id
int64
59
4.83M
tag
stringlengths
1
12.4k
cite
stringlengths
1
4.52k
fullcite
stringlengths
1
105k
summary
stringlengths
1
62.2k
spoken
stringlengths
1
35k
fulltext
stringlengths
4
388k
textLength
int64
4
388k
markup
stringlengths
35
397k
pocket
stringlengths
1
8k
hat
stringlengths
1
7.13k
block
stringlengths
1
16.2k
bucketId
int64
1
1.95M
duplicateCount
int64
1
5.63k
fileId
int64
1
172k
filePath
stringlengths
49
182
roundId
float64
565k
998k
side
stringclasses
2 values
tournament
stringlengths
1
95
round
stringclasses
56 values
opponent
stringlengths
1
65
judge
stringlengths
1
128
report
stringlengths
1
53.7k
opensourcePath
stringlengths
37
170
caselistUpdatedAt
stringlengths
19
19
teamId
float64
48.4k
86.5k
teamName
stringlengths
2
8
teamDisplayName
stringlengths
6
45
notes
stringclasses
631 values
debater1First
stringclasses
269 values
debater1Last
stringclasses
306 values
debater2First
stringclasses
224 values
debater2Last
stringclasses
259 values
schoolId
float64
18.7k
28.2k
schoolName
stringlengths
3
35
schoolDisplayName
stringlengths
3
40
state
stringclasses
49 values
chapterId
float64
23
114k
caselistId
float64
1k
2.01k
caselistName
stringclasses
40 values
caselistDisplayName
stringclasses
39 values
year
float64
2.01k
2.02k
event
stringclasses
3 values
level
stringclasses
2 values
teamSize
float64
1
2
4,379,114
Pleasure and pain are intrinsic value and disvalue – everything else regresses – robust neuroscience.
Blum et al. 18
Blum et al. 18 Kenneth Blum, 1Department of Psychiatry, Boonshoft School of Medicine, Dayton VA Medical Center, Wright State University, Dayton, OH, USA 2Department of Psychiatry, McKnight Brain Institute, University of Florida College of Medicine, Gainesville, FL, USA 3Department of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, Keck Medicine University of Southern California, Los Angeles, CA, USA 4Division of Applied Clinical Research & Education, Dominion Diagnostics, LLC, North Kingstown, RI, USA 5Department of Precision Medicine, Geneus Health LLC, San Antonio, TX, USA 6Department of Addiction Research & Therapy, Nupathways Inc., Innsbrook, MO, USA 7Department of Clinical Neurology, Path Foundation, New York, NY, USA 8Division of Neuroscience-Based Addiction Therapy, The Shores Treatment & Recovery Center, Port Saint Lucie, FL, USA 9Institute of Psychology, Eötvös Loránd University, Budapest, Hungary 10Division of Addiction Research, Dominion Diagnostics, LLC. North Kingston, RI, USA 11Victory Nutrition International, Lederach, PA., USA 12National Human Genome Center at Howard University, Washington, DC., USA, Marjorie Gondré-Lewis, 12National Human Genome Center at Howard University, Washington, DC., USA 13Departments of Anatomy and Psychiatry, Howard University College of Medicine, Washington, DC US, Bruce Steinberg, 4Division of Applied Clinical Research & Education, Dominion Diagnostics, LLC, North Kingstown, RI, USA, Igor Elman, 15Department Psychiatry, Cooper University School of Medicine, Camden, NJ, USA, David Baron, 3Department of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, Keck Medicine University of Southern California, Los Angeles, CA, USA, Edward J Modestino, 14Department of Psychology, Curry College, Milton, MA, USA, Rajendra D Badgaiyan, 15Department Psychiatry, Cooper University School of Medicine, Camden, NJ, USA, Mark S Gold 16Department of Psychiatry, Washington University, St. Louis, MO, USA, “Our evolved unique pleasure circuit makes humans different from apes: Reconsideration of data derived from animal studies”, U.S. Department of Veterans Affairs, 28 February 2018, accessed: 19 August 2020, https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC6446569/, R.S.
Pleasure is not only primary reward functions it also defines reward. functions of rewards, the reason why particular stimuli, objects, events, situations, and activities are rewarding due to pleasure. Pleasure, as the primary effect of rewards provides the basis for hedonic theories of reward function. We are attracted by rewards and exert intense efforts to obtain them because they are enjoyable using both humans and detailed invasive brain analysis of animals has discovered some critical ways that the brain processes pleasure Pleasure as a hallmark of reward is sufficient for defining a reward A reward may generate positive behavior because it contains substances that are essential for body function. evolution and its basic principles found mechanisms that steer behavior and biological development. organisms are the result of evolutionary competition. Dawkins stresses gene survival and propagation as the basic mechanism of life the fittest phenotype will make it. the ultimate, distal function of rewards is to increase evolutionary fitness Behavioral reward functions have evolved to help individuals to survive and propagate their genes people need to live well and long enough to reproduce. any small edge will ultimately result in evolutionary advantage Thus the distal reward function in gene propagation and evolutionary fitness defines the proximal reward functions that we see That is why foods, drinks, mates, and offspring are rewarding. pleasure is described as a state or feeling of happiness and satisfaction resulting from an experience that one enjoys. pathways for ordinary liking and pleasure are limited in scope there are many brain regions that significantly modulate our pleasure or even produce the opposite disgust and fear One region is organized like a computer keyboard, with particular stimulus triggers in rows the cortex has unique roles in the cognitive evaluation of our feelings of pleasure “liking” of something, or pure pleasure, is represented by regions in the limbic system part of larger neural circuits. researchers examined 247 specimens of neural tissue from six humans, five chimpanzees, and five macaque monkeys. investigators analyzed which genes were turned on or off in 16 regions of the brain. the differences among species were subtle, there was a remarkable contrast in the neocortices in an area of the brain that is much more developed in humans than in chimpanzees. ability to pursue various rewards that are perhaps months or even years away This may explain what often motivates people to work for things that have no apparent short-term benefit
Pleasure defines reward. the reason why particular stimuli are rewarding due to pleasure. Pleasure provides the basis for hedonic theories of reward organisms are the result of evolutionary competition. rewards increase fitness foods, drinks, mates, and offspring are rewarding. brain regions modulate pleasure or the opposite liking something is represented by regions in the limbic system researchers examined neural tissue neocortices in the brain much more developed in humans ability to pursue rewards that are years away
Pleasure is not only one of the three primary reward functions but it also defines reward. As homeostasis explains the functions of only a limited number of rewards, the principal reason why particular stimuli, objects, events, situations, and activities are rewarding may be due to pleasure. This applies first of all to sex and to the primary homeostatic rewards of food and liquid and extends to money, taste, beauty, social encounters and nonmaterial, internally set, and intrinsic rewards. Pleasure, as the primary effect of rewards, drives the prime reward functions of learning, approach behavior, and decision making and provides the basis for hedonic theories of reward function. We are attracted by most rewards and exert intense efforts to obtain them, just because they are enjoyable [10]. Pleasure is a passive reaction that derives from the experience or prediction of reward and may lead to a long-lasting state of happiness. The word happiness is difficult to define. In fact, just obtaining physical pleasure may not be enough. One key to happiness involves a network of good friends. However, it is not obvious how the higher forms of satisfaction and pleasure are related to an ice cream cone, or to your team winning a sporting event. Recent multidisciplinary research, using both humans and detailed invasive brain analysis of animals has discovered some critical ways that the brain processes pleasure [14]. Pleasure as a hallmark of reward is sufficient for defining a reward, but it may not be necessary. A reward may generate positive learning and approach behavior simply because it contains substances that are essential for body function. When we are hungry, we may eat bad and unpleasant meals. A monkey who receives hundreds of small drops of water every morning in the laboratory is unlikely to feel a rush of pleasure every time it gets the 0.1 ml. Nevertheless, with these precautions in mind, we may define any stimulus, object, event, activity, or situation that has the potential to produce pleasure as a reward. In the context of reward deficiency or for disorders of addiction, homeostasis pursues pharmacological treatments: drugs to treat drug addiction, obesity, and other compulsive behaviors. The theory of allostasis suggests broader approaches - such as re-expanding the range of possible pleasures and providing opportunities to expend effort in their pursuit. [15]. It is noteworthy, the first animal studies eliciting approach behavior by electrical brain stimulation interpreted their findings as a discovery of the brain’s pleasure centers [16] which were later partly associated with midbrain dopamine neurons [17–19] despite the notorious difficulties of identifying emotions in animals. Evolutionary theories of pleasure: The love connection BO:D Charles Darwin and other biological scientists that have examined the biological evolution and its basic principles found various mechanisms that steer behavior and biological development. Besides their theory on natural selection, it was particularly the sexual selection process that gained significance in the latter context over the last century, especially when it comes to the question of what makes us “what we are,” i.e., human. However, the capacity to sexually select and evolve is not at all a human accomplishment alone or a sign of our uniqueness; yet, we humans, as it seems, are ingenious in fooling ourselves and others–when we are in love or desperately search for it. It is well established that modern biological theory conjectures that organisms are the result of evolutionary competition. In fact, Richard Dawkins stresses gene survival and propagation as the basic mechanism of life [20]. Only genes that lead to the fittest phenotype will make it. It is noteworthy that the phenotype is selected based on behavior that maximizes gene propagation. To do so, the phenotype must survive and generate offspring, and be better at it than its competitors. Thus, the ultimate, distal function of rewards is to increase evolutionary fitness by ensuring the survival of the organism and reproduction. It is agreed that learning, approach, economic decisions, and positive emotions are the proximal functions through which phenotypes obtain other necessary nutrients for survival, mating, and care for offspring. Behavioral reward functions have evolved to help individuals to survive and propagate their genes. Apparently, people need to live well and long enough to reproduce. Most would agree that homo-sapiens do so by ingesting the substances that make their bodies function properly. For this reason, foods and drinks are rewards. Additional rewards, including those used for economic exchanges, ensure sufficient palatable food and drink supply. Mating and gene propagation is supported by powerful sexual attraction. Additional properties, like body form, augment the chance to mate and nourish and defend offspring and are therefore also rewards. Care for offspring until they can reproduce themselves helps gene propagation and is rewarding; otherwise, many believe mating is useless. According to David E Comings, as any small edge will ultimately result in evolutionary advantage [21], additional reward mechanisms like novelty seeking and exploration widen the spectrum of available rewards and thus enhance the chance for survival, reproduction, and ultimate gene propagation. These functions may help us to obtain the benefits of distant rewards that are determined by our own interests and not immediately available in the environment. Thus the distal reward function in gene propagation and evolutionary fitness defines the proximal reward functions that we see in everyday behavior. That is why foods, drinks, mates, and offspring are rewarding. There have been theories linking pleasure as a required component of health benefits salutogenesis, (salugenesis). In essence, under these terms, pleasure is described as a state or feeling of happiness and satisfaction resulting from an experience that one enjoys. Regarding pleasure, it is a double-edged sword, on the one hand, it promotes positive feelings (like mindfulness) and even better cognition, possibly through the release of dopamine [22]. But on the other hand, pleasure simultaneously encourages addiction and other negative behaviors, i.e., motivational toxicity. It is a complex neurobiological phenomenon, relying on reward circuitry or limbic activity. It is important to realize that through the “Brain Reward Cascade” (BRC) endorphin and endogenous morphinergic mechanisms may play a role [23]. While natural rewards are essential for survival and appetitive motivation leading to beneficial biological behaviors like eating, sex, and reproduction, crucial social interactions seem to further facilitate the positive effects exerted by pleasurable experiences. Indeed, experimentation with addictive drugs is capable of directly acting on reward pathways and causing deterioration of these systems promoting hypodopaminergia [24]. Most would agree that pleasurable activities can stimulate personal growth and may help to induce healthy behavioral changes, including stress management [25]. The work of Esch and Stefano [26] concerning the link between compassion and love implicate the brain reward system, and pleasure induction suggests that social contact in general, i.e., love, attachment, and compassion, can be highly effective in stress reduction, survival, and overall health. Understanding the role of neurotransmission and pleasurable states both positive and negative have been adequately studied over many decades [26–37], but comparative anatomical and neurobiological function between animals and homo sapiens appear to be required and seem to be in an infancy stage. Finding happiness is different between apes and humans As stated earlier in this expert opinion one key to happiness involves a network of good friends [38]. However, it is not entirely clear exactly how the higher forms of satisfaction and pleasure are related to a sugar rush, winning a sports event or even sky diving, all of which augment dopamine release at the reward brain site. Recent multidisciplinary research, using both humans and detailed invasive brain analysis of animals has discovered some critical ways that the brain processes pleasure. Remarkably, there are pathways for ordinary liking and pleasure, which are limited in scope as described above in this commentary. However, there are many brain regions, often termed hot and cold spots, that significantly modulate (increase or decrease) our pleasure or even produce the opposite of pleasure— that is disgust and fear [39]. One specific region of the nucleus accumbens is organized like a computer keyboard, with particular stimulus triggers in rows— producing an increase and decrease of pleasure and disgust. Moreover, the cortex has unique roles in the cognitive evaluation of our feelings of pleasure [40]. Importantly, the interplay of these multiple triggers and the higher brain centers in the prefrontal cortex are very intricate and are just being uncovered. Desire and reward centers It is surprising that many different sources of pleasure activate the same circuits between the mesocorticolimbic regions (Figure 1). Reward and desire are two aspects pleasure induction and have a very widespread, large circuit. Some part of this circuit distinguishes between desire and dread. The so-called pleasure circuitry called “REWARD” involves a well-known dopamine pathway in the mesolimbic system that can influence both pleasure and motivation. In simplest terms, the well-established mesolimbic system is a dopamine circuit for reward. It starts in the ventral tegmental area (VTA) of the midbrain and travels to the nucleus accumbens (Figure 2). It is the cornerstone target to all addictions. The VTA is encompassed with neurons using glutamate, GABA, and dopamine. The nucleus accumbens (NAc) is located within the ventral striatum and is divided into two sub-regions—the motor and limbic regions associated with its core and shell, respectively. The NAc has spiny neurons that receive dopamine from the VTA and glutamate (a dopamine driver) from the hippocampus, amygdala and medial prefrontal cortex. Subsequently, the NAc projects GABA signals to an area termed the ventral pallidum (VP). The region is a relay station in the limbic loop of the basal ganglia, critical for motivation, behavior, emotions and the “Feel Good” response. This defined system of the brain is involved in all addictions –substance, and non –substance related. In 1995, our laboratory coined the term “Reward Deficiency Syndrome” (RDS) to describe genetic and epigenetic induced hypodopaminergia in the “Brain Reward Cascade” that contribute to addiction and compulsive behaviors [3,6,41]. Furthermore, ordinary “liking” of something, or pure pleasure, is represented by small regions mainly in the limbic system (old reptilian part of the brain). These may be part of larger neural circuits. In Latin, hedus is the term for “sweet”; and in Greek, hodone is the term for “pleasure.” Thus, the word Hedonic is now referring to various subcomponents of pleasure: some associated with purely sensory and others with more complex emotions involving morals, aesthetics, and social interactions. The capacity to have pleasure is part of being healthy and may even extend life, especially if linked to optimism as a dopaminergic response [42]. Psychiatric illness often includes symptoms of an abnormal inability to experience pleasure, referred to as anhedonia. A negative feeling state is called dysphoria, which can consist of many emotions such as pain, depression, anxiety, fear, and disgust. Previously many scientists used animal research to uncover the complex mechanisms of pleasure, liking, motivation and even emotions like panic and fear, as discussed above [43]. However, as a significant amount of related research about the specific brain regions of pleasure/reward circuitry has been derived from invasive studies of animals, these cannot be directly compared with subjective states experienced by humans. In an attempt to resolve the controversy regarding the causal contributions of mesolimbic dopamine systems to reward, we have previously evaluated the three-main competing explanatory categories: “liking,” “learning,” and “wanting” [3]. That is, dopamine may mediate (a) liking: the hedonic impact of reward, (b) learning: learned predictions about rewarding effects, or (c) wanting: the pursuit of rewards by attributing incentive salience to reward-related stimuli [44]. We have evaluated these hypotheses, especially as they relate to the RDS, and we find that the incentive salience or “wanting” hypothesis of dopaminergic functioning is supported by a majority of the scientific evidence. Various neuroimaging studies have shown that anticipated behaviors such as sex and gaming, delicious foods and drugs of abuse all affect brain regions associated with reward networks, and may not be unidirectional. Drugs of abuse enhance dopamine signaling which sensitizes mesolimbic brain mechanisms that apparently evolved explicitly to attribute incentive salience to various rewards [45]. Addictive substances are voluntarily self-administered, and they enhance (directly or indirectly) dopaminergic synaptic function in the NAc. This activation of the brain reward networks (producing the ecstatic “high” that users seek). Although these circuits were initially thought to encode a set point of hedonic tone, it is now being considered to be far more complicated in function, also encoding attention, reward expectancy, disconfirmation of reward expectancy, and incentive motivation [46]. The argument about addiction as a disease may be confused with a predisposition to substance and nonsubstance rewards relative to the extreme effect of drugs of abuse on brain neurochemistry. The former sets up an individual to be at high risk through both genetic polymorphisms in reward genes as well as harmful epigenetic insult. Some Psychologists, even with all the data, still infer that addiction is not a disease [47]. Elevated stress levels, together with polymorphisms (genetic variations) of various dopaminergic genes and the genes related to other neurotransmitters (and their genetic variants), and may have an additive effect on vulnerability to various addictions [48]. In this regard, Vanyukov, et al. [48] suggested based on review that whereas the gateway hypothesis does not specify mechanistic connections between “stages,” and does not extend to the risks for addictions the concept of common liability to addictions may be more parsimonious. The latter theory is grounded in genetic theory and supported by data identifying common sources of variation in the risk for specific addictions (e.g., RDS). This commonality has identifiable neurobiological substrate and plausible evolutionary explanations. Over many years the controversy of dopamine involvement in especially “pleasure” has led to confusion concerning separating motivation from actual pleasure (wanting versus liking) [49]. We take the position that animal studies cannot provide real clinical information as described by self-reports in humans. As mentioned earlier and in the abstract, on November 23rd, 2017, evidence for our concerns was discovered [50] In essence, although nonhuman primate brains are similar to our own, the disparity between other primates and those of human cognitive abilities tells us that surface similarity is not the whole story. Sousa et al. [50] small case found various differentially expressed genes, to associate with pleasure related systems. Furthermore, the dopaminergic interneurons located in the human neocortex were absent from the neocortex of nonhuman African apes. Such differences in neuronal transcriptional programs may underlie a variety of neurodevelopmental disorders. In simpler terms, the system controls the production of dopamine, a chemical messenger that plays a significant role in pleasure and rewards. The senior author, Dr. Nenad Sestan from Yale, stated: “Humans have evolved a dopamine system that is different than the one in chimpanzees.” This may explain why the behavior of humans is so unique from that of non-human primates, even though our brains are so surprisingly similar, Sestan said: “It might also shed light on why people are vulnerable to mental disorders such as autism (possibly even addiction).” Remarkably, this research finding emerged from an extensive, multicenter collaboration to compare the brains across several species. These researchers examined 247 specimens of neural tissue from six humans, five chimpanzees, and five macaque monkeys. Moreover, these investigators analyzed which genes were turned on or off in 16 regions of the brain. While the differences among species were subtle, there was a remarkable contrast in the neocortices, specifically in an area of the brain that is much more developed in humans than in chimpanzees. In fact, these researchers found that a gene called ability to pursue various rewards that are perhaps months or even years away in the future. This same idea has been suggested by Dr. Robert Sapolsky, a professor of biology and neurology at Stanford University. Dr. Sapolsky cited evidence that dopamine levels rise dramatically in humans when we anticipate potential rewards that are uncertain and even far off in our futures, such as retirement or even the possible alterlife. This may explain what often motivates people to work for things that have no apparent short-term benefit [51]. In similar work, Volkow and Bale [52] proposed a model in which dopamine can favor NOW processes through phasic signaling in reward circuits or LATER processes through tonic signaling in control circuits. Specifically, they suggest that through its modulation of the orbitofrontal cortex, which processes salience attribution, dopamine also enables shilting from NOW to LATER, while its modulation of the insula, which processes interoceptive information, influences the probability of selecting NOW versus LATER actions based on an individual’s physiological state. This hypothesis further supports the concept that disruptions along these circuits contribute to diverse pathologies, including obesity and addiction or RDS.
18,378
<h4><strong>Pleasure and pain are intrinsic value and disvalue – everything else regresses – robust neuroscience. </h4><p>Blum et al. 18 </strong>Kenneth Blum, 1Department of Psychiatry, Boonshoft School of Medicine, Dayton VA Medical Center, Wright State University, Dayton, OH, USA 2Department of Psychiatry, McKnight Brain Institute, University of Florida College of Medicine, Gainesville, FL, USA 3Department of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, Keck Medicine University of Southern California, Los Angeles, CA, USA 4Division of Applied Clinical Research & Education, Dominion Diagnostics, LLC, North Kingstown, RI, USA 5Department of Precision Medicine, Geneus Health LLC, San Antonio, TX, USA 6Department of Addiction Research & Therapy, Nupathways Inc., Innsbrook, MO, USA 7Department of Clinical Neurology, Path Foundation, New York, NY, USA 8Division of Neuroscience-Based Addiction Therapy, The Shores Treatment & Recovery Center, Port Saint Lucie, FL, USA 9Institute of Psychology, Eötvös Loránd University, Budapest, Hungary 10Division of Addiction Research, Dominion Diagnostics, LLC. North Kingston, RI, USA 11Victory Nutrition International, Lederach, PA., USA 12National Human Genome Center at Howard University, Washington, DC., USA, Marjorie Gondré-Lewis, 12National Human Genome Center at Howard University, Washington, DC., USA 13Departments of Anatomy and Psychiatry, Howard University College of Medicine, Washington, DC US, Bruce Steinberg, 4Division of Applied Clinical Research & Education, Dominion Diagnostics, LLC, North Kingstown, RI, USA, Igor Elman, 15Department Psychiatry, Cooper University School of Medicine, Camden, NJ, USA, David Baron, 3Department of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, Keck Medicine University of Southern California, Los Angeles, CA, USA, Edward J Modestino, 14Department of Psychology, Curry College, Milton, MA, USA, Rajendra D Badgaiyan, 15Department Psychiatry, Cooper University School of Medicine, Camden, NJ, USA, Mark S Gold 16Department of Psychiatry, Washington University, St. Louis, MO, USA, “Our evolved unique pleasure circuit makes humans different from apes: Reconsideration of data derived from animal studies”, U.S. Department of Veterans Affairs, 28 February 2018, accessed: 19 August 2020, https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC6446569/, R.S.</p><p><u><strong><mark>Pleasure</strong></mark> is not only</u> one of the three <u>primary reward functions</u> but <u>it also <strong><mark>defines reward.</u></strong></mark> As homeostasis explains the <u>functions of</u> only a limited number of <u>rewards, <strong><mark>the</u></strong></mark> principal <u><strong><mark>reason why particular stimuli</strong></mark>, objects, events, situations, and activities <strong><mark>are rewarding</u></strong></mark> may be <u><strong><mark>due to pleasure</strong>.</u></mark> This applies first of all to sex and to the primary homeostatic rewards of food and liquid and extends to money, taste, beauty, social encounters and nonmaterial, internally set, and intrinsic rewards. <u><strong><mark>Pleasure</strong></mark>, as the primary effect of rewards</u>, drives the prime reward functions of learning, approach behavior, and decision making and <u><strong><mark>provides the basis for hedonic theories of reward</strong></mark> function. We are attracted by</u> most <u>rewards and exert intense efforts to obtain them</u>, just <u>because they are enjoyable</u> [10]. Pleasure is a passive reaction that derives from the experience or prediction of reward and may lead to a long-lasting state of happiness. The word happiness is difficult to define. In fact, just obtaining physical pleasure may not be enough. One key to happiness involves a network of good friends. However, it is not obvious how the higher forms of satisfaction and pleasure are related to an ice cream cone, or to your team winning a sporting event. Recent multidisciplinary research, <u>using both humans and detailed invasive brain analysis of animals has discovered some critical ways that the brain processes pleasure</u> [14]. <u>Pleasure as a hallmark of reward is sufficient for defining a reward</u>, but it may not be necessary. <u>A reward may generate positive</u> learning and approach <u>behavior</u> simply <u>because it contains substances that are essential for body function.</u> When we are hungry, we may eat bad and unpleasant meals. A monkey who receives hundreds of small drops of water every morning in the laboratory is unlikely to feel a rush of pleasure every time it gets the 0.1 ml. Nevertheless, with these precautions in mind, we may define any stimulus, object, event, activity, or situation that has the potential to produce pleasure as a reward. In the context of reward deficiency or for disorders of addiction, homeostasis pursues pharmacological treatments: drugs to treat drug addiction, obesity, and other compulsive behaviors. The theory of allostasis suggests broader approaches - such as re-expanding the range of possible pleasures and providing opportunities to expend effort in their pursuit. [15]. It is noteworthy, the first animal studies eliciting approach behavior by electrical brain stimulation interpreted their findings as a discovery of the brain’s pleasure centers [16] which were later partly associated with midbrain dopamine neurons [17–19] despite the notorious difficulties of identifying emotions in animals. Evolutionary theories of pleasure: The love connection BO:D Charles Darwin and other biological scientists that have examined the biological <u>evolution and its basic principles found</u> various <u>mechanisms that steer behavior and biological development.</u> Besides their theory on natural selection, it was particularly the sexual selection process that gained significance in the latter context over the last century, especially when it comes to the question of what makes us “what we are,” i.e., human. However, the capacity to sexually select and evolve is not at all a human accomplishment alone or a sign of our uniqueness; yet, we humans, as it seems, are ingenious in fooling ourselves and others–when we are in love or desperately search for it. It is well established that modern biological theory conjectures that <u><strong><mark>organisms are</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>result of evolutionary competition.</u></strong></mark> In fact, Richard <u>Dawkins stresses gene survival and propagation as the basic mechanism of life</u> [20]. Only genes that lead to <u>the fittest phenotype will make it.</u> It is noteworthy that the phenotype is selected based on behavior that maximizes gene propagation. To do so, the phenotype must survive and generate offspring, and be better at it than its competitors. Thus, <u>the ultimate, distal function of <strong><mark>rewards</strong></mark> is to <strong><mark>increase</strong></mark> evolutionary <strong><mark>fitness</u></strong></mark> by ensuring the survival of the organism and reproduction. It is agreed that learning, approach, economic decisions, and positive emotions are the proximal functions through which phenotypes obtain other necessary nutrients for survival, mating, and care for offspring. <u>Behavioral reward functions have evolved to help individuals to survive and propagate their genes</u>. Apparently, <u>people need to live well and long enough to reproduce.</u> Most would agree that homo-sapiens do so by ingesting the substances that make their bodies function properly. For this reason, foods and drinks are rewards. Additional rewards, including those used for economic exchanges, ensure sufficient palatable food and drink supply. Mating and gene propagation is supported by powerful sexual attraction. Additional properties, like body form, augment the chance to mate and nourish and defend offspring and are therefore also rewards. Care for offspring until they can reproduce themselves helps gene propagation and is rewarding; otherwise, many believe mating is useless. According to David E Comings, as <u>any small edge will ultimately result in evolutionary advantage</u> [21], additional reward mechanisms like novelty seeking and exploration widen the spectrum of available rewards and thus enhance the chance for survival, reproduction, and ultimate gene propagation. These functions may help us to obtain the benefits of distant rewards that are determined by our own interests and not immediately available in the environment. <u>Thus the distal reward function in gene propagation and evolutionary fitness defines the proximal reward functions that we see</u> in everyday behavior. <u><strong>That is why <mark>foods, drinks, mates, and offspring are rewarding</strong>.</mark> </u>There have been theories linking pleasure as a required component of health benefits salutogenesis, (salugenesis). In essence, under these terms, <u>pleasure is described as a state or feeling of happiness and satisfaction resulting from an experience that one enjoys.</u> Regarding pleasure, it is a double-edged sword, on the one hand, it promotes positive feelings (like mindfulness) and even better cognition, possibly through the release of dopamine [22]. But on the other hand, pleasure simultaneously encourages addiction and other negative behaviors, i.e., motivational toxicity. It is a complex neurobiological phenomenon, relying on reward circuitry or limbic activity. It is important to realize that through the “Brain Reward Cascade” (BRC) endorphin and endogenous morphinergic mechanisms may play a role [23]. While natural rewards are essential for survival and appetitive motivation leading to beneficial biological behaviors like eating, sex, and reproduction, crucial social interactions seem to further facilitate the positive effects exerted by pleasurable experiences. Indeed, experimentation with addictive drugs is capable of directly acting on reward pathways and causing deterioration of these systems promoting hypodopaminergia [24]. Most would agree that pleasurable activities can stimulate personal growth and may help to induce healthy behavioral changes, including stress management [25]. The work of Esch and Stefano [26] concerning the link between compassion and love implicate the brain reward system, and pleasure induction suggests that social contact in general, i.e., love, attachment, and compassion, can be highly effective in stress reduction, survival, and overall health. Understanding the role of neurotransmission and pleasurable states both positive and negative have been adequately studied over many decades [26–37], but comparative anatomical and neurobiological function between animals and homo sapiens appear to be required and seem to be in an infancy stage. Finding happiness is different between apes and humans As stated earlier in this expert opinion one key to happiness involves a network of good friends [38]. However, it is not entirely clear exactly how the higher forms of satisfaction and pleasure are related to a sugar rush, winning a sports event or even sky diving, all of which augment dopamine release at the reward brain site. Recent multidisciplinary research, using both humans and detailed invasive brain analysis of animals has discovered some critical ways that the brain processes pleasure. Remarkably, there are <u>pathways for ordinary liking and pleasure</u>, which <u>are limited in scope</u> as described above in this commentary. However, <u>there are <strong>many <mark>brain regions</u></strong></mark>, often termed hot and cold spots, <u>that significantly <strong><mark>modulate</u></strong></mark> (increase or decrease) <u>our <strong><mark>pleasure or</strong></mark> even <strong>produce <mark>the opposite</u></strong></mark> of pleasure— that is <u>disgust and fear</u> [39]. <u>One</u> specific <u>region</u> of the nucleus accumbens <u>is organized like a computer keyboard, with particular stimulus triggers in rows</u>— producing an increase and decrease of pleasure and disgust. Moreover, <u>the cortex has unique roles in the cognitive evaluation of our feelings of pleasure</u> [40]. Importantly, the interplay of these multiple triggers and the higher brain centers in the prefrontal cortex are very intricate and are just being uncovered. Desire and reward centers It is surprising that many different sources of pleasure activate the same circuits between the mesocorticolimbic regions (Figure 1). Reward and desire are two aspects pleasure induction and have a very widespread, large circuit. Some part of this circuit distinguishes between desire and dread. The so-called pleasure circuitry called “REWARD” involves a well-known dopamine pathway in the mesolimbic system that can influence both pleasure and motivation. In simplest terms, the well-established mesolimbic system is a dopamine circuit for reward. It starts in the ventral tegmental area (VTA) of the midbrain and travels to the nucleus accumbens (Figure 2). It is the cornerstone target to all addictions. The VTA is encompassed with neurons using glutamate, GABA, and dopamine. The nucleus accumbens (NAc) is located within the ventral striatum and is divided into two sub-regions—the motor and limbic regions associated with its core and shell, respectively. The NAc has spiny neurons that receive dopamine from the VTA and glutamate (a dopamine driver) from the hippocampus, amygdala and medial prefrontal cortex. Subsequently, the NAc projects GABA signals to an area termed the ventral pallidum (VP). The region is a relay station in the limbic loop of the basal ganglia, critical for motivation, behavior, emotions and the “Feel Good” response. This defined system of the brain is involved in all addictions –substance, and non –substance related. In 1995, our laboratory coined the term “Reward Deficiency Syndrome” (RDS) to describe genetic and epigenetic induced hypodopaminergia in the “Brain Reward Cascade” that contribute to addiction and compulsive behaviors [3,6,41]. Furthermore, ordinary <u>“<strong><mark>liking</strong></mark>” of <strong><mark>something</strong></mark>, or pure pleasure, <strong><mark>is represented by</u></strong></mark> small <u><strong><mark>regions</u></strong></mark> mainly <u><strong><mark>in the limbic system</u></strong></mark> (old reptilian part of the brain). These may be <u>part of larger neural circuits.</u> In Latin, hedus is the term for “sweet”; and in Greek, hodone is the term for “pleasure.” Thus, the word Hedonic is now referring to various subcomponents of pleasure: some associated with purely sensory and others with more complex emotions involving morals, aesthetics, and social interactions. The capacity to have pleasure is part of being healthy and may even extend life, especially if linked to optimism as a dopaminergic response [42]. Psychiatric illness often includes symptoms of an abnormal inability to experience pleasure, referred to as anhedonia. A negative feeling state is called dysphoria, which can consist of many emotions such as pain, depression, anxiety, fear, and disgust. Previously many scientists used animal research to uncover the complex mechanisms of pleasure, liking, motivation and even emotions like panic and fear, as discussed above [43]. However, as a significant amount of related research about the specific brain regions of pleasure/reward circuitry has been derived from invasive studies of animals, these cannot be directly compared with subjective states experienced by humans. In an attempt to resolve the controversy regarding the causal contributions of mesolimbic dopamine systems to reward, we have previously evaluated the three-main competing explanatory categories: “liking,” “learning,” and “wanting” [3]. That is, dopamine may mediate (a) liking: the hedonic impact of reward, (b) learning: learned predictions about rewarding effects, or (c) wanting: the pursuit of rewards by attributing incentive salience to reward-related stimuli [44]. We have evaluated these hypotheses, especially as they relate to the RDS, and we find that the incentive salience or “wanting” hypothesis of dopaminergic functioning is supported by a majority of the scientific evidence. Various neuroimaging studies have shown that anticipated behaviors such as sex and gaming, delicious foods and drugs of abuse all affect brain regions associated with reward networks, and may not be unidirectional. Drugs of abuse enhance dopamine signaling which sensitizes mesolimbic brain mechanisms that apparently evolved explicitly to attribute incentive salience to various rewards [45]. Addictive substances are voluntarily self-administered, and they enhance (directly or indirectly) dopaminergic synaptic function in the NAc. This activation of the brain reward networks (producing the ecstatic “high” that users seek). Although these circuits were initially thought to encode a set point of hedonic tone, it is now being considered to be far more complicated in function, also encoding attention, reward expectancy, disconfirmation of reward expectancy, and incentive motivation [46]. The argument about addiction as a disease may be confused with a predisposition to substance and nonsubstance rewards relative to the extreme effect of drugs of abuse on brain neurochemistry. The former sets up an individual to be at high risk through both genetic polymorphisms in reward genes as well as harmful epigenetic insult. Some Psychologists, even with all the data, still infer that addiction is not a disease [47]. Elevated stress levels, together with polymorphisms (genetic variations) of various dopaminergic genes and the genes related to other neurotransmitters (and their genetic variants), and may have an additive effect on vulnerability to various addictions [48]. In this regard, Vanyukov, et al. [48] suggested based on review that whereas the gateway hypothesis does not specify mechanistic connections between “stages,” and does not extend to the risks for addictions the concept of common liability to addictions may be more parsimonious. The latter theory is grounded in genetic theory and supported by data identifying common sources of variation in the risk for specific addictions (e.g., RDS). This commonality has identifiable neurobiological substrate and plausible evolutionary explanations. Over many years the controversy of dopamine involvement in especially “pleasure” has led to confusion concerning separating motivation from actual pleasure (wanting versus liking) [49]. We take the position that animal studies cannot provide real clinical information as described by self-reports in humans. As mentioned earlier and in the abstract, on November 23rd, 2017, evidence for our concerns was discovered [50] In essence, although nonhuman primate brains are similar to our own, the disparity between other primates and those of human cognitive abilities tells us that surface similarity is not the whole story. Sousa et al. [50] small case found various differentially expressed genes, to associate with pleasure related systems. Furthermore, the dopaminergic interneurons located in the human neocortex were absent from the neocortex of nonhuman African apes. Such differences in neuronal transcriptional programs may underlie a variety of neurodevelopmental disorders. In simpler terms, the system controls the production of dopamine, a chemical messenger that plays a significant role in pleasure and rewards. The senior author, Dr. Nenad Sestan from Yale, stated: “Humans have evolved a dopamine system that is different than the one in chimpanzees.” This may explain why the behavior of humans is so unique from that of non-human primates, even though our brains are so surprisingly similar, Sestan said: “It might also shed light on why people are vulnerable to mental disorders such as autism (possibly even addiction).” Remarkably, this research finding emerged from an extensive, multicenter collaboration to compare the brains across several species. These <u><strong><mark>researchers examined</strong></mark> 247 specimens of <strong><mark>neural tissue</strong></mark> from six humans, five chimpanzees, and five macaque monkeys.</u> Moreover, these <u>investigators analyzed which genes were turned on or off in 16 regions of the brain.</u> While <u>the differences among species were subtle, <strong>there was</strong> a <strong>remarkable contrast in</strong> the<strong> <mark>neocortices</u></strong></mark>, specifically <u><strong><mark>in</strong></mark> an area of <strong><mark>the brain</strong></mark> that <strong>is <mark>much more developed in humans</mark> </strong>than in chimpanzees.</u> In fact, these researchers found that a gene called <u><strong><mark>ability to pursue</strong></mark> various <strong><mark>rewards that are</strong></mark> perhaps months or even <strong><mark>years away </u></strong></mark>in the future. This same idea has been suggested by Dr. Robert Sapolsky, a professor of biology and neurology at Stanford University. Dr. Sapolsky cited evidence that dopamine levels rise dramatically in humans when we anticipate potential rewards that are uncertain and even far off in our futures, such as retirement or even the possible alterlife. <u>This may explain what often motivates people to work for things that have no apparent short-term benefit</u><strong> [51]. In similar work, Volkow and Bale [52] proposed a model in which dopamine can favor NOW processes through phasic signaling in reward circuits or LATER processes through tonic signaling in control circuits. Specifically, they suggest that through its modulation of the orbitofrontal cortex, which processes salience attribution, dopamine also enables shilting from NOW to LATER, while its modulation of the insula, which processes interoceptive information, influences the probability of selecting NOW versus LATER actions based on an individual’s physiological state. This hypothesis further supports the concept that disruptions along these circuits contribute to diverse pathologies, including obesity and addiction or RDS.</p></strong>
CPS R1 v Harker MK
1AC—Schengenlargement
1AC—Framing—Util
41,540
3,168
151,640
./documents/hsld22/MountainHouse/ElSu/MountainHouse-ElSu-Aff-CPS-LD-Invitational-Round-4.docx
957,717
A
CPS LD Invitational
4
Harker MK
Lukas Krause
1AC - Schengenlargement 1NC - T-cohen, EU CP, case 1AR - all 2NR - case 2AR - T case
hsld22/MountainHouse/ElSu/MountainHouse-ElSu-Aff-CPS-LD-Invitational-Round-4.docx
2023-01-02 23:45:29
79,525
ElSu
Mountain House ElSu
See 0 - Contact Info in cites for disclosure, etc.
