three different, and indeed incompatible interpretations; that is, there are three different conceptions of what WL is a law *of*. First, the physiological interpretation takes it as a manifestation of the "peculiar laws of excitation of the neural matter;"[28] second, the psychophysical (Fechnerian) interpretation takes WL as governing the interrelation between somatic and psychic activity (*PP* I: 392). Wundt rejects both of these in favor of a third, the psychological interpretation; his arguments are instructive. Against the physiological interpretation Wundt raises the following main point, viz. that > > > the estimation of the intensity of sensation > (*Empfindungsintensitat*) is a complicated process, upon > which--in addition to the central sensory excitation--the > effectiveness of the center of apperception will exert considerable > influence. We can obviously say nothing *immediate* about how > the central sense-excitations would be sensed independently of the > latter; thus Weber's Law, too, concerns only > *apperceived* sensations, and therefore can just as well have > its basis in the processes of the apperceptive comparison of sensation > as in the original constitution of the central sensory excitations. > (*PP* I: 391-2) > > > Now apperception (see below) is a purely psychological act in consciousness--and it is solely as a law of the psychological processes involved in the "measuring comparison of sensations" that Wundt understands WL (*PP* I: 393). In other words, WL > > > does not apply to sensations in and for themselves, but to processes > of apperception, without which a quantitative estimation of sensations > could never take place. (*PP* I: 393; cf. *PP* II: > 269) > > > Wundt sees WL as simply a mathematical description of the more general experience that > > > we possess in our consciousness no absolute, but merely a relative > measure of the intensity of the conditions [*Zustande*] > obtaining in it, and that we therefore measure in each case one > condition against another, with which we are obliged in the first > place to compare it. (*PP* I: 393) > > > For this reason Wundt's "psychological interpretation" makes WL into a special case of a more general law of consciousness, viz. "of the *relation* or *relativity of our inner conditions* [*Zustande*]" (*PP* I: 393). WL is therefore not a law of sensation so much as of apperception. This solution typifies Wundt's general view that the domains of psychic and physical phenomena do not stand in conflict, but rather constitute separate spheres of (causal) explanation. His interpretation of WL nicely illustrates how, on his view, physiological experiments can yield mathematically expressible results, not about the physical, somatic processes involved in sensation, but about the relationships among these sensations *as apperceived*, i.e., as *psychological* elements and objects of consciousness. He writes that "the psychological interpretation offers the advantage of not excluding a simultaneous [i.e. parallel] physiological explanation" (presumably once the neurophysiological facts of the matter have been better elucidated -- cf. *PP* I: 391); by contrast, the two competing interpretations "only permit a one-sided explanation" of WL (*PP* I: 393). ### 4.2 Consciousness Psychology finds consciousness to be constituted of three major act-categories: representation, willing, and feeling; our discussion is limited to the first two. Now while Wundt is forced to speak of representations and representational acts as distinct, he is nevertheless clear that they are merely different aspects of a single flowing process. This is his so-called theory of actuality (*Aktualitatstheorie*) (1911a: 145). Representations are representational *acts*, never the "objects with constant properties" propounded by adherents of a so-called theory of substantiality (*Substantialitatstheorie*) (1911a: 145). This identity of representation and representational act typifies what we may call Wundt's "monistic perspectivism".[29] Everywhere he insists that the "psychic processes form a *unitary* flow of events [*einheitliches Geschehen*[30] ]", the constituents of which--"representing, feeling, willing, etc."--are "only differentiated through psychological analysis and abstraction" (1911a: 145). Keeping in mind the underlying active unity of the psychic, let us examine some of Wundt's "analyses and abstractions". As discussed in the previous section, all consciousness originates in sensations. These, however, are never given to consciousness in a "pure" state as individual sensory atoms, but are always perceived as already compounded[31] into representations (*Vorstellungen*), that is, into "images of an object or of a process in the external world" (*PP* II: 3; 1). Representations may be either perceptions (*Wahrnehmungen*) or intuitions (*Anschauungen*): the same representation is called a "perception" if considered as the presentation of objective reality, and an "intuition" if considered in terms of the accompanying conscious, subjective activity (*PP* II: 1). If the representation's object is not real (cf. *PP* II: 479) but merely thought, then it is a so-called reproduced representation.[32] Now the formative *process*, by which sensations are connected into representations either through temporal sequencing or spatial ordering (*PP* II: 3), constitutes a main aspect of the activity we call consciousness; the other is the "coming and going of [these] representations" (*PP* II: 256). On the evidence of "innumerable psychological facts",[33] Wundt claims that all representations are formed through "psychological synthesis of sensations", and that this synthesis accompanies every representational act (*PP* II: 256). We are therefore entitled to take the act of representational synthesis as a "characteristic feature of consciousness itself" (*PP* II: 256). Although consciousness consists in the formation of representations, on the one hand, and of the coming and going of such representations, on the other hand--i.e., although its contents are a continuous streaming of fusing and diffusing representations--yet it is not merely this (*PP* II: 256). We are also aware within our consciousness of another activity operating upon our representations, namely of paying them attention (*PP* II: 266). Attention may be understood in terms of the differing degrees to which representations are present (*gegenwartig*) in consciousness. These varying degrees of presence correspond to the varying degrees to which consciousness is "turned towards [*zugewandt*]" them (*PP* II: 267). Wundt appeals to an analogy: > > > This feature of consciousness can be clarified by that common image we > use in calling consciousness an inner vision. If we say that the > representations present [*gegenwartig*] at a particular > moment are in consciousness's field of vision > [*Blickfeld*], then that part of the field upon which our > attention is turned may be called the inner focal point of vision > [*Blickpunkt*]. The entry of a representation into the field of > inner vision we call "perception", and its entry into the > focal point of vision we call "apperception". (*PP* > II: 267) > > > Thus consciousness is a function of the scope of attention, which may be broader (as perception) or narrower (as apperception[34] ). Apperception, in turn, may either actively select and focus upon a perceived representation, or it may passively find certain representations suddenly thrusting themselves into the center of attention (*PP* II: 267; 562). There is no distinct boundary between the perceived and the apperceived, and Wundt's analogy may be misleading (cf. esp. *PP* II: 268) to the extent that it gives the impression of two separable forms of attention able in principle to subsist together simultaneously (that is, apperception focusing upon a point in the perceptual field while that field continues to be perceived). No: perceptive attention becomes apperceptive attention just as it focuses more strenuously, constricting the perceptive field. The more it contracts, the "brighter" the representation appears, now becoming the focal point of apperception as the fringes of the perceptual field retreat into "darkness" (*PP* II: 268). For Wundt, the distinguishing feature of the apperceptive focus is that it "always forms a unitary representation", so that a narrower focal point (or rather, the focal "field" [*PP* II: 268; 477]) results in a correspondingly higher intensity of attention (*PP* II: 269). Hence > > > the degree of apperception is not to be measured according to the > strength of the external impression [i.e. physically or > physiologically], but solely according to the subjective activity > through which consciousness turns to a particular sense-stimulus. > (*PP* II: 269) > > > Thus, apperception[35] is closely akin to the will, indeed is a primordial expression of will: "the act of apperception in every case consists in an inner act of will [*Willenshandlung*]" (*L* I: 34). By contrast, Wundt argues that the processes by which the representations are themselves formed, fused, synthesized, and "delivered" into the perceptual field, are associative processes "independent of apperception" (*PP* II: 278-9; 437, ff). Passive apperception may be characterized simply by saying that here the associative form of representational connection is predominant (cf. *L* I: 34), whereas when "the active apperception successively raises representations into the focal field of consciousness", this *active* passage of representations obeys the special laws of what Wundt calls "apperceptive connection" (*PP* II: 279). He does not consider the types of association to be genuine psychological laws, i.e. laws governing the "succession of representations", because they merely generate the *possible* kinds of representational compounds. It is apperception, in accordance with its own laws, that "decides" which of these possible connections are realized in consciousness (*L* I: 34). We see here the important role played by his so-called voluntarism:[36] associationist psychologists, according to Wundt, cannot give an account of the (subjective) *activity* that immediately characterizes consciousness (cf. Wundt 1911b: 721, ff.; Lipps 1903: 202, ff.; cf. esp. *L* I: 33). Yet this is not to deny association of sensations altogether. Rather, it is to conceive of association as merely a subliminal process, the products of which, representations, then become the actual objects of consciousness. Thus the "apperceptive connections of representations presuppose the various types of association", especially the associative fusion[37] of sensations into representations.[38] Apperception operates according to its own peculiar laws (*PP* II: 470). These laws, like those of association, govern acts of combination (*Verbindung*) and separation (*Zerlegung*). How do apperceptive laws differ from those of association? Wundt writes: > > > Association everywhere gives the first impetus to [apperceptive] > combinations. Through association we combine, e.g., the > representations of a tower and of a > church.[39] > But no matter how familiar the coexistence of these representations > may be, mere association does not help us form the representation of a > church-tower. For this latter representation does not contain the two > constitutive representations in a merely external coexistence; rather, > in the [representation of the church-tower], the representation of the > church has come to adhere [*anhaften*] to the representation of > the tower, more closely determining the latter. In this way, the > *agglutination of representations* forms the first level of > apperceptive combination. (*PP* II: 476; on > "agglutination of representations", see also *L* I: > 38, f.) > > > It is on the basis of such "agglutinative" representations, exhibiting characteristics essentially different from their constituents, that apperception continues to synthesize ever more representations, a process resulting in their compression (*Verdichtung*) or displacement (*Verschiebung*) (*PP* II: 476-7; cf. *L* I: 43). The more the original associative or agglutinated representations are compressed or displaced, the more they disappear altogether from consciousness, leaving in their stead a *single* representation whose original composite structure has disappeared. This process, which Wundt calls "representational synthesis" proper, is reiterated at ever higher levels until even the sensory foundation vanishes, as in the case of abstract and symbolic concepts (*L* I: 39). Apperception is not only a synthetic process; it is also governed by rules of separation. Apperceptive separation operates only upon the representations already synthesized out of the "associative stock [*Assoziationsvorrath*]", but does not necessarily decompose them into their original parts (*PP* II: 478). Wundt's notion of apperceptive separation is one of the most philosophically original, consequential, and ambiguous of his theories. He argues that it is usually the case that > > > the original representational totality [*ursprungliche > Gesammtvorstellung*] is present to our consciousness at first as > an indistinct complex of individual representations. These individual > parts and the manner of their connection become distinct only through > the separative activity of apperception. (*PP* II: 478) > > > Thus, conscious thought and judgment (on judgment, see *SP* I: 34, ff., esp. 37, ff.) (separating and combining subject and predicate) is not, as may seem at first blush, an act of > > > gathering together [representational] components and then fitting them > together in the successive articulation of the total representation > [*Gesammtvorstellung*]. (*PP* II: 478) > > > Rather, "the whole, albeit in an indistinct form, must have been apperceived prior to its parts" (*PP* II: 478). Only in this way can one explain the > > > well-known fact that we can easily and without trouble finish > [composing] a complicated sentence-structure. This would be impossible > if the whole had not been represented at the outset. The > accomplishment of the judgment-function therefore consists, from the > psychological point of view, only in our successively making clearer > the obscure outlines of the total picture [*Gesammtbild*], so > that at the end of the composite thought-act the whole, too, stands > more clearly before our consciousness. (*PP* II: 478) > > > Because according to Wundt's principle of "actuality [*Aktualitat*]" consciousness is purely an activity, it is impossible to render his theory in terms of "structures". It consists in constantly interacting *processes*: on the one hand, there are associative processes that fuse sensations into elemental representations. These stream into and thereby constitute a *fluctuating* field of attention: flowing and broad, it is called "perception;" ebbing and concentrate, "apperception". As an activity, attention is an expression of will; since consciousness just is attention in its shifting forms, it is the activity of will manifested in the selection, combination, and separation of disposable representations (*PP* II: 564). These representations are constantly "worked over" by apperception, which through its synthetic and diaeretic activity constructs them into ever "higher developmental forms of consciousness", such that in the end their origins in sensation and perception might be completely erased. In other words, as the apperceptive activity becomes increasingly intense it seems as it were to rise above the field of perception, above the field of its own constructs, becoming aware of itself as *pure* activity, as pure *self*-consciousness: > > > rooted in the constant activity [*Wirksamkeit*] of > apperception, [self-consciousness] ... retreats completely into > apperception alone, so that, after the completion of the development > of consciousness, the *will* appears as the only content of > self-consciousness.... (*PP* II: > 564)[40] > > > Thus the self as will appears to itself as independent from and opposed to an external world of both sensation and culture, though Wundt hastens to add that this is but an illusion; in reality, "the abstract self-consciousness maintains constantly the full sensible background of the empirical self-consciousness" (*PP* II: 564).[41] ## 5. The theoretical framework of experimental psychology As we have seen (Section 3.2), for Wundt the possibility of a physiological *psychology* (as opposed to a purely physiological inquiry into sensation, behavior, learning, etc.) depends on the possibility of self-observation. Self-observation, in turn, is of scientific use only if the sequence of "inner" phenomena of consciousness is assumed to fall under an independent principle of psychic causality. For if it does not, then these phenomena could never be more than a chaotic muddle, of which there could be no science. Alternatively, if the "inner" phenomena could be shown to fall under the physical causality of the natural sciences, then there would be no need for a special psychological method, such as self-observation (cf. Natorp 1912). In fact, however, a system of psychic causality can be determined, Wundt argues, one that at no point is reducible to physical causality: "no connection of physical processes can ever teach us anything about the manner of connection between psychological elements" (Wundt 1894: 43, quoted in Kusch 1995: 134). This "fact", which Wundt thinks is given in the psycho-physiological experiments described above, leads him to his so-called principle of psychophysical parallelism (PPP). The PPP has caused a great deal of confusion in the secondary literature, which persists in characterizing it as a metaphysical[42] doctrine somehow derived from Leibniz (e.g., Wellek 1967: 350; Thompson and Robinson 1979: 412) or Spinoza (cf. *L* I: 77). Wundt however is crystal-clear that the PPP is not a metaphysical "hypothesis". It is merely an admittedly misleading name for an "empirical postulate" necessary to explain the phenomenal "fact" of consciousness of which we are immediately aware (Wundt 1911a: 22; cf. esp. 28). By denying any metaphysical interpretation of his principle, Wundt insists that the "physical" and the "psychic" do not name two ontologically distinct realms whose events unfold on separate yet parallel causal tracks. He is therefore not an epiphenomenalist, as some commentators have claimed. Rather, the "physical" and "psychic" name two mutually irreducible perspectives from which one and the same world or Being (*Sein*) may be observed: "nothing occurs in our consciousness that does not find its sensible foundation in certain physical processes", he writes, and *all* psychological acts (association, apperception, willing) "are accompanied by physiological nerve-actions" (*PP* II: 644). In distinguishing the empirical from the metaphysical PPP, Wundt contrasts his own view against Spinoza's, which, according to Wundt, makes the realm of material substance exist separately from, though parallel to that of mental substance (Wundt 1911a: 22, 44-5; cf. esp. Wundt 1911a: 143, ff.). The investigator of psychological phenomena, therefore, must assume, solely for heuristic reasons, two "parallel" and irreducible causal chains by which two distinct types of phenomena may be accounted for (Wundt 1911a: 143; cf. Van Rappard 1979: 109). Wundt compares the distinction between psychological and physiological explanation to the different viewpoints taken by chemistry and physics of the same object, a crystal. The chemical and physical accounts are not of two different entities; rather, they describe and explain the same entity from two distinct points of view, and in this sense the two accounts are "parallel". Similarly, (neuro-) physiology and psychology do not describe different processes, one neural and one mental, but the same process seen from the outside and the inside, respectively. As Wundt writes, > > > "inner" and "outer" experience merely > designate distinct *perspectives* that we can apply in our > grasp and scientific investigation of what is, in itself, a unitary > experience. (Wundt 1896a; quoted at Natorp 1912: 264). > > > ## 6. *Volkerpsychologie* Whereas experimental psychology focuses in the first place on the effects of the physical (outer) upon the psychic (inner), the willing consciousness is characterized by intervening in the external world, that is, by *expressing* the *internal* (*PP* I: 2). This latter feature of consciousness lies beyond the scope of experiment, because the origins of conscious expression cannot be controlled. Moreover, psychological development is obviously not determined merely by sensation, but also by the meaningful influences of the individual's "spiritual [*geistig*] environment"--his culture--influences again not obviously susceptible to experimentation.[43] Hence, just as Wundt reserved for physiology an ancillary role in experimental psychology, so too he now argues for the utility of a distinct methodological approach to analyze and explain the > > > psychic processes that are bound, in virtue of their genetic and > developmental conditions, to spiritual communities [*geistige > Gemeinschaften*]. (*L* III: 224) > > > It is the inquiry into "cultural products [*Erzeugnisse*]" of the "totality of spiritual life [*geistiges Gesammtleben*] in which certain psychological laws have embodied themselves", specifically, language, art, myth, and customs (*Sitten*) (*PP* I: 5; *L* III: 230). These objects cannot be investigated in the same way as those of individual "inner" experience, but require a mode of explanation appropriate to their external, yet non-physical phenomenology. This inquiry, which complements and together with experimental psychology completes the discipline of psychology, Wundt calls "*Volkerpsychologie*" (hereafter abbreviated: *VP*) (*L* III: 225).[44] While Wundt had already discussed the role of a *VP* necessary for the completion of psychology in his early writings, it was not until old age that he committed himself to its realization. The result was his ten-volume work, entitled *Volkerpsychologie*. While an examination of the contents of these tomes lies beyond the scope of this article, his justification and clarification of the *volkerpsychologisch* project as such are of interest for those interested in truth and method in the social and human sciences. Wundt stresses that although *VP* shares object-domains with such sciences as history, philology, linguistics,[45] ethnology,[46] or anthropology (*L* III: 226), yet it is only interested in these domains insofar as they "are determined by general psychological laws, and not just by historical conditions" (*PP* I: 5). In other words, *VP* is not interested in the unique and specific facts of this nation's history or that tribe's language as such, but only insofar as these reveal "the general psychological developments that arise from the connection of individual [developments]" (*L* III: 226). This quotation is important. While *VP* does not concern itself with historical or linguistic facts as such, this does not mean that it is not concerned with individuality. Indeed, it is through the study of the psychological motives only apparent in history or language--i.e., in communal existence--that our understanding of the *individual* is completed (cf. *L* III: 224, 228). This view is typical of Wundt's perspectivism. Just as psychology is an alternative perspective to that of physiology, so too (*within* psychology) *VP* provides an alternative perspective to that of experimental psychology. Wundt considers none of these various perspectives dispensable, since each one is a complement necessary for total science. But while each of these perspectives reveals a (phenomenologically) irreducible ("parallel") network of causal chains, the *process* so explained, Wundt holds, is in every case one and the same. There is just *one* empirical world and reality, but many irreducible varieties of experience. Thus, in the case of *VP*, too, he claims that there is no "general law of spiritual events [*geistiges Geschehen*] that is not already completely contained in the laws of the individual consciousness" (*L* III: 225). ## 7. The order of knowledge ### 7.1 Psychology in its relation to the sciences As we have seen, Wundt was concerned not only with expanding the set of known psychological facts, but also with interpreting them within an appropriate explanatory framework. Of course, the necessity of establishing such a closed framework distinct from physiology amounted to distinguishing psychological causality from physical causality in general, and hence psychology from the natural sciences altogether. But psychology has to be defined against two other areas of "scientific" (*wissenschaftlich*) inquiry; first, in its *volkerpsychologisch* dimension, against the *Geisteswissenschaften* or "human sciences", and second, against the non-psychological domains of philosophy. As these relationships are laid out below, it must always be remembered that although these four areas--psychology, philosophy, natural science, human science--are irreducible, this irreducibility is not a metaphysical or ontological one, but merely one of explanatory function (and commensurate methodology). They do not have distinct objects, but again merely represent ways of describing irreducible perspectives upon the same object, namely experience. Wundt writes: > > > Objects of science do not in and of themselves yield starting points > for a classification of the sciences. Rather, it is only regarding the > *concepts* that these objects call for that we can undertake > this classification. Therefore, the same object [*Gegenstand*] > can become the object [*Objekt*] of several sciences: geometry, > epistemology, and psychology each deals with space, but space is > approached in each discipline from a different angle. ... The > tasks of the sciences are therefore never determined by the objects in > themselves, but are predominantly dependent upon the logical points of > view from which they are considered. (*SP* I: 12-3; cf. > *L* III: 228) > > > Wundt's monism has serious consequences for the sort of claim philosophy (and thus psychology) can make to be scientific. The most obvious is that neither can lay claim to synthetic knowledge that is not founded in or (also) describable in terms of the natural or human sciences. For Wundt, it is only the sciences that have methodologies by which to synthesize our representations, sensible as well as "processed", into "facts" or "pieces of" knowledge (*Erkenntnisse*). Hence, while strictly speaking he is committed to considering psychology (i.e., physiological psychology and *VP*) a part of philosophy, he usually speaks of them as distinct enterprises. This is because psychology is hybrid, adapting scientific methodologies to its particular aims; in this sense psychology, although part of philosophy, synthesizes facts, just like the sciences.[47] By contrast, philosophy's *pure* task is universal, operating over *all* scientific domains; it is, he writes, "the general science whose task it is to unify the general pieces of knowledge yielded by the particular sciences into a system free of contradiction" (*SP* I: 9). Philosophy's positive role, therefore, is not to provide the foundations of science, nor can it ever "step into the role of a particular science" (cf. Kusch 1995: 129); rather it is "to take in every case the already secured results of those sciences as *its* foundation", and organize them into a single, overarching system by determining their points of connection (*PP* I: 8; 6). Wundt calls this side of philosophy *Prinzipienlehre* or "doctrine of principles". By contrast, its negative or critical role is to regulate the sciences in accord with the imperative of consistent systematicity. In short, it has no constitutive but merely a regulative role *vis-a-vis* the sciences. Thus, when we return to the philosophical as opposed to the scientific aspect of psychology's hybrid structure, we see that this aspect consists in its aim (as opposed to its method) of explaining rules of genesis, connection, and separation of those mental representations with an epistemic character. Wundt calls this psychological contribution to philosophy *Erkenntnislehre* or "doctrine of knowledge" (i.e., the theory of the coming-to-be of knowledge). This explanation then provides to philosophy the scientific foundation for its pure task.[48] Wundt divides up the sciences into two large families, the "formal" sciences and the "real" sciences. The former include mathematics; the latter study the natural and spiritual aspects of reality,[49] and correspondingly are divided into the natural and the human sciences. The human sciences in turn are divided into two genera, one of which deals with spiritual processes (*geistige Vorgange*), the other with spiritual products (*geistige Erzeugnisse*). The former just is the science of psychology; the latter includes the general study of these products as such (e.g., philology, political science, law, religion, etc.), as well as the parallel historical study of these products as they have *in fact* been created (This taxonomy is given in *SP* I: 19-20). Since the process precedes the product (cf. Kusch 1995: 132), psychology as "the doctrine of spiritual [*geistig*] processes as such" is the foundation of all the other human sciences (*SP* I: 20).[50] Philosophy, in turn, takes *psychology*'s results and again abstracts from them the normative rules governing the organization of the human *and* natural sciences, something the latter cannot do themselves. In this way psychology as a science mediates between the sciences and philosophy. ### 7.2 Psychology and logic One aspect of Wundt's hierarchy of method and knowledge deserves special attention, namely the place of logic in the sciences. Like almost all the similarly titled tomes produced by the German mandarins, Wundt's *Logik* (in two, later three 600-page volumes in four editions) molders away in research libraries. Its contents are for the most part unrecognizable as "logic" in any contemporary sense. What most philosophers meant by "*Logik*" in Wundt's day was the rules and procedure of inference governing the sciences, where this often included lengthy treatments of the actual scientific application of these rules. What we would expect to find in a book called "*Logik*" today, viz., symbolic or mathematical logic, was called at that time "*Logistik*", and was considered by some a mathematical (that is, merely formal) game unworthy of philosophy's *scientific* (that is, substantive) role (cf., e.g., Natorp 1910: 4-10). Thus we should not be surprised to read Wundt, too, declare logic's task to be the justifying and accounting for "those laws of thinking active in scientific knowledge" (*L* I: 1). For Wundt, however, this task involves psychology, and indeed much of his *Logik* is devoted to this topic. As he reasonably points out, logic comprises the rules of correct thinking, and the principles of logic are known to us as conscious representations (*L* I: 76; 13; cf. Wundt 1920: 267); thinking and consciousness are objects of psychological inquiry; therefore any account of logic must include a psychological description of the genesis of logical principles (*L* I: 13). Even the normative character of logic had, in his view, to be given a psychological interpretation (cf. *L* I: 76). Inevitably Wundt was accused of logical *psychologism*--the all-purpose term of abuse flung about in fin-de-siecle German philosophical debate. Husserl, for example, condemned him for expounding an "extreme" form of psychologism (Husserl 1901: 124-5; cf. Farber 1943: 123, 208, ff.; cf. Wundt 1910b: 511, ff.), viz. "species-relativism", the notion that "truth varies with different species" of animal (Kusch 1995: 49). Yet Wundt himself calls his *Logik* the "most rigorous rejection of the psychologism that reigned at the time [i.e., 1880]" (Wundt 1920: 264), and held that "logical thinking is universally binding for every thinker" (Wundt 1920: 266). How can we reconcile these statements? Wundt's view of logic is unusual, but fully in line with his rigorously anti-metaphysical monistic perspectivism. That is, there is no logical "third realm", but merely a single process called "thinking [*Denken*]" (*L* I: 6); it is an immediately given fact of thinking that there are logical laws that stand over against all our other thoughts and representations as norms (*L* I: 76). Their psychological immediacy does not, Wundt thinks, compromise their normativity, since what is given in consciousness precisely *is* their normative character.[51] Once this character is taken for granted, the science of logic develops its systems of correct deductions (*Schliessen*) without further worry about the source of that normativity. All that remains is "develop[ing] the foundations and methods of scientific knowledge" (*L* I: 8). According to Wundt, the three features of logical thinking that set it apart from all other types of representational connection are its "spontaneity, evidence, and universal validity [*Spontaneitat, Evidenz, Allgemeingultigkeit*]" (*L* I: 76). Let us briefly describe these. Wundt's notion of the spontaneity of logical thinking is perhaps the most psychologistic-sounding of the three. Because, as was described above, thinking is > > > experienced immediately as an inner activity, ... we must regard > it as an act of will [*Willenshandlung*], and accordingly > regard the logical laws of thought [*Denkgesetze*] as laws of > the will. (*L* I: 76-7) > > > In other words, logical thinking is accompanied essentially by a feeling of the thinking subject's freedom in thinking. But while logical thinking may be accompanied by an especially strong self-awareness of the mind's own activity, this feeling is not unique to logical thinking, since active apperception more generally is also accompanied by the sense of subjective activity. By contrast, logical evidence and universal validity are characteristics possessed by logical thinking "to a higher degree than by any other psychic function" (*L* I: 78). By "evidence", Wundt means the character of compelling necessity accompanying a logical judgment, what we might call self-evidence (*L* I: 78, 79). A thought (*Gedanke*) may exhibit immediate certainty, obvious without any mediating thought-acts; or a thought may be mediately certain, grounded in prior thought-acts. Immediate and mediate evidence have their source and foundation in intuition (*Anschauung*): immediate evidence immediately, mediate evidence mediately (*L* I: 82-3). Intuition is not identical with evidence, for evidence only > > > comes to be at the moment when logical thinking relates the contents > of intuition and presupposes the relations of such intuitive contents > as objectively given. (*L* I: 83) > > > Wundt thus charts a middle course between, on the one hand, making logical evidence a "transcendent or transcendental" function of thinking (as Kant and "recent speculative philosophy" are alleged to do), and, on the other hand, considering it an "empirical trait of sensible objects" (as do empiricists and positivists) (*L* I: 83). By the standards of such philosophers as Husserl, Natorp, and Frege, Wundt appears committed to a logical psychologism. But it is worth considering his response to this charge, for it again illustrates his monistic perspectivism. While he rejects any interpretation of the origin of logical principles that would impugn their normative character of necessity, he also rejects the opposite extreme, what he calls "*Logizismus*"--the complete divorce of logical thinking from thinking as it actually occurs in minds. For Wundt, the logicist makes a metaphysical leap as suspect as it is unnecessary in conjuring up a "pure", "absolute", "transcendental", but in any case *separate* source of logical normativity (cf. Wundt 1910b: 515). Instead of solving the puzzle of logical normativity, he exacerbates it by adding the puzzles of the ontological status of a third realm, or of a transcendental ego, or of "pure thinking", and the *influence* of all of these on your thinking as you read this. Wundt finds a simpler solution in his perspectivism. The logical may be considered "purely" from a logical point of view, i.e., in terms of its normative character, *or* "genetically" from a psychological point of view. But there are no logical laws that are not also describable psychologically, just as there is no psychological phenomenon not also describable physiologically. But being "describable" in this sense is not the same as being *explicable*, and it is this separate task of explanation that falls to logic and psychology, respectively. The logical description saves the phenomenon of normativity, just as the psychological description saves the phenomenon of the interiority of consciousness. ## 8. Conclusion Wundt's conception of psychology was always controversial. At least in Germany, the struggle over the status and philosophical meaning of "consciousness" resulted, on the one hand, in the exclusion of Wundtian empiricism from philosophy departments, striving to maintain their speculative purity, and, on the other, the institutional establishment of experimental psychology as an independent discipline. This was not the outcome Wundt had desired. He had wished to reform *philosophy*, not as a synthetic science, but with a direct, indispensable, juridical relation *vis-a-vis* both the natural and human sciences. He never saw his psychological scientism as a threat to philosophy--on the contrary, he considered his psychology to be a part of philosophy (cf. Boring 1950: 325), one necessary for philosophy to take its proper place in the totality of the sciences. Indeed, philosophy could only assume that position through the mediating position of psychology (*PP* I: 3). Yet academic philosophers, denied the possibility of any legislative or executive functions in the sciences, rejected the juridical ones as well, bitterly resisting contamination of their pure pursuit by the empiricism of the new psychology. In Germany, resistance was especially stiff among neo-Kantians, and later the Phenomenologists. In the end, the quarreling parties ineluctably assumed positions similar to their opponents'--though of course in a "purified" way.[52] Let us return to James's mean remark[53] about Wundt: he has no *noeud vital*, no central idea, and so this would-be Napoleon-planarian can never be "killed all at once". Setting aside Wundt's need to be killed at once or in bits, a fair and attentive reader will respectfully reject such scintillating criticisms. For although Wundt has many ideas--"the theory of actuality", the "principle of psychophysical parallelism", "voluntarism", "creative resultants", etc., etc.--yet they all do have a single unifying node, namely what I have here called "monistic perspectivism". If Wundt has a big idea, it is that Being is a single flow of Becoming with many sides and many ways of being described. Consequently *we*, as part of this Being, have many ways of describing and explaining it. Few have as unblinkingly accepted the consequences of their starting points, or more doggedly pursued them to their various ends as Wundt.
wyclif
## 1. Life and Works ### 1.1 Life John Wyclif was born near Richmond (Yorkshire) before 1330 and ordained in 1351. He spent the greater part of his life in the schools at Oxford: he was fellow of Merton in 1356, master of arts at Balliol in 1360, and doctor of divinity in 1372. He definitely left Oxford in 1381 for Lutterworth (Leicestershire), where he died on 31 December, 1384. It was not until 1374 (when he went on a diplomatic mission to Bruges) that Wyclif entered the royal service, but his connection with John of Gaunt, Duke of Lancaster, probably dates back to 1371. His ideas on lordship and church wealth, expressed in *De civili dominio* (*On Civil Dominion*), caused his first official condemnation in 1377 by the Pope (Gregory XI), who censured nineteen articles. As has been pointed out (Leff 1967), in 1377-78 Wyclif made a swift progression from unqualified fundamentalism to a heretical view of the Church and its Sacraments. He clearly claimed the supremacy of the king over the priesthood (see for instance his *De ecclesia* [*On the Church*], between early 1378 and early 1379), and the simultaneous presence in the Eucharist of the substance of the bread and the body of Christ (*De eucharistia* [*On the Eucharist*], and *De apostasia* [*On Apostasy*], both ca. 1380). His theses would influence Jan Hus and Jerome of Prague in the 15th century. So long as he limited his attack to abuses and the wealth of the Church, he could rely on the support of a (more or less extended) part of the clergy and aristocracy, but once he dismissed the traditional doctrine of transubstantiation, his (unorthodox) theses could not be defended any more. Thus in 1382 Archbishop Courtenay had twenty-four propositions that were attributed to Wyclif condemned by a council of theologians, and could force Wyclif's followers at Oxford University to retract their views or flee. The Council of Constance (1414-18) condemned Wyclif's writings and ordered his books burned and his body removed from consecrated ground. This last order, confirmed by Pope Martin V, was carried out in 1428. The most complete biographical study of Wyclif is still the monograph of Workman 1926, but the best analysis of his intellectual development and of the philosophical and theological context of his ideas is Robson 1961. ### 1.2 Works Wyclif produced a very large body of work, both in Latin and English, a great portion of which has been edited by the Wyclif Society between the end of the 19th and the beginning of the 20th centuries, even though some of his most important books are still unpublished -- for instance, his treatises on time (*De tempore*) and on divine ideas (*De ideis*). W. R. Thomson 1983 wrote a full bibliography of Wyclif's Latin writings, among which the following can be mentioned: *De logica* (*On Logic* -- ca. 1360); *Continuatio logicae* (*Continuation of [the Treatise on] Logic* -- date of composition: about 1360-63 according to Thomson 1983, but between 1371 and 1374 according to Mueller 1985); *De ente in communi* (*On Universal Being* -- ca. 1365); *De ente primo in communi* (*On Primary Being* -- ca. 1365); *De actibus animae* (*On the Acts of Soul* - ca. 1365); *Purgans errores circa universalia in communi* (*Amending Errors about Universals* -- between 1366 and 1368); *De ente praedicamentali* (*On Categorial Being* -- ca. 1369); *De intelleccione Dei* (*On the Intellection of God* - ca. 1370); *De volucione Dei* (*On the Volition of God* - ca. 1370); *Tractatus de universalibus* (*Treatise on Universals* -- ca. 1368-69 according to Thomson 1983, but between 1373 and 1374 according to Mueller 1985); *De materia et forma* (*On matter and form* -- between late 1370 and early 1372 according to Thomson 1983, but about 1374-75 according to Mueller 1985). Many of these treatises were later arranged as a *Summa*, called *Summa de ente* (*Summa on Being*), in two books, containing seven and six treatises respectively. (On the genesis, nature, structure, and tasks of this work see Robson 1961, pp. 115-40.) ## 2. Logic ### 2.1 Some preliminary remarks Late medieval Nominalists, like Ockham and his followers, drew a distinction between things as they exist in the extra-mental world and the schemata by means of which we think of and talk about them. While the world consists only of two genera of individuals, substances and qualities, the concepts by which they are grasped and expressed are universal and of ten different types. Nor do the relations through which we connect our notions in a proposition analytically correspond to the real links that join individuals in a state of affairs. Thus, our conceptual forms do not coincide with the elements and structures of reality, and our knowledge does not reproduce its objects but merely *regards* them. Wyclif maintained that such an approach to philosophical questions was misleading and deleterious. Many times in his works he expressed the deepest hostility to such a tendency. He thought that only on the basis of a close isomorphism between language and the world could the signifying power of terms and statements, the possibility of definitions, and finally the validity and universality of our knowledge be explained and ensured. So the nucleus of his metaphysics lies in his trust in the scheme *object-label* as *the* general interpretative key of every logico-epistemological problem. He firmly believed that language was an ordered collection of signs, each referring to one of the constitutive elements of reality, and that true (linguistic) propositions were like pictures of those elements' inner structures or/and mutual relationships. From this point of view, universals are conceived of as the real essences common to many individual things, which are necessary conditions for our language to be significant. Wyclif thought that by associating common terms with such universal realities the fact could be accounted for that each common term can stand for many things at once and can label all of them in the same way. This conviction explains the main characteristic of his philosophical style, to which all his contributions can be traced back: a strong propensity towards hypostatisation. Wyclif methodically replaces logical and epistemological rules with ontological criteria and references. He thought of logic as turning on structural forms, independent of both their semantic contents and the mental acts by which they are grasped. It is through these forms that the network connecting the basic constituents of the world (individuals and universals, substances and accidents, concrete properties, like being-white, and abstract forms, like whiteness) is disclosed to us. His peculiar analysis of predication and his own formulation of the Scotistic formal distinction are logically necessary requirements of this philosophical approach. They are two absolute novelties in late medieval philosophy, and certainly the most important of Wyclif's contributions to the thought of his times. Wyclif's last formulation of the theory of difference and his theory of universals and predication are linked together, and rest upon a sort of componential analysis where things substitute for lexemes and ontological properties substitute for semantic features. Within Wyclif's world, difference (or distinction) is defined in terms of partial identity, and is the main kind of transcendental relation holding among the world's objects, since in virtue of its metaphysical composition everything is at the same time partially identical to and different from any other. When the objects at issue are categorial items, and among what differentiates them is their own individual being, the objects differ *essentially*. If the objects share the same individual being and what differentiates them is (at least) one of their *concrete* metaphysical components (or features), then the objects differ *really*, whereas if what differentiates them is one of their *abstract* metaphysical components, then they differ *formally*. Formal distinction is therefore the tool by means of which the dialectic of one-many internal to the world's objects is regulated. It explains why one and the same thing is at the same time an atomic state of affairs and how many different beings can constitute just one thing. ### 2.2 The formal distinction Wyclif explains the notion of formal distinction (or difference) in the *Purgans errores circa universalia in communi* (chap. 4, p. 38) and in the later *Tractatus de universalibus*. (On Wyclif's formulation of the formal distinction see Spade 1985, pp. xx-xxxi, and Conti 1997, pp. 158-63.) The two versions differ from each other on some important points, and are both unsatisfactory, since Wyclif's definitions of the different types of distinction are rather ambiguous. In the *Tractatus de universalibus* (chap. 4, pp. 90-92), Wyclif lists three main kinds of differences (or distinctions): 1. real-and-essential; 2. real-but-not-essential; and 3. formal (or notional). He does not define the real-and-essential difference, but identifies it through a rough account of its three sub-types. The things that differ really-and-essentially are those that differ from each other either (i) in genus, like man and quantity, or (ii) in species, like man and donkey, or (iii) in number, like two human beings. The real-but-not-essential difference is more subtle than the first kind, since it holds between things that are the same single essence but really differ from each other nevertheless -- like memory, reason, and will, which are one and the same soul, and the three Persons of the Holy Trinity, who are the one and same God. The third main kind of difference is the formal one. It is described as the difference by which things differ from each other even though they are constitutive elements of the same single essence or supposit. According to Wyclif, this is the case for: 1. the concrete accidents inherent in the same substance, since they coincide in the same particular subject but differ from each other because of their own natures; 2. the matter and substantial form of the same individual substance; 3. what is more common in relation to what is less common, like (*a*) the divine nature and the three Persons, (*b*) the world and this world; and, (*c*) among the categorial items belonging to the same category, a superior item and one of its inferiors. This account of the various kinds of distinctions is more detailed than that of the *Purgans errores circa universalia in communi*, but not more clear. What is the difference, for instance, between the definition of the real-but-not-essential distinction and the definition of the formal distinction? What feature do all the kinds of formal distinction agree in? Some points are obvious, however: 1. The real-and-essential distinction matches the traditional real difference. 2. The real-but-not-essential distinction and the first sub-type of the formal distinction (that is, the distinction that holds between two or more concrete accidents belonging to the same individual substance) are two slightly different versions of the Scotistic formal distinction as defined in Scotus' *Lectura* (book I, d. 2, p. 2, qq. 1-4, ed. Vaticana, vol. xvi, p. 216) and *Ordinatio* (book I, d. 2, p. 2, qq. 1-4, ed. Vaticana, vol. ii, pp. 356-57; book II, d. 3, p. 1, q. 6, ed. Vaticana, vol. vii, pp. 483-84). 3. The third sub-type of the formal distinction is a reformulation of the Scotistic formal distinction as described in Scotus' *Reportata Parisiensia* (book I, d. 33, qq. 2-3, and d. 34, q. 1, ed. Vives, vol. xxii, pp. 402-8, 410). The main apparent dissimilarities between the analyses proposed in the *Tractatus de universalibus* and in the *Purgans errores circa universalia in communi* are the following: 1. There are three main kinds of differences instead of two. 2. Notwithstanding the presence of the qualification 'real', the real-but-not-essential difference in the *Tractatus de universalibus* is closer to the formal difference than is the corresponding kind of difference in the *Purgans errores circa universalia in communi*, since in the former the term 'essence' has the technical meaning of real entity with a given nature, and so is equivalent to 'thing'. 3. The difference between the matter and the substantial form of the same individual substance is seen as a sub-type of real difference in the *Purgans errores circa universalia in communi* and as a sub-type of formal distinction in the *Tractatus de universalibus*. ### 2.3 The analysis of predication Wyclif presents his opinion on universals as intermediate between those ones of St. Thomas (and Giles of Rome) and Walter Burley. Like Giles, whom he quotes by name, Wyclif recognizes three main kinds of universals: 1. *ante rem*, or ideal universals; that is, the ideas in God, archetypes of all that there is; 2. *in re*, or formal universals; that is, the common natures shared by individual things; and 3. *post rem*, or intentional universals; that is, mental signs by which we refer to the universals *in re*. The ideas in God are the causes of the formal universals, and the formal universals are the causes of the intentional universals. On the other hand, like Burley, Wyclif holds that formal universals exist *in actu* outside our minds, not *in potentia* as moderate Realists thought -- even though, unlike Burley, he maintains they are really identical with their own individuals. So Wyclif accepts the traditional realistic account of the relationship between universals and individuals, but translates it into the terms of his own system. According to him, universals and individuals are *really* the same, but *formally* distinct, since they share the same empirical reality (that of individuals) but, considered as universals and individuals, they have opposite constituent principles. On the logical side, this means that, notwithstanding real identity, not all that is predicated of individuals can be *directly* predicated of universals or *vice versa*, though an indirect predication is always possible. Hence Wyclif's description of the logical structure of the relationship between universals and individuals demanded the introduction of a new kind of predication, unknown to Aristotle, to cover cases, admitted by the theory, of indirect inherence of an accidental form in a substantial universal and of one second intention in another. Therefore Wyclif distinguished three main types of predication, which he conceived as a real relation that holds between metaphysical entities. (On Wyclif's theory of predication, see Spade 1985, pp. xxxi-xli, and Conti 1997, pp. 150-58.) In the *Purgans errores circa universalia in communi* (chap. 2), the three main types of predication are the following: formal predication, essential predication, and causal predication. In the *Tractatus de universalibus* (chap. 1, pp. 28-37), causal predication has been replaced by habitudinal predication -- a kind of predication that Wyclif had already recognized in the *Purgans errores circa universalia in communi*, but whose position within the main division of types of predication was not clear. In the *Tractatus de universalibus*, formal predication, essential predication, and habitudinal predication are described as three non-exclusive ways of predicating, each more general than the preceding. We speak of causal predication when the form designated by the predicate term is not present in the entity signified by the subject term, but is something caused by that entity. No instances of this kind of predication are given by Wyclif. Formal predication, essential predication, and habitudinal predication are defined in almost the same way in the *Purgans errores circa universalia* and in the *Tractatus de universalibus*. Formal predication is that in which the form designated by the predicate term is directly present in the entity signified by the subject term. This happens whenever an item in the categorial line is predicated of something inferior, or an accident is predicated of its subject of inherence. In fact, in both cases, the subject term and the predicate term refer to the same reality in virtue of the form connoted by the predicate term itself. To speak of essential predication, it is sufficient that the same empirical reality is both the real subject and the predicate, even though the formal principle connoted by the predicate term differs from that connoted by the subject term. 'God is man' and 'The universal is particular' are instances of this kind of predication. In fact, the same empirical reality (or essence) that is a universal is also an individual, but the forms connoted by the subject term and by the predicate term differ from each other. Finally we speak of habitudinal predication when the form connoted by the predicate term does not inhere, either directly or indirectly, in the essence designated by the subject, but simply implies a relation to it, so that the same predicate may be at different times truly or falsely spoken of its subject without there being any change in the subject itself. According to Wyclif, we use such a kind of predication mainly when we want to express theological truths, like: God is known and loved by many creatures, and brings about, as efficient, exemplar, and final cause, many good effects. It is evident that habitudinal predication does not require any kind of identity between the entity signified by the subject term and the entity signified by the predicate term, but formal predication and essential predication do. So the ontological presuppositions of the most general type of predication, implied by the other types, are completely different from those of the other two. The final result of Wyclif's revolution is therefore an incomplete system of intensional logic, which he superimposes on the standard extensional system inherited from Aristotle. As a result, the copula of the philosophical propositions that are dealt with cannot be extensionally interpreted, since it does not properly mean that a given object is a member of a certain set or that a given set is included in another; rather it means degrees of identity. Only in virtue of renouncing any extensional approach to the matter were Wyclif's followers able to give a logically satisfactory solution of the problem of the relationship between universals and individuals, which had always been the most difficult issue for medieval Realists. ### 2.4 Supposition and meaning The relationship between thought and reality was a focal point of Wyclif's reflection. On the one hand, Wyclif believed that thought was linguistically constrained by its own nature; on the other hand, he considered thought to be related to reality in its elements and constitution. Hence he deemed language, thought, and external reality to be of the same logical coherence (see Conti 2006, pp. 114-18, and Spruyt 2008, pp. 24-25). Within this context, the theory of supposition was intended to explain the different roles that words (or phrases) can have in relation to language and the extra-mental world when they appear as extremes (that is, as subject or predicate) in propositions. Characteristically, his theory of supposition provides an account not only of the truth-values of a sentence, but also of its meaning; it is not therefore simply a theory of reference, but a sort of complex analysis of language viewed as a semiotic system whose unique interpretative model was the reality itself. It gives clear evidence of Wyclif's realist choice and of his conviction that any kind of linguistic and semantic features must be grounded on ontological structures. In what follows, I shall consider the most important aspects of Wyclif's theory of supposition, trying to set it in relation to the medieval tradition of treatises on signification and supposition and particularly to its main source, the theory expounded by Walter Burley in his *De puritate artis logicae tractatus longior* (composed between 1325 and 1328), which contains an original and intelligent defence of the old view of signification and simple supposition against Ockham's attacks. Wyclif defines supposition as the signification of one categorematic extreme of a proposition (subject or predicate) in relation to the other extreme (*De logica*, chap. 12, vol. I, p. 39). This definition, which is drawn from Burley's *De suppositionibus* (composed in 1302), sounds partially different from the standard definition of supposition, as it seems to somehow equate signification and supposition, since supposition is considered as a particular kind of signification. On the contrary, according to the most common view, which went back to Peter of Spain's *Summulae logicales*, signification and supposition of terms were clearly distinct functions, inasmuch as the latter presupposed the former, but it was a *proprietas terminorum* (a term property) totally different from it. In fact, (1) signification consisted in the relation of a linguistic sign to what it signifies apart from any propositional context; (2) a word capable of standing for something else or for itself in a proposition had first to have signification; (3) a term only had supposition in a propositional context; and (4) the kind of supposition a term had depended on its propositional context. In any case, in a traditional realist perspective, supposition served to tell us which things are involved in the truth-conditions of a given sentence: whether they are expressions, real universals, or individuals. At the very beginning of the chapter on supposition, like Walter Burley, Wyclif divides supposition into improper, in which a term stands for something different from its primary significatum by special custom (*ex usu loquendi*), and proper, in which a term stands for something by the virtue of the expression itself. So a term has improper supposition when it is used in a figurative speech. It is the case of the term 'cup' in the sentence 'I have drunk a cup <of wine>'. Wyclif divides proper supposition into material, when the term stand for itself or its sound (as it occurs in "'I' is a pronoun" or "'Iohannes' is trisyllabic"), and formal, when the term stands for what it properly signifies. Formal supposition is twofold: simple and personal. Like William of Sherwood, Peter of Spain, and Burley, and against Ockham and his followers, Wyclif affirms that the supposition is simple if the term stands for an extra-mental universal only, as it occurs in 'Man can be predicated of every man', and 'Man is a species'. According to Wyclif, in both cases the term 'man' supposits for the human nature, which is an extra-mental form common to a multiplicity of singulars. Simple supposition is divided into equal and unequal. A term is in simple equal supposition if it stands for the common nature that it directly signifies, as it occurs in 'man is a species'. A term is in simple unequal supposition when it stands for (1) a less common nature than that it signifies, as it occurs in 'substance is a species', or (2) a concrete accident or the characterizing property (*pro accidente vel proprio primo*), as it occurs in 'this universal-man is capable of laughing' ('*hic homo communis est risibilis*') -- where the presence of the demonstrative 'this' modifies the significate of the subject-term 'universal-man', so that in the sentence it supposits for that concrete exemplification (the human nature proper to an individual man) which is identical with the subject of inherence (a given human being) of the accidental form, or characterizing property (in the example, the capacity-of-laughing), signified by the predicate-term. The supposition is personal when the term which plays the role of subject in a sentence stands for one or more individuals. In the first case, the supposition is personal and singular, as it occurs in 'this man is' ('*hic homo est*'); in the second one, it is personal and common. The personal and common supposition is twofold. If the term stands for many singulars considered separately or for some (that is, at least one) determinate individual named by the common term itself, the supposition is *personalis distincta* (or determinate, as Wyclif calls it in the final section of the chapter 12), as it occurs in 'these (men) are' ('*isti sunt*'). If the term stands for many singulars considered together, the supposition is a personal universal supposition (*personalis universalis*). In turn, the personal universal supposition is divided into confused and distributive (*confusa distributiva*) and merely confused (*confusa tantum*). There is *suppositio personalis communis universalis confusa distributiva* when the (subject-)term stands for everything which has the form it signifies, as it occurs in 'every man is' ('*omnis homo est*'). There is *suppositio personalis communis universalis confusa tantum* when the form (or property) signified by the term at issue is affirmed (or not affirmed) equally well of one of the bearers of that form as of another, since it applies (or does not apply) to each for exactly the same reasons, as it occurs in 'both of them are one of the two' ('*uterque istorum est alter istorum*'), where the expression 'one of the two' has merely confused supposition, since none of the two can be both of them. The confused suppositions are so called since they involve many different individuals, and this is the case for the subject of a universal affirmative proposition (*De logica*, chap. 12, pp. 39-40). Wyclif takes a resolutely realist stand, as his formulation and division of supposition (where simple supposition is described as that possessed by a term in relation to a universal outside the intellect and personal supposition as that possessed by a term in relation to one or more individual) make evident. In this way, he stresses the ontological entailments of Burley's theory. In his *De suppositionibus* and *De puritate artis logicae* Burley had adopted a semantic point of view in describing supposition, since he had defined formal supposition as the supposition that a term has when it stands for its own *significatum* or for the (individual) items which fall under it. In the first case, we properly speak of simple supposition, and in the second, we speak of personal supposition. Wyclif makes clear what Burley had stated only implicitly: the *significatum* of a common term is always a common nature (that is, a universal form) really existing outside the intellect. This fits in with his theory of meaning and his ontology. In the first chapter of his treatise on logic (*De logica*, chap. 1, pp. 2-7) Wyclif maintains that: (1) a categorematic term is a *dictio* to which a mental concept, sign of a thing, corresponds in the soul. (2) Categorematic terms are divided into common (namely, general expressions), like 'man' and 'dog', and discrete (namely, singular referring expressions), such as personal and demonstrative pronouns and proper names. (3) Common terms originally and primarily signify common natures -- for instance, the term 'man' originally and primarily signifies the human nature. (4) Categorematic terms can be divided into substantial terms, such as 'man', and accidental terms, such as 'white'. A substantial term signifies a common nature proper to a set of individuals (of which the term is the name) without connoting any accidental property; while an accidental term signifies (but we would rather say: 'referes to') a common essence, proper to a set of individuals, and also (we would add: connotes) an accidental property, that is, a property which is not constitutive of the essence referred to. (5) Categorematic common terms can be divided also into abstract and concrete. According to Wyclif, a concrete term, like 'man', is a term which signifies a thing that can have both simple and personal supposition at once. On the contrary, an abstract term is a term which signifies only a common nature without connoting anything else, like 'humanity' and 'whiteness'. It is worth noticing that in defining concrete terms Wyclif a) plainly attributes the capacity for suppositing to things; b) does not clarify the metaphysical composition of such things signified by concrete terms; and c) describes the twofold supposition of concrete terms as a sort of signification. (6) Finally, categorematic terms can be divided into terms of first and second intention. A term of first intention is a sign which signifies without connoting the properties of being-individual or being-universal which characterize categorial items. For example, 'God' and 'man' are terms of first intention. On the contrary, a term of second intention is a term which connotes such properties and refers to a common nature without naming it. 'Universal' and 'primary substance' are terms of second intention. As is evident, the basic ideas of Wyclif's theory of meaning are that (1) every simple expression in our language is like a label naming just one essence in the world; and (2) distinctions among terms as well as their linguistic and semantic properties are derived from the ontological features of signified things. He affirms that everything which exists signifies in a complex manner that it is something real (*De logica*, chap. 5, p. 14 -- see Cesalli 2005); expressly claims that supposition is also a property of signified things; and explains the semantic difference between general terms, such as 'man', which can name a set of individuals, and singular expressions, such as 'Socrates' or 'a certain man' ('*aliquis homo*'), which name just one item, by means of the different modalities of existence of their different signified things (*significata*). Singular expressions name and signify individuals, albeit general terms name and signify common natures. In Wyclif's view, a common term gives name to a certain set of individuals only by way of the nature that it originally and directly signifies, and is common to a certain group of individuals as their own quiddity (*De logica*, chap. 1, p. 7). As is evident from what he says in the first three chapters of his *De logica* (on terms, universals, and categories respectively), Wyclif identifies secondary substances (that is, the universals of the category of substance) with the *significata* of general (concrete) terms of that category (such as 'man' or 'animal') and individual substances with the *significata* of singular expressions of that category (such as 'this man', which refers to a single human individual only). Furthermore, he holds that (1) common terms of the category of substance, when used predicatively, specified which kind of substance a certain individual substance is; (2) individual substances are unique physical entities, located at a particular place in space and time; and (3) universal substances are the specific or generic natures proper to the individual substances, immanent in them, and apt to be common to many individuals at the same time. As a result, like Burley, Wyclif thinks of universals and individuals as linked together by a sort of relation of instantiation. In other words, he conceives of individuals as the tokens of universal natures, and universal natures as the types of individuals. This consequence is common also to many other Realist authors of the 13th and 14th centuries. But, because of his peculiar reading of the relation between universals and individuals, Wyclif derives from it an original conception of the signification and suppostion of concrete accidental terms, such as 'white', that inspired the new theories and divisions of supposition developed in Oxford between 14th and 15th centuries. According to them, any concrete accidental term which occurs as an extreme in a proposition can stand for (1) the substrate of inherence of the accidental form that it connotes (*suppositio personalis*), or (2) the accidental form itself (*suppositio abstractiva*), or (3) the aggregate composed of the individual substance, which plays the role of the substrate of the form, and the singular accidental form at issue (*suppositio concretiva*) (so, for instance, William Penbygull in his treatise on universals). Wyclif ends chapter 12 of his *De logica* with three *notanda* (pp. 40-42), by which he completes his treatment of supposition. In the first one, he recalls that categorematic common concrete terms can supposit both *personaliter* and *simpliciter* at once (*mixtim*) when the propositions where they occur as subjects are universal affirmative or indefinite. For instance, the term 'animal' in (1) 'every animal was in Noah's ark' ('*omne animal fuit in archa Noe*' as well as the term 'man' in (2) 'man dies' ('*homo moritur*') can supposit personaliter for every individual animal and man respectively, and if so, the first sentence is false and the second true, and *simpliciter* for every species of animals and the human nature respectively, and then both sentences are true. In the second *notandum*, Wyclif contends that proper names, personal and demonstrative pronouns, and those terms of second intention by which we speak of the singular items considered as such (namely, expression like '*persona*' and '*individuum*') cannot supposit distributively, since they were devised in order to signify *discrete vel singulariter* only. Finally, in the third one, he lays down the following rules about the supposition possessed by the subject-term and the predicate-term in the Square of Oppositions: (1) in every universal affirmative proposition, the subject supposits *mobiliter*, that is: it has confused and distributive supposition, while the predicate has *suppositio confusa tantum* or simple. The supposition is merely confused if it does not allow for descent to a certain singular nor a universal -- in other words, a (predicate-)term has the supposition *confusa tantum* when it is used attributively of its extension. The supposition is simple if the predicate-term refers to a common nature, as it is the case in 'every man is man', where the predicate 'man' supposits for the human nature. (2) Both the subject and predicate of a universal negative proposition have confused distributive supposition, if they are common terms, as it occurs in 'no man is a stone'. (3) In particular affirmative propositions, such as 'some man is animal', both the subject and predicate have determinate supposition. (4) In particular negative propositions, the subject-term has determinate supposition and the predicate-term has distributive confused supposition. Wyclif's own discussion of the sophism *I promise you a coin that I do not promise* (*Logicae continuatio*, tr. 3, chap. 3, vol. 2, pp. 55-72; but see also the *Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 7, pp. 133-35) makes evident the realist stand showed by his theories of meaning and supposition. Like Burley before him, in his *Logicae continuatio* Wyclif defends the claim that what is explicitly promised in such a promise, 'I promise you one or other of these coins I have in my hands' (*promitto tibi alterum illorum denariorum in altera manuum mearum*), is the universal-coin, and not a singular one, even if I can fulfil the promise only by giving any singular coin, since a universal cannot be given or possessed except by a singular (*Logicae continuatio*, tr. 3, chap. 3, p. 62). Thanks to his distinction between simple and personal supposition, Wyclif is able to explain from a semantic point of view the difference between promising a coin in general and promising a particular coin: in the first case the term 'coin' (*denarius*) has simple supposition, and therefore the proposition is true if and only if what is said is true of the universal-coin; on the contrary, if the term 'coin' has personal supposition (more precisely, personal and singular supposition), the proposition is true if and only if what is said is true of *a* particular coin. According to him, by promising a singular, a universal is promised *secundarie* and *confuse*, and conversely (*ibid*., p. 64). So, given two coins in my hands, the coin *A* and the coin *B*, the proposition 'I promise you one or other of these coins' is true, even though, when asked whether I promised the coin *A*, my answer is 'No', and so too when asked whether I promised the coin *B*. In fact, according to Wyclif, what I promised is the universal-coin, since the phrase 'one or other of these coins' has simple supposition and therefore stands for a universal, however restricted in its instantiations to one or other of the two coins in my hands (*ibid*., p. 67). This does not mean that the universal-coin is a sort of third coin over and above the two coins in my hands. Wyclif had already rejected this mistaken conclusion in the previous chapter of the *Logicae continuatio*. He argues that to add the universal-man as a third man to Socrates and Plato, given that there are only these two individual men in the world, exhibits a fallacy of equivocation. When a number is added to a term of first intention (like 'man'), the presence of this numerical term modifies the kind of supposition from simple to personal; but one can refer to a universal only with a term with simple supposition. As a consequence the universal cannot be counted with its individuals - and in fact any universal is really identical to each one of its individuals, and so it cannot differ in number from each of them (*ibid*., chap. 2, p. 48). ## 3. Metaphysics ### 3.1 Being and analogy The point of departure for Wyclif's metaphysics is the notion of being, since it occupies the central place in his ontology. After Duns Scotus, the real issue for metaphysics was the relationship between being and, on the other side, God and creatures, as Scotus' theory of the univocity of the concept of being was an absolute novelty, full of important consequences for the development of later medieval philosophy. Wyclif takes many aspects from Scotus' explanation, but strongly stresses the ontological implications of the doctrine. Wyclif, like Scotus, claims that the notion of being is the most general one, a notion entailed by all others, but he also states that an extra-mental reality corresponds to the concept of being-in-general (*ens in communi*). This extra-mental reality is predicated of everything (God and creatures, substances and accidents, universal and individual essences) according to different degrees, since God *is* in the proper sense of the term and any other entity is (something real) only insofar as it shares the being of God (*De ente in communi*, chap. 1, pp. 1-2; chap. 2, p. 29; *De ente praedicamentali*, chap. 1, p. 13; chap. 4, p. 30; *Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 4, p. 89; chap. 7, p. 130; chap. 12, p. 279; *De materia et forma*, chap. 6, p. 213). If being is a reality, it is then clear that it is impossible to affirm its univocity. The *Doctor Subtilis* thought of being as simply a concept, and therefore could describe it as univocal in a broad sense (one name -- one concept -- many natures). Wyclif, on the contrary, is convinced that the being-in-general is an extra-mental reality, so he works out his theory at a different level than does Scotus: no more at the intensional level (the meaning connected with the univocal sign, or *univocum univocans*), but at the extensional one (the thing signified by the mental sign, considered as shared by different entities according to different degrees). For that reason, he cannot use Aristotelian univocation, which hides these differences in sharing. Thus he denies the univocity of being and prefers to use one of the traditional notions of analogy (*De ente praedicamentali*, chap. 3, pp. 25, 27), since the being of God is the measure of the being of other things, which are drawn up on a scale with the separated spiritual substances at the top and prime matter at the bottom. Therefore he qualifies being as an ambiguous genus (*ibidem*, p. 29), borrowing an expression already used by Grosseteste in his commentary on Aristotle's *Posterior Analytics*. The analogy of being does not entail a multiplicity of correlated meanings, however, as in Thomas Aquinas. Since Wyclif hypostatizes the notion of being and considers equivocity, analogy, and univocity as real relations between things, not as semantic relations between terms and things, his analogy is partially equivalent to the standard Aristotelian univocity, since what differentiates analogy from univocity is the way a certain nature (or property) is shared by a set of things: analogous things (*analoga*) share it according to different degrees (*secundum magis et minus*, or *secundum prius et posterius*), while univocal things (*univoca*) share it all in the same manner and at the same degree. This is the true sense of his distinction between ambiguous genera, like being and accident (*accidens*), and logical genera, like substance (*De ente praedicamentali*, chap. 4, pp. 30, 32). Hence, according to this account, being in general is the basic component of the metaphysical structure of each reality, which possesses it in accordance with its own nature, value, and position in the hierarchy of created beings. Unfortunately, this theory is weak in an important point, since Wyclif does not clarify the relation between being-in-general and God. On the one hand, being is a creature, the first of all the creatures; on the other hand, God should share it, as being-in-general is the most common reality, predicated of all, and according to him to-be-predicated-of something means to-be-shared-by it. As a consequence, a creature would be in some respect superordinated to God -- a theological puzzle that Wyclif failed to acknowledge. ### 3.2 Being and truth According to Wyclif, the constitutive property of each kind of being is the capacity to be the object of a complex act of signifying (*De ente in communi*, chap. 3, p. 36; *De ente primo in communi*, chap. 1, p. 70). This choice implies a revolution in the standard medieval theory of transcendentals, since Wyclif actually replaces being (*ens*) with true (*verum*). According to the common belief, among the transcendentals (being, thing, one, something, true, good) being was the primitive notion, from which all the others stemmed by adding a specific connotation in relation to something else, or by adding some new determination. So true (*verum*) was nothing but being (*ens*) itself considered in relation to an intellect, no matter whether divine or human. In Wyclif's view, on the contrary, being is no longer the main transcendental and its notion is not the first and simplest; rather there is something more basic to which being can be reduced: truth (*veritas* or *verum*). According to the English philosopher, only what can be signified by a complex expression is a being, and whatever is the proper object of an act of signifying is a truth. Truth is therefore the true name of being itself (*Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 7, p. 139). Thus everything that is is a truth, and every truth is something not simple but complex. Absolute simplicity is unknown within Wyclif's metaphysical world. From the semantic point of view, this means the collapsing of the fundamental distinction in the common Aristotelian theory of meaning, the one between simple signs (like nouns) and compound signs (like propositions). From the ontological point of view, this entails the uniqueness in type of what is signified by every class of categorematic expressions (*Logica*, chap. 5, p. 14). Within Wyclif's world, it is the same kind of object that both concrete terms and propositions refer to, as individual substances have to be regarded as (atomic) states of affairs. According to him, from the metaphysical point of view a singular man is nothing but a real proposition (*propositio realis*), where actual existence in time as an individual plays the role of the subject, the common nature (i.e., human nature) plays the role of the predicate, and the singular essence (i.e., that by means of which this individual is a man) plays the role of the copula (*ibid*., pp. 14-15). Despite appearances, Wyclif's opinion on this subject is not just a new formulation of the theory of the *complexe significabile*. According to the supporters of the *complexe significabile* theory, the same things that are signified by simple concrete terms are signified by complex expressions (or propositions). In Wyclif's thought, on the contrary, there are no simple things in the world that correspond to simple concrete terms; rather, simple concrete terms designate real propositions, that is, atomic states of affairs. Wyclif's real proposition is that everything that is, as everything save God is composed at least of potency and act (*De ente praedicamentali*, chap. 5, pp. 38-39), can therefore be conceived of and signified both in a complex (*complexe*) and in a non-complex manner (*incomplexe*) (*Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 2, pp. 55-56; chap. 3, pp. 70, 74, and 84; chap. 6, pp. 118-19). When we conceive of a thing in a complex manner, we consider that thing according to its metaphysical structure, and so according to its many levels of being and kinds of essence. As a consequence, Wyclif's metaphysical world, like his physical world, consists of atomic objects, that is, single essences belonging to the ten different types or categories. But these metaphysical atoms are not simple but rather composite, because they are reducible to something else, belonging to a different rank of reality and unable to exist by themselves: being and essence, potency and act, matter and form, abstract genera, species and differences. For that reason, everything one can speak about or think of is both a thing and an atomic state of affairs, while every true sentence expresses a molecular state of affairs, that is, the union (if the sentence is affirmative) or the separation (if the sentence is negative) of two (or more) atomic objects (on Wyclif's theory of proposition see Cesalli 2005). ### 3.3 Being and essence Among the many kinds of beings Wyclif lists, the most important set is that consisting of categorial beings. They are characterized by the double fact of having a nature and of being the constitutive elements of finite corporeal beings or atomic states of affairs. These categorial items, conceived of as instances of a certain kind of being, are called by Wyclif 'essences' (*essentiae*). An essence therefore is a being that has a well defined nature, even if the name 'essence' does not make this nature known (*De ente primo in communi*, chap. 3, pp. 88-89; *De ente praedicamentali*, chap. 5, p. 43; *Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 7, pp. 128-29; *De materia et forma*, chap. 4, pp. 185-86). So the term 'essence' (*essentia*) is less general than 'being' (*ens*), but more general than 'quiddity' (*quidditas*), since (i) every essence is a being, and not every being is an essence, and (ii) every quiddity is an essence, and not every essence is a quiddity, as individual things are essences but are not quiddities (see Kenny 1985, pp. 21 ff.; and Conti 1993, pp. 171-81). According to Wyclif, being is the stuff that the ten categories modulate according to their own nature, so that everything is immediately something that is (*De ente praedicamentali*, chap. 4, p. 30; *Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 7, p. 130); therefore, he maintains no real distinction between essence and being. The essences of creatures do not precede their beings, not even causally, since every thing is identical with its essence. The being of a thing is brought into existence by God at the same instant as its essence, since essence without being and being without essence would be two self-contradictory states of affairs. In fact, essence without being would imply that an individual could be something of a given type without being real in any way, and being without essence would imply that there could be the existence of a thing without the thing itself (*Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 6, pp. 122-23). As a consequence, the *pars destruens* of his theory of being and essence is a strong refutation of the twin opinions of St. Thomas and Giles of Rome. Although Wyclif does not name either the Dominican master or the Augustinian one, it is nevertheless clear from the context that their conceptions are the object of his criticisms (*ibid.*, pp. 120-22). On the other hand, it is evident that while from the extensional point of view the being and essence of creatures are equipollent, since every being is an essence and *vice versa*, from the intensional point of view there is a difference, because the being of a thing *logically* presupposes its essence and not *vice versa* (*De materia et forma*, chap. 4, pp. 184-85). Moreover, in Wyclif's opinion, every creature has two different kinds of essence and four levels of being. Indeed, he clearly distinguishes between singular essence and universal essence (*essentia quidditativa speciei vel generis*) -- that is, the traditional *forma partis* and *forma totius*. The singular essence is the form that in union with the matter brings about the substantial composite. The universal essence is the type that the former instantiates; it is present in the singular substance as a constitutive part of its nature, and it discloses the inner metaphysical structure of the substantial composite (*Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 6, pp. 116-18). Furthermore, he speaks of four-fold level of reality (*esse*): 1. First, the eternal mental being (*esse ideale*) that every creature has in God, as an object of His mind. 2. Second, the potential being everything has in its causes, both universal (genus, species) and particular. This is closely connected with the nature of the individual substance on which the finite corporeal being is founded, and is independent of its actual existence. It is called '*esse essentiae*' or '*esse in genere*'. 3. Third, the actual existence in time as an earthly object. 4. Fourth, the accidental being (*modus essendi accidentalis substantiae*) caused in a substance by the inherence in it of its appropriate accidental forms (*Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 7, pp. 126-28). Thus the identity between essence and being cannot be complete. Consequently Wyclif speaks of a formal difference (*distinctio* or *differentia formalis*) -- which he also calls a 'difference of reason' (*distinctio rationis*) -- between essence and being. More precisely, he holds that: 1. The *esse ideale* is formally distinct from the singular essence; 2. The actual existence is formally distinct from the universal essence; and 3. The singular essence is formally distinct from the actual existence. In this way, Wyclif establishes a close connection between singular essence and essential being, on the one hand, and a real identity between universal and individual (that is, between universal essence and singular essence), on the other hand. Essential being is the level of being that matches singular essence, while actual existence is in a certain way accidental to the singular essence, as the latter is nothing else but the universal essence considered as informing matter. ### 3.4 Being and categories Since Wyclif thought of substance as the ultimate substrate of existence and subject of predication in relation to anything else, the only way to demonstrate the reality of the items belonging to other categories was to conceive of them as forms and attributes of substance. Accordingly, he insists that quantity, quality, and relations, considered as accidents, are forms inherent in the composite substances (cf. *De ente praedicamentali*, ch. 6, p. 48). In this way, just like Walter Burley, Wyclif wanted to safeguard the reality of accidents as well as their (real) distinction from substance and from each other, while at the same time affirming their dependence on substance in existence. ### 3.4.1 Quantity Among the nine genera of accidents, quantity is the most important one, as it is the basis of all further accidents, because every other accident presupposes it. Indeed, quantity orders substance for receiving quality and the other accidental forms. In his commentary on the *Categories* (ch. 10, SS 4) and in the first part of his *Summa Logicae* (*pars* I, ch. 44) Ockham had claimed that it was superfluous to posit quantitative forms really distinct from substance and quality, since quantity presupposes what it is intended to explain, that is, the extension of material substances and their having parts outside parts. As an accident, quantity presupposes substance as its substrate of inherence. Like Burley, Wyclif also denies that material substance can be actually extended without the presence of quantitative forms in it, thereby affirming their necessity (cf. *De ente praedicamentali*, ch. 6, p. 50.), and consequently he tries to confute Ockham's argumentation (*ibidem*, pp. 50-58). He admits that the existence of any quantity always implies that of substance, but he also believes that the actual existence of parts in a substance necessarily implies the presence of a quantitative form in it, distinct (1) from the substance (say Socrates) in which it inheres, and (2) from the truth, grounded on the substance at issue, that this same substance is a quantified thing (*ibidem*, pp. 51-53). He does not give us any sound metaphysical reason for this preference. Nevertheless, it is easily understandable, when considered from the point of view of his semantic presuppositions, according to which, the reality itself is the interpretative pattern of our language. As a consequence, the structure of language is a mere mirroring of that of reality. In Wyclif's opinion, therefore, some entities must correspond in the world to the abstract terms of the category of quantity (like '*magnitudo*') - entities really distinct from the things signified by the substantial terms. In any case, the most important evidence he offers for proving his thesis is a sort of abductive reasoning, whose implicit premise is the following inferential rule: if we can recognize a thing as the same thing before and after its undertaking a process of change, then what is changed is not the thing at issue, but a distinct entity really present in that thing as one of its real aspects. The second premise is the observation that men are of different size during their lives. And the conclusion is that those changes are due to an accidental form distinct from the substances in which it inheres (*ibidem*, p. 50). ### 3.4.2 Quality Immediately after quantity, quality comes. Following Aristotle (*Categories*, ch. 8, 8a 25), Wyclif defines quality as that in virtue of which substances are said to be qualified. The chief feature of Wyclif 's treatment of quality is his twofold consideration of quality as an abstract form and as a concrete accident. In *De ente praedicamentali* he clearly states that quality is an absolute entity, with a well determined nature, and really distinct from substance (cf. ch. 7, p. 61). Furthermore, even if incidentally, against Burley, he notes that qualitative forms can admit a more or a less, since the propria passio of the category of quality is to be more or less intense (see *ibidem*, ch. 3, p. 28). By contrast, in the *De actibus animae* (*pars* II, ch. 4), he seems to conceive of it as a mode of substance, without an actually distinct reality. Truly, there is no effective difference between the theses on quality maintained in those two works, but only a difference of point of view. As what he says about the real-and-essential distinction and the first sub-type of formal distinction makes evident, quality considered in an absolute way, according to its main level of being, is an abstract form, really distinct from substance; yet, if considered from the point of view of its existence as a concrete accident, it is not really distinct from the substance in which it is present, but only formally. In the latter case,it is a mere mode of the substance, like any other concrete accident. In fact, in the *De ente praedicamentali* Wyclif speaks of quality,using the abstract term, while in the *De actibus animae* he constantly utilises concrete expressions, such as '*quale*' and '*substantia qualis*.' ### 3.4.3 Relations and relatives Aristotle's treatment of relations in the *Categories* (ch. 7) and in the *Metaphysics* (V, ch.15) is opaque and incomplete. Because of this fact, in the Late Antiquity and in the Middle Ages many authors tried to reformulate the doctrine of relatives. Wyclif 's attempt is one of the most interesting among those of the whole Middle Ages, as he very likely was the first medieval author able to work out a concept of relation conceived of as an accidental form which is in both the relatives at once, even though in different ways. Consequently his relation can be considered the ontological equivalent to our modern functions with two variables, or two-place predicates, whereas all the other authors of the Middle Ages had thought of the relations in terms of monadic functions. As a matter of fact, according to Wyclif, relation is different from quality and quantity, since it presupposes them just as what follows by nature presupposes what precedes. Moreover, quantity and quality are, in a certain way, absolute entities, but relation qua such is a sort of link between two things (see *De ente praedicamentali*, ch. 7, p. 61). Wyclif thinks that the items directly falling into any categorial field are simple accidental forms, therefore he distinguishes between relations (*relationes*) and relatives (*relativa* or *ad aliquid*) - these latter being the aggregates formed by a substance, a relation, and the foundation (*fundamentum*), of the relation. Accordingly, the relationship between relation and relatives is, for him, similar to the ones between quantity and what is quantified, and quality and what is qualified. The relation is the very cause of the nature of the aggregates (that is, the relatives) of which it is a constituent; yet, unlike the other accidental forms, relations do not directly inhere in their substrates, but are present in them only by means of other accidental forms, that Wyclif, following a well established tradition, calls 'foundations of the relation'. In his view, quantity and quality only can be the foundation of a categorial relation (*ibidem*, pp. 61-62).Thus, according to Wyclif's description, in the act of relating one substance to another four different constitutive elements can be singled out: (1) the relation itself (for instance, the form of similarity); (2) the foundation of the relation, that is, the absolute entity in virtue of which the relation at issue is present in the two substances correlated to each other (in this case, the form of whiteness which makes the two substances at issue similar to each other); (3) the subject of the relation (or its first extreme), that is, the aggregate compound of (*a*) the substance which denominatively receives the names of the relation (in our example, the substance which is similar to another, say Socrates) and (*b*) of the foundation of the relation ; (4) the second extreme (of the relation), that is, another aggregate compund of a substance and its own foundation, that the subject of the relation is connected with, (in our example, a second substance which is, in its turn, similar to the first one, say Plato). The *fundamentum* of the relation is the main component, since it (1) joins the relation to the underlying substances, (2) lets the relation link the subject to the object, and (3) transmits to the relation some of its properties. Even though relation depends for its existence on the foundation, its being is really distinct from it, as when the foundation fails the relation also fails, but not vice versa (*ibidem*, pp. 62-64 and 67). Some rather important conclusions about the nature and the ontological status of relations and relatives follow from these premisses: 1. relation is a truth (*veritas*) whose kind of reality is feebler than that of any other accident, as it depends upon the simultaneous existence of three different things: the two extremes (of the relation) and the foundation. 2. A relation can (indirectly) inhere in a substance without any change in the latter, but simply because of a change in another one. For example: given two things, one white and the other black, if the black thing becomes white, then, because of such a change, a new accident, that is, a relation of similarity, will inhere also in the first thing, apart from any other change in it. 3. All the true relatives ( propria relativa) are simultaneous by nature (see *ibidem*, p. 64), since the real cause of being a relative is relation, which at the same time (indirectly) inheres in two things, thereby making both ones relatives. Like Duns Scotus, Wyclif divides relations into transcendental and categorial relations (*ibidem* p. 61-62), and, moreover, like many of his predecessors and contemporaries, among the latter he contrasts real relatives (*relativa secundum esse*) with relatives of reason (*relativa rationis*), or linguistic relatives (*relativa secundum dici* - see *ibidem*, pp. 62-64). Wyclif defines real relatives as those aggregates (1) made up of a substance and (2) an absolute accidental form (quantity or quality), (3) whose reality consists in being correlated to something else. If one of these three conditions is not fulfilled, we will speak of relatives of reason (cf. *ibidem*, p. 63). In this way, Wyclif eliminates from the description of the relatives of reason any reference to our mind, and utilizes objective criteria only, based on the framework of reality itself. In fact he maintains that there are three kinds of relations of reason, each one characterized by the occurrence of at least one of these negative conditions: (1) one of the two extremes of the relation is not a substance with its foundation; (2) both the extremes of the relation are not substances; (3) there is no foundation for the relation, or it is not an absolute accident - that is, a quantity, or a quality (*ibidem*). The strategy which supports this choice is evident: Wyclif attempts to substitute references to mental activity by references to external reality. In other words, he seeks to reduce epistemology to ontology, in accordance with his realist program. ## 4. Theology ### 4.1 Divine ideas Wyclif's world is ultimately grounded on divine essence. Thus there is a close connection between any kind of *truth* and the divine ideas (cf. *Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 15, pp. 371-74; *De materia et forma*, chap. 2, pp. 170-76). Divine ideas play a threefold role in relation to God and creatures: they are (i) the specific essences of individual things themselves, considered according to their intelligible being in the mind of God; (ii) God's principles of cognition of creatures; and (iii) the eternal models of creatures. If we also take into account that in his opinion (iv) divine ideas are really the same as the divine essence and formally distinct from it, and (v) this distinction originates from their being efficient (con)causes in relation to the different kinds of creatures, we can easily realize why Wyclif's position on this matter leads to heretical consequences from the point of view of the Catholic theology: (i) metaphysical and theological necessitarianism; (ii) restriction of divine omnipotence; (iii) negation of the process of transubstantiation in the Eucharist. In fact, Wyclif defines ideas as the divine nature in action, since they are the means by which God creates all that is outside Himself. In this way, any distinction between the ideas as pure *rationes* and the ideas as *exemplaria*, stated by St. Thomas in his *Summa theologiae* (I, q. 15), is abolished. Furthermore, ideas are the constitutive principles of divine nature, essentially identical with it. Thus divine ideas become as necessary as the divine nature itself. On the other side, ideas are the first of the four levels of being proper to creatures. Indeed, since God could not help but create this Universe (as we shall see in Section 4.2), everything which is is necessary and so is a necessary object of God's volition. Thus, the three spheres of possible, existent, and necessary totally coincide. As a matter of fact, Wyclif, having defined necessary truths as those truths which cannot not be the case, (i) distinguishes between absolutely necessary truths and conditionally (or relatively - *secundum quid*) necessary truths, and (ii) tries to show how relative necessity is consistent with supreme contingence (*Logicae continuatio*, tr. 1, chap. 11, vol. 1, pp. 156-65). He thought that such distinctions enabled him to maintain simultaneously the necessity of all that happens and human freedom (cf. *Tractatus de universalibus*, ch. 14, pp. 333-47); and many times he affirms that it would be heretical to say that all things happen by *absolute* necessity; but his attempt failed in achieving its goal. According to him, absolutely necessary truths are such truths as (i) those of theology (like the real proposition that God exists), that are *per se* necessary and do not depend on something else; (ii) those of geometry, that neither can, nor ever could, nor ever will be able to be otherwise, even though they depend on something else (*est ab alio sed non potuit non esse*); and (iii) the past and present truths (like the real proposition that I have existed - *me fuisse*), that cannot be, but might have been otherwise (*per accidens necessarium, quia est necessarium quod potuit non esse*). On the contrary, relative necessity applies to those events that must follow certain conditions in order to be or happen - so that any contingent truth is relatively necessary if considered in relation to its conditions (*Logicae continuatio*, tr. 1, chap. 11, p. 157). In its turn, relative necessity is divided into antecedent, consequent, and concomitant. (i) A certain truth is an antecedent relative necessity when its existence causes the existence of another contingent truth (*antecedens ut causa contingentis, inferens posterius naturaliter*). An instance of such a necessity is the necessity of volition, as where my unconstrained will or the unconstrained will of God is the cause which necessitates something else (*ibid*., p, 158). (ii) A certain truth is a consequent relative necessity when its existence is caused by an antecedent (relative) necessity. And finally, (iii) a certain truth is a concomitant relative necessity when it merely accompanies another true event (*ibid*., p. 157). These features proper to the relative necessity are not opposites, and the same truth may be necessary in all the three ways (*ibid*., pp. 157-58). Wyclif insists that all three kinds of relative necessity are contingent truths in themselves (*ibid*., p. 158), yet he was unable to show how this is possible. He thought he had an explanation, but he was mistaken. In his *Tractatus de universalibus* (where he uses all these distinctions in order to try to solve the problem of the relationship between divine power and human freedom), he explicitly maintains that in relation to the foreknowledge of God every effect is necessary to come about (*Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 14, p. 333), and the Aristotelian principle that everything which is, when it is, necessarily is (the well known formulation of the diachronic contingence), applies also to what will be and has been (*ibid*., p. 334). Taking into account that God himself cannot begin or cease actually to know or will something, and thus He cannot change from knowing that *p* to knowing that not-*p* (where *p* is a given truth), nor from volition to non-volition or *vice* *versa* (*ibid*., p. 335; cf. also *De volucione Dei*, chap. 3, p. 149), the logical result is that in Wyclif's world nothing may happen purely contingently. It is true that Wyclif insists that even if God can never change from volition to non-volition, the fact that God wills *p* is in itself contingent, if *p* is not a theological truth (*De volucione Dei*, chap. 7, p. 192), but, like Bradwardine, he maintains that God's antecedent will is naturally prior to what He foresees. Given that God is immutable, and hence that the divine power is not affected by the passage of time, and divine ideas, within Wyclif's system, are as necessary as the divine essence itself, the logical consequence is that, despite Wyclif's claims of the contrary, the whole history of the world is determined from eternity. As a matter of fact, Wyclif's conditional (or relative) necessity is as necessary as his absolute necessity: given God, the world's entire history follows. ### 4.2 Divine omnipotence This doctrine of divine ideas and the connected theory of being had a significant result also for the notion of divine omnipotence. In the Middle Ages, one of the most important features of divine omnipotence was the capacity of annihilating, which was viewed as the necessary counterpart of the divine capacity of creating. Wyclif denies the thesis of an opposition between creation and annihilation, and explicitly denies that God can annihilate creatures. He argues that nothing is contrary to creation, since the act of creating is peculiar to God, and nothing is opposite or contrary to God. In fact, *absolute* non-being (the only "thing" that could be considered opposite to God) is something self-contradictory, and therefore logically impossible. Accordingly, there cannot be any action opposite to creation. The only possible kind of non-being admitted by Wyclif is corruption (*corruptio*), that is, the natural destruction of the actual existence in time of an object in the world (*Tractatus de universalibus*, chap. 13, pp. 302-3). On the other hand, according to Wyclif, annihilation, if possible, would be equivalent to the total destruction of all of a creature's levels of being (*ibid.*, p. 307), and thus would imply the following absurdities: 1. God could not annihilate any creature without destroying the whole world at once, since universal-being is the basic constitutive element of the second level of being (the *esse essentiae* or *esse in genere*) of each creature (*ibid.*, pp. 307-8). 2. Since annihilation would be nothing but an accident, and more precisely an action, it would be really different from both the acting subject (i.e. God) and the object of the action (i.e., the thing that would be annihilated). But any accident requires a substrate of inherence. In this case, it cannot be God. Thus, it must be the object of annihilation. Yet, because of its particular nature, if there is annihilation, its substrate of inherence cannot be, and therefore the annihilation itself cannot be, since no accident can exist without any substrate of inherence -- an apparently self-contradictory state of affairs (*ibid.*, pp. 310-11). 3. God could not annihilate any creature without annihilating Himself at the same time, because the first and most basic level of being of every creature is rooted in the divine essence itself (*ibid.*, pp. 313-14). The image of God Wyclif draws here is not the Christian image of the Lord of the universe, who freely creates by an act of His will and has absolute power and control over everything, but a variation of the Neoplatonic notion of the One. Wyclif's God is simply the supreme principle of the universe from which everything necessarily flows. Within Wyclif's system, creation is a form of emanation, as each creature is necessarily connected with the divine essence itself by means of its *esse ideale*. God has been deprived of the power of revocation (*ibid*., pp. 304-5), and the only action He can, or rather has to, perform is creation. Because of the necessary links between (i) the divine essence and the eternal mental being that every creature has in God and (ii) this first level of being of creatures and the remaining three, for God to think of creatures is already to create them. But God cannot help thinking of creatures, since to think of Himself is to think of His constitutive principles, that is, of the ideas of creatures. Therefore, God cannot help creating. Indeed, He could not help creating just this universe. Wyclif's rejection of the possibility of annihilation and the subsequent new notion of divine onnipotence shed light on his theory of universals, as they help us to appreciate the difference between his thesis of the identity between universals and individuals and the analogous thesis of moderate Realists. For these latter theses, this identity meant that *the* individuals are *in potentia* universal; for Wyclif it means that *the* individuals are *the* universals *qua* existing *in actu* -- that is, the individuals are the outcome of a process of production that is inscribed into the nature of general essences themselves, and through which general essences change from an incomplete type of subsistence as forms to a full existence as individuals. This position is consistent with (i) his theory of substance, where the main and basic composition of every substance, both individual and universal, is not the hylemorphic one, but the composition of potency and act (*De ente praedicamentali*, chap. 5, pp. 38-39), and (ii) a Neoplatonic reading of Aristotelian metaphysics, where universal substances, and not individual ones as the Stagirite had taught, are the main and fundamental kind of being (on Wyclif's doctrine of the divine omnipotence see A. D. Conti, "*Annihilatio* e divina onnipotenza nel *Tractatus de* *universalibus* di John Wyclif," in MT. Fumagalli Beonio Brocchieri & S. Simoneta 2003, pp.71-85. ### 4.3 The Eucharist Wyclif's heretical theses concerning the Eucharist are the logical consequence of the application of this philosophical apparatus to the problem of the real presence of the body of Christ in the consecrated host. According to Catholic doctrine, after consecration the body of Christ is really present in the host instead of the substance of the host itself, while the accidents of the host are the same as before. St. Thomas's explanation of this process, called 'transubstantiation', was that the substance of the bread (and wine) was changed into the body (and blood) of Christ, whereas its quantity, through which the substance of the bread received physical extension and the other accidental forms, was now the entity that kept the other accidental forms physically in being. Duns Scotus and Ockham, on the contrary, had claimed that after consecration the substance of the bread (and wine) was annihilated by God, while the accidents of the bread (and wine) remained the same as before because of an intervention of divine omnipotence. Wyclif rejects both solutions as well as the Catholic formulation of the dogma, since he could not accept the ideas of the destruction of a substance by God and of the existence of the accidents of a given singular substance without and apart from that singular substance itself -- two evident absurdities within the metaphyisical framework of his system of thought. As a consequence, Wyclif affirms the simultaneous presence in the Eucharist of the body of Crhist and of the substance of the bread (and wine), which continues to exist even after the consecration. According to him, transubstantiation is therefore a twofold process, natural and supernatural. There is natural transubstantiation when a substitution of one substantial form for another takes place, but the subject-matter remains the same. This is the case with water that becomes wine. There is supernatural transubstantiation when a miraculous transformation of the substantial entity at issue takes place. This was the case, for instance, with the incarnation of the second person of the Trinity, who is God and became man (*De apostasia*, p. 170). The Eucharist implies this second kind of transubstantiation, since the Eucharist, like Christ, has a dual nature: earthly and divine. According to its earthly nature the Eucharist is bread (and wine), but according to its divine nature it is the body of Christ, which is present in the host spiritually or in a habitudinal fashion, since it is in virtue and by means of faith only that it could be received (*De apostasia*, pp. 180 and 210; *De eucharistia*, pp. 17, 19, 51-52, and 230; for a description of the habitudinal presence, see the definition of the habitudinal predication above, Section 2.3 - on the links between his realism and his eucharistic doctrine see P. J. J. M. Bakker, "Realisme et remanence. La doctrine eucharistique de Jean Wyclif," in MT. Fumagalli Beonio Brocchieri & S. Simoneta 2003, pp. 87-112; see also Kenny 1985, pp. 68-90). ## 5. Religious and Political Thought ### 5.1 The Bible and the Church Wyclif conceives of Sacred Scripture as a direct emanation from God himself, and therefore as a timeless, unchanging, and archetypal truth independent of the present world and of the concrete material text by means of which it is manifested. As a consequence, in his *De veritate Sacrae Scripturae* (*On the Truth of Sacred Scripture* -- between late 1377 and the end of 1378) he tries to show that, despite appearences, the Bible is free from error and contradictions. The exegetic principle he adopts is the following: since the authority of Scripture is greater than our capacity of understanding, if some errors and/or inconsistencies are found in the Bible, there is something wrong with our interpretation. The Bible contains the whole truth and nothing but the truth, so that nothing can be added to it or subtracted from it. Every part of it has to be taken absolutely and without qualification (*De veritate Sacrae Scripturae*, vol. 1, pp. 1-2, 395, 399; vol. 2, pp. 99, 181-84). In attributing inerrancy to the Bible, Wyclif was following the traditional attitude towards it, but the way he viewed the book detached him from Catholic tradition, as he thought that his own metaphysical system was the necessary interpretative key for the correct understanding of Biblical truth. In fact, in the *Trialogus* (*Trialogue* -- between late 1382 and early 1383), where Wyclif gives us the conditions for achieving the true meaning of the Bible, they are the following: 1. knowledge of the nature and ontological status of universals; 2. knowledge of the peculiar nature of accidents as dependent in existence on their substantial substrates; 3. knowledge of past and future states of affairs (*praeteritiones* and *futuritiones*) as real in the present as past and future truths, not as things (*res*) that have been real in the past and will be real in the future (a thesis of his already claimed in the *De ente praedicamentali*, chap. 1, pp. 2 and 5; *Purgans errores circa veritates in communi*, chap. 1, pp. 1-2; chap. 3, pp. 10-11); 4. knowledge of the eternal existence of creatures in God at the level of intelligible being really identical with the divine essence itself; 5. knowledge of the perpetual existence of material essences (*Trialogus*, book 3, chap. 31, pp. 242-43). Only on the basis of this logical and metaphysical machinery is it possible to grasp the five different levels of reality of the Bible, which are at the same time: 1. the book of life mentioned in the *Apocalypse*; 2. the ideal being proper to the truths written in the book of life; 3. the truths that are to be believed as they are written in the book of life; 4. the truths that are to believed as they are written in the natural books that are men's souls; 5. all the artificial signs of the truth (*De veritate Sacrae Scripturae*, vol. 1, p. 109). This same approach, when applied to the Church, led Wyclif to fight against it in its contemporary state. (On Wyclif's ecclesiology see Leff 1967, pp. 516-46.) The starting point of Wyclif's reflection on the Church is the distinction between the heavenly and the earthly cities that St. Augustine draws in his *De civitate Dei*. In St. Augustine such a division is metaphorical, but Wyclif made it literal. So he claims that the Holy Catholic Church is the mystical and indivisible community of the saved, eternally bound together by the grace of predestination, while the foreknown, i.e. the damned, are eternally excluded from it (*De civili dominio*, vol. 1, p. 11). This community of the elect is really distinct from the various particular earthly churches (*ibid.*, p. 381). It is timeless and outside space, and therefore is not a physical entity; its being, like the actual being of any other universal, is wherever any of its members is (*De ecclesia*, p. 99). All its members always remain in grace, even if temporally in mortal sin (*ibid.*, p. 409), as conversely the damned remain in mortal sin, even if temporally in grace (*ibid.*, p. 139). The true Church is presently divided into three parts: the triumphant Church in heaven; the sleeping Church in purgatory; and the militant Church on earth (*ibid.*, p. 8). But the militant Church on earth cannot be identified with the visible church and its hierarchy. Even more, since we cannot know who are the elect, there is no reason for consenting to recognize and obey the authority of the visible church (see *De civili dominio*, vol. 1, p. 409; *De ecclesia*, pp. 71-2). Authority and dominion rely on God's law manifested by Sacred Scripture. As a consequence, obedience to any member of the hierarchy is to be subordinated to his fidelity to the precepts of the Bible (*De civili dominio*, vol. 2, p. 243; *De potestate papae* [*On the Power of the Pope* -- ca. 1379], p. 149; *De ecclesia*, p. 465). Faithfulness to the true Church can entail the necessity of rebelling against the visible church and its members, when their requests are in conflict with the teaching of Christ (*De civili dominio*, vol. 1, pp. 384, 392). In conclusion, since the visible church cannot help the believers gain salvation, which is fixed from eternity, and its authority depends on its fidelity to divine revelation, it cannot perform any of the functions traditionally attributed to it, and it therefore has no reason for its own existence. To be ordained a priest offers no certainty of divine approval and authority (*De ecclesia*, p. 577). Orthodoxy can only result from the application of right reason to the faith of the Bible (*De veritate Sacrae Scripturae*, vol. 1, p. 249). The Pope, bishops, abbots, and priests are expected to prove that they really belong to the Holy Catholic Church through their exemplary behavior; they should be poor and free from worldly concerns, and they should spend their time preaching and praying (*De ecclesia*, pp. 41, 89, 129). In particular, the Pope should not interfere in worldly matters, but should be an example of holiness. Believers are always allowed to doubt the clergy's legitimacy, which can be evaluated only on the basis of its consistency with the Evangelic rules (*ibid.*, pp. 43, 456). Unworthy priests forfeit their right to exercise authority and to hold property, and lay lords might deprive them of their benefices (*De civili dominio*, vol. 1, p. 353; vol. 3, pp. 326, 413; *De ecclesia*, p. 257). ### 5.2 Dominion As Leff remarked (Leff 1967, p. 546), the importance of Wyclif's teaching on dominion and grace has been exaggerated. His doctrine depends on Richard Fitzralph's theory, according to which the original lordship is independent of natural and civil circumstances (on Fitzralph's conception see Robson 1961, pp. 70-96), and is only a particular application of Wyclif's general view on election and damnation. In fact, the three main theses of the first book of his *De civili dominio* are the following: 1. a man in sin has no right to dominion; 2. a man who is in a state of grace possesses all the goods of the world; 3. as a consequence, there can be no dominion without grace as its formal cause (*De civili dominio*, vol. 1, p 1). Wyclif defines dominion as the right to exercise authority and, indirectly, to hold property. According to him, there are three kinds of possession: natural, civil, and evangelical. Natural possession is the simple possession of goods without any legal title. Civil possession is the possession of goods on the basis of some civil law. Evangelical possession requires, beyond civil possession, a state of grace in the legal owner. Thus God alone can confer evangelical possession (*ibid.*, p. 45). On the other hand, a man in a state of grace is lord of the visible universe, but on the condition that he shares his lordship with all the other men who are in a state of grace, as all men in a state of grace have the same rights. This ultimately means that all the goods of God should be in common, just as they were before the Fall. Private property was introduced as a result of sin. From this point of view it is also evident that Aristotle's criticisms against Plato are unsound, since Platonic communism is correct in essence (*ibid.*, pp. 96 ff.). The purpose of civil law is to preserve the necessities of life (*ibid.*, pp. 128-29). The best form of government is monarchy. Kings must be obeyed and have taxes paid to them, even if they become tyrants, since they are God's vicars that He alone can depose -- so that only secular lordship is justified in the world (*ibid.*, p. 201).
