text
stringlengths 0
80
|
---|
merely in any one order, but absolutely. For since it is the part of a |
wise man to arrange and to judge, and since lesser matters should be |
judged in the light of some higher principle, he is said to be wise in |
any one order who considers the highest principle in that order: thus |
in the order of building, he who plans the form of the house is called |
wise and architect, in opposition to the inferior laborers who trim |
the wood and make ready the stones: "As a wise architect, I have laid |
the foundation" (1 Cor. 3:10). Again, in the order of all human life, |
the prudent man is called wise, inasmuch as he directs his acts to a |
fitting end: "Wisdom is prudence to a man" (Prov. 10: 23). Therefore |
he who considers absolutely the highest cause of the whole universe, |
namely God, is most of all called wise. Hence wisdom is said to be the |
knowledge of divine things, as Augustine says (De Trin. xii, 14). But |
sacred doctrine essentially treats of God viewed as the highest |
cause--not only so far as He can be known through creatures just as |
philosophers knew Him--"That which is known of God is manifest in |
them" (Rom. 1:19)--but also as far as He is known to Himself alone |
and revealed to others. Hence sacred doctrine is especially called |
wisdom. |
Reply Objection 1: Sacred doctrine derives its principles not from |
any human knowledge, but from the divine knowledge, through which, as |
through the highest wisdom, all our knowledge is set in order. |
Reply Objection 2: The principles of other sciences either are |
evident and cannot be proved, or are proved by natural reason through |
some other science. But the knowledge proper to this science comes |
through revelation and not through natural reason. Therefore it has no |
concern to prove the principles of other sciences, but only to judge |
of them. Whatsoever is found in other sciences contrary to any truth |
of this science must be condemned as false: "Destroying counsels and |
every height that exalteth itself against the knowledge of God" (2 |
Cor. 10:4, 5). |
Reply Objection 3: Since judgment appertains to wisdom, the twofold |
manner of judging produces a twofold wisdom. A man may judge in one |
way by inclination, as whoever has the habit of a virtue judges |
rightly of what concerns that virtue by his very inclination towards |
it. Hence it is the virtuous man, as we read, who is the measure and |
rule of human acts. In another way, by knowledge, just as a man |
learned in moral science might be able to judge rightly about virtuous |
acts, though he had not the virtue. The first manner of judging divine |
things belongs to that wisdom which is set down among the gifts of the |
Holy Ghost: "The spiritual man judgeth all things" (1 Cor. 2:15). And |
Dionysius says (Div. Nom. ii): "Hierotheus is taught not by mere |
learning, but by experience of divine things." The second manner of |
judging belongs to this doctrine which is acquired by study, though |
its principles are obtained by revelation. |
_______________________ |
SEVENTH ARTICLE [I, Q. 1, Art. 7] |
Whether God Is the Object of This Science? |
Objection 1: It seems that God is not the object of this science. For |
in every science, the nature of its object is presupposed. But this |
science cannot presuppose the essence of God, for Damascene says (De |
Fide Orth. i, iv): "It is impossible to define the essence of God." |
Therefore God is not the object of this science. |
Objection 2: Further, whatever conclusions are reached in any science |
must be comprehended under the object of the science. But in Holy Writ |
we reach conclusions not only concerning God, but concerning many |
other things, such as creatures and human morality. Therefore God is |
not the object of this science. |
Contrary: The object of the science is that of which it |
principally treats. But in this science, the treatment is mainly about |
God; for it is called theology, as treating of God. Therefore God is |
the object of this science. |
Response: God is the object of this science. The relation between |
a science and its object is the same as that between a habit or |
faculty and its object. Now properly speaking, the object of a faculty |
or habit is the thing under the aspect of which all things are |
referred to that faculty or habit, as man and stone are referred to |
the faculty of sight in that they are colored. Hence colored things |
are the proper objects of sight. But in sacred science, all things are |
treated of under the aspect of God: either because they are God |
Himself or because they refer to God as their beginning and end. Hence |
it follows that God is in very truth the object of this science. This |
is clear also from the principles of this science, namely, the |
articles of faith, for faith is about God. The object of the |
principles and of the whole science must be the same, since the whole |
science is contained virtually in its principles. Some, however, |
looking to what is treated of in this science, and not to the aspect |
under which it is treated, have asserted the object of this science to |
be something other than God--that is, either things and signs; or the |
works of salvation; or the whole Christ, as the head and members. Of |
all these things, in truth, we treat in this science, but so far as |
they have reference to God. |
Reply Objection 1: Although we cannot know in what consists the |
essence of God, nevertheless in this science we make use of His |
effects, either of nature or of grace, in place of a definition, in |
regard to whatever is treated of in this science concerning God; even |
as in some philosophical sciences we demonstrate something about a |
cause from its effect, by taking the effect in place of a definition |
of the cause. |