El.....
Su.....
null
null
26,667
MountainHouse
Mountain House
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
2,300,886
[6] Extinction comes first!
Pummer 15
Pummer 15 [Theron, Junior Research Fellow in Philosophy at St. Anne's College, University of Oxford. “Moral Agreement on Saving the World” Practical Ethics, University of Oxford. May 18, 2015] AT
There appears to be lot of disagreement in moral philosophy. Whether these many apparent disagreements are deep and irresolvable, I believe there is at least one thing it is reasonable to agree on right now : that it is very important to reduce the risk that all intelligent beings on this planet are eliminated by an enormous catastrophe, such as a nuclear war. we – whether we’re consequentialists, deontologists, or virtue ethicists – should all agree that we should try to save the world. Clearly one thing that makes an outcome good is that the people in it are doing well. There is little disagreement here. reducing existential risk is easily the most important thing in the whole world. This is for the familiar reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. There are so many possible future people that reducing existential risk is arguably the most important thing in the world, even if the well-being of these possible people were given only 0.001% as much weight as that of existing people. this case is strengthened by the fact that there’s a good chance that many existing people will, with the aid of life-extension technology, live very long and very high quality lives. You might think what I have just argued applies to consequentialists only. There is a tendency to assume that, if an argument appeals to consequentialist considerations (the goodness of outcomes), it is irrelevant to non-consequentialists. But that is a huge mistake. Non-consequentialism is the view that there’s more that determines rightness than the goodness of consequences or outcomes; it is not the view that the latter don’t matter. All ethical doctrines worth our attention take consequences into account in judging rightness. One which did not would simply be irrational, crazy. Minimally plausible versions of deontology and virtue ethics must be concerned in part with promoting the good, from an impartial point of view. They’d thus imply very strong reasons to reduce existential risk Even egoism, the view that each agent should maximize her own good, might imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. To be minimally plausible, egoism will need to be paired with a more sophisticated account of well-being. suppose that, while wearing it, Ayn could derive some pleasure by helping the poor, but instead could derive just a bit more by severely harming them. Hedonistic egoism would absurdly imply she should do the latter. To avoid this implication, egoists would need to build something like the meaningfulness of a life into well-being once these elements are included, we can (roughly, as above) argue that this sort of egoism will imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. We should also take into account moral uncertainty. What is it reasonable for one to do, when one is uncertain not (only) about the empirical facts, but also about the moral facts? there’s agreement among minimally plausible ethical views that we have strong reason to reduce existential risk – not only consequentialists, but also deontologists, virtue ethicists, and sophisticated egoists should agree. even those (hedonistic egoists) who disagree should have a significant level of confidence that they are mistaken, and that one of the above views is correct. Even if they were 90% sure that their view is the correct one they would have pretty strong reason, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, to reduce existential risk. even if we are only 1% sure that the well-being of possible future people matters, it is at least arguable that, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, reducing existential risk is the most important thing in the world. It is enough for my claim that there is moral agreement in the relevant sense if all minimally plausible moral views would converge on the conclusion that we should try to save the world. views that place significantly greater moral weight on avoiding suffering than on promoting happiness seem to be fairly implausible views. even if things did not go well for our ancestors, I am optimistic that they will overall go fantastically well for our descendants, if we allow them to. I suspect that most of us alive today – at least those of us not suffering from extreme illness or poverty – have lives that are well worth living, and that things will continue to improve. Given the scientific and technological discoveries of the last two centuries, the world has never changed as fast. If we act wisely in the next few centuries, humanity will survive its most dangerous and decisive period. Our descendants might, I believe, make the further future very good. But that good future may also depend in part on us. If our selfish recklessness ends human history, we would be acting very wrongly.
reducing existential risk is the most important thing in the whole world. so many people could exist in the future trillions upon trillions reducing existential risk is the most important even if the well-being of these possible people were given only 0.001% as much weight We should also take into account moral uncertainty. even if we are only 1% sure that well-being
There appears to be lot of disagreement in moral philosophy. Whether these many apparent disagreements are deep and irresolvable, I believe there is at least one thing it is reasonable to agree on right now, whatever general moral view we adopt: that it is very important to reduce the risk that all intelligent beings on this planet are eliminated by an enormous catastrophe, such as a nuclear war. How we might in fact try to reduce such existential risks is discussed elsewhere. My claim here is only that we – whether we’re consequentialists, deontologists, or virtue ethicists – should all agree that we should try to save the world. According to consequentialism, we should maximize the good, where this is taken to be the goodness, from an impartial perspective, of outcomes. Clearly one thing that makes an outcome good is that the people in it are doing well. There is little disagreement here. If the happiness or well-being of possible future people is just as important as that of people who already exist, and if they would have good lives, it is not hard to see how reducing existential risk is easily the most important thing in the whole world. This is for the familiar reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. There are so many possible future people that reducing existential risk is arguably the most important thing in the world, even if the well-being of these possible people were given only 0.001% as much weight as that of existing people. Even on a wholly person-affecting view – according to which there’s nothing (apart from effects on existing people) to be said in favor of creating happy people – the case for reducing existential risk is very strong. As noted in this seminal paper, this case is strengthened by the fact that there’s a good chance that many existing people will, with the aid of life-extension technology, live very long and very high quality lives. You might think what I have just argued applies to consequentialists only. There is a tendency to assume that, if an argument appeals to consequentialist considerations (the goodness of outcomes), it is irrelevant to non-consequentialists. But that is a huge mistake. Non-consequentialism is the view that there’s more that determines rightness than the goodness of consequences or outcomes; it is not the view that the latter don’t matter. Even John Rawls wrote, “All ethical doctrines worth our attention take consequences into account in judging rightness. One which did not would simply be irrational, crazy.” Minimally plausible versions of deontology and virtue ethics must be concerned in part with promoting the good, from an impartial point of view. They’d thus imply very strong reasons to reduce existential risk, at least when this doesn’t significantly involve doing harm to others or damaging one’s character. What’s even more surprising, perhaps, is that even if our own good (or that of those near and dear to us) has much greater weight than goodness from the impartial “point of view of the universe,” indeed even if the latter is entirely morally irrelevant, we may nonetheless have very strong reasons to reduce existential risk. Even egoism, the view that each agent should maximize her own good, might imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. It will depend, among other things, on what one’s own good consists in. If well-being consisted in pleasure only, it is somewhat harder to argue that egoism would imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk – perhaps we could argue that one would maximize her expected hedonic well-being by funding life extension technology or by having herself cryogenically frozen at the time of her bodily death as well as giving money to reduce existential risk (so that there is a world for her to live in!). I am not sure, however, how strong the reasons to do this would be. But views which imply that, if I don’t care about other people, I have no or very little reason to help them are not even minimally plausible views (in addition to hedonistic egoism, I here have in mind views that imply that one has no reason to perform an act unless one actually desires to do that act). To be minimally plausible, egoism will need to be paired with a more sophisticated account of well-being. To see this, it is enough to consider, as Plato did, the possibility of a ring of invisibility – suppose that, while wearing it, Ayn could derive some pleasure by helping the poor, but instead could derive just a bit more by severely harming them. Hedonistic egoism would absurdly imply she should do the latter. To avoid this implication, egoists would need to build something like the meaningfulness of a life into well-being, in some robust way, where this would to a significant extent be a function of other-regarding concerns (see chapter 12 of this classic intro to ethics). But once these elements are included, we can (roughly, as above) argue that this sort of egoism will imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. Add to all of this Samuel Scheffler’s recent intriguing arguments (quick podcast version available here) that most of what makes our lives go well would be undermined if there were no future generations of intelligent persons. On his view, my life would contain vastly less well-being if (say) a year after my death the world came to an end. So obviously if Scheffler were right I’d have very strong reason to reduce existential risk. We should also take into account moral uncertainty. What is it reasonable for one to do, when one is uncertain not (only) about the empirical facts, but also about the moral facts? I’ve just argued that there’s agreement among minimally plausible ethical views that we have strong reason to reduce existential risk – not only consequentialists, but also deontologists, virtue ethicists, and sophisticated egoists should agree. But even those (hedonistic egoists) who disagree should have a significant level of confidence that they are mistaken, and that one of the above views is correct. Even if they were 90% sure that their view is the correct one (and 10% sure that one of these other ones is correct), they would have pretty strong reason, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, to reduce existential risk. Perhaps most disturbingly still, even if we are only 1% sure that the well-being of possible future people matters, it is at least arguable that, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, reducing existential risk is the most important thing in the world. Again, this is largely for the reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. (For more on this and other related issues, see this excellent dissertation). Of course, it is uncertain whether these untold trillions would, in general, have good lives. It’s possible they’ll be miserable. It is enough for my claim that there is moral agreement in the relevant sense if, at least given certain empirical claims about what future lives would most likely be like, all minimally plausible moral views would converge on the conclusion that we should try to save the world. While there are some non-crazy views that place significantly greater moral weight on avoiding suffering than on promoting happiness, for reasons others have offered (and for independent reasons I won’t get into here unless requested to), they nonetheless seem to be fairly implausible views. And even if things did not go well for our ancestors, I am optimistic that they will overall go fantastically well for our descendants, if we allow them to. I suspect that most of us alive today – at least those of us not suffering from extreme illness or poverty – have lives that are well worth living, and that things will continue to improve. Derek Parfit, whose work has emphasized future generations as well as agreement in ethics, described our situation clearly and accurately: “We live during the hinge of history. Given the scientific and technological discoveries of the last two centuries, the world has never changed as fast. We shall soon have even greater powers to transform, not only our surroundings, but ourselves and our successors. If we act wisely in the next few centuries, humanity will survive its most dangerous and decisive period. Our descendants could, if necessary, go elsewhere, spreading through this galaxy…. Our descendants might, I believe, make the further future very good. But that good future may also depend in part on us. If our selfish recklessness ends human history, we would be acting very wrongly.” (From chapter 36 of On What Matters)
8,686
<h4>[6] Extinction comes first!</h4><p><u><strong>Pummer 15</u></strong> [Theron, Junior Research Fellow in Philosophy at St. Anne's College, University of Oxford. “Moral Agreement on Saving the World” Practical Ethics, University of Oxford. May 18, 2015] AT</p><p><u><strong>There appears to be lot of disagreement in moral philosophy. Whether these many apparent disagreements are deep and irresolvable, I believe there is at least one thing it is reasonable to agree on right now</u></strong>, whatever general moral view we adopt<u><strong>: that it is very important to reduce the risk that all intelligent beings on this planet are eliminated by an enormous catastrophe, such as a nuclear war.</u></strong> How we might in fact try to reduce such existential risks is discussed elsewhere. My claim here is only that <u><strong>we – whether we’re consequentialists, deontologists, or virtue ethicists – should all agree that we should try to save the world. </u></strong>According to consequentialism, we should maximize the good, where this is taken to be the goodness, from an impartial perspective, of outcomes. <u><strong>Clearly one thing that makes an outcome good is that the people in it are doing well. There is little disagreement here.</u></strong> If the happiness or well-being of possible future people is just as important as that of people who already exist, and if they would have good lives, it is not hard to see how<u><strong> <mark>reducing existential risk is </mark>easily <mark>the most important thing in the whole world.</mark> This is for the familiar reason that there are <mark>so many people </mark>who <mark>could exist in the future</mark> – there are <mark>trillions upon trillions</mark>… upon trillions. There are so many possible future people that <mark>reducing existential risk is</mark> arguably <mark>the most important</mark> thing in the world, <mark>even if the well-being of these possible people were given only 0.001% as much weight </mark>as that of existing people.</u></strong> Even on a wholly person-affecting view – according to which there’s nothing (apart from effects on existing people) to be said in favor of creating happy people – the case for reducing existential risk is very strong. As noted in this seminal paper, <u><strong>this case is strengthened by the fact that there’s a good chance that many existing people will, with the aid of life-extension technology, live very long and very high quality lives. You might think what I have just argued applies to consequentialists only. There is a tendency to assume that, if an argument appeals to consequentialist considerations (the goodness of outcomes), it is irrelevant to non-consequentialists. But that is a huge mistake.</u></strong> <u><strong>Non-consequentialism is the view that there’s more that determines rightness than the goodness of consequences or outcomes; it is not the view that the latter don’t matter.</u></strong> Even John Rawls wrote, “<u><strong>All ethical doctrines worth our attention take consequences into account in judging rightness. One which did not would simply be irrational, crazy.</u></strong>” <u><strong>Minimally plausible versions of deontology and virtue ethics must be concerned in part with promoting the good, from an impartial point of view.</u></strong> <u><strong>They’d thus imply very strong reasons to reduce existential risk</u></strong>, at least when this doesn’t significantly involve doing harm to others or damaging one’s character. What’s even more surprising, perhaps, is that even if our own good (or that of those near and dear to us) has much greater weight than goodness from the impartial “point of view of the universe,” indeed even if the latter is entirely morally irrelevant, we may nonetheless have very strong reasons to reduce existential risk. <u><strong>Even egoism, the view that each agent should maximize her own good, might imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk.</u></strong> It will depend, among other things, on what one’s own good consists in. If well-being consisted in pleasure only, it is somewhat harder to argue that egoism would imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk – perhaps we could argue that one would maximize her expected hedonic well-being by funding life extension technology or by having herself cryogenically frozen at the time of her bodily death as well as giving money to reduce existential risk (so that there is a world for her to live in!). I am not sure, however, how strong the reasons to do this would be. But views which imply that, if I don’t care about other people, I have no or very little reason to help them are not even minimally plausible views (in addition to hedonistic egoism, I here have in mind views that imply that one has no reason to perform an act unless one actually desires to do that act). <u><strong>To be minimally plausible, egoism will need to be paired with a more sophisticated account of well-being.</u></strong> To see this, it is enough to consider, as Plato did, the possibility of a ring of invisibility – <u><strong>suppose that, while wearing it, Ayn could derive some pleasure by helping the poor, but instead could derive just a bit more by severely harming them. Hedonistic egoism would absurdly imply she should do the latter. To avoid this implication, egoists would need to build something like the meaningfulness of a life into well-being</u></strong>, in some robust way, where this would to a significant extent be a function of other-regarding concerns (see chapter 12 of this classic intro to ethics). But <u><strong>once these elements are included, we can (roughly, as above) argue that this sort of egoism will imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk.</u></strong> Add to all of this Samuel Scheffler’s recent intriguing arguments (quick podcast version available here) that most of what makes our lives go well would be undermined if there were no future generations of intelligent persons. On his view, my life would contain vastly less well-being if (say) a year after my death the world came to an end. So obviously if Scheffler were right I’d have very strong reason to reduce existential risk. <u><strong><mark>We should also take into account moral uncertainty.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>What is it reasonable for one to do, when one is uncertain not (only) about the empirical facts, but also about the moral facts?</u></strong> I’ve just argued that <u><strong>there’s agreement among minimally plausible ethical views that we have strong reason to reduce existential risk – not only consequentialists, but also deontologists, virtue ethicists, and sophisticated egoists should agree.</u></strong> But <u><strong>even those (hedonistic egoists) who disagree should have a significant level of confidence that they are mistaken, and that one of the above views is correct. Even if they were 90% sure that their view is the correct one </u></strong>(and 10% sure that one of these other ones is correct), <u><strong>they would have pretty strong reason, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, to reduce existential risk.</u></strong> Perhaps most disturbingly still, <u><strong><mark>even if we are only 1% sure that </mark>the <mark>well-being </mark>of possible future people matters, it is at least arguable that, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, reducing existential risk is the most important thing in the world.</u></strong> Again, this is largely for the reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. (For more on this and other related issues, see this excellent dissertation). Of course, it is uncertain whether these untold trillions would, in general, have good lives. It’s possible they’ll be miserable. <u><strong>It is enough for my claim that there is moral agreement in the relevant sense if</u></strong>, at least given certain empirical claims about what future lives would most likely be like, <u><strong>all minimally plausible moral views would converge on the conclusion that we should try to save the world.</u></strong> While there are some non-crazy <u><strong>views that place significantly greater moral weight on avoiding suffering than on promoting happiness</u></strong>, for reasons others have offered (and for independent reasons I won’t get into here unless requested to), they nonetheless <u><strong>seem to be fairly implausible views.</u></strong> And <u><strong>even if things did not go well for our ancestors, I am optimistic that they will overall go fantastically well for our descendants, if we allow them to. I suspect that most of us alive today – at least those of us not suffering from extreme illness or poverty – have lives that are well worth living, and that things will continue to improve.</u></strong> Derek Parfit, whose work has emphasized future generations as well as agreement in ethics, described our situation clearly and accurately: “We live during the hinge of history. <u><strong>Given the scientific and technological discoveries of the last two centuries, the world has never changed as fast. </u></strong>We shall soon have even greater powers to transform, not only our surroundings, but ourselves and our successors. <u><strong>If we act wisely in the next few centuries, humanity will survive its most dangerous and decisive period. </u></strong>Our descendants could, if necessary, go elsewhere, spreading through this galaxy…. <u><strong>Our descendants might, I believe, make the further future very good. But that good future may also depend in part on us. If our selfish recklessness ends human history, we would be acting very wrongly.</u></strong>” (From chapter 36 of On What Matters)</p>
Harvard Round 7
null
Framework
12,186
5,631
72,468
./documents/hsld20/Oxford/Me/Oxford-Mehta-Aff-Harvard-Round7.docx
870,004
A
Harvard
7
North Allegheny RR
Daniel Herrera
1AC - China v7 1NC - LogCon Must Spec LAWs Must have Solvency Advocate Must Not Read Epistemic Modesty and Extinction ow Case 1AR - All 2NR - Eval after 1NC Must Not Read Epistemic Modesty and Extinction ow 2AR - Case Lying Voter Skep RVI Must Not Read Epistemic Modesty and Extinction ow
hsld20/Oxford/Me/Oxford-Mehta-Aff-Harvard-Round7.docx
null
73,609
ViMe
Oxford ViMe
null
Vi.....
Me.....
null
null
24,667
Oxford
Oxford
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
1,414,394
Only pleasure and pain are intrinsically valuable – all other frameworks collapse.
Moen 16
Moen 16 [Ole Martin Moen, Research Fellow in Philosophy at University of Oslo “An Argument for Hedonism” Journal of Value Inquiry (Springer), 50 (2) 2016: 267–281]
a widely shared judgment about intrinsic value and disvalue is that pleasure is intrinsically valuable and pain is intrinsically disvaluable. On virtually any proposed list of intrinsic values and disvalues (we will look at some of them below), pleasure is included among the intrinsic values and pain among the intrinsic disvalues. there is something undeniably good about the way pleasure feels and something undeniably bad about the way pain feels, and neither the goodness of pleasure nor the badness of pain seems to be exhausted by the further effects that these experiences might have. The special value statuses of pleasure and pain are manifested in how we treat these experiences in our everyday reasoning about values. I might ask: “What for?” This is a reasonable question, for when you go to the convenience store you usually do so for the sake of achieving something further that you deem to be valuable. If I then proceed by asking “But what is the pleasure of drinking the soda good for?” the discussion is likely to reach an awkward end. The reason is that the pleasure is not good for anything further; it is simply that for which going to the convenience store and buying the soda is good. : “We never ask [a man] what his end is in being pleased, because we assume that pleasure is choice worthy in itself. pleasure and pain are both places where we reach the end of the line in matters of value
pleasure is intrinsically valuable and pain is intrinsically disvaluable there is something undeniably good about pleasure and something undeniably bad about pain value statuses of pleasure and pain are manifested in how we treat experiences pleasure is not good for anything further pleasure and pain both reach the end of the line in matters of value
Let us start by observing, empirically, that a widely shared judgment about intrinsic value and disvalue is that pleasure is intrinsically valuable and pain is intrinsically disvaluable. On virtually any proposed list of intrinsic values and disvalues (we will look at some of them below), pleasure is included among the intrinsic values and pain among the intrinsic disvalues. This inclusion makes intuitive sense, moreover, for there is something undeniably good about the way pleasure feels and something undeniably bad about the way pain feels, and neither the goodness of pleasure nor the badness of pain seems to be exhausted by the further effects that these experiences might have. “Pleasure” and “pain” are here understood inclusively, as encompassing anything hedonically positive and anything hedonically negative.2 The special value statuses of pleasure and pain are manifested in how we treat these experiences in our everyday reasoning about values. If you tell me that you are heading for the convenience store, I might ask: “What for?” This is a reasonable question, for when you go to the convenience store you usually do so, not merely for the sake of going to the convenience store, but for the sake of achieving something further that you deem to be valuable. You might answer, for example: “To buy soda.” This answer makes sense, for soda is a nice thing and you can get it at the convenience store. I might further inquire, however: “What is buying the soda good for?” This further question can also be a reasonable one, for it need not be obvious why you want the soda. You might answer: “Well, I want it for the pleasure of drinking it.” If I then proceed by asking “But what is the pleasure of drinking the soda good for?” the discussion is likely to reach an awkward end. The reason is that the pleasure is not good for anything further; it is simply that for which going to the convenience store and buying the soda is good.3 As Aristotle observes: “We never ask [a man] what his end is in being pleased, because we assume that pleasure is choice worthy in itself.”4 Presumably, a similar story can be told in the case of pains, for if someone says “This is painful!” we never respond by asking: “And why is that a problem?” We take for granted that if something is painful, we have a sufficient explanation of why it is bad. If we are onto something in our everyday reasoning about values, it seems that pleasure and pain are both places where we reach the end of the line in matters of value
2,520
<h4>Only pleasure and pain are intrinsically valuable – all other frameworks collapse.</h4><p><strong>Moen 16</strong> [Ole Martin Moen, Research Fellow in Philosophy at University of Oslo “An Argument for Hedonism” Journal of Value Inquiry (Springer), 50 (2) 2016: 267–281]</p><p>Let us start by observing, empirically, that <u>a widely shared judgment about intrinsic value and disvalue is that <mark>pleasure is intrinsically valuable and pain is intrinsically disvaluable</mark>.</u> <u>On virtually any proposed list of intrinsic values and disvalues (we will look at some of them below), pleasure is included among the intrinsic values and pain among the intrinsic disvalues.</u> This inclusion makes intuitive sense, moreover, for <u><mark>there is something undeniably good about</mark> the way <mark>pleasure</mark> feels <mark>and something undeniably bad about</mark> the way <mark>pain</mark> feels, and neither the goodness of pleasure nor the badness of pain seems to be exhausted by the further effects that these experiences might have.</u> “Pleasure” and “pain” are here understood inclusively, as encompassing anything hedonically positive and anything hedonically negative.2 <u>The special <mark>value statuses of pleasure and pain are manifested in how we treat</mark> these <mark>experiences </mark>in our everyday reasoning about values.</u> If you tell me that you are heading for the convenience store, <u>I might ask: “What for?” This is a reasonable question, for when you go to the convenience store you usually do so</u>, not merely for the sake of going to the convenience store, but <u>for the sake of achieving something further that you deem to be valuable.</u> You might answer, for example: “To buy soda.” This answer makes sense, for soda is a nice thing and you can get it at the convenience store. I might further inquire, however: “What is buying the soda good for?” This further question can also be a reasonable one, for it need not be obvious why you want the soda. You might answer: “Well, I want it for the pleasure of drinking it.” <u>If I then proceed by asking “But what is the pleasure of drinking the soda good for?” the discussion is likely to reach an awkward end. The reason is that the <mark>pleasure is not good for anything further</mark>; it is simply that for which going to the convenience store and buying the soda is good.</u>3 As Aristotle observes<u>: “We never ask [a man] what his end is in being pleased, because we assume that pleasure is choice worthy in itself.</u>”4 Presumably, a similar story can be told in the case of pains, for if someone says “This is painful!” we never respond by asking: “And why is that a problem?” We take for granted that if something is painful, we have a sufficient explanation of why it is bad. If we are onto something in our everyday reasoning about values, it seems that <u><mark>pleasure and pain</mark> are <mark>both</mark> places where we <mark>reach the end of the line in matters of value</p></u></mark>
null
Util
null
21,420
4,449
38,491
./documents/hsld21/HarvardWestlake/Le2/Harvard%20Westlake-Leee-Neg-Cal-Round4.docx
888,401
N
Cal
4
Fairview CS
Aqui, Nikki
Innovation China Heg Util Theory-Actor Democracy bad
hsld21/HarvardWestlake/Le2/Harvard%20Westlake-Leee-Neg-Cal-Round4.docx
null
74,743
MaLe
Harvard Westlake MaLe
null
Ma.....
Le.....
null
null
25,010
HarvardWestlake
Harvard Westlake
CA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
1,944,270
Warming causes extinction.