wyclif-political
## 1. Wyclif's Later Works Government and the relation of divine justice to human law, both secular and ecclesiastical, figure as occasional themes throughout the treatises of the *Summa de Ente*. After receiving his doctorate in theology in 1373, his attention began to focus more completely on these topics, and his realism continued to undergird his thought at least through 1381, during which period he wrote the treatises that make up the second of his great *Summae*, the *Summa Theologie*. In late 1373, he began *De Dominio Divino*, which serves as bridge from the later, formal theological treatises of the *Summa de Ente* to the political, social, and ecclesiological subject matter of the *Summa Theologie*. He began royal service during this period, participating in an embassy to Bruges for negotiations with papal envoys in 1374. Wyclif remained in the service of John of Gaunt for the rest of his life; the Duke protected him from the formal prosecution prompted by five bulls of papal condemnation in 1377. After being condemned for his views on the Eucharist at Oxford in 1381, Wyclif withdrew to Lutterworth, where he remained until his death in December 1384. Though still protected by John of Gaunt, he was no longer in active service after 1379. During these tumultuous years, Wyclif wrote the ten treatises of the *Summa Theologie*: four on just human government, two on the structure and government of the church, one on scriptural hermeneutics, and three on specific problems afflicting the Church. Our interest lies in *De Mandatis Divinis* (1375-76), *De Statu Innocencie* (1376), and *De Civili Dominio* (1375-76), where he provides the theological foundation for the radical transformation of the church he prescribes in *De Ecclesia* (1378-79) *De Potestate Pape* (1379), and *De Officio Regis* (1379). Towards the end of his life, Wyclif summarized his entire theological vision in *Trialogus* (1382-83), reiterating the connections between his earlier philosophical works and later political treatises in a three-way dialogue written in language that would appeal to members of the royal court. ## 2. *Dominium* in Political Thought Before Wyclif *Dominium* and its generally accepted translation, 'lordship', suggest the sovereignty exercised by one individual over another, but Roman law allowed for complexity in distinguishing between property ownership, its primary referent, and jurisdiction, governance, and political power. When twelfth-century canon lawyers resurrected Roman law as the foundation for the ascendant papal monarchy, it was common to distinguish between jurisdictive authority, secular power, and the use and possession of private property.[1] By the beginning of the fourteenth century, *dominium* largely connoted property ownership, though this usually entailed jurisdictive authority. Most political theorists agreed with Thomas Aquinas in saying that a civil lord who supposed that his jurisdictive authority arose from property ownership rather than from a constitution would be a tyrant (*Summa Theologiae* IaIIae, Q.56, a.5; Q.58, a.2). Given that the legal use of *dominium* referred to property ownership and not to the authority to govern, it seems odd that Wyclif used the term to do so much more. The reason may be found in the connection of Augustinian theology to theories of the justice of property ownership. As the papal monarchy developed, its theorists, such as Giles of Rome, found it useful to identify all earthly justice, including just property ownership, with the source of justice in creation. ### 2.1 Augustine Augustine's *De Civitate Dei* was the basis for relating property ownership and secular justice to divine authority. Here the division between two classes of men is clear: some are members of the City of Man, motivated by love of self, while others are motivated by the love of God and a contempt for self, placing them in the City of God.[2] There is really only one true Lord in creation. Mastery of one man over another is the result of Original Sin and is therefore unnatural except in the case of paternity, which is founded on parental love for a child. Among members of the City of God, the relation of prince and subject is not political and does not entail the sort of mastery we see in the City of Man, but rather involves service and sacrifice, as exemplified by the parent/child relationship. Property ownership has been united to mastery in the City of Man because of Original Sin, whereby man turned away from God in the mistaken belief that he could make claims of exclusive ownership on created beings. This is not to say that Augustine thought that all private property relations are wrong; indeed, he is famous for having argued that all things belong to the just (*De Civitate Dei* 14, ch. 28). But people who own things are not *de facto* just. Those for whom ownership is not an end in itself but a means by which to do God's will are freed from the bondage of selfishness imposed by the Fall. They easily recognize the truth of the dictum that one should abstain from the possession of private things, or if one cannot do so, then at least from the love of property (*Enarratio in Psalmam* 132, ch.4). Augustine's thought on the relation of ownership to political authority is open to interpretation. One can easily read him as arguing that the Church, as the Body of Christ and earthly instantiation of the City of God, can best exemplify loving lord/subject relations through its ecclesiastical structure, thereby justifying a top-down papal monarchy. Likewise, one can read him as having so separated secular political authority from the rule of love as to make political and ecclesiastical jurisdictive authority utterly distinct. Again, one could interpret Augustine's 'all things belong to the just' as meaning that the Church is the arbiter of all property ownership in virtue of being the Body of Christ and seat of all created justice, or one could argue that the Church should abandon all claims to property ownership, just as the Apostles abstained from the possession of private property. This ambiguity in interpretation was the source of some of the competing theories that influenced Wyclif's position. ### 2.2 Giles of Rome During the conflict between Philip IV of France and Pope Boniface VIII in 1301, Giles of Rome wrote *De Ecclesiastica Potestate*, establishing the absolute secular superiority of the papacy. Giles' master Boniface VIII was responsible for the two famous Bulls, *Clericos laicos* (1296), which forbade clergy to give up property without papal approval, and *Unam sanctam* (1302), which declared that secular power is in the service of, and subject to, papal authority. *De Ecclesiastica Potestate* is an articulation of the concept of power underlying these two Bulls and arising from one of the two interpretations of Augustine described above. In it, Giles describes all power "spiritual and secular" as rooted in the papacy, likening its structure to a papal river from which smaller, secular streams branch out. The source of this river, he continues, is the sea, which is God: "God is a kind of font and a kind of sea of force and power, from which sea all forces and all powers are derived like streams."[3] Not only is secular power reliant on papal authority; all property ownership, insofar as it is just, is similarly dependent on an ecclesiastical foundation. The key element in just secular power and property ownership, he continues, is grace: without God's will directly moving in creation through the sacraments of the Church, power and ownership are empty claims, devoid of justice. Although Giles did not explicitly call the combination of ownership and temporal power *dominium*, his uniting the two in a consistent, Augustinian fashion was sufficient for the next generation of Augustinian theorists. ### 2.3 The Franciscans and Their Opponents Thirty years earlier, in Bonaventure's *Apologia pauperum* of 1269, the Franciscans had defined any property ownership, communal or individual, as inimical to the ideals of their Order. The Fall from paradise and the introduction of selfishness to human nature makes property ownership of any type, private or communal, an abberation. For the Franciscans, "all things belong to the just" only in the sense that "belonging" entails non-exclusive sharing (*usus pauper*), not ownership. Within three decades, the Franciscans were divided on this issue: one party, the Spirituals, demanded that the friars adopt *usus pauper* as their ideal of spiritual perfection, while the other, the Conventuals, argued for a more lenient interpretation of the Rule. The Spirituals, under the guidance of the philosopher John Peter Olivi and his follower Ubertino de Casale, outnumbered the Conventuals by century's end, and had become sufficiently vocal to attract the attention of the pope.[4] John XXII was deeply suspicious of the Spiritual Franciscans' arguments, perhaps fearing a reappearance of the communitarian Waldensian heresy. Private ownership, John argued, was not the result of Original Sin, but a gift from God that Adam enjoyed in Paradise and which the blessed still can enjoy, secure in the knowledge that their ownership is sanctioned by God's *dominium*. This argument was to have notable consequences. John's eventual controversy with the Spiritual's champion, William Ockham, led to the first important use of the concept of natural right. But for our analysis, the important thing is that *iurisdictio* and *proprietas* were united in the concept of *dominium*. Wyclif would make use of the Franciscans' arguments for apostolic poverty, as well as of John XXII's idea that divine *dominium* provides the basis for all human *dominium*, though in a way that would certainly have displeased both parties.[5] By the 1350s, opponents of the Franciscans had broadened their range of criticism to question the legitimacy of the Order itself. Richard Fitzralph, (d. 1360) wrote *De Pauperie Salvatoris*, a sustained examination of the Franciscans' claim to function without supervision by diocesan bishop in which he argues that if the friars rely on the justice of the owners of what they use, they are bound by the same laws that bind the owners. Thus, if the owners of what the friars use are ecclesiastical, it follows that the friars must obey ecclesiastical authority.[6] Fitzralph's position is important here because it argues that grace alone is the justification for any instance of *dominium* in creation, and that all just *dominium* ultimately relies on God's *dominium*. Both serve as cornerstones of Wyclif's position. God's *dominium* is a natural consequence of the act of creating, and with it comes divine governance and conservation of created being. The rational beings in creation, angels and human beings, enjoy the loan of elements of God's created universe, but this is not a divine abdication of ultimate authority since everything is still directly subject to divine *dominium*. When the nature of the *dominium* lent to Adam changed with the Fall, the love defining our natural *dominium* was affected, but not eradicated. Men devised political *dominium* to regulate property relations, and although sin keeps them from recognizing the borrowed nature of any *dominium*, it does not preclude there being grace-justified property ownership. In some cases, God infuses the artificial property-relations that we call *dominium* with sufficient grace to make them generally equivalent to prelapsarian *dominium*. These grace-favored cases of human dominium do not replicate the authority of God's *dominium*, but can exhibit the love that characterizes it. Fitzralph's expression of the Augustinian papal position makes grace the deciding factor in ownership relations and ultimately in political authority, both of which had become nested in the term *dominium*. Wyclif's interpretation of the Augustinian position would stretch past arguments about papal authority and the friars, even past arguments between popes and kings, to stir the very nature of the church as Christ's earthly body. All of this begins, he would argue, with an understanding of God's *dominium* as the causal exemplar of created lordship. ## 3. Divine *Dominium*: Creating, Lending, and Grace The relation of universal to particular defines Wyclif's conception of how God's *dominium* causes all instances of *dominium* in creation. Divine *dominium* is "the standard prior to and presupposition of all other *dominium*; if a creature has *dominium* over anything, God already has *dominium* over it, so any created dominium follows upon divine *dominium*" (*De Dominio Divino* I, ch. 3, p.16.18-22). This relation exceeds mere exemplarity, where human *dominium* only imitates God's *dominium* without divine causal determination. God's *dominium* has causal efficacy over all instances of human mastery such that no true created *dominium* is possible without direct participation in and constant reliance upon God's *dominium*. The instrument through which divine *dominium* moves is grace, which instills in human rulers an essential love defining their every ruling action. Thus, every case of just human *dominium* entails a constant reliance upon grace as the hallmark of its being an instantiation of God's universal *dominium*. God's *dominium* has six aspects, three identifiable with lordship's ruling element (creation, sustenance, and governance), and three that define lordship's proprietary nature (giving, receiving, and lending) (*De Dominio Divino* III, ch. 1, p.198.9).7 The necessary precondition for an act of *dominium* is creation, of which no created being is capable. This makes God's *dominium* the only true instance of *dominium* and the source of all created instances of *dominium*. Because the Divine Ideas and their created correlates, the universals, are ontologically prior to particular created beings, God's *dominium* over universals is prior to His *dominium* over particulars. This means that God creates, sustains, and governs the human species prior to ruling over -- and knowing -- individual people. This led to questions about determinism that served as a starting point for many refutations of Wyclif's theology. The second set of acts that define *dominium* -- giving, receiving, and lending -- provides the foundation for Wyclif's argument that all created *dominium* necessarily requires grace. God's giving of the divine essence in creating is the truest form of giving because God is giving of Himself through Himself, which no created being can do. Nor can any created being receive as God receives; God truly receives only from Himself through His giving. God gives up nothing in His giving, and acquires nothing in His receiving; creation is God's self-expression, an act in which the divine essence is neither decreased nor increased. The crucial act from the created standpoint is God's lending, for here there is real interaction between Lord and subjects. What human beings as conscious participants in God's lending relation can claim as their own is lent to them by divine authority, which they enjoy through grace. It is easy to confuse giving with lending because a lord who has only been "lent" a gift of God for use during his lifetime appears to have been "given" that gift. God's giving is communicative, not translative. For us, most giving is translative in that it involves the giver's surrender of every connection to the gift, making it natural for us to suppose that God renounces His authority over what He gives us. In fact, God's giving is communicative, which does not involve surrender of the gift. Because all that God gives to creation will ultimately return to Him, it makes more sense to speak of God's giving as lending. With any instance of lending, Wyclif explains, the lender seeks assurance that the borrower truly deserves what is to be lent. Human desert of the *dominium* they are lent is a matter of some complexity involving examination of the theological concept of grace. When a temporal lord lends his subject according to the subject's worthiness, the subject's merit is commensurable with the lord's, and the mutual agreement defining the loan can be made according to the respective merit of each party. The merit that allows the subject desert of consideration for the loan is "*condigna*", i.e., grounded in the *dignitas* shared by lender and subject. Condign merit implies that the meritorious truly deserve the reward, requiring the giver to give it to the merited as something due, as when an olympic athelete earns a gold medal by besting all her opponents. Such a loan is impossible between Creator and creature, because there is no way of placing a creature's merit on the same scale as God's perfect nature; all the creature has, including its worth, is from God, whereas God's perfection is per se. There is no way in which a creature can be considered to deserve anything from God in such a relation. Congruent merit obtains when the meritorious does not have the power to require anything of the giver. In instances of congruent merit, the goodness of the act does not require the giver to reward the agent, though it does provide sufficient cause for the reward to be given, as when one receives an Academy Award: although many of the audience members may deserve an Oscar, the winner receives it because something about her performance is somehow pleasing to the Academy. Still, Wyclif holds that "It is the invariable law of God that nobody is awarded blessedness unless they first deserve it" (*De Dominio Divino* III, ch. 4, p.229.18). We can move our wills to the good, and from this, Wyclif says, grace may -- but need not -- follow. Thus, we merit congruently thanks to God's generosity towards a will in accord with His own. In effect, God lends merit. Wyclif's theology of grace is the key to understanding how his theory of human *dominium* relates to divine *dominium*, its causal paradigm. Man's lordship is at once ownership and jurisdictive mastery, but when a human lord governs, or gives, or receives, or lends, these acts are only just insofar as the lord recognizes that his authority is that of a steward: "Any rational creature is only improperly called a lord, and is rather a minister or steward of the supreme Lord, and whatever he has to distribute, he has purely by grace" ([*De Dominio Divino* III, ch. 6, p.250.25-29). The essential characteristic of every instance of human *dominium* is the grace God lends to the individual lord, which itself is grounded in the grace of the Holy Spirit. The human lord appears to have proprietary and juristictive authority by virtue of his own excellence, but this is really only an instantiation of divine *dominium*, a grace-realized agent of God's lordship. This makes the human lord both master and servant; from the divine perspective, the lord is God's servant, but from the viewpoint of the subject, he is master. Wyclif is tireless in his emphasis on the illusory nature of this mastery; grace allows the human lord to recognize that he is, in fact, the servant of his subjects, ministering to them as a nurturing steward, not lording over them as would a powerful sovereign. ### 3.1 Natural *Dominium* *De Civili Dominio* begins with the motto, "Civil justice presupposes divine justice; civil *dominium* presupposes natural *dominium*." Man's *dominium* is threefold -- natural, civil, and evangelical -- but comprehensible as an instantiation of the justice of God's *dominium*. As he moved into his general analysis of human *dominium*, Wyclif's thoughts turned to the most fundamental instance of God's loving governance, the Scriptural commandments. The foundation of all that is right (*ius*) in creation, he explains, is divine justice (*iustitia*), so we cannot begin to understand right and wrong in creation without understanding God's uncreated right. This was a significant departure from the Aristotelian position that unaided human reason is capable of justice, and Wyclif explicitly rejects any conception of justice that does not rely on uncreated right.[8] The laws of Scripture are the purest expression of uncreated right available to human eyes, he explains, and are most clearly expressed in the Ten Commandments of Exodus 20, and again in the two greatest commandments of Matthew 22: 37-40. Wyclif's analysis of Christ's law of love and of the Ten Commandments proceeds directly from his disquisition on the relation of earthly justice to eternal right in *De Mandatis Divinis*. That Wyclif uses the same title Robert Grosseteste had used in his analysis of the decalogue is no accident; Wyclif's debt to Grosseteste's conceptions of sin, love of God, idolatry, and the substance of true faith is obvious throughout the treatise. In *De Statu Innocencie*, the innocence into which we were created before the Fall, he says, is the optimal condition for any rational being. In our prelapsarian state, our wills would have been in perfect concord with the divine will, so that all human action would be just, effortlessly aligned with the natural order of creation. In this condition, there would be no need for civil or criminal law, since we understood what is right naturally. This denial of the need for human law is of special import, for Wyclif later argues that the evangelical lord, or priest, as heir of Christ's restoration of the possibility of natural *dominium*, should never be concerned with such matters. In such a state, private property ownership was unknown. The natural *dominium* described in Genesis 1:26 is characterized by lack of selfishness, ownership, or any distinction between 'mine' and 'thine'. The true sense of Augustine's "All things belong to the just" is most fully apparent in the prelapsarian natural disposition to share in the use of creation while acting as faithful steward to its perfect lord. The Fall was brought about by the first sin, which Wyclif characterizes as a privation of God's right in man's soul. We are left with wills prone to value the physical, material world above spiritual concerns, and the unavoidable result is private property ownership. We no longer understand a given created good as a gift on loan from God, but can only see it in terms of our own self-interest, and the unfortunate result is civil *dominium*, an enslavement to material goods. ## 4. Types of Human *Dominium* Wyclif's definition of civil *dominium* as "proprietary lordship in a *viator* over the goods of fortune fully according to human law" is centered not on legislative authority, but on the private property ownership enjoyed by the *viator*, or wayfarer, along life's path (*De Civili Dominio* III ch. 11, p.178.9-17).[9] This is because all civil *dominium* is based on the use of goods owned, which is the basis for all postlapsarian conceptions of justice (recall that for Wyclif, only God truly owns created things because creating a thing is necessary for owning it; hence, human beings are only lent created things and can use them justly, or unjustly in case they appropriate them for themselves). Before the Fall, our use of created goods was communal, unencumbered by the complexity that follows upon selfishness. But now, Wyclif explains, there are three types of use: that directly consequent upon civil ownership, civil use without ownership, and evangelical use. The first two are natural results of the Fall, and the third is the result of Christ's Incarnation. Before the Incarnation, civil ownership and civil use were grounded in man-made laws designed primarily to regulate property ownership. These legal systems tended to have two general structures: they were either monarchies, as in most cases, or else they were aristocratic polities. The harmony of the aristocratic polity is certainly preferable because it most resembles the state enjoyed before the Fall; the benevolent aristocracy, as evidenced in the time of the Biblical judges, would foster the contemplative life, communalism, and an absence of corruptible governmental apparatus. The most common species of civil *dominium* is monarchy, in which a chief executive power holds ultimate legislative authority. This centralized authority in one man is necessary to implement order; there is no real possibility that the many are capable of ruling on behalf of the many, given the prevalence of sin. The point of civil *dominium* is not, as with Aristotle, the sustenance of individual virtuous activity. Civil *dominium* is a phenomenon based on Original Sin, and is therefore unlikely to produce justice per se. If the government of Caesar is occasionally just, it is because it has accidentally realized divine justice. But if civil *dominium* that is not grounded directly in divine *dominium* is incapable of sustained just governance, and if natural *dominium* is the instantiation of divine *dominium* for which man was created, how can any talk of just civil *dominium* be possible? To return to the opening dictum of *De Civili Dominio*, if natural *dominium* is free from private property ownership, how can civil *dominium* rely upon it in any way? Before resolving this problem, we will need to address evangelical *dominium* as yet another factor in Wyclif's conception of man's postlapsarian state. ### 4.1 Evangelical *Dominium* Christ restores the possibility of gaining our lost natural *dominium* both through His apostolic poverty and His redemptive sacrifice as described in Holy Scripture. Because of Christ's sinless nature, He was the first man since Adam capable of exhibiting the purity of natural *dominium*. This Christ shared with His disciples, who were able to renounce all exclusive claims to created goods in a recreation of the communal *caritas* lost in the Fall (*De Civili Dominio* III, 4, p. 51.17-24). This poverty is not simply the state of not owning things; one can live sinfully as easily in squalor as one can in luxury. The apostolic poverty of the early Church is a spiritual state, not an economic rejection of civil *dominium*. The similarity between Wyclif's conception of spiritual poverty as the ideal state for Christians and the Franciscan ideal is noteworthy. Wyclif seems to make a case similar to the Spiritual Franciscans: Christ's life was exemplary for all Christians and Christ lived in apostolic poverty; therefore, all Christians ought follow His example, or at the least have that option open to them. Wyclif's consonance with the Franciscan tradition is also suggested in his use of Bonaventure's definition of apostolic poverty in the third book of *De Civili Dominio*, but Wyclif's motives are distinctly different from the Friars' (*De Civili Dominio* III, 8, pp. 119-120). While the Franciscans argued that their rule allowed them to regain the ownership-free purity enjoyed by the early Apostolic church, Wyclif contended that Christ's redemptive sacrifice enabled all Christians to regain natural *dominium* itself, not just its purity. This suggested that the Franciscan life was a pale imitation of true Christianity, which Wyclif's Franciscan colleagues were quick to point out. One of the first critics of Wyclif's *dominium* thought was William Woodford, O.F.M., who argued that Wyclif had gone too far in equating apostolic, spiritual poverty with prelapsarian purity. The extensive third book of *De Civili Dominio* is Wyclif's response to Franciscan critics like Woodford, and in which lie the seeds of the antifraternalism that would characterize his later writings. Wyclif describes apostolic poverty as a mode of having with love, comprehensible in terms of the individual's use of a thing for the greatest spiritual benefit. God alone can bring about the love instantiating divine *dominium*, making grace necessary for apostolic poverty. Because the church is founded not on the materially-based laws of man, but on the spiritually-grounded *lex Christi*, it must be absolutely free of property ownership, the better to realize the spiritual purity required by apostolic poverty. Any material riches that the church comes upon as "goods of fortune" must be distributed as alms for the poor, following the practice of Christ and the disciples, and the apostolic church. This is the ideal to which the Church must aspire through the example of Christ, and some of the harshest invective in Wyclif's prose is directed against the Church's refusal to return to this apostolic state. The turning point in Church history was the Donation of Constantine, on the basis of which the Church claimed to have the civil *dominium* of a Caesar. Wyclif was vigorous in his condemnation of the Donation, and would likely have been pleased had he lived into the early fifteenth century, when Nicholas of Cusa argued persuasively that the document was a ninth-century forgery. ### 4.2 Civil *Dominium* Given the deleterious influence civil *dominium* has had on the evangelical *dominium* of Christ's law, it is difficult to imagine how Wyclif would set aside some civil lords as capable of instantiating divine justice. But apostolic poverty is not identical with an absence of property ownership; it is having with love. While the clergy as spiritual lords ought to follow Christ's example of material poverty, it does not follow that all ownership precludes love. God can certainly bestow grace on those whom He wills to be stewards of created goods. Wyclif envisions the just civil lord or king as the means by which the Church is relieved of its accumulated burden of property ownership. So long as the Church exists in postlapsarian society, it must be protected from thieves, heresy, and infidels. Certainly no evangelical lord ought to be concerned with such matters, given their higher responsibility for the welfare of Christian souls. As a result, the Church needs a guardian to ward off enemies while caring for its own weel-being and administering alms to the poor. This allows Wyclif to describe just, grace-favored civil *dominium* as different in kind from the civil lordship predicated on materialistic human concerns: "It is right for God to have two vicars in His church, namely a king in temporal affairs, and a priest in spiritual. The king should strongly check rebellion, as did God in the Old Testament, while priests ought minister the precepts mildly, as did Christ, who was at once priest and king." When he raises conventional topics in political thought, like the particulars of just rule, the responsibilities of royal councillors to their king, the nature of just war, and royal jurisdiction in commerce, his advice is priestly: "[A] lord ought not treat his subjects in a way other than he would rationally wish to be treated in similar circumstances; the Christian lord should not desire subjects for love of dominating, but for the correction and spiritual improvement of his subjects, and so to the efficacy of the church" (*De Officio Regis* ch. 1, p. 13.4-8). The king ought provide few and just laws wisely and accurately administered, and live subject to these laws, since just law is more necessary for the community than the king. Also, the king should strive to protect the lower classes' claims on temporal goods in the interests of social order, for "nothing is more destructive in a kingdom in its political life than immoderately to deprive the lower classes of the goods of fortune" (*De Officio Regis* ch. 5, p. 96.9-27).[10] On occasion he discusses the king's need of reliable councillors, generally when discussing the king's need for sacerdotal advice in directing church reform, but he never mentions Parliament as a significant aspect of civil rule. The most immediate concern of a civil lord living in an age when the Church is being poisoned by avarice should be the radical divestment of all ecclesiastical ownership. Wyclif is tireless in arguing for the king's right to take all land and goods, and indeed, even the buildings themselves, away from the Church. Should the clergy protest against royal divestment, threatening the king with excommunication or interdict, the king should proceed as a physician applies his lancet to an infected boil. No grace-favored civil lord will be disposed to save up the divested goods of the Church for his own enrichment, despite the obvious temptation. He will distribute the Church's ill-gotten lands and goods to the people. This, Wyclif explains, will be his continued responsibility even after the Church has been purged, for he is the Church's custodian as well as its protector. The hereditary succession by which civil lordship passes from father to son is a problem for Wyclif. People cannot inherit the grace needed to ensure just ownership and jurisdiction. Primogeniture imperils grace-founded civil lordship, making lords prone to rule on behalf of their own familial interests rather than in the interests of their subjects. The only means by which Wyclif can envision hereditary succession operating is through spiritual filiation, in which a civil lord instructs a worthy successor. He suggests adoption as the basis for the spiritual primogeniture by which lordship is passed on, which would be preferable to general election, for Wyclif is clear about the impossibility of widespread recognition of grace in a potential civil lord: "It does not follow, if all the people want Peter to be their civil lord, that therefore it is just" (*De Civili Dominio* I, 18, p. 130.6). Central to his ecclesiology is the impossibility of determining the presence of grace in another's soul, which militates against identifying members of the elect with certainty, and therefore against excommunicating any of them from the Church, as well as ruling out popular election as a means of instituting just civil *dominium*. Grants in perpetuity, commonly employed by civil lords to guarantee the ongoing obligation of subjects in return for a gift of land or political authority, are as impossible as hereditary inheritance. A lord might reward someone with a grant while acting as God's steward, but he certainly cannot thereby make his subject's progeny *deserve* the gift. ### 4.3 Tyranny History is rich with examples of kings who, wittingly or unwittingly, lose sight of their ministerial position and wield secular authority in their own interests, cruelly using the land and church for their own gain. Such tyrants cause Wyclif some problems, for in many cases it is difficult for the subjects to determine whether their lord is acting viciously as a crowned brigand, or sternly, as a physician purging a patient. For the same reason that Wyclif denies the suitability of popular elections, he is cautious regarding tyranny: it is impossible for human minds to gauge the absence of grace in another. What may look like cruel persecution of a subject may in fact be just punishment, while what may appear to be benign, permissive rule may in fact be the lassitude of misrule. Certainly no priest is in a position to assess the justice of a civil lord, given his dedication to apostolic ideals foreign to civil *dominium*. In some cases, Wyclif advises that one must suffer tyrannical rule as a divine punishment, particularly when a king deprives His subjects of material wealth. In other cases, especially when a civil lord fosters ecclesiastical decay by not persecuting heretics or regulating the Church's goods, Wyclif suggests that resistance to tyranny may be justifiable: better to focus on the greater danger of priestly tyranny; after all, a tyrannical civil lord can only do damage to one's material well-being, but a tyrannical priest can endanger one's eternal soul. The guardian against priestly tyranny must be the civil lord, whose responsibility to the Church requires him to monitor the clergy's execution of its spiritual duties. Those who argue that a civil lord has no business interfering with spiritual concerns overlook the fundamental relation holding between just civil law and divine law: because the civil lord's responsibility is to God, his first concern must be to ensure that nothing will impede obedience to divine law. The canon law that has built up over the centuries like barnacles on a ship's hull is held up as the means by which the Church regulates spiritual affairs, but this, Wyclif explains, is a superfluous creation of priests, ultimately hindering the Church by introducing material structure to what should be a purely spiritual enterprise. The king uses bishops, an office justly instituted by the early church, to monitor the spiritual offices of priests to counteract problems like simony, pluralism, absenteeism, and heresy. These bishops ought also to act as royal theological advisors, helping the civil lord to understand how Christ's law is best implemented in his own legislation. Just as a civil lord is God's steward and a servant to his subjects, a bishop is not superior to the laity or the priests, but a steward whose responsibility is to God and the divine law, which ordains subservience to the grace-favored civil lord. Wyclif continued to argue for the centrality of episcopal office throughout his life, despite his own troubles with the Bishop of London and the Archbishop of Canterbury.
xenocrates
## 1. Metaphysics Most of what we can reconstruct about Xenocrates pertains to his metaphysics. We do this largely by identifying views of his that appear in Aristotle's criticisms of the metaphysical views of his predecessors and contemporaries, and chaining together with these other texts that can plausibly be taken as dealing with his views. But there are a few sources other than Aristotle. One of them is Proclus, who says, commenting on the *Parmenides* (Cousin 1864, 888.11-19, 36-38; fr. 30H, 94IP): > > But to the ideas both belonged: both to be intelligible and {to be} > unchanging in substance, 'mounted on a holy pedestal', > that is, on pure mind, being such as to complete the things that are > in potentiality and being causes that give them their form; whence > {Plato} going up to these principles makes the whole of coming-to-be > dependent on them, just as Xenocrates says, positing that the idea is > a paradigmatic cause of the {things} that are always constituted > according to nature ... . Xenocrates, then, wrote down this > definition of the idea as in conformity with the founder, positing it > as a separate and divine cause; ... > 'The founder' is Plato. The phrase 'mounted on a holy pedestal' comes from Plato, *Phaedrus* 254b7, where the soul has been likened to a charioteer who sees the Forms of the beautiful and temperance so mounted. Some of the phrasing is no doubt neoplatonist rather than Xenocratean, but the formulation, 'the idea is a paradigmatic cause', seems to be, as Proclus says, Xenocrates' attempt to capture Plato's intent: see here Plato, *Parmenides* 132d. There is disagreement over the rest of the formulation Proclus attributes to Xenocrates: in speaking of 'the things that are always constituted according to nature', did Xenocrates intend to rule out forms for individuals, which are transitory, and for artefacts, which are not constituted according to nature? This is the way Proclus goes on to interpret Xenocrates, and it is hard to see how to get around that, although attempts have been made (see Cherniss 1944 [1962], 256). But there is indirect confirmation of Proclus' interpretation, at least where artefacts are concerned, from Clement of Alexandria, who tells us (in *Stromateis* II 5) that Xenocrates claimed that knowledge of the intelligible substance is theoretical as opposed to practical 'judgment'; at that rate, carpenters are not contemplating forms when they make beds and shuttles, despite what is said by Plato in *Republic* X 596b and *Cratylus* 389a-b, and (if it is by Plato) *Letter vii* 342d. But it should be noted that the rejection of forms for artefacts is in agreement with what Aristotle has to say about Plato and Platonists in *Metaphysics* I 9. 991b6-7, XII 3. 1070a13-19, and in the fragmentary remains of *On Ideas* in Alexander (see esp. Hayduck 1891, 79.23-24, 80.6). Likewise the rejection of forms for individuals squares with Aristotle's attack on the 'argument from thinking' (*Metaphysics* I 9. 990b14-15 = XIII 4. 1079a10-11, supplemented by Alexander, Hayduck 1891, 81.25-82.7): if every object of thought is a form, then there are forms also "for the perishables" (990b14 = 1079b10) or "for the particulars and perishables, such as Socrates, Plato" (Alexander, Hayduck 1891, 82.2-3). The version of the Theory of Forms associated with Xenocrates is that which Aristotle ascribes to the later Plato (see *Metaphysics* XIII 4. 1078b10-12 for the qualification 'later'), in which the Forms are 'generated' and are, in the first instance, numbers. Xenocrates operated, in parallel with Speusippus and Plato (as Aristotle reports Plato), with a scheme in which two principles--the One and something called any or all of 'the everflowing', 'plurality' (Aetius i 3. 23), or 'the Indefinite Dyad' (Theophrastus, *Metaphysics* vi)--generate these form-numbers, and then, in turn, lines, planes, solids, and perceptible things. The talk of generation Xenocrates reinterpreted as a mere pedagogical device; we hear about this technique from Aristotle, *De caelo* I 10. 279b32-280a2, and Simplicius' commentary ad loc. (Heiberg 1893, 303.33-34) names Xenocrates in this connection, as does Plutarch (*De animae procreatione in Timaeo* 3. 1013a-b, Cherniss 1976, 168-171). Here it is a device for interpreting the creation story in the *Timaeus*; that Xenocrates also applied it to the generation of the formal numbers we learn from Aristotle, *Metaphysics* XIV 4. 1091a28-29 and the commentary on that passage in pseudo-Alexander (Hayduck 1891, 819.37-820.3). In trying to understand what Aristotle tells us about formal numbers, it is necessary to bear in mind the fundamental distinction he draws between formal numbers and mathematical numbers: both are, according to Aristotle, composed of units, but formal numbers are composed of very strange units, such that those in one formal number cannot be combined with those in any other. The units of which mathematical numbers are composed can be added and subtracted freely. (See here *Metaphysics* XIII 6. 1080a15-b4.) And furthermore there is only one formal number for each of the numbers 2, 3, 4, etc., where there are indefinitely many instances of each among the mathematical numbers. (See here *Metaphysics* I 6. 987b14-18.) The mathematical numbers are the ones mathematicians work with, e.g. in performing arithmetical operations, and that is presumably why they are called 'mathematical'. There is a corresponding division between types of geometrical figures, but we hear too little about this; most of what follows will be concerned with numbers. The position that there are both formal numbers and mathematical numbers Aristotle ascribes to Plato. Speusippus rejects the formal numbers (and the entire theory of forms along with them; see the entry on Speusippus). The position Aristotle ascribes to Xenocrates is a bit more elusive. In *Metaphysics* VII 2, Aristotle tells us, in 1028b19-21, that Plato accepted three sorts of entities: forms, mathematicals, and perceptibles; in this context that means formal numbers, mathematical numbers, and perceptibles. He then, in b21-24, talks about Speusippus' views (see the entry on Speusippus). In both cases he gives us the names. Then, in b24-27 he says this: > > But some say that the forms and the numbers have the same nature, > while the others, lines and planes, come next, {and so on} down to the > substance of the heavens and to the perceptibles. > Asclepius' commentary on this passage (Hayduck 1888, 379.17-22) tells us that it is dealing with Xenocrates. The core of Xenocrates' view is that "the forms and the numbers have the same nature:" that is, the formal numbers and the mathematical numbers have the same nature. A series of half a dozen passages in the *Metaphysics* can, in consequence of this identification, be associated with Xenocrates (see XII 1. 1069a30-b2, XIII 1. 1076a20, 6. 1080b21-30, 8. 1083b1-8, 9. 1086a5-11, XIV 3. 1090b13-1091a5). From these passages it appears that he is saying that the distinction between formal and mathematical numbers (as well as the corresponding distinction among geometrical objects) is unnecessary; he does this by assimilating mathematical numbers to form-numbers and telling us that mathematics can be done entirely with formal numbers. In other words, since he thinks that mathematics can be done with formal numbers, he feels it acceptable to call formal numbers mathematical numbers. 1086a5-9 makes it sound as if some part of Xenocrates' case for his position was based on the consideration that all that can be based on the two ultimate principles, the One and the Indefinite Dyad, is the series of formal numbers. Without some further comment, it is hard to see much of an argument here, but we may be able to piece together a little about the relationship of the numbers to the One. In Eudemian Ethics (I 8. 1218a24-33) Aristotle attacks an Academic 'demonstration' aimed at showing that The One is the good itself, i.e the Idea of the good. He calls it 'tricky' or 'bizarre' (translations of parabolos vary considerably), and it is indeed bizarre: from the premises that the numbers aim for unification and that "all the things that are aim for some one good" it concludes that the good itself must be the One. As it stands, this is gappy, but what is really bizzare is the first premise, that numbers strive to get their units to stick together; that is too much for Aristotle (and no doubt for the rest of us as well). In the passage of Proclus' Parmenides commentary cited above there appears a passage dealing with a view that makes the participants in an Idea 'aim for' that Idea, which in turn aims for that which 'comes before' it, which must be the One. So Xenocrates looks to be the source for the 'bizarre' demonstration, and if so he is invoking final causality in relating the forms (which are formal numbers) to the One. Aristotle himself has the heavenly spheres move as they do out of a desire to emulate the unmoved mover (Metaphysics XII 7. 1072a26-b4), and even says that the matter in a form/matter compound 'aims at' its form (Physics I 9. 192a16-25), so this use of final causality was, one supposes, Academic. But about Xenocrates' 'demonstration' Aristotle is merciless: "one should ... not without reason give any credit at all to things it is not easy to believe even with reason". It may help a little, but not a lot, to notice that Xenocrates makes (see below) the soul is a self-moving number. In any case, the resulting position is possibly quite unstable: Aristotle certainly thinks so. For Plato and Speusippus, the addition of 2 and 3 is a matter of putting together a group of units that is a mathematical 2 with a disjoint group of units that is a mathematical 3 (that numbers are such collections of units is a view that can still be found later, perhaps most importantly, given his influence, in Euclid, *Elements* VII def. 2). Aristotle, too, understood addition in this way, although with a completely different take on the underlying ontology. We do not know how Xenocrates understood addition: perhaps as a sort of map telling you that if you are on the unique formal number 2 and you want to add the unique formal number 3 to it, you cannot, strictly speaking, do that, but taking three steps on in the series will get you to the unique formal number 5, and that is what '2 + 3 = 5' really means. There is, as far as I know, no evidence to support this conjecture, but it has the advantage of explaining Aristotle's complaint, voiced more than once in the passages cited (see 1080b28-30, 1083b4-6, 1086a9-11), that Xenocrates actually makes doing mathematics impossible: he ends up destroying mathematical number, and if the above guess should be correct about Xenocrates' handling of addition, it is readily seen how someone of Aristotle's persuasion might think that Xenocrates is not so much explaining addition as explaining it away. Aristotle complains in 1080b28-30 that on Xenocrates' view it is not so that every two units make up a pair, and also that on his view not every geometrical magnitude divides into smaller magnitudes. This has to do with Xenocrates' acceptance of the idea that there are indivisible lines; this idea Aristotle ascribes to Plato in *Metaphysics* I 9. 992a20-22, and Alexander's commentary on that passage adds the name Xenocrates, in a way that suggests that Xenocrates' acceptance of indivisible magnitudes was even better known than Plato's (Hayduck 1891, 120.6-7; see also Simplicius on *De caelo*, Heiberg 1894, 563.21-22 and many other passages in the commentators in which this ascription occurs: frs. 41-49H, 123-147IP). As Proclus understood Xenocrates' position, it applied to the Form of the line rather than to geometrical or physical magnitudes (see Diehl 1904, 245.30-246.4), but this is very much a minority view: Porphyry is quoted by Simplicius in the latter's commentary on the *Physics* (Diels 1882, 140.9-13) as saying that, according to Xenocrates, what is: > > ... is not divisible *ad infinitum*, but {division} stops > at certain indivisibles {*atoma*}. But these are not > indivisible as partless and least {magnitudes}, but while they are > cuttable with respect to quantity and matter and have parts, in form > they are indivisible and primary; he supposed that there were certain > primary indivisible lines and primary planes and solids composed out > of them. > This suggests that Xenocrates might have thought he could do with the notion of a *line* what Aristotle was prepared to do with notions such as *man*. Aristotle is prepared to say that a man is indivisible, and so a suitable unit for the arithmetician's contemplation, in the sense that if you divide a man into two parts what you get is not two men (see *Metaphysics* XIII 3. 1078a23-26). Xenocrates may have thought the notion of a line could be made to work in the same way: beyond a certain point, divisions will no longer yield lines. It is difficult to think how he could have made this plausible; once again, one can see why Aristotle might have regarded Xenocrates' position as unmathematical. Xenocrates' espousal of indivisible magnitudes has led to the conjecture that the pseudo-Aristotelian treatise *On Indivisible Lines* is at least in part an attack on him, and that the arguments recounted in its first chapter in favor of the claim that there are indivisible lines, which are rebutted in the sequel, might come from Xenocrates. Unfortunately, those arguments are quite obscure, and the text itself is not in very good shape (an admirably concise summary of the first four of these arguments may be found in Furley 1967, 105). But some of the arguments owe a lot to Zeno of Elea: that Xenocrates was influenced by Zeno is only what one would expect, and is confirmed elsewhere (see esp. the passage from Porphyry cited in part above, *apud* Simplicius on the *Physics*, Diels 1882, 140.6-18). In the passage of *Metaphysics* VII 2 quoted above, after we get the identification of formal and mathematical numbers, with the formal numbers actually carrying the weight, there is a brief description of the rest of the universe: "while the others, lines and planes, come next, {and so on} down to the substance of the heavens and to the perceptibles." It appears that Xenocrates pictured the universe as unfolding in the sequence: (1) forms = numbers; (2) lines; (3) planes; (4) solids; (5) solids in motion, i.e. astronomical bodies; ...; (n) ordinary perceptible things. Solid shapes aren't mentioned in this sentence, but they were earlier, in 1028b17-18, and they are a standard stage in this sequence. There is here an implicit contrast between Xenocrates and Speusippus, whose universe was to Aristotle discontinuous or disjointed: Xenocrates' universe is at least a more orderly one (see the entry on Speusippus). And something like this rather faint praise is echoed in Theophrastus' *Metaphysics*. Theophrastus complains that Pythagoreans and Platonists fail to give us a full story about the construction of the universe: they just go so far and stop (6a15-b6). Then he says (6b6-9): > > and none of the others {does any different} except Xenocrates: for he > places all things somehow around the world-order, alike perceptibles > and intelligibles, i.e. mathematicals, and again even the divine > {things}. > So we have it from Aristotle that Xenocrates' universe showed continuity, and from Theophrastus that it covered everything. Of course, we do not know how. Exactly what Theophrastus means by 'the divine things' is hard to say. There are two candidates: the objects of astronomical studies, which would connect with Aristotle's account, or those of theological studies, about which Xenocrates also had much to say. These are not exclusive candidates. A passage in Aetius (Diels 1879, 304b1-14) tells us that Xenocrates took the 'unit and the dyad' to be gods, the first male and the second female, and also thought of the heavenly bodies as gods; in addition he supposed there were sublunary *daimones*. These latter were beings intermediary between gods and men, also mentioned in Plato, *Symposium* 202d-203a. We hear more about the gods, *daimones*, and men from Plutarch, who tells us (*De defectu oraculorum* 416c-d, Babbitt 1936, 386-387) that Xenocrates associated them with types of triangle: gods with equilateral ones, *daimones* with isosceles ones, and men with scalene triangles: as isosceles triangles are intermediate between equilateral ones and scalene ones, so *daimones* are intermediate between gods and men. According to Plutarch (417b, *De Iside et Osiride* 360d-f: in Babbitt 1936, 390-391 and 58-61, respectively.), Xenocrates' *daimones* come in good and bad varieties: they may have had something to do with the explanation of the existence of evil. In addition, there are isolated snatches of other views of Xenocrates that might fall under the heading 'metaphysics'. Simplicius, in his commentary on Aristotle's *Categories* (Kalbfleisch 1907, 63.21-24) tells us that Xenocrates objected to Aristotle's list of ten categories as too long: he thought all that was needed was the distinction, visible in Plato, between things that are 'by virtue of themselves' and things that are 'relative to something' (see, e.g., *Sophist* 255c, and Dancy 1999). The standard examples help clarify this: the terms *man* and *horse* are of the first sort, whereas *large*, relative to *small*, *good* relative to *bad*, etc., are of the latter type. There was, it appears from a text also preserved by Simplicius (in his commentary on the *Physics*, Diels 1882, 247.30-248.20, from Hermodorus, an early associate of Plato's), an internal connection between these 'old academic categories' and the One and the Indefinite Dyad. The One was the heading over the category of things that are 'by virtue of themselves': such things are standalone entities, *one* thing. The Indefinite Dyad was the heading over the category of relatives: such a term refers to an indefinite continuum pointing in two directions. All this is referred to Plato, not Xenocrates, but if Xenocrates accepted Plato's later theory, or at least some of it, he presumably accepted this as well, and saw in Aristotle's proliferation of categories a threat to the basic two principles he shared with Plato. A text preserved in Arabic (see Pines 1961) has Alexander of Aphrodisias criticizing Xenocrates for saying that the (less general) species is prior to the (more general) genus because the latter, being an element in the definitions of the former, is a part of them (and wholes are subsequent to parts). A long passage in Themistius' commentary on Aristotle's *De anima* (Heinze 1899, 11.18-12.33) seems to stem from Xenocrates' *On Nature* (in 11.37-12.1 Themistius says "It is possible to gather all these {things} from the *On Nature* of Xenocrates"). This is a discussion of a story about the composition of the soul from the formal numbers 1, 2, 3, and 4 (although 1 was not normally considered a number), mentioned in *De anima* 408b18-27. The motivation for this account of the soul, in both Aristotle and Themistius, is the explanation of how we can know things about the universe: the universe is derivative from those numbers, and so, if the soul is similarly derivative, the soul can know things under the principle that like things are known by like. This cognitive sort of account is contrasted with another motivic type of account, that takes as the primary thing to be explained the fact that the soul can initiate motion. However, it is quite clear that, even if the story about the reduction of the soul to numbers stems from Xenocrates' *On Nature*, the numerical reduction was supposed by Themistius not to be Xenocrates', but (perhaps) Plato's. Aristotle and Themistius both give separate mention to the account of the soul that is traditionally ascribed to Xenocrates: that it is a self-moving number (*De anima* 408b32-33; Themistius in 12.30-33; the ascription to Xenocrates is supported by a large number of texts gathered as frs. 60H, 165-187IP: e.g., Alexander of Aphrodisias on Aristotle's *Topics*, Wallies 1891, 162.17). Both Aristotle and Themistius characterize this account as an attempt to combine the cognitive and the motivic ways of thinking about the soul; as Themistius puts it (12.30-33): > > And there were others who wove the two together into the explanation > of the soul, both moving and knowing, such as the one who asserted the > soul {to be} a number that moves itself, pointing by > 'number' to the capacity for knowing and by 'moving > itself' to that for moving. > Themistius does not here tell us that this is Xenocrates' account, but he does later on (see esp. 32.19-34, which refers expressly to Xenocrates' *On Nature* book 5). ## 2. Theory of Knowledge As already noted, this heading comes under 'logic' in Sextus Empiricus. No one reports anything for Xenocrates about what we would think of as pure logic; Sextus (*Adversus mathematicos* vii 147-149) gives us a scrap about epistemology. Xenocrates is supposed to have divided the substances or entities into three groups: perceptible, intelligible, and believable (also referred to as 'composite' and 'mixed'). The intelligible ones were objects of knowledge, which Xenocrates apparently spoke of as 'epistemonic logos' or 'knowing account', and were 'located' outside the heavens. The perceptible ones were objects of perception, which was capable of attaining truth about them but nothing that counted as knowledge; they were within the heavens. The composite ones were the heavenly objects themselves, and objects of belief, which is sometimes true and sometimes false. This scheme descends from that in Plato, *Republic* V *ad fin*., where the objects of knowledge were differentiated from those of belief, and from *Republic* VI *ad fin*., where that division is portrayed on a divided line. In the latter passage, Plato seems actually to have four divisions of types of cognition and their objects, but this is notoriously difficult (see Burnyeat 1987), and Xenocrates appears to have rethought it. His tripartite division of objects looks like that in Aristotle, *Metaphysics* XII 1. The phrase 'epistemonic logos' is one Sextus (145) also assigns to Speusippus; it also recalls discussions in Aristotle (e.g. *Metaphysics* VII 15) and the end of Plato's *Theaetetus*. An 'epistemonic logos' is the sort of account that carries knowledge with it. The intelligible domain must have included the formal numbers dealt with above, which was also, as mentioned, the domain of mathematics, while the special place for the heavens accords with the fact that one of the items in D.L.'s bibliography is "*On Astronomy*, 6 books". This picture seems to square with Aristotle's exempting Xenocrates from the charge, leveled against Speusippus, of producing a discontinuous universe, and with Theophrastus' comment to the effect that Xenocrates' universe encompassed everything. Here again we encounter Xenocrates the theologian: Sextus tells us (149) that Xenocrates associated the three fates with his three groups of substances: Atropos with the intelligible ones, Clotho with the perceptible ones, and Lachesis with the believable ones. This sounds a Xenocratean touch: it connects with the interpretation of Plato (see *Republic* X 620d-e) and takes mythology very seriously. ## 3. Ethics Here we are very much in the dark: we have only disconnected snippets to consider. Aristotle names Xenocrates in the *Topics* in connection with two ethical views: at II 6. 112a37-38 he ascribes to him the view that a happy man is one with a good soul, along with (perhaps) the claim that one's soul is one's *daimon*, whatever that means; at VII 1. 152a7-9 he ascribes to him an argument to the effect that the good life and the happy life are the same, employing as premises the claims that the good life and the happy life are both the most choosable (a little later, in 152a26-30, Aristotle objects to this argument). Plutarch claims (*De communibus notitiis adversus Stoicos* 1069e-f) that Xenocrates made happiness turn on living in accordance with nature; since this may derive from Antiochus of Ascalon, whose project it was to assimilate the Academy to Stoicism, it is suspect. Clement (*Stromateis* II 22) ascribes to him the view that happiness is the possession of one's own excellence in the soul. This view bears a family resemblance to Aristotle's (*NE* I 7. 1098a16-17, 9. 1099b26). The negative emphasis in Xenocrates' evaluation of philosophical activity as "stopping the disturbance of the affairs of life" ([Galen], *Historia philosophiae* 8, in Diels 1879 605.7-8) sounds like a step in the direction of the Hellenistic goal of undisturbedness.
xenophanes
## 1. Life and Works In his *Lives of the Philosophers* (Diels-Kranz, testimonium A1), Diogenes Laertius reports that Xenophanes was born in the small Ionian town of Colophon and flourished during the sixtieth Olympiad (540-537 BCE). Laertius adds that when Xenophanes was "banished from his native city" he "joined the colony planted at Elea" (in Italy), and also lived at Zancle and Catana (two Greek communities in Sicily). He credits Xenophanes with composing verses "in epic meter, as well as elegiacs and iambics attacking Hesiod and Homer and denouncing what they said about the gods", with reciting his own works, and with composing poems on the founding of Colophon and Elea. Later writers add that "he buried his sons with his own hands", was sold into slavery, and later released from it. By Xenophanes' own account (B8) he "tossed about the Greek land" for sixty-seven years, starting at the age of twenty-five. Diels-Kranz (DK) provides 45 fragments of his poetry (although B4, 13, 19, 20, 21 and 41 would be more accurately classified as *testimonia*), ranging from the 24 lines of B1 to the single-word fragments of B21a, 39, and 40. A number of the 'sympotic poems' (poems for drinking parties) (B1-3, 5, 6, 22, and the imitation in C2) were preserved by Athenaeus, while the remarks on the nature of the divine were quoted by Clement (B14-16 and 23), Sextus Empiricus (B11, 12, and 24), and Simplicius (B25 and 26). Other snippets survive in the accounts by Diogenes Laertius and Aetius, or as marginal notes in our manuscripts of various authors, or as entries in later rhetorical summaries and dictionaries. Seventy-four selections, of which the most extensive is the pseudo-Aristotelian treatise *On Melissus, Xenophanes, Gorgias* (*MXG*), make up the collection of *testimonia* in DK. Laertius' statement (A1) that Xenophanes "wrote in epic meter, also elegiacs, and iambics" is confirmed by extant poems in hexameters and elegiac meter, with one couplet (B14) a combination of hexameter and iambic trimeter. Ancient writers referred to a number of his compositions as *silloi*--'squints' or satires, and a critical tone pervades many of the surviving fragments. Three late sources credit Xenophanes with a didactic poem under the title *Peri Phuseos* ("On Nature") but not every allusion to an earlier author's views "on nature" represented a reference to a single work on that subject. ## 2. Criticisms of Greek Popular Religion Fragments B11 and B12 describe, and implicitly criticize, the stories about the gods told by Homer and Hesiod. > > Homer and Hesiod have attributed to the gods > > > all sorts of things that are matters of reproach and censure among > men: > > > theft, adultery, and mutual deception. (B11) > > > > > ...as they sang of numerous illicit divine deeds: > > > theft, adultery, and mutual deceit. (B12) > The basis for Xenophanes' unhappiness with the poets' accounts is not explained, but we may infer from the concluding call to pay due honor to the gods in Xenophanes' B1 that an attribution of scandalous conduct would be incompatible with the goodness or perfection any divine being must be assumed to possess (cf. Aristotle *Meta*. 1072b; Plato, *Rep*. 379b.) In the well-known fragments B14-16, Xenophanes comments on the general tendency of human beings to conceive of divine beings in human form: > > But mortals suppose that gods are born, > > > wear their own clothers and have a voice and body. (B14) > > > > > Ethiopians say that their gods are snub-nosed and black; > > > Thracians that theirs are are blue-eyed and red-haired. (B16) > B15 adds, probably in a satirical vein, that if horses and oxen had hands and could draw pictures, their gods would look remarkably like horses and oxen. B17, "...and bacchants of pine stand round the well-built house" may represent a criticism of the common ancient belief that a god could assume possession of a physical object so as to offer protection to its possessor. The ridiculing of Pythagoras' claim to have recognized the soul of a departed friend in the voice of a barking dog (B7), together with the attacks on divination credited to Xenophanes in A52, reflect the broader denial of knowledge of divine attributes and operations set out in B34. Xenophanes is prepared to offer a positive account of the nature of the deity (see the following section) but his position appears to be that while no mortal being will ever know about the gods with any degree of certainty, we can at least avoid adopting beliefs and practices clearly at odds with the special nature any divine being must be assumed to possess. ## 3. The Nature of the Divine So far as is known, Xenophanes was the first Greek thinker to offer a complex and at least partially systematic account of the divine nature. We have already noted how an implicit assumption of divine perfection may underlie his criticisms of Homer, Hesiod, and the tendency to imagine the gods in human form. Of the positive characterizations of the divine made in B23-26, perhaps the most fundamental is B23: > > One god greatest among gods and men, > > > not at all like mortals in body or in thought. > Although the remark has often been read as a pioneering expression of monotheism, this reading is made problematic by the nearby reference to 'gods' in the plural in the first line and the possibility that Xenophanes sought to highlight not the *one* god but rather the one *greatest* god (cf. Homer, *Iliad* 12, 243 for the use of 'one' (Greek *heis*) reinforcing a superlative). The relevant measures of divine 'greatness' are not specified, but the two most obvious choices would be greatness in honor and power, with honor perhaps the more basic of the two (cf. *Iliad* 2, 350; 2, 412; 4, 515; *Od*. 3, 378; 5,4; Hesiod, *Theogony* 49, 534, 538, etc.). Greatness in power would in turn explain the characterizations of the divine as perceptive and conscious in all its parts (B24), able to shake all things by the exercise of his thought (B25), and able to accomplish everything while remaining forever in the same place or condition (B26). It is unclear, however, how far Xenophanes himself realized the interconnections among the different divine attributes or sought to exploit those connections for didactic purposes. At least as they have come down to us, none of the remarks on the divine nature (B23-26) contains any of the inferential particles (*gar, epei, oun, hoti*, etc.) one would normally expect to find in a piece of reasoned discourse. Some later writers (A28.6, 31.2, 34-36) report that Xenophanes identified his 'one greatest god' with the entire physical universe--often termed 'the whole' or 'all things', and some modern accounts portray Xenophanes as a pantheist. But this understanding of Xenophanes' doctrines seems inconsistent with his assertion that "god shakes all things" (B25) that "all things are from the earth and to the earth all things come in the end" (B27), and that "all things which come into being and grow, are earth and water" (B29). On the whole, Xenophanes' remarks on the divine nature are perhaps best read as an expression of a traditional Greek piety: there exists a being of extraordinary power and excellence, and it is incumbent on each of us to hold it in high regard. ## 4. Social Criticism Five fragments touch on traditional subjects of Greek sympotic verse--on proper conduct at symposia (drinking parties), the measures of personal excellence, and the existence of various human foibles or failures. Xenophanes appears to have been particularly interested in identifying and discouraging conduct that failed to pay due honor to the gods or posed a risk to the stability and well-being of the city (or perhaps both). Although these passages may be insufficiently abstract and demonstrative in character to count as 'philosophical teachings', they do represent an important bridge between Greek poetry of the archaic period and the kind of moral theorizing practiced by many 5th and 4th-century thinkers. Xenophanes' disparagement of the honors accorded to athletes (B2), his call to censor the stories the poets tell about the gods (B1), and counsel to live a life of moderation (B3 and 5, and perhaps B21) all anticipate views expressed in Plato's *Republic* (cf. 607a, 378b, 372b.) His criticism of the pursuit of useless luxuries (B3) also anticipates Socrates' rebuke of his fellow citizens for caring more about wealth and power than about virtue (cf. *Apology* 30b.) His cautionary remarks about knowledge (B34) and reminder of the subjectivity of human taste (B38: "If god had not made yellow honey, they would think that figs were far sweeter") also reflect a traditional view of human judgment as limited and conditioned by personal experience. In each of these areas, Xenophanes' social commentary represents a continuation of the Greek poetic tradition as well as a step toward explicit philosophical theorizing. ## 5. Scientific Interests We may reasonably conclude from several surviving fragments and a large number of *testimonia* that Xenophanes was well aware of the teachings of the Milesian philosopher-scientists (Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes), and sought to improve on them. While many of the details of his own 'scientific' views remain obscure, the range and interconnectedness of his interests make him an important figure in the development of Ionian scientific theory. Theodoretus, Stobaeus, and Olympiodorus (all in A 36) credit him with a view of earth as the *arche* or "first principle" of all things. Yet Galen (also in A36) rejects this attribution, and B29 equates "all things which come into being and grow" with "earth *and* water". A two-substance *arche* would, moreover, be compatible with the many references to physical mixtures. A33 credits Xenophanes with a view of the sea as containing many mixtures, while B37 notes the presence of water in rocky caves, and A50 reports a view of the soul as earth and water. Insofar as some natural bodies are described as consisting entirely of water (or of a part of water, as in A46 where "the sweet portion" of the water is drawn up from the sea and separated off), it would be best to understand Xenophanes' "two-substance theory" in a distributed sense: all things are either earth, or water, or earth combined with water. Xenophanes appears to have explored many of the same phenomena studied at an earlier date by the Milesians. B28 presents a view of the nature and extent of the earth's depths; B30 identifies the sea as the source of clouds, wind, and rain; B32 comments on the nature of Iris (rainbow); B37 notes the presence of water in caves; B39 and 40 mention "cherry trees" and "frogs"; A38-45 discuss various astronomical phenomena, and A48 indicates an interest in periodic volcanic eruptions in Sicily. Hippolytus (A33) credits Xenophanes with a theory of alternating periods of world-wide flood and drought that was inspired, at least in part, by the discovery of fossilized remains of sea creatures at inland locations. Whether or not Xenophanes himself traveled to Syracuse, Paros, and Malta where these remains were found, his use of this information as the basis for a broad explanation of phenomena is an implicit testimonial to the heuristic value of information gained through travel and observation. Many *testimonia* credit Xenophanes with an interest in meteorological and astronomical phenomena. Not only are these comments of interest in their own right, they also present us what was arguably his single most important scientific contribution--his contention that clouds or cloud-like substances play a basic role in a great many natural phenomena. The term *nephos* ("cloud") appears only twice in the fragments of his work (in B30 and 32) but many *testimonia* either bear directly on the nature of clouds or make use of clouds in order to explain the nature of other phenomena. To cite an example of the first type, according to Diogenes Laertius "he says...the clouds are formed by the sun's vapor [i.e. vapor caused by the heat from the sun's rays] raising and lifting them to the surrounding air" (A1.24-5). Aetius (A46) provides a similar account: > > Xenophanes (says that) things in the heavens occur through the heat of > the sun as the initial cause; for when the moisture is drawn up from > the sea, the sweet portion, separating because of its fineness and > turning into mists, combines into clouds, trickled down in drops of > rain due to compression, and vaporizes the winds. > B30 gives us essentially the same view in Xenophanes' own words: > > The sea is the source of water and of wind, > > > For without the great sea, there would be no wind > > > Nor streams of rivers, nor rainwater from on high > > > But the great sea is the begetter of clouds, winds, and rivers. > Having accounted for the formation of clouds in mechanistic terms through processes of vaporization and compression Xenophanes proceeds to make use of clouds to explain a large number of meteorological and astronomical phenomena. The general claim appears in the pseudo-Plutarch *Miscellanies*: "he says that the sun and the stars come into being from the clouds" (A32), and Aetius gives us many specific applications: > > The stars come into being from burning clouds (A38). > > > The sort of fires that appear on ships--whom some call the Dioscuri > [St. Elmo's fire]--are tiny clouds glimmering in virtue of the > sort of motion they have (A39). > > > > The sun consists of burning clouds...a mass of little fires, > themselves constructed from the massing together of the moist > exhalation (A40). > > > > The moon is compressed cloud (A43). > > > > All things of this sort [comets, shooting stars, meteors] are either > groups or movements of clouds (A44). > > > > Flashes of lightning come about through the shining of the clouds > because of the movement (A45). > > > As it happens, clouds are natural candidates for the *explanans* in a scientific account. Since they are midway in form between a solid and gaseous state they are easily linked with solids, liquids, and gases of various kinds. And since they occupy a region midway between the surface of the earth and the upper regions of the heavens, they are well positioned to link the two basic substances of earth and water with many astronomical phenomena. Another important feature of Xenophanes' cloud-based approach to understanding natural phenomena is the application of this theory to a set of phenomena closely linked with traditional religious belief. We have already seen this in the thoroughly naturalistic accounts given of the "great sea", sun, moon, and stars, but nowhere is the contrast of the old and new ways of thinking more evident than in his comments on "Iris"--rainbow: > > And she whom they call Iris, this too is by nature a cloud. > > > Purple, red, and greenish-yellow to behold. (B32) > For the members of Xenophanes' audience "Iris" referred to the messenger goddess of Homer's *Iliad* (2, 686) and Hesiod's *Theogony* (780) and a set of atmospheric phenomena (halos, coronae, and cloud iridescence) commonly considered portents or signs of the intentions of divine beings. As the daughter of Thaumas ("marvel") Iris was the natural marvel *par* *excellence*. Yet for Xenophanes, 'she' is really an 'it' and a 'this' (the Greek neuter demonstrative *touto*), by nature a purple, red, and greenish-yellow cloud. It is, moreover, something that is there for us 'to behold' or 'to look at' (*idesthai*). Perhaps nowhere in presocratic philosophy can we find a clearer expression of the character of the Ionian 'intellectual revolution'--a decision to put aside an older way of thinking about events grounded in a belief in divine beings in favor of an approach to understanding the world that employs wide-ranging inquiry and direct observation and resorts to strictly physical causes and forces. Having deprived the gods of human form and clothing and removed the divine to some permanent and distant location, Xenophanes proceeds to strip a wide range of natural phenomena of all vestiges of religious or spiritual significance. His de-mythologized account of natural phenomena is, in short, the logical complement to his thoroughly de-naturalized account of the divine nature. Despite its several virtues, Xenophanes' physical theory appears to have had little impact on later thinkers. Anaxagoras followed his lead on the nature of the rainbow (cf. DK 59 B19) and Empedocles knew (but repudiated) his claim of the earth's indefinitely extended depths (DK 31 B39). But both Plato and Aristotle appear to have ignored Xenophanes' scientific views or assigned them little importance. One factor that may have contributed to this chilly reception was the absence of any expression by Xenophanes of the kind of commitment to teleology that both Plato and Aristotle regarded as essential to a proper understanding of the cosmos. Xenophanes' universe is controlled by a set of forces, but it is never described as "heading toward the best" nor is it directed toward some best result by a controlling intelligence. (Xenophanes' divine does "shake all things" by the thought of his mind (alone), but he is never described as in any way directing or controlling particular events.) It is also obvious that Xenophanes' heavenly bodies would have fallen far short of the level of perfection that, with Aristotle, became a hallmark of classical astronomical theory. Not only are Xenophanes' heavenly bodies not divine beings, they undergo creation and destruction at regular intervals. Only from the perspective of a much later period can the merits of Xenophanes' scientific views be fairly appreciated. Many centuries would have to pass before an emphasis on direct observation and the use of entirely natural causes and forces would become the scientific orthodoxy. ## 6. Reflections on Knowledge Five surviving fragments and roughly a dozen *testimonia* address what might be termed 'epistemological questions'--"How much can any mortal being hope to know?", "Does truth come to us through our own efforts or by divine revelation?", and "What role do our sense faculties play in the acquisition of knowledge?" Unfortunately, the picture that emerges from many of the *testimonia* largely contradicts what appear to be the views Xenophanes himself expressed. According to the summary in the pseudo-Plutarch *Miscellanies*, Xenophanes "declares that the senses are deceptive and generally rejects reason along with them" (A32.) Similarly, in his *Concerning Philosophy* Aristocles reports that "...since they think that sense perceptions and appearances must be rejected and trust only reason. For at one earlier time Xenophanes, Parmenides, Zeno, and Melissus said something of this sort" (A49). Similarly, Aetius declares that "Pythagoras, Empedocles, and Xenophanes (say that) sense perceptions are deceptive" (A49). Yet, as we have noted, B28 refers without qualification to "the upper limit of the earth that is seen (*horatai*) here at our feet" and B32 appears to encourage those in Xenophanes' audience to 'look at' or 'observe' (*idesthai*) the multi-colored cloud that is the rainbow. The realistic description of the sumptuous banquet in B1 and the wide range of Xenophanes' reported geographical and geological interests all sit poorly with an Eleatic "rationalism" that would dismiss all information gained through our faculties of sense and construct on the basis of reason alone a view of "what is" as a motionless, changeless and eternal unity. Xenophanes' most extended comment on knowledge is B34: > > ...and of course the clear and certain truth no man has seen > > > nor will there be anyone who knows about the gods and what I say about > all things. > > > For even if, in the best case, one happened to speak just of what has > been brought to pass, > > > still he himself would not know. But opinion is allotted to all. > Portions of these remarks were quoted, and thereby preserved for posterity, by the ancient skeptics who hailed Xenophanes as the founder of their particular variety of philosophical skepticism. Recent interpretations of B34 reject the skeptical interpretation in favor of other less extreme readings. On some accounts, B34 is concerned to deny only a direct perceptual awareness. Others find in his comments a distinction between natural science, where only probabilities can be achieved, and theology, where certainty is possible. Still others read Xenophanes' remarks as a blanket endorsement of "fallibilism"--the view that while each individual is free to express his or her opinion, the possibility of error can never be completely excluded. Since B34 opens with the phrase "and indeed..." it is likely that we do not have the whole of the remark, or all the premises from which its main conclusion was intended to follow. However, the use of the term *saphes* ("clear", in the first line of the fragment) by Xenophanes' Ionian contemporary, the historian Herodotus, provides a helpful clue to the logic of the argument. At several points in his *History* Herodotus speaks of what is *saphes*, or what can be known in a *sapheos* manner, as what can be confirmed to be the case on the basis of first-hand observation: > > And wishing to gain sure knowledge of these things (*thelon > de touton peri saphes ti eidenai*) from a point where this > was possible, I took ship to Tyre in Phoenicia, where I heard there > was a very holy temple of Heracles. There I saw it (*eidon*) > richly equipped... Then I went to Thasos where I also found a > temple of Heracles...Therefore what I have discovered by inquiry > clearly shows (*ta men nun historemena deloi > sapheos*) that Heracles is an ancient god. (*History* > II, 44) > Since the gods were believed to inhabit a realm far removed from that of mortal beings, it would be natural for Xenophanes to hold that no account of their nature and activities could possibly be confirmed on the basis of first-hand observation, hence known for certain to be correct. And since the pioneering cosmological accounts put forward by his Milesian predecessors held that a single material substance underlay phenomena in *all* places and times it would be equally impossible for any individual to confirm such a universal claim on the basis of first-hand observation, hence know for certain that it was true--even if in fact it was true. The sentiments expressed in lines three and four can be read as reinforcing this cautionary sentiment. Their point would be that no one (moreover) should be credited with knowledge (of the certain truth concerning the gods or the nature of all things) simply on the basis of having correctly described, perhaps even predicted, individual events as they take place (perhaps a reference to self-styled paragons of wisdom and predictors of events such as Epimenides and Pythagoras). The overall message of B34, from its opening reference to "no man" to its concluding phrase "fashioned for all" would have been that there never has been nor ever will be anyone who has the capacity to achieve certainty with respect to these important matters. Xenophanes' reference to a second-best level of comprehension or awareness--'opinion' or 'conjecture' (*dokos*) should not be read as inherently negative or dismissive. By Platonic standards, opinion--even when correct--would be an inferior possession, unstable and subject to removal through persuasion. But we have no reason to assume that Xenophanes shared Plato's view on this topic. And in fact B35, quoted by Plutarch in connection with encouraging a bashful speaker to express his views, appears to present what one 'opines' or believes in a fairly positive light: > > ...Let these things be believed (*dedoxastho*) as > like the realities... > The similarity between the verbal *dedoxastho* of B35 and the nominative *dokos* of B34 permits us to combine the two fragmentary remarks into a single coherent view: of course there can be no knowledge of the certain truth concerning the gods and the basic principles governing the cosmos, but *dokos*--opinion or conjecture--is available and should be accepted when it corresponds with how things really are. The full sense of B36, however, may never be determined. Neither its context (a grammatical treatise of Herodian) nor its wording ("...however many they have made evident for mortals to look upon") provides definitive guidance. Perhaps Xenophanes was seeking to set an upper limit to the range of things that can be known by human beings (i.e. to caution others that they could know only as many as things as the gods had made available to them to experience). But it is equally possible that the remark was intended (as B32 above) to encourage the members of his audience to explore and inquire on their own (i.e. to encourage them to investigate "however many things" the gods have made available to them to experience). B18 has often been hailed as an expression of an optimistic outlook or "faith in human progress"--the conviction that humankind has made and will continue to make improvements in the arts and conditions of life generally. Yet none of the other surviving fragments reflects such an optimism and several (e.g. B2 and 3) suggest that Xenophanes was not at all optimistic about his city's prospects for survival. In the light of his reported repudiation of divination (A52), de-mythologizing of various natural phenomena (B30 and 32), and evident enthusiasm for inquiry into a wide range of subjects, B18 is perhaps best read as an expression of faith in the value of 'inquiry' or 'seeking' as the preferred approach to gaining knowledge of 'all things'. To sum up: Xenophanes' attitude toward knowledge appears to have been the product of two distinct impulses. While he believed that inquiry in the form of travel and direct observation was capable of yielding useful information about the nature of things, he remained sufficiently under the influence of an older piety to want to caution others against seeking to understand matters that lay beyond the limits of all human experience. Here, as in other aspects of his thought, Xenophanes stands with one foot in the world of the archaic poet and the other in the "new science" of the late 6th and early 5th centuries BCE ## 7. Xenophanes' Legacy Many later writers identified Xenophanes as the teacher of Parmenides and the founder of the Eleatic "school of philosophy"--the view that, despite appearances, what there is is a motionless, changeless, and eternal 'One'. This view of Xenophanes is based largely on Plato's reference to "our Eleatic tribe, beginning from Xenophanes as well as even earlier" (*Sophist* 242d) and Aristotle's remark that "...with regard to the whole universe, he says that the one is the god" (*Meta*. A5, 986b18), along with some verbal similarities between Xenophanes' description of the "one greatest, unmoving god" and Parmenides' account of a "motionless, eternal, and unitary being". But the Xenophanes who speaks to us in the surviving fragments is a combination of rhapsode, social critic, religious teacher, and keen student of nature. Euripides' *Heracles* 1341 ff. echoes his attack on the stories told about the gods by Homer and Hesiod (B11-12) and a passage of Euripides' *Autolycus* quoted by Athenaeus (C2) repeats portions of the attack on the honors accorded to athletes delivered in B2. In the *Republic*, Plato shows himself the spiritual heir of Xenophanes when he states that the guardians of his ideal state are more deserving of honors and public support than the victors at Olympia, criticizes the stories told about the gods by the poets, and calls for a life of moderate desire and action. A pronounced ethic of moderation, sometimes bordering on asceticism, runs through much of ancient Greek ethical thought, beginning with Solon and Xenophanes and continuing through Socrates and Plato to the Epicureans and Cynics. Xenophanes' conception of a "one greatest god" who "shakes all things by the thought (or will) of his mind" (*noou phreni*) may have helped to encourage Heraclitus' belief in an 'intelligence' (*gnome*) that steers all things (B41), Anaxagoras' account of the *nous* that orders and arranges all things (B12), and Aristotle's account of a divine *nous* that inspires a movement toward perfection without actually doing anything toward bringing it about (*Metaphysics* Lambda.) In his Dictionnaire historique et critique (1697) Pierre Bayle began the modern philosophical discussion of the problem of evil by quoting Xenophanes' remark (as reported in Diogenes Laertius 9.19) that "most things give way to mind" (*ta polla hesso nou*). Accepting the conjecture proposed by the classical scholar Meric Casaubon, Bayle took Xenophanes to be asserting that God was unable to make all things conform to his benevolent will. Bayle then assembled a set of texts in support of the view that in fact the amount of evil in the universe far exceeds the amount of good. Bayle's article sparked a reply from Leibniz (in his Theodicee of 1710). In his Candide (1759), Voltaire supported Bayle's view by ridiculing Leibniz's contention that this is the best of all possible worlds. Although there may be no direct line of influence, we may also consider Feuerbach's critique of religious belief as a 'projection' of human attributes, and Freud's analysis of religious belief as an instance of 'wish-fulfillment', as two modern successors to Xenophanes' observation of the general tendency of human beings to conceive of divine beings in terms of their own attributes and capacities. Xenophanes' most enduring philosophical contribution was arguably his pioneering exploration of the conditions under which human beings can achieve knowledge of the certain truth. The distinction between knowledge and true opinion set out in B34 quickly became an axiom of ancient Greek accounts of knowledge and survives in modern garb as the 'belief' and 'truth' conditions of the 'standard' or 'tripartite analysis' of knowledge. It can be plausibly argued that every later Greek thinker, at least until the time of Aristotle, undertook to respond to the basic challenge posed in Xenophanes' B34--how, given the severely limited character of human experience, anyone can plausibly claim to have discovered the truth about matters lying beyond anyone's capacity to observe first-hand. Xenophanes may also be credited with expanding the range of topics considered appropriate for philosophical inquiry and discussion. His Ionian predecessors had initiated the study of phenomena "above the heavens and below the earth" but, so far as we know, they did not turn their critical fire against the leading poets of ancient Greece nor did they seek through their teachings to correct or improve the conduct of their fellow citizens. Although many aspects of his thought remain the subject of scholarly debate, Xenophanes was clearly a multi-dimensional thinker who left his mark on many aspects of later Greek thought.
xunzi
## 1. Xunzi and *Xunzi* The name Xunzi means Master Xun and refers to Xun Kuang Xun Kuang , who was renowned in his day as "the most revered of teachers" (*zui wei laoshi* Zui Wei Lao Shi ). His precise dates are unknown, and extant sources contradict one another: in particular, there is disagreement as to whether he journeyed to the philosophical center of Qi Qi at the age of fifteen *sui* Sui (i.e. thirteen or fourteen years of age) or fifty *sui* (forty-eight or forty-nine). The former figure is more plausible (Goldin 1999: 110n.13; Knoblock 1982-83: 33-34), and would indicate a year of birth sometime around 310 BCE All we can surmise of his death is that it must have been after 238 BCE, because he was alive when his patron, Lord Chunshen Chun Shen Jun , was assassinated in that year. Virtually all available information about his life comes either from internal references in *Xunzi*, the posthumously edited collection of his works, or from his biography in *Records of the Historian* Shi Ji , by Sima Qian Si Ma Qian (145?-86? BCE), which is known to contain serious distortions, especially in its treatment of famous philosophers (Kern 2015). Hence modern attempts to piece together Xun Kuang's life (such as Knoblock 1988-94: I, 3-35; and Liao Mingchun 2005: 535-46) are necessarily tentative. Sima Qian relates that Xunzi polished his voluminous writings in his old age, but they do not survive in his own recension. All extant editions of *Xunzi* derive from a compilation by Liu Xiang Liu Xiang (79-8 BCE), a palace librarian who located 322 bamboo bundles of text (*pian* Pian ) that he confidently attributed to Xunzi, of which he eliminated 290 as duplicates. These high numbers suggest that Xunzi's essays had been circulating independently for about two centuries (Sato 2003: 27-36). The general consensus today is that *Xunzi* is a collection of predominantly authentic essays, but certainly not organized in a manner that Xun Kuang himself had authorized (e.g., Knoblock 1988-94: I, 105-28). One indication of the diversity of Liu Xiang's sources is that a few chapters (notably "A Debate about Warfare" ["Yibing" Yi Bing ]) refer to Xunzi as Sun Qingzi Sun Qing Zi , "Master Chamberlain Sun", a title that he himself would not have used.[1] The chapter divisions, in particular, seem unreliable: whereas some chapters read like self-standing essays, others do not. In "Refutation of Physiognomy" ("Feixiang" Fei Xiang ), for example, only the opening lines deal with physiognomy; the rest of the chapter seems to consist of stray passages that Liu Xiang did not quite know where to insert. There are also some chapters with generic instructional material, as well as poems and rhymed riddles that are rarely studied (Knechtges 1989). One of the consequences of this arrangement is that reconstructing Xunzi's arguments requires reading across chapter boundaries: taken as a whole, the book conveys a distinctive philosophical position, but individual chapters are inadequate, indeed sometimes incoherent, on their own (Kern 2016; Hutton 2014: xviii-xxiii). ## 2. Human Nature (*xing* Xing ) Chapter 23,[2] "Human Nature is Evil" (*Xing'e* Xing E ), is a reasonable point of entry into Xunzi's philosophy for multiple reasons: it exemplifies some of the textual problems mentioned above; it addresses one of the core themes of the collection; and it was, for centuries, the most frequently cited section of *Xunzi*. First, the two keywords need to be unpacked. *Xing*, commonly translated as "human nature", is a term of uncertain etymology that earlier philosophers had used in subtly dissimilar ways. Mencius (372-289 BCE?), for example, used it to refer to the ideal state than an organism is expected to attain under the right conditions, or perhaps an innate tendency toward that state (Graham 1989: 117-32; Graham 1990: 7-66). Famously, Mencius argued that the *xing* of human beings is good (*shan* Shan ), by which he meant that all human beings *have the capacity to become* good, even though, in reality, not all people are good, because they fail to exert themselves sufficiently--or even take the obligation seriously. In *Xunzi*, "Human Nature is Evil" is framed as an argument with Mencius (who was probably long dead), and takes the view that the *xing* of human beings is the very opposite of *shan*, namely *e*. The basic meaning of *e* is close to "detestable" (as a transitive verb, *wu* E means "to hate"); the translation "evil" is acceptable only with the understanding that something like an Augustinian conception of evil is not intended. (Some scholars opt for "bad", another standard antonym of "good" in English.) But in prosecuting this position, Xunzi uses *xing* in a fundamentally different sense: "What is so by birth is called *xing*" (*Xunzi* 22.1b).[3] Thus *xing* refers to the basic faculties, capacities, and desires that we have from birth, which cannot be called "good" because following the impulses of our *xing*, without reflecting on them and moderating them, will lead us to act harmfully (Hutton 2000; Tang 2016: 51). In effect, both Xunzi and Mencius argued that human beings all have the capacity to become good, even though some people develop this capacity and others do not (Graham 1989: 250; Shun 1997: 222-31). The main differences, only recently appreciated, are that they were not operating with the same implicit definitions of *xing*, and Xunzi's recommendations for moral self-cultivation--that is, how to overcome one's inherently detestable nature--were more complex than Mencius's, as we shall see. Because of Mencius's subsequent prestige, it was commonly supposed that Xunzi's definition of *xing* was heterodox, if not deliberately subversive. But a collection of Confucian manuscripts recently excavated from a tomb near the modern town of Guodian Guo Dian and dated to ca. 300 BCE suggests that it may have been *Mencius's* usage of *xing*, not Xunzi's, which was considered eccentric in ancient times.[4] The Guodian text called *The Xing Emerges from the Endowment* (*Xing zi ming chu* Xing Zi Ming Chu ) defines *xing* in a manner very similar to Xunzi: the set of inborn characteristics shared by all members of a species (Goldin 2005: 38). Fixating on the title "Human Nature Is Evil" (which may or may not derive from Xunzi himself) can lead to an elision of the second half of the chapter's credo: "what is good [in people] is their artifice" (*qi shan zhe wei ye* Qi Shan Zhe Wei Ye ). "Artifice" (*wei*)[5] refers to all the traits and habits that we acquire through our own conscious actions. And if we achieve any goodness, it must be because of our artifice: whereas > > > obeying one's *xing* and following one's emotions > must result in contention and robbery ... the transformation > [brought about by] the methods of a teacher and the Way of ritual and > morality will result in deference and courtesy, in accordance with > refinement and principles, and return to order. (*Xunzi* 23.1a) > > > > Thus the phrase that is used to denote moral self-cultivation is not to overcome or abandon the *xing*, but *to transform* it (*huaxing* Hua Xing ). For this reason, in addition to stylistic features that trouble some readers, the chapter is occasionally impugned as corrupt or inauthentic (Robins 2001-02; Zhou Chicheng 2014). ## 3. Modes of Moral Self-Cultivation: Ritual (*li* Li ) and Music (*yue* Le ) What prompted Xunzi to dissent from Mencius's characterization of *xing* as good if he ultimately agreed with Mencius's larger view: that people can perfect themselves and that such an achievement requires great exertion and self-motivation? Perhaps Xunzi wished to highlight his conviction that the proper models for moral behavior lie outside the self, which is fundamentally opposed to a Mencian notion of Four Beginnings (*siduan* Si Duan ) lodged within the human heart (e.g., *Mencius* 2A.6). Whereas Mencians have always emphasized looking inwards for moral direction--sometimes complicated by the acknowledgment that the heart can be corrupted--self-cultivation in the Xunzian style is inconceivable without looking *outwards*. Xunzi held that for most ordinary people, the best guide is the set of rituals (*li*) handed down by sages of yore (*sheng* Sheng or *shengren* Sheng Ren ). What are rituals and why did the sages institute them? In some passages, Xunzi attributes, in a manner superficially reminiscent of Hobbes or Rousseau, the genesis of the rituals to the sages' recognition that unbridled competition produces a globally unsustainable situation: > > > If people follow their desires, then boundaries cannot contain them > and objects cannot satisfy them. Thus the Former Kings restrained them > and established for them ritual and morality in order to divide them > [into classes]. (*Xunzi* 4.12; cf. 19.1a) > > > Sometimes these rituals are described as efficient social conventions (e.g., Perkins 2014: 189-97), but this is inadequate for two reasons. First, Xunzi elsewhere explicitly denies that an arbitrarily chosen set of rituals would be effective. Rather, the rituals of the sage kings are legitimate because they accord with "that which makes humans human" (*ren zhi suoyi wei ren zhe* Ren Zhi Suo Yi Wei Ren Zhe ); by implication, any competing ritual code would necessarily fail. Specifically, human beings, unlike any other species of animal, abide by certain distinctions (*bian* Bian )--male is distinguished from female, old from young, and so on--and it is altogether natural that we do so. The rituals of the sage kings confirm the distinctions that we are bound to make by nature (the core text is *Xunzi* 5.4; see also 10.3a and 19.1c). Second, rituals, in Xunzi's conception, not only facilitate social cohesion, but also foster moral and psychological development (Ivanhoe 2014; Yearley 2014: 92-101). Indeed, if they did not, they would be mere instruments of expedience, not rituals. These dimensions become clear when Xunzi begins to discuss specific rituals and their purposes. We observe regulations concerning funerary ceremonies and grave goods, for example, in order to learn how to avoid incivility and miserliness (19.4a-b). Similarly, the mandatory three-year mourning period for deceased rulers and parents helps us conduct ourselves properly by providing suitable forms for us to express emotions that are so deep as to be potentially debilitating: > > > When a wound is colossal, its duration is long; when pain is profound, > the recovery is slow. The three-year mourning period is a form > established with reference to emotions; it is the means by which one > conveys the acme of one's pain. (*Xunzi* 19.9a) > > > One ritual discussed *in extenso* is the village wine-drinking ceremony (*xiang* Xiang ). The fact that the host fetches the guest of honor himself, but expects the other guests to arrive on their own, underscores the distinctions that need to be drawn between noble and base. And the detail that each participant toasts the next, serially and according to their ages, demonstrates that one can align society according to seniority without excluding anyone. When the guest of honor retires, the host bows and escorts him out, and the formal occasion comes to an end: this is to make it known that one can feast at leisure without becoming disorderly. The clear implication is that by taking part in the rite, we can gradually comprehend the moral principles that the sages wished us to embody (*Xunzi* 20.5). Xunzi's rituals have such an important role to play in our emotional and moral development that he spends an entire chapter limning what are essentially rituals of artistic expression. The term he uses is "music" (*yue*), which is distinct from ritual, but Xunzi's conception of their origin and purpose is so similar that we can scarcely speak of one without the other. Thus "ritual and music" (*liyue*) can only be understood as two aspects of human artifice (*wei*): "ritual" refers to cultural forms that affect social cohesion, "music" to those involving the orderly expression of human emotions. The crucial point is that the sages created both. Like all Confucians, Xunzi accepts that human beings have certain irrepressible impulses (*Xunzi* 20.1), which are not objectionable in themselves. The problem is that unreflective outbursts driven solely by emotional responses may cause harm, and thus we are enjoined to be mindful of our impulses, rather than to extinguish them (compare *Xunzi* 22.5a). To aid us in this process, the Sages left behind appropriate musical compositions that we can use to channel our need to express ourselves. What Xunzi meant by this is the canonical collection of *Odes* (*Shi* Shi ), which all Confucians seem to have regarded as a nonpareil repository of edifying literature (Goldin 2005: 35). Xunzi's immediate purpose in this section was to counter the Mohist view that music is wasteful. Xunzi counters that by focusing exclusively on the material costs, Mo Di Mo Di (d. ca. 390 BCE) and his followers failed to recognize the psychological utility of music as an instrument of moral suasion (Cook 1997: 21-24; Graham 1989: 259-61). > > > When music is centered and balanced, the people are harmonious and not > dissipated. When music is stern and grave, the people are uniform and > not disorderly. When the people are harmonious and uniform, the army > is firm and the citadels secure; enemy states dare not invade. > (*Xunzi* 20.2) > > > As the last quote intimates, the proper implementation of ritual is also decisive in politics and international relations.[6] In the "Debate about Warfare", for example, Xunzi offers a distinctive variant of the old Confucian idea that a true king (*wang* Wang --always a moral term in Confucian discourse) will succeed on the battlefield without even having to fight, because the populace will not support a tyrant or hegemon (*ba* Ba , a lord who rules by brute force). What is unique is Xunzi's emphasis on ritual as the key to a well-ordered state. To be sure, earlier writings had also discussed the idea of ritual as the foundation of statecraft, and the *Zuo Commentary to the Springs and Autumns* (*Zuozhuan* Zuo Chuan ), in particular, is famous for its scenes in which a ruler who is about to attack his neighbor publicly justifies his aggression on the grounds that he is merely "punishing" his enemy's intolerable violations of ritual. But Xunzi raises the significance of ritual to a new level: in his view, the ruler's ability to govern his state in accordance with ritual is the sole criterion that will determine success or failure on the battlefield (*Xunzi* 15.1c; see also *Xunzi* 16.1). Having established that "exalting ritual" (*longli* Long Li ) is the true path to order and strength, Xunzi expatiates in characteristic language: > > > When kings and dukes follow [the rituals], that is how they obtain the > world; when they do not follow them, that is how they bring about the > perdition of their altars of soil and grain. (*Xunzi* 15.4) > > > > Even advanced military technology is no match for a king who "exalts ritual and esteems morality". Accordingly, in two passages assessing the mighty state of Qin Qin --which would go on to unify the Chinese world under the infamous First Emperor (r. 221-210 BCE)--Xunzi acknowledged its power but diagnosed a correctible weakness: it lacked schooled moral advisors (like himself) to guide the ruler and save him from self-defeating avarice and aggression. Such counselors, moreover, should have a Confucian orientation (*Xunzi* 8.2-10 and 16.4-6). The judgment of most ancient writers is that Qin never corrected this weakness. ## 4. The Source of the Rituals: Heaven (*tian* Tian ) and the Way (*dao* Dao ) Xunzi places so much emphasis on the role of the rituals in moral self-cultivation that one might ask how the sages managed to perfect themselves when they did not have such a model themselves. A glimpse of the answer was already afforded by Xunzi's insistence that the rituals surpass any arbitrary code of conduct because they accord with fundamental human tendencies. But elsewhere the question is addressed more fully. The rituals, it turns out, are the equivalent of helpful signposts. Just as those who ford rivers "mark" (*biao* Biao ) treacherous spots, the sages "marked the Way" (*biao dao* Biao Dao ) by means of rituals, so that people would no longer stumble (*Xunzi* 17.11). The Way that Xunzi invokes in this simile is sometimes called "constancy" (*chang* Chang ). Heaven's processes (*tianxing* Tian Xing ) do not change from one epoch to the next;[7] thus one must learn how to respond to them with "the right order" (*zhi* Zhi ), whereafter it would be either ignorant or hypocritical to blame Heaven for one's misfortune. When a ruler governs a state well, there are bound to be good results; when a ruler governs a state badly, there are bound to be bad results. Disasters can have no long-term consequences because a well governed state will prosper even in the face of disasters, and a poorly governed state will be vanquished even if it avoids disasters altogether. (Xunzi's opinion of foreseeable natural disasters such as hurricanes would undoubtedly have been that they strike *all* states, but a well governed state will be prepared for such an event, whereas a poorly governed state will be in no position to respond to the crisis.) Consequently, Heaven plays a sure but indirect role in determining our fortune or misfortune. Heaven never intercedes directly in human affairs, but human affairs are certain to succeed or fail according to a timeless pattern that Heaven determined before human beings existed. "The revolutions of the sun, moon, and stars, and the cyclical calendar--these were the same under Yu Yu and Jie Jie " (*Xunzi* 17.4), he notes, referring to a paradigmatic sage king and tyrant, respectively. The same is true of the regular and predictable sequence of the seasons--a particularly significant example, as we shall see. Next, Xunzi makes a crucial distinction between knowing Heaven (*zhi tian* Zhi Tian ) and knowing the Way (*zhi dao* Zhi Dao ). The former is impossible, and therefore a waste of time to attempt, but the latter is open to all who try. To cite a modern parallel, it is not difficult to understand *how* the force of gravity works by carefully observing its effects in the phenomenal world, but to understand *why* gravity works is a different matter altogether. Xunzi would say that one should constrain one's inquiries to learning how gravity works, and then think about how to apply this irresistible force of nature to improve the lives of humankind (Fraser 2016: 297-300). His attitude was not scientific in our sense. Speaking of "those who are enlightened about the distinction between Heaven and human beings", he says: > > Their aspiration with respect to Heaven is no more than to observe the > phenomena that can be taken as regular periods (e.g., the progression > of the seasons or stars). Their aspiration with respect to Earth is no > more than to observe the matters that yield (sc. crops). Their > aspiration with respect to the four seasons is no more than to observe > the data that can be made to serve [humanity]. Their aspiration with > respect to *yin* Yin and *yang* Yang is no more > than to observe their harmonious [interactions] that can bring about > order. (*Xunzi* 17.3b) > Thus rituals are not merely received practices or convenient social institutions; they are practicable forms in which the sages aimed to encapsulate the fundamental patterns of the universe. No human being, not even a sage, can know Heaven, but we can know Heaven's Way, which is the surest path to a flourishing and blessed life. Because human beings have limited knowledge and abilities, it is difficult for us to attain this deep understanding, and therefore the sages handed down the rituals to help us follow in their footsteps. ## 5. Is the Way Discovered or Constructed? Although this discussion has presented the Way as an unchanging cosmological reality to which we must conform (or suffer the consequences), it is sometimes understood, rather, as having been constructed by human beings. A.C. Graham first raised this issue by asking, "Is Xunzi saying that man imposes his own meaning on an otherwise meaningless universe?" (Graham 1989: 243). Although Graham himself answered his question in the negative, others have since pressed the point further. This is probably the greatest controversy in Xunzi studies today. One passage, in particular, is frequently cited as support for a constructivist position (Hagen 2007: 11.n31; Tang 2016: 59, 75, 118): "The Way is not the Way of Heaven, nor the Way of Earth; it is what people regard as the Way, what the noble man is guided by" (*Xunzi* 8.3). This seems to say, despite what we have seen about apprehending the constancy of Heaven and then applying it profitably to daily life, that we are supposed to disregard the Way of Heaven, and create our own Way instead. The basic problem is that the surviving text of *Xunzi* is vague enough to permit various interpretations, but the repeated references to the importance of observing and appropriately "responding" (*ying* Ying ) to the seasons would seem to rule out the interpretation that natural patterns are not to be taken as normative. Yang Liang Yang Jing (fl. 818 CE), the author of the oldest extant commentary on *Xunzi*, evidently recognized this problem, and tried to soften the impact of *Xunzi* 8.3 by making it fit with the rest of the text: > > > This emphasizes that the Way of the Former Kings was not a matter of > *yin* and *yang*, or mountains and rivers, or omens and > prodigies, but the Way that people practice. > > > Yang Liang's opinion is surely not decisive: he was but an interpreter, not the master himself, and his glosses are not always regarded as the most compelling today. But in this case he may have been right that Xunzi meant to say no more than that the Way is to be found not in prodigies and other freakish occurrences, but in the "constancies" that people can put into practice. Indeed, the very notion that the Way of Heaven, the Way of Earth, and the Way of human beings are distinct entities would contradict the frequently reiterated point that there is only one Way, e.g., "There are no two Ways in the world, and the Sage is never of two minds" (*Xunzi* 21.1). This single and holistic Way, moreover, serves as the enduring standard for all times because all ramified truths of the universe are unified within it (*Xunzi* 5.5, 21.6b, and 22.6b). What we need to understand, then, is the Way *as it pertains to human beings*. Unusual celestial phenomena such as shooting stars must, theoretically, be explainable by a comprehensive formulation of the Way--there can be no *violations* of the Way in the natural world--but this is exactly why we do not aim for a comprehensive formulation of the Way (cf. Hutton 2016a: 81-83). We can safely ignore shooting stars as irrelevant to human beings because they do not provide replicable patterns for use in moral and social development. Responding to the seasons with timely planting and harvesting is, once again, a more productive model. ## 6. Portents (*yao* Xian ) In accordance with his notion of the Way as the observable "constancies" that can be profitably applied to human conduct, Xunzi argued strongly against the notion that weird occurrences on earth can be rationalized as monitory signs from Heaven. Superficially terrifying occurrences such as shooting stars or squalling trees are merely "shifts in Heaven and Earth, transformations of *yin* and *yang*, material anomalies" (*Xunzi* 17.7). We should be concerned instead with "human portents" (*renyao* Ren Xian ), a term that would have seemed as counterintuitive in Xunzi's language as it does in ours. "Human portents" are the many shortsighted and immoral acts through which human beings bring on their own destruction: "poor plowing that harms the harvest, hoeing and weeding out of season, governmental malice that causes the loss of the people" (*Xunzi* 17.7). Heaven has no part in such wrongdoing. Now and then strange things may happen in the skies, but they have happened at all moments in history, and they have never been sufficient to destroy a prudent and moral society--whereas an imprudent and immoral society will fail even if it is spared an eclipse. Xunzi even extends this theory of "human portents" to contend that religious ceremonies have no numinous effect; we carry them out merely for their inherent beauty and the social cohesion that they promote.[8] > > > If the sacrifice for rain [is performed], and it rains, what of it? I > say: It is nothing. Even if there had been no sacrifice, it would have > rained. ... Thus the noble man takes [these ceremonies] to be > embellishment, but the populace takes them to be spiritual. To take > them as embellishment is auspicious; to take them as spiritual is > inauspicious. (*Xunzi* 17.8) > > > ## 7. Rectifying Names (*zhengming* Zheng Ming ) Xunzi's famous essay on language, "Rectifying Names" ("Zhengming" Zheng Ming ) includes some impressive insights into the nature of verbal communication (William S-Y. Wang 1989: 186-89), but the primary concern of the chapter is morality, not linguistics (Fraser 2016: 293-96). The thrust of the essay is easily missed because a few of Xunzi's comments sound as though they came out of a modern pragmatics textbook, e.g., "Names have no inherent appropriateness. We designate them [by some word] in order to name them" (*Xunzi* 22.2g). Although this may sound like something that Ferdinand de Saussure (1857-1913) could have written, Xunzi was not interested in the same questions as modern linguists. In "Rectifying Names", Xunzi also discusses sophistic paradoxes that were rampant in his day (the most famous being "A white horse is not a horse"),[9] dividing them into three typological categories. His conclusion discloses that his main purpose is not a proper taxonomy of falsidical paradoxes (for this term, see Quine 1976: 3), but an assertion of the moral purpose of language: > > > All heretical theories and aberrant sayings depart from the correct > Way and are presumptuously crafted according to these three categories > of delusion. (*Xunzi* 22.3d) > > > The paradoxes of the sophists cannot be used as a basis for moral governance, and thus would be objectionable even if they were not in fact false; they are "disputes with no use" (*Xunzi* 6.6). The only legitimate purpose of language, like that of government itself, is to serve as the king's tool in propagating moral excellence: > > > When one who is a king determines names, if names are fixed and > realities distinguished, if the Way is practiced and his intentions > communicated, then he may cautiously lead the people and unify them by > this means. (*Xunzi* 22.1c) > > > The task of determining names and then enforcing their use belongs to the king alone, not to any lord and certainly not to the people. "One who is a king" (*wangzhe* Wang Zhe ) refers not to the person who happens to be sitting on the throne, but someone who has lived up to the moral requirements of that office and duly rules the world by his charismatic example. Accordingly, a phrase like "leading and unifying the people" refers not to expedient rulership, but to implementing the Confucian project of morally transforming the world. Language is useful in that enterprise because, without it, the people could not even understand the ruler's wishes, let alone carry them out. Just as the rituals need to be based on the foundation of the Way, the ruler's names, though they can be arbitrary as designations, must correspond to reality. You can make up the word for "reality", but you cannot make up reality. "Same and different" (*tongyi* Tong Yi ) are distinguished by the so-called "Heaven-endowed bureaux" (*tianguan* Tian Guan ), i.e. the eyes, ears, mouth, nose, body, and heart-mind. For most of these, we might say "senses" or "sense organs" in English, but the heart-mind (*xin* Xin ) is an exceptional case, for it is said to be able to distinguish "statements, reasons, happiness, resentment, grief, joy, love, hate, and desire" (*Xunzi* 22.d), which are not simply sense data. The heart-mind will be treated more fully in the next section. The suggestion that we rely upon our senses to perceive the world around us represents a substantial claim on Xunzi's part, because other philosophers had already suggested that reality is not straightforwardly discerned; on the contrary, one's partial perspective on reality necessarily informs one's perception of it. This was, essentially, the argument in "Discourse on the Equality of Things" ("Qiwu lun" Qi Wu Lun ), an important chapter in *Zhuangzi* Zhuang Zi (e.g., Graham 1989: 176-83). For Xunzi, however, reality is reality, regardless of how we perceive it. Once again, some scholars (e.g., Hagen 2007: 59-84) question whether Xunzi is such a strong realist, but a constructivist interpretation is difficult to reconcile with Xunzi's repeated assertions that language must conform to reality and the Way, e.g., "Names are that by which one defines different real objects" (*Xunzi* 22.3f). ## 8. The Heart-Mind (*xin*) In many respects, the heart-mind is the keystone of Xunzi's philosophy, the one piece that links together all the others. The Chinese word *xin* means "heart", but Xunzi attributes such strong and varied mental processes to this organ that one has to construe it as not only the heart but also the mind. (The mind was not located in the brain in premodern Chinese philosophy.) First, the heart-mind is the organ that we use to discover the Way. Xunzi's discussion of Heaven presents his argument that moral self-cultivation is a matter of correctly perceiving and then applying the Way, but does not explain how we perceive the Way in the first place. Elsewhere, he states explicitly that we come "to know the Way" by means of our heart-mind (*Xunzi* 21.5d), which has three cardinal attributes: "emptiness" (*xu* Xu ) "unity" (*yi* Yi ), and "tranquility" (*jing* Jing ). Xunzi patently borrowed these three terms from earlier discourse, particularly *Zhuangzi* (e.g., Yearley 1980; Goldin 1999: 22-31; Stalnaker 2003), and uses them to denote three nurturable faculties that we all possess from birth, but do not employ to the same degree. (The title of the relevant chapter, "Resolving Blindness", refers to the self-destructive acts that people undertake because they fail to employ their heart-minds correctly.) "Emptiness" refers to the heart-mind's ability to store a seemingly unlimited amount of information: we do not have to erase one datum in order to make room for another. "Unity" refers to the heart-mind's ability to synthesize diverse data into meaningful paradigms. And "tranquility" refers to the heart-mind's ability to distinguish fantasy from rational thinking. Armed with these powers, we can infer the patterns of the Way by taking in, and then pondering, the data transmitted to the heart-mind by the senses. In addition, the heart-mind is the chief among the organs. It is the only organ that can command the others; indeed, it is the only organ with any self-consciousness. "The mind is the lord of the body ... It issues commands but does not receive commands" (*Xunzi* 21.6a). Because the heart-mind can control both itself and all other organs of the body, it is the font of "artifice", or the deliberate actions that begin to transform the morally deficient *xing*: "When the heart-mind reasons and the other faculties put it into action--this is called 'artifice'" (*Xunzi* 22.1b). The heart-mind is capable of overriding every human impulse, even the instinct of self-preservation, if it conflicts with the correct "patterns" (*li* Li ).[10] We have the necessary faculties to recognize immorality when we see it, and if we permit ourselves to tread an immoral path, we cannot blame our emotions or desires, but must accept that our heart-mind has failed to exert the requisite discipline. We know that we could have done better. Indeed, when we speak of "we", we are speaking of our heart-mind. For the heart-mind is the crucible where these teeming moral deliberations take place. Thus Xunzi ends, like all Confucians, with individual responsibility: in his case, the heart-mind's obligation to process the principles of the Way and then command the rest of the body to conform. Because we are not sages, we are advised to follow the rituals in order to attain this degree of understanding, but, fundamentally, the path to morality is open to anyone who sees and thinks (*Xunzi* 8.11 and 23.5b). Xunzi's conception of the heart-mind also figures in a distinctive congruence that he postulates between a kingdom and a human being. A kingdom possesses an initial set of features--it may be large or small, rich or poor, hilly or flat--but these are immaterial to its ultimate success or failure, for any territory, however small, provides enough of a base for a sage to conquer the world. Thus it is the management of the state, and not its natural resources, that determine whether it will become the demesne of a king or be conquered by its neighbors. This management, furthermore, comprises two elements: a proper method, namely the rituals of the sage kings; and a decisive agent, namely the lord, who chooses either to adopt the rituals or unwisely discard them. In much the same way, human beings are made up of two parts: their *xing*, or detestable initial condition, and *wei*, their conscious conduct. They may reform themselves or they may remain detestable: this depends entirely on their conduct. The management of the self, just like the management of the state, comprises two elements: a proper method, which is, once again, the rituals of the sage kings; and a decisive agent, which chooses either to adopt the rituals or unwisely discard them. This agent, the analogue of the lord of a state, is the heart-mind (Goldin 1999: 16-17).[11] As in the Broadway song, "It's not where you start; it's where you finish" (Fields *et al*. 1973 [1975: 54]). ## 9. Xunzi's Reception after His Death At[12] the end of his life, Xunzi was the leading teacher and philosopher in the Chinese world. Among his former students were some of the most influential men in politics, including Han Fei Han Fei (d. 233 BCE), Li Si Li Si (d. 208 BCE), and Zhang Cang Zhang Cang (ca. 250-151 BCE), as well as transmitters of several leading redactions of canonical texts, including Fuqiu Bo Fu Qiu Bo and perhaps Mao Heng Mao Heng (Goldin 1999: xii). The early Han Han dynasty statesman Lu Jia Lu Jia (ca. 228-ca. 140 BCE) is sometimes said to have been Xunzi's student as well (e.g., by Tang Yan Tang Yan [1857-1920] in Wang Liqi 1986: 222-23), but the two men's dates make this relationship unlikely. Perhaps Lu Jia was a disciple of Fuqiu Bo, and thus an intellectual grandson of Xunzi. Regardless, the strongest evidence of Lu Jia's indebtedness to Xunzi lies on the level of ideas (Li Dingfang 1980). Like Xunzi, Lu Jia appealed to the classics, the sages' textual legacy, as the best practical guide to government and moral self-cultivation (Puett 2002: 253-54; Jin Chunfeng 2006: 73-74). But Lu's most important philosophical thesis is that human beings bring about auspicious and inauspicious omens through their own actions. Xunzi, we recall, argued strongly against the belief in Heavenly portents. Lu Jia accepted Xunzi's framework, but with a single, consequential innovation: people bring about their own fortune or misfortune by emitting *qi* Qi : > > > Thus when societies fail and the Way is lost, it is not the work of > Heaven. The lord of the state has done something to cause it. Bad > government breeds bad *qi*; bad *qi* breeds disasters > and abnormalities. (Wang Liqi 1986: 155) > > > By adding the element of *qi*--a term that Xunzi rarely used, and certainly did not build into his metaphysics--Lu Jia retains Xunzi's volitionless and mechanistic Heaven but forges a novel philosophical justification for the arcane science of omenology, which Xunzi mercilessly deprecated. Where Xunzi counseled us to ignore abnormalities, Lu Jia accepts their validity as "admonitions" (*jie* Jie ). But, once again, Heaven itself has no effect on our success or failure. If we are faced with a host of wood-boring caterpillars, to use Lu's vivid example, the only way to account for them is to acknowledge that our government is responsible for their generation through its maleficent conduct (Zhou Guidian 1999: 51-53; Puett 2002: 249-52). Two coeval philosophers, Jia Yi Jia Yi (201-169 BCE) and Dong Zhongshu Dong Zhong Shu (ca. 198-ca. 107 BCE), agreed that human beings are responsible for their own fortune or misfortune, and thus have no cause to blame Heaven, although Jia Yi did not refer to *qi* in prosecuting his theory, whereas Dong Zhongshu did (Goldin 2007). Dong Zhongshu is reported to have written a paean to Xunzi (now lost), and writers of late antiquity, such as Wang Chong Wang Chong (27-ca. 100 CE) and Ban Gu Ban Gu (32-92 CE), still took him seriously as a philosopher. But thereafter, Xunzi's star began to set. In later centuries, the two tirelessly repeated cliches about Xunzi were that he propagated the anti-Mencian doctrine that human nature is evil, and that, by serving as Li Si's and Han Fei's teacher, he furthered the cause of Legalism (*fajia* Fa Jia ) and thus subverted high-minded principles. Ji Kang Ji Kang (223-262), for example, obliquely identified Xunzi as the chief architect of everything that Ji and his group disdained: artificial ritualism, counterfeit erudition, and an oppressive network of laws that serve only to interfere with the innocuous enjoyment of life (Goldin 2007: 140-42). By the Tang Tang dynasty, even literati who admired Xunzi--such as Han Yu Han Yu (768-824)--were careful to add that his works contain grave mistakes (Kong Fan 1997: 281; Liu Youming 2006: 48-50). In the Song Song , there were still some voices that praised him, but the opinion with the greatest long-term consequences was that of Zhu Xi Zhu Xi (1130-1200), who declared that Xunzi's philosophy resembled those of non-Confucians such as Shen Buhai Shen Bu Hai (fl. 354-340 BCE) and Shang Yang Shang Yang (d. 338 BCE), and that he was indirectly responsible for the notorious disasters of the Qin dynasty (Kong Fan 1997: 291-95). For the rest of imperial history, Xunzi was rejected by the cultural mainstream;[13] into the twentieth century, he was criticized by intellectuals such as Kang Youwei Kang You Wei (1858-1927), Tan Sitong Tan Si Tong (1865-1898), and Liang Qichao Liang Qi Chao (1873-1929) as the progenitor of the Confucian scriptural legacy, which, in their view, had derailed the original Confucian mission and plunged China into a cycle of authoritarianism and corruption that lasted more than two thousand years. Today the tide has reversed almost completely. Xunzi is one of the most popular philosophers throughout East Asia, and has been the subject of a large number of books published over the past two decades. From a twenty-first-century perspective, this revival of interest in Xunzi is not hard to explain: his body of work has always been one of the best preserved, and with the commonplace scholastic objections to his philosophy having lost most of their cogency, it is only to be expected that philosophical readers should be attracted to his creative but rigorous arguments. In this sense one could say that Xunzi has finally been restored, more than two millennia after his death, to his erstwhile position as *zui wei lao shi*.
yorck
## 1. Yorck's Life Count Paul Yorck von Wartenburg was born in Berlin on March 1, 1835. His grandfather was the famous Field Marshal Hans David Ludwig Yorck von Wartenburg. (The Field Marshal's courageous signing of the Convention of Tauroggen, originally unauthorized by the king and thus in effect treasonous, started the Prussian War of Liberation against Napoleon in 1813. It made the Field Marshal Yorck a national hero.) Paul Yorck's father, Ludwig David Yorck von Wartenburg, managed the family's estate at Klein-Oels in Silesia (near Breslau, today Wroklaw) where Paul Yorck grew up. Paul Yorck's parents were well-connected to a number of literary, philosophical, and artistic circles in Berlin and elsewhere. They were acquainted with Friedrich Schleiermacher, Ludwig Tieck, Bettina von Arnim, Alexander von Humboldt, Karl August Varnhagen, Johann Gustav Droysen, Karl Friedrich Schinkel, and Ernst von Wildenbruch, to name but a few. The family Yorck von Wartenburg belonged to the dominant elite in Prussia and the German Empire. Yorck's life-long enthusiasm for history and historical reality must be seen against this biographical background. In 1855 Paul Yorck began his university studies in law at Bonn, but soon moved to the university at Breslau where he also enrolled in philosophy courses. After passing the second law exam, Yorck published his exam essay "The Catharsis of Aristotle and Sophocles' Oedipus of Colonus" (Yorck 1866), the only publication by him during his lifetime. When his father passed away in 1865 Yorck took over the management of the family estate at Klein-Oels. He also assumed his father's hereditary seat in the Prussian Upper Chamber [*Herrenhaus*] where he participated in political debates. He took part in the Franco-Prussian war (1870-1871); and he was present at the Proclamation of the German Empire in the Hall of Mirrors at the Palace of Versailles in 1871. In the same year Yorck met Dilthey, who had been called to the University at Breslau. They quickly became friends and Dilthey was a frequent guest at Klein-Oels, often staying for prolonged working holidays. The posthumously published Dilthey-Yorck *Correspondence* (Yorck 1923) is an impressive testimony to this friendship. From the early 1890s Yorck worked on a manuscript on Heraclitus (Yorck 1896/97) and a book about the *Stances of Consciousness and History* (Yorck 1892-1897).[1] Before his death, Yorck declared the two works unfinished and not ready for publication. Published only posthumously, they are, in the words of Karlfried Grunder (1970, 55), "sketches" of first drafts for "great philosophical books." Paul Yorck died at Klein-Oels, September 12, 1897. His grandson, Count Peter Yorck, who had studied Yorck's unfinished works, was a leading member of the Kreisauer Circle, the German resistance cell responsible for the failed attempt to assassinate Hitler on July 20, 1944. ## 2. Correspondence with Dilthey When in 1923 the *Correspondence* between Yorck and Dilthey (Yorck 1923) (abbreviated hereafter as CR) was published as "a memorial" to their philosophical friendship (CR, VI), it established Yorck not only as an equal to Dilthey and a faithful interlocutor and eager co-worker on Dilthey's project(s),[2] but also as a philosopher and keen observer of his times in his own right. In 1892 Yorck writes to Dilthey: > > > Our time portends something of an end of an epoch. A token of this is > the disappearance of the elemental pleasure in historical realities. > The feeling that everything passes [*Gefuhl der > Verganglichkeit*] haunts the world once again. (CR, p. > 140) > > > Dilthey clearly shares this sentiment. In a more extensive note about the same topic Yorck writes: > > > It is my growing conviction that today we stand at a historical > turning point similar to the one of the 15th century. In > contradistinction to the scientific-technological progress, which > consists in increased abstraction and isolation, a new formation comes > into being because the human being in his entirety [*der ganze > Mensch*] once again takes a stand and faces the problems of life. > Every time it is a new stance towards life [*Lebensstellung*] > and a new conception of it that ushers in a new epoch, not any old > discovery or invention, even if it is of the greatest import. The > thread on which science hangs has become so long and spun ever so > thin, that now it is snapping in the face of the impetuous question: > What is truth? (CR, p. 128) > > > In yet another letter, Yorck claims that, since the Renaissance, science and knowledge--abstracted from feeling and volition--have followed an eccentric trajectory, in which they have lost sight of man, resulting in profound self-alienation: > > > The ripple effects caused by the eccentric principle, which ushered in > a new age more than four hundred years ago, seem to me to have become > exceedingly broad and flat; knowledge has advanced to the point of > nullifying itself, and man has become so far removed from himself that > he no longer catches sight of himself. 'Modern' man, that > is, man since the Renaissance, is fit for the grave. (CR, p. 83) > > > The general thrust of these reflections and the language used are reminiscent of Nietzsche's descriptions of the "uncanniest of all guests," nihilism. In fact, it is the usually so cautious Dilthey who, in one of his last letters to Yorck, remarks that the true but "horrible word about the age has been announced" by no one other than Nietzsche (CR, p. 238). There is no reason to believe that Yorck would have disagreed. Yorck's and Dilthey's awareness of an epochal shift, written some twenty years before World War I, could not fail to impress the generation of students who, in the aftermath of this European catastrophe, their predicament exacerbated by continued economic hardship and hyperinflation, returned to studying philosophy in the early 1920s. This may explain why, much later, in the 1980s, Gadamer would still speak of the enormous significance of the publication of the Dilthey-Yorck correspondence in 1923, calling it an "epoch-making moment" in its own right (Gadamer 1995, p. 8). According to Yorck, the analysis and evaluation of the contemporary intellectual-historical situation is integral to philosophy--all the more so if philosophy self-reflexively grasps its ineluctably historical nature, which in itself is one of Yorck's main philosophical interests. The basic idea for the historicity of philosophy is fairly straightforward. For Yorck, as for Dilthey, philosophy is "a manifestation of life" [*Lebensmanifestation*] (CR, p. 250), a product or an expression in which life articulates itself in a certain way. But all life is intrinsically historical. Life is inconceivable without its historical development. Yorck writes: > > > The entire given psycho-physical reality is not something that > *is*, but something that lives: that is the germ cell of > historicity. And self-reflection, which is directed not at an abstract > I, but the entirety of my own self, will find that I am historically > determined, just as physics grasps me as determined by the cosmos. > Just as I am nature, I am history. And in this decisive sense we have > to understand Goethe's dictum of [our] having lived > [*Gelebthaben*] for at least three thousand years. Conversely, > it follows that history as a scientific discipline exists only as > psychology of history. (CR 71/72) > > > For Yorck, as for Dilthey, human life is incorrectly understood if it is subsumed under the generic catch-all category of "existence." The first point is that human life is inconceivable without temporal and historical development, movement, and change; life always transcends itself, hence it never simply "is." The mode of being for humans is "life," not "existence."[3] And life, unlike existence, is intrinsically historical. Precisely this distinction is brought home by Yorck's demand to always observe "the generic difference between the ontic and the historical" (CR, p. 191). The ontic is what is simply "there" without inner life, temporality, or history. It includes the physical entities in the world, as well as abstract objects, numbers, essences, ideas, etc. The "ontic" is *toto caelo* other than "the historical." Yorck's second point is that all history is a development of human powers or *human psychology*, where psychology does not mean some inert or fixed "nature," but the constant play of forces, the ever shifting configurations between understanding, affectivity, and volition. (See Section 3.1 below.) In addition, Yorck emphasizes the "virtuality" or "effectivity" of history, i.e., the cumulative effects and results of individual persons exerting power and influence in transmitting the possibility and conception of life to their descendants. Successor-generations develop their own stance towards life in response to what they have inherited from the individuals and generations preceding them. History is the ongoing transmission of life's potentiality, including the transmission of power, ideas, and material conditions. > > > The child gains through the mother's sacrifice, her sacrifice > benefits the child. Without such virtual transmission of power > [*Kraftubertragung*] there is no history at all. (CR, p. > 155) > > > Yorck does not refer to some anonymous bio-power or power structures, as discussed in contemporary philosophy, but to the authority, sacrifice, and direct action and communication through which an individual person or groups of persons form and shape the lives and behaviours of coming generations. It is for this reason that Yorck insists that "person" is the key historical category (CR, p. 109). History is the history of historical, individual agents, projecting their power and authority into the future. Since Yorck understands history as a connecting band of ideas and conditions passed on from one person to another, and indeed from one generation to another, his position must not be associated with historicism. For Yorck, there is one continuous and common line of historical life--a living *syndesmos*. Past generations and past persons are not "outside" a present horizon in a past world of their own. Rather, they live on, as it were, in their descendents. Moreover, because of this connecting band, one can go "backwards" by way of what Yorck calls "transposition" (CR, p. 61), transposing oneself into the lives of others and thus "re-enacting," as Dilthey would say, the positions towards life that have been lived by one's predecessors. That life is historical means that each person is always already outside his or her own individual "nature" and placed within the historical connection to predecessor- and successor-generations. For Yorck, living self-consciousness is, to use Hegel's fortuitous phrase, "the *I* that is *we* and the *we* that is *I*" (Hegel 1807, p. 140). Consequently, Yorck rejects from the start the transcendental method in philosophy as insufficient for grasping lived historical reality. Transcendental philosophy reduces historical life to the merely "subjective," which misses the genuine characteristic of *Geist*, spirit or mind, namely its real, historical extension and connection. As Yorck puts it, "the transcendental method" merely suspends or sublates "the realm of the objective," but it fails to "extend the region of *Geist*" (CR, p. 194). Insisting that "the character of subjectivity does not even reach the realm of *Geist*" (CR, p. 194), Yorck clearly implies that the "realm of history" is the proper domain for *Geist*. It follows that, despite his criticism of the narrow confines of transcendental and/or subject-centred philosophy, Yorck's philosophical conception of history is still inscribed within the confines of *Geist*-philosophy. Following Hegel, who argues that everything hinges on the understanding that "substance is subject" (Hegel 1807, p. 19), Yorck agrees that everything hinges on the understanding that "substance is history" or "substance is historical spirit."[4] Yorck's primary category of historical life does not only challenge transcendental philosophy as too-narrow a foothold for philosophy. *A fortiori*, it also challenges the entire metaphysical tradition, which presupposes or searches for an ultimate objective reality (being, idea, substance, and so on), divorced from the ground of the always shifting historical life. Yorck rejects claims to "knowledge" *sub specie aeternitatis*. For Yorck, metaphysics is a flight from the historical reality 'on the ground.' By making historical life primary, Yorck effectively aims to dismantle the predominance of Greek metaphysics, including the modes of thought of modern science derived from it. But Yorck is not content with just opposing metaphysics and transcendental philosophy. Instead, he attempts to instill and to cultivate historical awareness in philosophy itself, based on the principle that all productions of life are as historical as life itself. He writes: Since "to philosophize is to live," "there is no real philosophizing which would not be historical" (CR, p. 251). More radical than Dilthey, Yorck calls for the "historicization" [*Vergeschichtlichung*] of philosophy: > > > Just as physiology cannot abstract from physics, so > philosophy--especially if it is critical--cannot abstract > from historicity [*Geschichtlichkeit*]. After all, the > uncritical *Critique* of Kant's can be understood > historically only, and thus be overcome. [Human] behaviour and > historicity are like breathing and air pressure--and--this > may sound somewhat paradoxical--the failure to historicize > philosophizing appears to me, in methodological respects, a > metaphysical remnant. (CR, 69) > > > It is therefore not surprising that, unlike Dilthey, Yorck specifically appreciates the emphasis on historicity [*Geschichtlichkeit*][5] in Hegel and some of his followers, despite his rejection of Hegel's speculative or ontical superstructure (CR, 59).[6] In light of the historical nature of philosophy, Yorck draws two decisive methodological inferences. First, he rejects as too rigid and untenable the opposition between theoretical or systematic philosophy and the history of ideas (CR, p. 251), because, as an ongoing historical development, philosophy always requires both a genetic and historical clarification, as well as a systematic and theoretical account. Instead of a mutually exclusive relation, Yorck sees a mutually productive combination. Second, because Yorck always includes the present situation within the domain of history, he calls for a "critical," and not "antiquarian," or quietistic mode of philosophizing (CR, p. 19). Speaking for Dilthey and himself, Yorck argues that this critical work of philosophy lays the groundwork for the practical intent or the historical vocation of philosophy: > > > The potential for practical application is of course the real > justification for any science. Yet mathematical *praxis* is not > the only kind. In practical terms, our standpoint is pedagogical in > intent, in the broadest and deepest sense of the word. It is the soul > of all true philosophy and the truth of Plato and Aristotle. (CR, pp. > 42/ 43) > > > In the condensed and all too general format of the *Correspondence* with Dilthey, Yorck develops the practical "application" of philosophy in only the most fragmentary fashion. Its most important part is the actual clarification of the contemporary situation, the determination of the given historical possibilities, and the avenues for implementing some of them. Yorck holds that since the Renaissance and through the works of such thinkers as Galileo, Descartes, and Hobbes, the self-interpretation of life has found its centre of gravity in the cultivation of the theoretical understanding [*Verstand*]. The primacy accorded to theoretical understanding and what it projects as objective, unchangeable, and ultimate reality (metaphysical & physical) has ushered in "the natural sciences," "nominalism," "rationalism," and "mechanism," (CR, pp. 68, 63 & 155). But this has come at the exclusion of the full thematization, expression, and appreciation of human affectivity [*Gefuhl*], including the underlying feeling of human connectivity through a shared life in history. Blocked-out are questions which affect the temporal, historical and personal existence of human beings, or what Yorck once calls "existential questions" [*Existenzialfragen*] (CR, p. 62), which relate to the life-goals human beings strive after, the recognition of dependency, and the awareness of human mortality, finitude, and death (CR, p. 120). The relative sidelining of these aspects in the psychology of human beings lies at the bottom of Yorck's diagnosis of the increasing self-alienation of modern man and the crisis of his time. With Dilthey, Yorck attempts to highlight the "full human being" [*den ganzen Menschen*] (CR, p. 157), as opposed to the rationalistically reduced, one-dimensional individual that has preoccupied modern philosophy and shaped modern culture. The historicization of philosophy belongs to this project, as does the acknowledgment of transcendence. According to Yorck, transcendence (CR, pp. 120, 144) facilitates the withdrawal from the world in its objective reality (as represented by thought and metaphysics). It lets human life pivot around the personal, historical, and affective dimension, foregrounding personal responsibility and accountability to the transcendent God. Against the theoretical-metaphysical stance directed at an ever present objective reality, Yorck insists on the primacy of the personal, historical relation to the transcendent God. Yorck's dictum "Transcendence contra metaphysics!" expresses not only a very strong leitmotif in his philosophical thought (CR, p. 42); it is actually the very capstone.[7] For this reason, Yorck has been interpreted as a religious existentialist (Kaufmann, 1928). This sets him apart from Dilthey. Yorck's conception of Christianity is heavily biased in favour of Luther's theology. According to Yorck, Luther's anti-metaphysical, historical stance towards transcendence remains a historical task for the future development of philosophy (CR, pp. 144 & 145). Since Yorck frequently and conspicuously uses the term *Bodenlosigkeit* [groundlessness], or *bodenloses Denken* [groundless thought] to describe the one-sided intellectualism of the scientific-technological civilization since the Renaissance (CR, pp. 39, 103, 250, 230, 143), questions have been raised about Yorck's preference for autochthony [*Bodenstandigkeit*] and the political implications thereof.[8] ## 3. Philosophical Fragments on History and Psychology More than half a century after his death, three philosophical fragments by Yorck--originally written in the last six years of his life--were published between 1956 and 1970 (see the Bibliography). The most important is entitled *Bewusstseinsstellung und Geschichte* ["Stances of Consciousness and History"] (abbreviated hereafter as ST). It addresses the sources and the development of human history, providing the philosophical underpinning and more detailed exploration of views that Yorck had mentioned in his *Correspondence* with Dilthey. The following section presents the major points of this systematic fragment. Yorck's main aim is to provide an analysis of the underlying psychology of human life, which he considers the basis for all historical development. According to Yorck, particular configurations in the psychology of man, or stances of consciousness, determine the dominant shape of historical epochs. In other words, certain positions adopted on the level of "primary life" [*primare Lebendigkeit*], the stances taken by consciousness within life, determine "historical life" [*historische Lebendigkeit*] at large and can define entire epochs (ST, p. 5; also pp. 52, 53). Therefore, Yorck speaks of the "psychology of history" and, the "philosophic history of philosophy" (which traces the stances of consciousness through empirical history) (ST, p. 10). All this is predicated on the supposition of our intuitive access to psychological or primary life through "self-reflection" [*Selbstbesinnung*]. Yorck interprets Dilthey's insight that one cannot go beyond life to mean that one cannot surpass or transcend "the empirical givenness of self-consciousness," which entails that philosophy is "empirical," not speculative (ST, pp. 8, 3). Evidence can only be found in self-consciousness. What does not pass the test in one's own life cannot count as a valid expression of life: The seat of all necessary truth is "self-experimentation" (ST, 9, also 54).[9] Not unlike Husserl, Yorck pursues, albeit without an elaborate set of methodological rules, a "re-duction" of all objectivity to self-consciousness, where self-consciousness is a living and historical structure that cannot be restricted to knowing or any other particular function of life. As Gadamer (1990, pp. 246-269) has pointed out, despite his critique of transcendental philosophy, Yorck may be read as actually expanding the transcendental focus, which traditionally used to be on knowing, so as to include the entire gamut of human experiences and their necessary conditions in human *life*. Following Dilthey, Yorck sees human consciousness as a living structure where the emphasis lies on its "aliveness," *Lebendigkeit*, which includes not only outward-directed intentionality towards objectivity (representation and volition), but also self-awareness, and self-feeling of inner life. Close to Schleiermacher, Yorck even specifies that "the ultimate datum" in self-consciousness is "the feeling of life" [*Lebensgefuhl*] itself (ST, p. 11). ### 3.1 Psychology of Life According to Yorck, life is divided and articulated in itself, namely as an ongoing process of self-differentiation relative to others and the environment. Yorck writes: > > > The primary and exclusive datum is self-consciousness, which, although > divided [*dirimiert*] into self and other, soul and lived body > [*Leib*], I and world, inner and outer, is nonetheless, > polarity [*Gegensatzlichkeit*] and articulateness > [*Gegliedertheit*] in one. But self-consciousness experiences > itself in the play and counter-play of its constitutive factors, that > is, as something alive [*ein Lebendiges*]. This aliveness is > the basic constitution. (ST, p. 8) > > > But there is no way that this aliveness can ever be grasped in its purity outside the fundamental differentiation. The antithetical division in "self" and "other" is so fundamental that one cannot go back behind it. > > > The separation [*Trennung*] of self and other, I and world, > soul and lived body [*Leib*] is such an early separation, > indeed, the first act of life, as it were, such that these derivatives > appear as absolute, autonomous, and self-sufficient. (ST, pp. > 11/12) > > > Yorck concludes: "The self is only through the other, just as the other is only through the self" (ST, p. 11). Yet "life" remains the primary datum for Yorck. Reminiscent of German Idealism, particularly Hegel and Holderlin, Yorck understands life as "differentiated unity" [*differenzierte Einheitlichkeit*] (ST, p. 38). Life explicates itself in form of an inner division and polarity. Each stance of life is a particular configuration of life's original division [*Urtheil* or *Urtheilung*] (ST, p. 25). Yorck writes: > > > Observation shows that primary life manifests a double diremption into > [1] polarity [*Gegensatzlichkeit*] and [2] difference > [*Verschiedenheit*], such that the character of polarity > permeates and determines the elements of the articulation. (ST, p. > 10) > > > Life *articulates* or expresses itself *differently* in three "functions" or "comportments" [*Verhaltungen*], as life is lived in [1] "feeling" [*Empfinden*] or affectivity, [2] "willing" [*Wollen*], and [3] "cognizing" [*Vorstellen*] (ST, 32). Life is *divided* between the two antithetical or opposite poles of spontaneity and dependence (ST, p. 9), which, applied to the different comportments or functions of life, yields [1] the tension between motivation and spontaneity in volition, [2] the opposition in cognition between objective, matter-of-fact representation [*Sachlichkeit*] and spontaneous projection of formed images [*Bildlichkeit*] as the object of knowledge, and [3] the polarity between dependence on others versus ownness [*Eigenheit*] in the domain of affectivity (ST, p. 32). Yorck claims that the three psychological "functions" or comportments circumscribe the fixed and unalterable "natural ground" [*Naturboden*], or the parameters within which all human history is played out (ST, p. 26). There is no history without such fixed reference points. The economy of the three functions is not fixed (unlike the functions as such), but is always open to the play of shifting configurations and imbalances (ST, p. 24 & 54). More specifically, the three functions are neither reducible to each other nor derivable from another source, making them in effect equiprimordial. However, they stand in a variable and inverse relationship to each other, where the relative preponderance of one function is offset by the relative subordination of the remaining ones, but at no time can any particular function be cancelled out altogether (ST, p. 98). This inverse relationship, coupled with the internal polarity within each function, accounts for "the restlessness of primary life" (ST, p. 32). Since life does not exist in some generality, but only as a particular configuration or alignment of its functions, the overall "totality" of the shape of a particular life is always determined by a pre-dominant position of one of its functions (ST, p. 55). This onesidedness, which necessarily fails to express life in its "entire fullness"[10] (ST, p. 54), results in the instability of each particular shape of consciousness. Each real configuration of consciousness and its particular bias to one function, as well as one of the antithetical poles within, lends itself to a new transformation, without ever reaching a stable or final state. Since "historical life" is nothing other than "primary life" writ large, Yorck holds that this inbuilt instability and restlessness in primary life also constitutes the "motor of history" (ST, 33). (See Section 3.2 below.) Yorck holds that two functions of life, willing and cognition, are "eccentric;" they pursue objects that are projected outside the felt interiority of self-consciousness (ST, p. 120). Concerning representation or cognition, Yorck writes: > > > Self-reflection reveals representation [*Vorstellen*] as an act > of exteriorization, as a projection, which therefore is primarily > marked by its opposition to feeling. The feature of projection, > [i.e.,] expulsion from within [*innere Entfernen*], being the > characteristic element of all representation, is spatialization > [*Verraumlichung*] as such. (ST, p. 70) > > > Spatialization is thus necessary for representation or the work of the understanding, thought. By contrast, temporality (located in affectivity) is not at all necessary for cognition or representation: > > > Thought can abstract from temporality. Indeed, every act of thought > contains [...] an abstraction from [temporality], inasmuch as > thought involves an expropriation [of inner feeling]. By contrast, > spatiality is the precondition of all > thought.[11] > (ST, p. 147) > > > All thought is inherently spatial, representing objects at a distance in space: "Spatiality is the basic character of all thought" (ST, p. 119). According to Yorck, thought or cognition may abstract from particular characters of space, such as "direction" and "place," but it cannot do without the projective opening of spatiality as such (ST, p. 100). And Yorck suggests that it is the inherent spatiality in all thought which, within the intellectualist tradition of the West, has rendered "space" an unsurpassable "metaphysical" reality, or transcendental condition of reality as such (ST, p. 100). Since thought or cognition is an achievement of life in abstraction from temporality and feeling, space itself appears as eternal, neutral exteriority. Yorck emphasizes that cognition of objects in space amounts to an act of "liberation," because what has been "placed" at a "psychological distance" in the realm of an eternal, and neutral objectivity has lost its power over the representing subject, has no impact on the person's affectivity, and can no longer excite the feeling that everything passes away (ST, p. 74). There is thus a positive correlation between cognition and volition. Cognitive projection is already an attempt to gain a foothold relative to "the flight of impressions, appearances, and strivings," and the fixation of an object in space goes hand in hand with the search for self-constancy and "self-affirmation" [*Selbstbehauptung*] (ST, p. 66). Therefore, Yorck holds that philosophy and science, as cognitive comportments in life, are rooted in the striving for self-affirmation. He thus attributes an eminent ethical impetus to them. "Freedom" and "autonomy" are the psychological motivation for philosophy and science (ST, p. 42). In contrast to cognition and volition, which are "eccentric" and directed towards the "outer," feeling or affectivity [*Gefuhl* or *Empfindung*] is the awareness of inwardness or interiority. Yorck writes: "The essence of the inner [*des Innen*] is feeling [*Empfindung*]" (ST, p. 71). At the limit, feeling is object-less and an immersion in subjective life. As Yorck explains, feelings are only secondarily attached to objects. Pain or pleasure, for instance, has no "representational content" [*Vorstellungsinhalt*]. Yorck writes: When "I feel, I stay within me" (ST, 71)--*chez moi*, *bei mir*. Feeling is only minimally projective. However, since polarity permeates all psychological functions, Yorck is quick to recognize "a relation" to the other, for there is no "inner" without an "outer."[12] But the centre of feeling or affectivity is the sphere of one's own, pure interiority, not as representation, but as something felt. Therefore, it is the actual seat of "all things personal" [*alles Personliche*], the innermost centre of personal life (ST, p. 85). It is the "central" and immediate pulse of life, antecedent to the objectifications by cognition and volition (ST, p. 14). Yorck writes: "The relation of self to feeling is more immediate" than the subject's relation to representation (ST, p. 99). Since the personal is something *felt* in the interiority of one's life, and not something *thought* or represented and projected outwards, Yorck concludes that self-relation is not cognitive in the first place; it is not "knowledge" (ST, p. 72). Therefore, Yorck also finds it a misguided effort "to grasp natural and historical communities by means of representation," because it misses the felt personal attachment, which alone lends reality to the historical connectivity and relation (ST, p. 72). Already in the *Correspondence*, Yorck had stated that "historical reality is a reality of feeling [*Empfindungsrealitat*]" (CR, p. 113). Next, Yorck also claims that "time originates in feeling" (ST, p. 135). But as feeling is non-projective, it follows that, originally, "temporality" is not "objective"[13] (ST, 146). Yorck distinguishes between the feeling of transitoriness, i.e., that everything passes away [*Verganglichkeitsgefuhl*] (ST, p. 33), and the feeling or awareness of one's own mortality [*Sterblichkeitsgefuhl*][14] (ST, p. 90). Acquiescence into one's own mortality constitutes the opposite pole to self-affirmation: "self-renunciation" [*Selbsthingabe*] (ST, p. 14), which is thus distinct from and even antithetical to the ethical impetus in philosophy and science. Yorck argues that the inversion of volitional and cognitive projection in feeling and its concentration in pure, passive interiority amounts to a "religious comportment" and the feeling of dependency (ST, 121). To the extent that the religious concentration of life in interiority is inversely related to projective representation, Yorck understands religious life in terms of its "freedom from the world" or *Weltfreiheit* (ST, p. 81 & 112). Psychologically, freedom from the world is the precondition for the consciousness of a world-transcendent God, or the consciousness of transcendence (ST, p. 105). Yorck only hints at the projection *sui generis* involved in transcendence. But it is a projection that has no cognitive or volitional content: God is intended without becoming "an object," and willing becomes a "non-willing," albeit without loss of energy (ST, 104). Drawing on Dilthey and Schleiermacher, Yorck argues that the immediate and indubitable reality of life is exclusively "guaranteed" through volition and affectivity alone. Yorck writes: "That which opposes me or that which I feel, I call real," because I cannot doubt what resists my will or affects my personal life, whereas it is always possible to doubt objects neutrally represented in space outside me (ST, p. 89). What is thought and grasped as an unchanging, stable and self-same object in the space of thought does not affect me or solicit a desire. For Yorck, cognition, in abstraction from feeling and volition, is the realm of pure "phenomenality," which is always open to doubt in virtue of its being merely represented or thought (ST, p. 88). Because "the category of reality is a predicate of feeling and willing" alone (ST, p. 128), Yorck concludes that it is an "utterly uncritical" and self-contradictory undertaking to attempt to prove "the reality of the world" by means of the understanding (ST, p. 129). What Yorck writes to Dilthey in a more general vein is also applicable to this particular problem: > > > Thinking moves in circles and the people appear to me like flies which > always bump into the window pane when they try to get out into the > open. Someone has got to open the window, but much work and leisure is > required for > that.[15] > > > ### 3.2 History of Life According to Yorck, the characteristics of human psychology and the economy of primary life delimit the course of history, since historical life merely repeats or amplifies the primary stances of consciousness. Although there is thus a natural ground for history, Yorck is at pains to emphasize that the three psychological functions outline "possibilities" only, without any inbuilt teleology or fixed equilibrium, or a relation to "an unchanging *ordo*" as a permanent backdrop for history (ST, p. 4). Against such approximations of history to nature, Yorck argues for a thoroughly historical conception of the historical: "History has nothing of the isolation [*Selbstandigkeit*] of the natural [order]" (ST, p. 6), but rather, in each of its phases, history is self-reflexively involved in its own historicity--"as the ferment of its aliveness"--and thus opens itself to the ever new "historical *contrapposto*" (ST, p. 6). Nothing is exempt from historical change. Philosophical categories through which the world is understood are historical products of life and hence inextricably bound up with the historicity of humankind. For instance, Yorck explicitly claims that the category of "being" is itself "a result of life" (ST, p. 8). This liberates history from all relation to an unchanging, fixed point of reference outside historical life.[16] Although Yorck provides only an unfinished sketch of the empirical course of the history of life, he marks three decisive turning-points: (1) The breakthrough to philosophy and science on the basis of the dominant stance of the psychological function of representation or cognition, primarily in ancient Greece and India; (2) the predominance of willing in the Roman and Jewish stance towards the world; and (3) the focal centrality of feeling and interiority in Christianity, particular in the Reformation, i.e., Luther. Somewhat like Hegel, Yorck holds that history unfolds through particular primary stances towards life which then become dominant in particular historical peoples.[17] #### 3.2.1 The Greek World According to Yorck, in Ancient Greece consciousness displayed a particular configuration of the primacy of cognition. For the Greeks, the stance of consciousness towards the world is pure looking. It is through looking that reality is understood. Affectivity (feeling) and volition are not countenanced as functions that disclose the world as such.[18] Truth lies in the beholding eye alone; contemplation, *theoria*, and intuition take centre stage. > > > It is as if the clear-sighted eye is expressed in words. On the basis > of this condition of consciousness, the function of looking > [*Anschauung*], ocularity [*Okularitat*], becomes > the organ of all free work of the mind, particularly of philosophy. > (ST, p. 30) > > > Yorck finds evidence for the prevalence of ocularity or the aesthetic attitude, which is centred on plasticity [*Gestaltlichkeit*], in Homer, Pythagoras, Plato, and Aristotle, among others. > > > Form and content constitute the aesthetic dichotomy which governs > Greek thought in its entirety, the result of the liberation of > ocularity from all other sensuality, the aesthetic liberation, which > strikes a chord in everyone who has entered the threshold of Greek > life. Looking is the essential comportment; hence, Gestalt or Form > [qualifies as] ousia or > substance.[19] > (ST, p. 31) > > > That Greek metaphysics seeks the unchangeable and impassable is the result of the relative suppression of feeling and willing latent in all cognition, which abstracts from desires, feelings, and temporality (ST, p. 42). Put differently, the structural timelessness of thought as such is intensified in metaphysical thought where it becomes "absolute" (ST, p. 42). Yorck emphasizes that "negation of temporality" marks "the decisive metaphysical step" (ST, p. 66). Metaphysics constitutes the counter-move against the feeling of temporality (that everything passes away), as well as the liberation from the dependence on objects desired by the will. According to Yorck, the escape from temporality and attachment determines the entire metaphysical tradition up to and including Hegel (because even Hegel "ontologizes" life and renders it ontic) (ST, p. 83). #### 3.2.2 The Roman & Jewish World The breakthrough to a form of life predominantly lived through striving and volition is, according to Yorck, characteristic of the Jewish and Roman world. Concerning the former, Yorck writes: > > > Whereas the Greek, metaphysical cast of mind abstracts from > temporality, temporality is the determining element [in the Hebrew > world], as the non-aesthetic character of the Jewish way of thought is > already expressed in *Genesis* where time takes precedence over > space. Yet the moment of time is here placed in some metaphysical > distance, is, as it were, projected into the future, the realization > of which is the prerogative of God. Thus, the stance of consciousness > is one of hope. The messiah, who does not fulfil the law, but, rather, > delivers on the promise, is hoped for. (ST, p. 20) > > > Thus, the feeling of time is here aligned with volition and its projective exteriorization. Relative to the Greek contemplation of the everlasting presence of the cosmos, the intensive expectation of the future reality in the Jewish world is "a-cosmic." Comparing the Greek to the Jewish world, Yorck writes: > > > Here, contemplative, eternal presence; there, intense hope for an > invisible futurity. Here, knowledge and science; there, coupled with a > radical devaluation of the object of knowledge, faith as personally > grown postulate. Here, pleasant expansion and the fullness of existing > objectivity; there, formless energy directed at the reality > anticipated. (ST, p. 22) > > > The unfinished character of Yorck's manuscript is apparent especially in these passages, for there is no further exploration or exposition of the Jewish world (let alone anything like a justification for the juxtaposition of the Jewish world with the Roman period). Yorck's comments concerning the Roman world are likewise very sketchy at best. Although Yorck positions the Romans as a world-historical people of the will, he does not do much more than to refer to the popular notion of the "imperialist drive of the Romans" (ST, p. 30). Once, in a letter to Dilthey, Yorck emphasizes that the Roman pursuit of power locks life into pure immanence, without temporality and transcendence: "Might is everything," he writes (CR, p. 120). Yorck continues by contending that the proverbial epithet of Rome as the "Eternal City" is by no means a mere saying. Rather, for Yorck, it captures something of the ostentatious display of Rome's imperial power--its splendid oblivion of time. Yorck writes: "Rome does not, just as no Roman ever does, comprehend--death" (CR, p. 120). By way of historical contraposition, Yorck then describes, in the same letter, the "mute, simple crosses" scratched into the walls of the underground *Carcere Mamertino* by imprisoned early Christians. Yorck characterizes these crosses as "light-points on the underground sky [of the prison], signs of the transcendence of consciousness" (CR, p. 120). The immanence of a life lived for power and might is contrasted with the interiority of a conscious feeling of transcendence. #### 3.2.3 Christianity For Yorck, the Christian life is the breakthrough to a fully historical life. Unencumbered by the projection of objective knowledge (Greek metaphysics and ocularity) and freed from the expectation of a messiah (hope for the promised future), the Christian lives the temporality of "absolute aliveness" [*absolute Lebendigkeit*] in the depths of inwardness or interiority[20] (ST, p. 4). Since Christian consciousness has its dominant focus in interiority and feeling, it is free from the cognitive and volitional bonds to any objectivity, but free for the rhythm of temporality and history. The Christian "freedom from the world" [*Weltfreiheit*] (ST, p. 81) is at the same time freedom *for* history and transcendence, i.e., the world-transcendent God, and the personal, felt relationship to him, which is based on the personal responsibility for one's historical life before God. Yorck writes: > > > Through Christianity an essentially transcendent stance of > consciousness is achieved, namely by way of the basic factor of > feeling. This is a transcendent stance, in contradistinction to a > metaphysical > one,[21] > because feeling [*Gefuhl*]--the focal point of > aliveness [*Lebendigkeit*]--is here turned inwards, even > turned against itself and hence free of all givenness > [*Gegebenheit*]. (ST, pp. 13/14) > > > The release from cognitive and volitional projection facilitates an inversion of life's tendency; it leaves behind the goals of "certainty and security" (CR, p. 143) and grounds life in the personal and intrinsically historical relationship to God. On the one hand, Yorck emphasizes the absolute focus on inner life and individual conscience, and the entirely unpredictable and historical relationship to God, this side of all objective worldly realities and public opinion.[22] The individual person is singled out in his relationship to God. On the other hand, Yorck also holds that the Christian inversion of the projective tendency of life ultimately results in "self-renunciation" [*Selbstaufgabe*], which expresses the religious pole, opposite to ethical self-affirmation through philosophy and science. But precisely through this self-renunciation, life is lived *as* life, instead of being lost in the preoccupation with that which is merely intended through life--the objectively known and desired world. With reference to *Matthew* (10:39), Yorck writes: > > > He who finds his life, will lose it, he who loses it, will find it. > This word of the Lord describes the law of life itself, the basic > condition of all life. Death is a mark of life and the radical > transcendence of the deepest, the Christian standpoint postulates life > as a mark of death. (ST, p. 58) > > > Yorck's well-known love for paradox has its definitive origin here.[23] Freed from the bonds to objective representation and the objective world, Christian religion realizes the most concentrated or enhanced form of living life *as* life; it is "supreme aliveness" [*hochste Lebendigkeit*] and thus supreme historicity (ST, p. 104; CR, p. 154). The Christian life is not distracted by the aims of cognition (objectivity) or the ties to objects of desire within the world (in the past, present, or future). Accordingly, Yorck holds that the historical "origin" and "supreme" manifestation of life--fully lived as *historical life*--lies in Christianity. In his *Einleitung in die Geisteswissenschaften* (1883), Dilthey had made a similar, but by no means identical, point, arguing that "historical consciousness" first came into existence through the Christian freedom from the outer world (the cosmos) and the newfound centre of life in inwardness (Dilthey 1959, p. 254). Dilthey writes: > > > For the Greek mind, knowledge was the depiction [*Abbilden*] of > something objective, [given] to intelligence. Now [after the emergence > of Christianity], lived experience [*Erlebnis*] becomes the > centre point of all interests for the new communities; but this is > nothing other than the simple, inner awareness [*Innewerden*] > of what is given to the person in self-consciousness. (Dilthey 1959, > p. 251) > > > Yet Dilthey sees this as the first potential breakthrough to a new science, the science of inner experience and the historical disciplines, the Humanities or *Geisteswissenschaften*. According to Dilthey, Augustine's fateful dependence on Greek conceptuality made it impossible to fully articulate the new Christian sense of inwardness and history (Dilthey 1959, p. 264). Only through the work of Schleiermacher and Kant has there been progress in articulating the original Christian insight into inwardness and historicity of life (Dilthey 1959, p. 267). Not only does Dilthey fully accept that the meaning of the original Christian experience is thus adequately comprehended and harnessed for the understanding, but he also sees his own work on the logic of the historical sciences as a continuation and fulfilment of this same project. By contrast, Yorck eschews all cooptation of the Christian breakthrough to supreme historical aliveness and historicity for the establishment of a science, fearing that this would not only conceptualize life as something "ontic," always present and available for the understanding, but also ignore the vital consciousness of transcendence, or bury it in a new scholasticism.[24] Yorck, who always regarded Luther's work as the vital re-affirmation of the early Christian historical life, suggests, therefore, that instead of Kant and Schleiermacher, a return to Luther's conception of life is the more fruitful way of safeguarding and cultivating the breakthrough to historical life. Acknowledging this difference, Yorck writes to Dilthey: > > > You will not agree when I say that Luther should and must be more > topical to the present time than Kant, if this present time is to have > a historical future [*historische Zukunft*]. (CR, p. 145) > > >
zabarella