Ng 19
Ng 19 [Yew-Kwang; May 2019; Professor of Economics at Nanyang Technology University, Fellow of the Academy of Social Sciences in Australia and Member of the Advisory Board at the Global Priorities Institute at Oxford University, Ph.D. in Economics from Sydney University; Global Policy, “Keynote: Global Extinction and Animal Welfare: Two Priorities for Effective Altruism,” vol. 10, no. 2, p. 258-266; RP]
climate change causing global extinction is possible due to interrelated factors of non‐linearity, cascading effects, positive feedbacks, multiplicative factors, critical thresholds and tipping points A imminent tipping point could be ‘an abrupt ice sheet collapse [that] could cause rapid sea level rise’ There are many avenues for positive feedback replacement of an ice sea by a liquid surface from melting increases absorption of sunlight, leading to faster warming drying of forests increases forest fires and release of more carbon ocean temperatures lead to release of methane producing runaway global warming ‘The world is completely unprepared to envisage, and deal with CCC’ The threat of sea‐level rising from warming is well known, but there likely and imminent threats to the survivability of mankind the adaptability limit to climate change due to heat stress from high temperature ‘even modest warming could expose large fractions of the [world] to unprecedented heat stress’ and with substantial warming, ‘the area of land rendered uninhabitable would dwarf sea level’ making extinction likely and the moderate assessment models unreliably low we cannot rule it out probabilities of 5 per cent, 0.5 per cent or even 0.005 per cent of excessive warming and resulting extinction probabilities cannot be ruled out and are unacceptable. Even if there is only a 1 per cent probability that there is a bomb in the airplane, you want to change your flight. Extinction of the whole world is more important to avoid by a trillion times
climate causing extinction is due to non‐linearity, cascading feedbacks and tipping points ice sheet collapse cause rapid sea rise’ faster warming forest fires and release of methane producing runaway warming adaptability limit to mak extinction likely and moderate models unreliabl Even if there is 1 per cent probability Extinction is more important by a trillion
Catastrophic climate change Though by no means certain, CCC causing global extinction is possible due to interrelated factors of non‐linearity, cascading effects, positive feedbacks, multiplicative factors, critical thresholds and tipping points (e.g. Barnosky and Hadly, 2016; Belaia et al., 2017; Buldyrev et al., 2010; Grainger, 2017; Hansen and Sato, 2012; IPCC 2014; Kareiva and Carranza, 2018; Osmond and Klausmeier, 2017; Rothman, 2017; Schuur et al., 2015; Sims and Finnoff, 2016; Van Aalst, 2006).7 A possibly imminent tipping point could be in the form of ‘an abrupt ice sheet collapse [that] could cause a rapid sea level rise’ (Baum et al., 2011, p. 399). There are many avenues for positive feedback in global warming, including: the replacement of an ice sea by a liquid ocean surface from melting reduces the reflection and increases the absorption of sunlight, leading to faster warming; the drying of forests from warming increases forest fires and the release of more carbon; and higher ocean temperatures may lead to the release of methane trapped under the ocean floor, producing runaway global warming. Though there are also avenues for negative feedback, the scientific consensus is for an overall net positive feedback (Roe and Baker, 2007). Thus, the Global Challenges Foundation (2017, p. 25) concludes, ‘The world is currently completely unprepared to envisage, and even less deal with, the consequences of CCC’. The threat of sea‐level rising from global warming is well known, but there are also other likely and more imminent threats to the survivability of mankind and other living things. For example, Sherwood and Huber (2010) emphasize the adaptability limit to climate change due to heat stress from high environmental wet‐bulb temperature. They show that ‘even modest global warming could … expose large fractions of the [world] population to unprecedented heat stress’ p. 9552 and that with substantial global warming, ‘the area of land rendered uninhabitable by heat stress would dwarf that affected by rising sea level’ p. 9555, making extinction much more likely and the relatively moderate damages estimated by most integrated assessment models unreliably low. While imminent extinction is very unlikely and may not come for a long time even under business as usual, the main point is that we cannot rule it out. Annan and Hargreaves (2011, pp. 434–435) may be right that there is ‘an upper 95 per cent probability limit for S [temperature increase] … to lie close to 4°C, and certainly well below 6°C’. However, probabilities of 5 per cent, 0.5 per cent, 0.05 per cent or even 0.005 per cent of excessive warming and the resulting extinction probabilities cannot be ruled out and are unacceptable. Even if there is only a 1 per cent probability that there is a time bomb in the airplane, you probably want to change your flight. Extinction of the whole world is more important to avoid by literally a trillion times.
2,957
<h4>Warming causes extinction.</h4><p><strong>Ng 19 </strong>[Yew-Kwang; May 2019; Professor of Economics at Nanyang Technology University, Fellow of the Academy of Social Sciences in Australia and Member of the Advisory Board at the Global Priorities Institute at Oxford University, Ph.D. in Economics from Sydney University; Global Policy, “Keynote: Global Extinction and Animal Welfare: Two Priorities for Effective Altruism,” vol. 10, no. 2, p. 258-266; RP]</p><p>Catastrophic <u><mark>climate</mark> change</u> Though by no means certain, CCC <u><mark>causing</mark> <strong>global <mark>extinction</strong> is</mark> possible <mark>due to</mark> <strong>interrelated factors</strong> of <strong><mark>non‐linearity</strong>, <strong>cascading</mark> effects</strong>, <strong>positive <mark>feedbacks</strong></mark>, <strong>multiplicative factors</strong>, <strong>critical thresholds</strong> <mark>and <strong>tipping points</u></strong></mark> (e.g. Barnosky and Hadly, 2016; Belaia et al., 2017; Buldyrev et al., 2010; Grainger, 2017; Hansen and Sato, 2012; IPCC 2014; Kareiva and Carranza, 2018; Osmond and Klausmeier, 2017; Rothman, 2017; Schuur et al., 2015; Sims and Finnoff, 2016; Van Aalst, 2006).7 <u>A</u> possibly <u><strong>imminent</strong> tipping point could be</u> in the form of <u>‘an abrupt <strong><mark>ice sheet collapse</strong></mark> [that] could <mark>cause</u></mark> a <u><strong><mark>rapid</strong> sea</mark> level <mark>rise’</u></mark> (Baum et al., 2011, p. 399). <u>There are many avenues for <strong>positive feedback</u></strong> in global warming, including: the <u>replacement of an ice sea by a liquid</u> ocean <u>surface from melting</u> reduces the reflection and <u><strong>increases</u></strong> the <u><strong>absorption</strong> of sunlight, leading to <strong><mark>faster warming</u></strong></mark>; the <u>drying of <strong>forests</u></strong> from warming <u>increases <mark>forest fires and</u></mark> the <u>release of <strong>more carbon</u></strong>; and higher <u>ocean temperatures</u> may <u>lead to</u> the <u><mark>release of <strong>methane</u></strong></mark> trapped under the ocean floor, <u><mark>producing</mark> <strong><mark>runaway</strong></mark> global <mark>warming</u></mark>. Though there are also avenues for negative feedback, the scientific consensus is for an overall net positive feedback (Roe and Baker, 2007). Thus, the Global Challenges Foundation (2017, p. 25) concludes, <u>‘The world is</u> currently <u><strong>completely unprepared</strong> to envisage, and</u> even less <u>deal with</u>, the consequences of <u>CCC’</u>. <u>The threat of <strong>sea‐level rising</strong> from</u> global <u>warming is well known, but there</u> are also other <u><strong>likely</strong> and</u> more <u><strong>imminent</strong> threats to the <strong>survivability of mankind</u></strong> and other living things. For example, Sherwood and Huber (2010) emphasize <u>the <strong><mark>adaptability limit</strong> to</mark> climate change due to <strong>heat stress</strong> from high</u> environmental wet‐bulb <u>temperature</u>. They show that <u>‘even <strong>modest</strong> </u>global <u>warming could</u> … <u>expose <strong>large fractions</strong> of the [world]</u> population <u>to <strong>unprecedented</strong> heat stress’</u> p. 9552 <u>and</u> that <u>with substantial</u> global <u>warming, ‘the area of land rendered <strong>uninhabitable</u></strong> by heat stress <u>would dwarf</u> that affected by rising <u>sea level’</u> p. 9555, <u><mark>mak</mark>ing <strong><mark>extinction</u></strong></mark> much more <u><strong><mark>likely</strong> and</mark> the</u> relatively <u><mark>moderate</u></mark> damages estimated by most integrated <u>assessment <mark>models <strong>unreliabl</mark>y low</u></strong>. While imminent extinction is very unlikely and may not come for a long time even under business as usual, the main point is that <u>we cannot rule it out</u>. Annan and Hargreaves (2011, pp. 434–435) may be right that there is ‘an upper 95 per cent probability limit for S [temperature increase] … to lie close to 4°C, and certainly well below 6°C’. However, <u>probabilities of 5 per cent, 0.5 per cent</u>, 0.05 per cent <u>or even <strong>0.005 per cent</strong> of excessive warming and</u> the <u>resulting <strong>extinction probabilities</strong> cannot be ruled out and are <strong>unacceptable</strong>. <mark>Even if there is</mark> only a <strong><mark>1 per cent probability</strong></mark> that there is a</u> time <u>bomb in the airplane, you</u> probably <u>want to change your flight. <mark>Extinction</mark> of the <strong>whole world</strong> <mark>is <strong>more important</strong></mark> to avoid <mark>by</mark> </u>literally <u><mark>a <strong>trillion</mark> times</u></strong>.</p>
1nc
OFF
null
5,339
2,139
57,355
./documents/hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/LaPe/Mamaroneck-Land-Peters-Neg-toc-Round1.docx
734,302
N
toc
1
gunn os
pak, andrew
1ac -- mandatory minimums 2nr -- cap
hspolicy20/Mamaroneck/LaPe/Mamaroneck-Land-Peters-Neg-toc-Round1.docx
null
62,633
LaPe
Mamaroneck LaPe
null
Ja.....
La.....
Lu.....
Pe.....
21,706
Mamaroneck
Mamaroneck
NY
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
541,455
Decline cascades – nuclear war
Maavak 21
Maavak 21 – Mathew Maavak, PhD in Risk Foresight from the Universiti Teknologi Malaysia, External Researcher (PLATBIDAFO) at the Kazimieras Simonavicius University, Expert and Regular Commentator on Risk-Related Geostrategic Issues at the Russian International Affairs Council, “Horizon 2030: Will Emerging Risks Unravel Our Global Systems?”, Salus Journal – The Australian Journal for Law Enforcement, Security and Intelligence Professionals, Volume 9, Number 1, p. 2-8
scholars regard global social instability as the greatest threat The catalyst has been postulated to be a Second Great Depression which, in turn, will have profound implications for global security and national integrity emerging risks are intertwined Tight couplings in global systems have enabled risks accrued in one area to snowball into a full-blown crisis elsewhere banking, utility, farming, healthcare and retail sectors etc. are increasingly entwined. Risks accrued in one system may cascade into an unforeseen crisis the behaviour of intersecting systems is determined by complex and largely invisible interactions at the substratum a global financial crash will lead to a trickle-down meltdown, impacting all areas of human activity and lead to a Second Great Depression Economic stressors may induce radical geopolitical realignments. Bullions now carry more weight than NATO’s security guarantees in Eastern Europe this erosion in regional trust was based on historical precedents with two global Titanics – the U S and China on a collision course the seismic ripples will be felt far, wide and for a considerable period What happens to the environment when our economies implode? Think of a debt-laden workforce at sensitive nuclear and chemical plants, along with a concomitant surge in industrial accidents? Economic stressors pose the biggest threats to the environment global risks can no longer be boxed into a taxonomical silo Our JIT world aggravates the cascading potential of risks Production and delivery delays will eventually require industrial overcompensation Interlinked ecosystems may be hijacked The environmental fallouts loom like a Sword of Damocles over this decade The primary catalyst behind WWII was the Great Depression history often repeats itself, expect familiar bogeymen to reappear in societies roiling with impoverishment Anti-Semitism may reach alarming proportions possibly forcing Israel to undertake reprisal operations how will affected nations react? Balloon effects present a classic problematic Contemporary geopolitical risks include a possible Iran-Israel war; US-China military confrontation over Taiwan or the South China Sea; North Korean proliferation of nuclear and missile technologies; an India-Pakistan nuclear war; an Iranian closure of the Straits of Hormuz; fundamentalist-driven implosion in the Islamic world; or a nuclear confrontation between NATO and Russia
a Second Depression will have implications for global security couplings in global systems enabled risks in one area to snowball into full-blown crisis elsewhere banking farming, health and retail are entwined Economic stressors induce geopolitical realignments with U S and China ripples will be felt Think of a debt-laden workforce at nuclear and chemical plants with a surge in accidents The catalyst behind WWII was the Depression history repeats itself Balloon effects include Iran war; US-China confrontation over Taiwan India-Paki nuclear war NATO and Russia
Various scholars and institutions regard global social instability as the greatest threat facing this decade. The catalyst has been postulated to be a Second Great Depression which, in turn, will have profound implications for global security and national integrity. This paper, written from a broad systems perspective, illustrates how emerging risks are getting more complex and intertwined; blurring boundaries between the economic, environmental, geopolitical, societal and technological taxonomy used by the World Economic Forum for its annual global risk forecasts. Tight couplings in our global systems have also enabled risks accrued in one area to snowball into a full-blown crisis elsewhere. The COVID-19 pandemic and its socioeconomic fallouts exemplify this systemic chain-reaction. Onceinexorable forces of globalization are rupturing as the current global system can no longer be sustained due to poor governance and runaway wealth fractionation. The coronavirus pandemic is also enabling Big Tech to expropriate the levers of governments and mass communications worldwide. This paper concludes by highlighting how this development poses a dilemma for security professionals. Key Words: Global Systems, Emergence, VUCA, COVID-9, Social Instability, Big Tech, Great Reset INTRODUCTION The new decade is witnessing rising volatility across global systems. Pick any random “system” today and chart out its trajectory: Are our education systems becoming more robust and affordable? What about food security? Are our healthcare systems improving? Are our pension systems sound? Wherever one looks, there are dark clouds gathering on a global horizon marked by volatility, uncertainty, complexity and ambiguity (VUCA). But what exactly is a global system? Our planet itself is an autonomous and selfsustaining mega-system, marked by periodic cycles and elemental vagaries. Human activities within however are not system isolates as our banking, utility, farming, healthcare and retail sectors etc. are increasingly entwined. Risks accrued in one system may cascade into an unforeseen crisis within and/or without (Choo, Smith & McCusker, 2007). Scholars call this phenomenon “emergence”; one where the behaviour of intersecting systems is determined by complex and largely invisible interactions at the substratum (Goldstein, 1999; Holland, 1998). The ongoing COVID-19 pandemic is a case in point. While experts remain divided over the source and morphology of the virus, the contagion has ramified into a global health crisis and supply chain nightmare. It is also tilting the geopolitical balance. China is the largest exporter of intermediate products, and had generated nearly 20% of global imports in 2015 alone (Cousin, 2020). The pharmaceutical sector is particularly vulnerable. Nearly “85% of medicines in the U.S. strategic national stockpile” sources components from China (Owens, 2020). An initial run on respiratory masks has now been eclipsed by rowdy queues at supermarkets and the bankruptcy of small businesses. The entire global population – save for major pockets such as Sweden, Belarus, Taiwan and Japan – have been subjected to cyclical lockdowns and quarantines. Never before in history have humans faced such a systemic, borderless calamity. COVID-19 represents a classic emergent crisis that necessitates real-time response and adaptivity in a real-time world, particularly since the global Just-in-Time (JIT) production and delivery system serves as both an enabler and vector for transboundary risks. From a systems thinking perspective, emerging risk management should therefore address a whole spectrum of activity across the economic, environmental, geopolitical, societal and technological (EEGST) taxonomy. Every emerging threat can be slotted into this taxonomy – a reason why it is used by the World Economic Forum (WEF) for its annual global risk exercises (Maavak, 2019a). As traditional forces of globalization unravel, security professionals should take cognizance of emerging threats through a systems thinking approach. METHODOLOGY An EEGST sectional breakdown was adopted to illustrate a sampling of extreme risks facing the world for the 2020-2030 decade. The transcendental quality of emerging risks, as outlined on Figure 1, below, was primarily informed by the following pillars of systems thinking (Rickards, 2020): • Diminishing diversity (or increasing homogeneity) of actors in the global system (Boli & Thomas, 1997; Meyer, 2000; Young et al, 2006); • Interconnections in the global system (Homer-Dixon et al, 2015; Lee & Preston, 2012); • Interactions of actors, events and components in the global system (Buldyrev et al, 2010; Bashan et al, 2013; Homer-Dixon et al, 2015); and • Adaptive qualities in particular systems (Bodin & Norberg, 2005; Scheffer et al, 2012) Since scholastic material on this topic remains somewhat inchoate, this paper buttresses many of its contentions through secondary (i.e. news/institutional) sources. ECONOMY According to Professor Stanislaw Drozdz (2018) of the Polish Academy of Sciences, “a global financial crash of a previously unprecedented scale is highly probable” by the mid- 2020s. This will lead to a trickle-down meltdown, impacting all areas of human activity. The economist John Mauldin (2018) similarly warns that the “2020s might be the worst decade in US history” and may lead to a Second Great Depression. Other forecasts are equally alarming. According to the International Institute of Finance, global debt may have surpassed $255 trillion by 2020 (IIF, 2019). Yet another study revealed that global debts and liabilities amounted to a staggering $2.5 quadrillion (Ausman, 2018). The reader should note that these figures were tabulated before the COVID-19 outbreak. The IMF singles out widening income inequality as the trigger for the next Great Depression (Georgieva, 2020). The wealthiest 1% now own more than twice as much wealth as 6.9 billion people (Coffey et al, 2020) and this chasm is widening with each passing month. COVID-19 had, in fact, boosted global billionaire wealth to an unprecedented $10.2 trillion by July 2020 (UBS-PWC, 2020). Global GDP, worth $88 trillion in 2019, may have contracted by 5.2% in 2020 (World Bank, 2020). As the Greek historian Plutarch warned in the 1st century AD: “An imbalance between rich and poor is the oldest and most fatal ailment of all republics” (Mauldin, 2014). The stability of a society, as Aristotle argued even earlier, depends on a robust middle element or middle class. At the rate the global middle class is facing catastrophic debt and unemployment levels, widespread social disaffection may morph into outright anarchy (Maavak, 2012; DCDC, 2007). Economic stressors, in transcendent VUCA fashion, may also induce radical geopolitical realignments. Bullions now carry more weight than NATO’s security guarantees in Eastern Europe. After Poland repatriated 100 tons of gold from the Bank of England in 2019, Slovakia, Serbia and Hungary quickly followed suit. According to former Slovak Premier Robert Fico, this erosion in regional trust was based on historical precedents – in particular the 1938 Munich Agreement which ceded Czechoslovakia’s Sudetenland to Nazi Germany. As Fico reiterated (Dudik & Tomek, 2019): “You can hardly trust even the closest allies after the Munich Agreement… I guarantee that if something happens, we won’t see a single gram of this (offshore-held) gold. Let’s do it (repatriation) as quickly as possible.” (Parenthesis added by author). President Aleksandar Vucic of Serbia (a non-NATO nation) justified his central bank’s gold-repatriation program by hinting at economic headwinds ahead: “We see in which direction the crisis in the world is moving” (Dudik & Tomek, 2019). Indeed, with two global Titanics – the United States and China – set on a collision course with a quadrillions-denominated iceberg in the middle, and a viral outbreak on its tip, the seismic ripples will be felt far, wide and for a considerable period. A reality check is nonetheless needed here: Can additional bullions realistically circumvallate the economies of 80 million plus peoples in these Eastern European nations, worth a collective $1.8 trillion by purchasing power parity? Gold however is a potent psychological symbol as it represents national sovereignty and economic reassurance in a potentially hyperinflationary world. The portents are clear: The current global economic system will be weakened by rising nationalism and autarkic demands. Much uncertainty remains ahead. Mauldin (2018) proposes the introduction of Old Testament-style debt jubilees to facilitate gradual national recoveries. The World Economic Forum, on the other hand, has long proposed a “Great Reset” by 2030; a socialist utopia where “you’ll own nothing and you’ll be happy” (WEF, 2016). In the final analysis, COVID-19 is not the root cause of the current global economic turmoil; it is merely an accelerant to a burning house of cards that was left smouldering since the 2008 Great Recession (Maavak, 2020a). We also see how the four main pillars of systems thinking (diversity, interconnectivity, interactivity and “adaptivity”) form the mise en scene in a VUCA decade. ENVIRONMENTAL What happens to the environment when our economies implode? Think of a debt-laden workforce at sensitive nuclear and chemical plants, along with a concomitant surge in industrial accidents? Economic stressors, workforce demoralization and rampant profiteering – rather than manmade climate change – arguably pose the biggest threats to the environment. In a WEF report, Buehler et al (2017) made the following pre-COVID-19 observation: The ILO estimates that the annual cost to the global economy from accidents and work-related diseases alone is a staggering $3 trillion. Moreover, a recent report suggests the world’s 3.2 billion workers are increasingly unwell, with the vast majority facing significant economic insecurity: 77% work in part-time, temporary, “vulnerable” or unpaid jobs. Shouldn’t this phenomenon be better categorized as a societal or economic risk rather than an environmental one? In line with the systems thinking approach, however, global risks can no longer be boxed into a taxonomical silo. Frazzled workforces may precipitate another Bhopal (1984), Chernobyl (1986), Deepwater Horizon (2010) or Flint water crisis (2014). These disasters were notably not the result of manmade climate change. Neither was the Fukushima nuclear disaster (2011) nor the Indian Ocean tsunami (2004). Indeed, the combustion of a long-overlooked cargo of 2,750 tonnes of ammonium nitrate had nearly levelled the city of Beirut, Lebanon, on Aug 4 2020. The explosion left 204 dead; 7,500 injured; US$15 billion in property damages; and an estimated 300,000 people homeless (Urbina, 2020). The environmental costs have yet to be adequately tabulated. Environmental disasters are more attributable to Black Swan events, systems breakdowns and corporate greed rather than to mundane human activity. Our JIT world aggravates the cascading potential of risks (Korowicz, 2012). Production and delivery delays, caused by the COVID-19 outbreak, will eventually require industrial overcompensation. This will further stress senior executives, workers, machines and a variety of computerized systems. The trickle-down effects will likely include substandard products, contaminated food and a general lowering in health and safety standards (Maavak, 2019a). Unpaid or demoralized sanitation workers may also resort to indiscriminate waste dumping. Many cities across the United States (and elsewhere in the world) are no longer recycling wastes due to prohibitive costs in the global corona-economy (Liacko, 2021). Even in good times, strict protocols on waste disposals were routinely ignored. While Sweden championed the global climate change narrative, its clothing flagship H&M was busy covering up toxic effluences disgorged by vendors along the Citarum River in Java, Indonesia. As a result, countless children among 14 million Indonesians straddling the “world’s most polluted river” began to suffer from dermatitis, intestinal problems, developmental disorders, renal failure, chronic bronchitis and cancer (DW, 2020). It is also in cauldrons like the Citarum River where pathogens may mutate with emergent ramifications. On an equally alarming note, depressed economic conditions have traditionally provided a waste disposal boon for organized crime elements. Throughout 1980s, the Calabriabased ‘Ndrangheta mafia – in collusion with governments in Europe and North America – began to dump radioactive wastes along the coast of Somalia. Reeling from pollution and revenue loss, Somali fisherman eventually resorted to mass piracy (Knaup, 2008). The coast of Somalia is now a maritime hotspot, and exemplifies an entwined form of economic-environmental-geopolitical-societal emergence. In a VUCA world, indiscriminate waste dumping can unexpectedly morph into a Black Hawk Down incident. The laws of unintended consequences are governed by actors, interconnections, interactions and adaptations in a system under study – as outlined in the methodology section. Environmentally-devastating industrial sabotages – whether by disgruntled workers, industrial competitors, ideological maniacs or terrorist groups – cannot be discounted in a VUCA world. Immiserated societies, in stark defiance of climate change diktats, may resort to dirty coal plants and wood stoves for survival. Interlinked ecosystems, particularly water resources, may be hijacked by nationalist sentiments. The environmental fallouts of critical infrastructure (CI) breakdowns loom like a Sword of Damocles over this decade. GEOPOLITICAL The primary catalyst behind WWII was the Great Depression. Since history often repeats itself, expect familiar bogeymen to reappear in societies roiling with impoverishment and ideological clefts. Anti-Semitism – a societal risk on its own – may reach alarming proportions in the West (Reuters, 2019), possibly forcing Israel to undertake reprisal operations inside allied nations. If that happens, how will affected nations react? Will security resources be reallocated to protect certain minorities (or the Top 1%) while larger segments of society are exposed to restive forces? Balloon effects like these present a classic VUCA problematic. Contemporary geopolitical risks include a possible Iran-Israel war; US-China military confrontation over Taiwan or the South China Sea; North Korean proliferation of nuclear and missile technologies; an India-Pakistan nuclear war; an Iranian closure of the Straits of Hormuz; fundamentalist-driven implosion in the Islamic world; or a nuclear confrontation between NATO and Russia. Fears that the Jan 3 2020 assassination of Iranian Maj. Gen. Qasem Soleimani might lead to WWIII were grossly overblown. From a systems perspective, the killing of Soleimani did not fundamentally change the actor-interconnection-interaction adaptivity equation in the Middle East. Soleimani was simply a cog who got replaced.