## 1. Life and Works Giacomo (or Jacopo) Zabarella was born into an old and noble Paduan family on the 5th of September in 1533. From his father Giulio Zabarella he inherited the title of palatine count. Zabarella enjoyed a humanist education and entered the University of Padua, where he received the doctorate in 1553. Zabarella had many famous teachers, like Francesco Robortello in the humanities, Bernardino Tomitano in logic, Marcantonio Genua in physics and metaphysics, and Pietro Catena in mathematics. Unlike most of his contemporaries who had studied natural philosophy, Zabarella never took a degree in medicine. His entire teaching career was spent at his native university. He began his career in 1564 when he obtained the first chair (or professorship) of logic succeeding Bernardino Tomitano. Five years later he moved to the more prestigious and more lucrative second chair of the extraordinary professor of natural philosophy. In 1577 he was promoted to the first extraordinary chair of natural philosophy. Finally, in 1585, Zabarella obtained the second ordinary chair of natural philosophy, which he held until his death. The statutes of the University of Padua prevented him, as a native Paduan, from obtaining the first ordinary chair in natural philosophy. Zabarella died at the age of 56 on the 15th of October in 1589. The publications of Zabarella reflect his teaching in the Aristotelian tradition. The first of his publications was *Opera logica*, which appeared in Venice in 1578. Zabarella had time to write this collection of logical works in 1576, when a plague raged in Veneto sending Zabarella into the countryside with his family. This was one of the very few times in his life when he left the city of Padua. Zabarella's next published work, *Tabula logicae*, came out two years later and his commentary on Aristotle's *Posterior Analytics* appeared in 1582. *De doctrinae ordine apologia,* which appeared in 1584, was a reply to Francesco Piccolomini who had criticised Zabarella's ideas on logic. The first of Zabarella's works in natural philosophy, *De naturalis scientiae constitutione*, came out in 1586. This introduction to the field was connected to his major opus in natural philosophy, *De rebus naturalibus*, the first edition of which was published posthumously in 1590. It contained 30 different treatises on Aristotelian natural philosophy and Zabarella wrote the introduction of the book only few weeks before his death. Zabarella's two sons edited his two incomplete commentaries on Aristotle's texts, which were also published posthumously: the commentary on *Physics* (1601) and the commentary on *On the Soul* (1605) (Mikkeli 1992, p. 19). Giacomo Zabarella followed a very systematic style of writing in his publications. His idea was to build a coherent body of Aristotelian logic and natural philosophy. Therefore he was also interested in the classification of the disciplines and the relationships between various areas of academic learning. His use of Aristotle and other authorities was both eclectic and critical. Zabarella's sources thus included newly recovered Greek commentators such as Alexander of Aphrodisias, Philoponus, Simplicius and Themistius, as well as medieval commentators such as Thomas Aquinas, Walter Burley and Averroes. In Zabarella's view, Averroes, unlike his followers, accurately understood Aristotle's philosophy despite not knowing the the original texts or even the Greek language (Martin 2007, p. 15). Zabarella himself read Greek and could therefore consult the Greek text of Aristotle and the commentators. He devoted much effort to presenting what he considered to be the true meaning of Aristotle's texts. However, he resisted the tendency of the humanists to expunge all medieval barbarisms, preferring philosophical precision to classical elegance (W.R. Laird 2000, p. 695). ## 2. Arts and Sciences The Aristotelian distinction between arts (*artes*) and sciences (*scientiae*) serves as the starting-point for Zabarella's philosophical system. At the beginning of his *Opera logica*, Zabarella draws a distinction between the eternal world of nature and the contingent human world. From this distinction he proceeds to two corresponding kinds of knowledge, and two distinct methods of defining them. Zabarella maintained that, properly speaking, sciences are concerned with the eternal world of nature and thus are contemplative disciplines, whereas arts are concerned with the contingent world of human beings and thus are non-contemplative, being productive instead. The sciences in the proper sense of that term, as pertaining to demonstrative knowledge, are limited to those disciplines that deal with the necessary and eternal or with what can be deduced from necessary principles. Zabarella notes that Aristotle requires two kinds of certainty from science. One is in the knowable things, which are necessary as such (*simpliciter*); the other is in the mind of the scientist, who must be absolutely sure that things cannot be otherwise. The necessity involved is therefore both ontological, with respects to the objects known, and cognitive, with respect to the knowing subject (Kessler 1998, p. 837). The hierarchy of different disciplines was a widely debated topic in Renaissance philosophy. Also Zabarella emphasized the hierarchical nature of the division between different disciplines; the whole of active philosophy aiming ultimately at the higher sphere of contemplation. According to Zabarella, both in Plato and Aristotle happiness in the active life is not the ultimate goal for a human being. Instead it is contemplation, which is man's finest objective that may lead to total perfection. In Zabarella's view the purpose of active philosophy is to remove hindrance to the acquisition of knowledge and therefore contemplative philosophy is the ultimate end and master of all active philosophy. In productive disciplines (i.e., arts) it is not necessary to define the objects under production as strictly as in the contemplative sciences, because the productive arts do not aim at knowledge, and thus the knowledge they need do not have to be perfect. Zabarella identifies therefore the basic difference between arts and sciences. Science deals with what already exists, but art is concerned with creation. The subject-matter of a science is immutable, but the subject-matter of an art is the formation of things as yet non-existent, but which can be made by human being. The contemplative philosopher is not interested in initiating anything, but rather wants to comprehend and arrange the forms of existing, eternal things. Moreover, the ultimate purpose of the contemplative science is the pursuit of knowledge for its own sake, but in the productive arts the end-result is an actual product (Mikkeli 1997, pp. 212-213). However, Zabarella was not concerned solely with the separation between the theoretical sciences and the practical and productive disciplines, but dealt also with the relationships and hierarchy among the theoretical sciences themselves. The contemplative or speculative sciences, for Zabarella, are in Aristotelian manner only three in number: divine science, also called metaphysics, mathematics, and natural philosophy. Zabarella presents these contemplative sciences as being the only defenders of true knowledge. Zabarella emphasised in many instances that each speculative science should demonstrate their own principles and not borrow them from metaphysics. According to Zabarella, each discipline can be distinguished from others either with respect to the object considered (*res considerata*) or with respect to the way of considering (*modus considerandi*) (Pozzo 1998). Natural philosophy, which deals with corporeal beings that have an inner principle of movement, differs from metaphysics (which contemplates being as being) and from mathematics (which deals with abstracted beings) in both ways. As a result, natural philosophy is autonomous and independent of both the other contemplative sciences. Zabarella also developed a theory of the middle (or mixed) sciences that, contrary to the prevailing view, afforded sciences such as astronomy and optics full demonstrative status despite their borrowing principles from pure mathematics. Nevertheless, Zabarella's approach to the study of nature remained causal and qualitative in the traditional Aristotelian vein rather than mathematical. Therefore he gave little attention to the possible uses of mathematics as a tool for understanding the physical world (Laird 1983, Ch. 8). ## 3. The Nature of Logic Zabarella's introductory treatise on the nature of logic, *De natura logicae*, is basic to his teaching in logic. He defines logic as being neither a science nor an art, but, in keeping with the traditional meaning of the word *organon*, just an instrument (*instrumentum*) of the arts and sciences. As an instrumental discipline it furnishes a useful tool of inquiry for all the arts and sciences. Logic does not have a real subject of its own, but deals with concepts, which stand for real beings. In this it is comparable to grammar. The difference between grammar and logic is that the former is concerned with the perfect verbal expression of concepts, and hence is a linguistic discipline, while the latter invents second notions (*notiones secundae*) or second intentions, that are able to create order among concepts. Therefore logic serves to recognize the truth and distinguish it from falsehood in every instance. Logic is thus a rational discipline (*disciplina rationalis*) that is not itself philosophy, but springs from philosophy and is devoted to philosophical ends (Vasoli 2011). Zabarella followed Averroes in dividing logic into two parts: universal logic, which is common to all subjects; and particular logic, which is specific to particular subjects. The first three books of Aristotle's Organon, the *Categories, On Interpretation* and the *Prior Analytics* constitute the universal part of logic. Aristotle's *Posterior Analytics, Topics* and *Sophistical Refutations* are said to deal with particular logic as much as they deal respectively with the demonstrative syllogism, the dialectical syllogism and the sophistical syllogism. Following the Neoplatonic commentators (above all Simplicius), Zabarella also included Aristotle's *Rhetoric* and *Poetics* within logic. The former is included because it teaches the use of the rhetorical syllogism or enthymeme, and rhetorical induction or example; the latter because it also teaches the use of example, not to persuasive ends, but for imitation. Since logic, viewed as the universal instrument for distinguishing between the true and the false, differs according to the objects to which it is applied and the ends for which it is used, its nature depends on the realm of possible objects and ends. Rhetoric and poetics are special cases because they deal not with knowledge but with the political disciplines in so far as they are concerned with the good of the people. Sophistical syllogistic is another special case, because it is directed towards deception and prefers to use falsehood as its material. Dialectic and demonstration, however, are directed towards the expression of truth. Dialectic is aimed at the production of opinion, and deals with probable and contingent material; demonstration is dedicated to the acquisition of truth, and so it is exclusively occupied with necessary, true objects (Kessler 1998, p. 837). ## 4. Orders of Presentation and Methods of Discovery For Zabarella method also serves to differentiate the sciences from the arts. The term can be understood in two ways, either in a wide sense as a method of presenting existing knowledge, which he prefers to call an order (*ordo*) of presentation, or in a narrow sense as a method of discovering knowledge, for which he reserves method (*methodus*) in its proper understanding. According to Zabarella, *ordo* is an instrumental *habitus* through which we are prepared so to dispose the parts of each discipline so that the discipline may be taught as well and easily as possible. As regards these methods of presentation, Zabarella denies Galen's view that these are four in number. Zabarella himself recognizes only two orders, the compositive and the resolutive. The order starts with what is either necessary or useful for teaching and learning. In the contemplative (or theoretical) sciences, which aim at perfect knowledge, order of presentation follows the so-called way of composition (*compositio*) from general principles to particular beings; in moral philosophy and in the arts, which aim at action or production, order follows the so-called way of resolution (*resolutio*) from the desired end to its first principles. For Zabarella the methods in the strict sense of the word are intellectual instruments proceeding from the known to produce knowledge of the unknown. Such methods have argumentative force and they deal with specific problems of the disciplines instead of arranging the contents of a whole discipline, as do the orders of presentation. As with orders, Zabarella denied the possibility of more than two methods. He shows that other procedures, like the composition and division used in the hunt of definitions as well as the so-called dialectical syllogisms are not genuinely productive of knowledge and therefore not methods in the proper sense of the term. Therefore he recognized only two methods, which he labeled demonstrative and resolutive. Demonstrative method (or composition) proceeds from cause to effect and involves demonstration "of the reasoned fact" or "most powerful" demonstration, best exemplified in the mathematical sciences. Resolutive method (or resolution) proceeds from effect to cause and, despite its name, also involves demonstration, but of an inferior kind, that is called demonstration "of the fact" or "from a sign". Related to this alter type of demonstration is the process of induction (*inductio*), which is helpful for discovering principles that are known naturally but are not immediately evident. Zabarella believes that, by the force of induction, human intellect is capable of distinguishing the universal, which is hidden in particulars. Induction, or resolutive method makes up the first phase in the *regressus*-method, which was, in his opinion, the only proper method for natural philosophy. It is this very distinction between the method of inquiry and the order of teaching that led Zabarella to a bitter controversy with his Paduan college Francesco Piccolomini (1523-1607). They both agreed that ethical inquiry must proceed by deduction from an understanding of the end. In Zabarella's view all the disciplines whose end is action should be explained in this same way. But Piccolomini could not bring himself to admit that the order of teaching, in ethics as well as in in other practical disciplines, should follow this order of apprehension. Thus the fundamental question embedded in this dispute is the following: Is the order of teaching a particular discipline necessary or contingent? Zabarella argued for the former: both in discovery and in teaching, one should follow the synthetic order in the sciences and the analytic order in the arts. By making a sharp distinction between the method of discovery and the order of teaching, Piccolomini instead embraced a contingent view of pedagogical method. Wishing to teach others, Piccolomini saw his duty as that of starting out from first principles (*a primis principiis*). In such a case it is better to begin with the simpler matters and progress toward the end or goal. (Lines 2002, pp. 254-263) Through their rival claims about *ordo doctrinae* Zabarella and Piccolomini revealed as well very different perceptions of academic and civil order, and very different ways of conceiving and pursuing the office of philosopher within that order. Zabarella wholeheartedly endorsed the purely contemplative nature of philosophy and the superiority of the contemplative life (Mikkeli 1992, pp. 25-35). He also was frequently dismissive in his treatment of the disciplines he regarded as active or operative, for example law, medicine, ethics, politics and mechanics. Piccolomini's position was sharply opposed. For him, philosophy is, indeed, crucial for the spiritual perfection of man. However, in the form of *scientia civilis* it is also the key to the this-wordly perfection that can be attained in the just administration of the Venetian republic (Jardine 1997). ## 5. The *Regressus*-Method The so-called *regressus-*method is a model for combining composition and resolution: the idea of this combinatory process is found in the Aristotelian tradition from Averroes on, and it was vitally revived among the Italian Aristotelians and medical authors. According to this method, the natural philosopher should first infer from the known effect the existence of the cause of this very effect. Sometimes he may use induction, but usually resolution, which was also called *demonstratio quia* or demonstration from the fact. Then in the second step, in the so-called *demonstratio propter quid* or demonstration from the reasoned fact (or composition), the natural philosopher should infer from the cause to the effect. The effect is now known through its cause, and hence in a scientific manner (Risse 1983). The crucial problem with this procedure is how to avoid mere circular reasoning, or rather, how to make sure that the cause, whose existence is demonstrated in the first step, is indeed the cause of this very effect. From the beginning of the sixteenth century, it had become clear that it was necessary to introduce a third, intermediary step, which involved some kind of intellectual consideration (*negotiatio intellectus*) (Kessler 1998, p. 838). Zabarella also had to face the question, how the intellect in fact made this mental consideration. He solves the problem in terms of his psychology of knowledge and calls this third step a mental examination (*examen mentale*). Since for him the task of this intermediary step is to make distinct the confused knowledge of the cause that was acquired through the first step, he refers to his work on the agent mind (*Liber de mente agente*) in which he develops an account of the transformation of confused into distinct knowledge through the analysis of a given whole in terms of its parts. He presents this process as the specific ability of the human mind. Thus once more method as a means of acquiring knowledge is based on the cognitive structure of knowing subject rather than on the ontological structure of the object of knowledge. In his commentary on the *Posterior Analytics* Zabarella identified Aristotle's proofs that the planets are near and that the moon is a sphere as instances of the *regressus-*method. Other examples of the same method he analyzed are Aristotle's proof of the existence of "first matter" (*materia prima*) from substantial change and his proof of an "eternal first mover" (*primus motor aeternus*) from local motion (Wallace 1999, p. 338). The interminable discussion of the methodology of arts and sciences in the sixteenth century may be seen as an attempt to defend the scientific status of either the recently found autonomous sciences, like natural philosophy, or, on the other hand, the empirically based productive arts. The discussions of orders and methods, resolutions, compositions and the *regressus*-method are, therefore, not merely further elaborations of an old Aristotelian tradition, but also expressions of opinions in a lively debate concerning the changing relationships between various arts and sciences in sixteenth-century Italian universities (Mikkeli 1997, p. 228). ## 6. The Science of the Soul The most influential section in the Aristotelian tradition, where the relationship between the theoretical or speculative sciences is dealt with, is the beginning of Aristotle's treatise *On the Soul.* Aristotle gives two criteria for the hierarchy: the dignity of their subject-matter and the exactness of their demonstrations. In his posthumous commentary on *De anima* Zabarella raises the question of the hierarchy of the sciences. In most cases, in Zabarella's view, the science with a nobler subject-matter can be considered superior, but not always. All human knowledge can be compared and there are no grounds for giving either of these criteria absolute priority. In the contemplative sciences the nobility of the subject-matter should be considered superior to the causality of knowledge. In logic, however, where the instruments of science are considered, the nobler instrument is the one that is more precise and produces more certain knowledge. Zabarella, then, did not give one decisive criterion according to which all arts and sciences could be arranged into one single hierarchy. However, when dealing with the place of the science of the soul among the other sciences, Zabarella gives an description of the nobility of this part of natural philosophy. Zabarella opposed the definition of the science of the soul as a middle discipline between physics and metaphysics. He states that Aristotle did not only wish to compare the science of the soul with other sciences, but to compare it with other parts of natural science. In Zabarella's view it is obvious that the science of the soul is the most noble part of natural philosophy, the king and emperor of every other part, which are all dependent upon it, because it shows the first cause and the sum of everything that is in animals and in plants. The science of the soul is more exquisite and certain than all the parts of natural philosophy, because the causes of the science of the soul are more exact, not only to us, but also according to nature (Mikkeli 1997, p. 220). Zabarella's position here can be interpreted as an attempt to raise the status of an independent natural philosophy by emphasizing the nobility of the science of the soul. In fact, it seems that he wanted to elevate the status of *De anima* to that of a special science among other natural disciplines that is the noblest and most precise of all natural sciences on which all the other parts of natural philosophy could rely. What in the medieval times had perhaps been considered to be part of metaphysics was now the most valuable part of natural philosophy. Following the Alexandrian tradition, Zabarella himself left the question of the immortality of the soul to the theologians, because it did not belong to natural philosophy, and since Aristotle, as a natural philosopher, had not been explicit about it (Kessler 2011, p. 52). It is, in fact, hard to be sure, whether Zabarella himself thought that the soul was mortal. However, in his commentary on Aristotle's treatise *On the Soul* Zabarella tried at least to prove that Aristotle himself did not consider it immortal (Mitrovic 2009; Valverde 2012). Zabarella reconstructed the process of intellection on the lines of sense-perception, that is that the intelligible *species*, produced concurrently by the *phantasma* and the illuminating agent intellect, moved the possible intellect into cognition. To be known, the *phantasma,* which was gained by sense-perception, had to undergo a double process. Itself material and consequently containing the universal structure needed in science only in a confused and unintelligible way, it had to be illuminated by the agent intellect, so that the universal in the individual was rendered distinct and intelligible. Since the illumination was generally required for any act of knowledge in the same way, its agent did not have to be an individual operating individually in the different acts of intellection, but rather could be an universal one, which rendered reality in general intelligible, thus serving as an all-embracing guarantee of intelligibility. The agent intellect could therefore be identified with God himself as the principle of intelligibility. When identifying the active intellect with God as the first cause of all that exists and can be known, Zabarella has clearly in his mind that the active intellect does no longer play a substantial role in this naturalistic philosophy of nature after this initial act of intellection (Kessler 2011, pp. 56-57). Therefore with the metaphysical requirements of intellection taken for granted, the main epistemological problem shifted to the manner in which the intelligible *species* was turned into a known object. Zabarella, considering the agent intellect as the divine cause of general intelligibility, could renounce innate principles and retain the Aristotelian teaching of the inductive acquisition of the first principles themselves. But Zabarella had instead the problem of restoring to the human mind an active faculty which would account for the act of judgement. Therefore he redefined the possible intellect as an active faculty as well. This equally active and passive human intellect (which Zabarella called *patibilis* instead of *possibilis*) considered all that was offered to it by the illuminated *phantasma*, contemplated whatever it wanted to, and in doing so selected and abstracted those structures it wished to know and through judging understood them and became itself the object of knowledge. For Zabarella intellection therefore was not a process automatically determined whenever an exterior impulse was given, but rather depended essentially on human will and intention. In Zabarella's view, the science of the soul was concerned with what was necessary and therefore always equally present in any human mind, even if unconsciously. Methodology, on the other hand, was concerned with the use a human being made of these natural faculties. Since this use could be true or false, better or worse, truth and error depended entirely on whether or not the correct method was being used (Kessler 1988, pp. 530-534). ## 7. The Perfection of the Philosophy of Nature Natural philosophy has to know and teach the very essence of natural beings. First, it has to deal with their basic principles, such as matter and motion, which are not natural beings themselves. These principles of natural philosophy are discussed in Aristotle's *Physics*. Moreover, natural philosophy has to deal with the accidents of natural beings understood through their causes. These are the subject of Aristotle's other writings on nature, from *On the Heavens* to *On the Soul* (on Zabarella's ideas on *Physics*, see Biard 2005). In *De naturalis scientiae constitutione*, the first treatise in his collected works on natural philosophy (*De rebus naturalibus*), Zabarella deals in detail with the questions of the order and perfection of the natural sciences. He claims, for example, that the book on minerals is necessary because the natural philosophy would otherwise be incomplete. The place of the book on minerals in Aristotelian *corpus* on natural philosophy is immediately after the book *On Meteorology.* Whether Aristotle himself wrote on minerals is questionable, but he at least recognized the importance of the subject. However, later both Theophrastus and Albertus Magnus wrote on this important subject. Thus Zabarella did not consider Aristotle's works as a complete *corpus* to which nothing could be added. In *De methodis* Zabarella states that Aristotle wrote on subjects of his own choice, but it would be an exaggeration to claim that he was incapable of making mistakes. Aristotle was not infallible and it would be erroneous to insist that he knew the truth of everything he wrote. Nevertheless, he was an outstanding scholar in Zabarella's view, who, for example, turned the study of logic into a discipline. In the last chapter of *De naturalis scientiae constitutione* Zabarella discusses the question of the perfection of the natural sciences (*De perfectione scientiae naturalis ac de eius ordine*). Zabarella states that Aristotle's philosophy of nature may be perfect in structure and form, but it is incomplete in terms of its reference to natural beings. There is much Aristotle did not discuss at all and indeed much that was outside his cognisance. Although he dealt comparatively little with plants and animals, it is not difficult to pinpoint their proper palces in the Aristotelian system of the natural sciences. Therefore Zabarella emphasizes that Aristotle's philosophy of nature is complete at least in theory. Zabarella compares Aristotle's works on natural philosophy to the geometry and arithmetic of Euclid. There are many theorems which can be demonstrated from his works even if he did not himself actually write them. For Zabarella this is no reason to judge Euclid's geometry or arithmetic defective or incomplete. If Euclid had wished, he could have demonstrated all the particular cases, but his book would have become so enormous that it surely would have daunted the reader. Zabarella suggests that this is exactly why Euclid entitled his book *The Elements*, and from this foundation all the other theorems can be demonstrated. In parallel view Zabarella thinks that Aristotle's natural philosophy can be called perfect, since it deals with all the knowledge that is possible for human intellect to obtain, either in practice or at least in theory. Also in his logical works Zabarella emphasizes the idea of a perfect natural philosophy, which consists of a perfect and distinct knowledge of natural beings through their causes. Zabarella reminds that scientific knowledge can never be called confused or imperfect. Therefore the scientific ideal Zabarella presents is profoundly different from the modern view of a scientist making new discoveries. According to Zabarella, science can be "new" only in a restricted sense; the work of a scientist is more like correcting the mistakes and filling the gaps in a ready-made Aristotelian world-system (Mikkeli 1992; 1997, pp. 214-215; 2010, p. 189) ## 8. Natural Philosophy and Medicine Among the Paduan Aristotelians Zabarella was probably the author who discussed most thoroughly the relationship between the philosophy of nature and medical art. While in subject-matter these disciplines were close to each other, in their essence and methodology they were far apart. Unlike many of his contemporaries, Zabarella did not consider medicine to subalternated to the philosophy of nature. Nor did he see the distinction between theoretical and practical medicine as accidental; instead he wanted to consider the whole art of medicine as operational. In spite of medicine's prominent place among the arts; Zabarella sharply denied its scientific status, and insisted that writers who claim that medicine is a science are mistaken. Neither the art of medicine nor its singular parts can be considered as science. For him it was enough to admit that it is the noblest of all arts. In his *De natura logicae* (part of the *Opera logica*) Zabarella attacks writers who put medicine alongside the philosophy of nature among the sciences. Contemplative philosophy appropriates nothing from the productive arts, but instead the arts adopt everything from philosophy. No matter how valuable and precise medicine may be, it could never be a science because it is practised not for the sake of knowledge, but for an end product: that is, the maintenance or restoration of health. If knowledge of the human body is considered purely for its own sake, rather than for curative purposes, it should be called natural philosophy rather than medicine. Even if it were admitted that medicine could be practised for the sake of knowledge, it could not be called a pure science, because it does not explain the first causes, and without this comprehension the other causes cannot be clearly apprehended. Health cannot be fully comprehended and the goal of medicine cannot be achieved, if a physician does not comprehend all the parst of a human body and their nature, composition, purpose, and function. Zabarella recognizes two different ways in which a physician can know the parts of a human body. First, he may learn them through perceptive knowledge and anatomical observations, thereby assimilating the matter of his discipline without understanding its rationale. A physician can also become familiar with the parts of human body through philosophy of nature where he may learn the reasons, which lie behind what he actually sees. Zabarella thinks Aristotle made the same distinction in his books the *History of Animals* and the *Parts of Animals.* In the first he relies on sense perception to classify the different parts of animals. In the second, he offers causal explanations for what he is considering. In Zabarella's opinion this order of understanding results from our own inability to comprehend everything at once. It is thus better to progress gradually from confuse to distinct knowledge. In *De rebus naturalibus* Zabarella points out that the art of medicine adopts the physiological part from the philosophy of nature. If medical writers want to know the anatomy of the human body, they must therefore follow Aristotle methodologically. Therefore they should not study the *History of Animals*, but instead the *Parts of Animals*, which shows us the functions of different parts of the bodies in question. The subject-matter of medicine involves maintaining or recovering health only in human beings, not in other animals. Since the whole discipline deals only with the human body, it cannot be a science in Zabarella's view. What a natural philosopher writes about animals, a medical writer should apply to human beings. Zabarella moves from the universal and scientific discussion of natural philosophy to a consideration of its particular aspects from the standpoint of operation, not knowledge. Moreover, Zabarella believed that natural philosophy and medicine differ not only in their aims and subject-matters, but also in their methods. The resolutive method is proper to medicine and the compositive method to the philosophy of nature. A physician does not use demonstrations, and if he does, he borrows them from natural philosophy. In medical art the resolutive order of presentation proceeds from knowledge to cure. The end, that is maintaining or recovering health, is broken down into principles, on which the operation is then based. In the order of presentation Zabarella wants to differentiate between the presentation of a whole discipline and that of a part of it. For example, the first part of the art of medicine, physiology, has a compositive order as against the medicine as a whole, which is arranged according to a resolutive order. In Zabarella's view this shows that physiology does not really belong to medicine at all, but to natural philosophy, because in physiology the nature of a human body is studied apart from operation. Zabarella's conclusion about the relationship between the art of medicine and natural philosophy is that the latter must consider the universal qualities of health and sickness, while the former concentrates on finding remedies for particular diseases. Zabarella suggests that Aristotle wrote a book of health and sickness of which nothing but a small fragment remains. These fragments are on the borderline of these two disciplines. Zabarella sums this up: where the philosopher ends, there the physician begins (*ubi desinit philosophus, ibi incipit medicus*). From the universal consideration of sickness and health the physician descends to the treatment of all particular diseases and to knowledge of their causes. While discussing the principles of medical art Zabarella compares anatomical principles with principles derived from natural philosophy. In his view, only the philosophy of nature, not anatomy, can provide a solid basis for medical practioners (Mikkeli 1997, pp. 221-225). ## 9. Aftermath From the things considered above, it becomes clear that Zabarella cannot be considered as a precursor of modern experimental science. In spite of its empirical basis, Zabarella's natural philosophy is not concerned with anything akin to experiment. Indeed, if experiments were to be developed, they would find their place in the productive arts rather than in natural philosophy. Zabarella did not use experiments in order to verify or falsify theories in the modern sense. (Schmitt 1969) However, he made observations of natural things, but they were just made to exemplify and illustrate the demonstrative reasoning used in the theoretical natural philosophy (Rossi 1983, p. 146). During the past decades Zabarella's name has been linked to modern science. John Herman Randall published already in 1940 (and again in 1961) his famous idea on "the School of Padua" that would have been the precursor of modern science. Following Ernst Cassirer, Randall referred to the Renaissance discussions of *regressus-*method up to Zabarella as a preparation for Galileo Galilei's new method of natural science. However, the Aristotelian terminology and doctrines that Zabarella and Galileo share, seem for the most part to have been commonplaces of late medieval and Renaissance thought. Galileo may have known Zabarella's writings, but far more important source for Galileo was the Jesuit scholars, above all Paolo della Valle, working at the Collegio Romano at Rome (Wallace 1999, p. 338). Instead of overemphasizing the connection between Zabarella and Galileo, it should be noted that Zabarella's thought had a large impact among Protestant Aristotelians in Germany and in the Low Countries during the late sixteenth century and first part of the seventeenth century (Backus 1989; Maclean 2002). Zabarella's books were known even in the remote Scandinavian countries surprisingly early already at the turn of the seventeenth-century (Mikkeli 2002). Zabarella's clear and systematic interpretation of Aristotle's logic and natural philosophy was used as a basis for numerous Aristotelian textbooks printed in Germany. Moreover, the Protestant academics found Zabarella's instrumentalist view of logic useful for their theological purposes (Kusukawa 2002). Also in the British Isles the Scholastic revival of the early seventeenth century owed much to Zabarella's writings (Sgarbi 2012; Sgarbi 2013, 53-78). Recently there has been some considerations whether Zabarella's distinction between the objects of science (*res considerata*) and the way of considering (*modus considerandi*) had an impact on the distinction between matter and form in Immanuel Kant's philosophy (Sgarbi 2010). Even some modern scholars of Aristotle have still consulted his commentaries with profit.
zeno-elea
## 1. Life and Writings The dramatic occasion of Plato's dialogue, *Parmenides*, is a visit to Athens by the eminent philosopher Parmenides and Zeno, his younger associate, to attend the festival of the Great Panathenaea. Plato describes Parmenides as about sixty-five years old, Zeno as nearly forty, and Socrates, with whom they converse, as "quite young then," which is normally taken to mean about twenty. Given that Socrates was a little past seventy when executed by the Athenians in 399 B.C.E., this description suggests that Zeno was born about 490 B.C.E. He would appear to have been active in Magna Graecia, that is, the Greek-speaking regions of southern Italy, during the mid-fifth century B.C.E. There is otherwise little credible information about the circumstances of his life. Diogenes Laertius's brief "Life of Zeno" (D.L. 9.25-9) is largely taken up with stitching together conflicting reports of his involvement in a brave plot to overthrow one of the local tyrants, but how much truth these reports contain cannot be determined. Although Diogenes also says that Zeno so loved his native Elea that he had no interest in immigrating to Athens, this report is not inconsistent with his having spent some time there; and Plutarch's report that Pericles heard Zeno expounding on the nature of things in the manner of Parmenides (Plu. *Pericles* 4.5) suggests that Zeno may indeed have visited Athens and read his famous book, as Plato's *Parmenides* implies, to a group of intellectually keen Athenians. Vivid evidence of the cultural impact of Zeno's arguments is to be found in the interior of a red-figure drinking cup (Rome, Mus. Villa Giulia, inv. 3591) discovered in the Etrurian city of Falerii and dated to the mid-fifth century B.C.E. It depicts a heroic figure racing nimbly ahead of a large tortoise and has every appearance of being the first known "response" to the Achilles paradox. Plato's *Parmenides* depicts Socrates going as a young man to hear Zeno reading from the famous book he has brought to Athens for the first time. Parmenides himself and some others, including Pythodorus (the dramatic source of Plato's report) are portrayed as entering toward the end of the reading so that they hear only a little of Zeno's recitation. Plato then presents an exchange between Socrates and Zeno, the first part of which is as follows: > > > Once Socrates had heard it, he asked Zeno to read the first hypothesis > of the first argument again, and, after it was read, he said: > "What do you mean by this, Zeno? 'If the things that are > are many, that then they must be both like and unlike, but this is > impossible. For neither can unlike things be like, nor like things > unlike'? Is this not what you say?" "Yes," > said Zeno. "Then if it is impossible both for things unlike to > be like and for like things to be unlike, then it's also impossible > for there to be many things? For if there were many things, they would > incur impossibilities. So is this what your arguments intend, nothing > other than to maintain forcibly, contrary to everything normally said, > that there are not many things? And do you think that each of your > arguments is a proof of this very point, so that you consider yourself > to be furnishing just as many proofs that there are not many things as > the arguments you have written? Is this what you say, or do I not > understand correctly?" "Not at all," said Zeno, > "but you have understood perfectly well what the treatise as a > whole intends" (Pl. *Prm*. 127d6-128a3). While the dialogue's scenario, and thus this exchange, are clearly fictional, this passage is nonetheless normally taken as indicating that Zeno composed a single treatise comprising numerous arguments, cast in the form of antinomies, all purporting to demonstrate the untenability of the commonsense presumption that there are many things. While the later tradition unreliably ascribes other works to Zeno, there is some interesting evidence in the commentary on the *Parmenides* by the Athenian Neoplatonist Proclus (5th c. C.E.) that he was familiar with a work transmitted under Zeno's name containing forty arguments or *logoi* (Procl. *in Prm*. 694, 17-18 Steel). Much of what Proclus says about Zeno in his commentary simply recasts what is already present in the above exchange, but this comment that this work of Zeno's contained forty arguments, taken with certain other things he says, suggests that Proclus had access to a work with some sort of Zenonian pedigree, a work known to earlier commentators as well (as evidenced by Procl. *in Prm*. 630.26ff., especially 631.25-632.3). If there was a work available in later antiquity entitled *The Forty Arguments of Zeno*, it is however unlikely to have been a fair replica of any original treatise of Zeno's. In the first place, some of Proclus' apparent references to this work suggest that it fathered upon Zeno arguments akin to some of those in Parmenides' own elaborate dialectical exercise later in the *Parmenides*. Furthermore, Aristotle implies that people were reworking Zeno's arguments soon after they were first propounded. In *Physics* 8.8, after giving a basic reconstruction of the so-called Stadium paradox (see below, sect. 2.2.1) recalling its presentation in *Physics* 6.9, Aristotle then notes that some propound the same argument in a different way; the alternative reconstruction he then describes (Arist. *Ph*. 8.8, 263a7-11) is in effect a new version of the original argument. Returning to the *Parmenides* passage, it should also be noted that Socrates' description of Zeno's book, which Plato has Zeno endorse, indicates that its arguments had a certain structure and purpose. Specifically, the passage indicates that all Zeno's arguments opposed the common-sense assumption that there are many things. It might also suggest that these arguments took the form of antinomies like the one Socrates specifically cites, so that the general pattern of Zeno's argumentation would have been: if there are many things, these must be both *F* and not-*F*; but things cannot be both *F* and not-*F*; therefore, it cannot be the case that there are many things. Although this description has inspired some to attempt to accommodate the extant paradoxes (of motion, plurality, and place) within a unified architecture that would have provided the plan for Zeno's original book, if in fact he wrote only one, none of these attempts have proved convincing. Since Plato's description is in a number of respects difficult to square with what we know from other sources of Zeno's actual arguments, one should be wary of making it the basis for hypotheses regarding the book's plan of organization. For one thing, the paradoxes of motion reported by Aristotle do not evidently target the assumption that there are many things, nor do they take the form of antinomies. Moreover, only one of the arguments against plurality elsewhere reported, the antinomy of limited and unlimited, conforms to the pattern of argumentation exemplified in the antinomy of like and unlike described by Plato's Socrates (see below, 2.1.1). The remaining argument, the antinomy of large and small (see 2.1.2), purports to show not only that the assumption that there are many things leads to an apparent contradiction, but, rather more ambitiously, it purports to reduce each of the contradictory consequences to absurdity. Plato does not actually state, of course, that all Zeno's arguments took the form of antinomies. In the end, if the characterization of Zeno's treatise by Plato's Socrates in the passage above is not quite accurate, there remains no more plausible view from antiquity regarding the general thrust of his arguments, to the extent that there may have been a single one. One can, moreover, easily broaden Socrates' specification of the target to encompass the arguments against motion and place by changing it to the slightly more complex thesis that there are many things that move from place to place. Socrates might easily have been taking it for granted that, for Zeno, such motion goes along automatically with plurality. What we know of Zeno's arguments certainly accords with the notion that they were meant to challenge ordinary assumptions about plurality and motion. His arguments are quite literally "para-doxes"--from the Greek *para* ("contrary to" or "against") and *doxa* ("belief" or "opinion")--arguments for conclusions contrary to what people ordinarily believe. What more there might be to say about Zeno's purposes will be discussed below, after presentation of what we know of his actual arguments. ## 2. The Extant Paradoxes The task of reconstructing Zeno's arguments is sometimes insufficiently distinguished from the task of developing responses to them. How one reconstructs Zeno's reasoning certainly determines to some extent what will constitute an effective response. The danger is that one's idea of how to formulate an effective response may affect one's reconstruction of Zeno's actual reasoning, particularly if one imports into his arguments concepts more developed or precise than the ones with which he was actually operating. In some cases, as with the one called the Achilles, the paradox's power derives to a significant extent from the very simplicity of the notions it deploys. The reconstructions provided here therefore aim to preserve something of the manner of Zeno's own argumentation as we know it from verbatim quotation of at least portions of some of the preserved paradoxes. More formal reconstructions are possible and available. As already noted, at least one effort at improving Zeno's argumentation was already known to Aristotle. But such efforts can come at the cost of historical accuracy, which is the primary goal of this article. How it might be possible to improve Zeno's arguments will be left to others. Since it is also essential to appreciate just how much (or how little) we know of Zeno's arguments, the primary evidence for each major argument is presented along with a reconstruction. ### 2.1 The Arguments Against Plurality #### 2.1.1 The Antinomy of Limited and Unlimited In his commentary on book 1 of Aristotle's *Physics*, the Alexandrian Neoplatonist Simplicius (6th c. C.E.) quotes verbatim Zeno's argument that if there are many things, they are limited and unlimited, as follows: "If there are many things, it is necessary that they be just so many as they are and neither greater than themselves nor fewer. But if they are just as many as they are, they will be limited. If there are many things, the things that are are unlimited; for there are always others between these entities, and again others between those. And thus the things that are are unlimited" (Zeno fr. 3 DK, i.e., Simp. *in Ph*. 140.29-33 Diels). This is the only Zenonian antinomy that has the appearance of being preserved in its entirety. The argument here may be reconstructed as follows. Its overall structure is: If there are many things, then there must be finitely many things; and if there are many things, then there must be infinitely many things. The assumption that there are many things is thus supposed to have been shown to lead to contradiction, namely, that things are both finitely and infinitely many. The particular argument for the first arm of the antinomy seems to be simply: If there are many things, then they must be just so many as they are. If the many things are just so many as they are, they must be finitely many. Therefore, if there are many things, then there must be finitely many things. Simplicius somewhat loosely describes the antinomy's second arm as demonstrating numerical infinity through dichotomy (Simp. *in Ph*. 140.33-4). In fact, the argument depends on a postulate specifying a necessary condition upon two things being distinct, rather than on division *per se*, and it may be reconstructed as follows: If there are many things, they must be distinct, that is, separate from one another. Postulate: Any two things will be distinct or separate from one another only if there is some other thing between them. Two representative things, *x*1 and *x*2, will be distinct only if there is some other thing, *x*3, between them. In turn, *x*1 and *x*3 will be distinct only if there is some other thing, *x*4, between them. Since the postulate can be repeatedly applied in this manner unlimited times, between any two distinct things there will be limitlessly many other things. Therefore, if there are many things, then there must be limitlessly many things. #### 2.1.2 The Antinomy of Large and Small In the same stretch of his commentary on Aristotle's *Physics*, Simplicius reports at length one of Zeno's numerous arguments designed to show how the claim that there are many things leads to contradiction. "One of these," Simplicius says, "is the argument in which he demonstrates that if there are many things, they are both large and small: so large as to be unlimited in magnitude, and so small as to have no magnitude. Indeed, in this argument he shows that what has neither magnitude nor thickness nor bulk would not even exist. 'For if', he says, 'it were added to another entity, it would not make it any larger; for since it is of no magnitude, when it is added, there cannot be any increase in magnitude. And so what was added would just be nothing. But if when it is taken away the other thing will be no smaller, and again when it is added the other thing will not increase, it is clear that what was added and what was taken away was nothing'" (Zeno fr. 2 DK = Simp. *in Ph*. 139.7-15). After thus quoting this portion of the argument, Simplicius continues: "Zeno says this because each of the many things has magnitude and is infinite [reading *apeiron* instead of ms. *apeiron*], given that something is always in front of whatever is taken, in virtue of infinite division; this he shows after first demonstrating that none have magnitude on the grounds that each of the many is the same as itself and one" (Simp. *in Ph*. 139.16-19). Soon after this, Simplicius records the argument for unlimited magnitude he has alluded to in the first part of the passage just quoted, as follows: "Infinity in respect of magnitude he earlier proves in the same way. For having first shown that, if what is does not have magnitude, it would not even exist, he continues: 'But if it is, each must have some magnitude and thickness, and one part of it must extend away from another. And the same account applies to the part out ahead. For that part too will have magnitude and will have part of it out ahead. Indeed, it is the same to say this once as always to keep saying it; for no such part of it will be last, nor will one part not be related to another. Thus if there are many things, they must be both small and large, so small as to have no magnitude, and so large as to be unlimited'" (Zeno fr. 1 DK, = Simp. *in Ph*. 140.34-141.8). Simplicius only alludes to Zeno's argument for smallness, without setting it out: he says that Zeno derived the conclusion that "none have magnitude on the grounds that each of the many is the same as itself and one." Although this is not much to go on, the argument may plausibly be reconstructed as follows. Each of the many is the same as itself and one. Whatever has magnitude can be divided into distinguishable parts; whatever has distinguishable parts is not everywhere the same as itself; thus, whatever has magnitude is not everywhere, and so is not genuinely, the same as itself. Whatever is not the same as itself is not genuinely one. Thus, whatever has magnitude is not genuinely one. Therefore, each of the many has no magnitude. The basic assumption here is that to be "the same as itself" is what it means for something to be "one" in the strict sense Zeno envisages, whereas any magnitude, which will have distinguishable parts in virtue of being spatially extended, will fail to be strictly one and self-identical. The evidence in Simplicius indicates that Zeno then transitioned to the antinomy's other arm, the unlimited largeness of things, via the following lemma: since what has no magnitude would be nothing, each of the many must have some magnitude. Simplicius's report of how Zeno specifically argued for the second arm's conclusion, that each of the many is of unlimited magnitude, pertains primarily to its apparent sub-argument for the interim conclusion that each thing has limitlessly many parts, which ran as follows. Each of the many has some magnitude and thickness (from the lemma). Whatever has some magnitude and thickness will have (distinguishable) parts, so that each of the many will have parts. If *x* is one of the many, then *x* will have parts. Since each of these parts of *x* has some magnitude and thickness, each of these parts will have its own parts, and these parts will in turn have parts of their own, and so on, and so on, without limit. Thus each of the many will have a limitless number of parts. Whether or not Zeno then made explicit how the antinomy's final conclusion followed from this, here is a plausible reconstruction of the rest of the reasoning was presumably supposed to go: Every part of each thing has some magnitude; the magnitude of any object is equal to the sum of the magnitudes of its parts; and the sum of limitlessly many parts of some magnitude is a limitless magnitude. Therefore, the magnitude of each of the many is limitless. Taken as a whole, then, this elaborate *tour de force* of an argument purports to have shown that, if there are many things, each of them must have simultaneously no magnitude and unlimited magnitude. ### 2.2 The Paradoxes of Motion Aristotle is most concerned with Zeno in *Physics* 6, the book devoted to the theory of the continuum. In *Physics* 6.9, Aristotle states that Zeno had four arguments concerning motion that are difficult to resolve, gives a summary paraphrase of each, and offers his own analysis. The ancient commentators on this chapter provide little additional information. Thus reconstruction of these famous arguments rests almost exclusively on Aristotle's incomplete presentation. Note that Aristotle's remarks leave open the possibility that there were other Zenonian arguments against motion that he deemed less difficult to resolve. More importantly, Aristotle's presentation gives no indication of how these four arguments might have functioned within the kind of dialectical scheme indicated by Plato's *Parmenides*. #### 2.2.1 The Stadium, or The Dichotomy "First," Aristotle says, "there is the argument about its being impossible to move because what moves must reach the half-way point earlier than the end" (*Ph*. 6.9, 239b11-13). He says no more about this argument here but alludes to his earlier discussion of it in *Physics* 6.2, where, after arguing that both time and magnitude are continuous, he asserts: "Therefore the argument of Zeno falsely presumes that it is not possible to traverse or make contact with unlimited things individually in a limited time" (233a21-3). Subsequently, in *Physics* 8.8, he again raises the question of how to respond "to those posing the question of Zeno's argument, if one must always pass through the half-way point, and these are unlimited, and it is impossible to traverse things unlimited" (263a4-6), and he proceeds to offer what he claims is a more adequate solution than the one presented in *Physics* 6.2. The argument Aristotle is alluding to in these passages gets its name from his mention in *Topics* 8.8 of "Zeno's argument that it is not possible to move or to traverse the stadium" as a prime example of an argument opposed to common belief yet difficult to resolve (160b7-9). The following reconstruction attempts to remain true to this evidence and thus to capture something of how Zeno may originally have argued. For anyone (*S*) to traverse the finite distance across a stadium from *p*0 to *p*1 within a limited amount of time, *S* must first reach the point half way between *p*0 and *p*1, namely *p*2. ![S is on a line at p0 on a line that extends to p1. p2 is halfway between p0 and p1 and p3 is halfway between p0 and p2. p4 is halfway between p0 and p3.](graphic1.jpg) Before *S* reaches *p*2, *S* must first reach the point half way between *p*0 and *p*2, namely *p*3. Again, before *S* reaches *p*3, *S* must first reach the point half way between *p*0 and *p*3, namely *p*4. There is a half way point again to be reached between *p*0 and *p*4. In fact, there is always another half way point that must be reached before reaching any given half way point, so that the number of half way points that must be reached between any *p*n and any *p*n-1 is unlimited. But it is impossible for *S* to reach an unlimited number of half way points within a limited amount of time. Therefore, it is impossible for *S* to traverse the stadium or, indeed, for *S* to move at all; in general, it is impossible to move from one place to another. #### 2.2.2 The Achilles Immediately after his brief presentation of the Stadium, Aristotle introduces the most famous of Zeno's paradoxes of motion, that of Achilles and the Tortoise: "Second is the one called 'Achilles': this is that the slowest runner never will be overtaken by the fastest; for it is necessary for the one chasing to come first to where the one fleeing started from, so that it is necessary for the slower runner always to be ahead some" (*Ph*. 6.9, 239b14-18). Simplicius adds the identification of the slowest runner as the tortoise (*in Ph*. 1014, 5). Aristotle remarks that this argument is merely a variation on the Dichotomy, with the difference that it does not depend on dividing in half the distance taken (*Ph*. 6.9, 239b18-20), and his analysis, such as it is, emphasizes that this paradox is to be resolved in the same way as the first paradox of motion. Whether this is actually the case is debatable. If a tortoise starts ahead of Achilles in a race, the tortoise will never be overtaken by Achilles. Let the start of the race be represented as follows: ![At position 0, A is at a0, the beginning of the line, and T is at t0, the midpoint of the line](graphic2.jpg) During the time it takes Achilles to reach the point from which the tortoise started (*t*0), the tortoise will have progressed some distance (*d*1) beyond that point, namely to *t*1, as follows: ![At Postion 1, A is now at a1 = t0, T is at t1 = t0 + d1](graphic3.jpg) Likewise, during the time it then takes Achilles to reach the new point the tortoise has reached (*t*1), the tortoise will have progressed some new distance (*d*2) beyond the tortoise's new starting point, namely to *t*2, as follows: ![At Postion 2, A is now at a2 = t1, T is at t2 = t1 + d2](graphic4.jpg) The tortoise will again have progressed some further distance (*d*3) beyond *t*2, namely to *t*3, in the time it takes Achilles to move from *a*2(=*t*1) to *a*3(=*t*2). In fact, during the time it takes Achilles to reach the tortoise's location at the beginning of that time, the tortoise will always have moved some distance ahead, so that every time Achilles reaches the tortoise's new starting point, the tortoise will be ahead some. Therefore, the slowest runner in the race, the tortoise, will never be overtaken by the fastest runner, Achilles. #### 2.2.3 The Arrow Aristotle's discussion of the relation of motion and time in *Physics* 6.8 prepares the way for his objection to the Zenonian paradox of motion he mentions at the very beginning of *Physics* 6.9: "Zeno reasons fallaciously; for he says that if every thing always is resting whenever it is against what is equal, and what moves is always in the now, then the moving arrow is motionless" (*Ph*. 6.9, 239b5-7). Aristotle remarks that Zeno relies on the false supposition that time is composed of indivisible "nows" or instants (b8-9), a point he soon repeats in identifying the argument purporting to show that "the moving arrow is standing still" as the third of Zeno's paradoxes of motion (b30-3). In his *Life of Pyrrho*, Diogenes Laertius reports, "Zeno abolishes motion, saying, 'What moves moves neither in the place it is nor in a place it is not" (D.L. 9.72 = Zeno B4 DK; cf. Epiphanius, *Against the Heretics* 3.11). This report, which Diels and Kranz took to preserve a genuine fragment of Zeno's book, appears to suggest how the argument that the moving arrow is at rest may have figured as part of a broader argument against motion. Diogenes, however, is not a particularly good source for Zeno's arguments: his *Life of Zeno* notes only that he was the first to propound the "Achilles" argument, along with many others (D.L. 9.29). It is just as likely, therefore, that Diogenes' report depends on an intervening attempt to couch the paradoxes of motion reported by Aristotle in the dilemmatic form Plato indicates was typical of Zenonian argumentation. Even if Diogenes' report happens to be reliable, we still must rely on Aristotle in trying to reconstruct the argument that, as in Diogenes' report, what moves does not move in the place where it is. (We get no indication from him of any argument of Zeno's to show that what moves does not move where it is not; perhaps that was thought self-evident.) And Aristotle's evidence in this instance is an even more meager basis for reconstruction than usual. Thus, according to Aristotle, the moving arrow (*A*) is actually standing still. The argument for this conclusion seems to be as follows: What moves is always, throughout the duration of its motion, in the now, that is to say, in one instant of time after another. So, throughout its flight, *A* is in one instant of time after another. At any particular instant during its flight (*t*), *A* occupies a place exactly equivalent to its length, that is, *A* is "against what is equal." But whatever is against what is equal is resting. So *A* is resting at *t*. But *t* is no different than the other instants during *A*'s flight, so that what is the case with *A* at *t* is the case with *A* at every other instant of its flight. Thus *A* is resting at every instant of its flight, and this amounts to the moving arrow always being motionless or standing still. ## 2.2.4. The Moving Rows "Fourth," Aristotle says, "is the one about the things in the stadium moving from opposite directions, being of equal bulk, alongside things of equal size, with some moving from the end of the stadium and some from the middle, at equal speed, in which case he supposes it turns out that half the time is equal to its double" (*Ph*. 6.9, 239b33-240a1). Aristotle's ensuing discussion of what he takes to be Zeno's mistakes is based on an *exempli gratia* scenario normally taken as a basis for reconstruction, as it is here. "For example," Aristotle says, "let the resting equal masses be those marked AA, let those marked BB be beginning from the middle, being equal in number and size to these, and let those marked CC be beginning from the end, being equal in number and size to these, and moving at the same speed as the *B*s" (Arist. *Ph*. 6.9, 240a4-8). | | | | | | | | | | | | | --- | --- | --- | --- | --- | --- | --- | --- | --- | --- | --- | | | | | --- | | A A A A | | B B B B | - | | - | C C C C | Diagram 1 | | | | | --- | | A A A A | | B B B B | | C C C C | Diagram 2 | Diagram 1 represents a plausible way of understanding what Aristotle envisages as the starting position in Zeno's paradox, even though his description of this position is somewhat underdetermined. Aristotle continues: "It follows that the leading B and the leading C are at the end at the same time, once they move past one another" (240a9-10). This description suggests a final position as represented in Diagram 2. Since we have no other indication of how Zeno himself thought he could derive the conclusion Aristotle reports, that "half the time is equal to its double," from the description of this situation, we have to rely on Aristotle for this as well: "It follows," Aristotle says, "that the [leading] C has gone past all [the Bs], while the [leading] B has gone past half [the As], so that the time is half; for each of the two is alongside each other for an equal amount of time. But it also follows that the leading B has gone past all the Cs; for the leading C and the leading B will be at the opposite ends at the same time, because both are alongside the As for an equal time" (204a10-17). Apparently, Zeno somehow meant to infer from the fact that the leading B moves past two As in the same time it moves past all four Cs that half the time is equal to its double. The challenge is to develop from this less than startling fact anything more than a facile appearance of paradox. Since it is stressed that all the bodies are of the same size and that the moving bodies move at the same speed, Zeno would appear to have relied on some such postulate as that a body in motion proceeding at constant speed will move past bodies of the same size in the same amount of time. He could have argued that in the time it takes all the Cs to move past all the Bs, the leading B moves past two As or goes two lengths, and the leading B also moves past four Cs or goes four lengths. According to the postulate, then, the time the leading B travels must be the same as half the time it travels. Unfortunately, the evidence for this particular paradox does not enable us to determine just how Zeno may in fact have argued. Aristotle thinks the argument depends upon a transparent falsehood, and one must therefore keep in mind, if it seems he was right, that Aristotle's presentation and reconstruction may itself be colored by his desire to bear out his accusation. ### 2.3 Other Paradoxes Aristotle also gestures toward two additional ingenious arguments by Zeno, versions of which were also known to Simplicius. #### 2.3.1 The Millet Seed "Zeno's argument is not correct, that any portion of millet seed whatsoever makes a sound" (Arist. *Ph*. 7.5, 250a20-1). The version of this argument known to Simplicius represents Zeno as engaged in a fictional argument with Protagoras, wherein he makes the point that if a large number of millet seeds makes a sound (for example, when poured out in a heap), then one seed or even one ten-thousandth of a seed should also make its own sound (for example, in that process) (Simp. *in Ph*. 1108.18-28). Aristotle's report is too slight a basis for reconstructing how Zeno may in fact have argued, and Simplicius is evidently reporting some later reworking. The evidence nonetheless suggests that Zeno anticipated reasoning related to that of the sorites paradox, apparently invented more than a century later. #### 2.3.2 A Paradox of Place Toward the end of the introduction to his analysis of place, Aristotle notes that "Zeno's difficulty requires some explanation; for if every thing that is is in a place, it is clear that there will also be a place of the place, and so on to infinity" (Arist. *Ph*. 4.1, 209a23-5). His subsequent statement of the problem is even briefer but adds one key point: "Zeno raises the problem that, if place is something, it will be in something" (Arist. *Ph*. 4.3, 210b22-3; cf. Eudemus fr. 78 Wehrli, [Arist.] *De Melisso Xenophane Gorgia* 979b23-7, Simp. *in Ph*. 562, 3-6). Zeno would appear to have argued as follows. Everything that is is in something, namely a place. If a place is something, then it too must be in something, namely some further place. If this second place is something, it must be in yet another place; and the same reasoning applies to this and each successive place *ad infinitum*. Thus, if there is such a thing as place, there must be limitless places everywhere, which is absurd. Therefore, there is no such thing as place. This argument could well have formed part of a more elaborate argument against the view that there are many things, such as that if there are many things, they must be somewhere, i.e. in some place; but there is no such thing as place and thus no place for the many to be; therefore, there are not many things. This is, however, only speculation. ## 3. Zeno's Purposes The commonly found claim that Zeno aimed to defend the paradoxical monism of his Eleatic mentor, Parmenides, is based upon the speculations by the young Socrates of Plato's *Parmenides* on Zeno's ulterior motives. After the portion of the exchange between Socrates and Zeno quoted above (sect. 1), Socrates turns to Parmenides and says: > > > In a way, he has written the same thing as you, but he's changed it > around to try to fool us into thinking that he's saying something > different. For you say in the verses you've composed that the all is > one, and you do a fine and good job of providing proofs of this. He, > on the other hand, says there are not many things, and he too provides > numerous and powerful proofs. Given that one says "one" > and the other "not many," and that each speaks in this way > so as to appear to have said none of the same things, when you are in > fact saying virtually the same thing, what you've said seems said in a > way that's beyond the powers of the rest of > us. (Pl. *Prm*. 128a6-b6) Socrates virtually accuses Zeno of having plotted with Parmenides to conceal the fundamental identity of their conclusions. With so many readers of Plato accustomed to taking Socrates as his mouthpiece in the dialogues, it is not surprising that this passage has served as the foundation for the common view of Zeno as Parmenidean legatee and defender, by his own special means, of Eleatic orthodoxy. Unfortunately, this use of the Platonic evidence is unjustifiably selective, even prejudicial, in the weight it accords the words put in Socrates' mouth. Plato immediately has Zeno disabuse Socrates of his suspicions about the book's ulterior purpose. Zeno this time replies that Socrates has not altogether grasped the truth about his book. First, he says, the book had nothing like the pretensions Socrates has ascribed to it (*Prm*. 128c2-5). Zeno is made to explain his actual motivation as follows: > > > The treatise is in truth a sort of support for Parmenides' doctrine > against those attempting to ridicule it on the ground that, if one is, > the doctrine suffers many ridiculous consequences that contradict it. > This treatise, therefore, argues against those who say the many are, > and it pays them back with the same results and worse, intending to > demonstrate that their hypothesis "if many are" suffers > even more ridiculous consequences than the hypothesis of there being > one, if one pursues the issue sufficiently. (Pl. *Prm*. > 128c6-d6) Zeno's account of how he defended Parmenides against those who ridiculed him is designed to correct Socrates' mistaken impression that Zeno was basically just arguing for the same thing as Parmenides, that the all is one. Zeno is portrayed as trying to correct this mistaken view of his purposes as born of a superficial understanding of Parmenides' doctrine. Zeno's arguments against plurality will seem to entail Parmenides' doctrine only if his thesis, "one is" (*hen esti*), is taken to mean that only one thing exists. However, the elaborate examination of this very thesis, "one is" (*hen esti*), by Parmenides himself in the latter part of the dialogue shows that Plato thinks it is not to be understood in any such trivial sense. For not only does Parmenides end up examining the relation of his One to other things, which would have been impossible if his doctrine entailed their non-existence, but the relation other things have to the One actually proves responsible in a way for their existence. Zeno cannot be supposing that his arguments against plurality entailed the doctrine of Parmenides when that doctrine is represented in this same dialogue by Parmenides himself as something altogether more involved than the simple thesis that only one thing exists. Nevertheless, Zeno's description of the persons who attempted to ridicule Parmenides is perfectly compatible with *their* having understood the thesis, "one is" (*hen esti*), as an assertion that only one thing exists. Zeno's arguments constitute an *indirect* defense of Parmenides--"a sort of support" (*boetheia tis*, 128c6)--because they do nothing to disabuse his detractors of their superficial understanding of his doctrine. Instead, as Zeno says, he tried to show that the assumption that there are many things has consequences every bit as unpalatable as those Parmenides' critics suppose his position has (cf. Procl. *in Prm*. 619.15-21). Thus, while Zeno accepts Socrates' point that his own arguments aim to show that there are not many things, he corrects Socrates' impression that, in arguing this point, he was just saying the same thing as Parmenides in a different form. The evidence of Plato's *Parmenides*, then, does not license the conventional view that Zeno's arguments against plurality and motion were intended to support the strict monism of Parmenides. Claims to the contrary have rested upon selective and prejudicial use of this evidence due to the tendency to privilege Socrates' remarks on Zeno's purposes over Zeno's own qualifications and corrections of that analysis. What Plato actually suggests is that Zeno aimed to show those whose superficial understanding of Parmenides had led them to charge him with flying in the face of common sense, that common sense views concerning unity and plurality are themselves riddled with latent contradictions. Such is, essentially, the judgment of Jonathan Barnes: "Zeno was not a systematic Eleatic solemnly defending Parmenides against philosophical attack by a profound and interconnected set of reductive argumentations. Many men had mocked Parmenides: Zeno mocked the mockers. His *logoi* were designed to reveal the inanities and ineptitudes inherent in the ordinary belief in a plural world; he wanted to startle, to amaze, to disconcert. He did not have the serious metaphysical purpose of supporting an Eleatic monism" (Barnes 1982, 236). However, whether the historical Zeno was actually involved in anything like the dialectical context Plato envisages for him must remain uncertain. Even if there were already in Zeno's day individuals who mistook Parmenides' position for the thesis that only one thing exists, the idea that Zeno's arguments were motivated by a desire to respond to such individuals in kind is as historically unverifiable as the claim Plato puts in his mouth that his book was stolen and circulated before he could decide for himself whether to make his arguments public (Pl. *Prm*. 128d7-e1). Nevertheless, just as Socrates' initial remark that Zeno's arguments were all designed to show that there are not in fact many things remains basically plausible, so there are elements in Zeno's account of his own purposes that have the ring of historical truth and that square well with other evidence. Plato has Zeno continue his second response to Socrates (quoted above) by saying, "It was written by me in such a contentious spirit when I was still young. ... You are mistaken in this regard, then, Socrates, that you suppose it was written, not under the influence of youthful contentiousness, but under that of a more mature ambition" (Pl. *Prm*. 128d6-e3). The point is repeatedly made that Zeno's book was written in a spirit of youthful contentiousness or "love of victory" (*philonikia*, *Prm*. 128d7, e2). The more mature Zeno seems a little embarrassed by the combative manner evident in the arguments of his younger days, as well he might since that spirit would have come to be seen as typical of the eristic controversialists who sprang up in the sophistic era. Plato gives yet another nod to the idea that Zeno was a forerunner of eristic contentiousness when he has him say that his book "contradicts (*antilegei*) those who say the many are" (*Prm*. 128d2-3). This suggestion that Zeno was a practitioner of what came to be known as "antilogic," or the art of contradiction, is consistent with Plato's representation of him in other dialogues as something of a sophist. In the *Alcibiades*, Socrates reports that Pythodorus and Callias each paid Zeno a hundred minae to become clever and skilled in argument (*Alc*. 119a3-6; cf. *Prm*. 126b-c). Teaching for payment is of course one hallmark of the professional educators who styled themselves experts in wisdom. That Plato saw Zeno as a practitioner of the specific brand of argument known as antilogic is evidenced by the *Phaedrus*'s famous description of him as the "Eleatic Palamedes" for his ability to make the same things appear to his audience both like and unlike, one and many, moving and at rest (*Phdr*. 261d6-8). Again, at the beginning of the *Sophist*, when Theodorus introduces the Eleatic Visitor as an associate of Parmenides and Zeno and their followers, Socrates expresses concern that the Visitor may be "some god of refutation" until Theodorus reassures him that the Visitor is more moderate than those who spend their time in eristic and competitive disputation (*Sph*. 216a-b). Plato's references thus consistently connect Zeno with the rise of eristic disputation, and it is perfectly plausible that his arguments against plurality and motion would have been well-known examples of making the weaker case seem the stronger. The portrait of Zeno and his tactics that emerges from Plato's references makes it seem natural that Aristotle, in one of his lost dialogues, entitled *Sophist*, spoke of Zeno as the inventor of dialectic (D.L. 8.57; cf. 9.25; S.E. *M*. 7.7). Precisely what Aristotle meant by this remains a matter of speculation, given that Aristotle also attributes the invention of dialectic to Socrates (Arist. *Metaph*. M.4, 1078b25-30) and to Plato (*Metaph*. A.6, 987b31-3); he says he himself invented the *theory* of it (*SE* 34, 183b34-184b8). There is also the question of whether Aristotle viewed Zeno's arguments as more eristic than properly dialectical. The difference, according to Aristotle, is that dialectical arguments proceed from *endoxa* or "views held by everyone or by most people or by the wise, that is, by all, most, or the especially famous and respected of the wise," whereas eristic arguments proceed from what only seem to be, or what seems to follow from, *endoxa* (*Top*. 1.1, 100a29-30, b22-5). Aristotle clearly believes that some of Zeno's assumptions have only a specious plausibility (see *Top*. 8.8, 160b7-9, *SE* 24, 279b17-21, *Ph*. 1.2, 233a21-31, *Metaph*. B.4.1001b13-16), so that they would by Aristotle's own criteria be examples of eristic rather than properly dialectical arguments. For Aristotle, then, Zeno was a controversialist and paradox-monger, whose arguments were nevertheless both sophisticated enough to qualify him as the inventor of dialectic and were important for forcing clarification of concepts fundamental to natural science. Aristotle's view of Zeno thus seems largely in accordance with Plato's portrayal of him as a master of the art of contradiction. Should we then think of Zeno as a sophist? Certainly Isocrates, the rhetorician and contemporary of Plato, did not hesitate to lump Gorgias, Zeno, and Melissus together as among the other "sophists" flourishing in the era of Protagoras and all producing tedious treatises advocating the most outrageous claims (Isoc. *Hel*. [*Orat*. 10] 2-3). While there are difficulties in giving precise definition to the term "sophist," one feature common to those normally classed as such that Zeno lacks is an interest in the interrogation of cultural norms and values. Zeno's influence, however, on the great sophists who were his contemporaries and, more generally, on the techniques of argumentation promulgated among the sophists seems undeniable. Protagoras' development of the techniques of antilogic, rooted in his claim that there are two opposed arguments on every matter (D.L. 9.51), seems likely to have been inspired by Zeno's novel forms of argumentation as well as by his advocacy of the most counter-intuitive of theses. Zeno's influence is especially clear, moreover, in Gorgias' treatise, "On Nature, or On What Is Not," both in its penchant for argumentation via antithesis and *reductio* and in its use of premises drawn straight from Zeno himself (see [Arist.] *MXG* 979a23, b25, b37). It is even possible that the famous circle of contemporary intellectuals the great Athenian statesman Pericles gathered around himself provided a major conduit for Zeno's impact on the first generation of sophists. Plutarch, at any rate, records that "Pericles heard Zeno of Elea discoursing on nature in the manner of Parmenides, and practicing a kind of skill in cross-examination and in driving one's opponent into a corner by means of contradictory argument" (Plu. *Per*. 4.5). The skill Plutarch attributes to Zeno, still evident in the fragmentary remains of his arguments, is just the kind of skill in argument manifested in a great deal of sophistic practice. Although doubts have been raised about the reliability of Plutarch's report that Zeno, like Damon and Anaxagoras, was one of the many contemporary intellectuals whose company was avidly pursued by Pericles, there is little that seriously tells against it. Thus George Kerferd has argued both that the patronage of Pericles and his keen interest in the intellectual developments of his day must have been critically important to the sophistic movement and that Zeno's paradoxes were a profound influence on the development of the sophistic method of antilogic, which he sees as "perhaps the most characteristic feature of the thought of the whole period" (Kerferd 1981, 18-23, 59ff., 85). The evidence surveyed here suggests that Zeno's paradoxes were designed as provocative challenges to the common-sense view that our world is populated by numerous things that move from place to place. His apparent demonstrations of how the common-sense view is fraught with contradiction made him an influential precursor of sophistic antilogic and eristic disputation. It is not surprising that someone like Isocrates should have viewed Zeno as a sophist to be classed with Protagoras and Gorgias. To ask whether Zeno was in fact a sophist, a practitioner of antilogic, an eristic controversialist, or a proper dialectician is to some extent inappropriate, for these designations all acquired their normal meaning and range of application only after Zeno's time. While he perhaps does not fit exactly into any of these categories, still his development of sophisticated methods of argumentation to produce apparent proofs of the evidently false conclusions that motion is impossible and that there are not in fact many things made it quite natural for Plato, Aristotle, Isocrates, and others to refer to him under all these labels. It is remarkable that, while many of the responses to Zeno's paradoxes, and even some modern formulations of the paradoxes themselves, depend on advanced mathematical techniques, Zeno's original arguments do not themselves appear to have involved any particularly complicated mathematics. Several of the paradoxes involve no specifically mathematical notions at all. The Achilles is perhaps the best example since it employs only very ordinary notions, such as getting to where another has started from. The other extant arguments for the most part deploy similarly prosaic notions: being somewhere or being in a place, being in motion, moving past something else, getting halfway there, being of some size, having parts, being one, being like, being the same, and so on. Where Zeno seems to have leapt ahead of earlier thinkers is in deploying specifically quantitative concepts, most notably quantitative concepts of limit (*peras*) and the lack of limit (*to apeiron*). Earlier Greek thinkers had tended to speak of limitedness and unlimitedness in ways suggesting a qualitative rather than a quantitative notion. While one might suppose that Zeno's turn to a more strictly quantitative conception of limit and limitlessness could have been inspired by his familiarity with Pythagorean philosophers and mathematicians in Magna Graecia, we can in fact trace the philosophy of limiters and unlimiteds only back as far as Philolaus, a Pythagorean roughly contemporary with Socrates and thus a good deal younger than Zeno. Whatever may have spurred Zeno's development of his collection of paradoxes, his arguments quickly achieved a remarkable level of notoriety. They had an immediate impact on Greek physical theory. Zeno's powerful principle that any spatially extended entity must be limitlessly divisible would profoundly impact the development of the subtle and powerful physical theories of both Anaxagoras, who accepts the principle, and the early atomists, Leucippus and Democritus, who reject it. Zeno's arguments also had a formative influence on Aristotle's own theory of the continuum and of continuous motion. More generally, Zeno's arguments made it necessary for Greek natural philosophers to develop something more than an everyday conception of the composition of material bodies. His arguments, perhaps more than anything else, forced the Greek natural philosophers to develop properly *physical* theories of composition as opposed to the essentially chemical theories of earlier thinkers such as Empedocles. That mathematicians and physicists have worked ever since to develop responses to the more ingenious of his paradoxes is remarkable, though perhaps not surprising, for immunity to his paradoxes might be taken as a condition upon the adequacy of our most basic physical concepts. He may even have offered his collection of paradoxes to provoke deeper consideration of the adequacy of theretofore unexamined notions. If so, it is likewise remarkable that he simultaneously developed forms of argument--most notably, *reductio ad absurdum* by means of antinomical and/or regress arguments--that have ever since been fundamental to philosophical probing of conceptual adequacy.
paradox-zeno
## 1. Background Before we look at the paradoxes themselves it will be useful to sketch some of their historical and logical significance. First, Zeno sought to defend Parmenides by attacking his critics. Parmenides rejected pluralism and the reality of any kind of change: for him all was one indivisible, unchanging reality, and any appearances to the contrary were illusions, to be dispelled by reason and revelation. Not surprisingly, this philosophy found many critics, who ridiculed the suggestion; after all it flies in the face of some of our most basic beliefs about the world. (Interestingly, general relativity--particularly quantum general relativity--arguably provides a novel--if novelty *is* possible--argument for the Parmenidean denial of change: Belot and Earman, 2001.) In response to this criticism Zeno did something that may sound obvious, but which had a profound impact on Greek philosophy that is felt to this day: he attempted to show that equal absurdities followed logically from the denial of Parmenides' views. You think that there are many things? Then you must conclude that everything is both infinitely small and infinitely big! You think that motion is infinitely divisible? Then it follows that nothing moves! (This is what a 'paradox' is: a demonstration that a contradiction or absurd consequence follows from apparently reasonable assumptions.) As we read the arguments it is crucial to keep this method in mind. They are always directed towards a more-or-less specific target: the views of some person or school. We must bear in mind that the arguments are 'ad hominem' in the literal Latin sense of being directed 'at (the views of) persons', but not 'ad hominem' in the traditional technical sense of attacking the (character of the) people who put forward the views rather than attacking the views themselves. They work by temporarily supposing 'for argument's sake' that those assertions are true, and then arguing that if they are then absurd consequences follow--that nothing moves for example: they are '*reductio ad absurdum*' arguments (or 'dialectic' in the sense of the period). Then, if the argument is logically valid, and the conclusion genuinely unacceptable, the assertions must be false after all. Thus when we look at Zeno's arguments we must ask two related questions: whom or what position is Zeno attacking, and what exactly is assumed for argument's sake? If we find that Zeno makes hidden assumptions beyond what the position under attack commits one to, then the absurd conclusion can be avoided by denying one of the hidden assumptions, while maintaining the position. Indeed commentators at least since Aristotle have responded to Zeno in this way. So whose views do Zeno's arguments attack? There is a huge literature debating Zeno's exact historical target. As we shall discuss briefly below, some say that the target was a technical doctrine of the Pythagoreans, but most today see Zeno as opposing common-sense notions of plurality and motion. We shall approach the paradoxes in this spirit, and refer the reader to the literature concerning the interpretive debate. That said, it is also the majority opinion that--with certain qualifications--Zeno's paradoxes reveal some problems that cannot be resolved without the full resources of mathematics as worked out in the Nineteenth century (and perhaps beyond). This is not (necessarily) to say that modern mathematics is required to answer any of the problems that Zeno explicitly wanted to raise; arguably Aristotle and other ancients had replies that would--or should--have satisfied Zeno. (Nor shall we make any particular claims about Zeno's influence on the history of mathematics.) However, as mathematics developed, and more thought was given to the paradoxes, new difficulties arose from them; these difficulties require modern mathematics for their resolution. These new difficulties arise partly in response to the evolution in our understanding of what mathematical rigor demands: solutions that would satisfy Zeno's standards of rigor would not satisfy ours. Thus we shall push several of the paradoxes from their common sense formulations to their resolution in modern mathematics. (Another qualification: we shall offer resolutions in terms of 'standard' mathematics, but other modern formulations are also capable of dealing with Zeno, and arguably in ways that better represent his mathematical concepts.) ## 2. The Paradoxes of Plurality ### 2.1 The Argument from Denseness > > If there are many, they must be as many as they are and neither more > nor less than that. But if they are as many as they are, they would be > limited. If there are many, things that are are unlimited. For there > are always others between the things that are, and again others > between those, and so the things that are are unlimited. > (Simplicius(a) *On Aristotle's Physics*, 140.29) > This first argument, given in Zeno's words according to Simplicius, attempts to show that there could not be more than one thing, on pain of contradiction: if there are many things, then they are both 'limited' and 'unlimited', a contradiction. On the one hand, he says that any collection must contain some *definite* number of things, or in his words 'neither more nor less'. But if you have a definite number of things, he concludes, you must have a finite--'limited'--number of them; in drawing this inference he assumes that to have infinitely many things is to have an *indefinite* number of them. On the other hand, imagine any collection of 'many' things arranged in space--picture them lined up in one dimension for definiteness. Between any two of them, he claims, is a third; and in between these three elements another two; and another four between these five; and so on without end. Therefore the collection is also 'unlimited'. So our original assumption of a plurality leads to a contradiction, and hence is false: there are not many things after all. At least, so Zeno's reasoning runs. Let us consider the two subarguments, in reverse order. First are there 'always others between the things that are'? (In modern terminology, why must objects always be 'densely' ordered?) Suppose that we had imagined a collection of ten apples lined up; then there is indeed another apple between the sixth and eighth, but there is none between the seventh and eighth! On the assumption that Zeno is not simply confused, what does he have in mind? The texts do not say, but here are two possibilities: first, one might hold that for any pair of physical objects (two apples say) to be two distinct objects and not just one (a 'double-apple') there must be a third between them, physically separating them, even if it is just air. And one might think that for these three to be distinct, there must be two more objects separating them, and so on (this view presupposes that their being made of different substances is not sufficient to render them distinct). So perhaps Zeno is arguing against plurality given a certain conception of physical distinctness. But second, one might also hold that any body has *parts* that can be densely ordered. Of course 1/2s, 1/4s, 1/8s and so on of apples are not dense--such parts may be adjacent--but there may be sufficiently small parts--call them 'point-parts'--that are. Indeed, if between any two point-parts there lies a finite distance, and if point-parts can be arbitrarily close, then they are dense; a third lies at the half-way point of any two. In particular, familiar geometric points are like this, and hence are dense. So perhaps Zeno is offering an argument regarding the divisibility of bodies. Either way, Zeno's assumption of denseness requires some further assumption about the plurality in question, and correspondingly focusses the target of his paradox. But suppose that one holds that some collection (the points in a line, say) is dense, hence 'unlimited', or infinite. The first prong of Zeno's attack purports to show that because it contains a definite number of elements it is also 'limited', or finite. Can this contradiction be escaped? The assumption that any definite number is finite seems intuitive, but we now know, thanks to the work of Cantor in the Nineteenth century, how to understand infinite numbers in a way that makes them just as definite as finite numbers. The central element of this theory of the 'transfinite numbers' is a precise definition of when two infinite collections are the same size, and when one is bigger than the other. With such a definition in hand it is then possible to order the infinite numbers just as the finite numbers are ordered: for example, there are different, definite infinite numbers of fractions and geometric points in a line, even though both are dense. (See Further Reading below for references to introductions to these mathematical ideas, and their history.) So contrary to Zeno's assumption, it is meaningful to compare infinite collections with respect to the number of their elements, to say whether two have more than, or fewer than, or 'as many as' each other: there are, for instance, more decimal numbers than whole numbers, but as many even numbers as whole numbers. So mathematically, Zeno's reasoning is unsound when he says that because a collection has a definite number, it must be finite, and the first subargument is fallacious. (Though of course that only shows that infinite collections are mathematically consistent, not that any physically exist.) ### 2.2 The Argument from Finite Size > > ... if it should be added to something else that exists, it would > not make it any bigger. For if it were of no size and was added, it > cannot increase in size. And so it follows immediately that what is > added is nothing. But if when it is subtracted, the other thing is no > smaller, nor is it increased when it is added, clearly the thing being > added or subtracted is nothing. (Simplicius(a) *On > Aristotle's Physics*,139.9) > > > But if it exists, each thing must have some size and thickness, and > part of it must be apart from the rest. And the same reasoning holds > concerning the part that is in front. For that too will have size and > part of it will be in front. Now it is the same thing to say this once > and to keep saying it forever. For no such part of it will be last, > nor will there be one part not related to another. Therefore, if there > are many things, they must be both small and large; so small as not to > have size, but so large as to be unlimited. (Simplicius(a) *On > Aristotle's Physics*, 141.2) > > > Once again we have Zeno's own words. According to his conclusion, there are three parts to this argument, but only two survive. The first--missing--argument purports to show that if many things exist then they must have no size at all. Second, from this Zeno argues that it follows that they do not exist at all; since the result of joining (or removing) a sizeless object to anything is no change at all, he concludes that the thing added (or removed) is literally nothing. The argument to this point is a self-contained refutation of pluralism, but Zeno goes on to generate a further problem for someone who continues to urge the existence of a plurality. This third part of the argument is rather badly put but it seems to run something like this: suppose there is a plurality, so some spatially extended object exists (after all, he's just argued that inextended things do not exist). Since it is extended, it has two spatially distinct parts (one 'in front' of the other). And the parts exist, so they have extension, and so they also each have two spatially distinct parts; and so on without end. And hence, the final line of argument seems to conclude, the object, if it is extended at all, is infinite in extent. But what could justify this final step? It doesn't seem that because an object has two parts it must be infinitely big! And neither does it follow from any other of the divisions that Zeno describes here; four, eight, sixteen, or whatever finite parts make a finite whole. Again, surely Zeno is aware of these facts, and so must have something else in mind, presumably the following: he assumes that if the infinite series of divisions he describes were repeated infinitely many times then a definite collection of parts would result. And notice that he doesn't have to assume that anyone could actually carry out the divisions--there's not enough time and knives aren't sharp enough--just that an object can be geometrically decomposed into such parts (neither does he assume that these parts are what we would naturally categorize as distinct physical objects like apples, cells, molecules, electrons or so on, but only that they are geometric parts of these objects). Now, if--as a pluralist might well accept--such parts exist, it follows from the second part of his argument that they are extended, and, he apparently assumes, an infinite sum of finite parts is infinite. Here we should note that there are two ways he may be envisioning the result of the infinite division. First, one could read him as first dividing the object into 1/2s, then one of the 1/2s--say the second--into two 1/4s, then one of the 1/4s--say the second again--into two 1/8s and so on. In this case the result of the infinite division results in an endless sequence of pieces of size 1/2 the total length, 1/4 the length, 1/8 the length .... And then so the total length is (1/2 + 1/4 + 1/8 + ... of the length, which Zeno concludes is an infinite distance, so that the pluralist is committed to the absurdity that finite bodies are 'so large as to be unlimited'. What is often pointed out in response is that Zeno gives us no reason to think that the sum is infinite rather than finite. He might have had the intuition that any infinite sum of finite quantities, since it grows endlessly with each new term must be infinite, but one might also take this kind of example as showing that some infinite sums are after all finite. Thus, contrary to what he thought, Zeno has not proven that the absurd conclusion follows. However, what is not always appreciated is that the pluralist is not off the hook so easily, for it is not enough just to say that the sum *might* be finite, she must also show that it *is* finite--otherwise we remain uncertain about the tenability of her position. As an illustration of the difficulty faced here consider the following: many commentators speak as if it is simply obvious that the infinite sum of the fractions is 1, that there is nothing to infinite summation. But what about the following sum: \(1 - 1 + 1 - 1 + 1 -\ldots\). Obviously, it seems, the sum can be rewritten \((1 - 1) + (1 - 1) + \ldots = 0 + 0 + \ldots = 0\). Surely this answer seems as intuitive as the sum of fractions. But this sum can also be rewritten \(1 - (1 - 1 + 1 - 1 +\ldots) = 1 - 0\)--since we've just shown that the term in parentheses vanishes--\(= 1\). Relying on intuitions about how to perform infinite sums leads to the conclusion that \(1 = 0\). Until one can give a theory of infinite sums that can give a satisfactory answer to any problem, one cannot say that Zeno's infinite sum is obviously finite. Such a theory was not fully worked out until the Nineteenth century by Cauchy. (In Cauchy's system \(1/2 + 1/4 + \ldots = 1\) but \(1 - 1 + 1 -\ldots\) is undefined.) Second, it could be that Zeno means that the object is divided in half, then both the 1/2s are both divided in half, then the 1/4s are all divided in half and so on. In this case the pieces at any particular stage are all the same finite size, and so one could conclude that the result of carrying on the procedure infinitely would be pieces the same size, which if they exist--according to Zeno--is greater than zero; but an infinity of *equal* extended parts is indeed infinitely big. But this line of thought can be resisted. First, suppose that the procedure just described completely divides the object into non-overlapping parts. (There is a problem with this supposition that we will see just below.) It involves doubling the number of pieces after every division and so after \(N\) divisions there are \(2^N\) pieces. But it turns out that for any natural or infinite number, \(N\), \(2^N \gt N\), and so the number of (supposed) parts obtained by the infinity of divisions described is an even larger infinity. This result poses no immediate difficulty since, as we mentioned above, infinities come in different sizes. The number of times everything is divided in two is said to be 'countably infinite': there is a countable infinity of things in a collection if they can be labeled by the numbers 1, 2, 3, ... without remainder on either side. But the number of pieces the infinite division produces is 'uncountably infinite', which means that there is no way to label them 1, 2, 3, ... without missing some of them--in fact infinitely many of them. However, Cauchy's definition of an infinite sum only applies to countably infinite series of numbers, and so does not apply to the pieces we are considering. However, we could consider just countably many of them, whose lengths according to Zeno--since he claims they are all equal and non-zero--will sum to an infinite length; the length of *all* of the pieces could not be less than this. At this point the pluralist who believes that Zeno's division completely divides objects into non-overlapping parts (see the next paragraph) could respond that the parts in fact have no extension, even though they exist. That would block the conclusion that finite objects are infinite, but it seems to push her back to the other horn of Zeno's argument, for how can all these zero length pieces make up a non-zero sized whole? (Note that according to Cauchy \(0 + 0 + 0 + \ldots = 0\) but this result shows nothing here, for as we saw there are uncountably many pieces to add up--more than are added in this sum.) We shall postpone this question for the discussion of the next paradox, where it comes up explicitly. The second problem with interpreting the infinite division as a repeated division of all parts is that it does not divide an object into distinct parts, if objects are composed in the natural way. To see this, let's ask the question of what parts are obtained by this division into 1/2s, 1/4s, 1/8s, .... Since the division is repeated without end there is no last piece we can give as an answer, and so we need to think about the question in a different way. If we suppose that an object can be represented by a line segment of unit length, then the division produces collections of segments, where the first is either the first or second half of the whole segment, the second is the first or second quarter, or third or fourth quarter, and in general the segment produced by \(N\) divisions is either the first or second half of the previous segment. For instance, writing the segment with endpoints \(a\) and \(b\) as \([a,b]\), some of these collections (technically known as 'chains' since the elements of the collection are ordered by size) would start \(\{[0,1], [0,1/2], [1/4,1/2], [1/4,3/8], \ldots \}\). (When we argued before that Zeno's division produced uncountably many pieces of the object, what we should have said more carefully is that it produces uncountably many chains like this.) The question of which parts the division picks out is then the question of which part any given chain picks out; it's natural to say that a chain picks out the part of the line which is contained in *every one* of its elements. Consider for instance the chain \(\{[0,1/2], [1/4,1/2], [3/8,1/2], \ldots \}\), in other words the chain that starts with the left half of the line and for which every other element is the right half of the previous one. The half-way point is in every one of the segments in this chain; it's the right-hand endpoint of each one. But no other point is in all its elements: clearly no point beyond half-way is; and pick any point \(p\) before half-way, if you take right halves of [0,1/2] enough times, the left-hand end of the segment will be to the right of \(p\). Thus the only part of the line that is in all the elements of this chain is the half-way point, and so that is the part of the line picked out by the chain. (In fact, it follows from a postulate of number theory that there is exactly one point that all the members of *any* such a chain have in common.) The problem is that by parallel reasoning, the half-way point is also picked out by the distinct chain \(\{[1/2,1], [1/2,3/4], [1/2,5/8], \ldots \}\), where each segment after the first is the left half of the preceding one. And so both chains pick out the same piece of the line: the half-way point. And so on for many other pairs of chains. Thus Zeno's argument, interpreted in terms of a repeated division of *all* parts into half, doesn't divide the line into distinct parts. Hence, if we think that objects are composed in the same way as the line, it follows that despite appearances, this version of the argument does not cut objects into parts whose total size we can properly discuss. (You might think that this problem could be fixed by taking the elements of the chains to be segments with no endpoint to the right. Then the first of the two chains we considered no longer has the half-way point in any of its segments, and so does not pick out that point. The problem now is that it fails to pick out any part of the line: the previous reasoning showed that it doesn't pick out any point greater than or less than the half-way point, and now it doesn't pick out that point either!) ### 2.3 The Argument from Complete Divisibility > > ... whenever a body is by nature divisible through and through, > whether by bisection, or generally by any method whatever, nothing > impossible will have resulted if it has actually been divided > ... though perhaps nobody in fact could so divide it. > > > What then will remain? A magnitude? No: that is impossible, since then > there will be something not divided, whereas *ex hypothesi* the > body was divisible *through and through*. But if it be admitted > that neither a body nor a magnitude will remain ... the body will > *either* consist of points (and its constituents will be > without magnitude) *or* it will be absolutely nothing. If the > latter, then it might both come-to-be out of nothing and exist as a > composite of nothing; and thus presumably the whole body will be > nothing but an appearance. But if it consists of points, it will not > possess any magnitude. (Aristotle *On Generation and > Corruption*, 316a19) > > > These words are Aristotle's not Zeno's, and indeed the argument is not even attributed to Zeno by Aristotle. However we have Simplicius' opinion ((a) *On Aristotle's Physics*, 139.24) that it originates with Zeno, which is why it is included here. Aristotle begins by hypothesizing that some body is completely divisible, 'through and through'; the second step of the argument makes clear that he means by this that it is divisible into parts that themselves have no size--parts with any magnitude remain incompletely divided. (Once again what matters is that the body is genuinely composed of such parts, not that anyone has the time and tools to make the division; and remembering from the previous section that one does not obtain such parts by repeatedly dividing all parts in half.) So suppose the body is divided into its dimensionless parts. These parts could either be nothing at all--as Zeno argued above--or 'point-parts'. If the parts are nothing then so is the body: it's just an illusion. And, the argument concludes, even if they are points, since these are unextended the body itself will be unextended: surely any sum--even an infinite one--of zeroes is zero. Could that final assumption be questioned? It is (as noted above) a consequence of the Cauchy definition of an infinite sum; however Grunbaum (1967) pointed out that that definition only applies to countable sums, and Cantor gave a beautiful, astounding and extremely influential 'diagonal' proof that the number of points in the segment is uncountably infinite. There is no way to label *all* the points in the line with the infinity of numbers 1, 2, 3, ... , and so there are more points in a line segment than summands in a Cauchy sum. In short, the analysis employed for countably infinite division does not apply here. So suppose that you are just given the number of points in a line and that their lengths are all zero; how would you determine the length? Do we need a new definition, one that extends Cauchy's to uncountably infinite sums? It turns out that that would not help, because Cauchy further showed that any segment, of any length whatsoever (and indeed an entire infinite line) *have exactly the same number of points as our unit segment*. So knowing the number of points won't determine the length of the line, and so nothing like familiar addition--in which the whole is determined by the parts--is possible. Instead we must think of the distance properties of a line as logically posterior to its point composition: *first* we have a set of points (ordered in a certain way, so that there is some fact, for example, about which of any three is between the others) *then* we define a function of pairs of points which specifies how far apart they are (satisfying such conditions as that the distance between \(A\) and \(B\) plus the distance between \(B\) and \(C\) equals the distance between \(A\) and \(C\)--if \(B\) is between \(A\) and \(C)\). Thus we answer Zeno as follows: the argument assumed that the size of the body was a sum of the sizes of point parts, but that is not the case; according to modern mathematics, a geometric line segment is an uncountable infinity of points plus a distance function. (Note that Grunbaum used the fact that the point composition fails to determine a length to support his 'conventionalist' view that a line has no determinate length at all, independent of a standard of measurement.) As Ehrlich (2014) emphasizes, we could even stipulate that an 'uncountable sum' of zeroes is zero, because the length of a line is not equal to the sum of the lengths of the points it contains (addressing Sherry's, 1988, concern that refusing to extend the definition would be ad hoc). Hence, if one stipulates that the length of a line is the sum of any complete collection of proper parts, then it follows that points are not properly speaking *parts* of a line (unlike halves, quarters, and so on of a line). In a strict sense in modern measure theory (which generalizes Grunbaum's framework), the points in a line are incommensurable with it, and the very set-up given by Aristotle in which the length of the whole is analyzed in terms of its points is illegitimate. ## 3. The Paradoxes of Motion ### 3.1 The Dichotomy > > The first asserts the non-existence of motion on the ground that that > which is in locomotion must arrive at the half-way stage before it > arrives at the goal. (Aristotle *Physics*, 239b11) > This paradox is known as the 'dichotomy' because it involves repeated division into two (like the second paradox of plurality). Like the other paradoxes of motion we have it from Aristotle, who sought to refute it. Suppose a very fast runner--such as mythical Atalanta--needs to run for the bus. Clearly before she reaches the bus stop she must run half-way, as Aristotle says. There's no problem there; supposing a constant motion it will take her 1/2 the time to run half-way there and 1/2 the time to run the rest of the way. Now she must also run half-way to the half-way point--i.e., a 1/4 of the total distance--before she reaches the half-way point, but again she is left with a finite number of finite lengths to run, and plenty of time to do it. And before she reaches 1/4 of the way she must reach \(1/2\) of \(1/4 = 1/8\) of the way; and before that a 1/16; and so on. There is no problem at any finite point in this series, but what if the halving is carried out infinitely many times? The resulting series contains no first distance to run, for any possible first distance could be divided in half, and hence would not be first after all. However it does contain a final distance, namely 1/2 of the way; and a penultimate distance, 1/4 of the way; and a third to last distance, 1/8 of the way; and so on. Thus the series of distances that Atalanta is required to run is: ..., then 1/16 of the way, then 1/8 of the way, then 1/4 of the way, and finally 1/2 of the way (for now we are not suggesting that she *stops* at the end of each segment and then starts running at the beginning of the next--we are thinking of her continuous run being composed of such parts). And now there is a problem, for this description of her run has her travelling an *infinite* number of *finite* distances, which, Zeno would have us conclude, must take an infinite time, which is to say it is never completed. And since the argument does not depend on the distance or who or what the mover is, it follows that no finite distance can ever be traveled, which is to say that all motion is impossible. (Note that the paradox could easily be generated in the other direction so that Atalanta must first run half way, then half the remaining way, then half of that and so on, so that she must run the following endless sequence of fractions of the total distance: 1/2, then 1/4, then 1/8, then ....) A couple of common responses are not adequate. One might--as Simplicius ((a) *On Aristotle's Physics*, 1012.22) tells us Diogenes the Cynic did by silently standing and walking--point out that it is a matter of the most common experience that things in fact do move, and that we know very well that Atalanta would have no trouble reaching her bus stop. But this would not impress Zeno, who, as a paid up Parmenidean, held that many things are not as they appear: it may appear that Diogenes is walking or that Atalanta is running, but appearances can be deceptive and surely we have a logical proof that they are in fact not moving at all. Alternatively if one doesn't accept that Zeno has given a proof that motion is illusory--as we hopefully do not--one then owes an account of what is wrong with his argument: he has given reasons why motion is impossible, and so an adequate response must show why those reasons are not sufficient. And it won't do simply to point out that there are some ways of cutting up Atalanta's run--into just two halves, say--in which there is no problem. For if you accept all of the steps in Zeno's argument then you must accept his conclusion (assuming that he has reasoned in a logically deductive way): it's not enough to show an unproblematic division, you must also show why the *given* division is unproblematic. Another response--given by Aristotle himself--is to point out that as we divide the distances run, we should also divide the total time taken: there is 1/2 the time for the final 1/2, a 1/4 of the time for the previous 1/4, an 1/8 of the time for the 1/8 of the run and so on. Thus each fractional distance has just the right fraction of the finite total time for Atalanta to complete it, and thus the distance can be completed in a finite time. Aristotle felt that this reply should satisfy Zeno, however he also realized (*Physics*, 263a15) that it could not be the end of the matter. For now we are saying that the *time* Atalanta takes to reach the bus stop is composed of an infinite number of finite pieces--..., 1/8, 1/4, and 1/2 of the total time--and isn't that an infinite time? Of course, one could again claim that some infinite sums have finite totals, and in particular that the sum of these pieces is \(1 \times\) the total time, which is of course finite (and again a complete solution would demand a rigorous account of infinite summation, like Cauchy's). However, Aristotle did not make such a move. Instead he drew a sharp distinction between what he termed a 'continuous' line and a line divided into parts. Consider a simple division of a line into two: on the one hand there is the undivided line, and on the other the line with a mid-point selected as the boundary of the two halves. Aristotle claims that these are two distinct things: and that the latter is only 'potentially' derivable from the former. Next, Aristotle takes the common-sense view that time is like a geometric line, and considers the time it takes to complete the run. We can again distinguish the two cases: there is the continuous interval from start to finish, and there is the interval divided into Zeno's infinity of half-runs. The former is 'potentially infinite' in the sense that it could be divided into the latter 'actual infinity'. Here's the crucial step: Aristotle thinks that since these intervals are *geometrically* distinct they must be *physically* distinct. But how could that be? He claims that the runner must do something at the end of each half-run to make it distinct from the next: she must stop, making the run itself discontinuous. (It's not clear why some other action wouldn't suffice to divide the interval.) Then Aristotle's full answer to the paradox is that the question of whether the infinite series of runs is possible or not is ambiguous: the potentially infinite series of halves in a continuous run is possible, while an actual infinity of discontinuous half runs is not--Zeno does identify an impossibility, but it does not describe the usual way of running down tracks! It is hard--from our modern perspective perhaps--to see how this answer could be completely satisfactory. In the first place it assumes that a clear distinction can be drawn between potential and actual infinities, something that was never fully achieved. Second, suppose that Zeno's problem turns on the claim that infinite sums of finite quantities are invariably infinite. Then Aristotle's distinction will only help if he can explain why potentially infinite sums are in fact finite (couldn't we potentially add \(1 + 1 + 1 +\ldots\), which does not have a finite total); or if he can give a reason why potentially infinite sums just don't exist. Or perhaps Aristotle did not see infinite sums as the problem, but rather whether completing an infinity of finite actions is metaphysically and conceptually and physically possible. We will briefly discuss this issue--of 'Supertasks'--below, but note that there is a well-defined run in which the stages of Atalanta's run are punctuated by finite rests, arguably showing the possibility of completing an infinite series of finite tasks in a finite time (Huggett 2010, 21-2). Finally, the distinction between potential and actual infinities has played no role in mathematics since Cantor tamed the transfinite numbers--certainly the potential infinite has played no role in the modern mathematical solutions discussed here. ### 3.2 Achilles and the Tortoise > > The [second] argument was called "Achilles," accordingly, > from the fact that Achilles was taken [as a character] in it, and the > argument says that it is impossible for him to overtake the tortoise > when pursuing it. For in fact it is necessary that what is to overtake > [something], before overtaking [it], first reach the limit from which > what is fleeing set forth. In [the time in] which what is pursuing > arrives at this, what is fleeing will advance a certain interval, even > if it is less than that which what is pursuing advanced > .... And in the time again in which what is pursuing will > traverse this [interval] which what is fleeing advanced, in this time > again what is fleeing will traverse some amount .... And > thus in every time in which what is pursuing will traverse the > [interval] which what is fleeing, being slower, has already advanced, > what is fleeing will also advance some amount. (Simplicius(b) *On > Aristotle's Physics*, 1014.10) > This paradox turns on much the same considerations as the last. Imagine Achilles chasing a tortoise, and suppose that Achilles is running at 1 *m/s*, that the tortoise is crawling at 0.1 *m/s* and that the tortoise starts out 0.9m ahead of Achilles. On the face of it Achilles should catch the tortoise after 1s, at a distance of 1m from where he starts (and so 0.1m from where the Tortoise starts). We could break Achilles' motion up as we did Atalanta's, into halves, or we could do it as follows: before Achilles can catch the tortoise he must reach the point where the tortoise started. But in the time he takes to do this the tortoise crawls a little further forward. So next Achilles must reach this new point. But in the time it takes Achilles to achieve this the tortoise crawls forward a tiny bit further. And so on to infinity: every time that Achilles reaches the place where the tortoise was, the tortoise has had enough time to get a little bit further, and so Achilles has another run to make, and so Achilles has an infinite number of finite catch-ups to do before he can catch the tortoise, and so, Zeno concludes, he never catches the tortoise. One aspect of the paradox is thus that Achilles must traverse the following infinite series of distances before he catches the tortoise: first 0.9m, then an additional 0.09m, then 0.009m, .... These are the series of distances ahead that the tortoise reaches at the start of each of Achilles' catch-ups. Looked at this way the puzzle is identical to the Dichotomy, for it is just to say that 'that which is in locomotion must arrive [nine tenths of the way] before it arrives at the goal'. And so everything we said above applies here too. But what the paradox in this form brings out most vividly is the problem of completing a series of actions that has no final member--in this case the infinite series of catch-ups before Achilles reaches the tortoise. But just what is the problem? Perhaps the following: Achilles' run to the point at which he should reach the tortoise can, it seems, be completely decomposed into the series of catch-ups, none of which take him to the tortoise. Therefore, nowhere in his run does he reach the tortoise after all. But if this is what Zeno had in mind it won't do. Of course Achilles doesn't reach the tortoise at any point of the sequence, for every run in the sequence occurs *before* we expect Achilles to reach it! Thinking in terms of the points that Achilles must reach in his run, 1m does not occur in the sequence 0.9m, 0.99m, 0.999m, ..., so of course he never catches the tortoise during that sequence of runs! (And the same situation arises in the Dichotomy: no first distance in the series, so it does not contain Atalanta's start!) Thus the series of catch-ups does not after all completely decompose the run: the final point--at which Achilles does catch the tortoise--must be added to it. So is there any puzzle? Arguably yes. Achilles' run passes through the sequence of points 0.9m, 0.99m, 0.999m, ..., 1m. But does such a strange sequence--comprised of an infinity of members followed by one more--make sense mathematically? If not then our mathematical description of the run cannot be correct, but then what is? Fortunately the theory of transfinites pioneered by Cantor assures us that such a series is perfectly respectable. It was realized that the order properties of infinite series are much more elaborate than those of finite series. Any way of arranging the numbers 1, 2 and 3 gives a series in the same pattern, for instance, but there are many distinct ways to order the natural numbers: 1, 2, 3, ... for instance. Or ... , 3, 2, 1. Or ... , 4, 2, 1, 3, 5, .... Or 2, 3, 4, ... , 1, which is just the same kind of series as the positions Achilles must run through. Thus the theory of the transfinites treats not just 'cardinal' numbers--which depend only on how many things there are--but also 'ordinal' numbers which depend further on how the things are arranged. Since the ordinals are standardly taken to be mathematically legitimate numbers, and since the series of points Achilles must pass has an ordinal number, we shall take it that the series is mathematically legitimate. (Again, see 'Supertasks' below for another kind of problem that might arise for Achilles'.) ### 3.3 The Arrow > > The third is ... that the flying arrow is at rest, which result > follows from the assumption that time is composed of moments > .... he says that if everything when it occupies an equal > space is at rest, and if that which is in locomotion is always in a > now, the flying arrow is therefore motionless. (Aristotle > *Physics*, 239b30) > > > Zeno abolishes motion, saying "What is in motion moves neither > in the place it is nor in one in which it is not". (Diogenes > Laertius *Lives of Famous Philosophers*, ix.72) > > > This argument against motion explicitly turns on a particular kind of assumption of plurality: that time is composed of moments (or 'nows') *and nothing else*. Consider an arrow, apparently in motion, at any instant. First, Zeno assumes that it travels no distance during that moment--'it occupies an equal space' for the whole instant. But the entire period of its motion contains only instants, all of which contain an arrow at rest, and so, Zeno concludes, the arrow cannot be moving. An immediate concern is why Zeno is justified in assuming that the arrow is at rest during any instant. It follows immediately if one assumes that an instant lasts 0s: whatever speed the arrow has, it will get nowhere if it has no time at all. But what if one held that the smallest parts of time are finite--if tiny--so that a moving arrow might actually move some distance during an instant? One way of supporting the assumption--which requires reading quite a lot into the text--starts by assuming that instants are indivisible. Then suppose that an arrow actually moved during an instant. It would be at different locations at the start and end of the instant, which implies that the instant has a 'start' and an 'end', which in turn implies that it has at least two parts, and so is divisible, contrary to our assumption. (Note that this argument only establishes that nothing can move during an instant, not that instants cannot be finite.) So then, nothing moves during any instant, but time is entirely composed of instants, so nothing ever moves. A first response is to point out that determining the velocity of the arrow means dividing the distance traveled in some time by the length of that time. But--assuming from now on that instants have zero duration--this formula makes no sense in the case of an instant: the arrow travels 0m in the 0s the instant lasts, but 0/0 m/s is not any number at all. Thus it is fallacious to conclude from the fact that the arrow doesn't travel any distance in an instant that it is at rest; whether it is in motion at an instant or not depends on whether it travels any distance in a *finite* interval that includes the instant in question. The answer is correct, but it carries the counter-intuitive implication that motion is not something that happens at any instant, but rather only over finite periods of time. Think about it this way: time, as we said, is composed only of instants. No distance is traveled during any instant. So when does the arrow actually move? How does it get from one place to another at a later moment? There's only one answer: the arrow gets from point \(X\) at time 1 to point \(Y\) at time 2 simply in virtue of being at successive intermediate points at successive intermediate times--the arrow never changes its position during an instant but only over intervals composed of instants, by the occupation of different positions at different times. In Bergson's memorable words--which he thought expressed an absurdity--'movement is composed of immobilities' (1911, 308): getting from \(X\) to \(Y\) is a matter of occupying exactly one place in between at each instant (in the right order of course). For further discussion of this 'at-at' conception of time see Arntzenius (2000) and Salmon (2001, 23-4). ### 3.4 The Stadium > > The fourth argument is that concerning equal bodies which move > alongside equal bodies in the stadium from opposite > directions--the ones from the end of the stadium, the others from > the middle--at equal speeds, in which he thinks it follows that > half the time is equal to its double.... (Aristotle > *Physics*, 239b33) > Aristotle goes on to elaborate and refute an argument for Zeno's final paradox of motion. The text is rather cryptic, but is usually interpreted along the following lines: picture three sets of touching cubes--all exactly the same--in relative motion. One set--the \(A\)s--are at rest, and the others--the \(B\)s and \(C\)s--move to the right and left respectively, at a constant equal speed. And suppose that at some moment the rightmost \(B\) and the leftmost \(C\) are aligned with the middle \(A\), as shown (three of each are pictured for simplicity). | | | | | | | | --- | --- | --- | --- | --- | --- | | | \(A\) | \(A\) | \(A\) | | | | \(B\) | \(B\) | \(B\) | | | | | | | \(C\) | \(C\) | \(C\) | | Since the \(B\)s and \(C\)s move at same speeds, they will be aligned with the \(A\)s simultaneously. | | | | | | | | --- | --- | --- | --- | --- | --- | | | \(A\) | \(A\) | \(A\) | | | | | \(B\) | \(B\) | \(B\) | | | | | \(C\) | \(C\) | \(C\) | | | At this moment, the rightmost \(B\) has traveled past all the \(C\)s, but only half the \(A\)s; since they are of equal size, it has traveled both some distance *and* half that distance. The putative contradiction is not drawn here however, presumably because it is clear that these contrary distances are *relative* to the \(C\)s and \(A\)s respectively; there's generally no contradiction in standing in different relations to different things. Instead, the distances are converted to times by dividing the distances by the speed of the \(B\)s; half the distance at a given speed takes half the time. Then a contradiction threatens because the time between the states is unequivocal, not relative--the process takes some (non-zero) time and half that time. The general verdict is that Zeno was hopelessly confused about relative velocities in this paradox. If the \(B\)s are moving with speed *S m/s* to the right with respect to the \(A\)s, and if the \(C\)s are moving with speed *S m/s* to the left with respect to the \(A\)s, then the \(C\)s are moving with speed \(S+S = 2\)*S m/s* to the left with respect to the \(B\)s. And so, of course, while the \(B\)s travel twice as far relative to the \(C\)s as the \(A\)s, they do so at twice the relative speed, and so the times are the same either way. But could Zeno have been this confused? (Sattler, 2015, argues against this and other common readings of the stadium.) Perhaps (Davey, 2007) he had the following in mind instead (while Zeno is smarter according to this reading, it doesn't quite fit Aristotle's words so well): suppose the \(A\)s, \(B\)s and \(C\)s are of the smallest spatial extent, 'point-sized', where 'points' are of zero size if space is continuous, or finite if space is 'atomic'. Suppose further that there are no spaces between the \(A\)s, or between the \(B\)s, or between the \(C\)s. During the motion above the leading \(B\) passes all of the \(C\)s, and half of the \(A\)s, so half as many \(A\)s as \(C\)s. Now, as a point moves continuously along a line with no gaps, there is a 1:1 correspondence between the instants of time and the points on the line--to each instant a point, and to each point an instant. Therefore, the number of '\(A\)-instants' of time the leading \(B\) takes to pass the \(A\)s is half the number of '\(C\)-instants' takes to pass the \(C\)s--even though these processes take the same amount of time. If we then, crucially, assume that half the instants means half the time, we conclude that half the time equals the whole time, a contradiction. We saw above, in our discussion of complete divisibility, the problem with such reasoning applied to continuous lines: any line segment has the same number of points, so nothing can be inferred from the number of points in this way--certainly not that half the points (here, instants) means half the length (or time). The paradox fails as stated. But doesn't the very claim that the intervals contain the same number of instants conflict with the step of the argument that concludes that there are half as many \(A\)-instants as \(C\)-instants? This issue is subtle for infinite sets: to give a different example, 1, 2, 3, ... is in 1:1 correspondence with 2, 4, 6, ..., and so there are the same number of each. It is in this sense of 1:1 correspondence--the precise sense of 'same number' used in mathematics--that any finite line has the same number of points as any other. However, informally speaking, there are also 'half as many' even numbers as whole numbers: the pairs (1, 2), (3, 4), (5, 6), ... can also be put into 1:1 correspondence with 2, 4, 6, .... Similarly, there are--informally speaking--half as many \(A\)-instants as \(C\)-instants: \(A\)-instants are in 1:1 correspondence with pairs of \(C\)-instants. So there is no contradiction in the number of points: the informal half equals the strict whole (a different solution is required for an atomic theory, along the lines presented in the final paragraph of this section). (Let me mention a similar paradox of motion--the 'millstone'--attributed to Maimonides. Imagine two wheels, one twice the radius and circumference of the other, fixed to a single axle. Let them run down a track, with one rail raised to keep the axle horizontal, for one turn of both wheels [they turn at the same rate because of the axle]: each point of each wheel makes contact with exactly one point of its rail, and every point of each rail with exactly one point of its wheel. Does the assembly travel a distance equal to the circumference of the big wheel? Of the small? Both? Something else? How? This problem too requires understanding of the continuum; but it is not a paradox of Zeno's so we shall leave it to the ingenuity of the reader.) A final possible reconstruction of Zeno's Stadium takes it as an argument against an atomic theory of space and time, which is interesting because contemporary physics explores such a view when it attempts to 'quantize' spacetime. Suppose then the sides of each cube equal the 'quantum' of length and that the two moments considered are separated by a single quantum of time. Then something strange must happen, for the rightmost \(B\) and the middle \(C\) pass each other during the motion, and yet there is no moment at which they are level: since the two moments are separated by the smallest possible time, there can be no instant between them--it would be a time smaller than the smallest time from the two moments we considered. Conversely, if one insisted that if they pass then there must be a moment when they are level, then it shows that cannot be a shortest finite interval--whatever it is, just run this argument against it. However, why should one insist on this assumption? The problem is that one naturally imagines quantized space as being like a chess board, on which the chess pieces are frozen during each quantum of time. Then one wonders when the red queen, say, gets from one square to the next, or how she gets past the white queen without being level with her. But the analogy is misleading. It is better to think of quantized space as a giant matrix of lights that holds some pattern of illuminated lights for each quantum of time. In this analogy a lit bulb represents the presence of an object: for instance a series of bulbs in a line lighting up in sequence represent a body moving in a straight line. In this case there is no temptation to ask when the light 'gets' from one bulb to the next--or in analogy how the body moves from one location to the next. (Here we touch on questions of temporal parts, and whether objects 'endure' or 'perdure'.) ## 4. Two More Paradoxes Two more paradoxes are attributed to Zeno by Aristotle, but they are given in the context of other points that he is making, so Zeno's intent cannot be determined with any certainty: even whether they are intended to argue against plurality and motion. We will discuss them briefly for completeness. ### 4.1 The Paradox of Place > > Zeno's difficulty demands an explanation; for if everything that > exists has a place, place too will have a place, and so on *ad > infinitum*. (Aristotle *Physics*, 209a23) > When he sets up his theory of place--the crucial spatial notion in his theory of motion--Aristotle lists various theories and problems that his predecessors, including Zeno, have formulated on the subject. The argument again raises issues of the infinite, since the second step of the argument argues for an infinite regress of places. However, Aristotle presents it as an argument against the very idea of place, rather than plurality (thereby likely taking it out of context). It is hard to feel the force of the conclusion, for why should there not be an infinite series of places of places of places of ...? Presumably the worry would be greater for someone who (like Aristotle) believed that there could not be an actual infinity of things, for the argument seems to show that there are. But as we have discussed above, today we need have no such qualms; there seems nothing problematic with an actual infinity of places. The only other way one might find the regress troubling is if one holds that bodies have 'absolute' places, in the sense that there is always a unique privileged answer to the question 'where is it'? The problem then is not that there are infinitely many places, but just that there are many. And Aristotle might have had this concern, for in his theory of motion, the natural motion of a body is determined by the relation of its place to the center of the universe: an account that requires place to be determinate, because natural motion is. (See Sorabji 1988 and Morrison 2002 for general, competing accounts of Aristotle's views on place; chapter 3 of the latter especially for a discussion of Aristotle's treatment of the paradox.) But supposing that one holds that place is absolute for whatever reason, then for example, where am I as I write? If the paradox is right then I'm in my place, and I'm also in my place's place, and my place's place's place, and my .... Since I'm in all these places any might seem an appropriate answer to the question. Various responses are conceivable: deny absolute places (especially since our physics does not require them), define a notion of place that is unique in all cases (arguably Aristotle's solution), or perhaps claim that places are their own places thereby cutting off the regress! ### 4.2 The Grain of Millet > > ... Zeno's reasoning is false when he argues that there is > no part of the millet that does not make a sound; for there is no > reason why any part should not in any length of time fail to move the > air that the whole bushel moves in falling. (Aristotle > *Physics*, 250a19) > In context, Aristotle is explaining that a fraction of a force many not produce the same fraction of motion. For instance, while 100 stevedores can tow a barge, one might not get it to move at all, let alone 1/100th of the speed; so given as much time as you like he may not move it as far as the 100. (We describe this fact as the effect of friction.) Similarly, just because a falling bushel of millet makes a whooshing sound as it falls, it does not follow that each individual grain would, or does: given as much time as you like it won't move the same amount of air as the bushel does. However, while refuting this premise Aristotle does not explain what role it played for Zeno, and we can only speculate. It's not even clear whether it is part of a paradox, or some other dispute: did Zeno also claim to show that a single grain of millet does *not* make a sound? One speculation is that our senses reveal that it does not, since we cannot hear a single grain falling. Then Aristotle's response is apt; and so is the similar response that hearing itself requires movement in the air above a certain threshold. ## 5. Zeno's Influence on Philosophy In this final section we should consider briefly the impact that Zeno has had on various philosophers; a search of the literature will reveal that these debates continue. * The Pythagoreans: For the first half of the Twentieth century, the majority reading--following Tannery (1885)--of Zeno held that his arguments were directed against a technical doctrine of the Pythagoreans. According to this reading they held that all things were composed of elements that had the properties of a unit number, a geometric point and a physical atom: this kind of position would fit with their doctrine that reality is fundamentally mathematical. However, in the middle of the century a series of commentators (Vlastos, 1967, summarizes the argument and contains references) forcefully argued that Zeno's target was instead a common sense understanding of plurality and motion--one grounded in familiar geometrical notions--and indeed that the doctrine was not a major part of Pythagorean thought. We have implicitly assumed that these arguments are correct in our readings of the paradoxes. That said, Tannery's interpretation still has its defenders (see e.g., Matson 2001). * The Atomists: Aristotle (*On Generation and Corruption* 316b34) claims that our third argument--the one concerning complete divisibility--was what convinced the atomists that there must be smallest, indivisible parts of matter. See Abraham (1972) for a further discussion of Zeno's connection to the atomists. * Temporal Becoming: In the early part of the Twentieth century several influential philosophers attempted to put Zeno's arguments to work in the service of a metaphysics of 'temporal becoming', the (supposed) process by which the present comes into being. Such thinkers as Bergson (1911), James (1911, Ch 10-11) and Whitehead (1929) argued that Zeno's paradoxes show that space and time are not structured as a mathematical continuum: they argued that the way to preserve the reality of motion was to deny that space and time are composed of points and instants. However, we have clearly seen that the tools of standard modern mathematics are up to the job of resolving the paradoxes, so no such conclusion seems warranted: if the present indeed 'becomes', there is no reason to think that the process is not captured by the continuum. * Applying the Mathematical Continuum to Physical Space and Time: Following a lead given by Russell (1929, 182-198), a number of philosophers--most notably Grunbaum (1967)--took up the task of showing how modern mathematics could solve all of Zeno's paradoxes; their work has thoroughly influenced our discussion of the arguments. What they realized was that a purely mathematical solution was not sufficient: the paradoxes not only question abstract mathematics, but also the nature of physical reality. So what they sought was an argument not only that Zeno posed no threat to the mathematics of infinity but also that that mathematics correctly describes objects, time and space. It would not answer Zeno's paradoxes if the mathematical framework we invoked was not a good description of actual space, time, and motion! The idea that a mathematical law--say Newton's law of universal gravity--may or may not correctly describe things is familiar, but some aspects of the mathematics of infinity--the nature of the continuum, definition of infinite sums and so on--seem so basic that it may be hard to see at first that they too apply contingently. But surely they do: nothing guarantees *a priori* that space has the structure of the continuum, or even that parts of space add up according to Cauchy's definition. (Salmon offers a nice example to help make the point: since alcohol dissolves in water, if you mix the two you end up with less than the sum of their volumes, showing that even ordinary addition is not applicable to every kind of system.) Our belief that the mathematical theory of infinity describes space and time is justified to the extent that the laws of physics assume that it does, and to the extent that those laws are themselves confirmed by experience. While it is true that almost all physical theories assume that space and time do indeed have the structure of the continuum, it is also the case that quantum theories of gravity likely imply that they do not. While no one really knows where this research will ultimately lead, it is quite possible that space and time will turn out, at the most fundamental level, to be quite unlike the mathematical continuum that we have assumed here. One should also note that Grunbaum took the job of showing that modern mathematics describes space and time to involve something rather different from arguing that it is confirmed by experience. The dominant view at the time (though not at present) was that scientific terms had meaning insofar as they referred directly to objects of experience--such as '1m ruler'--or, if they referred to 'theoretical' rather than 'observable' entities--such as 'a point of space' or '1/2 of 1/2 of ... 1/2 a racetrack'--then they obtained meaning by their logical relations--via definitions and theoretical laws--to such observation terms. Thus Grunbaum undertook an impressive program to give meaning to all terms involved in the modern theory of infinity, interpreted as an account of space and time. * Supertasks: A further strand of thought concerns what Black (1950-51) dubbed 'infinity machines'. Black and his followers wished to show that although Zeno's paradoxes offered no problem to mathematics, they showed that after all mathematics was not applicable to space, time and motion. Most starkly, our resolution to the Dichotomy and Achilles assumed that the complete run could be broken down into an infinite series of half runs, which could be summed. But is it really possible to complete any infinite series of actions: to complete what is known as a 'supertask'? If not, and assuming that Atalanta and Achilles can complete their tasks, their complete runs cannot be correctly described as an infinite series of half-runs, although modern mathematics would so describe them. What infinity machines are supposed to establish is that an infinite series of tasks cannot be completed--so any completable task cannot be broken down into an infinity of smaller tasks, whatever mathematics suggests. * Infinitesimals: Finally, we have seen how to tackle the paradoxes using the resources of mathematics as developed in the Nineteenth century. For a long time it was considered one of the great virtues of this system that it finally showed that infinitesimal quantities, smaller than any finite number but larger than zero, are unnecessary. (Newton's calculus for instance effectively made use of such numbers, treating them sometimes as zero and sometimes as finite; the problem with such an approach is that how to treat the numbers is a matter of intuition not rigor.) However, in the Twentieth century Robinson showed how to introduce infinitesimal numbers into mathematics: this is the system of 'non-standard analysis' (the familiar system of real numbers, given a rigorous foundation by Dedekind, is by contrast just 'analysis'). Analogously, Bell (1988) explains how infinitesimal line segments can be introduced into geometry, and comments on their relation to Zeno. Moreover, McLaughlin (1992, 1994) shows how Zeno's paradoxes can be resolved in non-standard analysis; they are no more argument against non-standard analysis than against the standard mathematics we have assumed here. It should be emphasized however that--contrary to McLaughlin's suggestions--there is no need for non-standard analysis to solve the paradoxes: either system is equally successful. (Reeder, 2015, argues that non-standard analysis is unsatisfactory regarding the arrow, and offers an alternative account using a different conception of infinitesimals.) The construction of non-standard analysis does however raise a further question about the applicability of analysis to physical space and time: it seems plausible that all physical theories can be formulated in either terms, and so as far as our experience extends both seem equally confirmed. But they cannot both be true of space and time: either space has infinitesimal parts or it doesn't. ## Further Readings After the relevant entries in this encyclopedia, the place to begin any further investigation is Salmon (2001), which contains some of the most important articles on Zeno up to 1970, and an impressively comprehensive bibliography of works in English in the Twentieth Century. One might also take a look at Huggett (1999, Ch. 3) and Huggett (2010, Ch. 2-3) for further source passages and discussion. For introductions to the mathematical ideas behind the modern resolutions, the Appendix to Salmon (2001) or Stewart (2017) are good starts; Russell (1919) and Courant *et al*. (1996, Chs. 2 and 9) are also both wonderful sources. Finally, three collections of original sources for Zeno's paradoxes: Lee (1936 [2015]) contains everything known, Kirk *et al* (1983, Ch. 9) contains a great deal of material (in English and Greek) with useful commentaries, and Cohen *et al*. (1995) also has the main passages.