15,116
<h4>Decline <u>cascades</u> – nuclear war</h4><p><strong>Maavak 21</strong> – Mathew Maavak, PhD in Risk Foresight from the Universiti Teknologi Malaysia, External Researcher (PLATBIDAFO) at the Kazimieras Simonavicius University, Expert and Regular Commentator on Risk-Related Geostrategic Issues at the Russian International Affairs Council, “Horizon 2030: Will Emerging Risks Unravel Our Global Systems?”, Salus Journal – The Australian Journal for Law Enforcement, Security and Intelligence Professionals, Volume 9, Number 1, p. 2-8</p><p>Various <u>scholars</u> and institutions <u>regard <strong>global social instability</strong> as the <strong>greatest threat</u></strong> facing this decade. <u>The catalyst has been postulated to be <mark>a <strong>Second</mark> Great <mark>Depression</strong></mark> which, in turn, <mark>will have</mark> <strong>profound <mark>implications</strong> for <strong>global security</strong></mark> and national integrity</u>. This paper, written from a broad systems perspective, illustrates how <u>emerging risks are</u> getting more complex and <u><strong>intertwined</u></strong>; blurring boundaries between the economic, environmental, geopolitical, societal and technological taxonomy used by the World Economic Forum for its annual global risk forecasts. <u><strong>Tight <mark>couplings</strong> in</u></mark> our <u><strong><mark>global systems</strong></mark> have</u> also <u><mark>enabled risks</mark> accrued <mark>in <strong>one area</strong> to <strong>snowball</strong> into </mark>a <strong><mark>full-blown crisis</strong> <strong>elsewhere</u></strong></mark>. The COVID-19 pandemic and its socioeconomic fallouts exemplify this systemic chain-reaction. Onceinexorable forces of globalization are rupturing as the current global system can no longer be sustained due to poor governance and runaway wealth fractionation. The coronavirus pandemic is also enabling Big Tech to expropriate the levers of governments and mass communications worldwide. This paper concludes by highlighting how this development poses a dilemma for security professionals. Key Words: Global Systems, Emergence, VUCA, COVID-9, Social Instability, Big Tech, Great Reset INTRODUCTION The new decade is witnessing rising volatility across global systems. Pick any random “system” today and chart out its trajectory: Are our education systems becoming more robust and affordable? What about food security? Are our healthcare systems improving? Are our pension systems sound? Wherever one looks, there are dark clouds gathering on a global horizon marked by volatility, uncertainty, complexity and ambiguity (VUCA). But what exactly is a global system? Our planet itself is an autonomous and selfsustaining mega-system, marked by periodic cycles and elemental vagaries. Human activities within however are not system isolates as our <u><mark>banking</mark>, utility, <mark>farming, <strong>health</strong></mark>care <mark>and retail</mark> sectors etc. <mark>are</mark> increasingly <strong><mark>entwined</strong></mark>. Risks accrued in <strong>one system</strong> may <strong>cascade</strong> into an <strong>unforeseen crisis</u></strong> within and/or without (Choo, Smith & McCusker, 2007). Scholars call this phenomenon “emergence”; one where <u>the behaviour of <strong>intersecting systems</strong> is determined by <strong>complex</strong> and largely <strong>invisible interactions</strong> at the <strong>substratum</u></strong> (Goldstein, 1999; Holland, 1998). The ongoing COVID-19 pandemic is a case in point. While experts remain divided over the source and morphology of the virus, the contagion has ramified into a global health crisis and supply chain nightmare. It is also tilting the geopolitical balance. China is the largest exporter of intermediate products, and had generated nearly 20% of global imports in 2015 alone (Cousin, 2020). The pharmaceutical sector is particularly vulnerable. Nearly “85% of medicines in the U.S. strategic national stockpile” sources components from China (Owens, 2020). An initial run on respiratory masks has now been eclipsed by rowdy queues at supermarkets and the bankruptcy of small businesses. The entire global population – save for major pockets such as Sweden, Belarus, Taiwan and Japan – have been subjected to cyclical lockdowns and quarantines. Never before in history have humans faced such a systemic, borderless calamity. COVID-19 represents a classic emergent crisis that necessitates real-time response and adaptivity in a real-time world, particularly since the global Just-in-Time (JIT) production and delivery system serves as both an enabler and vector for transboundary risks. From a systems thinking perspective, emerging risk management should therefore address a whole spectrum of activity across the economic, environmental, geopolitical, societal and technological (EEGST) taxonomy. Every emerging threat can be slotted into this taxonomy – a reason why it is used by the World Economic Forum (WEF) for its annual global risk exercises (Maavak, 2019a). As traditional forces of globalization unravel, security professionals should take cognizance of emerging threats through a systems thinking approach. METHODOLOGY An EEGST sectional breakdown was adopted to illustrate a sampling of extreme risks facing the world for the 2020-2030 decade. The transcendental quality of emerging risks, as outlined on Figure 1, below, was primarily informed by the following pillars of systems thinking (Rickards, 2020): • Diminishing diversity (or increasing homogeneity) of actors in the global system (Boli & Thomas, 1997; Meyer, 2000; Young et al, 2006); • Interconnections in the global system (Homer-Dixon et al, 2015; Lee & Preston, 2012); • Interactions of actors, events and components in the global system (Buldyrev et al, 2010; Bashan et al, 2013; Homer-Dixon et al, 2015); and • Adaptive qualities in particular systems (Bodin & Norberg, 2005; Scheffer et al, 2012) Since scholastic material on this topic remains somewhat inchoate, this paper buttresses many of its contentions through secondary (i.e. news/institutional) sources. ECONOMY According to Professor Stanislaw Drozdz (2018) of the Polish Academy of Sciences, “<u>a global financial crash</u> of a previously unprecedented scale is highly probable” by the mid- 2020s. This <u>will lead to a <strong>trickle-down meltdown</strong>, impacting <strong>all areas</strong> of human activity</u>. The economist John Mauldin (2018) similarly warns that the “2020s might be the worst decade in US history” <u>and</u> may <u>lead to a <strong>Second Great Depression</u></strong>. Other forecasts are equally alarming. According to the International Institute of Finance, global debt may have surpassed $255 trillion by 2020 (IIF, 2019). Yet another study revealed that global debts and liabilities amounted to a staggering $2.5 quadrillion (Ausman, 2018). The reader should note that these figures were tabulated before the COVID-19 outbreak. The IMF singles out widening income inequality as the trigger for the next Great Depression (Georgieva, 2020). The wealthiest 1% now own more than twice as much wealth as 6.9 billion people (Coffey et al, 2020) and this chasm is widening with each passing month. COVID-19 had, in fact, boosted global billionaire wealth to an unprecedented $10.2 trillion by July 2020 (UBS-PWC, 2020). Global GDP, worth $88 trillion in 2019, may have contracted by 5.2% in 2020 (World Bank, 2020). As the Greek historian Plutarch warned in the 1st century AD: “An imbalance between rich and poor is the oldest and most fatal ailment of all republics” (Mauldin, 2014). The stability of a society, as Aristotle argued even earlier, depends on a robust middle element or middle class. At the rate the global middle class is facing catastrophic debt and unemployment levels, widespread social disaffection may morph into outright anarchy (Maavak, 2012; DCDC, 2007). <u><mark>Economic stressors</u></mark>, in transcendent VUCA fashion, <u>may</u> also <u><mark>induce</mark> <strong>radical <mark>geopolitical realignments</strong></mark>. Bullions now carry more weight than NATO’s <strong>security guarantees</strong> in <strong>Eastern Europe</u></strong>. After Poland repatriated 100 tons of gold from the Bank of England in 2019, Slovakia, Serbia and Hungary quickly followed suit. According to former Slovak Premier Robert Fico, <u>this <strong>erosion</strong> in <strong>regional trust</strong> was based on historical precedents</u> – in particular the 1938 Munich Agreement which ceded Czechoslovakia’s Sudetenland to Nazi Germany. As Fico reiterated (Dudik & Tomek, 2019): “You can hardly trust even the closest allies after the Munich Agreement… I guarantee that if something happens, we won’t see a single gram of this (offshore-held) gold. Let’s do it (repatriation) as quickly as possible.” (Parenthesis added by author). President Aleksandar Vucic of Serbia (a non-NATO nation) justified his central bank’s gold-repatriation program by hinting at economic headwinds ahead: “We see in which direction the crisis in the world is moving” (Dudik & Tomek, 2019). Indeed, <u><mark>with</mark> two global Titanics – the <strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>and China</u></mark> – set <u>on a <strong>collision course</u></strong> with a quadrillions-denominated iceberg in the middle, and a viral outbreak on its tip, <u>the <strong>seismic <mark>ripples</strong> will be felt</mark> <strong>far</strong>, <strong>wide</strong> and for a <strong>considerable period</u></strong>. A reality check is nonetheless needed here: Can additional bullions realistically circumvallate the economies of 80 million plus peoples in these Eastern European nations, worth a collective $1.8 trillion by purchasing power parity? Gold however is a potent psychological symbol as it represents national sovereignty and economic reassurance in a potentially hyperinflationary world. The portents are clear: The current global economic system will be weakened by rising nationalism and autarkic demands. Much uncertainty remains ahead. Mauldin (2018) proposes the introduction of Old Testament-style debt jubilees to facilitate gradual national recoveries. The World Economic Forum, on the other hand, has long proposed a “Great Reset” by 2030; a socialist utopia where “you’ll own nothing and you’ll be happy” (WEF, 2016). In the final analysis, COVID-19 is not the root cause of the current global economic turmoil; it is merely an accelerant to a burning house of cards that was left smouldering since the 2008 Great Recession (Maavak, 2020a). We also see how the four main pillars of systems thinking (diversity, interconnectivity, interactivity and “adaptivity”) form the mise en scene in a VUCA decade. ENVIRONMENTAL <u>What happens to the <strong>environment</strong> when our <strong>economies implode</strong>? <mark>Think of a <strong>debt-laden</strong> workforce at</mark> sensitive <strong><mark>nuclear</strong> and <strong>chemical plants</strong></mark>, along <mark>with a</mark> concomitant <strong><mark>surge</strong> in</mark> <strong>industrial <mark>accidents</strong></mark>? <strong>Economic stressors</u></strong>, workforce demoralization and rampant profiteering – rather than manmade climate change – arguably <u>pose the <strong>biggest threats</strong> to the environment</u>. In a WEF report, Buehler et al (2017) made the following pre-COVID-19 observation: The ILO estimates that the annual cost to the global economy from accidents and work-related diseases alone is a staggering $3 trillion. Moreover, a recent report suggests the world’s 3.2 billion workers are increasingly unwell, with the vast majority facing significant economic insecurity: 77% work in part-time, temporary, “vulnerable” or unpaid jobs. Shouldn’t this phenomenon be better categorized as a societal or economic risk rather than an environmental one? In line with the systems thinking approach, however, <u>global risks can no longer be boxed into a <strong>taxonomical silo</u></strong>. Frazzled workforces may precipitate another Bhopal (1984), Chernobyl (1986), Deepwater Horizon (2010) or Flint water crisis (2014). These disasters were notably not the result of manmade climate change. Neither was the Fukushima nuclear disaster (2011) nor the Indian Ocean tsunami (2004). Indeed, the combustion of a long-overlooked cargo of 2,750 tonnes of ammonium nitrate had nearly levelled the city of Beirut, Lebanon, on Aug 4 2020. The explosion left 204 dead; 7,500 injured; US$15 billion in property damages; and an estimated 300,000 people homeless (Urbina, 2020). The environmental costs have yet to be adequately tabulated. Environmental disasters are more attributable to Black Swan events, systems breakdowns and corporate greed rather than to mundane human activity. <u>Our JIT world aggravates the <strong>cascading potential</strong> of risks</u> (Korowicz, 2012). <u>Production and delivery delays</u>, caused by the COVID-19 outbreak, <u>will eventually require industrial <strong>overcompensation</u></strong>. This will further stress senior executives, workers, machines and a variety of computerized systems. The trickle-down effects will likely include substandard products, contaminated food and a general lowering in health and safety standards (Maavak, 2019a). Unpaid or demoralized sanitation workers may also resort to indiscriminate waste dumping. Many cities across the United States (and elsewhere in the world) are no longer recycling wastes due to prohibitive costs in the global corona-economy (Liacko, 2021). Even in good times, strict protocols on waste disposals were routinely ignored. While Sweden championed the global climate change narrative, its clothing flagship H&M was busy covering up toxic effluences disgorged by vendors along the Citarum River in Java, Indonesia. As a result, countless children among 14 million Indonesians straddling the “world’s most polluted river” began to suffer from dermatitis, intestinal problems, developmental disorders, renal failure, chronic bronchitis and cancer (DW, 2020). It is also in cauldrons like the Citarum River where pathogens may mutate with emergent ramifications. On an equally alarming note, depressed economic conditions have traditionally provided a waste disposal boon for organized crime elements. Throughout 1980s, the Calabriabased ‘Ndrangheta mafia – in collusion with governments in Europe and North America – began to dump radioactive wastes along the coast of Somalia. Reeling from pollution and revenue loss, Somali fisherman eventually resorted to mass piracy (Knaup, 2008). The coast of Somalia is now a maritime hotspot, and exemplifies an entwined form of economic-environmental-geopolitical-societal emergence. In a VUCA world, indiscriminate waste dumping can unexpectedly morph into a Black Hawk Down incident. The laws of unintended consequences are governed by actors, interconnections, interactions and adaptations in a system under study – as outlined in the methodology section. Environmentally-devastating industrial sabotages – whether by disgruntled workers, industrial competitors, ideological maniacs or terrorist groups – cannot be discounted in a VUCA world. Immiserated societies, in stark defiance of climate change diktats, may resort to dirty coal plants and wood stoves for survival. <u>Interlinked ecosystems</u>, particularly water resources, <u>may be <strong>hijacked</u></strong> by nationalist sentiments. <u>The <strong>environmental fallouts</u></strong> of critical infrastructure (CI) breakdowns <u>loom like a <strong>Sword of Damocles</strong> over this decade</u>. GEOPOLITICAL <u><mark>The</mark> <strong>primary <mark>catalyst</strong> behind <strong>WWII</strong> was the</mark> <strong>Great <mark>Depression</u></strong></mark>. Since <u><mark>history</mark> often <strong><mark>repeats itself</strong></mark>, expect <strong>familiar bogeymen</strong> to <strong>reappear</u></strong> <u>in societies roiling with <strong>impoverishment</u></strong> and ideological clefts. <u>Anti-Semitism</u> – a societal risk on its own – <u>may reach alarming proportions</u> in the West (Reuters, 2019), <u>possibly <strong>forc</strong>ing Israel to undertake <strong>reprisal operations</u></strong> inside allied nations. If that happens, <u>how will <strong>affected nations</strong> react?</u> Will security resources be reallocated to protect certain minorities (or the Top 1%) while larger segments of society are exposed to restive forces? <u><strong><mark>Balloon effects</u></strong></mark> like these <u>present a classic</u> VUCA <u>problematic</u>. <u>Contemporary geopolitical risks <mark>include</mark> a possible <strong><mark>Iran</mark>-Israel <mark>war</strong>; <strong>US-China</mark> military <mark>confrontation</strong> over <strong>Taiwan</strong> </mark>or the <strong>S</strong>outh <strong>C</strong>hina <strong>S</strong>ea; <strong>North Korean proliferation</strong> of <strong>nuclear</strong> and <strong>missile technologies</strong>; an <strong><mark>India-Paki</mark>stan <mark>nuclear war</strong></mark>; an <strong>Iranian closure</strong> of the Straits of <strong>Hormuz</strong>; <strong>fundamentalist-driven implosion in the Islamic world</strong>; or a <strong>nuclear confrontation</strong> between <strong><mark>NATO</strong> and <strong>Russia</u></strong></mark>. Fears that the Jan 3 2020 assassination of Iranian Maj. Gen. Qasem Soleimani might lead to WWIII were grossly overblown. From a systems perspective, the killing of Soleimani did not fundamentally change the actor-interconnection-interaction adaptivity equation in the Middle East. Soleimani was simply a cog who got replaced.</p>
null
1NC—OFF
1NC---DA
2,073
1,998
7,588
./documents/hsld22/ArchbishopMitty/JoYu/ArchbishopMitty-JoYu-Neg-Mid-America-Cup-Round-3.docx
929,481
N
Mid America Cup
3
Stanford OHS Amanda Yu
Misra
1ac telehealth 1nc disclosure t multi cp blockchain cp econ da hacking da 1ar all 2nr econ da 2ar all
hsld22/ArchbishopMitty/JoYu/ArchbishopMitty-JoYu-Neg-Mid-America-Cup-Round-3.docx
2022-09-25 18:07:47
80,058
JoYu
Archbishop Mitty JoYu
null
Jo.....
Yu.....
null
null
26,924
ArchbishopMitty
Archbishop Mitty
CA
10,150
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
3,298,060
1 – Extinction o/ws under any framework, even under moral uncertainty – infinite future generations
Pummer 15
Pummer 15 — (Theron Pummer, Junior Research Fellow in Philosophy at St. Anne's College, University of Oxford, “Moral Agreement on Saving the World“, Practical Ethics University of Oxford, 5-18-2015, Available Online at http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2015/05/moral-agreement-on-saving-the-world/, accessed 7-2-2018, HKR-AM) **we do not endorse ableist language=
There appears to be lot of disagreement in moral philosophy. there is at least one thing it is reasonable to agree on right now, whatever general moral view we adopt: that it is very important to reduce the risk that all intelligent beings on this planet are eliminated by an enormous catastrophe, such as a nuclear war. . If the happiness or well-being of possible future people is just as important as that of people who already exist, and if they would have good lives, it is not hard to see how reducing existential risk is easily the most important thing in the whole world. This is for the familiar reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. There are so many possible future people that reducing existential risk is arguably the most important thing in the world, even if the well-being of these possible people were given only 0.001% as much weight as that of existing people there’s a good chance that many existing people will, with the aid of life-extension technology, live very long and very high quality lives. You might think what I have just argued applies to consequentialists only. There is a tendency to assume that, if an argument appeals to consequentialist considerations (the goodness of outcomes), it is irrelevant to non-consequentialists Non-consequentialism is the view that there’s more that determines rightness than the goodness of consequences or outcomes; it is not the view that the latter don’t matter. Even John Rawls wrote, “All ethical doctrines worth our attention take consequences into account in judging rightness. One which did not would simply be irrational, crazy.” Minimally plausible versions of deontology and virtue ethics must be concerned in part with promoting the good, from an impartial point of view. They’d thus imply very strong reasons to reduce existential risk, We should also take into account moral uncertainty. What is it reasonable for one to do, when one is uncertain not (only) about the empirical facts, but also about the moral facts? I’ve just argued that there’s agreement among minimally plausible ethical views that we have strong reason to reduce existential risk – not only consequentialists, but also deontologists, virtue ethicists, and sophisticated egoists should agree . Even if they were 90% sure that their view is the correct one (and 10% sure that one of these other ones is correct), they would have pretty strong reason, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, to reduce existential risk. Perhaps most disturbingly still, even if we are only 1% sure that the well-being of possible future people matters, it is at least arguable that, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, reducing existential risk is the most important thing in the world Derek Parfit, whose work has emphasized future generations as well as agreement in ethics, described our situation clearly and accurately: Given the scientific and technological discoveries of the last two centuries, the world has never changed as fast. We shall soon have even greater powers to transform, not only our surroundings, but ourselves and our successors. If we act wisely in the next few centuries, humanity will survive its most dangerous and decisive period. Our descendants could, if necessary, go elsewhere, spreading through this galaxy…. Our descendants might, I believe, make the further future very good. But that good future may also depend in part on us. If our selfish recklessness ends human history, we would be acting very wrongly
reducing existential risk is the most important there are trillions upon trillions future people even if the well-being were given 0.001% weight Non-consequentialism is not that the latter don’t matter Minimally plausible versions of deont and virtue ethics must be concerned with promoting the good imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk Even if they were 90% sure they would have reason, from moral uncertainty, to reduce existential risk
There appears to be lot of disagreement in moral philosophy. Whether these many apparent disagreements are deep and irresolvable, I believe there is at least one thing it is reasonable to agree on right now, whatever general moral view we adopt: that it is very important to reduce the risk that all intelligent beings on this planet are eliminated by an enormous catastrophe, such as a nuclear war. How we might in fact try to reduce such existential risks is discussed elsewhere. My claim here is only that we – whether we’re consequentialists, deontologists, or virtue ethicists – should all agree that we should try to save the world. According to consequentialism, we should maximize the good, where this is taken to be the goodness, from an impartial perspective, of outcomes. Clearly one thing that makes an outcome good is that the people in it are doing well. There is little disagreement here. If the happiness or well-being of possible future people is just as important as that of people who already exist, and if they would have good lives, it is not hard to see how reducing existential risk is easily the most important thing in the whole world. This is for the familiar reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. There are so many possible future people that reducing existential risk is arguably the most important thing in the world, even if the well-being of these possible people were given only 0.001% as much weight as that of existing people. Even on a wholly person-affecting view – according to which there’s nothing (apart from effects on existing people) to be said in favor of creating happy people – the case for reducing existential risk is very strong. As noted in this seminal paper, this case is strengthened by the fact that there’s a good chance that many existing people will, with the aid of life-extension technology, live very long and very high quality lives. You might think what I have just argued applies to consequentialists only. There is a tendency to assume that, if an argument appeals to consequentialist considerations (the goodness of outcomes), it is irrelevant to non-consequentialists. But that is a huge mistake. Non-consequentialism is the view that there’s more that determines rightness than the goodness of consequences or outcomes; it is not the view that the latter don’t matter. Even John Rawls wrote, “All ethical doctrines worth our attention take consequences into account in judging rightness. One which did not would simply be irrational, crazy.” Minimally plausible versions of deontology and virtue ethics must be concerned in part with promoting the good, from an impartial point of view. They’d thus imply very strong reasons to reduce existential risk, at least when this doesn’t significantly involve doing harm to others or damaging one’s character. What’s even more surprising, perhaps, is that even if our own good (or that of those near and dear to us) has much greater weight than goodness from the impartial “point of view of the universe,” indeed even if the latter is entirely morally irrelevant, we may nonetheless have very strong reasons to reduce existential risk. Even egoism, the view that each agent should maximize her own good, might imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. It will depend, among other things, on what one’s own good consists in. If well-being consisted in pleasure only, it is somewhat harder to argue that egoism would imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk – perhaps we could argue that one would maximize her expected hedonic well-being by funding life extension technology or by having herself cryogenically frozen at the time of her bodily death as well as giving money to reduce existential risk (so that there is a world for her to live in!). I am not sure, however, how strong the reasons to do this would be. But views which imply that, if I don’t care about other people, I have no or very little reason to help them are not even minimally plausible views (in addition to hedonistic egoism, I here have in mind views that imply that one has no reason to perform an act unless one actually desires to do that act). To be minimally plausible, egoism will need to be paired with a more sophisticated account of well-being. To see this, it is enough to consider, as Plato did, the possibility of a ring of invisibility – suppose that, while wearing it, Ayn could derive some pleasure by helping the poor, but instead could derive just a bit more by severely harming them. Hedonistic egoism would absurdly imply she should do the latter. To avoid this implication, egoists would need to build something like the meaningfulness of a life into well-being, in some robust way, where this would to a significant extent be a function of other-regarding concerns (see chapter 12 of this classic intro to ethics). But once these elements are included, we can (roughly, as above) argue that this sort of egoism will imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. Add to all of this Samuel Scheffler’s recent intriguing arguments (quick podcast version available here) that most of what makes our lives go well would be undermined if there were no future generations of intelligent persons. On his view, my life would contain vastly less well-being if (say) a year after my death the world came to an end. So obviously if Scheffler were right I’d have very strong reason to reduce existential risk. We should also take into account moral uncertainty. What is it reasonable for one to do, when one is uncertain not (only) about the empirical facts, but also about the moral facts? I’ve just argued that there’s agreement among minimally plausible ethical views that we have strong reason to reduce existential risk – not only consequentialists, but also deontologists, virtue ethicists, and sophisticated egoists should agree. But even those (hedonistic egoists) who disagree should have a significant level of confidence that they are mistaken, and that one of the above views is correct. Even if they were 90% sure that their view is the correct one (and 10% sure that one of these other ones is correct), they would have pretty strong reason, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, to reduce existential risk. Perhaps most disturbingly still, even if we are only 1% sure that the well-being of possible future people matters, it is at least arguable that, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, reducing existential risk is the most important thing in the world. Again, this is largely for the reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. (For more on this and other related issues, see this excellent dissertation). Of course, it is uncertain whether these untold trillions would, in general, have good lives. It’s possible they’ll be miserable. It is enough for my claim that there is moral agreement in the relevant sense if, at least given certain empirical claims about what future lives would most likely be like, all minimally plausible moral views would converge on the conclusion that we should try to save the world. While there are some non-crazy views that place significantly greater moral weight on avoiding suffering than on promoting happiness, for reasons others have offered (and for independent reasons I won’t get into here unless requested to), they nonetheless seem to be fairly implausible views. And even if things did not go well for our ancestors, I am optimistic that they will overall go fantastically well for our descendants, if we allow them to. I suspect that most of us alive today – at least those of us not suffering from extreme illness or poverty – have lives that are well worth living, and that things will continue to improve. Derek Parfit, whose work has emphasized future generations as well as agreement in ethics, described our situation clearly and accurately: “We live during the hinge of history. Given the scientific and technological discoveries of the last two centuries, the world has never changed as fast. We shall soon have even greater powers to transform, not only our surroundings, but ourselves and our successors. If we act wisely in the next few centuries, humanity will survive its most dangerous and decisive period. Our descendants could, if necessary, go elsewhere, spreading through this galaxy…. Our descendants might, I believe, make the further future very good. But that good future may also depend in part on us. If our selfish recklessness ends human history, we would be acting very wrongly.” (From chapter 36 of On What Matters) Afc paragraph theory
8,707
<h4>1 – Extinction o/ws under any framework, even under moral uncertainty – infinite future generations </h4><p><strong>Pummer 15</strong> — (Theron Pummer, Junior Research Fellow in Philosophy at St. Anne's College, University of Oxford, “Moral Agreement on Saving the World“, Practical Ethics University of Oxford, 5-18-2015, Available Online at http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2015/05/moral-agreement-on-saving-the-world/, accessed 7-2-2018, HKR-AM) **we do not endorse ableist language=</p><p><u>There appears to be lot of disagreement in moral philosophy.</u> Whether these many apparent disagreements are deep and irresolvable, I believe <u>there is at least one thing it is reasonable to agree on right now, whatever general moral view we adopt: that it is very important to reduce the risk that all intelligent beings on this planet are eliminated by an enormous catastrophe, such as a nuclear war.</u> How we might in fact try to reduce such existential risks is discussed elsewhere. My claim here is only that we – whether we’re consequentialists, deontologists, or virtue ethicists – should all agree that we should try to save the world. According to consequentialism, we should maximize the good, where this is taken to be the goodness, from an impartial perspective, of outcomes. Clearly one thing that makes an outcome good is that the people in it are doing well. There is little disagreement here<u>. If the happiness or well-being of possible future people is just as important as that of people who already exist, and if they would have good lives, it is not hard to see how <mark>reducing existential risk is</mark> easily <mark>the most important</mark> thing in the whole world. This is for the familiar reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – <mark>there are</mark> <mark>trillions upon trillions</mark>… upon trillions.</u> <u>There are so many possible <mark>future people</mark> that reducing existential risk is arguably the most important thing in the world,</u> <u><mark>even if the well-being</mark> of these possible people <mark>were</mark> <mark>given</mark> only <mark>0.001% </mark>as much <mark>weight</mark> as that of existing people</u>. Even on a wholly person-affecting view – according to which there’s nothing (apart from effects on existing people) to be said in favor of creating happy people – the case for reducing existential risk is very strong. As noted in this seminal paper, this case is strengthened by the fact that <u>there’s a good chance that many existing people will, with the aid of life-extension technology, live very long and very high quality lives. You might think what I have just argued applies to consequentialists only. There is a tendency to assume that, if an argument appeals to consequentialist considerations (the goodness of outcomes), it is irrelevant to non-consequentialists</u>. But that is a huge mistake. <u><mark>Non-consequentialism </mark>is the view that there’s more that determines rightness than the goodness of consequences or outcomes; it <mark>is not</mark> the view <mark>that the latter don’t matter</mark>. Even John Rawls wrote, “All ethical doctrines worth our attention take consequences into account in judging rightness. One which did not would simply be irrational, crazy.” <mark>Minimally plausible versions of deont</mark>ology <mark>and virtue ethics must be concerned</mark> in part <mark>with promoting the good</mark>, from an impartial point of view. They’d thus <mark>imply</mark> very <mark>strong reasons to reduce existential risk</mark>, </u>at least when this doesn’t significantly involve doing harm to others or damaging one’s character. What’s even more surprising, perhaps, is that even if our own good (or that of those near and dear to us) has much greater weight than goodness from the impartial “point of view of the universe,” indeed even if the latter is entirely morally irrelevant, we may nonetheless have very strong reasons to reduce existential risk. Even egoism, the view that each agent should maximize her own good, might imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. It will depend, among other things, on what one’s own good consists in. If well-being consisted in pleasure only, it is somewhat harder to argue that egoism would imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk – perhaps we could argue that one would maximize her expected hedonic well-being by funding life extension technology or by having herself cryogenically frozen at the time of her bodily death as well as giving money to reduce existential risk (so that there is a world for her to live in!). I am not sure, however, how strong the reasons to do this would be. But views which imply that, if I don’t care about other people, I have no or very little reason to help them are not even minimally plausible views (in addition to hedonistic egoism, I here have in mind views that imply that one has no reason to perform an act unless one actually desires to do that act). To be minimally plausible, egoism will need to be paired with a more sophisticated account of well-being. To see this, it is enough to consider, as Plato did, the possibility of a ring of invisibility – suppose that, while wearing it, Ayn could derive some pleasure by helping the poor, but instead could derive just a bit more by severely harming them. Hedonistic egoism would absurdly imply she should do the latter. To avoid this implication, egoists would need to build something like the meaningfulness of a life into well-being, in some robust way, where this would to a significant extent be a function of other-regarding concerns (see chapter 12 of this classic intro to ethics). But once these elements are included, we can (roughly, as above) argue that this sort of egoism will imply strong reasons to reduce existential risk. Add to all of this Samuel Scheffler’s recent intriguing arguments (quick podcast version available here) that most of what makes our lives go well would be undermined if there were no future generations of intelligent persons. On his view, my life would contain vastly less well-being if (say) a year after my death the world came to an end. So obviously if Scheffler were right I’d have very strong reason to reduce existential risk. <u>We should also take into account moral uncertainty. What is it reasonable for one to do, when one is uncertain not (only) about the empirical facts, but also about the moral facts? I’ve just argued that there’s agreement among minimally plausible ethical views that we have strong reason to reduce existential risk – not only consequentialists, but also deontologists, virtue ethicists, and sophisticated egoists should agree</u>. But even those (hedonistic egoists) who disagree should have a significant level of confidence that they are mistaken, and that one of the above views is correct<u>. <mark>Even if they were 90% sure </mark>that their view is the correct one (and 10% sure that one of these other ones is correct), <mark>they would have </mark>pretty strong <mark>reason, from </mark>the standpoint of <mark>moral uncertainty, to reduce existential risk</mark>. Perhaps most disturbingly still, even if we are only 1% sure that the well-being of possible future people matters, it is at least arguable that, from the standpoint of moral uncertainty, reducing existential risk is the most important thing in the world</u>. Again, this is largely for the reason that there are so many people who could exist in the future – there are trillions upon trillions… upon trillions. (For more on this and other related issues, see this excellent dissertation). Of course, it is uncertain whether these untold trillions would, in general, have good lives. It’s possible they’ll be miserable. It is enough for my claim that there is moral agreement in the relevant sense if, at least given certain empirical claims about what future lives would most likely be like, all minimally plausible moral views would converge on the conclusion that we should try to save the world. While there are some non-crazy views that place significantly greater moral weight on avoiding suffering than on promoting happiness, for reasons others have offered (and for independent reasons I won’t get into here unless requested to), they nonetheless seem to be fairly implausible views. And even if things did not go well for our ancestors, I am optimistic that they will overall go fantastically well for our descendants, if we allow them to. I suspect that most of us alive today – at least those of us not suffering from extreme illness or poverty – have lives that are well worth living, and that things will continue to improve. <u>Derek Parfit, whose work has emphasized future generations as well as agreement in ethics, described our situation clearly and accurately:</u> “We live during the hinge of history. <u>Given the scientific and technological discoveries of the last two centuries, the world has never changed as fast. We shall soon have even greater powers to transform, not only our surroundings, but ourselves and our successors. If we act wisely in the next few centuries, humanity will survive its most dangerous and decisive period.</u> <u>Our descendants could, if necessary, go elsewhere, spreading through this galaxy…. Our descendants might, I believe, make the further future very good. But that good future may also depend in part on us. If our selfish recklessness ends human history, we would be acting very wrongly</u>.” (From chapter 36 of On What Matters)</p><p>Afc paragraph theory</p>
null
1
null
12,186
5,631
108,451
./documents/hsld18/Harker/Vi/Harker-Vinod-Neg-Valley-Round2.docx
820,813
N
Valley
2
John Paul II BP
Tom Enven
1AC - Whole res 1N - Terror Lashout Util 1AR - New theory substance 2N - AFC bad
hsld18/Harker/Vi/Harker-Vinod-Neg-Valley-Round2.docx
null
70,285
AdVi
Harker AdVi
null
Ad.....
Vi.....
null
null
23,743
Harker
Harker
null
null
1,026
hsld18
HS LD 2018-19
2,018
ld
hs
1
2,591,169
Util- You should vote AFF if the 1AC’s contingently true---even if they’re right about everything else.
Baum & Barrett 18
Seth D. Baum & Anthony M. Barrett 18. Global Catastrophic Risk Institute. 2018. “Global Catastrophes: The Most Extreme Risks.” Risk in Extreme Environments: Preparing, Avoiding, Mitigating, and Managing, edited by Vicki Bier, Routledge, pp. 174–184.
Taken literally, a global catastrophe can be any event that is in some way catastrophic across the globe This suggests a rather low threshold However, in common usage, a global catastrophe would be catastrophic for a significant portion of the globe Others have emphasized catastrophes that cause long-term declines in the trajectory of human civilization that human civilization does not recover from that drastically reduce humanity’s potential for future achievements Bostrom using the term “existential risk”), or that result in human extinction A common theme across all these treatments of GCR is that some catastrophes are vastly more important than others Without nuclear winter, a global nuclear war might kill several hundred million people. This is obviously a major catastrophe, but humanity would presumably carry on. However, with nuclear winter humanity could go extinct. The loss would be not just an additional four billion or so deaths, but the loss of all future generations the loss would be billions and billions of lives, or even more Sagan estimated 500 trillion lives, assuming humanity would continue for ten million more years, which he cited as typical for a successful species. Sagan’s 500 trillion number may even be an underestimate An open question in astronomy is whether it is possible for the descendants of humanity to continue living for an infinite length of time or instead merely an astronomically large but finite length of time the stakes with global catastrophes could be much larger than the loss of 500 trillion lives. Debates about the infinite vs. the merely astronomical are of theoretical interest but they have limited practical significance. This can be seen when evaluating GCRs from a standard risk-equals-probability-times-magnitude framework. Using Sagan’s 500 trillion lives estimate, it follows that reducing the probability of global catastrophe by a mere one-in-500-trillion chance is of the same significance as saving one human life. Phrased differently, society should try 500 trillion times harder to prevent a global catastrophe than it should to save a person’s life. Or, preventing one million deaths is equivalent to a one-in500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe. This suggests society should make extremely large investment in GCR reduction, at the expense of virtually all other objectives. society should be willing to spend $1 million for a one-in-500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe while reasonable disagreement exists on how large of a VSL to use and how much to count future generations, even low-end positions suggest vast resource allocations should be redirected to reducing GCR. This conclusion is only strengthened when considering the astronomical size of the stakes as long as something along the lines of the standard riskequals-probability-times-magnitude framework is being used, then even tiny GCR reductions merit significant effort. This point holds especially strongly for risks of catastrophes that would cause permanent harm to global human civilization. The discussion thus far has assumed that all human lives are valued equally. This assumption is not universally held People often value some people more than others Great debates rage on across moral philosophy, economics, and other fields about how much people should value others This debate is crucial While everyone has the right to their own views and feelings the strongest arguments are for the widely held position that all human lives should be valued equally. Philosophers speak of an agent-neutral, objective “view from nowhere” or a “veil of ignorance” in which each person considers what is best for society irrespective of which member of society they happen to be Such a perspective suggests valuing everyone equally, regardless of who they are or where or when they live. This in turn suggests a very high value for reducing GCR, or a high degree of priority for GCR reduction efforts.
some catastrophes are vastly more important than others humanity could go extinct loss of all future generations. 500 trillion lives may be an underestimate risk-equals-probability-times-magnitude society should try 500 trillion times harder to prevent global catastrophe than to save a person’s life While everyone has the right to their own views the strongest arguments are for the widely held position that all human lives should be valued equally Philosophers speak of a a “veil of ignorance” in which each considers what is best for society irrespective of which member they happen to be valuing everyone equally suggests a very high value for reducing GCR
2. What Is GCR And Why Is It Important? Taken literally, a global catastrophe can be any event that is in some way catastrophic across the globe. This suggests a rather low threshold for what counts as a global catastrophe. An event causing just one death on each continent (say, from a jet-setting assassin) could rate as a global catastrophe, because surely these deaths would be catastrophic for the deceased and their loved ones. However, in common usage, a global catastrophe would be catastrophic for a significant portion of the globe. Minimum thresholds have variously been set around ten thousand to ten million deaths or $10 billion to $10 trillion in damages (Bostrom and Ćirković 2008), or death of one quarter of the human population (Atkinson 1999; Hempsell 2004). Others have emphasized catastrophes that cause long-term declines in the trajectory of human civilization (Beckstead 2013), that human civilization does not recover from (Maher and Baum 2013), that drastically reduce humanity’s potential for future achievements (Bostrom 2002, using the term “existential risk”), or that result in human extinction (Matheny 2007; Posner 2004). A common theme across all these treatments of GCR is that some catastrophes are vastly more important than others. Carl Sagan was perhaps the first to recognize this, in his commentary on nuclear winter (Sagan 1983). Without nuclear winter, a global nuclear war might kill several hundred million people. This is obviously a major catastrophe, but humanity would presumably carry on. However, with nuclear winter, per Sagan, humanity could go extinct. The loss would be not just an additional four billion or so deaths, but the loss of all future generations. To paraphrase Sagan, the loss would be billions and billions of lives, or even more. Sagan estimated 500 trillion lives, assuming humanity would continue for ten million more years, which he cited as typical for a successful species. Sagan’s 500 trillion number may even be an underestimate. The analysis here takes an adventurous turn, hinging on the evolution of the human species and the long-term fate of the universe. On these long time scales, the descendants of contemporary humans may no longer be recognizably “human”. The issue then is whether the descendants are still worth caring about, whatever they are. If they are, then it begs the question of how many of them there will be. Barring major global catastrophe, Earth will remain habitable for about one billion more years 2 until the Sun gets too warm and large. The rest of the Solar System, Milky Way galaxy, universe, and (if it exists) the multiverse will remain habitable for a lot longer than that (Adams and Laughlin 1997), should our descendants gain the capacity to migrate there. An open question in astronomy is whether it is possible for the descendants of humanity to continue living for an infinite length of time or instead merely an astronomically large but finite length of time (see e.g. Ćirković 2002; Kaku 2005). Either way, the stakes with global catastrophes could be much larger than the loss of 500 trillion lives. Debates about the infinite vs. the merely astronomical are of theoretical interest (Ng 1991; Bossert et al. 2007), but they have limited practical significance. This can be seen when evaluating GCRs from a standard risk-equals-probability-times-magnitude framework. Using Sagan’s 500 trillion lives estimate, it follows that reducing the probability of global catastrophe by a mere one-in-500-trillion chance is of the same significance as saving one human life. Phrased differently, society should try 500 trillion times harder to prevent a global catastrophe than it should to save a person’s life. Or, preventing one million deaths is equivalent to a one-in500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe. This suggests society should make extremely large investment in GCR reduction, at the expense of virtually all other objectives. Judge and legal scholar Richard Posner made a similar point in monetary terms (Posner 2004). Posner used $50,000 as the value of a statistical human life (VSL) and 12 billion humans as the total loss of life (double the 2004 world population); he describes both figures as significant underestimates. Multiplying them gives $600 trillion as an underestimate of the value of preventing global catastrophe. For comparison, the United States government typically uses a VSL of around one to ten million dollars (Robinson 2007). Multiplying a $10 million VSL with 500 trillion lives gives $5x1021 as the value of preventing global catastrophe. But even using “just" $600 trillion, society should be willing to spend at least that much to prevent a global catastrophe, which converts to being willing to spend at least $1 million for a one-in-500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe. Thus while reasonable disagreement exists on how large of a VSL to use and how much to count future generations, even low-end positions suggest vast resource allocations should be redirected to reducing GCR. This conclusion is only strengthened when considering the astronomical size of the stakes, but the same point holds either way. The bottom line is that, as long as something along the lines of the standard riskequals-probability-times-magnitude framework is being used, then even tiny GCR reductions merit significant effort. This point holds especially strongly for risks of catastrophes that would cause permanent harm to global human civilization. The discussion thus far has assumed that all human lives are valued equally. This assumption is not universally held. People often value some people more than others, favoring themselves, their family and friends, their compatriots, their generation, or others whom they identify with. Great debates rage on across moral philosophy, economics, and other fields about how much people should value others who are distant in space, time, or social relation, as well as the unborn members of future generations. This debate is crucial for all valuations of risk, including GCR. Indeed, if each of us only cares about our immediate selves, then global catastrophes may not be especially important, and we probably have better things to do with our time than worry about them. While everyone has the right to their own views and feelings, we find that the strongest arguments are for the widely held position that all human lives should be valued equally. This position is succinctly stated in the United States Declaration of Independence, updated in the 1848 Declaration of Sentiments: “We hold these truths to be self-evident: that all men and 3 women are created equal”. Philosophers speak of an agent-neutral, objective “view from nowhere” (Nagel 1986) or a “veil of ignorance” (Rawls 1971) in which each person considers what is best for society irrespective of which member of society they happen to be. Such a perspective suggests valuing everyone equally, regardless of who they are or where or when they live. This in turn suggests a very high value for reducing GCR, or a high degree of priority for GCR reduction efforts.