zermelo-set-theory
## 1. The Axioms The introduction to Zermelo's paper makes it clear that set theory is regarded as a fundamental theory: > > Set theory is that branch of mathematics whose task is to > investigate mathematically the fundamental notions > "number", "order", and > "function", taking them in their pristine, simple form, > and to develop thereby the logical foundations of all of arithmetic > and analysis; thus it constitutes an indispensable component of the > science of mathematics. > (1908b: 261)[1] > > > This is followed by an acknowledgment that it is necessary to replace the central assumption that we can 'assign to an arbitrary logically definable notion a "set", or "class", as its "extension" ' (1908b: 261). Zermelo goes on: > > In solving the problem [this presents] we must, on the one hand, > restrict these principles [distilled from the actual operation with > sets] sufficiently to exclude all contradictions and, on the other, > take them sufficiently wide to retain all that is valuable in this > theory. (1908b: 261) > > > The 'central assumption' which Zermelo describes (let us call it the Comprehension Principle, or CP) had come to be seen by many as the principle behind the derivation of the set-theoretic inconsistencies. Russell (1903: SS104) says the following: > > Perhaps the best way to state the suggested solution [of the > Russell-Zermelo contradiction] is to say that, if a collection of > terms can only be defined by a variable propositional function, > then, though a class as many may be admitted, a class as one must be > denied. We took it as axiomatic that the class as one is to be found > wherever there is a class as many; but this axiom need not be > universally admitted, and appears to have been the source of the > contradiction. By denying it, therefore, the whole difficulty will > be overcome. > > > But it is by no means clear that 'the whole difficulty' is thereby 'overcome'. Russell makes a clear identification of the principle he cites (a version of CP) as the source of error, but this does not in the least make it clear what is to take its place.[2] In his *Grundgesetze* (see e.g., Frege 1903: SS146-147) Frege recognises that his (in)famous Law V is based on a conversion principle which allows us to assume that for any concept (function), there is an object which contains precisely those things which fall under that concept (or for which the function returns the value 'True'). Law V is then the principle which says that two such extension objects *a*, *b* stemming from two concepts *F*, *G* are the same if, and only if, *F* and *G* are extensionally equivalent. Frege clearly considers the 'conversion' of concepts to extensions as fundamental; he also regards it as widely used in mathematics (even if only implicitly), and thus that he is not 'doing anything new' by using such a principle of conversion and the attendant 'basic law of logic', Law V. (The CP follows immediately from Law V.) Frege was made aware by Russell (1902) that his Law V is contradictory, since Russell's paradox flows easily from it. In the Appendix to *Grundgesetze* (Frege 1903), Frege says this: > > Hardly anything more unwelcome can befall a scientific writer > than to have one of the foundations of his edifice shaken after the > work is finished. This is the position into which I was put by a > letter from Mr Bertrand Russell as the printing of this volume was > nearing completion. The matter concerns my Basic Law (V). I have > never concealed from myself that it is not as obvious as the others > nor as obvious as must properly be required of a logical > law. Indeed, I pointed out this very weakness in the foreword to the > first volume, p. VII. I would gladly have dispensed with this > foundation if I had known of some substitute for it. Even now, I do > not see how arithmetic can be founded scientifically, how the > numbers can be apprehended as logical objects and brought under > consideration, if it is not--at least > conditionally--permissible to pass from a concept to its > extension. May I always speak of the extension of a concept, of a > class? And if not, how are the exceptions to be recognised? May one > always infer from the extension of one concept's coinciding with > that of a second that every object falling under the first concept > also falls under the latter? These questions arise from Mr Russell's > communication. ...What is at stake here is not my approach to a > foundation in particular, but rather the very possibility of any > logical foundation of > arithmetic. (p. 253)[3] > > > The difficulty could hardly be summed up more succinctly. It was the replacement of assumptions involving the unfettered conversion of concepts to objects which was Zermelo's main task in his axiomatisation. Zermelo's system was based on the presupposition that > > Set theory is concerned with a "domain" B of > individuals, which we shall call simply "objects" and > among which are the "sets". If two symbols, *a* > and *b*, denote the same object, we write *a* = *b*, > otherwise > *a* [?] *b*. We say of an > object *a* that it "exists" if it belongs to the > domain B; likewise we say of a class K of objects that > "there exist objects of the class K" if B > contains at least one individual of this class. (1908b: 262) > > > Given this, the one fundamental relation is that of set membership, 'e' , which allows one to state that an object *a* belongs to, or is in, a set *b*, written '*a* e *b*'.[4] Zermelo then laid down seven axioms which give a partial description of what is to be found in *B*. These can be described as follows: 1. *Extensionality* This says roughly that sets are determined by the elements they contain. 2. *Axiom of Elementary Sets* This asserts (a) the existence of a set which contains no members (denoted '0' by Zermelo, now commonly denoted by '[?]'); (b) the existence, for any object *a*, of the singleton set {*a*} which has *a* as its sole member; and (c) the existence, for any two objects *a*, *b*, of the unordered pair {*a*, *b*}, which has just *a*, *b* as its members. 3. *Separation* (*Aussonderungsaxiom*) This asserts that, for any given set *a*, and any given 'definite' property of elements in B (more on this below), one can 'separate' out from *a* as a set just those elements which satisfy the given property. 4. *Power Set* This says that for any set, the collection of all subsets of that set is also a set. 5. *Union* This says that for any set, the collection of the members of the members of that set also forms a set. 6. *Choice* This says that for any set of pairwise disjoint, non-empty sets, there exists a set (which is a subset of the union set to which the given set gives rise) which contains exactly one member from each member of the given set. 8. *Infinity* This final axiom asserts the existence of an infinitely large set which contains the empty set, and for each set *a* that it contains, also contains the set {*a*}. (Thus, this infinite set must contain [?], {[?]}, {{[?]}}, ....) With the inclusion of this last, Zermelo explicitly rejects any attempt to *prove* the existence of an infinite collection from other principles, as we find in Dedekind (1888: SS66), or in Frege via the establishment of what is known as 'Hume's Principle'. The four central axioms of Zermelo's system are the Axioms of Infinity and Power Set, which together show the existence of uncountable sets, the Axiom of Choice, to which we will devote some space below, and the Axiom of Separation. This latter allows that any 'definite' property ph does in fact give rise to a set, namely the set of all those things which are already included in some set *a* and which have the property ph, in other words, gives rise to a certain subset of *a*, namely the subset of all the ph-things in *a*. Thus, it follows from this latter that there will generally be many sets giving partial extensions of ph, namely the ph-things in *a*, the ph-things in *b*, the ph-things in *c*, and so on. However, there will be no guarantee of the existence of a unique extension-set for ph, as, of course, there is under the CP, namely *a* = {*x* : ph(*x*)}. Zermelo shows that, on the basis of his system, the two central paradoxes, that of the greatest set and that of Russell, cannot arise. In fact, Zermelo proves: > > Every set *M* possesses at least one > subset *M*0 that is not an element > of *M*. (1908b: 265) > > > The proof is an easy modification of the argument for Russell's Paradox, using the contradiction this time as *a reductio*. By Separation, let *M*0 be the subset of *M* consisting of those elements *x* of *M* such that *x* [?] *x*. Now either *M*0 [?] *M*0 or *M*0 [?] *M*0. Assume that *M*0 [?] *M*0. Since *M*0 is a subset of *M*, this tells us that *M*0 [?] *M*. But *M*0 is then a member of *M* which fails to satisfy the condition for belonging to *M*0, showing that *M*0 [?] *M*0, which is a contradiction. Hence, necessarily, *M*0 [?] *M*0. But now if we suppose that *M*0 were in *M*, then *M*0 itself is bound to be in *M*0 by the defining condition of this set. Hence, *M*0 [?] *M* on pain of contradiction. The argument for the Russell paradox is used here to constructive effect: one person's contradiction is another person's *reductio*. Zermelo comments: > > It follows from the theorem that not all objects *x* of the > domain B can be elements of one and the same set; that is, > the domain B is not itself a set, and this disposes of the > "Russell antinomy" so far as we are concerned. (1908b: > 265) > > For, in the absence of something like the CP, there is no overriding reason to think that there must *be* a universal set.[5] But although this deals with the Russell paradox and the paradox of the universal set, it does not tackle the general consistency of the system. Zermelo was well aware of this, as is clear from the Introduction to his paper: > > I have not yet even been able to prove rigorously that my axioms > are "consistent", though this is certainly very > essential; instead I have had to confine myself to pointing out now > and then that the "antinomies" discovered so far vanish > one and all if the principles here proposed are adopted as a > basis. But I hope to have done at least some useful spadework hereby > for subsequent investigations in such deeper problems. (1908b: > 262) > > > It should be remarked in passing that Zermelo doesn't deal specifically with the Burali-Forti paradox either, for the simple reason that it cannot be properly formulated in his system, since it deals either with well-orderings generally or with the general concept of ordinal number. We will come back to this below. However, assuming that the known paradoxes *can* be avoided, another question comes to the fore: if the Separation Axiom is to be the basic principle for the workaday creation of sets, is it *adequate*? This question, too, will be taken up later. There were attempts at the statement of axioms before Zermelo, both publicly and in private correspondence.[6] In particular, Cantor, in correspondence with Hilbert and Dedekind in the late 1890s, had endeavoured to describe some principles of set existence[7] which he thought were legitimate, and would not give rise to the construction of what he called 'inconsistent totalities', totalities which engender contradictions. (The best known of these totalities were the totality of all ordinals and the totality of all cardinals.) These principles included those of set union and a form of the replacement axiom, as well as principles which seem to guarantee that every cardinal number is an aleph, which we call for short the 'Aleph Hypothesis (AH)'. Despite this, there are reasons for calling Zermelo's system the first real axiomatisation of set theory. It is clear above all that Zermelo's intention was to reveal the fundamental nature of the theory of sets and to preserve its achievements, while at the same time providing a general replacement for the CP. ## 2. The Background to Zermelo's Axiomatisation ### 2.1 Hilbert's Axiomatic Method Hilbert's early work on the axiomatic method is an important part of the context of Zermelo's axiomatisation. Hilbert developed a particular version of the axiomatic approach to fundamental mathematical theories in his work on geometry in the period 1894-1904 (see Hallett and Majer 2004). This was to be seen as a distinct alternative to what Hilbert called the 'genetic approach' to mathematics. (For a short, historically informed description, see Felgner 2010: 169-174.) Ebbinghaus's book on Zermelo makes it very clear how embedded Zermelo was in the Hilbert foundational circle in the early years of the century.[8] This is not meant to suggest that Zermelo adopted Hilbert's approach to the foundations of mathematics in all its aspects. Indeed, Zermelo developed his own, distinctive approach to foundational matters which was very different from Hilbert's, something which emerges quite clearly from his later work. Nevertheless, there are two elements of Zermelo's procedure which fit very well with Hilbert's foundational approach in the early part of the century. The first element concerns what might be called the programmatic element of Hilbert's treatment of the foundations of mathematics as it emerged in the later 1890s, and especially with regard to the notion of mathematical existence. And the second concerns proof analysis, a highly important part of Hilbert's work on Euclidean geometry and geometrical systems generally. These matters are intricate, and cannot be discussed adequately here (for fuller discussion, see both Hallett 2008 and 2010a). But it is important for understanding Zermelo's work fully that a rough account be given. #### 2.1.1 Programmatic elements First, Hilbert adopted the view that a mature presentation of a mathematical theory must be given axiomatically. This, he claims, requires several things: 1. The postulation of the existence of a domain, of a 'system (or systems) of things'. 3. The insistence, however, that nothing is known about those things except what is expressed in, or can be derived from, a finite list of axioms. 4. The requirement, along with this, of finite proofs, which begin with axioms and proceed from these to a conclusion by a 'finite number of inferences' (i.e., acceptable inferential steps). 5. The rather imprecise notion of the 'completeness' of the axiomatisation, which involves, loosely, showing that the axioms can prove all that they 'ought' to prove. 6. The provision of a consistency proof for these axioms, showing that no contradiction is derivable by a proof constructed in the system given. For one thing, Hilbert was very clear (especially in his unpublished lectures on geometry: see Hallett and Majer 2004) that, although a domain is asserted to 'exist', all that is known about the objects in the domain is what is given to us by the axioms and what can be derived from these through 'finite proof'. In other words, while a domain is postulated, nothing is taken to be known about the things in it independently of the axioms laid down and what they entail. The basic example was given by geometrical systems of points, lines and planes; although the geometrical domain is made up of these things, nothing can be assumed known about them (in particular no 'intuitive' geometrical knowledge from whatever source) other than what is given in the axioms or which can be derived from them by legitimate inference. (The axioms themselves might sum up, or be derived from, 'intuitive' knowledge, but that is a different matter. And even here it is important that we can detach the axioms from their intuitive meanings.) Secondly, while 'existence' of the objects is just a matter (as Zermelo says) of belonging to the domain (a fact which is established by the axioms or by proofs from those axioms), the mathematical existence of the domain itself, and (correspondingly) of the system set out by the axioms, is established only by a consistency proof for the axioms. Thus, to take the prime example, the 'existence' of Euclidean geometry (or more accurately Euclidean geometries) is shown by the consistency proofs given by means of analytic geometry.[9] Thus, the unit of consistency is not the concept nor the individual propositions, but rather the system of axioms as a whole, and different systems necessarily give accounts of different primitives. The expectation is that when a domain is axiomatised, attention will turn (at some point) to a consistency proof, and this will deal finally with the question of mathematical existence. In any case, the task of showing existence is a mathematical one and there is no further ontological or metaphysical mystery to be solved once the axioms are laid down. Many aspects of Hilbert's position are summed up in this passage from his 1902 lectures on the foundations of geometry: the axioms 'create' the domains, and the consistency proofs justify their existence. As he puts it: > > The things with which mathematics is concerned are > defined through axioms, *brought into life*. > > > The axioms can be taken quite arbitrarily. However, if these axioms > contradict each other, then no logical consequences can be drawn from > them; the system defined then does not exist for the > mathematician. (Hilbert 1902: 47 or Hallett and Majer 2004: 563) > > > This notion of 'definition through axioms', what came to be known as the method of 'implicit definition', can be seen in various writings of Hilbert's from around 1900. His attitude to existence is illustrated in the following passage from his famous paper on the axiomatisation of the reals: > > The objections which have been raised against the existence of > the totality of all real numbers and infinite sets generally lose > all their justification once one has adopted the view stated above > [the axiomatic method]. By the set of the real numbers we do not > have to imagine something like the totality of all possible laws > governing the development of a fundamental series, but rather, as > has been set out, a system of things whose mutual relations are > given by the *finite and closed* systems of axioms I-IV [for > complete ordered fields] given above, and about which statements > only have validity in the case where one can derive them via a > finite number of inferences from those axioms. (Hilbert 1900b: > 184)[10] > > > The parallels between this 'axiomatic method' of Hilbert's and Zermelo's axiomatisation of set theory are reasonably clear, if not exact.[11] Particularly clear are the assumption of the existence of a 'domain' B, the statement of a finite list of axioms governing its contents, and the recognition of the requirement of a general consistency proof. There's also implicit recognition of the requirements of 'finite proof'; this leads us to the second important aspect of the Hilbertian background, namely proof analysis and the use of the Axiom of Choice. #### 2.1.2 Proof analysis and Zermelo's Well-Ordering Theorem [WOT] A great deal of Hilbert's work on geometry concerned the analysis of proofs, of what can, or cannot, be derived from what. Much of Hilbert's novel work on geometry involved the clever use of (arithmetical) models for geometrical systems to demonstrate a succession of independence results, which, among other things, often show how finely balanced various central assumptions are.[12] Moreover, a close reading of Hilbert's work makes it clear that the development of an appropriate axiom system itself goes hand-in-hand with the reconstruction and analysis of proofs. One straightforward kind of proof analysis was designed to reveal what assumptions there are behind accepted 'theorems', and this is clearly pertinent in the case of Zermelo's Axiom of Choice (his sixth axiom) and the WOT. What Zermelo's work showed, in effect, is that the 'choice' principle behind the Axiom is a necessary and sufficient condition for WOT; and he shows this by furnishing a Hilbertian style proof for the theorem, i.e., a conclusion which follows from (fairly) clear assumptions by means of a finite number of inferential steps. Indeed, the Axiom is chosen so as to make the WOT provable, and it transpired subsequently that it also made provable a vast array of results, mainly (but not solely) in set theory and in set-theoretic algebra. To understand the importance of Zermelo's work, it's necessary to appreciate the centrality of the WOT. ### 2.2 The Well-Ordering Problem and the Well-Ordering Theorem #### 2.2.1 The importance of the problem before Zermelo In one of the fundamental papers in the genesis of set theory, Cantor (1883a) isolated the notion of a well-ordering on a collection as one of the central conceptual pillars on which number is built. Cantor took the view that the notion of a counting number must be based on an underlying ordering of the set of things being counted, an ordering in which there is a first element counted, and, following any collection of elements counted, there must be a next element counted, assuming that there are elements still uncounted. This kind of ordering he called a 'well-ordering', which we now define as a total-ordering with an extra condition, namely that any subset has a least element in the ordering. Cantor recognised that each distinct well-ordering of the elements gives rise to a distinct counting number, what he originally called an '*Anzahl* [enumeral]', later an '*Ordnungszahl* [ordinal number]', numbers which are conceptually quite different from *cardinal numbers* or *powers*, meant to express just the size of collections.[13] This distinction is hard to perceive at first sight. Before Cantor and the rise of the modern theory of transfinite numbers, the standard counting numbers were the ordinary finite numbers.[14] And, crucially, for finite collections, it turns out that any two orderings of the same underlying elements, which are certainly well-orderings in Cantor's sense, are order-isomorphic, i.e., not essentially distinct.[15] This means that one can in effect identify a number arrived at by counting (an ordinal number) with the cardinal number of the collection counted. Thus, the ordinary natural numbers appear in two guises, and it is possible to determine the size of a finite collection directly by counting it. Cantor observed that this ceases to be the case in rather dramatic fashion once one considers infinite collections; here, the same elements can give rise to a large variety of distinct well-orderings. Nevertheless, Cantor noticed that if one collects together all the countable ordinal numbers, i.e., the numbers representing well-orderings of the set of natural numbers, this collection, which Cantor called the *second number-class* (the first being the set of natural numbers), must be of greater cardinality than that of the collection of natural numbers itself. Moreover, this size is the cardinal *successor* to the size of the natural numbers in the very clear sense that any infinite subset of the second number-class is either of the power of the natural numbers or of the power of the whole class; thus, there can be no size which is strictly intermediate. The process generalises: collect together all the ordinal numbers representing well-orderings of the second number-class to form the third number-class, and this must be the immediate successor in size to that of the second number-class, and so on. In this way, Cantor could use the ordinal numbers to generate an infinite sequence of cardinalities or powers. This sequence was later (Cantor 1895) called the aleph-sequence, 0 (the size of the natural numbers), 1 (expressing the size of the second number-class), 2 (expressing the size of the third number-class), and so on. Since the intention was that ordinal numbers could be generated arbitrarily far, then so too, it seems, could the alephs. This raises the possibility of reinstating the centrality of the ordinal numbers as the fundamental numbers even in the case of infinite sets, thus making ordinality the foundation of cardinality for all sets. In work after 1883, Cantor attempted to show that the alephs actually represent a scale of infinite cardinal number. For instance, it is shown that the ordinal numbers are comparable, i.e., for any two ordinal numbers a, b, either a < b, a = b or a > b, a desirable, perhaps essential, property of counting numbers. Through this, comparability therefore transfers to the alephs, and Cantor was able to give clear and appropriate arithmetical operations of addition, multiplication and exponentiation, generalising the corresponding notions for finite collections, and the statement and proof of general laws concerning these. In 1878, Cantor had put forward the hypothesis that there is no infinite power between that of the natural numbers and the continuum. This became known as Cantor's Continuum Hypothesis (CH). With the adumbration of the number classes, CH takes on the form that the continuum has the power of the second number-class, and with the development of the aleph-scale, it assumes the form of a conjecture about the exponentiation operation in the generalised cardinal arithmetic, for it can be expressed in the form 20 = 1. The *continuum problem* more generally construed is really the problem of where the power of the continuum is in the scale of aleph numbers, and the generalised continuum hypothesis is the conjecture that taking the power set of an infinite set corresponds to moving up just one level in the aleph scale. For example, in 1883, Cantor had assumed (without remark) that the set of all real functions has the size of the third number-class. Given the CH, this then becomes the conjecture that 21 = 2. But adopting the aleph scale as a framework for infinite cardinality depends on significant assumptions. It is clear that any collection in well-ordered form (given that it is represented by an ordinal) must have an aleph-number representing its size, so clearly the aleph-sequence represents the sizes (or *powers* as Cantor called them) of all the well-ordered sets. However, can *any* set be put into well-ordered form? A particular question of this form concerns the continuum itself: if the continuum is equivalent to the second number-class, then clearly it can be well-ordered, and indeed this is a necessary condition for showing that the continuum is represented at all in the scale. But *can* it be well-ordered? More generally, to assume that *any* cardinality is represented in the scale of aleph numbers is to assume in particular that *any* set can be well-ordered. And to assume that the aleph-sequence is *the* scale of infinite cardinal number is to assume at the very least that sets generally can be compared cardinally; i.e., that for any *M*, *N*, either *M* [?] *N* or *N* [?] *M*, COMP for short. But is this correct? When introducing the notion of well-ordering in 1883, Cantor expressed his belief that the fact that any set ('manifold') can be well-ordered is 'a law of thought [Denkgesetz]', thus putting forward what for convenience we can call the well-ordering hypothesis (WOH): > > The concept of *well-ordered set* reveals itself as > fundamental for the theory of manifolds. That it is always possible to > arrange any *well-defined* set in the form of a *well-ordered* set is, it > seems to me, a very basic law of thought, rich in consequences, and > particularly remarkable in virtue of its general validity. I will > return to this in a later memoir. (Cantor 1883a or 1932: 169) > > > Cantor says nothing about what it might mean to call the well-ordering hypothesis a 'law of thought', and he never did return to this question directly; however, in one form or another, this claim is key. It could be that Cantor at this time considered the WOH as something like a logical principle.[16] This, however, is not particularly clear, especially since the study of formal logic adequate for mathematical reasoning was only in its infancy, and the set concept itself was new and rather unclearly delimited. Another suggestion is that well-orderability is intrinsic to the way that 'well-defined' sets are either presented or conceived, e.g., that it is impossible to think of a collection's being a set without at the same time allowing that its elements can be arranged 'discretely' in some way, or even that such arrangement can be automatically deduced from the 'definition'. Thus, if one views sets as necessary for mathematics, and one holds that the concept of set itself necessarily involves the discrete arrangement of the elements of the set, then WOH might appear necessary, too. But all of this is imprecise, not least because the notion of set itself was imprecise and imprecisely formulated. One clear implication of Cantor's remark is that he regards the WOH as something which does not require proof. Nonetheless, not long after he had stated this, Cantor clearly had doubts both about the well-orderability of the continuum and about cardinal comparability (see Moore 1982: 44). All of this suggested that the WOH, and the associated hypothesis that the alephs represent the scale of infinite cardinality, do require proof, and cannot just be taken as 'definitional'. Thus, it seemed clear that the whole Cantorian project of erecting a scale of infinite size depends at root on the correctness of the WOH. Work subsequent to 1884 suggests that Cantor felt the need to supply arguments for well-ordering. For instance (Cantor 1895: 493) to show that every infinite set *T* has a countable subset (and thus that 0 is the smallest cardinality), Cantor set out to *prove the existence* of a subset of *T* which is well-ordered like the natural numbers. The key point to observe here is that Cantor felt it necessary to *exhibit* a well-ordered subset of *T*, and did not simply proceed by first assuming (by appeal to his '*Denkgesetz*') that *M* can be arranged in well-ordered form. He exhibits such a subset in the following way: > > *Proof.* If one has removed from *T* a finite number of > elements *t*1, *t*2, > ..., *t*n[?]1 according to some rule, > then the possibility always remains of extracting a further > element *t*n. The set {*t*n}, > in which n denotes an arbitrary finite, cardinal number, is a > subset of *T* with the cardinal number 0, > because {*t*n} [?] {n}. (Cantor 1895: > 493) > > > In 1932, Zermelo edited Cantor's collected papers (Cantor 1932), and commented on this particular proof as follows: > > The "proof" of Theorem A, which is purely intuitive > and logically unsatisfactory, recalls the well-known primitive > attempt to arrive at a *well-ordering* of a given set by successive > removal of arbitrary elements. We arrive at a correct proof only > when we *start from* an already *well-ordered* set, whose smallest > transfinite initial segment in fact has the cardinal number > 0 sought. (Zermelo in Cantor 1932: 352) > > > The second context in which an argument was given was an attempt by Cantor (in correspondence first with Hilbert and then Dedekind) to show that every set must have an aleph-number as a cardinal.[17] What Cantor attempts to show, in effect, is the following. Assume that O represents the sequence of all ordinal numbers, and assume (for a *reductio* argument) that *V* is a 'multiplicity' which is not equivalent to any aleph. Then Cantor argues that O can be 'projected' into *V*, in turn showing that *V* must be what he calls an 'inconsistent multiplicity', i.e., not a legitimate set. It will follow that all sets have alephs as cardinals, since they will always be 'exhausted' by such a projection by some ordinal or other, in which case they will be cardinally equivalent to some ordinal number-class.[18] Zermelo's dismissal of this attempted proof is no surprise, given the comments just quoted. But he also comments further here exactly on this 'projection': > > The weakness of the proof outlined lies precisely > here. It is *not* proved that the whole series of numbers O can be > "projected into" any multiplicity *V* which does not > have an aleph as a cardinal number, but this is rather taken from a > somewhat vague "intuition". Apparently *Cantor* imagines the > numbers of O successively and arbitrarily assigned to elements > of *V* in such a way that every element of *V* is only used > once. *Either* this process must then come to an end, in that all > elements of *V* are used up, in which case *V* would be then > be coordinated with an *initial* segment of the number series, and its > power consequently an aleph, contrary to assumption; *or* *V* would > remain inexhaustible and would then contain a component equivalent to > the whole of O, thus an inconsistent component. Here, the > intuition of time [*Zeitanschauung*] is being applied to a process which > goes beyond all intuition, and a being [*Wesen*] supposed which can make > *successive* arbitrary choices and thereby define a subset *V*' > of *V* which is not definable by the conditions given. (Zermelo in Cantor 1932: > 451)[19] > > > If it really is 'successive' selection which is relied on, then it seems that one must be assuming a subset of instants of time which is well-ordered and which forms a base ordering from which the 'successive' selections are made. In short, what is really presupposed is a well-ordered subset of temporal instants which acts as the basis for a recursive definition. Even in the case of countable subsets, if the 'process' is actually to come to a conclusion, the 'being' presupposed would presumably have to be able to distinguish a (countably) infinite, discrete sequence of instants within a finite time, and this assumption is, as is well-known, a notoriously controversial one. In the general case, the position is actually worse, for here the question of the well-orderability of the given set depends at the very least on the existence of a well-ordered subset of temporal instants of arbitrarily high infinite cardinality. This appears to go against the assumption that time is an ordinary continuum, i.e., of cardinality 20, unless of course the power set of the natural numbers itself is too 'big' to be counted by any ordinal, in which case much of the point of the argument would be lost, for one of its aims is presumably to show that the power of the continuum is somewhere in the aleph-sequence.[20] Part of what is at issue here, at least implicitly, is what constitutes a proof. It seems obvious that if a set is non-empty, then it must be possible to 'choose' an element from it (i.e., there must exist an element in it). Indeed, the obviousness of this is enshrined in the modern logical calculus by the way the inference principle of Existential Instantiation (EI) usually works: from [?]*x**P**x* one assumes *Pc*, where '*c*' is a new constant, and reasons on that basis; whatever can be inferred from *P*(*c*) (as long as it does not itself contain the new constant '*c*') is then taken to be inferable from [?]*x**P**x* alone. Furthermore, it is clear how this extends to finite sets (or finite extensions) by stringing together successive inferential steps. But how can such an inferential procedure be extended to infinite sets, if at all? Some evidence of the centrality of WOH is provided by Problem 1 on Hilbert's list of mathematical problems in his famous lecture to the International Congress of Mathematicians in Paris in 1900. He notes Cantor's conviction of the correctness of CH, and its 'great probability', then goes on to mention another 'remarkable assertion' of Cantor's, namely his belief that the continuum, although not (in its natural order) in well-ordered form, can be rearranged as a well-ordered set. However, Russell, writing at roughly the same time, expressed doubts about precisely this: > > Cantor assumes as an axiom that every class is the field of some > well-ordered series, and deduces that all cardinals can be > correlated with ordinals .... This assumption seems to me > unwarranted, especially in view of the fact that no one has yet > succeeded in arranging a class of 2a0 > terms in a well-ordered series. (Russell 1903: 322-323) > > > He goes on: > > We do not know that of any two different cardinal numbers one > must be the greater, and it may be that > 2a0 is neither greater nor less that > a1 and a2 and their successors, > which may be called well-ordered cardinals because they apply to > well-ordered series. (Russell 1903: > 323)[21] > > > And recall that, at the International Congress of Mathematicians in Heidelberg in 1904, Konig had given an apparently convincing proof that the continuum *cannot* be an aleph. Konig's argument, as we know, turned out to contain fatal flaws, but in any case, the confusion it exhibits is instructive.[22] In short, the clear impression in the immediate period leading up to Zermelo's work was *both* that only the WOH would provide a solid foundation on which to build a reasonable notion of infinite cardinal number as a proper framework for tackling CH, *and* that WOH requires justification, that it must become, in effect, the WOT, the WO-Theorem. In short, establishing the WOT was closely bound up with the clarification of what it is to count as a set. #### 2.2.2 Zermelo's 1904 Proof of the Well-Ordering Theorem Zermelo's approach to the well-ordering problem took place in three stages. He published a proof of WOT in 1904 (Zermelo 1904, an extract from a letter to Hilbert), where he first introduced the 'choice' principle, a principle designed (despite the name it has come to bear) to move away from the Cantorian 'choosing' arguments which almost universally preceded Zermelo's work, and which postulates that arbitrary 'choices' have already been made. This paper produced an outcry, to which Zermelo responded by producing a new proof (1908a), which again uses the choice principle, but this time in a somewhat different form and expressed now explicitly as an axiom. The first three pages of this paper give the new proof; this was then followed by seventeen pages which reply in great detail to many of the objections raised against the first proof. These consisted in objections to the choice principle itself, and also objections to the unclarity of the underlying assumptions about, and operation with, sets used in the proof. This paper was followed just two months later by Zermelo's official axiomatisation (1908b), an axiomatisation which to a large degree was prefigured in the paper (1908a). Zermelo's 1904 proof can be briefly described. (1) Let *M* be an arbitrarily given set, and let **M** be its power set. Assume given what Zermelo calls a 'covering' of **M**, i.e., a function g from non-empty elements of **M** to *M* such that g(*X*) [?] *X*, in other words, what would now be called a choice function. The argument then shows that such a g determines a unique well-ordering of *M*.[23] (2) Using a fixed such g, Zermelo then defines the so-called g-sets *M*g. These satisfy the following conditions: 1. *M*g [?] *M*; 2. *M*g is well-ordered by some ordering [?] specific to *M*g; 3. If a [?] *M*g, then *a* must determine an initial segment *A* of *M*g under [?]; but now g and [?] must be related in such a way that *a* = g(*M* [?] *A*), i.e., *a* is the 'distinguished element' (as Zermelo calls it) of the complement of *A* in *M*. (3) There clearly are g sets: {*m*1} is one such, where *m*1 = g(*M*) and where we take the trivial well-ordering. The set {*m*1, *m*2} is also a g-set, where again *m*1 = g(*M*), *m*2 = g(*M* [?] {*m*1}), and {*m*1, *m*2} is given the ordering which places *m*2 after *m*1. (Note that {*m*1, *m*2} with the other ordering would not be a g-set.) In fact, it is easy to see that if *M*' [?] *M* is to be a g-set, then condition (2)(c) means that [?] is uniquely (one is tempted to say, recursively) determined. (4) Indeed, following this, Zermelo shows that of any two distinct g-sets, one is identical to an initial segment of the other, and the well-ordering of the latter extends the well-ordering of the former. (5) Zermelo now considers the set *L*g, which is the union taken over all the g-sets. It is not difficult to see that *L*g itself must be a g-set, indeed, the largest such. By definition, *L*g [?] *M*; but Zermelo shows that equality must hold. If not, then *M* [?] *L*g would be a non-empty subset of *M*, in which case we can consider g(*M* [?] *L*g) = *m*1'. Now form *L*g' *L*g [?] {*m*1'}, and supply it with the well-ordering which is the same as that in *L*g, except that we extend it by fixing that *x* [?] *m*1' for any *x* [?] *L*g. Clearly now *L*g' is a g-set, but one which properly extends *L*g, which is a contradiction. Thus *L*g' = *M*, and so *M* can be well-ordered by the ordering of *L*g'.[24] As Zermelo points out (p. 516 of his paper), the WOT establishes a firm foundation for the theory of infinite cardinality; in particular, it shows, he says, that every set ('for which the totality of its subsets etc. has a sense') can be considered as a well-ordered set 'and its power considered as an aleph'. Later work of Hartogs (see Hartogs 1915) showed that, not only does WOT imply COMP as Zermelo shows, but that COMP itself implies WOT, and thus in turn Zermelo's choice principle. Thus, it is not just COMP which is necessary for a reasonable theory of infinite cardinality, but WOT itself. Despite Zermelo's endorsement here, the correctness of the hypothesis that the scale of aleph numbers represents *all* cardinals (AH, for short) is a more complicated matter, for it involves the claim that every set is actually equivalent to an initial segment of the ordinals, and not just well-orderable. In axiomatic frameworks for sets, therefore, the truth of AH depends very much on which ordinals are present as sets in the system. The subsequent work showing the independence of AC from the other axioms of set theory vindicates Zermelo's pioneering work; in this respect, it puts Zermelo's revelation of the choice principle in a similar position as that which Hilbert ascribes to the Parallel Postulate in Euclid's work. Hilbert claims that Euclid must have realised that to establish certain 'obvious' facts about triangles, rectangles etc., an entirely *new* axiom (Euclid's Parallel Postulate) was necessary, and moreover that Gauss was the first mathematician 'for 2100 years' to see that Euclid had been right (see Hallett and Majer 2004:261-263 and 343-345). This 'pragmatic attitude', which is on display in Zermelo's second paper on well-ordering from 1908, became, in effect, the reigning attitude towards the choice principle: If certain problems are to be solved, then the choice principle must be adopted. In 1908, Zermelo brings out this parallel explicitly: > > Banishing fundamental facts or problems from science merely > because they cannot be dealt with by means of certain prescribed > principles would be like forbidding the further extension of the > theory of parallels in geometry because the axiom upon which this > theory rests has been shown to be unprovable. (Zermelo 1908a: > 115) > > > Zermelo does not in 1904 call the choice principle an axiom; it is, rather, designated a 'logical principle'. What Zermelo has to say by way of an explanation is very short: > > This logical principle cannot, to be sure, be reduced to a still > simpler one, but it is applied without hesitation everywhere in > mathematical deduction. (Zermelo 1904: 516) > > > It is not clear from this whether he thinks of the choice principle as a 'law of thought', as the term 'logical principle' might suggest, or whether he thinks it is just intrinsic to mathematical reasoning whenever sets are involved, a position suggested by the reference to its application 'everywhere in mathematical deduction'. By the time of his second well-ordering paper of 1908, Zermelo seems to have moved away from the idea of AC as a 'logical' principle in the sense of a logical law, and appears to put the emphasis more on the view of it as intrinsic to the subject matter; there it appears as Axiom IV, and, as we saw, Axiom VI of Zermelo 1908b.[25] #### 2.2.3 Objections to the 1904 Proof There were three central objections. 1. Objections to the Choice Principle. 2. Objections to Zermelo's general operation with sets, especially well-orderings. 3. Objections to impredicative definitions. Let us briefly deal with these. (a) The objections to the choice principle were of two kinds. The main objection was put forward by Borel in 1905 in the *Mathematische Annalen* (Borel 1905), the journal which published Zermelo's paper, and it is also widely discussed in correspondence between some leading French mathematicians, and also published in that year in the same Journal (see Hadamard et al. 1905). The objection is basically that Zermelo's principle fails to specify a 'law' or 'rule' by which the choices are effected; in other words, the covering used is not explicitly defined, which means that the resulting well-ordering is not explicitly defined either. In a letter to Borel, Hadamard makes it clear that the opposition in question is really that between the assumption of the existence of an object which is fully described, and of the existence of an object which is *not* fully described (see Hadamard et al. 1905, esp. 262). In his reply, Zermelo remarks that the inability to describe the choices is why the choice principle is in effect an *axiom*, which has to be added to the other principles. In effect, the position is that if one wants to do certain things which, e.g., rely on the WOT, then the choice principle is indispensable. His position, to repeat, is like the one that Euclidean geometry takes towards parallels. (b) An objection to the choice principle was also put forward by Peano. This objection seems to be that since the choice principle cannot be proved 'syllogistically' (i.e., from the principles of Peano's *Formulario*), then it has to be rejected (see Peano 1906). (Peano does think, however, that finite versions of the choice principle are provable, relying essentially on repeated applications of a version for classes of the basic logical principle EI mentioned above (SS2.2.1). Zermelo's reply is the following. Axiom systems like Peano's are constructed so as to be adequate for mathematics; but how does one go about selecting the 'basic principles' required? One cannot assemble a complete list of adequate principles, says Zermelo, without careful inspection of actual mathematics and thereby a careful assessment of what principles are actually necessary to such a list, and such inspection would show that the choice principle is surely one such; in other words, a selection of principles such as Peano's is very much a *post hoc* procedure. The reply to Peano is of a piece with the reply to Borel, and recalls strongly the invocation in Zermelo (1908b: 261), that it is necessary to distill principles from the actual operation with sets. He supports his claim that the choice principle is necessary by a list of seven problems which 'in my opinion, could not be dealt with at all without the principle of choice' (Zermelo 1908a: 113).[26] In particular he points out that the principle is indispensable for any reasonable theory of infinite cardinality, for only it guarantees the right results for infinite unions/sums, and in addition is vital for making sense of the very definition of infinite product. That Peano cannot establish the choice principle from his principles, says Zermelo, strongly suggests that his list of principles is not 'complete' (Zermelo 1908a: 112). (c) Another line of objection, represented in different ways by Bernstein (Bernstein 1905), Jourdain (Jourdain 1904, 1905b) and Schoenflies (Schoenflies 1905), was that Zermelo's general operation with sets in his proof was dangerous and flirts with paradox. (See also Hallett 1984, 176-182.) In its imprecise form, the objection is that Zermelo is less than explicit about the principles he uses in 1904, and that he employs procedures which are reminiscent of those used crucially in the generation of the Burali-Forti antinomy, e.g., in showing that if the set *L*g [?] *M*, then it can be extended. (What if *L*g is already the collection *W*?) Zermelo's reply is dismissive, but there is something to the criticism. Certainly Zermelo's 1904 proof attempts to show that WOT can be proved while by-passing the general abstract theory of well-ordering and its association with the Cantorian ordinals, and therefore also bypassing the 'the set *W*' (as it was widely known) of *all* Cantorian ordinals (denoted 'O' by Cantor), and consequently the Burali-Forti antinomy. However, whatever Zermelo's *intention*, there is no *explicit* attempt to exclude the possibility that *L*g = *W* and thus the suggestion that antinomy might threaten. Of course, Zermelo, referring to critics who 'base their objections upon the "Burali-Forti antinomy" ', declares that this antinomy '*is without significance* for my point of view, since the principles I employed *exclude* the existence of a set *W* [of all ordinals]' (Zermelo 1908a: 128, with earlier hints on 118-119) that the real problem is with the 'more elementary' Russell antinomy. It is also true that at the end of the 1904 paper, Zermelo states that the argument holds for those sets *M* 'for which the totality of subsets, and so on, is meaningful', which, in retrospect is clearly a hint at important restrictions on set formation. Even so, Zermelo's attitude is unfair. It could be that the remark about 'the totality of subsets etc.' is an indirect reference to difficulties with the comprehension principle, but even so the principle is not repudiated explicitly in the 1904 paper, neither does Zermelo put in its place another principle for the conversion of properties to sets, which is what the *Aussonderungsaxiom* of the 1908 axiomatisation does. Moreover, he does not say that the existence principles on which the proof is based are the *only* set existence principles, and he does not divorce the proof of the theorem from the Cantorian assumptions about well-ordering and ordinals. Indeed, Zermelo assumes that 'every set can be well-ordered' is equivalent to the Cantorian 'every cardinality is an aleph' (Zermelo 1904: 141). And despite his later claim (Zermelo 1908a: 119), he does *appear* to use the ordinals and the informal theory of well-ordering in his definition of g-sets, where a g-set is 'any well-ordered *M*g...', without any specification of how 'well-ordered set' is to be defined. What assurance is there that *this* can all be reduced to Zermelo's principles? One important point here is that it had not yet been shown that all the usual apparatus of set-theoretic mathematics (relations, ordering relations, functions, cardinal equivalence functions, order-isomorphisms, etc.) could be reduced to a few simple principles of set existence. All of this was to come in the wake of Zermelo's axiomatisation, and there is little doubt that this line of criticism greatly influenced the shape of the second proof given in 1908, of which a little more below. (d) The last line of objection was to a general feature of the 1904 proof, which was not changed in the second proof, namely the use of what became known as 'impredicative definition'. An impredicative definition is one which defines an object *a* by a property *A* which itself involves reference, either direct or indirect, to all the things with that property, and this must, of course, include *a* itself. There is a sense, then, in which the definition of *a* involves a circle. Both Russell and Poincare became greatly exercised about this form of definition, and saw the circle involved as being 'vicious', responsible for all the paradoxes. If one thinks of definitions as like construction principles, then indeed they are illegitimate. But if one thinks of them rather as ways of singling out things which are already taken to exist, then they are not illegitimate. In this respect, Zermelo endorses Hilbert's view of existence. To show that some particular thing 'exists' is to show that it is in B, i.e., to show by means of a finite proof from the axioms that it exists in B. What 'exists', then, is really a matter of what the axioms, taken as a whole, determine. If the separation, power set and choice principles are axioms, then for a given *M* in the domain, there will be choice functions/sets on the subsets of *M*, consequently well-orderings, and so forth; if these principles are not included as axioms, then such demonstrations of existence will not be forthcoming. From this point of view, defining within the language deployed is much more like what Zermelo calls 'determination', since definitions, although in a certain sense arbitrary, have to be supported by existence proofs, and of course in general it will turn out that a given extension can be picked out by several, distinct 'determinations'. In short, Zermelo's view is that definitions pick out (or determine) objects from among the others in the domain being axiomatised; they are not themselves responsible for showing their *existence*. In the end, the existence of a domain B has to be guaranteed by a consistency proof for the collection of axioms. Precisely this view about impredicative definitions was put forward in Ramsey (1926: 368-369) and then later in Godel's 1944 essay on Russell's mathematical logic as part of his analysis of the various things which could be meant by Russell's ambiguously stated Vicious Circle Principle. (See Godel 1944: 136, 127-128 of the reprinting in Godel 1990. See also Hadamard's letters in Hadamard et al. 1905.) To support his view, Zermelo points out that impredicative definitions are taken as standard in established mathematics, particularly in the way that the least upper bound is defined; witness the Cauchy proof of the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra. Once again, Zermelo's reply is coloured by the principle of looking at the actual practice of mathematics.[27] #### 2.2.4 Zermelo's second proof of the WOT, 1908 As mentioned, Zermelo published a second proof of the WOT, submitted to *Mathematische Annalen* just two weeks before the submission of his 'official' axiomatisation, and published in the same volume as that axiomatisation. This proof is too elaborate to be described here; a much fuller description can be found in Hallett (2010b: 94-103), but some brief remarks about it must be made nevertheless. Recall that the purpose of the proof was, in large part, to reply to (some of) the criticisms raised in objection to the 1904 proof, and not least to clarify the status of the choice principle. Suppose *M* is the set given, and suppose (using Zermelo's notation) that U*M* is the set of its subsets ('*Untermengen*'). The basic procedure in the 1904 proof was to single out certain subsets of *M* and to show that these can in effect be 'chained' together, starting from modest beginnings (and using the choice function g); thus we have {*m*1}, where *m*1 = g(*M*), {*m*1, *m*2}, where again *m*1 = g(*M*) and *m*2 = g(*M* [?] {*m*1}), and so on. In this way, the proof shows that one can 'build up' to the whole of *M* itself.[28] This 'build-up' is one of the things which provoked scepticism, and particularly the step which shows that *M* itself must be embraced by it. In the 1908 proof, the basic idea is to start from *M* itself, and consider 'cutting down' by the element 'chosen' by the choice principle, instead of building up. Thus, if one accepts that if *M* is a legitimate set, then so is U*M*, and there is not the same danger of extending into inconsistent sets, not even the appearance of danger. Again the key thing is to show that the sets defined are in fact 'chained' together and are in the right way exhaustive. In the 1904 proof, there are points where it looks as if Zermelo is appealing to arbitrary well-orderings, and thus indirectly arbitrary ordinals. This is avoided in the 1908 proof (as it could have been in the 1904 proof) by focusing on the particular 'chain' which the proof gives rise to. It is this chain itself which exhibits the well-ordering. In the modern understanding of set theory, to show that there is a well-ordering on *M* would be to show that there is a set of ordered pairs of members of *M* which is a relation satisfying the right properties of a well-ordering relation over *M*. It is well to remember that Zermelo's task in 1908 was constrained in that he had to establish the existence of a well-ordering using only the set-theoretical material *available to him*. This material did not involve the general notion of ordinal and cardinal numbers, not even the general notions of relation and function. What Zermelo used, therefore, was the *particular* relation *a* [?] *b* of being a subset, and it is important to observe that the chain produced is ordered by this relation. Why would one expect this latter to work? Well, the chain produced is naturally a subset well-ordering, for it is both linear and also such that the intersection of arbitrary elements of members of the chain is itself a member of the chain, and thus there is a natural subset-least element for each subset of members of the chain. But the wider explanation is hinted at towards the end of Zermelo's proof. Suppose a set *M* is (speaking informally) *de facto* well-ordered by an ordering relation [?]. Call the set R[?](*a*) = {*x* [?] *M* : *a* [?] *x*} the 'remainder [*Rest*]' determined by *a* and the ordering [?]. Consider now the set of 'remainders' given by this ordering, i.e., {R[?](*x*) : *x* [?] *M*}. This set is in fact well-ordered by reverse inclusion, where the successor remainder to R[?](*a*) is just the remainder determined by *a*'s successor *a*' under [?], and where intersections are taken at the limit elements (the intersection of a set of remainders is again a remainder). But not only is this set well-ordered by reverse inclusion, the ordering is *isomorphic* to the ordering [?] on *M*, that is: > > *a* [?] *b* if and only if > R[?](*b*) [?] > R[?](*a*). > Zermelo's 1908 construction is now meant to define a 'remainder set' directly without detour through some [?]; the resultant inclusion ordering is then 'mirrored' on *M*. The key thing is to show that the chain of subsets of *M* picked out really matches *M* itself. But if there were some element *a* [?] *M* which did not correspond to a remainder R[?](*a*), then it must be possible to use the choice function to 'squeeze' another remainder into the chain, which would contradict the assumption that all the sets with the appropriate definition are already in the chain.[29] We have spoken of functions and relations here. But in fact Zermelo avoids such talk. He defines *M* as being 'well-ordered' when each element in *M* 'corresponds' uniquely to such a 'remainder' (Zermelo 1908a: 111). This shows, says Zermelo, that the theory of well-ordering rests 'exclusively upon the elementary notions of set theory', and that 'the uninformed are only too prone to look for some mystical meaning behind Cantor's relation *a* [?] *b*' (Zermelo 1908a). One can be considerably more precise about the relation between orderings on *M* and 'remainder inclusion orderings' in U*M*. Much of this was worked out in Hessenberg (1906), and was therefore known to Zermelo (Zermelo and Hessenberg were in regular contact), and simplified greatly by Kuratowski in the 1920s. We will have reason to refer to Kuratowski briefly in the next section.[30] What about the choice principle? In 1904, this is framed in effect as a choice function, whose domain is the non-empty subsets on *M*. But in 1908, Zermelo frames it differently: > Axiom IV. A set *S* that can be decomposed into a > set of disjoint parts *A*, *B*, *C*, ..., each > containing at least one element, possesses at least one > subset *S*1 having exactly one element in common with > each of the parts *A*, *B*, *C*, ... > considered. (Zermelo 1908a: 110) > > > In other words, the choice principle is now cast in a *set* form, and not in the function form of 1904. In the 1908 axiomatisation, the axiom is stated in much the same way, but is called there (though not in the well-ordering paper) the 'Axiom of Choice'. However, the 1908 paper on WOT does say that the axiom provides a set (the *S*1) of 'simultaneous choices', to distinguish them from the 'successive choices' used in the pre-Zermelo versions of well-ordering. It is to be noted that in 1921, Zermelo wrote to Fraenkel in partial repudiation of the designation 'Axiom of Choice', saying that 'there is no sense in which my theory deals with a real "choice" '.[31] #### 2.2.5 The Axioms of the 1908 WOT Paper What axioms governing set-existence does Zermelo rely on in Zermelo (1908a)? At the start of the paper, Zermelo list two 'postulates' that he explicitly depends on, a version of the separation axiom, and the power set axiom. Later on he lists Axiom IV, which, as noted, asserts the existence of a choice set for any set of disjoint non-empty sets. In addition to this, Zermelo makes use of the existence of various elementary sets, though he doesn't say exactly which principles he relies on. In the axiomatisation which follows two weeks later, Zermelo adopts all these axioms, but adds clarification about the elementary sets. He also adds the Axiom of Infinity, to guarantee that there are infinite sets, and the Axiom of Extensionality, which codifies the assumption that sets are really determined by their members, and not by the accidental way in which these members are selected. In addition, as we have noted, he now calls the Axiom of Choice by this name. ## 3. The Major Problems with Zermelo's System Zermelo's system, although it forms the root of all modern axiomatisations of set theory, initially faced various difficulties. These were: 1. Problems with the Axiom of Choice. 2. Problem with the formulation of the Separation Axiom. 3. Problems of 'completeness', one of Hilbert's important desiderata on the adequacy of an axiom system. Specifically, there were problems representing ordinary mathematics purely set-theoretically, and also problems representing fully the transfinite extension of mathematics which Cantor had pioneered. The problems concerning the Axiom of Choice were discussed above; we now discuss the difficulties with the formulation of Separation and those of 'completeness'. ### 3.1 Separation The problem with the Axiom of Separation is not with the obviousness of the principle; it *seems* straightforward to accept that if one has a set of objects, one can separate off a subclass of this set by specifying a property, and treat this in turn as a set. The question here is a subtler one, namely that of how to formulate this principle as an axiom. What means of 'separating off' are to be accepted? What are allowable as the properties? As a matter of practice, we use a language to state the properties, and in informal mathematics, this is a mixture of natural language and special mathematical language. The Richard Paradox (see Richard 1905 and also the papers of Poincare 1905, 1906a,b) makes it clear that one has to be careful when defining properties, and that the unregulated use of 'ordinary language' can lead to unexpected difficulties. Zermelo's answer to this, in moving from the system of the second well-ordering paper to the axiomatisation, is to try specifying what properties are to be allowed. He calls the properties to be allowed 'definite properties' ('*Klassenaussagen*' or 'propositional functions'), and states: > > A question or assertion E is said to be > "*definite*" if the fundamental relations of the domain, by > means of the axioms and the universally valid laws of logic, determine > without arbitrariness whether it holds or not. Likewise a > "propositional function" E(*x*), in which the > variable term *x* ranges over all individuals of a > class K, is said to be "definite" if it is definite > for each single individual *x* of the class K. Thus the > question whether > *a* e *b* or not is always > definite, as is the question whether *M* > [?] *N* or not. > > > Zermelo asserts that this shows that paradoxes involving the notions of definability (e.g., Richard's) or denotation (Konig's) are avoided, implying that what is crucial is the restriction to the 'fundamental relations of the domain' (so, e, =). The basic problem is that it is not explained by Zermelo what the precise route is from the fundamental relations e and = to a given 'definite property'; it is this which gives rise to a general doubt that the Separation Axiom is not, in fact, a safe replacement for the comprehension principle (see Fraenkel 1927: 104). This plays into the hands of those, who, like Poincare, consider adoption of the Separation Axiom as insufficiently radical in the search for a solution to the paradoxes. Poincare writes: > > Mr. Zermelo does not allow himself to consider the set of all the > objects which satisfy a certain condition because it seems to him that > this set is never closed; that it will always be possible to introduce > new objects. On the other hand, he has no scruple in speaking of the > set of objects which are part of a certain *Menge* *M* and which > also satisfy a certain condition. It seems to him that one cannot > possess a *Menge* without possessing at the same time all its > elements. Among these elements, he will choose those which satisfy a > given condition, and will be able to make this choice very calmly, > without fear of being disturbed by the introduction of new and > unforeseen elements, since he already has all these elements in his > hands. By positing beforehand this *Menge* *M*, he has erected an > enclosing wall which keeps out the intruders who could come from > without. But he does not query whether there could be intruders from > within whom he enclosed inside his wall. (Poincare 1909: 477; > p. 59 of the English translation) > > > Here, Poincare is referring indirectly to his view that the paradoxes are due to impredicative set formation, and this of course will be still be possible even with the adoption of the Axiom of Separation. The problem of the lack of clarity in Zermelo's account was addressed by Weyl in 1910 (Weyl 1910; see especially p. 113) and then again by Skolem in 1922 (Skolem 1923, p. 139 of the reprint). What Weyl and Skolem both proposed, in effect, is that the question of what 'definite properties' are can be solved by taking these to be the properties expressed by 1-place predicate formulas in what we now call first-order logic. In effect, we thus have a recursive definition which makes the definite properties completely transparent by giving each time the precise route from e, = to the definite property in question. This does not deal with all aspects of Poincare's worry, but it does make it quite clear what definite properties are, and it does also accord with Zermelo's view that the relations =, e are at root the only ones used.[32] Fraenkel (1922 and later) took a different approach with a rather complicated direct axiomatisation of the notion of definite property, using recursive generation from the basic properties giving a notion which appears to be a subset of the recursively defined first-order properties. Zermelo accepted none of these approaches, for two reasons. First, he thought that the recursive definitions involved make direct use of the notion of finite number (a fact pointed out by Weyl 1910), which it ought to be the business of set theory to explain, not to presuppose. Secondly, he became aware that using essentially a first-order notion condemns the axiomatic system to countable models, the fundamental fact pointed out in Skolem (1923). His own approach was, first, to give a different kind of axiomatisation (see Zermelo 1929), and then to use (in Zermelo 1930) an essentially second-order notion in characterising the axiom of separation.[33] ### 3.2 Completeness There were also problems with the completeness of Zermelo's theory, since there were important theoretical matters with which Zermelo does not deal, either for want of appropriate definitions showing how certain constructions can be represented in a pure theory of sets, or because the axioms set out in Zermelo's system are not strong enough. #### 3.2.1 Representing Ordinary Mathematics Zermelo gives no obvious way of representing much of 'ordinary mathematics', yet it is clear from his opening remarks that he regards the task of the theory of sets to stand as *the* fundamental theory which should 'investigate mathematically the fundamental notions "number", "order", and "function" '. (See SS1.) The first obvious question concerns the representation of the ordinary number systems. The natural numbers are represented by Zermelo as by [?], {[?]}, {{[?]}}, ..., and the Axiom of Infinity gives us a set of these. Moreover, it seems that, since both the set of natural numbers and the power set axiom are available, there are enough sets to represent the rationals and the reals, functions on reals etc. What are missing, though, are the details: how exactly does one represent the right equivalence classes, sequences etc.? And assuming that one *could* define the real numbers, how does one characterise the field operations on them? In addition, as mentioned previously, Zermelo has no natural way of representing either the general notions of relation or of function. This means that his presentation of set theory has no natural way of representing those parts of mathematics (like real analysis) in which the general notion of function plays a fundamental part. A further difficulty is that the lack of the notion of function makes the general theory of the comparison of sets by size (or indeed by order) cumbersome. Zermelo does develop a way of expressing, for disjoint sets *a*, *b*, that *a* is of the same size as *b*, by first defining a 'product' of two disjoint sets, and then isolating a set of unordered pairs (a certain subset of this product) which 'maps' one of the sets one-to-one onto the other. But this is insufficiently general, and does not in any case indicate any way to introduce 'the' size of *a*. Russell's method (defining the cardinality of *M* as the set *card*(*M*) = {*N* : *N* [?] *M*} (where '[?]' means 'cardinally equivalent to') is clearly inappropriate, since with a set *a* = {*b*}, *card*(*a*) (which should be the cardinal number 1) is as big as the universe, and the union set of 1 would indeed be the universal 'set'. Over and above this, there is the more specific problem of defining the aleph numbers. The second major difficulty is along the same lines, concerning, not functions, but relations, and thus ordering relations and ordinal numbers. As we have seen (in SS2.2.4), Zermelo has the beginnings of an answer to this in his second proof of the WOT, for this uses a theory of subset-orderings to represent the underlying ordering of a set. It turns out that the method given in this particular case suggests the right way to capture the general notion. #### 3.2.2 Ordinality Zermelo's idea (1908a) was pursued by Kuratowski in the 1920s, thereby generalising and systematising work, not just of Zermelo, but of Hessenberg and Hausdorff too, giving a simple set of necessary and sufficient conditions for a subset ordering to represent a linear ordering. He also argues forcefully that it is in fact *undesirable* for set theory to go beyond this and present a general theory of ordinal *numbers*: > > In reasoning with transfinite numbers one implicitly uses an > axiom asserting their *existence*; but it is desirable both from the > logical and mathematical point of view to pare down the system of > axioms employed in demonstrations. Besides, this reduction will free > such reasoning from a foreign element, which increases its > aesthetic value. (Kuratowski 1922: 77) > > > The assumption here is clearly that the (transfinite) numbers will have to be added to set theory as new primitives. Kuratowski however undertakes to *prove* that the transfinite numbers can be dispensed with for a significant class of applications.[34] Application of the ordinal numbers in analysis, topology, etc. often focuses on some process of definition by transfinite recursion over these numbers. Kuratowski succeeds in showing that in a significant class of cases of this kind, the ordinals can be avoided by using purely set-theoretic methods which are reproducible in Zermelo's system. As he notes: > > From the viewpoint of Zermelo's axiomatic theory of sets, one can > say that the method explained here allows us to deduce theorems of a > certain well-determined general type *directly* from Zermelo's axioms, > that is to say, without the introduction of any independent, > supplementary axiom about the existence of transfinite > numbers. (Kuratowski 1922: > 77)[35] > > > It is in this reductionist context that Kuratowski develops his very general theory of maximal inclusion orderings, which shows, in effect, that all orderings on *a* can really be represented as inclusion orderings on appropriate subsets of the power set of *a*, thus reducing ordering to Zermelo's primitive relation e. One immediate, and quite remarkable, result of this work is that it shows how one can *define* the general notions of relation and function in purely set-theoretic terms. It had long been recognised that relations/functions can be conceived as sets of ordered pairs, and Kuratowski's work now shows how to define the ordered pair primitively. The ordered pair (*a*, *b*) can be considered informally as the unordered pair *M* = {*a*, *b*}, together with an ordering relation *a* < *b*. Suppose this relation is treated now via the theory of inclusion chains. The only maximal inclusion chains in the power set of *M* are {[?], {*a*}, {*a*, *b*}} and {[?], {*b*}, {*a*, *b*}}. Using Kuratowski's definition of the ordering '<' derived from a maximal inclusion chain, these chains must then correspond to the orderings *a* < *b* and *b* < *a* on {*a*, *b*} respectively. If [?] is ignored, the resulting chain {{*a*}, {*a*, *b*}} is thus associated with the relation *a* < *b*, and so with the ordered set (pair) (*a*, *b*). It is then quite natural to *define* (*a*, *b*) as {{*a*}, {*a*, *b*}} (see Kuratowski 1921: 170-171). One can now define the product *a* x *b* of *a* and *b* as the set of all ordered pairs whose first member is in *a* and whose second member is in *b*; relations on *a* can now be treated as subsets of *a* x *a*, and functions from *a* to *b* as certain subsets of *a* x *b*. Thus, many of the representational problems faced by Zermelo's theory are solved at a stroke by Kuratowski's work, building as it does on Zermelo's own. #### 3.2.3 Cardinality But there was a problem concerning cardinality which is independent of the problem of definitional reduction. It was pointed out by both Fraenkel and Skolem in the early 1920s that Zermelo's theory cannot provide an adequate account of cardinality. The axiom of infinity and the power set axiom together allow the creation of sets of cardinality [?] *n* for each natural number *n*, but this (in the absence of a result showing that 20 > *n* for every natural number *n*) is not enough to guarantee a set whose power is [?] o, and a set of power o is a natural next step (in the Cantorian theory) after those of power *n*. Fraenkel proposed a remedy to this (as did Skolem independently) by proposing what was called the *Ersetzungsaxiom*, the Axiom of Replacement (see Fraenkel 1922: 231 and Skolem 1923: 225-226). This says, roughly, that the 'functional image' of a set must itself be a set, thus if *a* is a set, then {*F*(*x*) : *x* [?] *a*} must also be a set, where '*F*' represents a functional correspondence. Such an axiom is certainly sufficient; assume that *a*0 is the set of natural numbers {0, 1, 2, ...}, and now assume that to each number *n* is associated an *a**n* with power *n*. Then according to the replacement axiom, *a* = {*a*0, *a*1, *a*2, ...} must be a set, too. This set is countable, of course, but (assuming that the *a**n* are all disjoint) the union set of *a* must have cardinality at least o. The main difficulty with the Replacement Axiom is that of how to formulate the notion of a functional correspondence. This was not solved satisfactorily by Fraenkel, but the Weyl/Skolem solution works here, too: a functional correspondence is (in effect) just any first-order 2-place predicate ph(*x*, *y*) which satisfies the condition of uniqueness, i.e., [?]*x*, *y*, *z*{[ph(*x*, *y*) [?] ph(*x*, *z*)] - *y* = *z*}. With this solution, the Replacement Axiom will be (as required) stronger than Zermelo's original Separation Axiom and indeed can replace it; however, in Fraenkel's system, one can prove his version of the Replacement Axiom from his version of the Separation Axiom, which shows that his separate definition of function is not sufficiently strong. (For details, see Hallett 1984: 282-286.) Zermelo initially had doubts about the Replacement Axiom (see the letter to Fraenkel from 1922 published in Ebbinghaus 2007: 137), but he eventually accepted it, and a form of it was included in his new axiomatisation published in 1930 (Zermelo 1930). Skolem's formulation is the one usually adopted, though it should be noted that von Neumann's own formulation is rather different and indeed stronger.[36] #### 3.2.4 Ordinals Although Kuratowski's work solved many of the representational problems for Zermelo's theory, and the Replacement Axiom shows how the most obvious cardinality gap can be closed, there still remained the issue (Kuratowski's view to one side) of representing accurately the full extent of the theory which Cantor had developed, with the transfinite numbers as fully fledged objects which 'mirror' the size/ordering of sets. Once the ordinal number-classes are present, the representation of the alephs is not a severe problem, which means that the representation of transfinite numbers amounts to assuring the existence of sufficiently many transfinite *ordinal* numbers. Indeed, as was stated above, the hypothesis that the scale of aleph numbers is sufficient amounts to the claim that any set can be 'counted' by some ordinal. There are then two interrelated problems for the 'pure' theory of sets: one is to show how to define ordinals as sets in such a way that the natural numbers generalise; the other problem is to make sure that there are enough ordinals to 'count' all the sets. The problem was fully solved by von Neumann in his work on axiomatic set theory from the early 1920s. Cantor's fundamental theorems about ordinal numbers, showing that the ordinals are the *representatives* of well-ordered sets, are the theorem that every well-ordered set is order-isomorphic to an initial segment of the ordinals, and that every ordinal is itself the order-type of the set of ordinals which precede it. These results prove crucial in the von Neumann treatment. Von Neumann's basic idea was explained by him as follows: > > What we really wish to do is to take as the basis of our > considerations the proposition: 'Every ordinal is the type of > the set of all ordinals that precede it'. But in order to avoid > the vague notion 'type', we express it in the form: > 'Every ordinal is the set of the ordinals that precede > it'. (von Neumann 1923, p. 347 of the English translation) > > > According to von Neumann's idea, 1 is just {0}, 2 is just {0, 1}, 3 is just {0, 1, 2} and so on. On this conception, the first transfinite ordinal o is just {0, 1, 2, 3, ..., *n*, ...}, and generally it's clear that the immediate successor of any ordinal a is just a [?] {a}. If we identify 0 with [?], as Zermelo did, then we have available a reduction of the general notion of ordinal to pure set theory, where the canonical well-ordering on the von Neumann ordinals is just the subset relation, i.e., a < b just in case a [?] b, which von Neumann later shows is itself equivalent to saying a [?] b. (See von Neumann 1928, p. 328 of the reprinting.) So again, inclusion orderings are fundamental. Von Neumann gives a general definition of his ordinals, namely that a set a is an ordinal number if and only if it is a set ordered by inclusion, the inclusion ordering is a well-ordering, and each element x in a equals the set of elements in the initial segment of the ordering determined by x. This connects directly with Kuratowski's work in the following way. Suppose *M* is a well-ordered set which is then mirrored by an inclusion chain **M** in the power set of *M*. Then the first few elements of the inclusion chain will be the sets [?], {*a*}, {*a*, *b*}, {*a*, *b*, *c*}, ..., where *a*, *b*, *c*, ... are the first, second, third ...elements in the well-ordering of *M*. The von Neumann ordinal corresponding to *M* will also be an inclusion ordering whose first elements will be > [?], {[?]}, {[?], {[?]}}, {[?], {[?]}, > {[?], {[?]}}}, ... (in other words, 0, 1, 2, 3...), and we have 0 [?] 1 [?] 2 [?] 3 [?]... in mirror image of [?] [?] {*a*} [?] {*a*, *b*} [?] {*a*, *b*, *c*} [?] ... These von Neumann ordinals had, in effect, been developed before von Neumann's work. The fullest published theory, and closest to the modern account, is to be found in Mirimanoff's work published in 1917 and 1921 (see Mirimanoff 1917a,b, 1921), though he doesn't take the final step of identifying the sets he characterises with the ordinals (for an account of Mirimanoff's work, see Hallett 1984: 273-275). It is also clear that Russell, Grelling and Hessenberg were close to von Neumann's general set-theoretic definition of ordinals. But crucially Zermelo himself developed the von Neumann conception of ordinals in the years 1913-1916, (for a full account, see Hallett 1984: 277-280 and Ebbinghaus 2007: 133-134). Zermelo's idea was evidently well-known to the Gottingen mathematicians, and there is an account of it in Hilbert's lectures '*Probleme der mathematischen Logik*' from 1920, pp. 12-15.[37] Despite all these anticipations, it is still right to ascribe the theory to von Neumann. For it was von Neumann who revealed the extent to which a full theory of the ordinals depends on the Axiom of Replacement. As he wrote later: > > A treatment of ordinal number closely related to mine was known > to Zermelo in 1916, as I learned subsequently from a personal > communication. Nevertheless, the fundamental theorem, according to > which to each well-ordered set there is a similar ordinal, could not > be rigorously proved because the replacement axiom was unknown. (von > Neumann 1928: 374, n. 2) > > > The theorem von Neumann states is the central result of Cantor's mentioned here in the second paragraph of this section. As von Neumann goes on to point out here (also p. 374), it is the possibility of definition by transfinite induction which is key, and a rigorous treatment of this requires being able to prove at each stage in a transfinite inductive process that the collection of functional correlates to a set is itself a set which can thus act as a new argument at the next stage. It is just this which the replacement axiom guarantees. Once justified, definition by transfinite induction can be used as the basis for completely general definitions of the arithmetic operations on ordinal numbers, for the definition of the aleph numbers, and so on. It also allows a fairly direct transformation of Zermelo's first (1904) proof of the WOT into a proof that every set can be represented by (is equipollent with) an ordinal number, which shows that in the Zermelo system with the Axiom of Replacement added there *are* enough ordinal numbers.[38] It is thus remarkable that von Neumann's work, designed to show how the transfinite ordinals can be incorporated directly into a pure theory of sets, builds on and coalesces with both Kuratowski's work, designed to show the *dispensability* of the theory of transfinite ordinals, and also the axiomatic extension of Zermelo's theory suggested by Fraenkel and Skolem. ## 4. Further reading For a summary of the Cantorian theory as it stood in the early years of the twentieth century, see Young and Young (1906), and the magisterial Hausdorff (1914); for further reading on the development of set theory, see the books Ferreiros 1999, Hallett 1984, Hawkins 1970, and Moore 1982. See also the various papers on the history of set theory by Akihiro Kanamori (especially Kanamori 1996, 1997, 2003, 2004, 2012) and the joint paper with Dreben (Dreben and Kanamori 1997). For the place of set theory in the development of modern logic, see Mancosu et al., 2009, especially pages 345-352. For an account of the various axiom systems and the role of the different axioms, see Fraenkel et al. (1973). For a detailed summary of the role of the Axiom of Choice, and insight into the question of its status as a logical principle, see Bell (2009). This entry will be supplemented by a further entry on axiomatizations of set theory after Zermelo from 1920 to 1940.
zhuangzi
## 1. Zhuangzi's Life and Times Zhuangzi flourished through the latter half of the 4th century BC roughly contemporary with Mencius, and the movement known as the School of Names (Ming Jia *ming-jia* name school). Zhuangzi shows familiarity with Classical Chinese theories of pragmatic-semantics and makes his own theoretical contributions to it. The traditionally recognized figures in this school included Gongsun Long and Hui Shi--Zhuangzi's close friend and most frequent direct philosophical discussant. With the recovery of the Later Mohist dialectical work detailing their theory of language, we find compelling evidence that the linguistic turn in Classical thinking was a widespread feature of this mature phase of the Classical period. The later Confucian thinker, Xunzi, follows Zhuangzi in reacting to and incorporating this linguistic turn in his thinking. Most of what we infer about Zhuangzi's life, we draw from evidence within the *Zhuangzi*, although the Han biographers did speculate about his place of origin (the state of Meng) his personal name (Zhou), and the official posts he held (minor in Qiyuan in his home state) and period he lived (during Prince Wei reign over Chu--which ended about 327 BC). Scholars have found it hard to confirm any details of his life from outside this text and from his being discussed by later thinkers. The text itself contains scattered stories about Zhuangzi, but given its frequent use of fantasy, even these we must season with the salt of textual skepticism. We attribute a large chunk of the extant text of the *Zhuangzi* to "students of Zhuangzi" but we have little hint of who his students were or if he even had students in any formal sense. ## 2. Evolving Text Theory A scholar working around 600 years later after the fall of the Han, Guo Xiang (d. 312), edited and reduced what he saw as a haphazardly accumulated cluster of apocryphal and possibly authentic texts. He concluded that many were added after the time Zhuangzi lived. Guo reports compressing that prior collection of writings from fifty-two chapters to thirty-three. This is the extant text on which our knowledge is based. Guo divided the chapters he had chosen into three sections: the "Inner Chapters" (1-7), the "Outer Chapters" (8-22) and the "Miscellaneous Chapters" (23-33). He attributed only the first section to the period dating from Zhuangzi's lifetime--hence possibly originating from Zhuangzi himself. The second grouping may have included writings of a "School of Zhuangzi." Modern scholarship assigns various sources of other influences found in both the second "outer" and final "miscellaneous" chapters. Graham drawing on work of the Chinese theorist, Kuan Feng and followed with some variation by Liu Xiaogan and Harold Roth, divides these influences into roughly four variously named groups: * Zhuangzi's students or the School of Zhuangzi credited with those later writings committed most closely to the views expressed in the "inner chapters." * Authors with egoist views associated with Yang Zhu (4th century BC). The *Mencius* presented Yang's thought as a version of an ethical egoism that rejected conventional altruistic social *dao*s. * The third group Graham dubbed the 'primitivists'. Primitivists share Yang Zhu's antipathy to social, historical or conventional *dao*s--typically those supporting social norms extending beyond agricultural village life--in favor of more natural ways. This group shares attitudes with the text of the *Laozi* (*Daode Jing*) mixed with Yangist themes. * The final group, dominated the "miscellaneous" sections, Graham called them syncretists (eclectics) who seemingly attempted comprehensiveness by combining all points of view into a single complete *dao*. However widely assumed, Zhuangzi's authorship of any of the "inner" chapters remains a speculative hypothesis. Guo's original assessment that Zhuangzi did not author any of the remaining sections remains conventional scholarly wisdom, but religious Daoists treat the entire book as a Canon--The *Nanhua Zhen-Jing*. Combining all these elements into a single volume reflects a familiar Classical pattern of embellishing the teachings of a master, adapting the additions to the namesake's writing style and expanding on his themes and insights in distinctive ways. The four schools contributing to the extant text shared an emphasis on natural -usually as opposed to social-cultural, *dao*s. Yangism or egoism largely rejected social or moral *dao*s on the apparent assumption that natural guiding *dao*s essentially recommend self-preserving behavior. Its paradigm is the anti-social hermit. Motivation by self-interest was normatively prior to any conventional *dao*. They preserved their natural purity from social corruption by rejecting society's mores. Primitivism similarly rejected social and conventionally moral daos (mores), but has its own conception of a natural, pre-social, typically intuitive, way of life that supports rustic, agricultural, village life. It supports populist and anarchist political tendencies. Syncretism does not reject social *dao*s per se, but does reject any particular *dao* as biased and narrow in contrast to a more, "rounded," idealized, or comprehensive *dao*. This is often expressed in an ideal observer form (the sage, perfect human, or Tian *tian*nature:sky's *dao*). These views tend toward epistemic supernaturalism--claims to superlative cognitive or religious access to some transcendently correct *dao*. Both tend to deny that their correct *daos* can be expressed and transmitted in language or words. The discussions in the "Inner Chapters," particularly in the 2nd chapter, by contrast, treat language as also natural and social-conventional *dao*s as themselves natural *dao*s. It undermines the otherwise presupposed contrast of natural vs. conventional *dao*s. Humans are naturally social animals and execute natural causal processes when their walking, speaking, writing, and other practices leave marks in nature, (like a trail or a text) which become physically accessible to later *walkers* as history (stored in memory, legend, writings, or footprints etc.). The pivotal 2nd chapter draws relativist and skeptical conclusions from its normative naturalism. It rejects the religious traditionalism of Confucianism and the Gaia-hypothesis implicit in the Mohist attempt at utilitarian naturalism. Nature provides us with many ways to go, but does not favor or *command* our making any choices among them. *Shi-fei* Shi Fei (This way not that) judgments are made by living creatures in nature, not by Tian *tian*nature:sky itself. We can find guiding structures, *dao*s, in nature but not a favored or dictated *dao* of nature. Like the later syncretist chapters, the "Inner Chapter" Zhuangists accept that social *dao*s are continuous with natural ones, but they do not endorse any imagined or alleged, comprehensive judgments from everywhere, from all natural points of view. The cosmic judgement from nowhere is a non-judgment. Zhuangists are not committed to Laozi's conception of an exclusive choice of natural (Tian *tian*sky:nature) over social (Ren *ren*human) daos. They are skeptical of any claim of special access to contextless guiding knowledge by alleged or self-styled sages, "ideal observers" or perfect exemplars of epistemic virtues. They accept language but also accept our natural capacity and inclination to toy with it, alter it, and mould it to our use in various situations of practical choice. Zhuangzi's exemplars are butchers, musicians, cicada catchers, wheelmakers--exemplars of mundane and focused action guidance. Each is an exemplar of one of the many ways of life (*dao*s) who execute their particular specialties in a highly cultivated, precise, smooth, and seemingly easily executed way. The imagined eclectic synthesis of all the various ways of life into some total-comprehensive *dao* is no more than de-facto restatement of their co-existence in a single natural world as optional ways of life. The cosmos makes no judgment that they should exist--though it combines them into a cosmic *dao* that is the history of everything. That the cosmos has this outcome does not mean it makes a human-like choice which humans could or should execute. We are ill advised to strive for skill in *everything*. The eclectics were probably the last community working with the text, adding to it and carrying it into later periods. The Laozi had become enmeshed with a ruler cult worship of The Yellow Emperor. Laozi became the far more influential figure during the entire Confucian orthodoxy of the Han (206-220 BC). ## 3. Competing Interpretive Narratives The wide range of views of Zhuangzi stem from the style of the text and the ways it has figured in China's intellectual history as well as the ways it was caught up in the modern interaction between China and the modern, scientific West. Zhuangzi's style is the philosophical parable, typically a brief discussion or exchange between two points of view. There is slight plurality of humans among the discussants joined by natural and imaginary creatures. Its fictional characters are usually cleverly named, some are Confucian icons (Confucius or his alleged teacher, Lao Dan). Some discussants are animals (real and fictional fish, birds, snakes), a talking skull, the wind, musicians, debaters, tigers, trainers, butchers, butterflies, burglars and the myriad "pipes of nature." Expressive brevity and subtlety of detail enhances the impact of the often complex and elusive point of the parables--they seldom explicitly formulate the moral or point explicitly. Most commonly, the author(s) end discussions in a doubting tone, a double rhetorical question or some pithy enigmatic parting shot. They may make their point by having the two parties walking away shaking their heads, agreeing only to disagree; both appreciating that they barely understand one another, and yet feeling that something has been learned from the exchange. Translation into Western languages invites biases that are hard to avoid. The main effect is loss of the conceptual cohesion of the original, but the parables still engage our Western philosophical curiosity. We get the exhilaration of immersion in an independent philosophical tradition of comparable antiquity and richness. Readers in and out of China invariably suspect that the *Zhuangzi*'s appealing style is infused with philosophical genius, even as they disagree about its philosophical upshot. Indeed, much of the *Zhuangzi*'s philosophical appeal may stem from its seemingly deliberate open-ended texture, the interpretive malleability of its dialogues which invites, even perhaps requires, us to join the author(s) in their philosophical reflection. This appeal stems only partly from the quality and sophistication of his episodes; each illuminated a patch of philosophical territory ending with a question for further pondering--rather like Nietzsche or the Later Wittgenstein. Each exchange presents or illustrates shards of insight with open-textured conclusions--all laced with Zhuangzi's obvious joy in exploring paradox--particularly linguistic ones of the sort that appeal to analytic Western thinkers. Each is an expression of some natural, but perhaps inaccessible, alternative way of life. The frequent enigmatic conclusions "the answer is X" leaves interpreters arguing centuries later, Fermat-like, how X can be an answer--or what X is (e.g., "free and easy wandering," "walking two paths," "goblet words," "clarity," and so forth). Each seems easily to fit into a range of puzzles familiar to thinkers in both traditions. One suspects that we find the correct interpretation by finding our way, like Wittgenstein's fly, out of some philosophical bottle. The correct philosophy coincides with the correct interpretation of Zhuangzi. The traditional religious Zhuangzi narratives placed him as the disciple of Laozi, whom they regard as a quasi-divine founder of a mystical religion worshipping a mysterious entity translators tended to render as a definite descriptive term, but capitalized it as if it were a singular name, "The Dao." Compatible philosophical treatments were versions of metaphysical monism, epistemic intuitionism (often explicitly anti-rationalist), political anarchism and a vague normative absolutism--follow The Dao. The bulk of popular and religious treatments still follow this interpretive line, treating Laozi as the earliest layer of "Daoist mystical thought" or "Lao-Zhuang" thought and situating Zhuangzi as his "follower." The story of the religious view of Zhuangzi starts a century after Zhuangzi lived (4th century BC). Philosophical schools were closed, books burned and thought repressed during the superstitious Qin dynasty (221-206 BC) which followed the classical period. This initiated China's philosophical "Dark Age." The more orthodox Confucian Han Dynasty (206 BC to 220) followed. Over two decades (109-91 BC) the Han emperor's hereditary Grand Historians, Sima Tan and Sima Qian (a father and son team), wrote an official history from the mythical Yellow Emperor (c. 3rd Millennium BC) to the Han. It is in this account that the classification of thinkers into three concept schools, Daoist, Legalist, and School of Names first occurs. Graham speculates that the assumption of an affiliation of Zhuangzi to Laozi may have originated from the Outer Chapters. There Zhuangzi's students used the mythical teacher of Confucius, Lao Dan or Laozi, to ridicule Confucius in a cycle of dialogues. A cult of Huang-Lao, worshipping the Yellow emperor and Laozi as divinities, had grown up in the Qin. The father and son historians were students of Huang-Lao masters. At the fall of the Han the narrative of Zhuangzi as a follower/elaborator of a semi-divine Laozi was well entrenched. The post-Han resurgence, known as Neo-Daoism, began with the editing of the received edition of, first, the *Laozi* (Wang Bi 226-249) then the *Zhuangzi* (Guo Xiang d. 312 see above). Neo-Daoist discussion practices and ideas were influential in bringing Buddhist and Chinese thought into interaction and Daoism became enmeshed with Buddhism in the popular view (especially with Chinese Chan Buddhism). A Daoist "religion", borrowing models of religious institutions from Buddhism (monasteries, monks and nuns) influenced discourse about Daoism throughout the period of Buddhist domination of the Chinese intellectual world (achieved gradually during the Six Dynasties period 220-589 and extending through the Tang 618-907). Neo-Confucians from the medieval period on treated Buddhism and Daoism as essentially similar religions. Modern text theory concerning the *Zhuangzi* grows from two recent discoveries. 