7,162
<h4><strong>Util- You should vote AFF if the 1AC’s contingently true---even if they’re right about everything else. </h4><p></strong>Seth D. <strong>Baum &</strong> Anthony M. <strong>Barrett 18<u></strong>. Global Catastrophic Risk Institute. 2018. “Global Catastrophes: The Most Extreme Risks.” Risk in Extreme Environments: Preparing, Avoiding, Mitigating, and Managing, edited by Vicki Bier, Routledge, pp. 174–184.</p><p></u>2. What Is GCR And Why Is It Important? <u>Taken <strong>literally</strong>, a global catastrophe can be any event that is in some way catastrophic across the globe</u>. <u>This suggests a rather low threshold</u> for what counts as a global catastrophe. An event causing just one death on each continent (say, from a jet-setting assassin) could rate as a global catastrophe, because surely these deaths would be catastrophic for the deceased and their loved ones. <u>However, in common usage, a global catastrophe would be <strong>catastrophic</strong> for a significant portion of the globe</u>. Minimum thresholds have variously been set around ten thousand to ten million deaths or $10 billion to $10 trillion in damages (Bostrom and Ćirković 2008), or death of one quarter of the human population (Atkinson 1999; Hempsell 2004). <u>Others have emphasized catastrophes that cause <strong>long-term declines in the trajectory of human civilization</u></strong> (Beckstead 2013), <u>that human civilization <strong>does not recover from</u></strong> (Maher and Baum 2013), <u>that drastically reduce humanity’s potential for future achievements</u> (<u>Bostrom</u> 2002, <u>using the term “<strong>existential risk</strong>”), or that result in <strong>human extinction</u></strong> (Matheny 2007; Posner 2004). <u>A common theme across all these treatments of GCR is that <strong><mark>some</mark> <mark>catastrophes</mark> <mark>are vastly more important than others</u></strong></mark>. Carl Sagan was perhaps the first to recognize this, in his commentary on nuclear winter (Sagan 1983). <u>Without nuclear winter, a global nuclear war might kill several hundred million people. This is obviously a major catastrophe, but humanity would presumably carry on. However, with <strong>nuclear winter</u></strong>, per Sagan, <u><strong><mark>humanity</mark> <mark>could go extinct</strong></mark>. The loss would be not just an additional four billion or so deaths, but the <mark>loss of <strong>all future generations</u></strong>.</mark> To paraphrase Sagan, <u>the loss would be billions and billions of lives, or even <strong>more</u></strong>. <u>Sagan estimated <strong><mark>500 trillion lives</strong></mark>, assuming humanity would continue for ten million more years, which he cited as typical for a successful species. Sagan’s 500 trillion number <mark>may</mark> even <mark>be an <strong>underestimate</u></strong></mark>. The analysis here takes an adventurous turn, hinging on the evolution of the human species and the long-term fate of the universe. On these long time scales, the descendants of contemporary humans may no longer be recognizably “human”. The issue then is whether the descendants are still worth caring about, whatever they are. If they are, then it begs the question of how many of them there will be. Barring major global catastrophe, Earth will remain habitable for about one billion more years 2 until the Sun gets too warm and large. The rest of the Solar System, Milky Way galaxy, universe, and (if it exists) the multiverse will remain habitable for a lot longer than that (Adams and Laughlin 1997), should our descendants gain the capacity to migrate there. <u>An open question in astronomy is whether it is possible for the descendants of humanity to continue living for an <strong>infinite length of time</strong> or instead merely an <strong>astronomically large but finite</strong> length of time</u> (see e.g. Ćirković 2002; Kaku 2005). Either way,<u> the stakes with global catastrophes <strong>could</strong> be <strong>much larger than the loss of 500 trillion lives. </strong>Debates about the infinite vs. the merely astronomical are of theoretical interest</u> (Ng 1991; Bossert et al. 2007), <u>but they have <strong>limited practical significance</strong>. This can be seen when <strong>evaluating GCRs from a standard <mark>risk-equals-probability-times-magnitude</mark> framework</strong>. Using Sagan’s 500 trillion lives estimate, it follows that reducing the probability of global catastrophe by a mere one-in-500-trillion chance is of the same significance as saving one human life. Phrased differently, <mark>society should <strong>try 500 trillion times harder to prevent</mark> a <mark>global catastrophe</mark> <mark>than</mark> it should <mark>to save a person’s life</strong></mark>. Or, preventing one million deaths is equivalent to a one-in500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe. This suggests society should <strong>make extremely large investment in GCR reduction, at the expense of virtually all other objectives. </u></strong>Judge and legal scholar Richard Posner made a similar point in monetary terms (Posner 2004). Posner used $50,000 as the value of a statistical human life (VSL) and 12 billion humans as the total loss of life (double the 2004 world population); he describes both figures as significant underestimates. Multiplying them gives $600 trillion as an underestimate of the value of preventing global catastrophe. For comparison, the United States government typically uses a VSL of around one to ten million dollars (Robinson 2007). Multiplying a $10 million VSL with 500 trillion lives gives $5x1021 as the value of preventing global catastrophe. But even using “just" $600 trillion, <u>society should be willing to spend</u> at least that much to prevent a global catastrophe, which converts to being willing to spend at least <u>$1 million for a one-in-500-million reduction in the probability of global catastrophe</u>. Thus <u>while reasonable disagreement exists on how large of a VSL to use and how much to count future generations, even low-end positions suggest <strong>vast resource allocations</strong> should be redirected to reducing GCR. This conclusion is only <strong>strengthened</strong> when considering the <strong>astronomical size of the stakes</u></strong>, but the same point holds either way. The bottom line is that, <u>as long as something along the lines of the standard riskequals-probability-times-magnitude framework is being used, then <strong>even tiny GCR reductions</strong> merit significant effort. This point holds especially strongly for risks of catastrophes that would cause <strong>permanent harm to global human civilization</strong>. The discussion thus far has assumed that all human lives are valued equally. This assumption is <strong>not universally held</u></strong>. <u>People often value some people more than others</u>, favoring themselves, their family and friends, their compatriots, their generation, or others whom they identify with. <u>Great debates rage on across moral philosophy, economics, and other fields about how much people should value others</u> who are distant in space, time, or social relation, as well as the unborn members of future generations. <u>This debate is crucial</u> for all valuations of risk, including GCR. Indeed, if each of us only cares about our immediate selves, then global catastrophes may not be especially important, and we probably have better things to do with our time than worry about them. <u><mark>While everyone has the right to their <strong>own views</mark> and feelings</u></strong>, we find that <u><mark>the strongest arguments are for the <strong>widely held position</strong> that <strong>all human lives should be valued equally</strong></mark>.</u> This position is succinctly stated in the United States Declaration of Independence, updated in the 1848 Declaration of Sentiments: “We hold these truths to be self-evident: that all men and 3 women are created equal”. <u><mark>Philosophers speak of a</mark>n agent-neutral, objective “view from nowhere”</u> (Nagel 1986) <u>or <mark>a “veil of ignorance”</u></mark> (Rawls 1971) <u><mark>in which each</mark> person <mark>considers what is best for society <strong>irrespective of which member</mark> of society <mark>they happen to be</u></strong></mark>. <u>Such a perspective <strong>suggests <mark>valuing everyone equally</strong></mark>, regardless of who they are or where or when they live. This in turn <mark>suggests a <strong>very high value for reducing GCR</mark>, or a high degree of priority for GCR reduction efforts. </p></u></strong>
2AC
K
ROB
1,570
2,142
82,989
./documents/ndtceda19/Navy/LeGu/Navy-Lewis-Gutierrez-Aff-Kentucky-Round7.docx
614,404
A
Kentucky
7
Missouri State KR
Patrice
1AC -Same a RD1 1NC - Technomilitarism K 2NR - D-Dev
ndtceda19/Navy/LeGu/Navy-Lewis-Gutierrez-Aff-Kentucky-Round7.docx
null
52,018
LeGu
Navy LeGu
null
Wi.....
Le.....
Ni.....
Gu.....
19,275
Navy
Navy
null
null
1,009
ndtceda19
NDT/CEDA 2019-20
2,019
cx
college
2
933,530
The “United States federal government” means the three branches of the central government
OECD, 87
OECD, 87
Political and organisational structure of government The United States of America is a federal republic consisting of 50 states The Federal Government is composed of three branches: the legislative branch, the executive branch, and the judicial branch
The U S is a federal republic The Federal Government is composed of three branches: legislative executive and judicial
(Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development Council, 1987, “United States,” The Control and Management of Government Expenditure, p. 179) JD 1. Political and organisational structure of government The United States of America is a federal republic consisting of 50 states. States have their own constitutions and within each State there are at least two additional levels of government, generally designated as counties and cities, towns or villages. The relationships between different levels of government are complex and varied (see Section B for more information). The Federal Government is composed of three branches: the legislative branch, the executive branch, and the judicial branch. Budgetary decisionmaking is shared primarily by the legislative and executive branches. The general structure of these two branches relative to budget formulation and execution is as follows.
897
<h4>The “United States federal government” means the <u>three branches</u> of the central government</h4><p><strong>OECD, 87</strong> </p><p>(Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development Council, 1987, “United States,” The Control and Management of Government Expenditure, p. 179) JD</p><p>1. <u>Political and organisational structure of government</u> <u><mark>The U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates of America <mark>is a federal republic</mark> consisting of 50 states</u>. States have their own constitutions and within each State there are at least two additional levels of government, generally designated as counties and cities, towns or villages. The relationships between different levels of government are complex and varied (see Section B for more information). <u><mark>The Federal Government is composed of three branches<strong>:</strong></mark> the <mark>legislative</mark> branch, the <mark>executive</mark> branch, <mark>and</mark> the <mark>judicial</mark> branch</u>. Budgetary decisionmaking is shared primarily by the legislative and executive branches. The general structure of these two branches relative to budget formulation and execution is as follows.</p>
1NC
Off
1NC
23,993
1,475
22,681
./documents/ndtceda21/LibertyUniversity/RaWa/Liberty%20University-Ramsey-Wallenmeyer-Neg-Texas-Round2.docx
625,310
N
Texas
2
Kansas BaSp
Rebecca Steiner
1AC - Cybernetics 1NC - Cap K T-USFG 2NR - Cap K
ndtceda21/LibertyUniversity/RaWa/Liberty%20University-Ramsey-Wallenmeyer-Neg-Texas-Round2.docx
null
52,755
RaWa
Liberty University RaWa
null
Jo.....
Ra.....
Ju.....
Wa.....
19,395
LibertyUniversity
Liberty University
null
null
1,011
ndtceda21
NDT/CEDA 2021-22
2,021
cx
college
2
3,203,379
“In the area” means all of the activities within the area
UN 13
UN 13, United Nations Law of the Sea Treaty, http://www.un.org/depts/los/convention_agreements/texts/unclos/part1.htm PART I¶ INTRODUCTION¶ Article 1
activities in the Area" means all activities of the Area
activities in the Area" means all activities of the Area
Use of terms and scope¶ 1. For the purposes of this Convention: (1) "Area" means the seabed and ocean floor and subsoil thereof, beyond the limits of national jurisdiction; (2) "Authority" means the International Seabed Authority; (3) "activities in the Area" means all activities of exploration for, and exploitation of, the resources of the Area;t
349
<h4>“In the area” means all of the activities within the area</h4><p><strong>UN 13</strong>, United Nations Law of the Sea Treaty, http://www.un.org/depts/los/convention_agreements/texts/unclos/part1.htm PART I¶ INTRODUCTION¶ Article 1</p><p>Use of terms and scope¶ 1. For the purposes of this Convention: (1) "Area" means the seabed and ocean floor and subsoil thereof, beyond the limits of national jurisdiction; (2) "Authority" means the International Seabed Authority; (3) "<u><mark>activities in the Area" means all activities</u></mark> of exploration for, and exploitation of, the resources <u><mark>of the Area</u></mark>;t</p>
null
null
x
1,351,739
8
103,672
./documents/ndtceda18/WichitaState/HiPh/Wichita%20State-Hinecker-Phillips-Neg-kentucky-Round3.docx
609,460
N
kentucky
3
Missouri state
Allison Harper
1ac - trade 1nc - t-restrict wto cp oil cp esr cp executive powers midterms dollar heg da on case 2nr - midterms
ndtceda18/WichitaState/HiPh/Wichita%20State-Hinecker-Phillips-Neg-kentucky-Round3.docx
null
51,654
HiPh
Wichita State HiPh
null
Al.....
Hi.....
Bo.....
Ph.....
19,231
WichitaState
Wichita State
null
null
1,008
ndtceda18
NDT/CEDA 2018-19
2,018
cx
college
2
3,629,550
Economic decline leads to nuclear war.
Tonnesson 15
Tonnesson 15 [Stein Tonnesson, Research Professor, Peace Research Institute Oslo; Leader of East Asia Peace program, Uppsala University, 2015, “Deterrence, interdependence and Sino–US peace,” International Area Studies Review, Vol. 18, No. 3, p. 297-311] JS
recent works have made contributions to the current understanding of how and under what circumstances nuclear deterrence and economic interdependence may reduce the risk of war between major powers interdependence may both inhibit and drive conflict Interdependence raises the cost of conflict but asymmetrical or unbalanced dependencies and negative trade expectations generate tensions leading to trade wars among inter-dependent states that increase the risk of military conflict decisions for war are taken by very few people, who act on the basis of their future expectations If leaders begin to seriously fear or anticipate their own nation’s decline they may blame external dependence, appeal to anti-foreign sentiments, contemplate the use of force to gain credibility, adopt protectionist policies, and refuse to be deterred by nuclear arms or prospects of socioeconomic calamities. Such a dangerous shift could happen abruptly in East Asia The greatest risk is not a territorial dispute but that changes in the world economy alter those circumstances in ways that render inter-state peace more precarious This could have unforeseen consequences in the field of security, with nuclear deterrence remaining the only factor to protect the world from Armageddon, and unreliably so. Deterrence could lose its credibility great powers might gamble that the other yield in a cyber-war or conventional war
Interdependence raises the cost of conflict If leaders seriously anticipate their nation’s decline they may blame external dependence, appeal to anti-foreign sentiments, contemplate force and refuse to be deterred by nuclear arms a shift could happen abruptly The greatest risk is changes in the world economy alter circumstances in ways that render inter-state peace precarious This could have consequences with nuclear deterrence the only factor to protect from Armageddon, Deterrence could lose credibility great powers might gamble in a cyber or conventional war
Several recent works on China and Sino–US relations have made substantial contributions to the current understanding of how and under what circumstances a combination of nuclear deterrence and economic interdependence may reduce the risk of war between major powers. At least four conclusions can be drawn from the review above: first, those who say that interdependence may both inhibit and drive conflict are right. Interdependence raises the cost of conflict for all sides but asymmetrical or unbalanced dependencies and negative trade expectations may generate tensions leading to trade wars among inter-dependent states that in turn increase the risk of military conflict (Copeland, 2015: 1, 14, 437; Roach, 2014). The risk may increase if one of the interdependent countries is governed by an inward-looking socio-economic coalition (Solingen, 2015); second, the risk of war between China and the US should not just be analysed bilaterally but include their allies and partners. Third party countries could drag China or the US into confrontation; third, in this context it is of some comfort that the three main economic powers in Northeast Asia (China, Japan and South Korea) are all deeply integrated economically through production networks within a global system of trade and finance (Ravenhill, 2014; Yoshimatsu, 2014: 576); and fourth, decisions for war and peace are taken by very few people, who act on the basis of their future expectations. International relations theory must be supplemented by foreign policy analysis in order to assess the value attributed by national decision-makers to economic development and their assessments of risks and opportunities. If leaders on either side of the Atlantic begin to seriously fear or anticipate their own nation’s decline then they may blame this on external dependence, appeal to anti-foreign sentiments, contemplate the use of force to gain respect or credibility, adopt protectionist policies, and ultimately refuse to be deterred by either nuclear arms or prospects of socioeconomic calamities. Such a dangerous shift could happen abruptly, i.e. under the instigation of actions by a third party – or against a third party. Yet as long as there is both nuclear deterrence and interdependence, the tensions in East Asia are unlikely to escalate to war. As Chan (2013) says, all states in the region are aware that they cannot count on support from either China or the US if they make provocative moves. The greatest risk is not that a territorial dispute leads to war under present circumstances but that changes in the world economy alter those circumstances in ways that render inter-state peace more precarious. If China and the US fail to rebalance their financial and trading relations (Roach, 2014) then a trade war could result, interrupting transnational production networks, provoking social distress, and exacerbating nationalist emotions. This could have unforeseen consequences in the field of security, with nuclear deterrence remaining the only factor to protect the world from Armageddon, and unreliably so. Deterrence could lose its credibility: one of the two great powers might gamble that the other yield in a cyber-war or conventional limited war, or third party countries might engage in conflict with each other, with a view to obliging Washington or Beijing to intervene.
3,361
<h4><strong>Economic decline leads to nuclear war.</h4><p><u>Tonnesson 15</u></strong> [Stein Tonnesson, Research Professor, Peace Research Institute Oslo; Leader of East Asia Peace program, Uppsala University, 2015, “Deterrence, interdependence and Sino–US peace,” International Area Studies Review, Vol. 18, No. 3, p. 297-311] JS</p><p>Several <u><strong>recent works</u></strong> on China and Sino–US relations <u><strong>have made</u></strong> substantial <u><strong>contributions to the current understanding of how and under what circumstances</u></strong> a combination of <u><strong>nuclear deterrence and economic interdependence may reduce the risk of war between major powers</u></strong>. At least four conclusions can be drawn from the review above: first, those who say that <u><strong>interdependence may both inhibit and drive conflict</u></strong> are right. <u><strong><mark>Interdependence raises the cost of conflict</u></strong></mark> for all sides <u><strong>but</u></strong> <u><strong>asymmetrical or unbalanced dependencies and negative trade expectations</u></strong> may <u><strong>generate tensions leading to trade wars among inter-dependent states that</u></strong> in turn <u><strong>increase the risk of military conflict</u></strong> (Copeland, 2015: 1, 14, 437; Roach, 2014). The risk may increase if one of the interdependent countries is governed by an inward-looking socio-economic coalition (Solingen, 2015); second, the risk of war between China and the US should not just be analysed bilaterally but include their allies and partners. Third party countries could drag China or the US into confrontation; third, in this context it is of some comfort that the three main economic powers in Northeast Asia (China, Japan and South Korea) are all deeply integrated economically through production networks within a global system of trade and finance (Ravenhill, 2014; Yoshimatsu, 2014: 576); and fourth, <u><strong>decisions for war</u></strong> and peace <u><strong>are taken by very few people, who act on the basis of their future expectations</u></strong>. International relations theory must be supplemented by foreign policy analysis in order to assess the value attributed by national decision-makers to economic development and their assessments of risks and opportunities. <u><strong><mark>If leaders</u></strong></mark> on either side of the Atlantic <u><strong>begin to <mark>seriously</mark> fear or <mark>anticipate their</mark> own <mark>nation’s decline</u></strong></mark> then <u><strong><mark>they may blame</u></strong></mark> this on <u><strong><mark>external dependence, appeal to anti-foreign sentiments, contemplate</mark> the use of <mark>force</mark> to gain</u></strong> respect or <u><strong>credibility, adopt protectionist policies, <mark>and</u></strong></mark> ultimately <u><strong><mark>refuse to be deterred by</u></strong></mark> either <u><strong><mark>nuclear arms</mark> or prospects of socioeconomic calamities. Such <mark>a</mark> dangerous <mark>shift could happen abruptly</u></strong></mark>, i.e. under the instigation of actions by a third party – or against a third party. Yet as long as there is both nuclear deterrence and interdependence, the tensions <u><strong>in East Asia</u></strong> are unlikely to escalate to war. As Chan (2013) says, all states in the region are aware that they cannot count on support from either China or the US if they make provocative moves. <u><strong><mark>The greatest risk is</mark> not</u></strong> that <u><strong>a territorial dispute</u></strong> leads to war under present circumstances <u><strong>but that <mark>changes in the world economy alter</mark> those <mark>circumstances in ways that render inter-state peace</mark> more <mark>precarious</u></strong></mark>. If China and the US fail to rebalance their financial and trading relations (Roach, 2014) then a trade war could result, interrupting transnational production networks, provoking social distress, and exacerbating nationalist emotions. <u><strong><mark>This could have</mark> unforeseen <mark>consequences</mark> in the field of security, <mark>with nuclear deterrence</mark> remaining <mark>the only factor to protect</mark> the world <mark>from Armageddon, </mark>and </strong>unreliably so. <mark>Deterrence<strong> could lose</mark> its <mark>credibility</u></strong></mark>: one of the two <u><strong><mark>great powers might gamble</mark> that the other yield <mark>in a cyber</mark>-war <mark>or conventional</u></strong></mark> limited <u><strong><mark>war</u></strong></mark>, or third party countries might engage in conflict with each other, with a view to obliging Washington or Beijing to intervene.</p>
null
Advantage 1 is Econ
null
142
3,586
120,839
./documents/hsld17/LaSalle/To/La%20Salle-Towner-Aff-Berkeley-Round4.docx
808,551
A
Berkeley
4
Harvard Westlake JN
John Overing
1AC Corporations 1NC Abolish T Mueller DA Case 1AR Must check T interps All 2NR 1AR shell Mueller DA Case 2AR Case DA Impact Turns
hsld17/LaSalle/To/La%20Salle-Towner-Aff-Berkeley-Round4.docx
null
69,286
AsTo
La Salle AsTo
null
As.....
To.....
null
null
23,482
LaSalle
La Salle
null
null
1,025
hsld17
HS LD 2017-18
2,017
ld
hs
1
2,474,035
That is the only egalitarian metric – anything else collapses cooperation on collective action crises and makes extinction inevitable
Khan 18. /
Risalat Khan 18. Risalat, activist and entrepreneur from Bangladesh passionate about addressing climate change, biodiversity loss, and other existential challenges. He was featured by The Guardian as one of the “young climate campaigners to watch” (2015). As a campaigner with the global civic movement Avaaz (2014-17), Risalat was part of a small core team that spearheaded the largest climate marches in history with a turnout of over 800,000 across 2,000 cities. After fighting for the Paris Agreement, Risalat led a campaign joined by over a million people to stop the Rampal coal plant in Bangladesh to protect the Sundarbans World Heritage forest, and elicited criticism of the plant from Crédit Agricolé through targeted advocacy. Currently, Risalat is pursuing an MPA in Environmental Science and Policy at Columbia University as a SIPA Environmental Fellow, “5 reasons why we need to start talking about existential risks,” https://www.weforum.org/agenda/2018/01/5-reasons-start-talking-existential-risks-extinction-moriori/
Infinite possibilities human culture is far from immutable we can master them and rise to unprecedented challenges even this does not make us masters of our own destiny. We can make visionary choices, but the future can still surprise us. faced with an uncertain future, the only wise thing we can do is prepare the possibilities seem endless. They range from abundance to the end of humanity Among the infinite future possibilities, only one outcome is truly irreversible: extinction Concerns are dismissed as apocalyptic alarmism repeating that mankind is still here after 70 years of existential warning about nuclear warfare is a straw man argument. The fact that a 1000-year flood has not happened does not negate its possibility there have been far too many nuclear near-misses to rest easy. Davos discusses five reasons why the possibility of existential risks should raise the stakes of conversation: Extinction is the rule, not the exception 99.9% of all the species that ever existed are gone Deep time is unfathomable if one cares to take a tour of the billions of years of life’s history, we find a litany of forgotten species. 99.9% of all human cultures that have ever existed are extinct. It is only in the very recent past that we became a truly global civilization 15,000 scientists just issued a ‘warning to humanity’ Diamond charts the history of past societies overpopulation and resource use beyond the carrying capacity have often been important, of collapse. we must achieve tremendous changes in our response to several major environmental crises. Bostrom cites a survey of industry experts that projected a 50% chance of the development of artificial superintelligence by 2050 and a 90% chance by 2075 Visionaries warned of the existential risks from artificial superintelligence. Throughout history, we have rallied against the ‘other’ Tribes overpowered tribes, empires have conquered rivals our fiercest displays of unity typically happen at wartime. We we 21st-century citizens find ourselves on an increasingly unstable island. We may have a violent past, but we have no more dangerous enemy than ourselves Our task is to find Our own shared contract, based on equity, would help us navigate safely. would ensure a future that unleashes the full potential of our still-budding human civilization, in all its diversity. We cannot do this unless we are humbly grounded in the possibility of our own destruction Survival is life’s primal instinct In the absence of a common enemy, we must find common cause in survival. Our future may depend on whether we realize this.
human culture is far from immutable. we can rise to challenges faced with an uncertain future, the only wise thing we can do is prepare only one outcome is truly irreversible: extinction. Concerns are dismissed there have been far too many nuclear near-misses to rest easy. Extinction is the rule 99.9% of all the species that ever existed are gone. Deep time is unfathomable billions of years of life’s history find litany of forgotten species displays of unity typically happen at wartime. We may have a violent past, but no more dangerous enemy than ourselves equity, would help us navigate safely. a future that unleashes the full potential of our civilization We cannot do this unless we are humbly grounded in the possibility of our own destruction. Survival is life’s primal instinct. In the absence of a common enemy, we must find common cause in survival.