1. The reconstruction of the Later Mohist dialectical works and 2. Archeological reconstructions of the text of the *Daode Jing*. The following section discusses their twin impact on our view of Zhuangzi. Developments at the end of the 19th and early 20th century in China led Chinese intellectuals to adopt the European concept of philosophy (Zhe Xue ) with its implicit distinction from religion. This distinction was seen as pivoting on logic--the theory of proof or argument. They started to segregate their own writings which seemed most like argument, inference and logic from those sustained mainly by credulity and tradition. They began to sort out the philosophical aspects of their traditional thought from its more religious and superstitious elements. Sun Yirang's (1848-1908) 1897 reconstruction of the Mohist Canon provided convincing evidence that analytically inspired and rigorous thinking had grown up in Classical China. This example encouraged 19th century intellectuals like Yan Fu (1854-1921) and Liang Qichao (1873-1929). They started to emphasize the ancient schools that more clearly related to the logical paradigms of Western philosophy and Mohist analytics. Hu Shih (1891-1962) continued this tradition of reconceiving and re-centering Chinese thought away from the Confucian scholasticism that had dominated since the decline of Buddhism. The early 20th century logic-inspired reformation recently began to influence the interpretation of the *Zhuangzi* and the *Xunzi* in the west, largely inspired by Angus Graham who had observed that both ancient texts demonstrated a mastery of the technical vocabulary of Mohist linguistic theory. Modern philosophical appreciation of the *Zhuangzi*, probably stems from Graham's 1969 "[Zhuangzi]'s Essay on Seeing Things as Equal" (Graham 1969, predating his work on Mohism). Wryly replying to Wang Fuzhi's speculation that Shen Dao, not Zhuangzi had authored the beloved chapter, Graham averred that whoever wrote that philosophically rich text is the person we would want to think of as Zhuangzi. Graham proposed looking at the text's seemingly conflicting thoughts as analogous to the "inner dialogue" of a reflective thinker who formulates a view, considers then rejects it. Graham also noted the writer's deep involvement and apparent fluency in the technical language and obscure issues arising in Classical Chinese theories of language which he then only beginning to study. Graham's outlook conflicted overtly with a traditional Chinese narrative of a disciple Zhuangzi following a semi-divine Laozi in worship of The Mystical Dao. Zhuangzi, Graham quipped, didn't know he was a Daoist. Graham later argued that the internal evidence suggested Zhuangzi had never seen the text of the Laozi (The *Dao De Jing*) and probably thought of Lao Dan as a Confucian. Most interpretive disputes are, to a greater or lesser degree, a result of the tension between Graham's textual arguments and the traditional Historian's picture of Zhuangzi as a religious mystical Daoist follower of the semi-divine Laozi, similarly worshipping "The Dao." Graham's textual arguments were indirectly supported by archeological discoveries of different Laozi texts. The discoveries in the early 1970s and 1990s together implied a relatively late date for the emergence of the Laozi text--probably some years after Zhuangzi had lived and perhaps overlapping the composition of a series of dialogues between Laozi and Confucius in the "Outer Chapters" section. Graham speculated that Zhuangzi's students, who were writing the cycle of Laozi-Confucius dialogues, may have rhetorically chosen to use the legendary Lao Dan (mythical teacher of Confucius) to give him authority to lecture and ridicule the revered master. When we abandon the traditional identification of Zhuangzi as a Laozi follower, it opens the door for speculation about his relation to the relativist, linguistic theorist, Hui Shi, traditionally treated as belonging to the School of Names. Christoph Harbesmeier speculated he may have been either Zhuangzi's teacher, mentor or fellow student. If he was a teacher, he came to accept his student as an equal or even superior. Zhuangzi portrays him as playing a role in Zhuangzi's philosophical skill development as an intimate philosophical interlocutor and eventually as a foil for sharpening his analysis. Among those texts that concentrate on Ming *ming*names, Hui Shi's ten theses mark him as a relativist response to Mohist realism on the relation of names and "stuff"--focusing especially on comparative and indexical terms. We can read Zhuangzi's relativism, accordingly as an alternative, arguably more reflectively subtle, indexical relativism about Shi Fei **shi-fei**this-not that judgments regarding choices of paths (*dao*s) of correct use of names/words/concepts as guideposts to our Xing *xing*walking:behavior. This can both explain Zhuangzi's relativist direction of analysis and his recognition of sound Mohist/realist responses to Hui Shi's version of that relativist direction of thought. This article develops and expands on Graham's philosophical interpretation and emphasizes this relation to Hui Shi rather than to Laozi. Between the traditional, piously mystical Daoist religious interpretation and that view's nearest philosophical neighbors, lies the bulk of the interpretive historical and religious literature. Given the philosophically oriented venue of this article, what follows should not be treated as ecumenical. ## 4. A Modern Philosophical Interpretation ### 4.1 The Background Dispute about Social Normative Daos Confucian *dao*s were broadly humanist. The earliest version (Confucius 551-479 BC) traced normativity to earlier human invention. Metaphorical trails are left by past human walkings, i.e. social practices. Language was an example of such an invented social practice which intertwined with routine activities (rituals) to yield the *correct*, sage-king inspired way of life--the social Dao *dao*path. A later version (Mencius 372-239 BC) focused on natural human psychology. The correct path is that to which our natural moral psychology inclines us. Humans have a Xin *xin*heart-mind that is naturally *shan*good-at normative choice and practice. Mencius may have been reacting to Mohism. Mozi (470-391 BC) had earlier initiated a shift in focus to more natural and objective, less culturally relative way of grounding normative judgment. His claim that Tian *tian*nature:sky exhibited a tendency to a course leading to human utility or well-being. So humans should use that natural norm, the Bian *bian*distinction between Li Hai *li-hai* benefit-harm in constructing our social *dao*, including the norms of language. Correctly using terms is using them to mark the path of cooperative behaviors that lead to general human benefit--a social Dao *dao*path utilitarianism, rather than a law or rule version. Nature *intends* us to follow its natural structures in ways that lead to universal human Li *li*benefit. Ethical questions thus have a single correct answer in an ideally engineered and shared normative linguistic practice. Mohist utilitarian metaethics pointed to natural realism. Daoist primitivism (symbolized by the mythical Laozi and the anonymous text known as the *Daode Jing*) was, as noted above, a further trend toward a broader ethical naturalism with anti-language absolutist implications. We should forget or ignore all social norms and practices, including linguistic ones. Utility (perhaps egoistic utility) does motivate our behavior as naturally as water follows the paths created by natural contours of earth. Language should not interfere in any way with this natural guiding interaction between us and the course(es) of nature. ### 4.2 The Conceptual Foci of Chinese Daoist Normative Theorizing Understanding the *Zhuangzi* is made more difficult by the huge differences not only in the philosophical context, but in the pervasive metaphors that structure and focus discussions of norms of behavior in the Chinese vs Indo-European classical traditions. His positions invite comparisons with modern metaethical naturalism but he does not focus them with concepts linked to grammatical sentences such as "laws" or "rules" (sentences in *all* form) or "facts" (sentence-sized chunks of reality) or "properties (realities corresponding to sentence predicates)." Zhuangzi used the traditional Dao *dao*path metaphor together with the technical terminology developed in Mohism of *shi-fei*this-not that, *bian*distinction and *ke*permissible. The metaphor shaping most Chinese discussions of pragmatic knowing, choice and behavior was *dao*--a path or trail. Questions we would phrase in terms of moral propositions, laws, or principles are questions about finding, choosing and following *dao*s, paths or ways. *Dao*s can be social or natural structures that guide us in answering practical questions: what to do or how to do it. As the focus of warring Chinese conceptions of guidance, *dao* guidance has three phases. We must find or notice them, choose one from among those we notice, and then follow or interpret the selected *dao* in Xing *xing*walking:behavior. We Bian *bian*distinguish, discover and recognize them; choose or approve (*shi*this:right) them or reject (*fei*not-that:wrong ) them, and treat them as *ke*permissible or not. Our capacity to engage in these three processes governing natural guiding structures, *dao*s, is an internal *dao*--our De *de*virtuosity. Our De *de*virtuosity at interacting with the web of *dao*s reads and interprets the path-marks thus generating our Xing *xing*walking:behavior. The *dao* metaphor corresponds closely with the Western translation metaphor of 'a way' which, while ubiquitous in philosophical discourse, is rarely a central focus of philosophical analysis of normativity. The salient differences between the two traditions accounts of behavior are that the Chinese does not focus on sentential items (actions, events, beliefs) particularly as conclusions of belief plus desire mental arguments. Instead, it focuses on the interplay of natural processes grounded in the temporally shifting distributions of Qi *qi*physical stuff that yields path-like guidance structures for living things. Confucians and Mohists had their own theories of the both the right *dao*s and the right De *de*virtuosity to use together in guiding behavior. Confucian *dao*s tended to be those enshrined in past practice and their version of De *de*virtuosity tended toward the intuitive, typically appealing to Ren *ren*humanity. Mohists advocated guiding reform of conventional social *dao*s using a natural normative Bian *bian*distinction of Li Hai *li-hai*benefit-harm. For Mohists, Li Hai *li-hai*benefit-harm was a Tian *tian*natural way of finding, choosing, reforming and interpreting social *dao*s. In contrast to Confucians, Mohists sought to elaborate their natural ways of selecting *dao*-like social practices as operational, objective, measurement-like processes accessible to ordinary people and not subject to training and indoctrination. Chinese linguistic analysis folded naturally into similar language--it concerns ways of using words--*dao*s (norms) of linguistic behavior focused on word use. The more philosophically inclined schools began to see such norms of the use of words as underlying the explicit disagreements among schools about which norms or *dao*s to follow and how to follow them. The discussion of norms of use are typically couched in behavioral formulations such as Qu *qu*choose, Ju *ju* pick-out Ke *ke*assertible:admissible Bian *bian*distinction Zhi *zhi*point and *he*combine. The core psychological attitude is Wei *wei*deem:do which may be expressed as a tendency (in speech, both inner and expressed) to express a Shi Fei *shi-fei*this-not that judgment regarding the use of a word. A phonetically and semantically related tendency is Wei *wei*calling it by the term. Behaviorally, it amounts to dealing with it under that word-concept. Conversely we can *shi* or *fei* the use of a name of some contextual object--*wei*call it or *wei*deem it properly associated with that Ming *ming*name. To Wei *wei*deem:do can be either to express the category assignment in one's behavior--either speech-behavior or behaving toward the object as people would be expected to, given that they assigned the object to that category. The behavior for the category would be found in the social or natural *dao*path they follow. A Wei *wei*deem:do state is less a mental picture of a fact (a belief) than a disposition to treat or identify some object as deserving the term in question. Instead of the western reality vs. appearance dialectic, Chinese discussion revolves around the contrast of natural (Tian *tian*nature:sky) *dao*s and human (Ren *ren*human) or socially constructed, *dao*s. The human *dao*s are constructed with the help of Ming *ming*names strung together into Yan *yan*language. Mozi, as we noted above, appealed to what he regarded as a natural utility standard to judge the acceptability of *yan*language use and Confucius relied more on past usage ranging back to the mythical sage kings. Problems of justifying approvals and disapprovals of word usage led such later Confucians as Mencius, to rely more on cultivating an intuition. Since the account of cultivation typically presupposed practice in conformity with the social practice requiring justification, the threat of circularity pushed traditionalists eventually to teach about and appeal to an allegedly innate or pre-social human psychology. By contrast, the craft-inspired Mohists went on to emphasize the use of measurement tools and operations as the standards guiding term use. They argued that such operational standards would be more accessible to ordinary people who could rely only on their "eyes and ears." The Confucians, by contrast, were forced to flip between appealing to some cultivated authority and attributing an innate moral inclination to the existing conventional language *dao* to such ordinary people. Shi Fei *Shi-fei*this-not that judgments can concern choice of a *dao* or the interpretive performances of a chosen *dao*. Chinese writers similarly focused on Ke *ke*assertible:permissible which may be said of a *dao*, or of a permissible walking of some *dao*--including those of language use. Disagreement could be at the level of *dao*s, or at the interpretive level--endorsing or rejecting a Wei *wei*deem:do. The endorsing-rejecting Shi Fei *shi-fei*this-not that and Ke *ke*permissible behaviors themselves involve either choosing or interpreting *dao*s. Each time we make any of these judgments we contribute to further constructing our socially shared *dao* with its implied practices of Ming *ming*names use. ### 4.3 Zhuangzi's Distinctive Approach Zhuangzi conforms to the general pre-Han model, using a path metaphor to discuss normativity in general. This fuels the traditional view of him as a Daoist. Most of his discussion, moreover, further conforms to the practice of focusing on social *dao*s--undermining treatment as religious disciple of Laozi's insistence we follow only Tian *tian*natural *dao*s. What links him to a naturalist theme is his reluctance to draw the usual contrast between natural and social *dao*s. (Is it nature? Is it man?). Human social *dao*s **are** natural behaviors of natural animals. This grounds Zhuangzi's pattern of talking about and with other equally natural creatures. Humans are as natural as monkeys, birds, and fish. "How can *dao*s be hidden such that there are authentic and artificial?" he asks rhetorically? (Harvard Yenching *Zhuangzi Yinde* hereafter HY 4/2/24-5) All the different social traditions expand the number and kinds of naturally existing *dao*s. Other animals' walking patterns also construct natural *dao*s which, similarly, become available for human finding, choosing and walking. Zhuangzi's discussion, particularly in the philosophically most sophisticated second chapter, is mainly about the plurality and relativity of second-level *dao*s, our naturally endowed, internal *dao*sways of finding, choosing and following one of many natural ways of life in the maze or network presented by nature. This stance makes the complexity of the natural network only the first level of variety and possibility. Recursion of *dao*s explodes the complexity. A tripartite recursion follows because there are many *dao*s of finding, of choosing, and of translating the first level plethora. The many layered complexity of *dao*s of *dao*s yields the human sphere of life. "Fish interact in water; humans interact in *dao*s" (*Ibid*., HY 18/6/72) He naturalizes *dao*s less by attending to natural physical guiding structures (e.g. *dao*s of water) than to the variety of human *dao*s presented by analogy to the variety of creatures with different *dao*s. Alternately, he encourages us not to assume we have found all the available ways to behave or he reflects on the variety of sources of *dao*s of choice or of different capacities to catch on and follow within us--our different natural organs and the range of different ways we may train or habituate them. This complexity of *dao* structures fuels, in turn, both his skepticism of absolutes, of authority, of ideal observers, of social dogmas and his qualified advice to leave the finding, choice and interpretation to a working out from the variety of perspectives that make up the behaving units in the particular circumstance. *Dao* choices are best made from the perspective of walkers.(*Ibid*., HY 4/2/33) The other distinctive feature of Zhuangzi's approach lies in the sophistication of his handling the issues of language in explicating this natural complexity of *dao*s. Graham interpreted a famous Zhuangzi trope (the pipes of Tian *tian*nature:sky) as Zhuangzi's way of positioning language as *tian* (natural) sound. > The pipes of earth, these are the hollows everywhere; > the pipes of men, these are rows of tubes. Tell me about the pipes > of Heaven.' Who is it that blows the ten thousand disputing > voices, who when of themselves they stop their talk has sealed them, > and puffs out of them the opinions that they choose for > themselves?' HY 3/2/4-9 Graham elaborates: > > These are apparently the holes in the heart through which thought > courses and the mouths which utter it, so that the breath blown by > heaven through the inner formations of different men issues in > contradictory utterances. (Graham 1969:149) Zhuangzi's Daoism, thus, starts by removing *tian*constant nature from its role as ultimate normative authority--the role it played in virtually all the rival accounts of which *dao* we should follow. All *dao*s that are practically available at the point of choice for walking (actually existing *dao*s) are similarly *tian*. *Tian* (nature) generates *dao*s as it generates the Wu *wu*thing-kinds (humans and other animals) that find and follow them. Neither it nor the cosmos can play the role of an authority, far less of an anthropomorphic authority commanding or dictating our choice among the network of naturally existing *dao*s. *Dao*s are chosen from those found in nature, but none represents nature's choice for us--none of the *dao*s in nature is **the** *dao* **of** nature. Dialectically, Zhuangzi's replacement for *tian*'s role as source of normative guidance would be the entire complex network of *dao* structures that permeate the natural world. He situates us at indexed points in this network seeking paths forward from *here and now*, choosing from among the plethora of those accessible which, if any, to follow. The philosophical advantage of Zhuangzi's way of discussing *dao*s, thus, does not leave him suggesting that what is natural is moral (analogous to implying "ought" from "is"). Nature gives us a complex network of iterative guiding structures among which we are about to *swim*. In our waking hours, we continue constructing systems of contending, resolving and agreeing on Shi Fei *shi-fei*this-not that judgments--the rejected ones buried in rubble of ongoing construction of normative language marking behavioral paths. (HY 3/2/11-13) We recognize greater and lesser models of both--the more reflective and engaging vs. a lazier, more wordy type. As we *walk* through a day, we encounter attitudinal states--joy, sorrow, surprise, ennui etc. We don't know what role these play but they seem central to our choosing activity--indeed to our having a perspective, an 'I'. (HY 3/2/11-14) When we describe that entire structure, e.g. as resembling a natural network of links (*dao*s) between temporally and spatially indexed points we can see how it might generate talk of a single cosmic dao. All guidance is at a point in the network and available to and for some emergent object--physical, living, animal or human. The inner processes of seeking, choosing, and following *dao*s from node to node are themselves part of the natural network. We are not sure what the normative point of our natural reactions in walking through the nature's maze. Each step or utterance adds a Shi Fei *shi-fei*this-not that to the edifice of guiding discourse marking paths for ourselves and for others. It's as if there is some natural authority guiding the construction process, though we can't see marks of its authority. We can reliably walk paths or *dao*s but can't see the shape of the authority. We light on paths and react with heart-mind responses. That's it. (*Ibid*., HY 4/2/14-16) Human *dao*s of finding, choosing and following are capacities normally attributed to the Xin *xin*heart-mind. Zhuangzi recognizes its involvement in the construction process, but is skeptical of making it a kind of natural authority. It is, after all, only one of the natural organs involved--our daily reactions include being directed by our stomachs, our eyes, etc. Why, Zhuangzi wonders, should we think they need a single authority? (HY 4/2/14-16) Even, then, if we take the Xin *xin*heart-mind as an authority, it's not clear how it can help us deal with the role of judgments of greater and lesser wisdom and different ways of using Shi Fei *shi-fei*this-not that. Aren't all the hearts involved in the evolving construction equally natural--the sages and the fools? (HY 4/2/21-22) Any output from our Xin *xin*heart-mind into this construction of a *dao* to follow from here is itself a product of our having walked one of a range of possible *dao*s to this point. (HY 4/2/20) > "To get a Shi Fei > *shi-fei*this-not > that from the > Xin *xin*heart-mind without > it's having been constructed there is like going to > *Yue* today and arriving yesterday, like getting something > from nothing." Even the wisest of mythical sages (Yao) > can't know how to do that! (*Ibid*., HY > 4/2/22-23) There are many natural ways of finding and choosing ways. Humans naturally exhibit variety in how they find or choose a course of behavior. This recursive complex of *dao*s of choosing is part of nature. No single one need be considered *the* *dao* *of* nature to the exclusion of others. They may be capacities of individuals or of social groups, embodied in their social practices. The gestalt set of past commitments and acquired inclinations to choose and interpret paths is another component of our situation or location in a complex web of *dao*s. The given *dao*s of choice are what Zhuangzi treats as Cheng *cheng*constructed/mature within our body as we traverse the nodes of the network of *dao*s. Our heart-minds reach an indexed point with a given momentum vector--a speed on an existing trajectory--this is our a point of view or perspective, complete with prior commitments to *dao*sways of appreciating and selecting among available paths. These second-level *dao*s can also be chosen and walked correctly or incorrectly. Choosing an epistemic *dao*, in turn, depends on other a practically available *dao*s for guiding that meta-choice... and so on. Zhuangzi does not view it as a rational or logical construction, but a complicated, multi-layered natural one. He speaks of "eight De *de*virtuosities" involved in constructing *dao*s and guiding expressions, starting with the indexical locatives, left and right, then human relations, then mores, divisions (categories?), distinctions (disputes), competition and then strife. (HY 5/2/55-6) A similar recursion concerns *dao*s of finding and interpreting *dao*s. This network of recursive natural guidance structures constitutes the complex network of natural *dao*. We rely on meta-*dao*s, practically available links in this network, in choosing and in interpreting practically available ground-level *dao*s. Humans navigate in a sea of *dao*s. Then who or what does the choosing? Zhuangzi's theory here is similarly detached and natural. He focuses less on the consciousness or subjectivity of some mental substance or cognitive self or agent, but on a grammatical locus of judgment, a Wo *wo*I:me within the linguistic *dao* structure--the grammatical indexical marks a choosing point in the conceptual and space-time structure. Like Hume's self, without the naturally occurring grab-bag of attitudes, it would not be there to play its choosing role. The Wo *wo*I:me is situated in a frame of reference with its own complicated Cheng *cheng*commitment trajectory in the iterative *dao*s of choice. The *wo*I:me that knows-how is situated in existing commitments embedded in an indexed here-now in the network of ways it will assign to *shi-fei*this-not that. Each *shi-fei*this-not that it "shoots out" further commits it to a path. (The narrator had introduced the above "pipes of heaven" metaphor to describe a gestalt he describes as having "said farewell to my *wo*I:me.") > "Its eruptions are like a repeating > crossbow" expresses how it manages > Shi Fei > *shi-fei*this-not that > judgments. "Its resting on them like an oath or treaty" > expresses how it clings to past winners, "its death is like > autumn and winter" expresses how it daily declines, a > weakening brought about by this (the weight of accumulated > commitments?) and it cannot start the process over. "Its > rejections are like tightening bonds" puts into language these > aging channels. As the *xin*heart-mind nears > death, nothing can restore its dynamism. (HY 3/2/11-13) > > > > Joy, anger, sadness, pleasure, worrying, sighing, resisting, clinging, > being drawn to, eschewing, launching, and committing, like music from > empty holes, dampness generating mushrooms, these day and night > replace each other before us and yet none can know from what they > emerge. Let it be! Let it be! They come from where they > emerge--without these, there would be no Wo > *wo*I:me and without a > *wo*I:me there would be no choosing. (HY > 3/2/13-14) > > For Zhuangzi, the issue is not mind or consciousness, but the behavioral inclinations and the normative authority of these roving indexical perspectives scattered within the natural *dao* network. Their choices of which *dao*s to walk furthers the construction ( Cheng *cheng*fixing) of our perspective for the next choice. > It seems as if there is a natural authority, but we > cannot find its authoritative source. There is sufficient reliability > that this is walkable, but we don't see it's > [authorizing?] shape--it has natural reality but no visible > shape. (HY4/2/15-16) The first level paths have a shape, but the *dao*s of correct choice and performance are inside the performer and not plainly visible. The trend from social construction humanism toward naturalism had been gradual. Mozi's argument for basing such constructions on a natural distinction of benefit and harm was an early step. Graham had separately theorized that Mencius developed both his response to Mozi and his account of the role of Ren *ren*humanity as arguments that Confucian ritual behavior had evolved from *tian*natural intuitive response patterns in the Xin *xin*heart-mind. This implicitly endorsed Mozi's reliance on a *tian*natural ground for the social construction of morality. ### 4.4 Doubting Intuitionism Graham's Zhuangzi then addressed this Mencian response in a passage that extends the Hume-like skepticism about any identifiable "inner self". That should be what guides the naturally occurring emotive reactions that are necessary for a *wo*I:me that chooses. It seems, he says, there must be one, but we find no evidence of it. We approve of behaviors and place our trust in its reactions but find no sign of what is authorizing or making them. > Hundreds of parts, nine > openings and six viscera included and completed > (Cheng *cheng*fixed) > in place in us, with which should I feel most akin? Should I be > pleased with them all? Is there a *wo*I:me > among them? Among them, should we deem some as rulers and as > servants? Are the rulers and servants incapable of governing each > other? Are they not capable of taking turns as ruler and servants? Is > there a genuine ruler among them? It's as if trying and > failing to grasp its real character has no bearing on whether it is > genuine. (*Ibid*., HY 4/2/16-18) Mozi had worried that it would be circular to appeal to intuitions about the word use in a social *dao* to authorize that very practice, for example Confucian ritual. Being a product of ritual training. acquired intuitions could not be a sufficiently neutral way of justifying our choosing *ritual* as our social guide. Nor could one trained practitioner have authority over another in resolving interpretive disputes about how to execute the ritual, e.g., about how to apply the terms found in ritual texts to concrete real-time behaviors. He insisted we need a neutral, non-cultural or natural basis for such meta-choices of social practices of choosing and interpreting practices. The narrative history of Classical thought found near the end of the *Zhuangzi* (*Ibid*., HY 90/33/1) takes off from this dispute between Confucians and Mohists. It welcomes Mozi's implicit search for neutrality, universality, and greater objectivity. However, the school viewed the familiar debate between a utilitarian and traditional morality as interminable because Mozi's *dao*guide, like Confucius's, starts from different standards, different Cheng *cheng*constructed commitments to linguistic practices. Each relies on their past practice of judging how to use the key moral Ming *ming*names. Confucians would reject Mozi's standards because they led to what Confucians view as the wrong conclusions (e.g., *implied* Confucians should abandon Yi *yi* moral rituals such as burial). The Mohists reject burial rituals because they use Yi *yi* morality of the social mores reformed according to their standard of general utility. The pivotal statement of Zhuangzi's position is expressed as a riff on the relativity or dependence of Shi Fei *shi-fei*this-not that judgments about language use on natural circumstances, naturally existing past practice, commitments and attitudinal gestalt shifts. > Where can > Dao *dao*guides hide such that there are > genuine and artificial? Where can > Yan *yan*language hide such that > there is Shi Fei *shi-fei*this-not > that. Where can *dao*s hide such that they do not > exist? How can a Yan *yan*language exist > and not be Ke *ke*assertible? > *Dao*s hide behind small achievements and language hides > behind rhetorical flourishes and elaboration. So you have the > "this is right-that is wrong" of the Confucians and > Mohists. Of what one says "this is right" the other says > "that is wrong" and of what they say "that is > wrong" says "this is right." If you want to > "wrong" what the other "rights" and > "right" what the other 'wrong's, nothing > matches Ming *ming*discerning. (*Ibid*., > HY4/2/24-7) Though balanced in judging this impasse, the *Zhuangzi*'s interesting target is the Mohist aspiration to objectivity. Many stories in the text target the notion that *utility* is a naturally constant value--particularly the *human* utility that Mozi champions. Among this series of parables, the most famous, the useless tree, illustrates the relativity of usefulness to Hui Shi. (*Ibid*., HY 3/1/46-7) Not only are we implicitly appealing to a *dao* in choosing to adopt a benefit/harm standard, we are also going to appeal to interpretive *dao* to judge whether we have followed it correctly or not. Mozi had treated moral disputes as disagreements about how to Bian *bian*distinguish in applying terms like Yi *yi*morality and Shan *shan*good-at. He had also objected to Confucian reliance on acquired intuition since it made access to such judgments esoteric. He argued that standards governing such evaluative word use should be made by Fa *fa*measurement standards that are accessible to the "eyes and ears" of ordinary people. His utility standard, Zhuangzi is suggesting, is still relative to the *way* of translating it to behavior. Others in the ethical debate, notably Yang Zhu and related Primitivists, also appealed to *tian* (natural constancy) as a normative arbiter. The growing awareness that norms of behavior are intertwined with norms of language use, produced another feature of this strand of thought bringing the natural world into our guidance. Primitivists came to advocate silence--letting the natural paths of the world take over completely. For most of history, the *Laozi* has exemplified this rejection of language. It treated all social Dao *dao*spaths as implicit rejections of the natural Dao *dao*path. Graham has argued that echoes of this line of thinking lay in the background of Mencius's thought. That concern led him to attempt to substitute natural moral psychology (a natural moral disposition in human Xin *xin*heart-mind) for positive social mores. A paradigm of this anti-language, silence trend (cited in the *Zhuangzi*'s internal history just before discussing the *Laozi* group ) was Shen Dao. Shen Dao postulated a "Great *Dao*" (essentially the actual course of cosmic history from past to future) which "even a clod of earth" will follow. We all will follow Great *Dao*. We can (and should) therefore abandon knowledge of how to make linguistic distinctions (Shi Fei *shi-fei*this-not that judgments) to follow Great *Dao*. Shen Dao, based on his version of logical determinism (i.e., There being an actual complete history of space-time entails your behavior tomorrow is included) draws an anti-normative, quietist and stoic conclusion. Later Mohist writings contain several acute critiques of such a trending pro-silence posture. Deeming all Yan *yan*language as not-Ke *ke*assertible is not Ke *ke*assertible. The explanation, later Mohists noted, lies in the asserter's own use of Yan *yan*language. Rejecting (*fei*-ing) all *shi-fei* judgments is *fei* (wrong, to be rejected). Similarly self-defeating is "teaching not to teach." Zhuangzi's "pipes of nature" metaphor signals his departure from these defective *Laozi*-like or Primitivist anti-language positions. Language is natural and arguments for silence are self-condemning. So the point of Zhuangzi's own reflections on the absence of natural normative endorsement of our *shi-fei*this-not that decisions should not guide us to stop making them. Making them is what *we* naturally do when we find *our* *dao*s *in* nature. It is natural for us to make a judgment, but not nature making it. Normativity arises from within nature, but nature only makes all its normative, behavior-guiding paths for us naturally *available*. ### 4.5 Relativism: It depends on ... The *Zhuangzi* emphasizes the plurality of natural stances or points of view from which one may see paths of possible behavior as "natural." For one of the paths to be available for *me* will be dependent on where I am and my *given*trajectory in the network. All the appeals to *tiannature* as an authority are right in insisting their *dao*s are natural, but mistaken in using that as a reason to deny a similar status to the *dao*s of rival normative thinkers. *Tian* cannot serve as an arbiter of which rival norm is correct since it equally "puffs" all of them out. This allows each to claim their choices are of *tian*natural *dao*s but does not allow them the corollary that their rival's choices violate *tian*. They, like us, conform with *tian*'s constancies in being committed to their *dao*s. Any *shi-fei*this:right judgment concerning a *dao* may be either a Yin *yin*dependent *shi,* based on prior or enacted commitments, gestalts orientations, and inner processes or it may be an arbitrary posited (Wei *wei*do:deem) *shi*. Dependency arises from past (*cheng*fixed) commitments to the *dao* structures through which we worked our way to our *here-now*. We always encounter such choices as we are already engaged in walking along some *dao*. Those past *dao* commitments bring us to a normative stance from which successive judgments of *shi-fei* and Ke *ke*permissible vs. not *ke* arise. Zhuangzi's pivotal illustration pairs Shi shithis with Bi *bi*that as near and far indexicals. His use of another indexical here signals his view that Shi *shi*this:right used normatively as opposite to Fei *fei*not-that:wrong is relative to a commitment index. Local justifications for having *shi-fei*this-not that or *ke*assertible are delivered in accordance our *cheng*fixed commitment momentum along the *dao*s that guided us to this point. This relativity of normative dependence underpins Zhuangzi's mildly ironic, skepticism of special or extraordinary normative statuses we give to, e.g., sages. The skepticism must apply even to the quietist posture that *shi-fei*this-not that judgments are "bad" or unnatural. We should doubt any transcendent or allegedly perfect, totalistic epistemic access to nature's inexpressible normative know-how. There are no naturally ideal observers. > > Will the eventual result be there is both Shi > *shi*this:right and Bi > bithat? Will the eventual result be there is > neither shi nor bi? We can call the situation of neither > *shi* nor *fei* finding its opposite the > "pivot of Dao *dao*guides." > The pivot sets the start of the center of a sphere from which there > are inexhaustible responses--inexhaustible *shi* > and inexhaustible *fei*. Hence the saying > "nothing matches Ming > *ming*discernment." (*Ibid*., HY > 4/2/30-31) This cautious skepticism undergirds Zhuangzi's departure from the primitivists'. He neither thinks we should conclude that we must not issue *shi-fei* judgments nor that we must reject or deny our natural, situational inclinations to *shi-fei*. We should, however, adopt an attitude of epistemic modesty in making our perspective based choices and recommending our interpretations to others. That modesty arises from *ming*discerning that their perspectives, like ours, arise from within a immensely complex and complicated natural *dao* structure. Epistemic modesty also undergirds Zhuangzi's openness and willingness to interact with others. If nature has a point of view, it is that one in which all *actual dao*s of *shi-fei*-ing in nature are available as natural guiding structures. Hence nature makes no choice that implies a more absolute, or superior normative status on either perspective. Nature makes them possible candidate guiding *dao*s for us to choose and walk. A question implicitly and repeatedly left to the reader is what Zhuangzi means by Ming *ming*discerning. Does it amount to taking the view *of* nature but of *nowhere* in particular or is it a naturally occurring, perspective on perspectives, a recognition of the plurality of natural perspectives? He usually recommends to our attention insights gained from realizing that our choice is one among a wide range of naturally available *dao*s. He provokes us to realize that we may make progress and improve our guiding perspective by simulating the guiding perspectives of others. Some tales, by contrast, warn us not to expect the *dao*s of others to mesh with our capacities and character--as with the boy from Shouling who goes to learn the Handan way of walking, which "cripples" his original ability. Still a third outcome of the interaction, as with violent gangsters, reminds us simply to keep our distance. However, in the standard cases, we learn from simulating others' perspectives, choices and interpretations of the natural *dao*-structures either from projecting or communicating--sharing methods and techniques we did not grasp before (new ways to use gourds or hand-salve or find ways to accommodate and interact while "walking two ways"). New accumulated insights about natural structures may improve our range of options, from our own point of view. Learning can also help us see how to walk in the natural paths together without getting in the other's *way*. In understanding other's trajectories along their *dao*s, we *may* judge them as correct or incorrect. First, we do this from our own present perspective. We neither judge all to be right nor all to be wrong--nor even that all are equal. Certainly, not all are equally worthy of *our* choice. We need not judge that all are good choices for those following them--only that the grounds of their choice may be different from ours. They might still be dogmatic, careless, or unwarranted even given the situational grounds of their choice. Nothing about the *naturalness* of such choices arising makes them right. All this is compatible with recognizing others as natural creatures guided by natural inner processes along natural guiding *dao*s. We neither seek to follow all at once or each equally--as Hui Shi seems to suggest. Nor do we resolve to follow none--as Shen Dao suggests. We do judge that we might gain from being aware of and engaging in open exchanges--as in Zhuangzi's dialogues. We are more inclined to follow a path, and given our similarities, think we might pursue it with benefit when we know some natural being like us found and followed it. And Zhuangzi clearly does ridicule the social moralists (Confucians and Mohists) as well as Hui Shi for the narrowness of their range of choices--their failure to appreciate the richness and complexity of alternative ways of life. Our tendency to appreciate and share others' values, to mirror their behavior cooperatively, together with our awareness of the wide variety of perspectives, many of which we judge to be worthless, mistaken, or dangerous, makes it hard to treat any projected transcendental, comprehensive viewpoint as the single answer. Zhuangzi's "pivot of *dao*s," his "view from nowhere," is not a final *shi-fei* judgment. It is the point prior to any *shi-fei* and from which all diverge. Each commitment propels us down a different path at a *cheng*fixed momentum. We rely on *cheng*fixed commitments to prior *shi-fei* in all *shi-**fei* judgment. All *shi-**fei* are indexed within the network. The judgment from no-where-when is no-judgment. We learn from openness and exchange because we acquire commitments from simulating others' path following behavior. That we progress in such exchanges is something we ourselves judge, not the cosmos. No judgment comes from some point outside of or everywhere in the network of *dao*s. We are naturally influenced by others' evaluations, their judgments of our choices and their behavioral virtuosity--especially when the others are our parents, perceived superiors and respected models. These, again, are the Yin *yin*dependencies on which present judgments depend. This gives Zhuangzi's indexical relativism a different contour from Hui Shi's. The latter structures his analysis mainly on comparatives. This leads him to a version of normative 'error theory' -the conclusion that we should abandon normative semantic distinctions as all wrong. Since the Bian *bian*distinctions on which they are based are relative, they are unreal. Ergo, there are no real distinctions and the world is actually one. Any distinction making judgment, any *shi-fei*this-not that, unnaturally divides what is naturally one. Hui Shih's Tenth Thesis is: > Flood concern on all the 10,000 thing-kinds; The cosmos is > one Ti *ti*unit. (HY > 93/33/74) Graham, relying on his hypothesis that Zhuangzi frequently considers positions which he later rejects, had already targeted the stereotype view of Zhuangzi as agreeing with Hui Shi's monism. Graham's translation reveals the reductio that puts monism in a "considered and rejected" category. It amounts to the self-rebutting anti-language stance targeted by the Later Mohists--the error Zhuangzi's naturalism of all perspectives (the "pipes of heaven") was intended to avoid. > "[H]eaven and earth were born together with me > and the myriad things and I are one." > > > > Now that we are one, can I still say anything? Now that I have called > us one, did I succeed in not saying something? One and the saying make > two, two and one make three. Proceeding from here even an expert > calculator cannot get to the end of it, much less a plain > man. (HY5/2/52-54) > > ### 4.6 Zhuangzi on Language Zhuangzi's relativism expresses choice, commitment, and interpretive performance on analogy to natural processes involved in following a path. Commitment is setting off along a path. We have momentum and a trajectory. The shape of the path combines with these and *commits* us to walk on or continue in a way that depends on the discernible shape of the path. Walking a path involves staying *mostly* within its physical boundaries. This account allows us to capture the flavor of Zhuangzi's discussion which does not employ the familiar Western sentence-based metaphors of laws, rules, principles with norms of *obedience*, *belief* or propositional desire. Using the Western idiom, along with the associated practical syllogism of belief-desire explanation would give Zhuangzi the basis for a distinction between a cause and a reason--a distinction he seems not to draw in his talk of Yin *yin*dependence. There is a kind of inference from *dao*s of choice, interpretation etc. of a path and an internal feedback *dao* (our De *de* virtuosity at) "reading" external paths to guide behavior. Zhuangzi would not make that point in terms of deduction from a normative premise or principle. The internal and external paths themselves have a causal and normative relation to our walking behavior. A more sentential focus would similarly mean describing the outcome as an action rather than an extended *course of* walking/following behavior. A sentence would state the action or the intent--rather like the conclusion of a practical syllogism rather than, as as fits in this metaphorical space, as performing a role in a play or or part in a symphony. Zhuangzi's use of the path metaphor did extend to the understanding of language but, again, not with a focus on sententials. Rather than constructing *dao*s in sentential form, Zhuangzi construes language in *dao* form. The focus of ancient Chinese theory was on names on the analogy of path markers: "go past the tree, turn right and then down to the water." Names take on importance as sign-posts along physical structures. Confucian social versions emphasized the names of social roles and statuses more than of natural kinds. Primitivist opposition to social *dao*s led them into the sweeping anti-naming postures that Later Mohists showed to be self-condemning. Graham's interpretation of Zhuangzi's pipes of nature gave him a way to evade this anti-language abyss. Human language is a natural sound. Hui Shi's using relativist premises about names to derive an absolutist monism which threatened to collapse to the primitivist anti-distinction, anti-naming quietism. Making everything one is equivalent to denying Bian *bian*distinctions thereby denying any real basis for the *shi-fei*this way-not that statuses implicit in all Ming *ming*names and yanwords:language. Zhuangzi's naturalism is anti-dogmatic, it neither denies nor asserts any particular set of distinctions as authentic. Distinctions arise from indexed here-now points in the actual network of *dao* perspectives--by travelers on a trajectory along one of the *dao*s choosing Shi Fei *shi-fei* this-not that from among multiple possible courses of behavior afforded by the cosmos. The cosmos does not select which way to make the choice. Zhuangzi's analogy of language and wind, however, had its own problems. Graham had noted that Zhuangzi returns to the metaphor nearer the middle of the dialogue, noting that here Zhuangzi seems to be taking back some of its implications. Having disposed of Mencius's appeal to intuition and Hui Shi's attempt to make everything normatively equal, he here addresses a more challenging position. The Later Mohists advocated a version of pragmatic-semantic realism. The Later Mohists had also argued that when a Bian *bian*distinction was formulated as a *shi-fei*, e.g., one of the disputants calls it "ox" and the other "not-ox", one of them must Sheng *sheng*win i.e., Dang *dang*hit on it. The Later Mohists' version of common-sense realism incorporated social conventions. Conventions set out what Wu *wu*natural-kind each term "selects out" or *bian*distinguishes from the rest. We then extend that distinction to pick out new objects based on their objective similarity or difference (those accessible to "eyes and ears" of ordinary people). This is the basis of a social standard of correct word use enshrined in past practice. Hui Shi, however, had undermined that simple version of realism with his observation that between any two Wu *wu*natural-kinds we can find *some* similarity and *some* difference. The world, in effect, gives us many ways of establishing conventional distinctions and assigning names. The Later Mohists had failed to find an adequate account of what similarities would and would not lead to what they called Kuang Ju *kuangju*wild picking out . Zhuangzi's analogy of language to the noises made by wind had seemed to echo Hui Shi's normlessness about language. In this later passage, however, he revisits the wind analogy, and retreats, accepting the Mohist insight that language is more than a "natural sound." > > > Language is not blowing; those who use > language, have language. (Graham translates: "Saying is > not blowing breath, saying says something.) That which it languages is > decidedly not yet fixed. Is the eventual result that they have (there > is) language? Or there has never been language? Deeming it as > different from bird calls: does that mark a distinction? Or is > there no distinction?" (HY4/2/23-4) (This passage is followed by > the passage cited in the "Intuition" sub-section > above) > > This frustrating vagueness and signature indecision in the text leaves interpreters to philosophize about what Zhuangzi's implicit answer (Ming mingdiscern:clear) might be. However, the analogy with bird calls is a fortuitous suggestion. We arrange, adapt and modulate the elements of our language to fit our environment, abilities, and opportunities (e.g., mating). Would Zhuangzi have guessed the same about birds? The claim following that concurs that the "aboutness" of a language exists but aboutness is not fixed. This can be explicated with the above discussion of the indexicals Shi *shi*this:right and Bi *bi*that. Zhuangzi carries the diectic character over to his treatment of the ubiquitous *shi-fei*this-not that that undergird the norms guiding how to use names (words). We endorse and recommend (*shi* this:right) our guiding terms, language and linked behavior. We may base that on our correctly following prior commitments to *dao*s of word use--relying on a Confucian traditional standard, the past and existing practices of our linguistic community. In one passage, Zhuangzi allows this appeal to past or existing common practice but does not endorse it as right--merely as useful. Conventions are useful because they facilitate communication. He he adds a tone of "that is all" hinting we need not regard them as plausible candidates for being absolutely right--a single transcendent standard of use. > Only those who "break through" know how to > communicate with it as a "one." Because of this, we > don't use that strategy and instead locate things in the > conventional realm. The > conventional is useful; the useful, communicable, and the communicable > achievable. If you hit on the achievable, you are almost there and > dependent *shi*s end. (*Ibid*., HY 4/2/36-37) > Zhuangzi describes our past *shis* of this kind as "like an oath or treaty." (*Ibid*., HY 3/2/11) They have "enactment force" committing us to a *dao* governing their later use. We may conform to (correctly follow) and further construct our transmitted linguistic *dao* in expressing or performing (Wei *wei*deeming) other things as *shi-fei*. Our trajectory along our paths incorporates these accumulated commitments to prior practices of language use. As our *dao*s now bring us to new situations, how do we know to project the correct indexed choice from the prior history of differently-indexed behavior? That actual language behavior commits us to a linguistic *dao*-type, but it's not clear what the commitment entails at this choice point. The Mohists and Confucians are both claiming, from their different directional perspectives, to be following similar commitments to existing *dao*s of practice. Mozi's recommending naturally or empirically available *dao*s for reforming shared linguistic practice was itself, Mozi thought, following existing natural practice. He even noticed that our ongoing linguistic practice rejects treating something's merely being a shared past practice as automatically making it right. Our existing evaluation practices remind us that shared and unquestioned past practices can be wrong. Mozi appealed to what he would also have regarded as a purely natural practice. Practical efficiency (*li*benefit) is a standard accessible to all ordinary people's "eyes and ears." Each time we apply some natural, empirically guided interpretation in practice, we participate in shaping evolving normative practices (both linguistic and behavioral practices). Each such decision commits us *and others* to a *dao* of interpreting our social *dao*. We understand our commitment to that *dao* as a commitment to practice and transmit it correctly--where the standard of 'correct' is itself either enshrined in a past practice or in natural utility. This is the basis for Zhuangzi's claim that social *dao*s, including linguistic *dao*s, are natural *dao*s--and there are many of them. Further, as the *Laozi* would later famously observe, *dao*s can be interpretively guided. They are changeable *dao*s. Humans, in finding ways to walk and walking them, initiate the construction of social paths, naturally and perhaps unintentionally, by leaving prints in the natural world. Zhuangzi links the path metaphor to a society's linguistic practice thus: > That which we treat as Ke *ke*assertible > is Ke *ke*assertible; > that which we treat as not assertible is not > assertible. *Dao*s are made by walking them; thing-kinds > are made Ran *ran*so so by > being called 'so'. (*Ibid*., HY 4/2/33) > This sense of the immense complexity and the fluid nature of normative commitments to a *dao*path underlie Zhuangzi's skeptical themes. Ming *Ming*clear:discerning seems linked to the gestalt in which we accept ourselves as embedded, along with others similarly situated, in nature's endlessly complex evolution of guiding structures. How do we know either that our past practice was correct or that we are correctly following them in this new situation, here and now, based solely on our eyes and ears? ### 4.7 Skepticism Zhuangzi's stance toward Mohist formal realism (if we disagree on a *shi-fei*, one party must Sheng *sheng*win) becomes clearer now. The Mohists did not specify any objective mechanism of "winning" beyond some vague suggestion of tipping a balance. However Zhuangzi's point in response appears to track the *warning function* of a norm of truth (even when justified by our best available judging standards, we may still be wrong). Zhuangzi takes *sheng*winning as a vague primitive in arguing that we cannot finally settle skeptical doubts by appeal to winning disputes. The main mechanism Zhuangzi discusses is appeal to a judge or authority. We appreciate that all judges will also use terms like *shi-fei*this-not that indexed by their acquired commitment momentum. Their judgments, like ours, express their momentum along a *dao* of using *these* words *here, now* and projecting the usage to *that, there, then*. > Given that you and > I have been brought to Bian > *bian*dispute and you win me over and I > don't win you over, in such a case is your distinction > substantively Shi *Shi*this:right? Mine > substantively Fei *fei*? If I win you over and > you don't win me over; is mine substantively right? And yours?; > substantively wrong? Are they partly right and partly wrong? Or > jointly right and jointly wrong? You and I cannot know between > ourselves, so another human inherently inherits our obscurity and > doubt. To whom can we go to correct us? Employing someone who agrees > with you, given that they are like you, how can they correct the > situation? Employing someone who agrees with me, given that they are > like me, how can they correct it? Employ someone different from both > me and you to correct it, given that they are different from us both, > how can they correct it? Employ someone who is like both of us to > correct it, given that they are like us both, how can they correct it? > So you and I and others cannot know, and in these condition on what > other can we rely? The changing sounds' mutual dependence is like their > conjoint autonomy. Harmonize them with glances at nature and make them > dependent on eventual consensus and with that exhaust the > years. (*Ibid*., HY 7/2/84-92) It is not clear if the conclusion is supposed to be a solution to the skeptical problem posed or merely a way to cope constructively with complexity and uncertainty. The passage rules out any appeal to a special authority of any other point of view--while giving equal authority in the construction to all. Even where we all share some "conventional wisdom" it does not have special authority--say over other creatures. This, was implicit in Mozi's rejection of socially agreed *dao*s. Zhuangzi's notorious toying with the perspectives of animals expanded it (for naturalists). . > Gap-tooth asked > Kingsley, "Do you know that which all natural kinds agree in > *shi*endorse-ing?" > He answers > "How would I know that?" > "Then, do you know of > what you don't know?" > "And how could I know > that?" > "So, does no natural kind know > anything?" > "And how would I know that? Nonetheless, > let me try to put it in language. How would I know that what I call > 'knowing' is not not-knowing? And what I call > 'not-knowing', is knowing." > > > > And let me try a question on you. If people sleep in the damp, they > get pains and paralysis; would eels? If in a tree, they tremble in > fear; would monkeys? Of the three, does any know the correct place to > live? ... From where I see it, the origins of goodness and > morality, painting things as 'this/right' or > 'not-that/wrong' are, as boundaries, both confused and > complicated; how could I know how to distinguish them? > (*Ibid*., HY 6/2/64-70) > > > This passage reinforces the conclusion that norms of correct word use is Zhuangzi's core skeptical target. So we may indeed know how to act, according to some norms of using 'know how' and not if judged by some other *dao* of correct usage of the knowing/ignorant distinction. Linguistic skepticism easily metastasizes to virtually any commitment. According to which *dao* of projecting past practice should we judge *this* linguistic behavior as conforming to our commitment or not. Normative skepticism, in a use-theory is hard to contain--especially when the model of all judgments is as some indexed Shi Fei *shi-fei*this-not that assignment. It sweeps in metaphysics, epistemics, and semantics. A consequence is that Zhuangzi's skepticism is broad but weak. Broad because it infects so many judgments, but weak not merely in the usual sense of denying absolute certainty, but in failing to imply that we should stop or refuse to make the judgment. It does not rest on any theory of the probability of an error, but that the concept of an error is subject to the same concerns as the original judgment. It neither undermines nor give us reason to withdraw our judgments. Appreciating that others reach their views as naturally as we do only removes our status to claim that our judgment is authentically and uniquely correct. Temporally, Zhuangzi's skepticism is buttressed by reminding us of our own past experiences of learning, of acquiring new gestalts, of realizing that what we had considered *the* way, was subject to reconsideration and improvement. The skepticism does not target any specific failure in my epistemic process. It does not advise me to abandon my present course. It reminds me only to remain open to the further possibility of learning more--about what? About the world? We can do that by learning more about other natural ways of processing and how they work in the world--other *dao*s. It counts as skepticism because it reminds us that we normally err on the side of overestimating than underestimating our epistemic security. We think we know and do not more often than we think we don't know and we do. And that is because we underestimate the range of possible alternative *dao*s. Hence the pragmatic upshot of his skepticism is to remind us to engage with more other points of view. Zhuangzi's skepticism is weak because it acknowledges that we may apply different concepts of 'knowing' in different situations. Implicitly, it does not deny that we could meet *some* particular standard of knowing, but that we could know for every situation which standard is the right one. What standard is the right one to use for acknowledging or denying someone knows well enough to satisfy, for example, the correct *dao* of assertion? This feature of Zhuangzi's skepticism lies at the heart of the famous debate between Zhuangzi and Hui Shi about the fish-pleasure in which Zhuangzi *defends* a claim to know against Hui Shi's challenge. Zhuangzi makes an assertion and Hui Shi initiates the skeptical challenge. His challenge implies that there is a favored or correct standard of knowing that turns out to be impossibly strict. All knowledge must come from inside. It's impossibly strict because it doesn't allow Hui Shi to issue the challenge in this conversation. > Zhuangzi and > Hui Shi wandered over the Hao River bridge. Zhuangzi said, > "those mini-fish coming from there and cruising around, relaxed > and unhurried, are fish at leisure." Hui Shi said "You are > not a fish; from whence do you know the leisure of fish?" Zhuangzi > retorted, "You are not me, from what perspective do you know my > not knowing fish at leisure?" Hui Shi responds, "I'm > not you, of course I don't know about you; You are not a fish > and that's enough to count as you're not knowing > fish's leisure." Zhuangzi concludes, "Let's > return to where we started. When you said 'from what perspective > do you know fish at leisure', you clearly knew my knowing it as you > asked me. I knew it here above the Hao." (*Ibid*., HY > 45/17/87-91) > Graham drew our attention to the role of perspective in this passage, noting that Hui Shi's challenge to Zhuangzi's assertion does not use the normal question form, (He hehow do you know?) but a locative question word (An anwhence?). This brings the debate into alignment with Zhuangzi's concern about the various perspectives from which to deploy a *dao* of word use. Here, as above, the word is Zhi *zhi*know. The norm of asserting, as in English, involves answering the challenge "how do you know?" What normative conditions allow me, here and now, correctly to use the term *zhi*know--hence to make the assertion about these fish below me? Hui Shi both knew Zhuangzi was relying on a *dao* of using 'know' "from zhuangzi's here" **and** Hui Shi knew Zhuangzi's situation from his own relevantly similar "here-now" and relying on **the same** Dao *dao*norm of claiming to know from a distinct perspective. Hui Shi cannot consistently insist that a speaker can only use Zhi *zhi*know when he occupies the perspective of the thing known. ### 4.8 Perspectives on Perspectives Notice, the argument about the fish implies we have a perspective on the perspectives of others. So skepticism grounded in dependence or relativity of perspective need not be predominantly negative. Zhuangzi, here, uses it to justify a way of claiming to knowing. In many other parables, he addresses the kind of knowing that comes with a gestalt shift, especially when we see our own and others' points of view as similar--see ourselves as others see us. This is the more comprehensive perspective Zhuangzi urges on us. We experience such gestalt shifts especially when we come appreciate we had been wrong before and now view things differently. We are confident from our own "now" that we have made epistemic progress--our new awareness seems "relatively" improved to us now. We reach a state where we judge our former perspective to be inferior to our present one. It includes insight into our relative situations. Evidently, this awareness of one's own perspective as one of many, equally natural points of view motivates us to wonder if we have made the final correction. This enhanced awareness of ourselves as one of many perspectives is an intelligible candidate reading of Zhuangzi's Ming *ming*clarity. It is harder to construct a coherent narrative for mystical and/or dogmatic readings--those that jump from an improved perspective to a perfect one. This kind of gestalt shift leads us to reflect on how narrow our past perspective had been. It features prominently in the "Autumn Floods" Chapter 17. The Earl of the Yellow River, having thought himself as the ultimate, discovers the North Sea and announces his former error and newfound awareness of his lesser significance in "the greater path." The North Sea Overlord tells him that he too sees himself as situated in a modest status in a still greater scheme and rejects the River Earl's attempts to identify the North Sea's as ultimate. He casts doubt on there being a final, ultimately small or large. > The lord of He river said, "So can I consider > cosmos 'large' and the tip of a hair as > 'small'?" North Sea Ruo replied, "No! Thing > kinds have unlimited measurement (ways of measuring); Time has no end; > distinctions have no constancy, beginning and ending no inherent > cause. Because of this great knowing is viewed within a range of > distant and close. ...We calculate that what humans know is never > as great as what they do not know, their temporal extent of life is > not as great as not as much as the time before life, and from the very > small to try to take in the scope of the very large, is an invitation > to confusion and disorder and not that from which we can > gain. (*Ibid*., HY 42/17/14-20) Can we describe Zhuangzi's *ming* as "having a sense of our limited perspective?" Credulous, dogmatic and imperious absolutists do not appreciate themselves as being in one of a variety of natural perspectives. Broad open-mindedness and mild skepticism come together in the *ming*clarity Zhuangzi encourages in us. It has a dual nature--an epistemically modest perspective on ourselves that arises from improving our epistemic status and encourages us to continue. It helps us appreciate that we are still as naturally situated and others with whom we may disagree and still grow. Further improvement can come from further exchange of perspectives. The naive Confucian-Mohist advocates of imposing a single social *dao* thus disrupt the natural process by which social *dao*s evolve in real time as we seek a harmony guided by "glances at nature." Seeing things from another's perspective both alerts us to how we could be wrong and makes us feel that we now understand things better than with our former, narrower perspective. Yet, the *Zhuangzi* repeatedly reminds us not to abandon epistemic modesty when we make epistemic progress. That we now see things from a perspective in common with another does not make us both right. Yet, the more comprehensive our perspective, the "clearer" the new gestalt should seem. The search for this kind of perspective on ourselves and others seems to motivate Zhuangzi's willingness to engage and interact with others, seeking to understand their perspective as having a natural status and role for them as ours does for us. This is partly illustrated by common sense examples of our judging from our own current perspective that theirs "adds something" enriching our own perspective by our own lights. Sometimes it's dangerous to try to mix others' perspectives with your own. > And have you alone not > heard tell of those from Shou-ling who studied walking with those in > Handan? They never mastered the country's skill and lost their > original way of walking, and stumbled and crawled > back. (*Ibid*., HY45/17/79-80) Aside from its frequent usefulness from our point of view, the main benefit from the self-recognition as a natural creature embedded as are others at a perspective-point within a natural network structure is to encourage being open-minded. Part of the value is the humbling of our epistemic pride, mildly disrupting our judgment equilibrium. Without such an occasional perspective on ourselves, we too easily fall into exaggerating our epistemic exceptionalism. The reminder that we are intermingled with others in a web of natural perspectives gives us an appropriate, realistic correction. A Zhuangzi story illustrates such a moment. > > Zhuangzi was wandering in Diaoling fields when he glimpsed a > weird magpie-like-thing flying in from the south. It had a wingspan of > over seven-feet and passed so close his forehead, he could feel > it. Then it gathered its wings and settled in a chestnut > grove. Zhuangzi thought "what bird is that? Massive > wings of such power and eyes so large it couldn't see > me." He hiked up his robe and hurriedly tiptoed closer holding his > cross-bow at the ready. Then he spotted a cicada settling in the > shaded shelter without a worry for itself, but a preying mantis > opened its pincers about to grab it, also focused on its gain and > ignoring its own bodily danger. The strange magpie burst out and > harvested them both--similarly unaware of the natural dangers he > faced. > > > > But Zhuangzi was suddenly seized with this thought, "We natural > kinds are all interconnected! We two different species are mutually > seeing things in our own ways." He dismantled his crossbow and > fled, himself now himself pursued by the game warden shouting out his > crimes. (*Ibid*., HY 54/20/61-5) > > > Overall, Zhuangzi clearly recommends open-minded flexibility as when he scolds Hui Shi for being tied to conventional thinking about how to use giant gourds. He illustrates it again with his story about different uses of a salve that prevents chapping. He models such openness in his conversations with cripples (righteously shunned by Confucians), freaks, thieves, strange creatures, the wind, a shadow and a skull. He imagines many other conversations illustrating the differences of perspectives, capacities and needs. While we cannot help making our own judgments and commitments, he seems to see tolerance and accommodation as values that follow from appreciating other natural perspectives: > A monkey keeper says (to the monkeys) "I'll > give you three [rations] in the morning and four in the > evening." The monkeys seemed angry. "Ok, I'll give > you four in the morning and three in the evening." The monkeys > were happy. So with no substantive loss, he could change their anger > to happiness. This is an example of a *shi* judgment > being dependent on circumstances. So the sage uses > *shi-fei*this-not that judgments to > harmonize and rests in the natural balance. And we can call this > walking as pairs. (*Ibid*., HY 5/2/38-40) We are, as it happens, capable of understanding the perspectives of others well enough to accommodate and cooperate with them, to borrow insights and to reach agreements. However, the *Zhuangzi* seems skeptical that we can extrapolate from this ordinary capacity to broaden our perspective to having some absolute or comprehensive insight--as it were from *all* points of view. Nor, as we saw above, can we assume that because the two disputants come to a resolution or agreement, it constitutes knowing from a cosmically or absolutely higher perspective. Hui Shi's relativism, recall, does point to such an infinite expansion ending in a single universal point of view. Here, however, we are reminded that while we experience a gestalt broadening of perspective as revealing something real and significant (like waking from a dream), we cannot extrapolate from that to the claim to be able to know the final result of such gestalt leaps to broader perspectives. Even though North Sea Lord denies there is any final or ultimately broad perspective from which we can make *shi-fei*this-not that judgments, the parable suggests a progressive path toward broader perspectives with those further along having the epistemic status to guide those with less comprehensive perspectives. However, arguments in Chapter 2 suggest that progress must always be judged from a moving frame of reference along a *dao* that is already *cheng*fixed in our *xin*heart-mind that *shoots-out* the *shi-fei*. Our location and trajectory makes us receptive to some and not other avenues of learning. The boy was unable to master the Handan way of walking because of the way he had already learned to walk. The monkey keeper could accommodate the monkeys, but still disagreed with them about the importance of the breakfast-dinner choice. That someone understands and agrees with both of us does not make his judgment correct. The final skepticism concerns whether these paths of progress of perspectives must or will converge on a single outcome. The epistemic modesty implicit in Zhuangzi's skepticism targets mainly the paternalistic, superior attitude toward other points of view exemplified by Confucian and Mohist moralistic posture. When we have an accommodation (you and I come to a common agreement) you and I may both rate it as progress. However, it does not imply we have moved to a higher state of overall insight along an absolute scale--or from any arbitrary third point of view. Exchange of points of view can be valuable to each (perhaps in different ways) and broadening perspective in this way can make us wiser--but always as judged from our already operative Cheng *cheng*fixed *dao*s . We can advise and recommend our normative perspective on others, but their being able to appreciate and use it depends on their capacities, options and situation. At this point, Zhuangzi starts to draw an analogy of dreaming and waking up to the shift in gestalt that comes when we leap to a more comprehensive perspective. At awakening, we immediately appreciate the unreality of the dream, yet within the dream, we can have a similar gestalt shift and dream of having dreamed and interpreted that deeper dream. > How do I know that loving life is not a form of ignorance? > How do I know disliking death is not a weak farewell of the sort when > we don't know about the return? Miss Li Zhi cries when she is > betrothed to someone's son, and when she first goes off to the Jin > state soaks her clothing with her tears; but then she arrives at the > kings abode, sleeps with the king in his bed, eats fattened > livestock and then starts to regret her tears. How do I know the dead > do not regret their former clinging to life, We dream of eating and > drinking and on awaking cry bitterly, we dream of weeping and wailing > and awake in a good mood to go off hunting. When we dream, we don't > know it as a dream, and in our dreams, judge something else as a > dream. On awakening, we know it was a dream, and there could be > another greater awakening in which we know a greater dream, and under > these the conditions the ignorant think they are as enlightened as if > they had learned it by an investigation. Gentlemen to shepherds > inherently do this! (*Ibid*., HY 6/2/78-83) So, is there an ultimate or final possible such shift in gestalt--some final state of knowing what to do? Zhuangzi's relativism is mildly skeptical because he cannot know either that there is not nor that there is a final or ultimate "awakening" The dream theme is memorably carried over to the story of Zhuangzi dreaming a butterfly and/or vice versa. It seems to suggest that the gestalt sense of liberation from error may even be reciprocal. Perhaps our subsequent perspective is one from which most would move to our former perspective. Adolescent conversion can be to or from a religion. > Once before, Zhuangzi dreamt of being a butterfly, gaily > butterflying and himself embodied in this sense of purpose! He knew > nothing of Zhuangzi. Suddenly awakening, he then is rooted in > Zhuangzi. He doesn't know if Zhuangzi dreamt being a butterfly > or a butterfly is dreaming being Zhuangzi--though there must be a > difference. This is called "things change." (*Ibid*., > HY7/2/94) Elaborating the complexity this way makes Zhuangzi's proposals seem disappointing as solutions. They amount to mildly suggesting that we allow the exchange of views to go on without the domination of any dogma and with some vague "glances at natural constancies" and see what comes out "in the long run." Zhuangzi's conception of *dao*s in nature, from a here-now to a there-then, differs from a Mohist (broadly utilitarian) naturalism. Utilitarianism is a natural constraint, an allegedly single naturally correct way for all of us to choose our course. In effect, Zhuangzi is more of a natural pluralist, with the natural outcome of morality the product of ongoing individual and social construction. *Dao*s are in nature but not choices of nature for us. So the discussion, competition, and even strife between *dao*s and their advocates are factors in an ongoing natural Dao *dao*guiding process. We and our circumstances change as we each find, choose and walk different naturally evolving paths. This does not entail we should not advocate our own way. Such exchanges are part of the natural process of construction of Dao *dao*spaths and making them available to others. Such a dialogue of competing *dao*s constitutes the natural evolutional *dao* of guidance. Realizing this, we should not flatter ourselves, posing as the Confucian father shaping his child's character, but as a contributor in this competition among similarly natural ways. We express perspectives located in a real world of indexed points from which we choose behavioral paths. Some characters in Zhuangzi's dialogues wonder about exceptional figures who allegedly have abilities that justify that paternal posture--the capacity to transcend our location in points of view and to lecture all of us from a privileged perspective. The *Zhuangzi*'s response typically remind them that such idealized points of view are neither intelligible to us nor relevant to what *we* should do. Either these exceptional observers have their own naturally *cheng*fixed frames of reference in the natural world, or they are outside of the natural world in some unrealistically free realm. If the latter, then their views are both unintelligible and irrelevant to us. What they would do in our situation does not constitute helpful advice to us. To advocate following the advice of these ideal observers is to speak practical nonsense to non-ideal, actual actors. Gap Tooth, following Kingsley's skeptical formulation above says: > > So you don't know what is beneficial or harmful, does the > "fully arrived human" necessarily not know them? > Kingsley replied, "the fully arrived person becomes pure > sapience, he could be in a blazing forest and not be able to feel any > heat, the rivers of our civilization could freeze and he > couldn't feel any chill, devastating lighting could pulverize > mountains and the wind raise a tidal wave and he could not experience > surprise. Someone like that could ride on clouds and air, straddle the > sun and moon, and wander beyond the four oceans. Death and life > are not different for him, much less the inclinations of benefit and > harm." > > > > Master Ju Que asked master Zhang Wu, "I've heard from > my teacher that a sagely man does not find social dealings worth > engaging, doesn't pursue utility, doesn't avoid harm, > doesn't take delight in striving, doesn't follow > *dao*s, in silence says things, and in saying things is > silent, and roams outside the nitty-gritty of the actual world. Master > regarded this as romantic fantasy but I deem it the execution of a > mysterious *dao*. My kind sir what do you say of > this?" > > > > Zhang Wu replied, "This is something that, were the yellow > emperor to hear, it would be like buzzing, and so how could the likes > of Confucius come to know it? Furthermore, you have jumped to > conclusions... . I'll give you some absurd talk and you absurdly > listen." (*Ibid*., HY 6/2/71-7) > > > However, in later chapters, Zhuangzi himself seems to recommend to us examples of such spectacular capacities--the most beautifully and elaborately expressed of which is the passage celebrating Butcher Ding. > Butcher Ding carved an ox for Lord Wen Hui; his point > of contact, the way he inclined his torso, his foot position, the > angle of his knee ... gliding, flowing! The knife sang > "whuaa" with nothing out of tune. It was as if he were > dancing the Faun Ballet or directing an opera. > > > Lord Wen Hui exclaimed "Ole! Splendidly done! Can talent > extend even to this?. > > > > Butcher Ding gestured with his knife, explaining, > > > > > > > "What your > > servant pursues is *dao*; which is what skill aims > > at. When I began to carve oxen, what I saw was nothing but the > > oxen. After three years, I had ceased seeing them as wholes, and now > > my sapience mingles so that I don't see with my eyes, Sensory > > know-how ends and my sapient desires take over my performance. I rely > > on natural guiding structures, separate out the great chunks and steer > > through empty gaps depending on the anatomy. I evade places where > > cords and filaments intertwine, much less the large bones. > > > > > > A good cook gets a new knife every year; he chops! Mediocre cooks > > change knives monthly; they hack. My knife now has 19 years on it; > > it's carved several thousand oxen and the edge is as if I had > > just taken it from the sharpener. > > > > > > > > Those joints have gaps, and the knife's edge no thickness, to > > put something infinitesimally thin in an empty space?! Effortless! It > > even allows the edge wander in with ample room to play. That is why, > > with 19 years on it, this knife's edge is grindstone > > fresh." > > > > > > > (*Ibid*., 7/3/2-8) The *Zhuangzi* plays several variations on this theme. Sometimes the virtuoso performer catches cicadas on a sticky rod, another crafts chariot wheels, there are musicians, debaters, and thieves. The theme extends to animals, millipedes with their expertise in coordinating their limbs while maintaining a smooth flow, snakes flashing by while slithering on their stomachs, One implicit example is Zhuangzi's own relation with his relativist rival and buddy, Hui Shi. Bemoaning his loss while visiting his sidekick's grave, Zhuangzi spins a tale of a virtuoso ax-thrower who sliced specks off the nose of his crony, but lost his "knack" when his co-performer passed away. (*Ibid*., HY 66/24/48-51) The tales often highlight the tranquil state that accompanies behavior that skillfully follows a natural path. The performances look and feel effortless. The spontaneity of the flow along a natural path gives performers the sense that their behavior is "world-guided" rather than internally controlled. These behaviors become second-nature. We move beyond anything like sub-vocalizing instructions, deliberating or reflecting--and yet we are concentrating intently on the behavior. The range of his examples reminds us that such satisfying states of performance can be experienced in even the most low caste and mundane of activities, including butchering, criminal skills, as well as in the finest of arts, and philosophy. Another feature of this theme is the observation that such expertise in performance always comes with some kind of limitation--not least that each example is a different person with a different knack. There is no shortcut *dao* that gives you a knack at every activity. Cook Ding "comes to a hard place;" the cicada catcher tries to balance two coins on his stick--if he is not calm enough, he will have a bad night. The wheelwright could not teach his son the art; the musician cannot play all the notes and only reaches true perfection when he dwells in silence. And above all, the valorization of this kind of specialization in an art pulls in the opposite direction of Zhuangzi's encouragement to broaden and enlarge our perspectives and scope of appreciation. This theme of the limits of virtuosity is pursued explicitly in the *Zhuangzi*'s discussion of the necessary connection of Cheng *cheng*completion:success and Kui *kui* failure:deficiency. The theme of this weak skeptical relativism plays out smoothly into the classical Chinese focus on paths as the model of normativity and the objects of knowledge. Paths are everywhere, but guide natural kinds from particular space-time locations and can guide a wide range of behavior types, normative subject matters. Each leads to subsequent choices among *dao*spaths. Zhuangzi does not ground his skepticism in an account of specifically human epistemic deficiencies. We are one among many natural creatures with different capacities choosing paths from their indexed point in space and time. The skeptical theme is the wide range of our different perspectives. We are limited mainly in the sense that there is no behavior from the point of view of the whole--there is no omniscient perspective on the path structure. We may wonder if we have discovered all the available Dao *dao*spaths. And we may always wonder if our judgment about which is best now is about the best in the long run. All we can substitute for this global perspective is some local consensus. > Substantively, in the end, is there success and defect? > Substantively, in the end, is there neither success nor defect?....If > we can call these successful, then even I am also successful. If they > cannot be called successful, then neither I nor any other thing may be > called successful. For this reason, illumination of slippery doubt is > that which sages target. For this reason, we do not use it and let > things rest in the conventional. (*Ibid*., HY > 5/2/42-47) The weak skeptical conclusion is most strikingly expressed in the observation that introduces the chapter with the story of Cook Ding. > My life is limited and know-how is unlimited. To pursue > the unlimited with the limited is dangerous. (*Ibid*., HY > 7/3/1)
zhu-xi
## 1. Life and Works Zhu Xi was born in Youqi in Fujian in October 1130. Many anecdotes attest that he was a highly precocious child. It was recorded that at age five he ventured to ask what lay beyond Heaven, and by eight he understood the significance of the *Classic of Filiality* (*Xiaojing*). As a youth, he was inspired by Mencius' proposition that all people could become a sage. In Zhu Xi's childhood, his father Zhu Song (1097-1143) arranged for several old friends to educate Zhu Xi after his passing. Consequently, Zhu Xi was educated by several eclectic scholars who had delved into Daoism and Buddhism as well as Confucianism, and inclined him to be deep and wide-ranging in his intellectual predilections and cultural interests. Later he studied Chan (Zen) Buddhism with the monk Dao Qian of the Kaishan Temple, and reputedly met with the Chan master Da Hui (Dahui Zonggao, 1089-1163).[2] Traces of Huayan's holistic thought can also be discerned in the formation of Zhu Xi's system (Makeham 2018). Remarkably, Zhu passed the official *jinshi* exam (the "presented scholar" exam) at just nineteen, drawing on Chan Buddhism in his answers.[3] He continued to pursue Daoism and Buddhism until he met the Neo-Confucian master Li Tong (1093-1163) a decade later, and formally became his student in 1160. In fact, Zhu's father had recommended that he conduct his advanced studies under Li Tong, but Zhu postponed seeing Li for years until he finally admitted to himself that he was no longer making progress in his eclectic cultivation and suffered spiritual doubts. Li Tong was a master in the southern Yang Shi (1053-1135) lineage of the Cheng brothers' school, partial to the teachings of Cheng Yi. Importantly, Li Tong convinced Zhu of the cogency and superiority of the Confucian Way and cultivation. Meanwhile, having passed the *jinshi* examination, Zhu was eligible to hold office, and had been assigned to several prefectural administrative posts. But, since he disagreed with central court policy on several major issues, he preferred to hold temple guardianships, which gave him the leisure to conduct Confucian studies and cultivation in earnest, and shielded him from the ruthless court politics. Having chosen this career path, Zhu Xi had the leisure to study and reflect, so over time he made numerous contributions in classical studies, historical inquiries, literary studies, and philosophic reflections. He moreover developed into a man of letters and wrote subtle prose and elegant verse. A renowned teacher in later life, Zhu taught the classics and Neo-Confucian thought and practice to hundreds if not thousands of students. His oral discourses and discussions are preserved in the *Classified Dialogues of Master Zhu* (*Zhuzi yulei*), and his poetry, essays, correspondence, and other prose works are collected in the *Collected Works of Master Zhu* (*Zhuzi wenji*). He also published critical, annotated editions of several classics, including the *Book of Change* (*Yijing*) and the *Book of Odes* (*Shijing*), essential works of Neo-Confucianism, including by Zhou Dunyi, Zhang Zai, and the Cheng brothers, and a vital Neo-Confucian anthology, *Reflections on Things at Hand* (*Jinsilu*). He also edited and annotated an important early text of inner alchemy Daoism; the *Cantong qi* (*Unity of the Three*) by Wei Boyang (3rd cent. CE), which combines the cosmology of the *Yijing* and the Daoist teaching of *wuwei* (non-intentional action) with inner alchemy. Zhu Xi remained devoted to his spiritual and intellectual work virtually to his last breath, pondering and discussing problematic passages in the *Great Learning* during the last several days of his life. Throughout his life, Zhu Xi sought to reestablish the fundamental concepts and values of Confucianism to restore China's cultural and political integrity as a Confucian society, especially since people in search of spiritual guidance and solace were increasingly looking to Daoism and Buddhism rather than Confucianism, which was perceived as a state ideology and orthodoxy and had lost spiritual and ethical purchase. Moreover, Zhu believed that the empire needed the spiritual *elan* of Confucius' original ethical ideas and values to meet the challenge of barbarian encroachments. His own sincere patriotism, commitment to the tradition, and devotion to learning and scholarship have remained an inspiration to this day in East Asia and throughout the world. ## 2. Philosophy of Human Nature and Approach to Self-Cultivation Zhu Xi developed a theory of basic human propensities (nature, *xing*) to account for both the possibility of human evil and that of human goodness and perfectibility. On this theory, while (following Mencius, 372-289 BCE) insisting that people are basically good (well intended and sensitive to the sufferings of others), he accepted that the manner in which a person's basic disposition is manifested is conditioned and at times contained by their specific *qi* endowment (native talents and gifts, *qizhi*), family and social environment, and other factors. Such factors together yield their empirical personality, intelligence, and aptitude for spiritual-ethical cultivation. Zhu accepted that there are real differences in individual disposition, character, as well as aptitude for ethical self-cultivation and realization, owing to individual variations in *qi* endowment, environment, etc. Furthermore, he argued that people can become bad or evil due, for example, to a coarse or sensual *qi* endowment, the bad influence of ruthless kin or friends, a selfish or harsh social environment, a cruel streak, etc. Nonetheless, following Mencius, he firmly believed that anyone who was sincerely committed to moral self-cultivation and was fervent in their moral practice would surely make progress in achieving moral realization if not sagehood. Zhu Xi's teacher, Li Tong, and friend, Zhang Shi (1133-1180), presented him with different approaches to cultivation based on the premise of basic still and active mindsets, respectively. But, Zhu found that both of these approaches were one-sided and flawed. How is one to leap from quiet-sitting and stillness to making timely moral responses? When does one have the composure to introspect morally when their mind is constantly active and engaged? If neither the meditative approach nor the active approach to cultivation and practice were efficacious, what path remained open to Zhu Xi? Recent research shows that Zhu Xi embarked on a careful reading of the works of Zhou Dunyi during this period of spiritual-philosophical crisis in the course of which he rediscovered Zhou's doctrine of "the interpenetration of stillness and activity" for the human mind and spirit (Adler 2014). With this idea, Zhou Dunyi was advocating that whereas the states of action and rest are mutually exclusive in the case of physical objects, such states interpenetrate and are mutually implicative in the case of human mental and spiritual phenomena (Adler 2014). This doctrine piqued Zhu Xi's interest, and he came to see it as offering a way out of the dilemma between Li Tong's stress on stillness and Hu Hong's stress on activity in cultivation and practice, and their respective shortcomings. Zhou Dunyi's doctrine was particularly exciting to Zhu Xi for it highlighted the distinctness and potential religiosity of the human mind and spirit, which Zhou describes as not subject to the same limitations and restrictions as are physical phenomena. Zhou Dunyi moreover associates this idea with a vital and well integrated model of human mind and spirit, self-cultivation, and cosmos. Inspired by Zhou Dunyi's doctrine of the interpenetration of stillness and activity and related ideas, Zhu Xi worked out a twofold cultivation effort that incorporated at once nurturing one's feeling of reverence (*jing*) to purify mind while investigating things to discern their determinate or defining patterns (*li*). Cultivation of reverence, originally a religious virtue associated with ancestor worship and ceremonial rites, as described in the classics and taught by Confucius (551-479 BCE), serves to purify the mind, attune one to the promptings of the original good nature, and set one to act with appropriateness (*yi*). Moreover, by grasping the defining patterns (*li*) of relationship and intercourse that constitute the world, society, people, and proper conduct, one gains the master key to acting with utmost propriety (*zhongyong*). The mind that is imbued with reverence and comprehends these patterns will develop into a good will (*zhuzai*) dedicated to acting appropriately and with utmost propriety. Since *jing* takes on connotations of focus, concentration, and alertness, as well as reverence in Zhu Xi's discourses, mindfulness has been suggested as the English translation that covers the fullness of the term *jing* (Kalton 1988) in Zhu Xi's thought. In later life, Zhu started to regard this twofold approach to cultivation and realization as too complicated, gradual, and difficult to carry out in practice. Like Confucius before him and anticipating Wang Yangming after him, Zhu Xi came to accept that the sincere Confucian adept must, on embarking on his or her project of ethical self-cultivation, first strive to establish his or her sincere determination (*lizhi*) to realize the cardinal Confucian virtues and become an exemplary person (*junzi*), that is to say, a master of appropriateness in interpersonal conduct and human affairs generally. ## 3. Ethical Philosophy Zhu Xi's methodology for achieving perspicacity (*ming*) in ethical judgment and "appropriateness" (*yi*) in practice can be summed up in his call to investigate things to extend knowledge (*gewu zhizhi*). Zhu advocated this methodology to stress the need for people, as prospective moral agents, to notice the fine details, the distinguishing features of particular situations and to fashion on that basis the most discerning, appropriate response. These distinguishing features can suggest alternative moral considerations to be weighed (Pincoffs 1986). This call lay behind Zhu's promotion of the *Great Learning* (*Daxue*) and call for life-long learning and moral reflection in a bid to achieve a modicum of objectivity and break free of the moral intuitionism and resultant subjectivism typical of Neo-Confucians of his generation. ### 3.1 Investigating Things for Ethical Discernment and Practice Throughout his career, Zhu Xi focused on the twin problems of 1) determining the conditions of moral agency, and 2) setting forth a viable program of moral self-cultivation on that basis. Zhu saw moral agency as the expression of a moral will, which he understood to be the achievement of an inner self-mastery (*zhuzai*) that forms the core of a person's moral character, perceptivity, cognizance, and responsiveness. On this view, self-cultivation that is aimed at nurturing self-mastery must include forming a concentrated, reverential mind-set (*jing*) and a discerning sense of appropriateness. Early on, Zhu had emphasized the need to attain a working knowledge of the constitutive patterning (*li*) of reality and society in the light of which the norms and ritual action (*li*) prescribed for proper interpersonal relationships and intercourse are devised. He later found that establishing the determination (*lizhi*) to seek self-realization and conduct oneself appropriately counted for as much as the long-term cultivation process itself, during which one can lose sight of one's purpose and be side-tracked (see Qian Mu 1986: 123-127). Moreover, while still maintaining the importance of the norms and ritual action for character-building and the social order, Zhu began to emphasize the need to build up a sympathetic but realistic grasp of the warp and woof of real daily human life viewed in the perspective of such broad Confucian ethical ideals as humaneness (*ren*) and fairness (*gong*). He understood that, although the norms and ritual action are broadly applicable and reliable, many situations call for specifically tailored responses.[4] Consequently, against the moral intuitionism prevalent at the time in Neo-Confucianism, as espoused by his teacher Li Tong (1093-1163), his intellectual rival Lu Jiuyuan (1139-1193), and others, Zhu argued that intuitionism is inadequate for dealing effectively with the complex human affairs that people are apt to encounter in their lives.[5] Rather, he advocated dedicating oneself to the observation and study of the patterning/patterns (*li*) of relationship, interaction, and change among all things, among human beings in particular. He regarded "investigating things to extend knowledge" as the surest way to deepen and broaden one's discernment of the patterns that constitute the lived-world. Such knowledge, importantly, would sharpen one's sense of appropriateness by attuning oneself to the actual, subtle, distinguishing features of particular situations. Again, Zhu Xi conceived the world as a patterned (*li*) totality made up of a cosmic vapor (*qi*) that under various conditions condenses and solidifies into countless permutations, from the purest transparent *yuanqi* (primordial *qi*), to the *Yin-Yang* poles modulated by the primal *taiji* (supreme polarity) pattern, to the *wuxing* (five phases), each of which bears an identifying inner pattern and set of propensities (*xing*) that involve interconvertability and recombination with the other four phases, and finally to the phenomenal world: Heaven, Earth, and the myriad things (*tiandi wanwu*).[6] For Zhu Xi, the world presents a vital tapestry of relationships, cycles, processes, events, and things that are spontaneously arrayed in aesthetic order. In the nexus of these arrays, *li* are manifested three dimensionally and present different faces from different angles (Graham 1986a: 148; Qian Mu 1986: 133). *Li* are inherently perspectival. Zhu adopts metaphors of the grains in wood, the lines in jade, the "veins" in a leaf, the lines in marble, and even the sinewy texture of beef, to stress that *li* are manifested immanently rather than abstractly, and thus are to be sought concretely by observing phenomena in the world, not by pure, disengaged, abstract ratiocination (Needham 1956a: 473). Moreover, *li* are never presented in their putative optimal pure form. They always appear conditioned by the degree of purity of the *qi* through which they are manifested and of the environing conditions (Wade 2003). *Li* also structure the human mind, thought, and language, such that human beings are predisposed to grasp and attempt to respond appropriately to the things and situations they encounter.[7] Objective learning on this view can be understood as a facet of self-learning: indeed, by the principle of continuity, objective understanding enhances self-understanding, for by comprehending the warp and woof of the outer *li* of things, one gains insight into the inner *li* constituting one's mind and character (Qian Mu 1971: II 31-38). For Zhu Xi, while *li* structure the mind, thought, and language, this is not just at the cognitive level: *li* also structure the inner patterning (*xing*) and basic impulses that predispose us to have characteristically human emotions (*qing*), relationships, and responses (*ganying*) under various sets of conditions (Graham 1986a: 152-154; Qian Mu 1971: II. 25-30). In Zhu's Confucian view, *li* and *xing* predispose one to be sensitive and responsive; metaphorically, they provide the hardware of human nature. Self-cultivation and moral reflection are the means by which one actively conditions and fine-tunes these predispositions of sensitivity and response. They thus function as indispensable software for cultivating personhood. These are the contours of Zhu Xi's approach to moral self-cultivation and interpersonal ethics. The standard ethical norms work well in standard situations, normal families, good communities, and ordinary social circumstances. But, Zhu also understood that people are richly complicated and that human affairs often become complex, get out of hand, and go awry. Life is just not that ideal, not that simple. We sometimes encounter ethically anomalous situations to which the standard sets of feelings and responses as prescribed by the received norms and ritual actions simply do not fit. In many instances, standing on the norm and being moralistic simply would make matters worse. Zhu himself said that one must have ample experience and self-cultivation so that, > > > If, by chance, an anomalous affair should come up, one could > comprehend it. One wants to be in a position to grasp such affairs > thoroughly in order to understand their unfamiliar aspects. (YL: ch. > 19) > > > Zhu Xi considered how to tailor responses appropriate in problematic situations under the rubric of *quan* (weighing things up, discretion, expedient means).[8] He noted several kinds of situations in which recourse to discretion and expedient means might be advisable: 1) extraordinary situations that cannot be covered by the standard norms and ritual actions, 2) urgent situations that require a direct violation of the received norms and ritual actions to be satisfactorily resolved, and 3) situations in which it would be more humane and prudent not to observe the relevant norms and ritual actions (see Wei 1986). Situations of the first kind include those that call for a disruption of the given human order, for example the removal of an evil authority figure, such as a psychotic parent or a sociopathic tyrant. For situations of the second kind, Zhu had in mind emergencies when one would have to violate a norm in order to perform an emergency action, such as grasping the hand of a drowning sister-in-law, or shoving an old lady out of the path of a runaway oxcart.[9] Finally, the third kind of situation includes those in which it would be more compassionate to waive or overlook the ritual prescriptions, such as in cases of condoning the remarriage of a widow who would otherwise be destined to isolation and destitution. Clearly, such considerations lead us into unmapped ethical terrain. How far can one justifiably take such sidestepping of the received applicable norms and ritual actions? What qualifications and restrictions might apply? For his part, Zhu Xi mentioned at least two qualifications: a weak qualification that the expedient adopted not be otherwise ethically objectionable, and a stronger qualification stipulating that the expedient adopted be in compliance with the Way, i.e., that it satisfy some basic moral value, at least as basic as the values expressed in the relevant received norm and ritual action. Thus, any exercise of discretion that is undertaken in light of one's sense of appropriateness (*yi*), if exercised with sufficient probity and care, should satisfy the moral values embodied in the Way more adequately than would a routine observance of the standard norm. Humaneness is the core moral value that was invoked most often in such cases, but there are a number of others: filial piety, fraternity, fidelity, empathy, compassion, appropriateness, etc. Famous examples from the Confucian tradition include Mencius' reminder that one should overturn the propriety of not grasping the hand of a member of the opposite sex in order to rescue a drowning sister in law (*Mencius* 4A.17), and Cheng Yi argued for an exception to the impropriety of widows remarrying on the basis of filial piety (Rosenlee 2006: 134). Similarly, Socrates showed that Justice is not always realized by observance of the proprieties of truth-telling and faithfully returning a friend's property (Plato *Republic* 331c). Nonetheless, ever cognizant of temptation and moral weakness, Zhu insisted on the well established probity and integrity of anyone who would venture to use discretion and exercise expedient means. He stated: > > > Intending to weigh up a situation carefully [in order to exercise > expedient means], one must have cultivated the inner root daily, so > that one's mind is sensitive, perspicacious, pure, and > integrated; [even in that case,] one still must naturally weigh up > such situations most carefully. As Cheng Yi (1033-1107) said: Be > reverent in order to straighten oneself within; practice > appropriateness in order to square situations without. One's > sense of appropriateness comprises the moral fiber which one expresses > through sincere ritual action (YL 37, 37:6a, par. 36). > > > Only those who have extensively "investigated things to extend knowledge", and who are conversant with the subtle patternings of the human heart and human affairs would be qualified to consider exercising expedient means over simply following the norms. (Zhu knew that this ethical knowledge is as much a matter of practical experience as of book learning. At times, he told his occasionally priggish students that well-disposed people, even if morally untutored, can be more discerning and have better discretion than are some academicians!) While Zhu stressed making careful observations in situations in order to tailor the most fitting responses in context, at the same time he envisioned a cultivation process whereby one discerns ever more fundamental and yet far-reaching patterns (*li*) that shape nature and moral value. That is, Zhu sometimes construed the project of investigating things to extend knowledge as an ascendant movement whereby the learner finally arrives at the pinnacle--*taiji* (supreme polarity) that embraces and subsumes all derived patterns. To Zhu, grasping *taiji* in this sense was tantamount to grasping the master key, for it represented to him the apex of being and value, and bestowed realization and sagehood on those who sincerely and authentically comprehended and embraced it.[10] While this conception charts an ideal path to the pure, compassionate mind-set of sagehood, it obscures Zhu Xi's usual emphasis on fine-tuning and sharpening one's moral discernment and responsiveness in the midst of things--in full view of the situatedness of people in their daily life. This conception also neglects Zhu's equal emphasis on the claim that patterns as inborn propensities (*xing*) are manifested only in concrete specific *qi* formations, and thus that 1) patterns are to be discerned in their fine particularity, that 2) the moral impulses are to be nurtured in the stream of human life, and that 3) the emotions, when not obscured by desires or obsessions, for the most part are immediate expressions of the basic natural impulses. How, too, to square this broad vision of probing inquiry and deep understanding with the potentially constrictive Confucian moral psychology constructed tightly round the virtues of humaneness, appropriateness, ritual propriety, and wisdom, and their attendant emotions? Zhu Xi likely realized that these virtues functioned as thematic foci for cultivation as one establishes ones moral orientation and bearings and a balanced interpersonal stance. One needs to go through an initial stage of mastering these basic virtues in order to 1) reinforce one's altruistic impulses and curtail the egoistic ones, 2) be inclined to seek principled rapport and harmony in interpersonal affairs, and 3) be moved by a sense of oneness with others and all things. Subsequently, the more ethical human phenomena one observes and considers in advanced level learning and cultivation, the more one feels a broad sympathy for others that transcends the narrowly-graded love, the so-called love with distinctions that is attributed to the notion of *ren* (humaneness) in Confucianism (see *Mencius*, 1A.7, 3A.5, and 7A.45). The more one observes the nuances of human affairs and the springs of human action, the more one will express deference and respect in ways that do not necessarily coincide exactly with the general prescriptions of the norms and ritual actions. In this way, one will build up a repertoire of conduct that reflects one's personal ethical discernment and discretion, which expresses one's personal ethical attainment and style. Zhu Xi on occasion modeled his ethical conception of observing situations and fashioning the most appropriate response naturalistically on the butcher character, Cook Ding, portrayed in the Zhuangzi as a skilled artisan: just as the sure blade of Cook Ding's cleaver goes straight to the cartilage between the bones, the cultivated sense of appropriateness (*yi*) of Zhu Xi's moral adept strikes right at the heart of interpersonal situations (see Thompson 1988: 39-40). A.C. Graham once contrasted Zhu's perception/response model (*gan-ying*) of ethical action with that of Zhuangzi by suggesting that Zhu's notion of appropriate response was informed by rigorous adherence to rules and principles, whereas Zhuangzi's was relatively intuitive and spontaneous (Graham 1986a: 143-145). This apparent contrast can be resolved by separating the stages of cultivation and mastery: Zhuangzi's skilled artisans, such as Butcher Ding, all had to undergo prolonged periods of rigorously controlled apprenticeship before they could "forget" the "knowing that" in an integrated, spontaneous process of "knowing how". For his part, Zhu Xi knew that the years of learning and practice--one's moral apprenticeship--culminates in a responsive moral agent who can operate as intuitively and spontaneously in his or her personal and social ethical sphere as do Zhuangzi's skilled artisans in theirs.