Infinite future possibilities I find the story of the Moriori profound. It teaches me two lessons. Firstly, that human culture is far from immutable. That we can struggle against our baser instincts. That we can master them and rise to unprecedented challenges. Secondly, that even this does not make us masters of our own destiny. We can make visionary choices, but the future can still surprise us. This is a humbling realization. Because faced with an uncertain future, the only wise thing we can do is prepare for possibilities. Standing at the launch pad of the Fourth Industrial Revolution, the possibilities seem endless. They range from an era of abundance to the end of humanity, and everything in between. How do we navigate such a wide and divergent spectrum? I am an optimist. From my bubble of privilege, life feels like a rollercoaster ride full of ever more impressive wonders, even as I try to fight the many social injustices that still blight us. However, the accelerating pace of change amid uncertainty elicits one fundamental observation. Among the infinite future possibilities, only one outcome is truly irreversible: extinction. Concerns about extinction are often dismissed as apocalyptic alarmism. Sometimes, they are. But repeating that mankind is still here after 70 years of existential warning about nuclear warfare is a straw man argument. The fact that a 1000-year flood has not happened does not negate its possibility. And there have been far too many nuclear near-misses to rest easy. As the World Economic Forum’s Annual Meeting in Davos discusses how to create a shared future in a fractured world, here are five reasons why the possibility of existential risks should raise the stakes of conversation: 1. Extinction is the rule, not the exception More than 99.9% of all the species that ever existed are gone. Deep time is unfathomable to the human brain. But if one cares to take a tour of the billions of years of life’s history, we find a litany of forgotten species. And we have only discovered a mere fraction of the extinct species that once roamed the planet. In the speck of time since the first humans evolved, more than 99.9% of all the distinct human cultures that have ever existed are extinct. Each hunter-gatherer tribe had its own mythologies, traditions and norms. They wiped each other out, or coalesced into larger formations following the agricultural revolution. However, as major civilizations emerged, even those that reached incredible heights, such as the Egyptians and the Romans, eventually collapsed. It is only in the very recent past that we became a truly global civilization. Our interconnectedness continues to grow rapidly. “Stand or fall, we are the last civilization”, as Ricken Patel, the founder of the global civic movement Avaaz, put it. 2. Environmental pressures can drive extinction More than 15,000 scientists just issued a ‘warning to humanity’. They called on us to reduce our impact on the biosphere, 25 years after their first such appeal. The warning notes that we are far outstripping the capacity of our planet in all but one measure of ozone depletion, including emissions, biodiversity, freshwater availability and more. The scientists, not a crowd known to overstate facts, conclude: “soon it will be too late to shift course away from our failing trajectory, and time is running out”. In his 2005 book Collapse, Jared Diamond charts the history of past societies. He makes the case that overpopulation and resource use beyond the carrying capacity have often been important, if not the only, drivers of collapse. Even though we are making important incremental progress in battles such as climate change, we must still achieve tremendous step changes in our response to several major environmental crises. We must do this even while the world’s population continues to grow. These pressures are bound to exert great stress on our global civilization. 3. Superintelligence: unplanned obsolescence? Imagine a monkey society that foresaw the ascendance of humans. Fearing a loss of status and power, it decided to kill the proverbial Adam and Eve. It crafted the most ingenious plan it could: starve the humans by taking away all their bananas. Foolproof plan, right? This story describes the fundamental difficulty with superintelligence. A superintelligent being may always do something entirely different from what we, with our mere mortal intelligence, can foresee. In his 2014 book Superintelligence, Swedish philosopher Nick Bostrom presents the challenge in thought-provoking detail, and advises caution. Bostrom cites a survey of industry experts that projected a 50% chance of the development of artificial superintelligence by 2050, and a 90% chance by 2075. The latter date is within the life expectancy of many alive today. Visionaries like Stephen Hawking and Elon Musk have warned of the existential risks from artificial superintelligence. Their opposite camp includes Larry Page and Mark Zuckerberg. But on an issue that concerns the future of humanity, is it really wise to ignore the guy who explained the nature of space to us and another guy who just put a reusable rocket in it? 4. Technology: known knowns and unknown unknowns Many fundamentally disruptive technologies are coming of age, from bioengineering to quantum computing, 3-D printing, robotics, nanotechnology and more. Lord Martin Rees describes potential existential challenges from some of these technologies, such as a bioengineered pandemic, in his book Our Final Century. Imagine if North Korea, feeling secure in its isolation, could release a virulent strain of Ebola, engineered to be airborne. Would it do it? Would ISIS? Projecting decades forward, we will likely develop capabilities that are unthinkable even now. The unknown unknowns of our technological path are profoundly humbling. 5. 'The Trump Factor' Despite our scientific ingenuity, we are still a confused and confusing species. Think back to two years ago, and how you thought the world worked then. Has that not been upended by the election of Donald Trump as US President, and everything that has happened since? The mix of billions of messy humans will forever be unpredictable. When the combustible forces described above are added to this melee, we find ourselves on a tightrope. What choices must we now make now to create a shared future, in which we are not at perpetual risk of destroying ourselves? Common enemy to common cause Throughout history, we have rallied against the ‘other’. Tribes have overpowered tribes, empires have conquered rivals. Even today, our fiercest displays of unity typically happen at wartime. We give our lives for our motherland and defend nationalistic pride like a wounded lion. But like the early Morioris, we 21st-century citizens find ourselves on an increasingly unstable island. We may have a violent past, but we have no more dangerous enemy than ourselves Our task is to find our own Nunuku’s Law. Our own shared contract, based on equity, would help us navigate safely. It would ensure a future that unleashes the full potential of our still-budding human civilization, in all its diversity. We cannot do this unless we are humbly grounded in the possibility of our own destruction. Survival is life’s primal instinct. In the absence of a common enemy, we must find common cause in survival. Our future may depend on whether we realize this.
7,434
<h4>That is the only <u>egalitarian metric</u> – anything else collapses cooperation on <u>collective action</u> crises and makes extinction inevitable </h4><p>Risalat<strong> Khan 18. </strong>Risalat, activist and entrepreneur from Bangladesh passionate about addressing climate change, biodiversity loss, and other existential challenges. He was featured by The Guardian as one of the “young climate campaigners to watch” (2015). As a campaigner with the global civic movement Avaaz (2014-17), Risalat was part of a small core team that spearheaded the largest climate marches in history with a turnout of over 800,000 across 2,000 cities. After fighting for the Paris Agreement, Risalat led a campaign joined by over a million people to stop the Rampal coal plant in Bangladesh to protect the Sundarbans World Heritage forest, and elicited criticism of the plant from Crédit Agricolé through targeted advocacy. Currently, Risalat is pursuing an MPA in Environmental Science and Policy at Columbia University as a SIPA Environmental Fellow, “5 reasons why we need to start talking about existential risks,” https://www.weforum.org/agenda/2018/01/5-reasons-start-talking-existential-risks-extinction-moriori<u><strong><mark>/</p><p></mark>Infinite</u></strong> future <u><strong>possibilities</u></strong> I find the story of the Moriori profound. It teaches me two lessons. Firstly, that <u><mark>human culture is <strong>far from immutable</u></strong>.</mark> That we can struggle against our baser instincts. That <u><strong><mark>we can</mark> master them and <mark>rise to</mark> unprecedented <mark>challenges</u></strong></mark>. Secondly, that <u>even this does not make us masters of our own destiny. We can make visionary choices, but the future can still surprise us. </u>This is a humbling realization. Because <u><strong><mark>faced with an uncertain future, the only wise thing we can do is prepare</u></strong></mark> for possibilities. Standing at the launch pad of the Fourth Industrial Revolution, <u>the possibilities seem endless. They range from</u> an era of <u>abundance to the end of humanity</u>, and everything in between. How do we navigate such a wide and divergent spectrum? I am an optimist. From my bubble of privilege, life feels like a rollercoaster ride full of ever more impressive wonders, even as I try to fight the many social injustices that still blight us. However, the accelerating pace of change amid uncertainty elicits one fundamental observation. <u>Among the infinite future possibilities<strong>, <mark>only one outcome is truly irreversible: extinction</u></strong>. <u>Concerns</u></mark> about extinction <u><mark>are</u></mark> often <u><mark>dismissed</mark> as <strong>apocalyptic alarmism</u></strong>. Sometimes, they are. But <u>repeating that mankind is still here after 70 years of existential warning about nuclear warfare is a <strong>straw man argument</strong>.</u> <u><strong>The fact that a 1000-year flood has not happened does not negate its possibility</u></strong>. And <u><mark>there have been <strong>far too many nuclear near-misses to rest easy.</mark> </u></strong>As the World Economic Forum’s Annual Meeting in <u>Davos discusses</u> how to create a shared future in a fractured world, here are <u>five reasons why the possibility of existential risks should raise the stakes of conversation: </u>1. <u><strong><mark>Extinction is the rule</mark>, not the exception</u></strong> More than <u><mark>99.9% of all the species that ever existed are gone</u>. <u><strong>Deep time is unfathomable</u></strong></mark> to the human brain. But <u>if one cares to take a tour of the <mark>billions of years of life’s history</mark>, we <mark>find</mark> a <mark>litany of forgotten species</mark>. </u>And we have only discovered a mere fraction of the extinct species that once roamed the planet. In the speck of time since the first humans evolved, more than <u>99.9% of all</u> the distinct <u>human cultures that have ever existed are extinct.</u> Each hunter-gatherer tribe had its own mythologies, traditions and norms. They wiped each other out, or coalesced into larger formations following the agricultural revolution. However, as major civilizations emerged, even those that reached incredible heights, such as the Egyptians and the Romans, eventually collapsed. <u>It is only in the very recent past that we became a truly global civilization</u>. Our interconnectedness continues to grow rapidly. “Stand or fall, we are the last civilization”, as Ricken Patel, the founder of the global civic movement Avaaz, put it. 2. Environmental pressures can drive extinction More than <u>15,000 scientists just issued a ‘warning to humanity’</u>. They called on us to reduce our impact on the biosphere, 25 years after their first such appeal. The warning notes that we are far outstripping the capacity of our planet in all but one measure of ozone depletion, including emissions, biodiversity, freshwater availability and more. The scientists, not a crowd known to overstate facts, conclude: “soon it will be too late to shift course away from our failing trajectory, and time is running out”. In his 2005 book Collapse, Jared <u>Diamond charts the history of past societies</u>. He makes the case that <u>overpopulation and resource use beyond the carrying capacity have often been important, </u>if not the only, drivers <u>of collapse. </u>Even though we are making important incremental progress in battles such as climate change, <u>we must</u> still <u>achieve tremendous </u>step <u>changes in our response to several major environmental crises.</u> We must do this even while the world’s population continues to grow. These pressures are bound to exert great stress on our global civilization. 3. Superintelligence: unplanned obsolescence? Imagine a monkey society that foresaw the ascendance of humans. Fearing a loss of status and power, it decided to kill the proverbial Adam and Eve. It crafted the most ingenious plan it could: starve the humans by taking away all their bananas. Foolproof plan, right? This story describes the fundamental difficulty with superintelligence. A superintelligent being may always do something entirely different from what we, with our mere mortal intelligence, can foresee. In his 2014 book Superintelligence, Swedish philosopher Nick Bostrom presents the challenge in thought-provoking detail, and advises caution. <u><strong>Bostrom cites a survey of industry experts that projected a 50% chance of the development of artificial superintelligence by 2050</u></strong>, <u><strong>and a 90% chance by 2075</u></strong>. The latter date is within the life expectancy of many alive today. <u>Visionaries</u> like Stephen Hawking and Elon Musk have <u>warned of the existential risks from artificial superintelligence. </u>Their opposite camp includes Larry Page and Mark Zuckerberg. But on an issue that concerns the future of humanity, is it really wise to ignore the guy who explained the nature of space to us and another guy who just put a reusable rocket in it? 4. Technology: known knowns and unknown unknowns Many fundamentally disruptive technologies are coming of age, from bioengineering to quantum computing, 3-D printing, robotics, nanotechnology and more. Lord Martin Rees describes potential existential challenges from some of these technologies, such as a bioengineered pandemic, in his book Our Final Century. Imagine if North Korea, feeling secure in its isolation, could release a virulent strain of Ebola, engineered to be airborne. Would it do it? Would ISIS? Projecting decades forward, we will likely develop capabilities that are unthinkable even now. The unknown unknowns of our technological path are profoundly humbling. 5. 'The Trump Factor' Despite our scientific ingenuity, we are still a confused and confusing species. Think back to two years ago, and how you thought the world worked then. Has that not been upended by the election of Donald Trump as US President, and everything that has happened since? The mix of billions of messy humans will forever be unpredictable. When the combustible forces described above are added to this melee, we find ourselves on a tightrope. What choices must we now make now to create a shared future, in which we are not at perpetual risk of destroying ourselves? Common enemy to common cause <u>Throughout history, we have rallied against the ‘other’</u>. <u>Tribes</u> have <u>overpowered tribes,</u> <u>empires have conquered rivals</u>. Even today, <u>our fiercest <mark>displays of unity typically happen at wartime.</mark> We</u> give our lives for our motherland and defend nationalistic pride like a wounded lion. But like the early Morioris, <u>we 21st-century citizens find ourselves on an <strong>increasingly unstable island</strong>.</u> <u><mark>We may have a violent past, but</mark> <strong>we have <mark>no more dangerous enemy than ourselves</u></strong></mark> <u>Our task is to find</u> our own Nunuku’s Law. <u>Our own shared contract, based on <mark>equity, would help us navigate safely.</u></mark> It <u>would ensure <mark>a future that unleashes the full potential of our</mark> still-budding human <mark>civilization</mark>, in all its diversity. <mark>We cannot do this unless we are <strong>humbly grounded in the possibility of our own destruction</u></strong>. <u><strong>Survival is life’s primal instinct</u></strong>. <u>In the absence of a common enemy, we must find common cause in survival.</mark> Our future may depend on whether we realize this.</p></u>
null
Russia Debris
Debris---1AC
18,273
838
80,364
./documents/ndtceda19/Emory/GiSh/Emory-Giampetruzzi-Shaikh-Aff-Kentucky-Round2.docx
610,926
A
Kentucky
2
Kentucky KL
Adam Lipton
1AC - Heg Russia Debris 1NC - K 2NR - K
ndtceda19/Emory/GiSh/Emory-Giampetruzzi-Shaikh-Aff-Kentucky-Round2.docx
null
51,763
GiSh
Emory GiSh
null
Eu.....
Gi.....
Za.....
Sh.....
19,247
Emory
Emory
null
null
1,009
ndtceda19
NDT/CEDA 2019-20
2,019
cx
college
2
2,165,556
A] Extinction outweighs---it’s the upmost moral evil and disavowal of the risk makes it more likely.
Burns 2017 (
Burns 2017 (Elizabeth Finneron-Burns is a Teaching Fellow at the University of Warwick and an Affiliated Researcher at the Institute for Futures Studies in Stockholm, What’s wrong with human extinction?, http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/pdf/10.1080/00455091.2016.1278150?needAccess=true, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 2017)
extinction would prevent the existence of very many people it is a good thing for people to exist and extinction would deprive more people of enjoying this The ‘good could be understood in two ways. first it is good for that person that they come to exist if humans were to go extinct the utility foregone by the billions (or more) of people who could have lived but will now never get that opportunity billions of people would likely die painful deaths The worst thing about human extinction is that there would be no future generations the value of all those generations together greatly exceeds the value of the current generation there is value in human life and something valuable about creating future people When we talk about future lives being ‘prevented’, we are saying that a possible set of people who could potentially have existed will now never actually come to exist It would mean the loss of the only known form of intelligent life and all civilization and intellectual progress would be lost humans’ capacity for rationality is valuable in itself we ought also to prevent human extinction for the sake of biodiversity Existing people would endure physical pain and/or painful and/or premature deaths Each scenario would involve significant physical and/ non-physical harms extinction could cause premature death A nuclear winter that killed everyone or even just every woman under the age of 50 is a clear example of such a case being caused to die prematurely can be reason to reject a principle when it fails to show respect to the person as a rational agent appreciating the value of human life is primarily a matter of seeing human lives as to be respected taking someone’s life without their permission shows disrespect to that person if they are killed without their consent, their interests have not been taken into account a nuclear bomb that did not kill anyone, but did painfully render them infertile through illness or injury Existing people could endure non-physical harms the fact there would not be any future people could give rise to a personal reason there could be various deleterious psychological effects There are two main sources of this trauma The first relates to individual people and the undesired negative effect on well-being that would be experienced by those who would have wanted to have children this is by no means universa it is fair to say that a good proportion of people feel a strong pull towards reproduction The second is a higher level sense of hopelessness or despair that there will be no more humans and that your projects will end with you Even those who did not feel a strong desire to procreate themselves might feel a sense of hopelessness that any projects or goals they have for the future would not be fulfilled without the hope of posterity for our race all pleasures of the mind and senses sometimes seem to me no more than pathetic and crumbling defences shored up against our ruins’ Both sources of psychological harm are personal reasons to reject a principle that permitted human extinction
it is good for people to exist and extinction would deprive people of this billions of people would die painful deaths there would be no future generations the value of all those generations together greatly exceeds the value of the current generation It would mean the loss of the only known form of intelligent life humans’ capacity for rationality is valuable in itself Existing people would endure physical pain and painful premature deaths there could be various psychological effects sense of hopelessness there will be no more humans and that your projects will end with you.
Many, though certainly not all, people might believe that it would be wrong to bring about the end of the human species, and the reasons given for this belief are various. I begin by considering four reasons that could be given against the moral permissibility of human extinction. I will argue that only those reasons that impact the people who exist at the time that the extinction or the knowledge of the upcoming extinction occurs, can explain its wrongness. I use this conclusion to then consider in which cases human extinction would be morally permissible or impermissible, arguing that there is only a small class of cases in which it would not be wrong to cause the extinction of the human race or allow it to happen. 2.1. It would prevent the existence of very many happy people One reason of human extinction might be considered to be wrong lies in the value of human life itself. The thought here might be that it is a good thing for people to exist and enjoy happy lives and extinction would deprive more people of enjoying this good. The ‘good’ in this case could be understood in at least two ways. According to the first, one might believe that you benefit a person by bringing them into existence, or at least, that it is good for that person that they come to exist. The second view might hold that if humans were to go extinct, the utility foregone by the billions (or more) of people who could have lived but will now never get that opportunity, renders allowing human extinction to take place an incidence of wrongdoing. An example of this view can be found in two quotes from an Effective Altruism blog post by Peter Singer, Nick Beckstead and Matt Wage: One very bad thing about human extinction would be that billions of people would likely die painful deaths. But in our view, this is by far not the worst thing about human extinction. The worst thing about human extinction is that there would be no future generations. Since there could be so many generations in our future, the value of all those generations together greatly exceeds the value of the current generation. (Beckstead, Singer, and Wage 2013) The authors are making two claims. The first is that there is value in human life and also something valuable about creating future people which gives us a reason to do so; furthermore, it would be a very bad thing if we did not do so. The second is that, not only would it be a bad thing for there to be no future people, but it would actually be the worst thing about extinction. Since happy human lives have value, and the number of potential people who could ever exist is far greater than the number of people who exist at any one time, even if the extinction were brought about through the painful deaths of currently existing people, the former’s loss would be greater than the latter’s. Both claims are assuming that there is an intrinsic value in the existence of potential human life. The second claim makes the further assumption that the forgone value of the potential lives that could be lived is greater than the disvalue that would be accrued by people existing at the time of the extinction through suffering from painful and/or premature deaths. The best-known author of the post, Peter Singer is a prominent utilitarian, so it is not surprising that he would lament the potential lack of future human lives per se. However, it is not just utilitarians who share this view, even if implicitly. Indeed, other philosophers also seem to imply that they share the intuition that there is just something wrong with causing or failing to prevent the extinction of the human species such that we prevent more ‘people’ from having the ‘opportunity to exist’. Stephen Gardiner (2009) and Martin O’Neill (personal correspondence), both sympathetic to contract theory, for example, also find it intuitive that we should want more generations to have the opportunity to exist, assuming that they have worth-living lives, and I find it plausible to think that many other people (philosophers and non-philosophers alike) probably share this intuition. When we talk about future lives being ‘prevented’, we are saying that a possible person or a set of possible people who could potentially have existed will now never actually come to exist. To say that it is wrong to prevent people from existing could either mean that a possible person could reasonably reject a principle that permitted us not to create them, or that the foregone value of their lives provides a reason for rejecting any principle that permits extinction. To make the first claim we would have to argue that a possible person could reasonably reject any principle that prevented their existence on the grounds that it prevented them in particular from existing. However, this is implausible for two reasons. First, we can only wrong someone who did, does or will actually exist because wronging involves failing to take a person’s interests into account. When considering the permissibility of a principle allowing us not to create Person X, we cannot take X’s interest in being created into account because X will not exist if we follow the principle. By considering the standpoint of a person in our deliberations we consider the burdens they will have to bear as a result of the principle. In this case, there is no one who will bear any burdens since if the principle is followed (that is, if we do not create X), X will not exist to bear any burdens. So, only people who do/will actually exist can bear the brunt of a principle, and therefore occupy a standpoint that is owed justification. Second, existence is not an interest at all and a possible person is not disadvantaged by not being caused to exist. Rather than being an interest, it is a necessary requirement in order to have interests. Rivka Weinberg describes it as ‘neutral’ because causing a person to exist is to create a subject who can have interests; existence is not an interest itself.3 In order to be disadvantaged, there must be some detrimental effect on your interests. However, without existence, a person does not have any interests so they cannot be disadvantaged by being kept out of existence. But, as Weinberg points out, ‘never having interests itself could not be contrary to people’s interests since without interest bearers, there can be no ‘they’ for it to be bad for’ (Weinberg 2008, 13). So, a principle that results in some possible people never becoming actual does not impose any costs on those ‘people’ because nobody is disadvantaged by not coming into existence.4 It therefore seems that it cannot be wrong to fail to bring particular people into existence. This would mean that no one acts wrongly when they fail to create another person. Writ large, it would also not be wrong if everybody decided to exercise their prerogative not to create new people and potentially, by consequence, allow human extinction. One might respond here by saying that although it may be permissible for one person to fail to create a new person, it is not permissible if everyone chooses to do so because human lives have value and allowing human extinction would be to forgo a huge amount of value in the world. This takes us to the second way of understanding the potential wrongness of preventing people from existing — the foregone value of a life provides a reason for rejecting any principle that prevents it. One possible reply to this claim turns on the fact that many philosophers acknowledge that the only, or at least the best, way to think about the value of (individual or groups of) possible people’s lives is in impersonal terms (Parfit 1984; Reiman 2007; McMahan 2009). Jeff McMahan, for example, writes ‘at the time of one’s choice there is no one who exists or will exist independently of that choice for whose sake one could be acting in causing him or her to exist … it seems therefore that any reason to cause or not to cause an individual to exist … is best considered an impersonal rather than individual-affecting reason’ (McMahan 2009, 52). Another reply along similar lines would be to appeal to the value that is lost or at least foregone when we fail to bring into existence a next (or several next) generations of people with worth-living lives. Since ex hypothesi worth-living lives have positive value, it is better to create more such lives and worse to create fewer. Human extinction by definition is the creation of no future lives and would ‘deprive’ billions of ‘people’ of the opportunity to live worth-living lives. This might reduce the amount of value in the world at the time of the extinction (by killing already existing people), but it would also prevent a much vaster amount of value in the future (by failing to create more people). Both replies depend on the impersonal value of human life. However, recall that in contractualism impersonal values are not on their own grounds for reasonably rejecting principles. Scanlon himself says that although we have a strong reason not to destroy existing human lives, this reason ‘does not flow from the thought that it is a good thing for there to be more human life rather than less’ (104). In contractualism, something cannot be wrong unless there is an impact on a person. Thus, neither the impersonal value of creating a particular person nor the impersonal value of human life writ large could on its own provide a reason for rejecting a principle permitting human extinction. It seems therefore that the fact that extinction would deprive future people of the opportunity to live worth-living lives (either by failing to create either particular future people or future people in general) cannot provide us with a reason to consider human extinction to be wrong. Although the lost value of these ‘lives’ itself cannot be the reason explaining the wrongness of extinction, it is possible the knowledge of this loss might create a personal reason for some existing people. I will consider this possibility later on in section (d). But first I move to the second reason human extinction might be wrong per se. 2.2. It would mean the loss of the only known form of intelligent life and all civilization and intellectual progress would be lost A second reason we might think it would be wrong to cause human extinction is the loss that would occur of the only (known) form of rational life and the knowledge and civilization that that form of life has created. One thought here could be that just as some might consider it wrong to destroy an individual human heritage monument like the Sphinx, it would also be wrong if the advances made by humans over the past few millennia were lost or prevented from progressing. A related argument is made by those who feel that there is something special about humans’ capacity for rationality which is valuable in itself. Since humans are the only intelligent life that we know of, it would be a loss, in itself, to the world for that to end. I admit that I struggle to fully appreciate this thought. It seems to me that Henry Sidgwick was correct in thinking that these things are only important insofar as they are important to humans (Sidgwick 1874, I.IX.4).5 If there is no form of intelligent life in the future, who would there be to lament its loss since intelligent life is the only form of life capable of appreciating intelligence? Similarly, if there is no one with the rational capacity to appreciate historic monuments and civil progress, who would there be to be negatively affected or even notice the loss?6 However, even if there is nothing special about human rationality, just as some people try to prevent the extinction of nonhuman animal species, we might think that we ought also to prevent human extinction for the sake of biodiversity. The thought in this, as well as the earlier examples, must be that it would somehow be bad for the world if there were no more humans even though there would be no one for whom it is bad. This may be so but the only way to understand this reason is impersonally. Since we are concerned with wrongness rather than badness, we must ask whether something that impacts no one’s well-being, status or claims can be wrong. As we saw earlier, in the contractualist framework reasons must be personal rather than impersonal in order to provide grounds for reasonable rejection (Scanlon 1998, 218–223). Since the loss of civilization, intelligent life or biodiversity are per se impersonal reasons, there is no standpoint from which these reasons could be used to reasonably reject a principle that permitted extinction. Therefore, causing human extinction on the grounds of the loss of civilization, rational life or biodiversity would not be wrong. 2.3. Existing people would endure physical pain and/or painful and/or premature deaths Thinking about the ways in which human extinction might come about brings to the fore two more reasons it might be wrong. It could, for example, occur if all humans (or at least the critical number needed to be unable to replenish the population, leading to eventual extinction) underwent a sterilization procedure. Or perhaps it could come about due to anthropogenic climate change or a massive asteroid hitting the Earth and wiping out the species in the same way it did the dinosaurs millions of years ago. Each of these scenarios would involve significant physical and/or non-physical harms to existing people and their interests. Physically, people might suffer premature and possibly also painful deaths, for example. It is not hard to imagine examples in which the process of extinction could cause premature death. A nuclear winter that killed everyone or even just every woman under the age of 50 is a clear example of such a case. Obviously, some types of premature death themselves cannot be reasons to reject a principle. Every person dies eventually, sometimes earlier than the standard expected lifespan due to accidents or causes like spontaneously occurring incurable cancers. A cause such as disease is not a moral agent and therefore it cannot be wrong if it unavoidably kills a person prematurely. Scanlon says that the fact that a principle would reduce a person’s well-being gives that person a reason to reject the principle: ‘components of well-being figure prominently as grounds for reasonable rejection’ (Scanlon 1998, 214). However, it is not settled yet whether premature death is a setback to well-being. Some philosophers hold that death is a harm to the person who dies, whilst others argue that it is not.7 I will argue, however, that regardless of who is correct in that debate, being caused to die prematurely can be reason to reject a principle when it fails to show respect to the person as a rational agent. Scanlon says that recognizing others as rational beings with interests involves seeing reason to preserve life and prevent death: ‘appreciating the value of human life is primarily a matter of seeing human lives as something to be respected, where this involves seeing reasons not to destroy them, reasons to protect them, and reasons to want them to go well’ (Scanlon 1998, 104). The ‘respect for life’ in this case is a respect for the person living, not respect for human life in the abstract. This means that we can sometimes fail to protect human life without acting wrongfully if we still respect the person living. Scanlon gives the example of a person who faces a life of unending and extreme pain such that she wishes to end it by committing suicide. Scanlon does not think that the suicidal person shows a lack of respect for her own life by seeking to end it because the person whose life it is has no reason to want it to go on. This is important to note because it emphasizes the fact that the respect for human life is person-affecting. It is not wrong to murder because of the impersonal disvalue of death in general, but because taking someone’s life without their permission shows disrespect to that person. This supports its inclusion as a reason in the contractualist formula, regardless of what side ends up winning the ‘is death a harm?’ debate because even if death turns out not to harm the person who died, ending their life without their consent shows disrespect to that person. A person who could reject a principle permitting another to cause his or her premature death presumably does not wish to die at that time, or in that manner. Thus, if they are killed without their consent, their interests have not been taken into account, and they have a reason to reject the principle that allowed their premature death.8 This is as true in the case of death due to extinction as it is for death due to murder. However, physical pain may also be caused to existing people without killing them, but still resulting in human extinction. Imagine, for example, surgically removing everyone’s reproductive organs in order to prevent the creation of any future people. Another example could be a nuclear bomb that did not kill anyone, but did painfully render them infertile through illness or injury. These would be cases in which physical pain (through surgery or bombs) was inflicted on existing people and the extinction came about as a result of the painful incident rather than through death. Furthermore, one could imagine a situation in which a bomb (for example) killed enough people to cause extinction, but some people remained alive, but in terrible pain from injuries. It seems uncontroversial that the infliction of physical pain could be a reason to reject a principle. Although Scanlon says that an impact on well-being is not the only reason to reject principles, it plays a significant role, and indeed, most principles are likely to be rejected due to a negative impact on a person’s well-being, physical or otherwise. It may be queried here whether it is actually the involuntariness of the pain that is grounds for reasonable rejection rather than the physical pain itself because not all pain that a person suffers is involuntary. One can imagine acts that can cause physical pain that are not rejectable — base jumping or life-saving or improving surgery, for example. On the other hand, pushing someone off a cliff or cutting him with a scalpel against his will are clearly rejectable acts. The difference between the two cases is that in the former, the person having the pain inflicted has consented to that pain or risk of pain. My view is that they cannot be separated in these cases and it is involuntary physical pain that is the grounds for reasonable rejection. Thus, the fact that a principle would allow unwanted physical harm gives a person who would be subjected to that harm a reason to reject the principle. Of course the mere fact that a principle causes involuntary physical harm or premature death is not sufficient to declare that the principle is rejectable — there might be countervailing reasons. In the case of extinction, what countervailing reasons might be offered in favour of the involuntary physical pain/ death-inducing harm? One such reason that might be offered is that humans are a harm to the natural environment and that the world might be a better place if there were no humans in it. It could be that humans might rightfully be considered an all-things-considered hindrance to the world rather than a benefit to it given the fact that we have been largely responsible for the extinction of many species, pollution and, most recently, climate change which have all negatively affected the natural environment in ways we are only just beginning to understand. Thus, the fact that human extinction would improve the natural environment (or at least prevent it from degrading further), is a countervailing reason in favour of extinction to be weighed against the reasons held by humans who would experience physical pain or premature death. However, the good of the environment as described above is by definition not a personal reason. Just like the loss of rational life and civilization, therefore, it cannot be a reason on its own when determining what is wrong and countervail the strong personal reasons to avoid pain/death that is held by the people who would suffer from it.9 Every person existing at the time of the extinction would have a reason to reject that principle on the grounds of the physical pain they are being forced to endure against their will that could not be countervailed by impersonal considerations such as the negative impact humans may have on the earth. Therefore, a principle that permitted extinction to be accomplished in a way that caused involuntary physical pain or premature death could quite clearly be rejectable by existing people with no relevant countervailing reasons. This means that human extinction that came about in this way would be wrong. There are of course also additional reasons they could reject a similar principle which I now turn to address in the next section. 2.4. Existing people could endure non-physical harms I said earlier than the fact in itself that there would not be any future people is an impersonal reason and can therefore not be a reason to reject a principle permitting extinction. However, this impersonal reason could give rise to a personal reason that is admissible. So, the final important reason people might think that human extinction would be wrong is that there could be various deleterious psychological effects that would be endured by existing people having the knowledge that there would be no future generations. There are two main sources of this trauma, both arising from the knowledge that there will be no more people. The first relates to individual people and the undesired negative effect on well-being that would be experienced by those who would have wanted to have children. Whilst this is by no means universal, it is fair to say that a good proportion of people feel a strong pull towards reproduction and having their lineage continue in some way. Samuel Scheffler describes the pull towards reproduction as a ‘desire for a personalized relationship with the future’ (Scheffler 2012, 31). Reproducing is a widely held desire and the joys of parenthood are ones that many people wish to experience. For these people knowing that they would not have descendants (or that their descendants will endure painful and/or premature deaths) could create a sense of despair and pointlessness of life. Furthermore, the inability to reproduce and have your own children because of a principle/policy that prevents you (either through bans or physical interventions) would be a significant infringement of what we consider to be a basic right to control what happens to your body. For these reasons, knowing that you will have no descendants could cause significant psychological traumas or harms even if there were no associated physical harm. The second is a more general, higher level sense of hopelessness or despair that there will be no more humans and that your projects will end with you. Even those who did not feel a strong desire to procreate themselves might feel a sense of hopelessness that any projects or goals they have for the future would not be fulfilled. Many of the projects and goals we work towards during our lifetime are also at least partly future-oriented. Why bother continuing the search for a cure for cancer if either it will not be found within humans’ lifetime, and/or there will be no future people to benefit from it once it is found? Similar projects and goals that might lose their meaning when confronted with extinction include politics, artistic pursuits and even the type of philosophical work with which this paper is concerned. Even more extreme, through the words of the character Theo Faron, P.D. James says in his novel The Children of Men that ‘without the hope of posterity for our race if not for ourselves, without the assurance that we being dead yet live, all pleasures of the mind and senses sometimes seem to me no more than pathetic and crumbling defences shored up against our ruins’ (James 2006, 9). Even if James’ claim is a bit hyperbolic and all pleasures would not actually be lost, I agree with Scheffler in finding it not implausible that the knowledge that extinction was coming and that there would be no more people would have at least a general depressive effect on people’s motivation and confidence in the value of and joy in their activities (Scheffler 2012, 43). Both sources of psychological harm are personal reasons to reject a principle that permitted human extinction. Existing people could therefore reasonably reject the principle for either of these reasons. Psychological pain and the inability to pursue your personal projects, goals, and aims, are all acceptable reasons for rejecting principles in the contractualist framework. So too are infringements of rights and entitlements that we accept as important for people’s lives. These psychological reasons, then, are also valid reasons to reject principles that permitted or required human extinction.
25,053
<h4>A] Extinction outweighs---it’s the upmost moral evil and disavowal of the risk makes it more likely.</h4><p><strong>Burns 2017 (</strong>Elizabeth Finneron-Burns is a Teaching Fellow at the University of Warwick and an Affiliated Researcher at the Institute for Futures Studies in Stockholm, What’s wrong with human extinction?, http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/pdf/10.1080/00455091.2016.1278150?needAccess=true, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 2017)</p><p>Many, though certainly not all, people might believe that it would be wrong to bring about the end of the human species, and the reasons given for this belief are various. I begin by considering four reasons that could be given against the moral permissibility of human extinction. I will argue that only those reasons that impact the people who exist at the time that the extinction or the knowledge of the upcoming extinction occurs, can explain its wrongness. I use this conclusion to then consider in which cases human extinction would be morally permissible or impermissible, arguing that there is only a small class of cases in which it would not be wrong to cause the <u>extinction</u> of the human race or allow it to happen. 2.1. It <u>would prevent the existence of very many</u> happy <u>people</u> One reason of human extinction might be considered to be wrong lies in the value of human life itself. The thought here might be that <u><mark>it is </mark>a <mark>good </mark>thing <mark>for people to exist</u> </mark>and enjoy happy lives <u><mark>and extinction would deprive </mark>more <mark>people of </mark>enjoying <mark>this</u> </mark>good. <u>The ‘good</u>’ in this case <u>could be understood in</u> at least <u>two ways.</u> According to the <u>first</u>, one might believe that you benefit a person by bringing them into existence, or at least, that <u>it is good for that person that they come to exist</u>. The second view might hold that <u>if humans were to go extinct</u>, <u>the utility foregone by the billions (or more) of people who could have lived but will now never get that opportunity</u>, renders allowing human extinction to take place an incidence of wrongdoing. An example of this view can be found in two quotes from an Effective Altruism blog post by Peter Singer, Nick Beckstead and Matt Wage: One very bad thing about human extinction would be that <u><strong><mark>billions of people would </mark>likely <mark>die painful deaths</u></strong></mark>. But in our view, this is by far not the worst thing about human extinction. <u>The worst thing about human extinction is that <mark>there would be no future generations</u></mark>. Since there could be so many generations in our future, <u><strong><mark>the value of all those generations together greatly exceeds the value of the current generation</u></strong></mark>. (Beckstead, Singer, and Wage 2013) The authors are making two claims. The first is that <u>there is value in human life and</u> also <u>something valuable about creating future people</u> which gives us a reason to do so; furthermore, it would be a very bad thing if we did not do so. The second is that, not only would it be a bad thing for there to be no future people, but it would actually be the worst thing about extinction. Since happy human lives have value, and the number of potential people who could ever exist is far greater than the number of people who exist at any one time, even if the extinction were brought about through the painful deaths of currently existing people, the former’s loss would be greater than the latter’s. Both claims are assuming that there is an intrinsic value in the existence of potential human life. The second claim makes the further assumption that the forgone value of the potential lives that could be lived is greater than the disvalue that would be accrued by people existing at the time of the extinction through suffering from painful and/or premature deaths. The best-known author of the post, Peter Singer is a prominent utilitarian, so it is not surprising that he would lament the potential lack of future human lives per se. However, it is not just utilitarians who share this view, even if implicitly. Indeed, other philosophers also seem to imply that they share the intuition that there is just something wrong with causing or failing to prevent the extinction of the human species such that we prevent more ‘people’ from having the ‘opportunity to exist’. Stephen Gardiner (2009) and Martin O’Neill (personal correspondence), both sympathetic to contract theory, for example, also find it intuitive that we should want more generations to have the opportunity to exist, assuming that they have worth-living lives, and I find it plausible to think that many other people (philosophers and non-philosophers alike) probably share this intuition. <u>When we talk about future lives being ‘prevented’, we are saying that</u> <u>a possible</u> person or a <u>set</u> <u>of</u> possible <u>people who could potentially have existed will now never actually come to exist</u>. To say that it is wrong to prevent people from existing could either mean that a possible person could reasonably reject a principle that permitted us not to create them, or that the foregone value of their lives provides a reason for rejecting any principle that permits extinction. To make the first claim we would have to argue that a possible person could reasonably reject any principle that prevented their existence on the grounds that it prevented them in particular from existing. However, this is implausible for two reasons. First, we can only wrong someone who did, does or will actually exist because wronging involves failing to take a person’s interests into account. When considering the permissibility of a principle allowing us not to create Person X, we cannot take X’s interest in being created into account because X will not exist if we follow the principle. By considering the standpoint of a person in our deliberations we consider the burdens they will have to bear as a result of the principle. In this case, there is no one who will bear any burdens since if the principle is followed (that is, if we do not create X), X will not exist to bear any burdens. So, only people who do/will actually exist can bear the brunt of a principle, and therefore occupy a standpoint that is owed justification. Second, existence is not an interest at all and a possible person is not disadvantaged by not being caused to exist. Rather than being an interest, it is a necessary requirement in order to have interests. Rivka Weinberg describes it as ‘neutral’ because causing a person to exist is to create a subject who can have interests; existence is not an interest itself.3 In order to be disadvantaged, there must be some detrimental effect on your interests. However, without existence, a person does not have any interests so they cannot be disadvantaged by being kept out of existence. But, as Weinberg points out, ‘never having interests itself could not be contrary to people’s interests since without interest bearers, there can be no ‘they’ for it to be bad for’ (Weinberg 2008, 13). So, a principle that results in some possible people never becoming actual does not impose any costs on those ‘people’ because nobody is disadvantaged by not coming into existence.4 It therefore seems that it cannot be wrong to fail to bring particular people into existence. This would mean that no one acts wrongly when they fail to create another person. Writ large, it would also not be wrong if everybody decided to exercise their prerogative not to create new people and potentially, by consequence, allow human extinction. One might respond here by saying that although it may be permissible for one person to fail to create a new person, it is not permissible if everyone chooses to do so because human lives have value and allowing human extinction would be to forgo a huge amount of value in the world. This takes us to the second way of understanding the potential wrongness of preventing people from existing — the foregone value of a life provides a reason for rejecting any principle that prevents it. One possible reply to this claim turns on the fact that many philosophers acknowledge that the only, or at least the best, way to think about the value of (individual or groups of) possible people’s lives is in impersonal terms (Parfit 1984; Reiman 2007; McMahan 2009). Jeff McMahan, for example, writes ‘at the time of one’s choice there is no one who exists or will exist independently of that choice for whose sake one could be acting in causing him or her to exist … it seems therefore that any reason to cause or not to cause an individual to exist … is best considered an impersonal rather than individual-affecting reason’ (McMahan 2009, 52). Another reply along similar lines would be to appeal to the value that is lost or at least foregone when we fail to bring into existence a next (or several next) generations of people with worth-living lives. Since ex hypothesi worth-living lives have positive value, it is better to create more such lives and worse to create fewer. Human extinction by definition is the creation of no future lives and would ‘deprive’ billions of ‘people’ of the opportunity to live worth-living lives. This might reduce the amount of value in the world at the time of the extinction (by killing already existing people), but it would also prevent a much vaster amount of value in the future (by failing to create more people). Both replies depend on the impersonal value of human life. However, recall that in contractualism impersonal values are not on their own grounds for reasonably rejecting principles. Scanlon himself says that although we have a strong reason not to destroy existing human lives, this reason ‘does not flow from the thought that it is a good thing for there to be more human life rather than less’ (104). In contractualism, something cannot be wrong unless there is an impact on a person. Thus, neither the impersonal value of creating a particular person nor the impersonal value of human life writ large could on its own provide a reason for rejecting a principle permitting human extinction. It seems therefore that the fact that extinction would deprive future people of the opportunity to live worth-living lives (either by failing to create either particular future people or future people in general) cannot provide us with a reason to consider human extinction to be wrong. Although the lost value of these ‘lives’ itself cannot be the reason explaining the wrongness of extinction, it is possible the knowledge of this loss might create a personal reason for some existing people. I will consider this possibility later on in section (d). But first I move to the second reason human extinction might be wrong per se. 2.2. <u><strong><mark>It would mean the loss of the only known form of intelligent life </mark>and all civilization and intellectual progress would be lost</u></strong> A second reason we might think it would be wrong to cause human extinction is the loss that would occur of the only (known) form of rational life and the knowledge and civilization that that form of life has created. One thought here could be that just as some might consider it wrong to destroy an individual human heritage monument like the Sphinx, it would also be wrong if the advances made by humans over the past few millennia were lost or prevented from progressing. A related argument is made by those who feel that there is something special about <u><mark>humans’ capacity for rationality</u> </mark>which <u><mark>is valuable in itself</u></mark>. Since humans are the only intelligent life that we know of, it would be a loss, in itself, to the world for that to end. I admit that I struggle to fully appreciate this thought. It seems to me that Henry Sidgwick was correct in thinking that these things are only important insofar as they are important to humans (Sidgwick 1874, I.IX.4).5 If there is no form of intelligent life in the future, who would there be to lament its loss since intelligent life is the only form of life capable of appreciating intelligence? Similarly, if there is no one with the rational capacity to appreciate historic monuments and civil progress, who would there be to be negatively affected or even notice the loss?6 However, even if there is nothing special about human rationality, just as some people try to prevent the extinction of nonhuman animal species, we might think that <u>we ought also to prevent human extinction for the sake of biodiversity</u>. The thought in this, as well as the earlier examples, must be that it would somehow be bad for the world if there were no more humans even though there would be no one for whom it is bad. This may be so but the only way to understand this reason is impersonally. Since we are concerned with wrongness rather than badness, we must ask whether something that impacts no one’s well-being, status or claims can be wrong. As we saw earlier, in the contractualist framework reasons must be personal rather than impersonal in order to provide grounds for reasonable rejection (Scanlon 1998, 218–223). Since the loss of civilization, intelligent life or biodiversity are per se impersonal reasons, there is no standpoint from which these reasons could be used to reasonably reject a principle that permitted extinction. Therefore, causing human extinction on the grounds of the loss of civilization, rational life or biodiversity would not be wrong. 2.3. <u><strong><mark>Existing people would endure physical pain and</mark>/or <mark>painful </mark>and/or <mark>premature deaths</u></strong> </mark>Thinking about the ways in which human extinction might come about brings to the fore two more reasons it might be wrong. It could, for example, occur if all humans (or at least the critical number needed to be unable to replenish the population, leading to eventual extinction) underwent a sterilization procedure. Or perhaps it could come about due to anthropogenic climate change or a massive asteroid hitting the Earth and wiping out the species in the same way it did the dinosaurs millions of years ago. <u>Each</u> of these <u>scenario</u>s <u>would involve significant physical</u> <u>and/</u>or <u>non-physical harms</u> to existing people and their interests. Physically, people might suffer premature and possibly also painful deaths, for example. It is not hard to imagine examples in which the process of <u>extinction could cause</u> <u>premature death</u>. <u>A nuclear winter</u> <u>that killed everyone or even just every woman under the age of 50 is a clear example of such a case</u>. Obviously, some types of premature death themselves cannot be reasons to reject a principle. Every person dies eventually, sometimes earlier than the standard expected lifespan due to accidents or causes like spontaneously occurring incurable cancers. A cause such as disease is not a moral agent and therefore it cannot be wrong if it unavoidably kills a person prematurely. Scanlon says that the fact that a principle would reduce a person’s well-being gives that person a reason to reject the principle: ‘components of well-being figure prominently as grounds for reasonable rejection’ (Scanlon 1998, 214). However, it is not settled yet whether premature death is a setback to well-being. Some philosophers hold that death is a harm to the person who dies, whilst others argue that it is not.7 I will argue, however, that regardless of who is correct in that debate, <u>being caused to die prematurely can be reason to reject a principle when it fails to show respect to the person as a rational agent</u>. Scanlon says that recognizing others as rational beings with interests involves seeing reason to preserve life and prevent death: ‘<u>appreciating</u> <u>the value of human life is primarily a matter of</u> <u>seeing human lives as</u> something <u>to be respected</u>, where this involves seeing reasons not to destroy them, reasons to protect them, and reasons to want them to go well’ (Scanlon 1998, 104). The ‘respect for life’ in this case is a respect for the person living, not respect for human life in the abstract. This means that we can sometimes fail to protect human life without acting wrongfully if we still respect the person living. Scanlon gives the example of a person who faces a life of unending and extreme pain such that she wishes to end it by committing suicide. Scanlon does not think that the suicidal person shows a lack of respect for her own life by seeking to end it because the person whose life it is has no reason to want it to go on. This is important to note because it emphasizes the fact that the respect for human life is person-affecting. It is not wrong to murder because of the impersonal disvalue of death in general, but because <u>taking someone’s life without their permission shows disrespect to that person</u>. This supports its inclusion as a reason in the contractualist formula, regardless of what side ends up winning the ‘is death a harm?’ debate because even if death turns out not to harm the person who died, ending their life without their consent shows disrespect to that person. A person who could reject a principle permitting another to cause his or her premature death presumably does not wish to die at that time, or in that manner. Thus, <u><strong>if they are killed without their consent, their interests have not been taken into account</u></strong>, and they have a reason to reject the principle that allowed their premature death.8 This is as true in the case of death due to extinction as it is for death due to murder. However, physical pain may also be caused to existing people without killing them, but still resulting in human extinction. Imagine, for example, surgically removing everyone’s reproductive organs in order to prevent the creation of any future people. Another example could be <u>a nuclear bomb that did not kill anyone, but did painfully render them infertile through illness or injury</u>. These would be cases in which physical pain (through surgery or bombs) was inflicted on existing people and the extinction came about as a result of the painful incident rather than through death. Furthermore, one could imagine a situation in which a bomb (for example) killed enough people to cause extinction, but some people remained alive, but in terrible pain from injuries. It seems uncontroversial that the infliction of physical pain could be a reason to reject a principle. Although Scanlon says that an impact on well-being is not the only reason to reject principles, it plays a significant role, and indeed, most principles are likely to be rejected due to a negative impact on a person’s well-being, physical or otherwise. It may be queried here whether it is actually the involuntariness of the pain that is grounds for reasonable rejection rather than the physical pain itself because not all pain that a person suffers is involuntary. One can imagine acts that can cause physical pain that are not rejectable — base jumping or life-saving or improving surgery, for example. On the other hand, pushing someone off a cliff or cutting him with a scalpel against his will are clearly rejectable acts. The difference between the two cases is that in the former, the person having the pain inflicted has consented to that pain or risk of pain. My view is that they cannot be separated in these cases and it is involuntary physical pain that is the grounds for reasonable rejection. Thus, the fact that a principle would allow unwanted physical harm gives a person who would be subjected to that harm a reason to reject the principle. Of course the mere fact that a principle causes involuntary physical harm or premature death is not sufficient to declare that the principle is rejectable — there might be countervailing reasons. In the case of extinction, what countervailing reasons might be offered in favour of the involuntary physical pain/ death-inducing harm? One such reason that might be offered is that humans are a harm to the natural environment and that the world might be a better place if there were no humans in it. It could be that humans might rightfully be considered an all-things-considered hindrance to the world rather than a benefit to it given the fact that we have been largely responsible for the extinction of many species, pollution and, most recently, climate change which have all negatively affected the natural environment in ways we are only just beginning to understand. Thus, the fact that human extinction would improve the natural environment (or at least prevent it from degrading further), is a countervailing reason in favour of extinction to be weighed against the reasons held by humans who would experience physical pain or premature death. However, the good of the environment as described above is by definition not a personal reason. Just like the loss of rational life and civilization, therefore, it cannot be a reason on its own when determining what is wrong and countervail the strong personal reasons to avoid pain/death that is held by the people who would suffer from it.9 Every person existing at the time of the extinction would have a reason to reject that principle on the grounds of the physical pain they are being forced to endure against their will that could not be countervailed by impersonal considerations such as the negative impact humans may have on the earth. Therefore, a principle that permitted extinction to be accomplished in a way that caused involuntary physical pain or premature death could quite clearly be rejectable by existing people with no relevant countervailing reasons. This means that human extinction that came about in this way would be wrong. There are of course also additional reasons they could reject a similar principle which I now turn to address in the next section. 2.4. <u><strong>Existing people could endure non-physical harms</u></strong> I said earlier than <u>the fact</u> in itself that <u>there would not be any future people</u> is an impersonal reason and can therefore not be a reason to reject a principle permitting extinction. However, this impersonal reason <u>could give rise to a personal reason</u> that is admissible. So, the final important reason people might think that human extinction would be wrong is that <u><mark>there could be various </mark>deleterious <mark>psychological effects</u> </mark>that would be endured by existing people having the knowledge that there would be no future generations. <u>There are two main sources of this trauma</u>, both arising from the knowledge that there will be no more people. <u>The first relates to individual people and the undesired negative effect on well-being</u> <u>that would be experienced by those who would have wanted to have children</u>. Whilst <u><strong>this is by no means universa</u></strong>l, <u><strong>it is fair to say that a good proportion of people feel a strong pull towards reproduction</u></strong> and having their lineage continue in some way. Samuel Scheffler describes the pull towards reproduction as a ‘desire for a personalized relationship with the future’ (Scheffler 2012, 31). Reproducing is a widely held desire and the joys of parenthood are ones that many people wish to experience. For these people knowing that they would not have descendants (or that their descendants will endure painful and/or premature deaths) could create a sense of despair and pointlessness of life. Furthermore, the inability to reproduce and have your own children because of a principle/policy that prevents you (either through bans or physical interventions) would be a significant infringement of what we consider to be a basic right to control what happens to your body. For these reasons, knowing that you will have no descendants could cause significant psychological traumas or harms even if there were no associated physical harm. <u>The second is a</u> more general, <u>higher level <mark>sense of hopelessness </mark>or despair that <mark>there will be no more humans and that your projects will end with you</u>.</mark> <u>Even those who did not feel a strong desire to procreate themselves might feel a sense of hopelessness that any projects or goals they have for the future would not be fulfilled</u>. Many of the projects and goals we work towards during our lifetime are also at least partly future-oriented. Why bother continuing the search for a cure for cancer if either it will not be found within humans’ lifetime, and/or there will be no future people to benefit from it once it is found? Similar projects and goals that might lose their meaning when confronted with extinction include politics, artistic pursuits and even the type of philosophical work with which this paper is concerned. Even more extreme, through the words of the character Theo Faron, P.D. James says in his novel The Children of Men that ‘<u>without the hope of posterity for our race</u> if not for ourselves, without the assurance that we being dead yet live, <u>all pleasures of the mind and senses sometimes seem to me no more than pathetic and crumbling defences shored up against our ruins’</u> (James 2006, 9). Even if James’ claim is a bit hyperbolic and all pleasures would not actually be lost, I agree with Scheffler in finding it not implausible that the knowledge that extinction was coming and that there would be no more people would have at least a general depressive effect on people’s motivation and confidence in the value of and joy in their activities (Scheffler 2012, 43). <u>Both sources of psychological harm are personal reasons to reject a principle that permitted human extinction</u>. Existing people could therefore reasonably reject the principle for either of these reasons. Psychological pain and the inability to pursue your personal projects, goals, and aims, are all acceptable reasons for rejecting principles in the contractualist framework. So too are infringements of rights and entitlements that we accept as important for people’s lives. These psychological reasons, then, are also valid reasons to reject principles that permitted or required human extinction. </p>
null
null
Framing
17,673
1,153
65,994
./documents/hsld20/Harker/Sh/Harker-Shah-Aff-Florida%20Blue%20Key-Round6.docx
859,635
A
Florida Blue Key
6
Lake Highland Prep PSe
Rohith Sudhakar
1AC - Green New Deal 1NC - T-Extra K-Cap 2NR - T
hsld20/Harker/Sh/Harker-Shah-Aff-Florida%20Blue%20Key-Round6.docx
null
73,080
DeSh
Harker DeSh
null
De.....
Sh.....
null
null
24,534
Harker
Harker
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
4,508,883
Pandemics risk extinction - simulations, empirics, and surging connectivity prove.
Kim 21
Kim 21, Kiseong, et al. "Network Analysis to Identify the Risk of Epidemic Spreading." Applied Sciences 11.7 (2021): 2997. (Department of Bio and Brain Engineering, KAIST; R&D Center)//Re-cut by Elmer
epidemics, such as the Black Death and the Spanish flu, have threatened human life throughout history; however, it is unclear if humans will remain safe from the sudden and fast spread of epidemic diseases the transmission characteristics of epidemics remain undiscovered we present an epidemic simulation experiment revealing the relationship between epidemic parameters and pandemic risk certain diseases can infect all nodes in the human social networks these cause a pandemic when the average degree is larger than the threshold value. These results indicated certain diseases lead to human extinction The emergence of a pandemic is a human extinction event one of the global catastrophic risks in studies regarding the future several such as the Black Death Spanish flu smallpox SARS and Ebola have affected a large population throughout history. The risk of pandemics increases with an increase in population mobility threatening humankind It is essential to analyze the epidemic spread in society to minimize damage when the epidemic spreads to all nodes it can increase the pandemic risk We designed an epidemic simulation process We adapted the Monte Carlo method to determine the status of the transition Diseases causing extinctive spread are potential candidates of high pandemic risk extinctive spreading indicates disease will infect every person in the society Many previous studies have made stochastic SIR models to analyze the dynamics or stability of epidemic diseases However, they did not conduct a quantitative assessment of pandemic risk taking into account physical contact between people we consider various connectivity and disease characteristics The results revealed that certain infectious diseases can lead to extinction human extinction is possible Based on the simulation results we confirmed certain infectious diseases can lead to extinction identifying candidate diseases is crucial in addressing epidemic prevention activities
epidemics have threatened human life it is unclear if humans will remain safe from sudden and fast spread a epidemic simulation experiment certain diseases can infect all nodes in human social networks These results indicated certain diseases lead to human extinction the Black Death smallpox SARS and Ebola affected a large population risk increases with mobility threatening humankind previous studies did not conduct quantitative assessment of risk taking into account physical contact human extinction is possible simulation results confirmed certain infectious diseases can lead to extinction
Several epidemics, such as the Black Death and the Spanish flu, have threatened human life throughout history; however, it is unclear if humans will remain safe from the sudden and fast spread of epidemic diseases. Moreover, the transmission characteristics of epidemics remain undiscovered. In this study, we present the results of an epidemic simulation experiment revealing the relationship between epidemic parameters and pandemic risk. To analyze the time-dependent risk and impact of epidemics, we considered two parameters for infectious diseases: the recovery time from infection and the transmission rate of the disease. Based on the epidemic simulation, we identified two important aspects of human safety with regard to the threat of a pandemic. First, humans should be safe if the fatality rate is below 100%. Second, even when the fatality rate is 100%, humans would be safe if the average degree of human social networks is below a threshold value. Nevertheless, certain diseases can potentially infect all nodes in the human social networks, and these diseases cause a pandemic when the average degree is larger than the threshold value. These results indicated that certain infectious diseases lead to human extinction and can be prevented by minimizing human contact. 1. Introduction The emergence of a pandemic is one of the various scenarios frequently discussed as a human extinction event, and it is listed as one of the global catastrophic risks in studies regarding the future [1,2,3]. In particular, several pandemics, such as the Black Death [4,5], Spanish flu [6], and those caused by smallpox [7], severe acute respiratory syndrome (SARS) [8], and Ebola [9], have affected a large population throughout history. The risk of pandemics increases with an increase in population mobility between cities, nations, and continents, thereby threatening humankind [10,11,12]. It is essential to analyze the epidemic spread in society to minimize the damage from epidemic disasters; however, extinctive epidemic spreading experiments have limitations in real-world situations, as they predict stochastic effects on the spread without considering the structure of human society. Network-based approaches have been proposed to overcome these limitations and perform epidemic spreading simulations by considering the network structure of numerous real-world connections [13,14,15]. These methods use various models of epidemic spreading, such as the susceptible–infectious–susceptible (SIS) [16,17,18], susceptible–infectious–recovered (SIR) [19,20,21], and Watts threshold models [22]. While these methods are mathematically convenient, they are epidemiologically unrealistic for various infections because they require exponentially distributed incubation and infectious periods [23,24,25]. Moreover, previous epidemic studies did not perform quantitative assessment of the pandemic risk depending on the network connectivity in individuals and fatality rate of various diseases [26]. In the present study, we applied an SIR epidemic model to a scale-free network with Monte Carlo simulation to identify the quantitative relationship between infectious diseases and human existence. Our fundamental hypothesis states that when the epidemic spreads to all nodes of the network and the fatality rate is 100%, it can increase the pandemic risk. To address this, we initially constructed a scale-free network to simulate a society. Moreover, for the epidemic spreading simulation, an SIR model was applied to the network to describe the immune state of an individual after infection. From the simulation study, we found that the mean degree of a scale-free network was an essential factor in determining whether epidemics threaten humans. This approach provides important insights into epidemic spreading analysis by investigating the relationship between epidemic and scale-free network parameters. Furthermore, it highlights the necessity of determining information flow during an epidemic. 2. Materials and Methods We designed an epidemic simulation process to identify the relationship between pandemic risk and network parameters. This study was performed in four steps (Figure 1): (i) generating a scale-free network model to reflect real-world conditions; (ii) applying an SIR model to the scale-free network for epidemic spreading simulations; (iii) adapting the Monte Carlo method to reflect the stochastic process in the node status of the SIR model; and (iv) iteratively performing simulation for every parameter set and analyzing the results. We have provided the source code and sample results of epidemic simulation in Supplementary Materials. Figure 1. Overview of epidemic simulation process based on the Monte Carlo method. (A) We generated scale-free networks for a fixed population (N = 1,000,000) and various node degrees (k = 2, 5, 7, and 10). (B) Epidemic spreading was simulated by applying a susceptible–infectious–recovered (SIR) model to the scale-free network. We set the epidemic parameters, β and γd. β represents the spreading rate of epidemics, and γd is the reciprocal of γ and reflects the time interval between infection and recovery. Randomly, 0.05% of nodes were initially infected. (C) We adapted the Monte Carlo method to determine the status of the transition from the infection node to immunization node. Repeated simulations were performed until a steady state was achieved. (D) For every parameter set, 10,000 simulations were performed. 2.1. Network Generation Based on a Scale-Free Model We constructed a network model for the epidemic spreading simulation (Figure 1). The nodes and edges of the network represent people in the society and their physical contacts, respectively. We used a scale-free network model, which follows the preferential attachment property observed in numerous real-world networks, such as social networks, physical systems, and economic networks [27,28,29]. In the scale-free network, when a node is added to the network, its likelihood of connecting to existing nodes increases with an increase in the node’s degree. Hub nodes, which lead to fast and vast spreading of epidemics, exist. Two characteristic parameters, including N and k, affect the form of scale-free networks. The parameter N denotes all nodes in the network. In the real world, N indicates the whole population size. The parameter k is the average degree of the network, which determines the degree of the newly attached node for each step during network generation. Following the characteristics of the network model, we generated scale-free networks representing human contacts for epidemic spread. The scale-free network was generated by the Barabasi–Albert graph distribution, in which the network is constructed from a cycle graph with three vertices, followed by the addition of k edges at each construction step [30]. The k edges are randomly attached to the vertex based on the degree distribution of the vertex. After network generation, we investigated the degree distribution properties of the network (Figure 2). The results indicate that the degree distributions have similar tendency for networks with varying number of nodes and edges. This study constructed scale-free networks with the largest number of nodes considering computational complexity (N = 1,000,000). Figure 2. Degree distribution of the scale-free network. We analyzed the degree distribution of the network based on the number of nodes (N) and mean degree (k). 2.2. Epidemic Spreading Based on the SIR Model For the epidemic spreading simulations, we applied an SIR model to the generated scale-free network. The classical SIR model can be expressed by the following nonlinear differential equations [21]: where S, I, and R represent susceptible, infected, and recovered compartments, respectively, in the whole population. S represents people who have not been infected yet but can be infected in future. I represents infected people who can spread the epidemic to susceptible people through physical contact. R denotes people who have recovered or died from the epidemic and who no longer participate in the epidemic spreading process. The sum of the S, I, and R values represents the whole population size N. Epidemics have two parameters in the SIR model, transmission rate (β) and recovery rate (γ), which arise from the basic reproduction number R0 (Figure 1B). The basic reproduction number is the number of infections caused by one infective node [31,32,33]. If the R0 is more than 1, the infection can spread in a population, whereas if R0 is less than 1, the infection cannot spread. We express the basic reproduction number as R0 = β/γ, where β represents the spreading rate of epidemics between infective nodes and adjacent susceptible nodes and γ represents the probability of recovery from infection [34]. We mainly used γd, which is the reciprocal of γ and reflects the time interval between infection and recovery. 2.3. Investigation of Epidemic Status Based on the Monte Carlo Method The epidemic simulation was performed for a time series event by constructing epidemic status matrix (z) to represent the status of the nth node at time step t. For each node, the value of epidemic status matrix at time step t can be 0, 1, or 2, indicating that a node is susceptible, infective, or recovered, respectively. We initially (t = 0) set every value of epidemic status matrix to 0 because all nodes are susceptible before the epidemic spreads. At the initial infection stage, randomly selected 0.05% of nodes were infected. At every time period, we performed immunization and observed the infection stages (Figure 3). At the immunization stage, we identified infective nodes and determined whether these nodes would be recovered in the next time step. To calculate the transition probability of infected and recovered phenomena, the Monte Carlo method was applied [35,36]. When infection and recovery parameters are provided, it is possible to investigate whether a node transitions from an epidemic state to another state. To accomplish this, we compared the method revealing the change in each population in every compartment over time (Figure 4). The final steady state of the epidemic spreading simulation model indicates the total number of casualties of the epidemic who either are dead or have recovered from the disease. Infective nodes at time t (zn [t] = 1) are transformed to recovered nodes at time t + 1 (zn [t + 1] = 2) when 1/γd is larger than a random real number between 0 and 1. We determined whether the neighbor nodes of the infection node would be infected by identifying susceptible nodes adjacent to the infective nodes at time t (zn [t] = 0, with the adjacent infective node) (Figure 5). When β is larger than a random real number between 0 and 1, a susceptible node becomes an infective node at time t + 1 (zn [t + 1] = 1); this scenario represents epidemic spread. For each time step, we recorded the number of susceptible, infective, and recovered nodes during epidemic spread. 2.4. Simulation Parameters We carried out simulation trials for various mean degrees of networks (k = 2, 5, 7, and 10). Each network considered the following epidemic parameters: β ranges from 0.05 to 0.95 and γd ranges from 1 to 10. The Monte Carlo model was repeatedly simulated to observe saturation of the recovery process. Considering that the simulation pipeline contains random processes such as initial infection and Monte Carlo trials, we performed the simulation iteratively until the status of nodes remained unchanged. After simulation, time series data from every simulation were interpolated in the time domain. The fatality rate determines the ratio of deceased and recovered individuals in the final population [37,38,39]. If the fatality rate is below 100%, the recovered population contains both dead and recovered individuals. Such a situation does not always cause a pandemic. In this simulation, we assumed a 100% fatality rate. To accomplish this, we enumerated the recovered nodes as dead for considering the pandemic risk. 3. Results Through our method, we obtained epidemic spreading data with various network and epidemic parameter sets. In the present study, we focused on the case where the epidemic infects all nodes and defined this phenomenon as “extinctive spread”. Diseases causing extinctive spread are potential candidates of high pandemic risk. In the real world, extinctive spreading indicates that the disease will infect every person in the society. From the simulation data, we calculated the extinctive spread score by dividing the total number of simulation trials by the number of extinctive spread cases. Thereafter, we identified that the number of extinctive spread cases is mainly influenced by spreading speed, which is determined by β, γd, and k (Figure 6). The extinctive spread region (brown area in Figure 6) is expanded as the value of mean degree of network (k) is increased, thereby indicating that the area of extinctive spread becomes noticeably wider in a dense network than in a sparse network. Thus, the more contact between people, the higher the risk of epidemics. Moreover, high γd and high β cause extinctive spread across a large region, indicating that the high spreading rate and short time interval between infection and recovery are risk factors of epidemic diseases. In contrast, the infective nodes recover before they transmit the disease to their neighbors in low β and low γd scenarios, thus disconnecting the network and preventing extinctive spread. This occurs because the infective nodes need more time to transmit the disease in low β and high γd scenarios. Therefore, the disease begins to subside due to a lack of new infective nodes. Furthermore, we investigated the range of β and γd for existing epidemics of the common cold [40,41] and fatal diseases, namely, cholera [42,43], Marburg [44,45], Ebola (Congo and Uganda) [46,47,48,49], SARS [50], and MERS [51] (Table 1). We selected diseases with relatively well-known epidemic parameters, such as average duration of infection and basic number of reproductions from previous studies. Transmission rates were calculated using the mean duration of infectious periods and basic reproduction numbers of the epidemics. Different studies reveal multiple values of infectious period and transmission rate for some of these diseases; we considered these values separately [40,41,42,43,46,47,48,49]. For example, the infectious period of a common cold is from 3 to 7 days and that of Ebola is 6.5 days. Next, we placed the possible regions of these epidemics as a disease band for various k values (colored lines in Figure 6). When k > 5, fatal diseases have an opportunity to cause a pandemic. Even when k = 5, diseases such as cholera and Ebola (Congo) can be threatening in regions of low γd and high, thus demonstrating that the knowledge of network parameters of the society and the characteristics of epidemic diseases can aid in quantifying the risk of epidemics. 4. Discussion Many previous studies have made stochastic SIR models to analyze the dynamics or stability of epidemic diseases. They investigated the distribution of susceptible, infected, and removed populations for specific epidemic disease spreading, such as cholera, SARS, Marburg, and MERS, based on mathematical modelling [52,53,54,55]. However, they did not conduct a quantitative assessment of pandemic risk taking into account physical contact between people. To solve this limitation, we performed epidemic spreading simulations by applying an SIR model to scale-free networks with Monte Carlo simulation. In the simulation, we consider various connectivity and disease characteristics on scale-free networks. For each network and epidemic parameter set, the probability of extinctive spread was calculated. The results revealed that certain infectious diseases can lead to extinction. Moreover, even if the disease band extends over the extinctive spread regions, it does not indicate that human extinction results from the disease, as the fatality rate is below 100%; however, in the case of 100% fatality, the disease can cause a human extinction event. The risk of infectious disease is influenced by the network structure. A dense network has a higher risk of spreading infectious disease than a sparse network, as we observed in the extinctive spreading maps. According to our results, when the average degree of human social networks is below the risk threshold, i.e., less than 4 in this study, human society is safe from an extinctive outbreak based on our knowledge regarding the epidemic parameters of the infectious disease. Nevertheless, in other cases, human extinction is possible. For example, if the population is 1,000,000 and there are 4 or more instances of physical contact between people, human extinction events may occur, depending on the fatality rate of the epidemics. Hence, physical contact between people is closely related to an extinction event of infectious diseases. Eventually, from a public health perspective, lowering the average contact level of society is an appropriate way to increase the robustness of strategies against the occurrence of extinction. In the real world, reducing network density can be accomplished by epidemic prevention activity, such as isolation and quarantine treatment. This action prevents epidemic risk to the society, thereby avoiding human extinction. Additional considerations may improve our analysis. First, large population size and various proportions of initial infective nodes were not considered in the experiments. We have confirmed that the result was consistent when the proportion of initial infective nodes was 0.05% of the total population; however, this can vary depending on the distinct proportion of initial infective nodes in a different population. To achieve robust results, we need to perform additional experiments for various parameters; however, we could not address this issue due to computational complexity. Second, we did not consider numerous known epidemic diseases. We calculated the transmission rates of epidemic diseases using the known infectious periods and reproduction numbers of the epidemics from evidence in the literature. In the present study, we only considered five epidemic diseases, since the information on infectious periods and reproduction numbers of diseases was mostly unavailable for other epidemic diseases. Third, this study only considers the SIR model on scale-free networks in epidemic simulation. Since the dynamics of epidemic diseases can be varied in different models or networks, it is important to experiment in various simulation environments to confirm the robustness of the results. Nevertheless, these limitations can be considered in future experiments or using improved computational methods. With these further improvements, our approach can be used as a computational tool to analyze the risk of epidemic diseases. 5. Conclusions In this study, we analyzed the risk of epidemic diseases by creating an epidemic simulation on a scale-free network. Based on the simulation results for various epidemic parameters, we confirmed that certain infectious diseases can lead to extinction and can be prevented by minimizing human contact. We believe that identifying potential candidate diseases that may lead to human extinction is crucial in addressing epidemic prevention activities such as quarantine.