[11] Zhu's moral adept is in effect an artisan of interpersonal intercourse. Zhu could rightfully claim Confucius as a prime model for this view. After decades of cultivation, Confucius could say, "At sixty, my ear was attuned. At seventy, I could give my heart free rein and without overstepping the mark" (*Analects* 2.4). Viewed as a quest for knowledge as responsive pattern (*li*) discernment, enhanced by association, analogical reasoning, and generalization, Zhu Xi's approach to inquiry dovetails with recent studies on strategies for learning for effective, ethical living. Neuroscientist and gerontologist Daniel J. Levitin writes concerning intelligence and wisdom, > > Humans excel at... making associations, taking information... and > seeing how it interacts with other information. Whenever we encounter > new information, our brains place it in a conceptual frame and then > seek to associate it with other things we have experienced. The brain > is a giant pattern detector.... Our brains add to that the > ability to form analogies, ... [to perform] analogical > reasoning. The wisdom we find in older adults follow[s] from ... > these four things: association, experience, pattern recognition, and > the use of analogies. And, this is why we we gain more and more wisdom > as we age. Wisdom comes from the accumulated sets of things we've seen > and experienced, our ability to detect patterns in those experiences, > and our ability to predict future outcomes based on them. (And what is > intelligence if not that?) Naturally, the more you have experienced, > the more wisdom you are able to tap into.... [Old-timers] have > been witness to so many things that seem to cycle around again and > again. Wisdom enables you to handle some problems more quickly and > effectively than the raw firepower of youth. [In sum, m]aking > associations underpins learning. To assimilate new information we need > to associate it with what we've seen before. Life experience gives us > more associations to make, more patterns (*li*) to > recognize. (Levitin 2020, pp. 119-120) On the surface, it appears that while Zhu Xi's method of inquiry is specialized and prescriptive, Levitin's presentation is merely descriptive of normal human learning. However, Levitin is describing the optimal learning strategies of people who remain sensitive, alert, discerning, and responsive throughout mature life, traits that some people nurture going forward and that others ought to make efforts to cultivate themselves in order to be more vital, understanding, and effective human actors and lead more fulfilling lives. Zhu Xi's appropriateness approach to ethics has several distinct features. First, one is to be well-versed in the received norms and rituals that circumscribe interpersonal relationships and prescribe proper behavior in family and society. Second, one is to have made ample observations and responses in real life situations. Third, one is to have examined and reflected on ways in which others act and respond in situations, for reference. Fourth, through extensive observation and experience, one is to be cognizant of the range of considerations that come into play in real life situations: moral principle, utility, fairness, sympathy, compassion, and so forth.[12] Fifth, one is to remain flexible and open-minded as well as avoid making surmises, being insistent, stubborn, or self-centered (*Analects* 9.4). According to this view, while observing the ethical norms and rules of thumb in his or her community, the moral adept possesses a store of personal ethical sensitivity, responsiveness, and resourcefulness, by which to fashion the most fitting responses to situations. ### 3.2 Moral Cosmic Synthesis In his watershed essay, *A Treatise on Humanity* (*Renshuo*), Zhu Xi discourses on the classical Confucian teaching of humanity (*ren*) in a unified cosmic and human perspective. In concluding, he criticizes alternative accounts of humanity, i.e., Confucius' spirit of humaneness, on various conceptual and ethical grounds.[13] Following the early Han tradition, Zhu opens by associating humaneness with cosmic creativity. In its most basic manifestation, humaneness is characterized as the impulse of "heaven and earth" (the cosmos) to produce things. By extension, this impulse yields the cycle of seasons and the pervasive fecundity of nature. Advocates of this doctrine had found confirmation in the rich, productive Chinese soil and temperate climate, which supported their assumption that nature was generally fertile and afforded the right conditions for human flourishing. Pervasive, the impulse to produce appears in each and every one of the myriad creatures while in human beings it is refined into the virtue of "humaneness", which, when fully realized, involves one's caring attitude and dedicated responsibility toward others. Zhu Xi moreover correlates "origination, growth, flourishing and firmness", the fourfold initial stages of creativity and production in the cosmos and human nature first mentioned in early commentaries on the *Book of Change*, with humaneness, appropriateness, ritual conduct and wisdom, the four cardinal virtues enunciated by Confucius. Zhu Xi thus portrays the fully cultivated person as at once a complement to heaven and earth, a vital participant in cosmic creativity, and a catalyst for the flourishing and self-realization of others. On this basis, he goes on to formulate the definition of *ren* (humanity, humaneness) for the subsequent tradition: "the essential character of mind" and "the essential pattern of love". The virtue of humaneness thus grounds the disposition of mind as commiserative and describes the core of moral self-realization as love for others (other-directed concern), to be appropriately manifested. In the closing argument of the *Treatise on Humanity*, Zhu Xi stresses that while the stillness and activity phases of the emotions provide emotive stage setting for one's dedicated cultivation, realization, and practice of humaneness, what is crucial is the profound insight that, > > > If one could but truly *practice love and maintain it* (italics > added), one would possess the well-spring of all virtues and the root > of all good deeds. (based on Chan 1963, 212-227, edited) > > > Under this premise, Zhu cites Confucius' advice to Yan Hui, "Master the self by practicing ritual propriety" (*Analects* XII.1). For Zhu Xi, one masters oneself to rein in one's naive self-centeredness by paying ritual respect to others, which in turn spurs a change in the axis of one's moral concern to other people, especially those with whom one is related and daily interacts. What is important, then, is *the moral-ethical axis of one's motivations*. But, how is one to sustain and manifest this humanity consistently in attitude and practice? Zhu Xi does not appeal to philosophic reflection but recommends mindful (*jing*) daily cultivation and practice, i.e., being calm and focused, respectful in personal life, diligent in conducting affairs, and dedicated to upholding interpersonal relations.[14] Moreover, he considers that the emotions play a fundamental role in ethical cultivation and performance. After stressing serving one's parents with filiality and one's elder brother with fraternal respect, Zhu Xi urges: "Be loving in dealing with all things", which goes well beyond standard filtered and restrained "graded" Confucian love. Humaneness is not just a matter of being thoughtful and considerate and paying one's due respect to others ; Zhu Xi underscores the rigors of conducting oneself sincerely and authentically with humaneness, citing Confucius' examples of not only ministers who had declined official posts to maintain their integrity but of times when the exemplary person is willing to sacrifice his or her own life to fulfill humanity (*Analects* 15.8). Nonetheless, the animating spirit of Zhu Xi's *Treatise* remains: "love people gently and benefit things", as reflected in Mencius' four incipient ethical impulses and Confucius' four cardinal virtues.[15] ## 4. Natural Philosophy ### 4.1 Investigating Things for Natural Knowledge and Action While Shao Yong and Cheng Yi in the Northern Song had introduced and sketched out the idea of observation in terms of *guanwu* (observing things), *fanguan* (reflective perception), and *gewu* (investigating things), Zhu Xi not only discussed the idea of observation but offered a multitude of actual observations of celestial and terrestrial phenomena. In addition, his penchant for hierarchy and systemization led modern commentators in the twentieth century to draw comparisons with Plato, Aristotle, and even Thomas Aquinas. Around the mid-twentieth century, Joseph Needham vividly presented Zhu's system in terms of process philosophy as bearing organismic patterns of conceptualization and distinct parallels with scientific thinking: > > > I am prepared to suggest, in view of the fact that the term > *Li* always contained the notion of pattern, and that Chu Hsi > himself consciously applied it so as to include the most living and > vital patterns known to man, that something of the idea of > 'organism' was what was really at the back of the minds of > the Neo-Confucians, and that Chu Hsi was therefore further advanced in > insight into the nature of the universe than any of his interpreters > and translators, whether Chinese or European, have yet given him > credit for. (Needham 1956a: 474) > > > Soon thereafter, after undertaking a careful study of Zhu's dialogues (*Zhuzi yulei*), Hu Shih presented Zhu's method of inquiry, *gewu zhizhi* (investigate things to attain knowledge) as essentially a process of "hypothesis and verification by evidence" (Chan 1989: 566), consistent in spirit with a scientific approach to inquiry. Needham and Hu effectively cast Zhu's thought and method in a new light, as more creative, scientific, holistic, and practical than previously thought. Since then, many have discussed Zhu as a process thinker, but little has been written to consider the extent to which his system could accommodate a scientific worldview, and the extent to which his method of inquiry was consistent with a scientific approach. Yung Sik Kim offers an in-depth inquiry into the extent to which Zhu Xi anticipated genuine scientific methods of observation and conceptualization in *The Natural Philosophy of Chu Hsi* (2000). Zhu from childhood displayed a genuine interest in natural phenomena and in raising speculative questions. Later he tended to rein in this interest, for example by relating features of observed natural phenomena to human analogues for didactic purposes and by refraining from pressing his speculations very far, i.e., beyond the scope of verifiable knowledge and applicability. Zhu lived during a tumultuous period in Chinese history when Neo-Confucian scholars tended to draw upon the resources of their own tradition to revitalize the empire, an effort in which Zhu's *ouvre* constituted a watershed. He sought to wed the objective and subjective trends of the earlier movement into a practical synthesis in which objective inquiry played a key role in subjective cultivation. Subsequently, however, as his disciples refined his thought into a scholastic doctrine, subjective cultivation began to prevail over objective inquiry, which was increasingly redirected into the narrow limits of reading and interpersonal conduct. A Neo-Confucian master of the Ming dynasty, Wang Shouren (Yangming; 1472-1529), spurned Zhu's method of inquiry altogether after he made a futile attempt to observe the *li* (patterning) in the bamboo outside his gate. Holding that facts are obvious to a perceptive observer and do not require endless further investigation, Wang went on to formulate an idealist pragmatism that became influential. Intending to counter the scholasticism and careerism of his day, Wang, a military man, stressed volitionism and activism and spurned the sort of careful objective inquiry Zhu thought necessary to making balanced judgments and appropriate responses. Zhu conceptualized nature and natural phenomena in terms of *li* (pattern, patterning) and *gewu* (the investigation of things), *qi* (primal vapor), *yin-yang*, *wuxing* (five phases), *shu* (number, probability, ratio), *xiang* (images); figures from the *Book of Changes*), ghosts and spirits (*gui-shen*), heaven and the sage (*tian-shengren*), stimulus-response (*ganying*), and transformation and change (*bianhua*). In this context, it was important to treat *li* matter-of-factly as the intrinsic patterning of things and events. While the *li* involved with the identities of things are those facets of intrinsic patterning that pertain to their basic interactive propensities and functions, the *li* of a concrete thing form "a gestalt totality" (Kim 2000), nearly as complex as the thing itself. Thus, whereas scholars tend to take Zhu's assertion that "for a certain (kind of) thing to exist, there first must be that *li*" or "there must be this *li* for there to be that (kind of) thing" as indicative of a metaphysical principle of sufficient reason, in this context *li* simply affirm that things of identifiable kinds bear identifying patterns (*xing*) that make them what they are and interact as they do. *Li* indicate reference points for identities of things that influence their typical patterns of interaction with other things. *Li* thus conceived do not amount to principles of explanation and are more involved with definition, so references to the *li* of phenomena do not add anything cognitive or scientific.[16] At times, Zhu did present the idea of investigating things in chapter 5 of the *Great Learning* (*Daxue*) as involving a step-by-step approach, with an eye to discerning ever higher levels of commonality among the myriad *li* (patterns), aiming at an ultimate comprehension of the most basic form of pattern, *taiji* (supreme polarity). Although this approach lacks the rigor of a logical categorical system, when viewed together with Zhu's comments on Zhou Dunyi's *Diagram of the Supreme Polarity* (*Taiji tu*), it is suggestive for viewing phenomena and forms in a developmental, almost evolutionary context. As Needham comments: > > > Chu Hsi [Zhu Xi] wrote: > > > > > > > > > If one peers into the mystery, the *thai chi* [*taiji*, > > supreme polarity] seems a chaotic and disorderly wilderness lacking > > all signs of an arranger..., yet the *Li* (fundamental > > pattern) of motion and rest, and of Yin and Yang, is fully contained > > within it. > > > > > > > > > > Innumerable smaller organisms were also contained within it, and > indeed composed it. Some of them more highly organized than others. In > fact, the world was no more undifferentiated for the Neo-Confucians > than for modern organic philosophy; it manifested a series of > integrative levels of organization, wholes at one level being parts on > the next. A clear statement of this conception appears in the ninth > paragraph of the *Thai chi Thu Shuo* [Explanation of the > diagram of the supreme polarity], which indicated the inapplicability > of categories outside the level to which they belong. (Needham 1956a: > 466) > > > For Zhu, investigating things to attain knowledge involves arriving at a grasp of their constituent *li*; "knowing" or "understanding" such phenomena, thus, is a matter of grasping their *li*. While Zhu often speaks of knowing or comprehending something in terms of the metaphor of seeing it clearly, of having a clear discernment of it, which is nothing like rigid propositional knowledge, he does recognize several forms or levels of knowing, and regards the basic steps of learning in analytical propositional terms and the higher levels in more synthetic insight terms. That is, one first learns facts about the building blocks of the world and human life, e.g., what things are, what they mean, how they fit together; then, gradually, one gains insights into the broader patterns of relationship and intercourse that comprise the world and human life and that eventually afford sensitive glimpses of the inner root as well as the larger picture. Zhu's discourses are as full of detailed accounts of phenomena as they are of synthetic insights, which should be expected given that Zhu gives equal status and value to the various sorts of qualities that the Western tradition divides into primary (quantitative), secondary (qualitative), and tertiary (qualitative effects). As noted, Zhu drew on notions of *qi, yin-yang*, the five phases, *shu* (numbers, probablilities), and images as conceptual and categorical resources for classifying, characterizing, and understanding the world, especially cycles, processes, and particular things and events. Chinese thinkers, especially during the Han dynasty, used such notions to arrange categories of reality and compile lists of qualities for each category. While some of the associated qualities are directly or causally linked, many of them are arbitrary--perhaps assigned in light of long forgotten events or decrees. These sets of categories were compiled as systematic indices for grasping things and events in terms of categorical associations and imputations. Inevitably, these sets of categories bore a strongly cultural stamp and bias but were applied equally to natural phenomena, as if the natural world were an extension of the human world, not *vice versa*. Zhu often classified a natural phenomenon in terms of these categories and associations, and left it at that, unconcerned that the categories were haphazard and the associations arbitrary and inexplicable. Likely Zhu recognized that these categories and associations often were arbitrary and not particularly informative regarding physical reality but did not find it necessary or practical to pursue the matter. He presumably contented himself with assigning phenomena to these culturally colored sets of categories and associations because in those speech contexts those associations were more significant and interesting than the probing of purely physical categories and explanations would have been. These sorts of examples reflect the cultural common sense and conditions of common speech of his age. The question arises whether these sets of categories and associations were more a help or a hindrance to the development of science in traditional China. On the one hand, their loose criteria and arbitrary design allowed for easy classifications and "accounts" of phenomena that would have stymied serious scientific investigation while, on the other, the associations thus attributed to these phenomena sometimes might have yielded expectations or hypotheses of sorts, thus stimulating further inquiry. Interestingly, Zhu often sidestepped these sets of categories altogether in his serious thinking about natural phenomena and judged them by what he took to be the deciding factors in the cases themselves, often in light of analogies. Striking cases of this are Zhu's discussions on the structure of the cosmos (heaven and earth) and insightful explanations of phases of the moon and eclipses of the sun and moon. For example, Zhu often said that the earth was floating on water; both below the earth and surrounding its four sides were water, but he also said that *qi* surrounded the earth. And, he also spoke of vortices, centrifugal forces, and occasionally of the earth's motion. Zhu was interested in these accounts of the formation of the world, but saw no way to confirm any of them. He perhaps thought it was important to present such accounts as representative of an objective approach to a question that was more amenable to mystical or religious approaches. Zhu's notions of stimulus-response and transformation and change are noteworthy, for they are counterparts to the concepts of causation and change in Western science. Construing phenomena as resonant and sensitive, perhaps perceptive in a rudimentary sense, the notion of stimulus-response reinforces the interdependence of things. Assuming a resonance among things in terms of parallelisms among their forms, and affinities among their *qi*, this notion presents phenomena on a biological model and conduces to an ecological rather than a mechanical outlook. While providing an interactive way of talking about phenomena, it doesn't open the way or impel the inquirer to uncover the nuts and bolts of causation and change. Also, since the idea of stimulus-response was usually tied to the aforementioned sets of categories and associations, it was often vague and applied in arbitrary and superstitious ways. As might be expected, Zhu's notions of transformation and change also reflected biological and human-life models, with transformation indicating gradual change, as in the growth of a child or the passage of summer, and change indicating a sudden transformation, as from a caterpillar to a butterfly or from summer to winter and life to death. From the standpoint of developing science, by making change seem to be natural and inevitable, these notions of transformation and change tended to make further inquiry appear to be unwarranted. In contrast, Western ideas of eternal substance and inert matter, for example, made the observed changes on the earth and in the skies problematic and in urgent need of further inquiry and explanation. More pragmatic in spirit, the Chinese were concerned mainly with registering and grasping the observed patterns and sequences of change in and around them so as to be able to adapt their lives to the ever-changing circumstances. (The *Book of Changes* was a guide to making such adaptations.) Zhu Xi posits an ontological and causal continuity between the celestial and terrestrial realms, as well as between the animal and plant species and humanity. Indeed, there is no categorical difference between human beings and other life forms. Against this backdrop, Zhu carefully observed anomalies and sketched explanations based on the general ideas available to him. For example, when observing fossils of seashells atop a mountain, Zhu noted that the area had once been a seabed and hypothesized that the earth formerly was softer and more fluid and that, through wave motions, this seabed later rose to become a mountain top. Meanwhile, the entire earth dried as it grew older. While this explanation was not rigorous or determinate enough to count as a scientific hypothesis; Zhu appealed only to naturalistic concepts and principles in his comments. Zhu also made quantitative measurements of plant growth. Zhu once heard about a monk's claim that oould see evidence of the nourishing powers of "night vapor" by observing bamboo sprouts, which grow twice as fast at night as during the day. Later, during a stay at a Buddhist residence on Jade Mountain, Zhu observed that the bamboo sprouts there displayed the "same rate of growth day and night, exactly the opposite of the monk's claim". Qian Mu observes that Zhu's practice of *gewu* (investigating things) was fruitful because he made observations with questions or hypotheses in mind, adding that Wang Shouren's observations of bamboo had been fruitless and in vain because he had no question or hypothesis in mind to test. Wang was just undertaking bland looking (Qian 1986: 215f, 219). In contrast to analytical Western concepts used in studying the natural world, including matter, material quality, motion, and change, Zhu Xi adopted a holistic approach to understanding the physical world and phenomena. He drew upon received notions of *li* (pattern) and *qi* (cosmic vapor) to describe and account for the material, dynamic, and formal features of perceived phenomena. *Li* (pattern) refer to the inner patterns of both interaction and identifying form. As noted, *li* are not general overarching principles, but inner patternings implicated in things and events, from the discernible textures--grains in wood, veins in leaves--to the postulated identifying forms, *xing*, of things. In terms of dynamic interaction, *li* structure the primal *yin-yang* intercourse as *taiji*, and the intercourse among the five phases as their constitutive identifying forms. Zhu thus conceived of the cosmos as emerging from incipient *yin-yang* interaction in the initially formless primal *qi* (*yuanqi*). *Yin-yang* interaction and further permutations give rise to the five phases, which bear the full range of material and perceptual qualities and whose interaction gives rise to heaven, earth, and the myriad things, i.e., the cosmos. The Chinese system of five phases differs from traditional Western atomism on several counts. As *qi* (*yin-yang*) operates in essentially a wave-like manner, the world is manifested as a field of interacting *qi* forces. Change is a function of the attunement of forms and resonance of *qi*, and transformation is viewed according to chemical and biological models. That is, not only are the five phases derived from *yin-yang* interaction; they are divisible and inter-convertible. Moreover, while Western atoms bear only primary qualities in themselves, each of the five phases exhibits a range of perceptual qualities and effects, and the tradition attributes a plethora of qualities and associations to *yin* and *yang*. These flexible and adaptable concepts do not create the sorts of problems, the kinds of conflicts with observation, that prompt rethinking and further, more precise investigations of phenomena. Because perceptual properties of all sorts are propagated from the formation of the five phases, Zhu Xi and others in his tradition did not draw the critical distinction between primary and secondary qualities that formed a crucial linchpin in physical analysis in the West from antiquity. To be sure, Zhu spoke of a threshold between perceptible and imperceptible phenomena in terms of the expressions "above forms" (*xing er shang*) and "within forms" (*xing er xia)*. "Above forms" refers not to general principles or primary qualities but essentially to the immanental moral underpinnings of nature and humanity, i.e., the inner roots of order and harmony, ecologically conceived, primary examples of which are *dao* and *li*. Characterizing these fundamental notions as "above forms", Zhu insisted that people needed to comprehend them in light of their manifestations in perceived phenomena "within forms". Lacking the critical distinction between primary and secondary qualities, Zhu treated perceptual qualities, such as color and taste, as equally basic, innate, and real in material substances as any other, and as such he did not look to underlying principles, causes, or mechanisms in terms of which to explain these manifest qualities. Zhu Xi didn't feel the need to formulate a theory of motion as such either, because the factors were glossed in his commonsense grasp of the world and he didn't see any advantage in explicating them. Importantly, he couldn't conceive of their theoretical ramifications or especially of their practical implications, such as for engineering and technology. At the same time, Zhu did have a grasp of inertia and the relativity of motion, keys to solving the problems of motion, but it was not adequate to the task. The capacity to imagine ideal cases and relationships would have been necessary: for example, Galileo had to conceive of the paradigmatic case of motion in terms of an object moving in a straight line on a frictionless plane at a constant velocity, something that can never occur in nature, for any actual object inevitably will be environed and influenced by a variety of forces, such as gravity and friction. Essential, too, was the mathematical plotting of motions in nature that approximate the paradigmatic motions, such as Kepler's plotting of planetary motion and Galileo's plotting of the trajectories of projectiles, to produce precise representations of near-paradigmatic motions. Necessary, too, was an awareness of the possibility of mathematical calculation and precise predictions. Zhu's philosophy involved viewing all things interactively in relative context. If he had had a notion of paradigmatic (perpetual) motion, it would have been something like wave motions in the sea or the cyclical pumping action of the traditional Chinese waterwheel used for irrigation with rising full troughs of water complemented by the falling empty troughs (receptacles), which he had used to depict the *yin-yang* operation of *taiji*. Zhu also lacked the necessary notions of precise mathematicization, measurement, and calculation in terms of which to make the theory of motion bear fruit. Consequently, it is hardly to be expected that Zhu or any one else in his intellectual circle should have had occasion to formulate anything like a scientific theory of motion. Several features of Zhu Xi's thought and his notion of observation discouraged him from forming a genuinely scientific theory or making scientific observations. Zhu was loath to investigate the sorts of fundamental abstract concepts, such as element, compound, infinity, space, time, void, causality, and law, that were necessary for making breakthroughs in the scientific revolution. Because of the Confucian commonsense approach to things, Zhu was disinclined to pursue or investigate such abstract, intangible, and seemingly ephemeral notions. He tended to think that focusing on concepts like void, nothingness, infinity, and space would draw people away from the world of human affairs and ultimately incline them toward pointless introspection. Zhu's concern with the real world itself stymied his investigations into the very abstract concepts necessary for constructing a better grasp of this so-called real world. Zhu Xi had a "particularistic" tendency to investigate each phenomenon on its own terms, without attempting to relate it to more general explanatory principles, as in his treatment of inertia and the relativity of motion. In another case, he discussed the difficulty of boiling rice atop a particular mountain in terms of the characteristics of the *qi* (cosmic vapor) of that mountain, without relating the phenomenon generally to characteristics of *qi* (as air pressure) at high altitudes. Inevitably, this ignoring of general principles made Zhu less sensitive to the contradictions that arose when he offered more than one explanation of a single phenomenon. Why did Zhu Xi go to the trouble of constructing his elaborate system and making and discussing all these observations if they didn't carry him beyond common sense to a deeper and more accurate perception and account of reality, to go beyond the details of particular cases to more general principles and truths? Zhu's ultimate purpose was pragmatic rather than epistemic; that is, he was laying out the concepts, framework, and practices that he deemed most conducive to self-cultivation, self-realization, and ethical practice, rather than formulating objectively accurate concepts, systems, and methods for ascertaining objective truths about the world. So, he did not have a practical interest in pushing his inquiries in purely scientific directions. But, this way of putting it is not completely right because Zhu had considered a variety of philosophic positions and did think he had selected the best and most accurate of the concepts and systems at his disposal. And, he did attempt to render his ideas in a manner that was faithful to reality, the devotion to which was one of his core cultivation themes.[17] Clearly, he did not have the requisite concepts, framework, or style of thinking through which to conceive the world under overarching scientific principles and abstract generalities. Zhu Xi's working concepts and thought were typified by immanental patterns (*li*) rather than by transcendental principles. He regarded reality, the world, not in terms of logical order, but as manifesting aesthetic order. Reality for him was not composed of independent atoms operating under general laws; rather it formed a field in which particulars appeared as foci determined in context. To Zhu, ours is not an absolute, objective universe in which particular individuals are subsumed under generalities and behave according to universal laws; rather, the world unfolds before us in light of our increasing, expanding perception of the arrays of particular phenomena around us. The world we experience is a function of, a field manifested as, the tapestry formed through the resonance among the foci making up that field. Consequently, the task of investigating things is a process of unfolding (rather than an inductive process), an exhausting of the *li* constituting particular things and events, from their gestalt forms, such as the symmetrical bilateral forms of most biological entities, to their identifying forms to their functions and typical patterns of interaction. Proceeding in this way, we seek not the most general laws or principles governing particular atomic individuals, but rather the most basic or common patterns of interaction and formation among particulars as foci in fields. Consequently, for example, the ultimate pattern in Zhu's thought, *taiji*, the supreme polarity, is not an abstract ideal like a platonic form or a law of nature; it is an immanental pattern that is realized ubiquitously but distributively, not overarchingly or generally. Zhu was not working toward a scientific conception of the world, of reality, as constituted on general principles and abstract equations; he was traversing an alternative route by eliciting the formations of things and events in ecological context in a way that would open one's mind to the intimate resonance and intercourse among particulars as foci in fields. At the same time, by stressing the expression "*gewu qiongli*" (investigate things to exhaust their *li*), Zhu maintained a measure of analyticity in his insights to ensure that the knowledge people gleaned was nuanced and textured enough to contribute to life understanding and appropriate conduct. ### 4.2 Philosophic Synthesis Zhu Xi erected a philosophical synthesis that has been compared broadly to the systems of Plato, Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas, Whitehead, and others. These "Great Chain" systems are hierarchical and rooted in the distinction between form and matter. Recent immanental readings of Zhu Xi's thought have stirred comparisons with Spinoza and even Husserl (Choi 1999; Yeo 2013). Zhu Xi preserved the immanental character of his hierarchy by incorporating Zhou Dunyi's conception of world (and self) as shown in the *Diagram of the Supreme Polarity* (*Taiji tu*), as a way to combine the Cheng brothers' concept of *li* (pattern) with Zhang Zai's notion of *qi* (cosmic vapor) as organically integrated in a holistic system. In Zhou's treatise, *Explanation of the Diagram of the Supreme Polarity* (*Taiji tu shuo*) (Adler 2014), Zhu discerned a viable account of the formation of the world in stages from the original unformed *qi*, to *yin* and *yang*, the five phases, earth, wood, fire, water, and metal, and on to heaven, earth and the ten thousand things. Zhu blended this conception with ideas from the *Book of Change* and its commentaries in setting forth a comprehensive philosophy of cosmic and human creativity and providing philosophical grounds for the received Confucian concepts of human nature and self-cultivation. Zhu Xi's penchant for thinking in polarities, *li* and *qi*, in particular, has continued to stir critics to regard him as a dualist who used two fundamental concepts to explain reality. For his part, any viable account of the complexity of phenomena must involve two or more facets in order to register their complexity, variety, and changes. Zhu generalized the organic understanding of *li* and *qi* implied in Zhou Dunyi's *Explanation* under a principle of complementarity, inspired by Cheng Hao's observation that all things have their complement (discussed in the next section). At first, Zhu thought this principle only governed *qi* phenomena as patterned by *li*, but eventually he admitted that not only were *yin* and *yang* paradigmatic polar complements but that the supreme polarity (*taiji*) complemented the *yin-yang* polarity, and inferred that *li* and *qi*, as the references of *taiji* and *yin-yang*, respectively, too had to be complements. This meant that *li* and *qi* were functionally on a par and mutually implicative. Zhu still felt the need to prioritize *li* ontologically and ethically, however, for the reason that *li* underwrites both the possibility of *qi* ordering (to yield a world and phenomena) and the possibility of moral feelings and norms (to yield ethics and a system of rites). Treating *li* and *qi* as full ontological complements would quite possibly entail a Daoist conception of nature as pure spontaneity and ethics as just perspectival while prioritizing *qi* over *li* would be inadequate for understanding the world and phenomenal orders, and reduce ethics to the received norms. ## 5. Complementarity between *li* and *qi*, and among related terms Recognizing *li* and *qi* as complements serves to underscore their unity in difference and their implicatedness in not just the forms but in the flow of events comprising the world.[18] This complementary relationship, moreover, underscores the basic holism and power of Zhu's thought regarding the formation of the world and things. Zhu Xi was inspired by Cheng Hao's formulation of the principle of complementarity, which he placed prominently in sec. 1 of the authoritative Neo-Confucian anthology, *Reflections on Things at Hand* (par. 25): > > > Master Cheng Hao said: The *li* of heaven, earth and the myriad > things is that nothing exists in isolation; everything certainly has > its opposite/complement. This is spontaneously so and not artificially > arranged. When I reflect on this truth late at night, I feel delighted > as if my hands were waving and my feet were dancing. (based on Chan > 1967, edited) > > > Zhu Xi regarded this complementary pattern as describing the most fundamental ordering tendency of cosmos, phenomena, and self. Notably, this is *li* (pattern) in a new sense, now more as a *pattern of creative intercourse* than just as inherent patterning or order. It generalizes the significance of *taiji*, though it *prima facie* lacks *taiji*'s insistent implication of *li* into *qi* intercourse and derived phenomena. Zhu remarks that Cheng Hao felt delighted about his insight into this *li* because, > > > Once he had grasped deeply the truth that, "nothing exists in > isolation but certainly has its opposite/complement," it seemed > to him marvelous and joyous. (based on Chan 1967, edited) > > > *Zhuzi yulei* (Classified Dialogues of Master Zhu), *juan* 95, contains Zhu's discussions with students on this Cheng Hao quotation. As mentioned, Zhu usually construes this as a *li* pattern underlying the complementary relationships among *qi* phenomena, which *li* itself transcends, hence implying a vertical bifurcation between *li* and *qi*. When a disciple asks Zhu whether the complements have to be "things" or whether, "*Li* too could have a complement?" The Master replies, > > > As to the categories of above and below, small and great, clear and > turbid, they also pertain to *things*. But, if we were to say, > "having the above, there must be the below; having the large, > there must be the small", that would be purely a matter of > *li*, that is to say it *has to be* like this, as a sort > of logical necessity. For example, in nature's production of > things, there cannot only be *yin*, there must also be > *yang*; there cannot only be *yang*, there must also be > *yin*. These [*yin* and *yang*] are mutual > complements. The contexts of these complements are not themselves > complementary *li*. Rather, the *li* are the very reason > by which there are these complements. (trans. by the author) > > > Zhu also applies this *li* pattern creatively to number, speech, objects, and games. According to this pattern, "One complements two", "above forms" complements "within forms". Any word will bear its semantic complement within.[19] And, this object before your eyes has its complements of back, front, top, and bottom. Moreover, each side has its complement.... Any single thing bears its complement within.[20] For example, the paths on a checkerboard form series of complementary pairs. In the end, when only one path remains open and it seems that no other complement remains, this very path still complements the 360 other paths.[21] This is called a 'one-many complement', like the 'Way-implement complement' (*Zhuzi yulei*, *juan* 95). At the same time, Zhu hesitates to accept that *li* and *qi* themselves are complementary, but this primarily reflects his ethical concerns.[22] On the ontological side, he eventually does affirm that *li* and *qi* are complementary by saying: > > > As to what would be the complement of *taiji*, it is said that > *taiji* is *wuji* (free of polarity).... > *Taiji* also complements *yin-yang*.... [Regarding] > the Way above forms and... utensil within forms... these are > '*horizontal* oppositions'.... (trans. by the > author) > > > This is just like, > > > Having the tranquility of the pre-aroused emotions of pleasure and > anger, grief and joy, there is the harmony of these emotions when > aroused in due degree. (trans. by the author) > > > *Taiji* and *wuji* are opposed, apparently contradictory, expressions. Signifying the most basic complementarity, namely, that between *yin* and *yang*, *taiji* is the most primitive and original form of *li.* It is quintessential *li*, or elementary form (patterning). Signifying something unbounded and free of polarity, *wuji* describes the unformed primal *qi* whence *yin* and *yang* emerge through the *taiji* impulse. It is quintessential *qi*, pure potentiality. Hence, Zhou Dunyi's proposition, "*Wuji er taiji*" (Free from polarity, and yet the supreme polarity), expresses the identity of opposites (*li* and *qi*) that gives rise to the initial impulse of phenomena.[23] In the next step of this impulse, *yin* and *yang* are formed. They complement *taiji* as pure energy to pure form, thus expressing another dimension of the *li-qi* complementarity. Although the distinction between "above forms" and "within forms" does not strictly mark the distinction between *li* and *qi*; nevertheless, as the way is *correlated with li,* and implement is embodied *qi*, their "*horizontal* complementarity" implies a similar pattern for *li* and *qi*. Strikingly, whereas those who take this above-below forms distinction as "metaphysical" and "physical" would have to describe the opposition as "*vertical*", Zhu says plainly that it is *horizontal*, thus imputing a closer, more interactive relationship between these complements than could obtain had their relationship been strictly vertical. A final reason why Zhu Xi's ideas of *li* and *qi* ought to be taken as horizontal and not vertical complements, that is, as a complex unity and not as a metaphysical duality, is found when Zhu makes two seemingly contradictory claims about *li* and *qi*: (1) *Li* is prior to *qi.* 2) *Li* is not present apart from *qi* formations. Whereas 1) is usually regarded as a positive metaphysical claim, it means rather that *li* in this sense refers to "permanent possibilities of *qi* formation". For example, for any particular *qi* formation to have come about, it had to have been possible for the *qi* constituents to combine in that particular way to yield those properties and capacities.[24] Whereas (2) is often taken to mean that *li* subsist until instantiated, it means rather that *li* are the patterning of real processes and things; they exist immanently in processes and things, though they can be analyzed and discussed separately from their real contexts. This is why, methodologically, Zhu insists that learners acquaint themselves with the *li* of things, processes, affairs, ethics, etc., by examining actual things, processes, phenomena, etc. He regards the study of *li* in abstraction from phenomena to be wooden, hollow, empty, etc. Hence, Zhu's claims (1) and (2) and his methodological strategy all indicate that, for him, the relation of complementarity between *li* and *qi* is essentially horizontal. The "*li*" pattern in the Cheng Hao quotation thus turns out to be a "meta-*li*" *about* the dynamic *li-qi* complements that originate and comprise the world and its constituents, that is, as a second-order abstraction from the *li* and *qi* that are actually implicated in phenomena. Again, this meta-*li* confirms the basic unity and dynamism of Zhu's *li-qi* system. It reveals the pulse of life at the heart of *li* and affirms the possibilities of form in the vagaries of *qi* movement. It enlivens Zhu's system and makes it flexible and conceptually adaptable to experience and thinking. We may reflect that Zhu's original notion of *li* as pattern involves restrictions that conflict with experience or expression, so he reconfigures it in light of Zhou Dunyi's *Explanation of the Diagram of the Supreme Polarity* and the Cheng Hao quotation.[25] To work as intended, *li* has to tolerate and express simultaneous assertions of "contradictory" complementary terms. At the same time, this reconfiguration marks a step away from primarily immanental aesthetic pattern of the *li* conception to a more abstract, more self-consciously meta-pattern. ## 6. Major Interpreters of Zhu Xi Zhu Xi was an active scholar-intellectual who held discussions and disputes with other scholars, both in correspondence and in person. His thought can be understood by contrast with the thought of his intellectual rivals as well as through his positive views. For example, his series of letters with Zhang Shi on the topic of self-cultivation and moral psychology, preserved in the *Collected Writings of Master Zhu* (*Zhuzi wenji*), provides an illuminating record of these two dedicated Confucians' quest for a well-grounded, efficacious approach to self-cultivation. He debated with Lu Zuqian (1134-1181) on the nature of education. Zhu focused on the Confucian Way and moral practice in education while Lu argued for a broader-based humanities approach. Zhu held a series of debates with Lu Jiuyuan (Xiangshan: 1139-93) on the nature of realization and moral conduct. Whereas Zhu advocated regimens of study, reflection, observation, and practice, Lu spoke simply of reflecting on self and clarifying the mind, considering that once the mind was clear one would know spontaneously what to do in any situation. Zhu also corresponded with the "utilitarian" Confucian scholar Chen Liang (1143-94), who disputed Zhu's focus on individual moral realization and the received "Way" with a broader institutional approach that was more sensitive to empirical facts and conditions. Zhu generally eclipsed all of the other scholars of his day, partly because he outlived them and had so many students but mainly because his system was so compelling. It was comprehensive yet nuanced, tightly reasoned yet accommodating of individual differences. It preserved the essential Confucian Way, yet ramified it to meet the challenges of Buddhism and Daoism as spiritual teachings. Zhu's influence rose at the end of the Southern Song dynasty and became decisive during the Yuan dynasty when his edition of the *Four Books* was adopted as the basis of the imperial examination system arranged by scholars trained in his approach. While raising his standing in pedagogy, this focus on the *Four Books* came at the expense of Zhu's deeper, more nuanced texts and dialogues, and opened the door to undue philosophic criticism. The schematic presentation of Zhu's broad theory of *li* pattern and *qi* cosmic vapor that lay in the background of his commentary to the *Four Books* easily opened him to charges of dualism and of reading abstract categories into the down to earth, essentially practical ancient texts. Because his commentary was focused on reading and understanding the meaning, intent, and cultivation message of the *Four Books,* critics generalized that Zhu and his method were essentially scholastic and would be myopic and stilted in facing real situations. Anyone who peruses the corpus of Zhu's writings and dialogues, however, will find that his ontology is not a crude dualism but a holism built of complementary, mutually implicative elements that never exist in separation. Also, his reflections are always informed by knowledge of history, current events, practical observation, and personal reflection, as his method of observation applies generally to objects (and self) and phenomena while respecting texts, which he took to be handbooks of ethical insight and practice, after all. Even Zhu's comments on Confucius and Mencius often refer back to the person and the speech context, and thus are not entirely scholastic. His method of observation opened the door to breakthroughs beyond the "verities" of the classics, though he was careful not to play up this fact because most of his intellectual colleagues primarily sought the truth in the texts, thinking empirical facts were distractions from the essential Natural-patterning (*tianli*) that was reflected most adequately in the canonical texts. Whereas early generations of Zhu's followers were acquainted with his broad learning, incisive style, and open spirit, Confucians of the Ming and Qing dynasties knew him mostly through his edition of the *Four Books*, through which they targeted their criticisms of his thought. Zhu's most eminent critic was the Ming scholar-official Wang Yangming (1472-1529). He rejected Zhu's approach to observation as too objective and open-ended, as outward and diffuse and neglectful of concentration and inwardness. It could be said that, in his criticisms, Wang was reacting more to the scholastic attitudes fostered by the examination system than to Zhu Xi himself. Wang ultimately respected Zhu and went on to compile a text in which he argued that, in later life, Zhu's thought had taken a a subjective, practical turn that anticipated Wang's approach. Scholars of the late Ming through the early Qing period (mid-seventeenth to early eighteenth century), notably, Wang Fuzhi (1619-92) and Dai Zhen (Tai Chen, 1723-77), disputed Zhu on philosophical and textual grounds. Whereas Zhu had allegedly insisted on the priority of "pattern" over *qi*, (roughly, form over matter), Wang and Dai followed the Northern Song thinker Zhang Zai in affirming the priority of *qi*, viewing patterns as *a posteriori* evolutionary realizations of *qi* interactions. They thought this account dissolved the threat of any hint of dualism in cosmology, ontology, and human nature. For his part, Zhu Xi would have responded that, fundamentally, "pattern" is implicated in the very make-up and possible configurations of *qi*, which is why the regular *a posteriori* patterns can emerge. *Li* "patterning" provides for the standing orders and processes, based on the steady interactions of *yin-yang*, five phases, etc., that give rise to the heaven-earth world order, with its full complement of ten thousand things. The fundamental *a priori* patterns are necessary to the world order and provide the fecund context in which the *a posteriori* forms emerge continuously. Wang and Dai's *qi*-based view could not account for existence and the variegated yet systematic given world order in this sense. At the same time, Zhu did not think that "patterns" were absolutely determinative. They just set certain "possibilities of order" that are realized when the necessary *qi* conditions obtained. For the most part, he registered the range of randomness and free flow in *qi* activity that is best exemplified in the randomness of weather systems and seismic events. As to textual grounds, Wang and Dai argued that Zhu was so enamored of his metaphysics of pattern and *qi* that he constantly read them into the classical texts. For example, Dai said Zhu blandly associated Confucius' term *tian* (heaven) with his own notion of *li* (pattern), quoting *Analects* 11:9 where Confucius, in sorrow over the death of his disciple Yan Hui, cried that "Heaven has forsaken me". Da questioned how Zhu Xi could reasonably claim that Confucius was crying that *li* had forsaken him? Critics tend to find this counter-intuitive example of Dai's against Zhu's approach to be compelling. However, consulting Zhu's original commentary, we find that he noted that this phrase was not literally about heaven but rather expressed Confucius' utmost sorrow, that Confucius felt Yan Hui's death as if it was his own son's, without mentioning "pattern". This example does not support Wang and Dai's claim in the least. It illustrates that Zhu's commentary was nuanced and sensitive to pragmatic, situational usages despite his penchant to see his own notion of "pattern" in some of Confucius' usages of "heaven". Moreover, as the intellectual historian Daniel Gardner shows, Zhu's commentary was not intended as simply a glossary with comments. It was intended as a guide to self-cultivation. Hence, Zhu sometimes recast passages in the *Analects* more generally to show their broader implications for self-cultivation and realization, often with the isolated countryside student in mind. Gardner shows how Zhu had effectively enriched the text as a tool for self-cultivation whereas earlier commentaries of the Han and Tang dynasties had just given glosses necessary for answering examination questions. Known in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries in the West through the work of Jesuits in China, Zhu Xi's thought and texts were made more widely available to western scholarship in the late nineteenth century. Notably, James Legge (1815-1897) based his translations of the Chinese Classics on Zhu Xi's commentaries, which he quoted and discussed at length in his footnotes to the texts. Early in the twentieth century, a Chinese student of John Dewey (1859-1951) at Cornell, Hu Shi (1891-1962), initially followed the empirical, textual Qing scholars in viewing Zhu as a scholastic metaphysician. But, after reading Zhu's *Dialogues* for himself in old age, Hu contended that Zhu's method of observation was not scholastic but essentially scientific in nature. J.P. Bruce, who translated a book of Zhu's collected writings in the 1920s, viewed Zhu's notion of *li* (pattern; principle) in light of Stoic natural law. From the 1930s, the eminent historian of Chinese philosophy, Feng Youlan, interpreted *li* along the lines of platonic Forms making Zhu Xi appear to be an idealist and abstract thinker. In the 1950s, Carsun Chang naturalized the notion of *li* by aligning it with the Aristotelian "nature" or "essence", thereby locking Zhu's thought into a sort of rigid descriptive metaphysics. From the 1960s, Mou Zongsan interpreted and criticized Zhu's ontology and ethics on Kantian grounds, claiming Zhu had erected an *a priori* framework but then illicitly sought to derive further *a priori* knowledge (of patterns) by *a posteriori* means (observation). In the 1970s, the intellectual historian, Qian Mu examined and explained Zhu Xi's thought directly in traditional indigenous terms, without reading western concepts and logical patterns into his system. Scholars wanting to read Zhu Xi on his own terms, largely unmediated by western thought, turn to the five volume Zhu Xi anthology edited by Qian Mu as a rich starting point. In 1956, Joseph Needham, a chemist, made a significant breakthrough by interpreting Zhu's system in terms of a process philosophy, Whitehead's organic naturalism. Needham successfully recast much of Zhu's language in naturalistic rather than metaphysical terms. The cultural, moral dimension of Needham's account has been developed by Cheng-ying Cheng and John Berthrong while the scientific dimension has been examined by Yung Sik Kim. In the 1980s, A.C. Graham offered the most insightful and apt account of Zhu's terminology and pattern of thought in, "What Was New in the Ch'eng-Chu Theory of Human Nature?" and other writings. Graham showed decisively that the term *li* refers to an embedded contextual "pattern", rather than to any sort of abstract form or principle. He reminded us that the term *li* never figures in propositions or logical sequences, as would be natural for "principle". Rather, *li* are always conceived as structuring, balancing, modulating, guiding phenomena, processes, reflection and human discernment and response. For example, one never finds moral syllogisms in Zhu Xi's writings. Many of Zhu's discussions thus concern moral emotional intelligence: attunement, sensitivity, discernment, and response. Joseph Adler views *li* as indicative of an "ordering" tendency that may be manifested as "pattern" or as "principle" in differing contexts. (We might say that people devise principles in the light of observed patterns.) Adler also examines the key roles played by the *Book of Change* and Zhou Dunyi in the formation of Zhu's thought, and joins Thomas Wilson and Hoyt Tillman in showing the extent to which Zhu Xi re-visioned, revised, and recast the Confucian Way. Adler shows how Zhu Xi made Zhou Dunyi a pivotal figure in the succession of the Confucian Way while Wilson is interested in Zhu's account of the Way as a sort of educational-ideological revision, and Tillman is interested in how Zhu's account of the Way eventually outlasted other competing versions that might have offered more practical and liberal openings in late imperial China. Advances continue to be made in Zhu Xi studies in the present century. On the one hand, intellectual historians, such as Yingshi Yu, examine Zhu Xi's historical, political, and cultural backgrounds, as well as his intellectual milieu. Other intellectual historians, such as Hoyt Tilman and Hans van Ess study Zhu Xi's intellectual collaborators and rivals. Still others, such as Chun-chieh Huang and his colleagues examine the differing receptions and adaptations of Zhu Xi's thought by Confucian scholars around East Asia. On the other hand, philosophical interpreter Brook Ziporyn has developed a "coherence" reading of *li* (pattern). Drawing on the parallel model of *li* and *shi* in Huayan Buddhism, he views Zhu Xi's *li* as the organizing, cohering element in *qi* phenomena, writ large and small. Given the intimate connection between *li* and truth in Zhu Xi's thought, the coherence account of *li* recalls the coherence theory of truth in 20th century Western philosophy. While "coherence" is an apt and suggestive account of the organizing and cohering function of *li*, it cannot serve as a direct translation of the term *li*. Ethicists, such as Stephen Angle, Yong Huang, and Justin Tiwald examine Confucian ethics in general and Zhu Xi's ethics in particular as species of virtue ethics, as conceived in recent Anglo-American ethical thought. They have identified overlaps and similarities between these ethical approaches. Other scholars, such as Ming-huei Lee and the present author have identified Kantian elements in Zhu Xi's efforts to justify Confucian ethics and cultivation. Finally, Shui Chuen Lee and others find support in Zhu Xi's system of thought for a viable Confucian approach to environmental ethics. In summary, the depth and range of Zhu Xi's thought were unparalleled in the Chinese intellectual tradition and around East Asia. Zhu Xi studies globally continue to be vital, wide-ranging, and contentious, and continue to attract increasing interest around the world.
zombies
## 1. The idea of zombies Descartes held that non-human animals are automata: their behavior is wholly explicable in terms of physical mechanisms. But human behavior (he argued) could not be explained like that. Exploring the idea of a machine that would look and behave like a human being, he thought two things would unmask it: it could not use language creatively, and it could not produce appropriate non-verbal behavior in arbitrarily various situations (*Discourse V*). For him, therefore, no machine could behave like a human being. Knowing only seventeenth century technology, he concluded that to explain distinctively human behavior required something beyond the physical: an immaterial mind, interacting with processes in the brain and the rest of the body. (Importantly, he also had *a priori* arguments for the same conclusion, one of which anticipates the 'conceivability argument' discussed in Section 3 below.) If he is right, there could not be a world physically like the actual world but lacking such minds: human bodies would not work properly. If we suddenly lost our minds our bodies might continue to run on for a while: our hearts might continue to beat, we might breathe while asleep and digest food; we might even walk or sing in a mindless sort of way (so he implies in his *Reply to Objections IV*). But without the contribution made by minds, behavior could not show characteristically human features. So although Descartes did everything short of spelling out the idea of zombies, the question of their possibility did not arise for him. The nearest thing was automata whose behavior was easily recognizable as not fully human. In the nineteenth century scientists began to think that physics was capable of explaining all physical events that were explicable at all. It seemed that every physical effect has a physical cause: that the physical world is 'closed under causation'. The developing science of neurophysiology was set to extend such explanations to human behavior. But if human behavior is explicable physically, how does consciousness fit into the story? One response -- physicalism (or materialism) -- is to insist that consciousness too involves only physical processes. However, the phenomena of consciousness are hard to account for in those terms, and some thinkers concluded with Descartes that something nonphysical must be involved. Given they accepted the causal closure of the physical, they were forced to conclude that consciousness has no effects on the physical world. On this view human beings are 'conscious automata', as T. H. Huxley put it: all physical events, human behavior included, are explicable in terms of physical processes; and the phenomena of consciousness are causally inert by-products -- epiphenomena (see James 1890, Chapter 5). It eventually became clear that this view entailed there could be purely physical organisms exactly like us except for lacking consciousness. G. F. Stout argued that if epiphenomenalism (the more familiar name for the 'conscious automaton' theory) is true, > > it ought to be quite credible that the constitution and course of > nature would be otherwise just the same as it is if there were not and > never had been any experiencing individuals. Human bodies would still > have gone through the motions of making and using bridges, telephones > and telegraphs, of writing and reading books, of speaking in > Parliament, of arguing about materialism, and so on. There can be no > doubt that this is *prima facie* incredible to Common Sense > (Stout 1931: 138f.). > What Stout describes here and finds *prima facie* incredible is a zombie world: an entire world whose physical processes are closed under causation (as the epiphenomenalists he was attacking held) and exactly duplicate those in the actual world, but where there are no conscious experiences. Similar ideas were current in discussions of physicalism in the 1970s. As a counterexample to the psychophysical identity theory there was an 'imitation man', whose 'brain-states exactly paralleled ours in their physico-chemical properties' but who felt no pains and saw no colors (Campbell 1970). Zombies were put forward as a counterexample to physicalism in general, and arguments devised to back up the intuition that they are possible (Kirk 1974a, 1974b). However, these arguments fell short of their target because they depended on much the same cluster of intuitions as the original idea. Other kinds of systems were envisaged which behaved like normal human beings, or were even functionally like human beings, but lacked the 'qualia' we have (Block 1980a, 1980b, 1981; Shoemaker 1975, 1981). (Roughly, qualia are the properties by which we classify experiences according to 'what they are like': what it is like to smell roasting coffee beans, for example. Even physicalists can use this expression, although unlike dualists they take qualia to be physical.) The most systematic use of the zombie idea against physicalism is by David Chalmers 1996, whose important contributions to the debate will be considered shortly. If zombies are to be counterexamples to physicalism, it is not enough for them to be behaviorally and functionally like normal human beings: plenty of physicalists accept that merely behavioral or functional duplicates of ourselves might lack qualia. Zombies must be like normal human beings in *all* physical respects, and they must have the physical properties that physicalists suppose we have. This requires them to be subject to the causal closure of the physical, which is why their supposed lack of consciousness is a challenge to physicalism. If instead they were to be conceived of as creatures whose behavior could not be explained physically, physicalists would have no reason to bother with the idea: there is plenty of evidence that, as epiphenomenalists hold, our movements actually are explicable in physical terms (see e.g. Papineau 2002). The usual assumption is that none of us is actually a zombie, and that zombies cannot exist in our world. The central question, however, is not whether zombies can exist in our world, but whether they, or a whole zombie world (which is sometimes a more appropriate idea to work with), are possible in some broader sense. ## 2. Zombies and physicalism A metaphor of Saul Kripke's helps to show how the zombie idea threatens physicalism (Kripke 1972/80, 153f.). Imagine God creating the world and deciding to bring into existence the whole of the purely physical universe. Having created this physical universe, did he have to do any more work to provide for consciousness? Answering yes to this question implies there is more to consciousness than the physical facts alone can supply. If nothing else, it implies that consciousness depends at least partly on nonphysical properties, ones that would not exist in a purely physical world; it would be a zombie world. Physicalists, on the other hand, are committed to answering no. They have to say that by fixing the purely physical facts, God did everything necessary to fix the mental facts about the organisms thereby created, including their thoughts, feelings, emotions, and experiences. In other words, it seems that physicalists must say that in some sense the purely physical truths entail the mental truths (Kirk 1974a, 1974b argued that physicalism requires an 'Entailment Thesis' to that effect). If indeed fixing the physical facts alone is enough to fix the mental facts, then a zombie world is impossible. Not everyone agrees that physicalism entails the impossibility of zombies. One suggestion is that physicalists can concede there are possible worlds which are exact duplicates of our world in all purely physical respects, but where the physical properties which give rise to consciousness in our world are prevented from doing so by nonphysical items which block consciousness. That would let physicalists consistently allow the possibility of zombie worlds (Leuenberger 2008. On such 'blockers' see Hawthorne 2002b; Chalmers 2010, 163-165). This approach, however, is inconsistent with maintaining that actual conscious states are either identical with or constituted by physical or functional states. If my conscious state is the same as or constituted by a physical state, then there is no possible world where the latter exists without the former. It is therefore not clear that physicalists can consistently allow the possibility of consciousness-blockers. Lei Zhong 2021 takes a very different approach, challenging the widely held view that physicalism commits one to the supervenience of the mental on the physical. But what kind of impossibility is relevant here? Physicalists cannot just say zombies are ruled out by the laws of nature, since even dualists can agree they are impossible in that sense: that it is by *nomological* necessity that the physical facts about us bring consciousness with them. Physicalism therefore needs something stronger. Two further kinds of necessity are usually considered: logical and metaphysical. Now, many philosophers (largely influenced by the zombie idea) believe the connection from physical facts to consciousness cannot be logical even in a broad sense. And certainly the conceptual scheme of physics does not *appear* to leave room for logical links from physical to phenomenal (see e.g. Kriegel 2011; Stoljar 2006). However, some argue that nevertheless zombies are not really conceivable at all (Kirk 2005, 2008, 2013; Tye 2006); Kirk 2013 also maintains that although the physical facts do not entail the truth about conscious experience *a priori*, they nevertheless entail it by logical necessity. Still, many physicalists hold that what guarantees the impossibility of zombies is 'metaphysical' necessity. Typically they maintain that states of phenomenal consciousness are identical with physical states, and that these identities are necessary a posteriori as argued by Kripke (see e.g. McLaughlin 2005, and for criticism, Stoljar 2000). But the vocabulary of possibility and necessity is slippery. For example there is disagreement over whether logical and metaphysical possibility are different (section 3.1 below); when Kripke (1972/80) writes of 'logical' and 'metaphysical' possibility he seems to use those words interchangeably (Yablo 1999: 457n.), and some use 'logical' where others prefer 'conceptual' (Chalmers 1999: 477); compare Latham 2000, 72f.). Many think that if the physical facts entail consciousness by metaphysical necessity, then physicalists can maintain that even though zombies are metaphysically impossible, they are still *conceivable* (Balog 2012; Loar 1990/97; McLaughlin 2005; Sections 5.1, 5.2 below). To the contrary, Chalmers argues that conceivability actually entails metaphysical possibility. If he is right, then that popular brand of physicalism is mistaken. The so-called 'conceivability argument' for the possibility of zombies will provide a focus for discussing some of the main problems raised by the zombie idea. ## 3. The conceivability argument for the possibility of zombies The simplest version of this argument goes: 1. Zombies are conceivable. 2. Whatever is conceivable is possible. 3. Therefore zombies are possible. (Kripke used a similar argument in his 1972/80. For versions of it see Chalmers 1996, 93-171; 2010, 141-205; Levine 2001; Nagel 1974; Stoljar 2001. Michael Pelczar (2021) argues for the same conclusion without appealing to conceivability.) Clearly the conceivability argument is valid. However, both its premisses are problematic. They are unclear as stated, and controversial even when clarified. A key question is how we should understand 'conceivable' in this context. Many philosophers are willing to concede that zombies are conceivable in some sense (e.g. Hill 1997; Hill and McLaughlin 1999; Loar 1999; Yablo 1999). However, that sense is sometimes quite broad. For example, a claim that 'there are no substantive a priori ties between the concept of pain and the concept of C-fiber stimulation' has been backed up by the point that 'it is in principle possible to master either of these concepts fully without having mastered the other' (Hill 1997, 76). By that standard, though, it would be conceivable that the ratio of a circle's circumference to its diameter is a rational number, when it isn't. If conceivability in that sense entailed possibility, it would be both possible and impossible for the ratio to be rational; which would make such conceivability useless for the purposes of the conceivability argument. So understood, premiss (1) would be easy to swallow; but (2) would have to be rejected. Evidently, the lower the threshold for conceivability, the easier it is to accept (1) -- but the harder it is to accept (2). So the kind of conceivability invoked in premisses (1) and (2) needs to be strongly constrained. A common and useful definition, which will be followed here, is: *something is conceivable if and only if it cannot be ruled out a priori.* (For sophistication of these and related ideas see Chalmers 1999, 477; 2002; 2007; 2010; and 5.1 below.) Joseph Levine discusses a version of the conceivability argument, seeing the conceivability of zombies as 'the principal manifestation of the explanatory gap' (2001: 79). In his view, what creates this gap is the *epistemological* problem of explaining how the phenomenal is related to the physical. He sees no way to solve this problem, and thinks it remains even if zombies are impossible. Campbell, Copeland and Deng 2017 argue that, quite generally, for any conceivability argument there is a corresponding 'mirror argument' which can be rejected only at the cost of undermining the main argument, and conclude that all conceivability arguments are 'logically bankrupt'. We now face two key questions: Are zombies conceivable in the sense explained? If they are conceivable, does it follow that they are possible? Only if the answer to both questions is yes will the conceivability argument succeed. We can take them in that order. ## 4. Are zombies conceivable? Those who exploited the zombie idea in the 1970s typically assumed without argument that zombies are not just conceivable but possible (e. g. Campbell 1970, Nagel 1970). When Chalmers reactivated the idea he found the conceivability of zombies 'obvious', remarking that 'it certainly seems that a coherent situation is described; I can discern no contradiction in the description' (1996, p. 96). However, he also recognized that this intuition cannot be relied on. The nature of conscious experience is after all hard to understand: what strikes some people as obviously possible could still turn out to harbour hidden contradictions (Nagel 1998; Stoljar 2001). Clearly, those who maintain that zombies are conceivable must provide justification, recognizing that, being an epistemic claim dependent on our cognitive abilities, it is defeasible. ### 4.1 Arguments for the conceivability of zombies Chalmers (1996) set out five arguments against the view that there is an *a priori* entailment from physical facts to mental facts -- and so *for* the view that zombies are conceivable. Each argument would directly or indirectly reinforce the intuitive appeal of the zombie idea. The first will be considered shortly; the other four appeal respectively to the alleged possibility of 'inverted spectrum' without physical difference; the alleged impossibility of learning about conscious experience on the basis of purely physical information; Jackson's (1982) 'knowledge argument' (related to the last); and what Chalmers calls 'the absence of analysis': the point being that his opponents 'will have to give us some idea of *how* the existence of consciousness might be entailed by the physical facts', when (assuming the other arguments work) 'any attempt to demonstrate such an entailment is doomed to failure' (1996, p. 104). His first argument goes roughly as follows. Suppose a population of tiny people disable your brain and replicate its functions themselves, while keeping the rest of your body in working order (see Block 1980a); each homunculus uses a cell phone to perform the signal-receiving and -transmitting functions of an individual neuron. Would such a system be conscious? Intuitively one may be inclined to say not. Some, notably functionalists, bite the bullet and answer yes. However, the argument does not depend on assuming that the homunculus-head would not be conscious. It depends only on the assumption that its not being conscious is *conceivable* -- which many people find reasonable. In Chalmers's words, all that matters here is that when we say the system might lack consciousness, 'a meaningful possibility is being expressed, and it is an open question whether consciousness arises or not' (1996, p. 97). If he is right, then conceivably the system is not conscious. In that case it is already very much like a zombie, the only difference being that it has little people where a zombie has neurons. And why should that make a difference to whether the situation is conceivable? Why should switching from homunculi to neurons necessarily switch on the light of consciousness? (For doubts about the assumption that it is conceivable that the homunculus-head lacks consciousness, see e.g. Loar 1990/1997, pp. 613f.) Other considerations favoring the conceivability of zombies can be found in Block 1995, 2002; Levine 2001; Searle 1992. Chalmers 2010 develops his defense further. Brian Cutter 2020 offers an anti-materialist modal argument which does not rely on the assumption that the physical truths are compatible with the absence of consciousness. ### 4.2 Arguments against the conceivability of zombies Although in the past it was quite widely accepted that zombies are conceivable, skepticism has grown. Before considering direct attacks on the idea, let us briefly recall three views which once appeared to support the claim that we can know *a priori* that dualism is false -- hence, on reasonable assumptions, that zombies are not conceivable. The first is verificationism, according to which a (declarative) sentence is meaningful just in case its truth or falsity can be verified. This entails that unverifiable sentences are literally meaningless, so that no metaphysical claim according to which unobservable nonphysical items exist can be true. However, since our ability to think and talk about our experiences is itself a problem for verificationism, to presuppose this view when attacking the zombie idea would beg the question. The second view appeals to Wittgenstein's private language argument. Although not crudely verificationistic, it depends on the assumption that in order for words to be meaningful, their use must be open to public checking. But since this checkability assumption, if sound, would prove that we cannot talk about qualia in the ways defenders of the zombie possibility think we can, it too seems question-begging in the present context. According to the third view, behaviorism, there is no more to having mental states than being disposed to behave in certain ways. As a possible basis for attacking the zombie idea, behaviorism is in a similar situation to verificationism and the private language argument. Zombies would satisfy all behavioral conditions for full consciousness, so that if we could know a priori that behaviorism was correct, zombie worlds would be inconceivable for that reason. It seems unlikely, though, that behaviorism can be shown to be correct. (Dennett 1991 defends a position with strong affinities to behaviorism, though it might be better classified as a variety of functionalism). Functionalism is a much more widely supported approach to the mental. According to it, mental states are not just a matter of behavior and dispositions, but of causal or other functional relations among sensory inputs, internal states, and behavioral outputs. (It is important to take account of internal functions not necessarily reflected in behavioral dispositions, otherwise functionalism falls to the usual objections to behaviorism, such as the 'homunculus-head' described in the last section (Kirk 2005, 2013, 2017).) Now, since zombies would satisfy all the functional conditions for full consciousness, functionalism entails that zombies are impossible -- though it would obviously be question-begging to presuppose it when attacking the zombie idea. Increasingly sophisticated versions of functionalism are being developed, however, and any arguments for it are a fortiori arguments against the possibility of zombies. (For defenses of functionalism against zombies see Dennett 1991; 1995; 1999; Kirk 2017; Shoemaker 1999; Tye 2006; 2008; for doubts about functionalism's capacity to deal with zombies see for example Harnad 1995.) Apart from broad-front functionalist theories of the mental, there are more narrowly focused attacks on the conceivability of zombies, some of which are noted below. *Can we really imagine zombies?* Daniel Dennett thinks those who accept the conceivability of zombies have failed to imagine them thoroughly enough: 'they invariably underestimate the task of conception (or imagination), and end up imagining something that violates their own definition' (1995, p. 322. Marcus 2004 makes a related point). Given his broadly functionalist model of consciousness, he argues, we can see why the 'putative contrast between zombies and conscious beings is illusory' (325. See also his 1991; 1999). Consciousness is 'not a single wonderful separable thing ... but a huge complex of many different informational capacities' (1995, 324. Cottrell 1999 supports this approach). *The 'epistemic approach'.* Stoljar (2006, 2020) emphasizes that the conceivability argument presupposes we have a complete knowledge of the relevant physical facts, when it is likely that we don't. If that is right, we cannot properly conceive of the possibilities in question, in which case premiss (1) of the conceivability argument is false. A bonus of this view is that it leaves us free to suppose there is a reductive explanation of consciousness -- that the physical facts are such that there is consciousness in all possible worlds where those facts obtain -- even when we don't know what those facts are. *Zombies' utterances*. Suppose I smell roasting coffee beans and say, 'Mm! I love that smell!'. Everyone would rightly assume I was talking about my experience. But now suppose my zombie twin produces the same utterance. He too seems to be talking about an experience, but in fact he isn't because he's just a zombie. Is he mistaken? Is he lying? Could his utterance somehow be interpreted as true, or is it totally without truth value? Nigel Thomas (1996) argues that 'any line that zombiphiles take on these questions will get them into serious trouble'. *Knowing about and referring to qualia*. Recall that by definition a zombie world is just like our world as physicalists suppose it to be, but without consciousness. Since this implies that consciousness depends on something nonphysical, it follows that zombies (assuming they are possible in the first place) could be made conscious by the addition of something nonphysical, which might as well be qualia. And given that a zombie world would be causally closed, these qualia would have to be causally inert: perhaps still caused by the correlated physical processes, perhaps just parallel to them. It therefore seems that if a zombie world is conceivable, so is epiphenomenalism. (Of course this does not require epiphenomenalism to be *actually* true as well as conceivable.) If that is correct, objections to the conceivability of epiphenomenalism are also objections to the conceivability of zombies, the most obvious of these being simply that experiences have effects on behavior. A less obvious objection starts from the fact that we *refer to and know about* our conscious experiences -- which can hardly be denied, since otherwise we could not be discussing these ideas in the first place. The objection appeals to the widely held view that whatever we can know about or refer to must have effects on us, if only indirectly (Kripke 1972/80). On that basis our counterparts in epiphenomenalistic worlds could not know about or refer to their qualia, with the consequence that (given the above reasoning) neither epiphenomenalistic worlds nor zombie worlds are conceivable. To this attack Chalmers replies that the crucial consideration is that we are 'acquainted' with our experiences. This 'intimate epistemic relation' both ensures that we can refer to experiences and also justifies our claims to know about them. Since, in contrast, our zombie twins have no experiences, what appear to be their judgments about experience are unjustified. Chalmers suggests that even if qualia have no causal influence on our judgments, their mere presence in the appropriate physical context ensures that our thoughts are about those qualia. He thinks it also constitutes justification for our knowledge claims even if experiences are not explanatorily relevant to making the judgments in question (Chalmers 1996, 172--209; 1999, 493f; see also his 2003, 2010). *The problem of epistemic contact*. Just now it seemed that if zombies are conceivable, then epiphenomenalist and parallelist worlds are also conceivable. In that case the friends of zombies must explain how the epiphenomenal qualia in such worlds could possibly be objects of acquaintance, or indeed make any sort of intimate contribution to people's lives; and here Kirk (2005; 2008) suggests the zombie idea faces a further difficulty. This emerges when we consider such things as attending to, thinking about, comparing and -- especially -- remembering our experiences. These activities bring us into 'epistemic contact' with them and involve cognitive processing, which in turn involves changes causing other changes. Being causally inert, the epiphenomenal qualia themselves could not do that processing; so if they actually constitute our experiences (as epiphenomenalism and parallelism imply) then the necessary processing must be purely physical. The trouble is that the zombie story appears to make it impossible for such processing to put us into epistemic contact with epiphenomenal qualia. This is because the only resources it can appeal to for that purpose are the assumed causation of qualia by neural processes and their isomorphism with them: factors which cannot do the necessary cognitive work (Kirk 2005; 2008). If that is right, the notions of epiphenomenal qualia and zombies lead to a contradiction. They imply a conception of consciousness which requires people to be in epistemic contact with their qualia, while at the same time ruling out the possibility of such contact. *'Powerful qualities'*. Another interesting objection to the zombie idea is based on the (controversial) idea of 'powerful qualities': the view that all properties are both dispositional and qualitative, and indeed that a thing's dispositions are identical with its qualities. Alexander Carruth (2016), for example, argues that the conceivability argument presupposes that while physical properties are dispositional, phenomenal ones are qualitative. On that basis a zombie duplicate of our world would instantiate our world's dispositional properties but not its phenomenal ones. The powerful qualities view rules that out *a priori*, making it not even conceivable. For if a thing's dispositions are identical with its qualities, nothing can instantiate certain dispositional properties without also instantiating all qualities supposedly identical with them. Countering this line of argument, Henry Taylor (2017) claims it depends on an implausible account of the distinction between the physical and the phenomenal, arguing in particular that the physical cannot be confined to the dispositional. For other attacks on the conceivability of zombies see Balog 1999; Cottrell 1999; Harnad 1995; Kirk 2005, 2008, 2013; Marcus 2004; Shoemaker 1999; Stoljar 2001; Tye 2006. ## 5. Does conceivability entail possibility? Premise (2) of the conceivability argument is: Whatever is conceivable is possible. It has been attacked from several angles, as follows. ### 5.1 Objections based on *a posteriori* necessity A number of philosophers argue that Kripke's ideas about a posteriori necessary truth facilitate the defense of physicalism. They urge that even if a zombie world is conceivable, that does not establish it is possible in the way that matters. Conceivability is an epistemic notion, they say, while possibility is a metaphysical one: 'It is false that if one can in principle conceive that P, then it is logically possible that P; ... Given psychophysical identities, it is an 'a posteriori' fact that any physical duplicate of our world is exactly like ours in respect of positive facts about sensory states' (Hill and McLaughlin 1999, 446. See also Hill 1997; Loar 1990/1997; 1999; McLaughlin 2005; Webster 2006). Some philosophers reject even the assumption that conceivability is a *guide* to possibility, challenging the view that the burden of proof is on those who deny the zombie possibility (Block and Stalnaker 1999; Hill and McLaughlin 1999; Yablo 1993). Chalmers has responded in several places (1996, 131-134; 1999, 476-7; 2010, 141-205). His most detailed version of the conceivability argument (2010) uses the framework of two-dimensional semantics. This enables him to distinguish two kinds of possibility and two corresponding kinds of conceivability. In the 'primary' sense conceivability entails possibility; for example it is conceivable that water should have been a substance chemically different from H2O. In the other, 'secondary' sense, it is neither conceivable nor possible that water should have been chemically different. The difficulty for the conceivability argument can be expressed by saying that even if zombie worlds are primarily conceivable and therefore primarily possible, it does not follow that they are also secondarily possible. And a posteriori physicalists will typically deny that it follows, on the ground that only the secondary possibility of zombie worlds would entail the falsity of physicalism. At this point Chalmers in effect presents his opponents with a dilemma, which is (crudely summarizing his conclusions) that either the primary conceivability of zombies does after all entail their secondary possibility, in which case the conceivability argument works and materialism is false; or else 'Russellian monism', briefly considered at Section 5.3 below, is true. (See also Jackson 1998; and for discussions, Brueckner 2002; Loar 1999; Hill and McLaughlin 1999; Piccinini 2017; Sebastian 2017; Shoemaker 1999; Soames 2005; Yablo 1999.) ### 5.2 The phenomenal concept strategy Many physicalists hold that both the zombie idea and Frank Jackson's knowledge argument can be dealt with through a proper understanding of the nature of phenomenal concepts (roughly, the concepts we use when conveying the character of our experiences: for example 'sweet', 'the way I see blue'). Exponents of the conceivability argument hold that the supposed 'explanatory gap' between the physical and the phenomenal -- which is expressed in the idea that zombies are conceivable -- brings with it an ontological gap. According to the 'phenomenal concept strategy' (Stoljar 2005) there is really only a conceptual gap: phenomenal concepts have features which mislead us into supposing there is an ontological gap in addition to an epistemic one, when there isn't. Thus it is argued that even if a zombie world is conceivable, it does not follow that there are nonphysical properties in our world. If that is right, physicalists can concede the conceivability of zombies while insisting that the properties we pick out in terms of phenomenal concepts are physical. 'Given that properties are constituted by the world and not by our concepts', Brian Loar comments, 'it is fair of the physicalist to request a justification of the assumption that conceptually distinct concepts *must* express metaphysically distinct properties' (Loar 1999, 467; see also his 1997). He also argues that phenomenal concepts are 'recognitional', in contrast to physical concepts, which are 'theoretical'. Phenomenal concepts, Loar says, 'express the very properties they pick out, as Kripke observed in the case of 'pain'' (1999, 468). He thinks these points explain the conceivability of a zombie world, while maintaining that there is no possible world in which the relevant physical properties are distinct from consciousness. Chalmers objects that Loar's account does not justify the view that physical concepts refer to phenomenal properties (1999, 488). He argues further (2007) that exponents of this approach face a dilemma. Let C be whichever psychological 'key features' we have but zombies lack. Then if it is conceivable that the purely physical facts about us should have held without C, then C is not physicalistically explicable. On the other hand, if that is not conceivable, then in his view C cannot explain our epistemic situation as contrasted with that of zombies. So either C is not physicalistically explicable, or it cannot explain our epistemic situation. (For discussions see Ball 2009; Balog 2012; Carruthers 2005; Chalmers 1999; 2007; 2010; Crane 2005; Loar 1990/97; Papineau 2002; Pereboom 2011; Stoljar 2000; Tye 2008.) ### 5.3 Russellian monism Following Russell (1927), some philosophers suggest that physics tells us only about the 'structural' properties of things -- such as their dispositions and nomic relations -- rather than the 'intrinsic' properties which supposedly underlie and account for those structural properties. Thus Daniel Stoljar (2001) argues that there are two distinct notions of the physical and correspondingly of physicalism, depending on whether one appeals only to what is provided for by physics or also to the intrinsic properties of physical objects. He suggests that even if one of the corresponding two versions of the conceivability argument is sound, the other is not -- because (roughly) physicalists can always object that, since we do not know enough about the physical world (in particular, about its intrinsic properties), we cannot 'strongly' conceive of the possibility of zombies. These ideas are exploited in what Chalmers calls 'Russellian monism' (a variety of neutral monism). In our world, he suggests, the underlying intrinsic properties might be 'phenomenal properties, or they might be protophenomenal properties: properties that collectively constitute phenomenal properties when organized in the appropriate way' (2010: p. 151); while in some other worlds the corresponding intrinsic physical properties did not provide for consciousness. If the intrinsic properties which supposedly provide for our consciousness are nevertheless classified as physical, exponents can deny the possibility of zombies if these are understood to be our 'full' physical duplicates. At the same time they can concede the possibility of zombies which duplicate us only in their structural properties. As he points out, this view is 'a highly distinctive form of physicalism that has much in common with property dualism and that many physicalists will want to reject' (Chalmers 2010, p. 152; see also Pereboom 2011). One obstacle to counting it as physicalism is that it seems unable to explain why the special intrinsic properties in our world should provide for consciousness, while those which perform the same functions in those other worlds do not: this has to be accepted as a brute fact. Philip Goff (2010; see also his 2017) suggests that this loophole for Russellian versions of physicalism weakens the zombie argument. He recommends instead an argument from ghosts: pure subjects of experience without any physical nature. He argues that such ghosts are conceivable and possible, and that they provide an argument against physicalism which leaves no loophole for Russellian monism. (Physicalists are likely to object that arguments against the conceivability of zombies can also be mobilized against ghosts.) ### 5.4 Other objections *Special factors*. It has been suggested that there are special factors at work in the psychophysical case which have a strong tendency to mislead us. For example it is claimed that what enables us to imagine or conceive of states of consciousness is a different cognitive faculty from what enables us to conceive of physical facts: 'there are significant differences between the cognitive factors responsible for Cartesian intuitions [such as those about zombies] and those responsible for modal intuitions of a wide variety of other kinds' (Hill and McLaughlin 1999, p. 449. See also Hill 1997). The suggestion is that these differences help to explain the ease with which we seem able to conceive of zombies, and the difficulty we have in understanding the claim that they are nevertheless impossible. *Conditional analysis*. Another line of objection rests on conditional analyses of the concept of qualia. Roughly, the idea is that *if* there actually are certain nonphysical properties which fit our conception of qualia, then that is what qualia are, in which case zombies are conceivable; but *if* there are no such nonphysical properties, then qualia are whichever physical properties perform the appropriate functions, and zombies are not conceivable. It is argued that this approach enables physicalists to accept that the possibility of zombies is conceivable, while denying that zombies are conceivable (Hawthorne 2002a; Braddon-Mitchell 2003. For criticism see Alter 2007; Chalmers 2010, pp. 159-59). *Causal essentialism*. According to the theory of causal essentialism, the causal properties of physical properties are essential to them. Brian Garrett (2009) exploits this theory to argue that the zombie argument against physicalism depends on broadly Humean assumptions about the laws of nature and property identity which presuppose the falsity of causal essentialism. If we reject those assumptions and accept that some physical properties have essentially the capacity to produce consciousness, then 'we cannot accept the genuine possibility of zombie worlds' even if such worlds are conceivable (see also Aranyosi 2010). *More on zombies' utterances*. Consider a zombie world that is an exact physical duplicate of our world and contains zombie twins of all philosophers, including some who appeal to the conceivability argument. Katalin Balog (1999) argues that while their utterances would be meaningful, their sentences would not always mean what they do in our mouths. She further argues -- to oversimplify -- that if the conceivability argument were sound in actual philosophers' mouths, then it would be sound in the mouths of zombie philosophers too. But since by hypothesis physicalism is true in their world, their argument is not sound. Therefore the conceivability argument used by actual philosophers is not sound either. If this argument works, it has the piquant feature that 'the zombies that antiphysicalists think possible in the end undermine the arguments that allege to establish their possibility' (502. Chalmers offers brief replies in his 2003; 2010, pp. 159-60). *The anti-zombie argument for physicalism*. The conceivability argument -- which assumes physicalism entails that zombies are impossible -- purports to refute it by showing they are possible. As we saw, the simplest version of this argument goes: (1) zombies are conceivable; (2) whatever is conceivable is possible; (3) therefore zombies are possible. However, 'anti-zombies' -- duplicates of ourselves made conscious by the purely physical facts (Frankish 2007) -- also seem conceivable. So we have a parallel argument: (1\*) anti-zombies are conceivable; (2) whatever is conceivable is possible; (3\*) therefore anti-zombies are possible. But (3) and (3\*) cannot both be true, since if the purely physical facts about anti-zombies make them conscious, then the exactly similar physical facts about zombies make them conscious too, and they are not zombies after all (Frankish 2007; Marton 1998; Piccinini 2017; Sturgeon 2000, pp. 114-116). One moral is that we should reject the inference from conceivability to possibility. (Brown 2010 argues that if anti-zombies are conceivable, then zombies are inconceivable.) The most promising reply for exponents of the conceivability argument seems to be to deny that anti-zombies are conceivable (Chalmers 2010, 180). ## 6. Other issues The list of 'Related Entries' below indicates the range and depth of the issues raised by the zombie idea, only some of which have been touched on in this entry. If zombies are really possible, then not only is physicalism problematic, so are widely held views on other topics. Here are three striking examples. ### 6.1 Mental causation Descartes accepted the common assumption that not only do physical events have mental effects, but mental events have physical effects (for example, thinking about the political situation makes me write a letter). The difficulty for his dualism, it was thought, was to understand how the nonphysical could have effects on the physical. But if zombies are possible -- which requires the physical world to be causally closed -- there is no work for nonphysical qualia to do. In that case the difficulty is to understand how, in spite of appearances, the nonphysical could *fail* to have effects on the physical. Still supposing zombies are possible, it then becomes hard to see any alternative to parallelism or epiphenomenalism, with the radical revision of common assumptions about mental causation that those views entail. True, the friends of zombies do not seem compelled to be epiphenomenalists or parallelists about the *actual* world. They may be interactionists, holding that our world is not physically closed, and that as a matter of actual fact nonphysical properties do have physical effects. Or they may adopt some variety of panpsychism, according to which what is metaphysically fundamental is not physical properties, but phenomenal or perhaps 'protophenomenal' ones (Chalmers 1991, 297--299; 1999, 492; Goff 2017; Strawson 2008) -- a view arguably compatible with the causal closure of the physical. But neither of those options is easy. Abandoning causal closure appears to conflict with empirical evidence; while the idea that phenomenal or quasi-phenomenal properties are fundamental remains obscure. ### 6.2 The function of consciousness The apparent possibility of zombies also seems to pose a problem for evolutionary theory. Why did creatures with qualia survive rather than those creatures' zombie counterparts? If zombies could have survived, what's the use of consciousness? Owen Flanagan and Thomas Polger have used the apparent possibility of zombies to support the claim that 'There are as yet no credible stories about why subjects of experience emerged, why they might have won -- or should have been expected to win -- an evolutionary battle against very intelligent zombie-like information-sensitive organisms' (1995, 321): a problem not faced by those who reject the possibility of zombies. One response on behalf of those who do accept it is to suggest that there might be fundamental laws linking the phenomenal to the physical. Such laws would not depend on whether conscious creatures ever happened to evolve, in which case, arguably, evolution raises no special problem (Chalmers 1996, 171) -- although the existence of such laws would pose its own problems. ### 6.3 Other minds If qualia have no physical effects, then nothing will enable anyone to establish for certain that anyone else actually has qualia. Philosophers who believe they have a solid response to skepticism about other minds may therefore conclude that this consequence of the zombie idea is enough to condemn it. Others may draw the opposite conclusion and take the skeptical consequence as 'a confirmation', on the ground that we really are ignorant of others' minds (Campbell 1970, 120). (Of course not all responses to other minds skepticism imply that zombies are inconceivable.) ## 7. Conclusion The intuitive appeal of the zombie idea can be overwhelming. But that was true once of the idea that the earth stands still, and is true now of the idea that science can explain events without appealing to anything nonphysical. Some anti-physicalists believe their opponents' commitment makes them turn a blind eye to the difficulties: > > Some may be led to deny the possibility [of zombies] in order to make > some theory come out right, but the justification of such theories > should ride on the question of possibility, rather than the other way > round (Chalmers 1996, 96). > On the other hand, some physicalists believe the zombie idea exerts an irrational grip on anti-physicalist thinking, so that > > it is tempting to regard anti-physicalist arguments as > rationalizations of an intuition whose independent force masks their > tendentiousness (Loar 1990/1997, 598). > In spite of the fact that the arguments on both sides have become increasingly sophisticated -- or perhaps because of it -- they have not become more persuasive. The pull in each direction remains strong.