19,496
<h4>Pandemics risk extinction - <u>simulations</u>, <u>empirics</u>, and <u>surging connectivity</u> prove.</h4><p><strong>Kim 21</strong>, Kiseong, et al. "Network Analysis to Identify the Risk of Epidemic Spreading." Applied Sciences 11.7 (2021): 2997. (Department of Bio and Brain Engineering, KAIST; R&D Center)//Re-cut by Elmer</p><p>Several <u><strong><mark>epidemics</strong></mark>, such as the Black Death and the Spanish flu, <strong><mark>have</strong> <strong>threatened</strong> <strong>human life</mark> throughout history</strong>; however, <strong><mark>it is unclear if humans</u></strong> <u><strong>will remain safe</strong> <strong>from</strong> </mark>the <strong><mark>sudden and fast spread </mark>of epidemic diseases</u></strong>. Moreover, <u>the transmission <strong>characteristics</strong> of epidemics remain <strong>undiscovered</u></strong>. In this study, <u>we present</u> the results of <u><strong><mark>a</strong></mark>n <strong><mark>epidemic</strong> <strong>simulation experiment</u></strong></mark> <u>revealing the relationship between epidemic parameters and pandemic risk</u>. To analyze the time-dependent risk and impact of epidemics, we considered two parameters for infectious diseases: the recovery time from infection and the transmission rate of the disease. Based on the epidemic simulation, we identified two important aspects of human safety with regard to the threat of a pandemic. First, humans should be safe if the fatality rate is below 100%. Second, even when the fatality rate is 100%, humans would be safe if the average degree of human social networks is below a threshold value. Nevertheless, <u><strong><mark>certain</u></strong> <u>diseases</mark> <strong><mark>can</u></strong></mark> potentially <u><strong><mark>infect all nodes in</mark> the <mark>human</mark> <mark>social networks</u></strong></mark>, and <u>these</u> diseases <u>cause a pandemic when the average degree is <strong>larger than the threshold</strong> value. <mark>These</u></mark> <u><strong><mark>results indicated</u></strong> </mark>that <u><strong><mark>certain</u></strong> </mark>infectious <u><strong><mark>diseases</strong> <strong>lead to human extinction</u></strong></mark> and can be prevented by minimizing human contact. 1. Introduction <u>The emergence of a <strong>pandemic</u></strong> <u>is</u> one of the various scenarios frequently discussed as <u>a</u> <u><strong>human extinction event</u></strong>, and it is listed as <u>one of the global</u> <u><strong>catastrophic</u></strong> <u>risks in studies regarding the future</u> [1,2,3]. In particular, <u>several</u> pandemics, <u>such as <mark>the <strong>Black Death</u></strong></mark> [4,5], <u>Spanish flu</u> [6], and those caused by <u><strong><mark>smallpox</u></strong></mark> [7], severe acute respiratory syndrome (<u><strong><mark>SARS</u></strong></mark>) [8], <u><mark>and <strong>Ebola</u></strong></mark> [9], <u>have <mark>affected a <strong>large population</strong></mark> throughout history. The <mark>risk</mark> of pandemics <strong><mark>increases</u></strong> <u>with</mark> an increase in population <strong><mark>mobility</u></strong></mark> between cities, nations, and continents, thereby <u><mark>threatening <strong>humankind</u></strong></mark> [10,11,12]. <u>It is essential to analyze the epidemic spread in <strong>society</u></strong> <u>to</u> <u><strong>minimize</u></strong> the <u><strong>damage</u></strong> from epidemic disasters; however, extinctive epidemic spreading experiments have limitations in real-world situations, as they predict stochastic effects on the spread without considering the structure of human society. Network-based approaches have been proposed to overcome these limitations and perform epidemic spreading simulations by considering the network structure of numerous real-world connections [13,14,15]. These methods use various models of epidemic spreading, such as the susceptible–infectious–susceptible (SIS) [16,17,18], susceptible–infectious–recovered (SIR) [19,20,21], and Watts threshold models [22]. While these methods are mathematically convenient, they are epidemiologically unrealistic for various infections because they require exponentially distributed incubation and infectious periods [23,24,25]. Moreover, previous epidemic studies did not perform quantitative assessment of the pandemic risk depending on the network connectivity in individuals and fatality rate of various diseases [26]. In the present study, we applied an SIR epidemic model to a scale-free network with Monte Carlo simulation to identify the quantitative relationship between infectious diseases and human existence. Our fundamental hypothesis states that <u>when the epidemic spreads to all <strong>nodes</u></strong> of the network and the fatality rate is 100%, <u>it can increase the <strong>pandemic</strong> risk</u>. To address this, we initially constructed a scale-free network to simulate a society. Moreover, for the epidemic spreading simulation, an SIR model was applied to the network to describe the immune state of an individual after infection. From the simulation study, we found that the mean degree of a scale-free network was an essential factor in determining whether epidemics threaten humans. This approach provides important insights into epidemic spreading analysis by investigating the relationship between epidemic and scale-free network parameters. Furthermore, it highlights the necessity of determining information flow during an epidemic. 2. Materials and Methods <u>We designed an epidemic <strong>simulation process</u></strong> to identify the relationship between pandemic risk and network parameters. This study was performed in four steps (Figure 1): (i) generating a scale-free network model to reflect real-world conditions; (ii) applying an SIR model to the scale-free network for epidemic spreading simulations; (iii) adapting the Monte Carlo method to reflect the stochastic process in the node status of the SIR model; and (iv) iteratively performing simulation for every parameter set and analyzing the results. We have provided the source code and sample results of epidemic simulation in Supplementary Materials. Figure 1. Overview of epidemic simulation process based on the Monte Carlo method. (A) We generated scale-free networks for a fixed population (N = 1,000,000) and various node degrees (k = 2, 5, 7, and 10). (B) Epidemic spreading was simulated by applying a susceptible–infectious–recovered (SIR) model to the scale-free network. We set the epidemic parameters, β and γd. β represents the spreading rate of epidemics, and γd is the reciprocal of γ and reflects the time interval between infection and recovery. Randomly, 0.05% of nodes were initially infected. (C) <u>We adapted the <strong>Monte Carlo method</u></strong> <u>to determine the status of the transition</u> from the infection node to immunization node. Repeated simulations were performed until a steady state was achieved. (D) For every parameter set, 10,000 simulations were performed. 2.1. Network Generation Based on a Scale-Free Model We constructed a network model for the epidemic spreading simulation (Figure 1). The nodes and edges of the network represent people in the society and their physical contacts, respectively. We used a scale-free network model, which follows the preferential attachment property observed in numerous real-world networks, such as social networks, physical systems, and economic networks [27,28,29]. In the scale-free network, when a node is added to the network, its likelihood of connecting to existing nodes increases with an increase in the node’s degree. Hub nodes, which lead to fast and vast spreading of epidemics, exist. Two characteristic parameters, including N and k, affect the form of scale-free networks. The parameter N denotes all nodes in the network. In the real world, N indicates the whole population size. The parameter k is the average degree of the network, which determines the degree of the newly attached node for each step during network generation. Following the characteristics of the network model, we generated scale-free networks representing human contacts for epidemic spread. The scale-free network was generated by the Barabasi–Albert graph distribution, in which the network is constructed from a cycle graph with three vertices, followed by the addition of k edges at each construction step [30]. The k edges are randomly attached to the vertex based on the degree distribution of the vertex. After network generation, we investigated the degree distribution properties of the network (Figure 2). The results indicate that the degree distributions have similar tendency for networks with varying number of nodes and edges. This study constructed scale-free networks with the largest number of nodes considering computational complexity (N = 1,000,000). Figure 2. Degree distribution of the scale-free network. We analyzed the degree distribution of the network based on the number of nodes (N) and mean degree (k). 2.2. Epidemic Spreading Based on the SIR Model For the epidemic spreading simulations, we applied an SIR model to the generated scale-free network. The classical SIR model can be expressed by the following nonlinear differential equations [21]: where S, I, and R represent susceptible, infected, and recovered compartments, respectively, in the whole population. S represents people who have not been infected yet but can be infected in future. I represents infected people who can spread the epidemic to susceptible people through physical contact. R denotes people who have recovered or died from the epidemic and who no longer participate in the epidemic spreading process. The sum of the S, I, and R values represents the whole population size N. Epidemics have two parameters in the SIR model, transmission rate (β) and recovery rate (γ), which arise from the basic reproduction number R0 (Figure 1B). The basic reproduction number is the number of infections caused by one infective node [31,32,33]. If the R0 is more than 1, the infection can spread in a population, whereas if R0 is less than 1, the infection cannot spread. We express the basic reproduction number as R0 = β/γ, where β represents the spreading rate of epidemics between infective nodes and adjacent susceptible nodes and γ represents the probability of recovery from infection [34]. We mainly used γd, which is the reciprocal of γ and reflects the time interval between infection and recovery. 2.3. Investigation of Epidemic Status Based on the Monte Carlo Method The epidemic simulation was performed for a time series event by constructing epidemic status matrix (z) to represent the status of the nth node at time step t. For each node, the value of epidemic status matrix at time step t can be 0, 1, or 2, indicating that a node is susceptible, infective, or recovered, respectively. We initially (t = 0) set every value of epidemic status matrix to 0 because all nodes are susceptible before the epidemic spreads. At the initial infection stage, randomly selected 0.05% of nodes were infected. At every time period, we performed immunization and observed the infection stages (Figure 3). At the immunization stage, we identified infective nodes and determined whether these nodes would be recovered in the next time step. To calculate the transition probability of infected and recovered phenomena, the Monte Carlo method was applied [35,36]. When infection and recovery parameters are provided, it is possible to investigate whether a node transitions from an epidemic state to another state. To accomplish this, we compared the method revealing the change in each population in every compartment over time (Figure 4). The final steady state of the epidemic spreading simulation model indicates the total number of casualties of the epidemic who either are dead or have recovered from the disease. Infective nodes at time t (zn [t] = 1) are transformed to recovered nodes at time t + 1 (zn [t + 1] = 2) when 1/γd is larger than a random real number between 0 and 1. We determined whether the neighbor nodes of the infection node would be infected by identifying susceptible nodes adjacent to the infective nodes at time t (zn [t] = 0, with the adjacent infective node) (Figure 5). When β is larger than a random real number between 0 and 1, a susceptible node becomes an infective node at time t + 1 (zn [t + 1] = 1); this scenario represents epidemic spread. For each time step, we recorded the number of susceptible, infective, and recovered nodes during epidemic spread. 2.4. Simulation Parameters We carried out simulation trials for various mean degrees of networks (k = 2, 5, 7, and 10). Each network considered the following epidemic parameters: β ranges from 0.05 to 0.95 and γd ranges from 1 to 10. The Monte Carlo model was repeatedly simulated to observe saturation of the recovery process. Considering that the simulation pipeline contains random processes such as initial infection and Monte Carlo trials, we performed the simulation iteratively until the status of nodes remained unchanged. After simulation, time series data from every simulation were interpolated in the time domain. The fatality rate determines the ratio of deceased and recovered individuals in the final population [37,38,39]. If the fatality rate is below 100%, the recovered population contains both dead and recovered individuals. Such a situation does not always cause a pandemic. In this simulation, we assumed a 100% fatality rate. To accomplish this, we enumerated the recovered nodes as dead for considering the pandemic risk. 3. Results Through our method, we obtained epidemic spreading data with various network and epidemic parameter sets. In the present study, we focused on the case where the epidemic infects all nodes and defined this phenomenon as “extinctive spread”. <u>Diseases causing extinctive spread are potential candidates of <strong>high pandemic risk</u></strong>. In the real world, <u>extinctive spreading indicates</u> that the <u>disease will <strong>infect every person in the society</u></strong>. From the simulation data, we calculated the extinctive spread score by dividing the total number of simulation trials by the number of extinctive spread cases. Thereafter, we identified that the number of extinctive spread cases is mainly influenced by spreading speed, which is determined by β, γd, and k (Figure 6). The extinctive spread region (brown area in Figure 6) is expanded as the value of mean degree of network (k) is increased, thereby indicating that the area of extinctive spread becomes noticeably wider in a dense network than in a sparse network. Thus, the more contact between people, the higher the risk of epidemics. Moreover, high γd and high β cause extinctive spread across a large region, indicating that the high spreading rate and short time interval between infection and recovery are risk factors of epidemic diseases. In contrast, the infective nodes recover before they transmit the disease to their neighbors in low β and low γd scenarios, thus disconnecting the network and preventing extinctive spread. This occurs because the infective nodes need more time to transmit the disease in low β and high γd scenarios. Therefore, the disease begins to subside due to a lack of new infective nodes. Furthermore, we investigated the range of β and γd for existing epidemics of the common cold [40,41] and fatal diseases, namely, cholera [42,43], Marburg [44,45], Ebola (Congo and Uganda) [46,47,48,49], SARS [50], and MERS [51] (Table 1). We selected diseases with relatively well-known epidemic parameters, such as average duration of infection and basic number of reproductions from previous studies. Transmission rates were calculated using the mean duration of infectious periods and basic reproduction numbers of the epidemics. Different studies reveal multiple values of infectious period and transmission rate for some of these diseases; we considered these values separately [40,41,42,43,46,47,48,49]. For example, the infectious period of a common cold is from 3 to 7 days and that of Ebola is 6.5 days. Next, we placed the possible regions of these epidemics as a disease band for various k values (colored lines in Figure 6). When k > 5, fatal diseases have an opportunity to cause a pandemic. Even when k = 5, diseases such as cholera and Ebola (Congo) can be threatening in regions of low γd and high, thus demonstrating that the knowledge of network parameters of the society and the characteristics of epidemic diseases can aid in quantifying the risk of epidemics. 4. Discussion <u>Many <strong><mark>previous</strong> studies</mark> have made <strong>stochastic</u></strong> <u>SIR models to analyze the dynamics or stability of epidemic diseases</u>. They investigated the distribution of susceptible, infected, and removed populations for specific epidemic disease spreading, such as cholera, SARS, Marburg, and MERS, based on mathematical modelling [52,53,54,55]. <u>However, they <mark>did not conduct</mark> a</u> <u><strong><mark>quantitative</u></strong> <u>assessment</mark> <strong><mark>of</strong> </mark>pandemic <strong><mark>risk taking into account physical contact </mark>between people</u></strong>. To solve this limitation, we performed epidemic spreading simulations by applying an SIR model to scale-free networks with Monte Carlo simulation. In the simulation, <u>we consider <strong>various</strong> connectivity and <strong>disease</strong> characteristics</u> on scale-free networks. For each network and epidemic parameter set, the probability of extinctive spread was calculated. <u>The results <strong>reveal</strong>ed that <strong>certain infectious diseases can lead to extinction</u></strong>. Moreover, even if the disease band extends over the extinctive spread regions, it does not indicate that human extinction results from the disease, as the fatality rate is below 100%; however, in the case of 100% fatality, the disease can cause a human extinction event. The risk of infectious disease is influenced by the network structure. A dense network has a higher risk of spreading infectious disease than a sparse network, as we observed in the extinctive spreading maps. According to our results, when the average degree of human social networks is below the risk threshold, i.e., less than 4 in this study, human society is safe from an extinctive outbreak based on our knowledge regarding the epidemic parameters of the infectious disease. Nevertheless, in other cases, <u><strong><mark>human extinction is possible</u></strong></mark>. For example, if the population is 1,000,000 and there are 4 or more instances of physical contact between people, human extinction events may occur, depending on the fatality rate of the epidemics. Hence, physical contact between people is closely related to an extinction event of infectious diseases. Eventually, from a public health perspective, lowering the average contact level of society is an appropriate way to increase the robustness of strategies against the occurrence of extinction. In the real world, reducing network density can be accomplished by epidemic prevention activity, such as isolation and quarantine treatment. This action prevents epidemic risk to the society, thereby avoiding human extinction. Additional considerations may improve our analysis. First, large population size and various proportions of initial infective nodes were not considered in the experiments. We have confirmed that the result was consistent when the proportion of initial infective nodes was 0.05% of the total population; however, this can vary depending on the distinct proportion of initial infective nodes in a different population. To achieve robust results, we need to perform additional experiments for various parameters; however, we could not address this issue due to computational complexity. Second, we did not consider numerous known epidemic diseases. We calculated the transmission rates of epidemic diseases using the known infectious periods and reproduction numbers of the epidemics from evidence in the literature. In the present study, we only considered five epidemic diseases, since the information on infectious periods and reproduction numbers of diseases was mostly unavailable for other epidemic diseases. Third, this study only considers the SIR model on scale-free networks in epidemic simulation. Since the dynamics of epidemic diseases can be varied in different models or networks, it is important to experiment in various simulation environments to confirm the robustness of the results. Nevertheless, these limitations can be considered in future experiments or using improved computational methods. With these further improvements, our approach can be used as a computational tool to analyze the risk of epidemic diseases. 5. Conclusions In this study, we analyzed the risk of epidemic diseases by creating an epidemic simulation on a scale-free network. <u>Based on the <strong><mark>simulation results</u></strong></mark> for various epidemic parameters, <u>we</u> <u><strong><mark>confirmed</u></strong></mark> that <u><strong><mark>certain</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>infectious diseases <strong>can lead to extinction</u></strong></mark> and can be prevented by minimizing human contact. We believe that <u>identifying</u> potential <u><strong>candidate</u></strong> <u>diseases</u> that may lead to human extinction <u>is</u> <u><strong>crucial</u></strong> <u>in addressing epidemic prevention activities</u> such as quarantine.</p>
null
1
null
19,827
1,049
147,940
./documents/hsld22/CanyonCrestAcademy/PaJa/CanyonCrestAcademy-PaJa-Neg-Arizona-State-HDSHC-Invitational-Round-6.docx
960,797
N
Arizona State HDSHC Invitational
6
Mira Loma SG
Levinsky
ac - rawls, whole rez nc - disease, terr, climate, disclosure, case ar - disclosure, rvi nr - rvi, pic ar - rvi
hsld22/CanyonCrestAcademy/PaJa/CanyonCrestAcademy-PaJa-Neg-Arizona-State-HDSHC-Invitational-Round-6.docx
2023-01-07 22:02:23
80,571
PaJa
Canyon Crest Academy PaJa
null
Pa.....
Ja.....
null
null
27,055
CanyonCrestAcademy
Canyon Crest Academy
CA
18,972
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
3,419,157
“USFG should” means the debate is about a policy established by governmental means
ERICSON 3
Jon M. ERICSON, Dean Emeritus of the College of Liberal Arts – California Polytechnic U., et al., 3 [The Debater’s Guide, Third Edition, p. 4]
each topic contains An agent doing the acting The U S should adopt The verb should—the first part of a verb phrase that urges action should means to put a policy into action though governmental means The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur. What you agree to do, then, when you accept the affirmative side in such a debate is to offer sufficient and compelling reasons for an audience to perform the future action that you propose
each topic contains An agent doing the acting The U S should The verb should urges action should means to put a policy into action though governmental means The debate is about whether something ought to occur
The Proposition of Policy: Urging Future Action In policy propositions, each topic contains certain key elements, although they have slightly different functions from comparable elements of value-oriented propositions. 1. An agent doing the acting ---“The United States” in “The United States should adopt a policy of free trade.” Like the object of evaluation in a proposition of value, the agent is the subject of the sentence. 2. The verb should—the first part of a verb phrase that urges action. 3. An action verb to follow should in the should-verb combination. For example, should adopt here means to put a program or policy into action though governmental means. 4. A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired. The phrase free trade, for example, gives direction and limits to the topic, which would, for example, eliminate consideration of increasing tariffs, discussing diplomatic recognition, or discussing interstate commerce. Propositions of policy deal with future action. Nothing has yet occurred. The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur. What you agree to do, then, when you accept the affirmative side in such a debate is to offer sufficient and compelling reasons for an audience to perform the future action that you propose.
1,287
<h4>“USFG should” means the debate is about a policy established by governmental means</h4><p>Jon M. <strong>ERICSON</strong>, Dean Emeritus of the College of Liberal Arts – California Polytechnic U., et al., <strong>3</strong> [The Debater’s Guide, Third Edition, p. 4]</p><p>The Proposition of Policy: Urging Future Action</p><p>In policy propositions, <u><mark>each topic contains</u></mark> certain key elements, although they have slightly different functions from comparable elements of value-oriented propositions. 1. <u><mark>An agent doing the acting</u></mark> ---“The United States” in “<u><mark>The U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates <u><mark>should</mark> adopt</u> a policy of free trade.” Like the object of evaluation in a proposition of value, the agent is the subject of the sentence. 2. <u><mark>The verb should</mark>—the first part of a verb phrase that <mark>urges action</u></mark>. 3. An action verb to follow should in the should-verb combination. For example, <u><mark>should</u></mark> adopt here <u><mark>means to put a</u></mark> program or <u><mark>policy into action though governmental means</u></mark>. 4. A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired. The phrase free trade, for example, gives direction and limits to the topic, which would, for example, eliminate consideration of increasing tariffs, discussing diplomatic recognition, or discussing interstate commerce. Propositions of policy deal with future action. Nothing has yet occurred. <u><mark>The</mark> entire <mark>debate is about whether something ought to occur</mark>. What you agree to do, then, when you accept the affirmative side in such a debate is to offer sufficient and compelling reasons for an audience to perform the future action that you propose</u>. </p>
null
OFF
1NC – T
1,149
3,809
113,961
./documents/ndtceda17/Emory/YaSh/Emory-Yamout-Shaikh-Neg-texas-Round2.docx
595,136
N
texas
2
texas ac
hagney
1ac - juba 2nr - topicality
ndtceda17/Emory/YaSh/Emory-Yamout-Shaikh-Neg-texas-Round2.docx
null
50,757
YaSh
Emory YaSh
null
Ga.....
Ya.....
Za.....
Sh.....
19,101
Emory
Emory
null
null
1,007
ndtceda17
NDT/CEDA 2017-18
2,017
cx
college
2
3,005,654
“USfg should” means that the agent and verb indicate a debate about hypothetical government action
Ericson 3
Jon M Ericson 3, Dean Emeritus of the College of Liberal Arts – California Polytechnic U., et al., The Debater’s Guide, Third Edition, p. 4
each topic contains certain key elements An agent doing the acting ---“The United States” in “The United States should adopt a policy the agent is the subject of the sentence The verb should urges action should adopt here means to put a program or policy into action through governmental means A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur
each topic contains An agent doing the acting The U S in “The U S should adopt a policy the agent is the subject The verb should urges action should adopt means to put a policy into action through governmental means A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur
The Proposition of Policy: Urging Future Action In policy propositions, each topic contains certain key elements, although they have slightly different functions from comparable elements of value-oriented propositions. 1. An agent doing the acting ---“The United States” in “The United States should adopt a policy of free trade.” Like the object of evaluation in a proposition of value, the agent is the subject of the sentence. 2. The verb should—the first part of a verb phrase that urges action. 3. An action verb to follow should in the should-verb combination. For example, should adopt here means to put a program or policy into action through governmental means. 4. A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired. The phrase free trade, for example, gives direction and limits to the topic, which would, for example, eliminate consideration of increasing tariffs, discussing diplomatic recognition, or discussing interstate commerce. Propositions of policy deal with future action. Nothing has yet occurred. The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur. What you agree to do, then, when you accept the affirmative side in such a debate is to offer sufficient and compelling reasons for an audience to perform the future action that you propose.
1,288
<h4>“USfg should” means that the <u>agent and verb</u> indicate a debate about <u>hypothetical government action</h4><p></u>Jon M <strong>Ericson 3</strong>, Dean Emeritus of the College of Liberal Arts – California Polytechnic U., et al., The Debater’s Guide, Third Edition, p. 4</p><p>The Proposition of Policy: Urging Future Action In policy propositions, <u><strong><mark>each topic contains</mark> certain key elements</u></strong>, although they have slightly different functions from comparable elements of value-oriented propositions. 1. <u><strong><mark>An agent</mark> <mark>doing the acting</mark> ---“<mark>The U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates” <mark>in “The U</mark>nited <mark>S</mark>tates <mark>should</mark> <mark>adopt a policy</u></strong></mark> of free trade.” Like the object of evaluation in a proposition of value, <u><strong><mark>the agent is the subject </mark>of the sentence</u></strong>. 2. <u><strong><mark>The verb should</u></strong></mark>—the first part of a verb phrase that <u><strong><mark>urges action</u></strong></mark>. 3. An action verb to follow should in the should-verb combination. For example, <u><strong><mark>should adopt</mark> here <mark>means to put a</mark> program or <mark>policy into action through governmental means</u></strong></mark>. 4. <u><strong><mark>A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired</u></strong></mark>. The phrase free trade, for example, gives direction and limits to the topic, which would, for example, eliminate consideration of increasing tariffs, discussing diplomatic recognition, or discussing interstate commerce. Propositions of policy deal with future action. Nothing has yet occurred. <u><strong><mark>The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur</u></strong></mark>. What you agree to do, then, when you accept the affirmative side in such a debate is to offer sufficient and compelling reasons for an audience to perform the future action that you propose. </p>
1nc
1nc - Off
null
1,149
3,809
98,752
./documents/ndtceda18/ArizonaState/GuFe/Arizona%20State-Guthrie-Ferdowsian-Neg-UNLV-Round2.docx
601,828
N
UNLV
2
Weber MM
Jeanette Salcedo
1ac - Chicana narrative resistance - 'herstory' 2nr - fw
ndtceda18/ArizonaState/GuFe/Arizona%20State-Guthrie-Ferdowsian-Neg-UNLV-Round2.docx
null
51,188
GuFe
Arizona State GuFe
null
Lo.....
Gu.....
Sa.....
Fe.....
19,162
ArizonaState
Arizona State
null
null
1,008
ndtceda18
NDT/CEDA 2018-19
2,018
cx
college
2
3,683,296
“Resolved” before a colon reflects a legislative forum
Army Officer School ‘04
Army Officer School ‘04
(5-12, “# 12, Punctuation – The Colon and Semicolon”, http://usawocc.army.mil/IMI/wg12.htm) The colon introduces A formal resolution, after the word "resolved:" Resolved: (colon) That this council petition the mayor.
The colon introduces A formal resolution, after the word "resolved Resolved: (colon) this council petition the mayor.
(5-12, “# 12, Punctuation – The Colon and Semicolon”, http://usawocc.army.mil/IMI/wg12.htm) The colon introduces the following: a.  A list, but only after "as follows," "the following," or a noun for which the list is an appositive: Each scout will carry the following: (colon) meals for three days, a survival knife, and his sleeping bag. The company had four new officers: (colon) Bill Smith, Frank Tucker, Peter Fillmore, and Oliver Lewis. b.  A long quotation (one or more paragraphs): In The Killer Angels Michael Shaara wrote: (colon) You may find it a different story from the one you learned in school. There have been many versions of that battle [Gettysburg] and that war [the Civil War]. (The quote continues for two more paragraphs.) c.  A formal quotation or question: The President declared: (colon) "The only thing we have to fear is fear itself." The question is: (colon) what can we do about it? d.  A second independent clause which explains the first: Potter's motive is clear: (colon) he wants the assignment. e.  After the introduction of a business letter: Dear Sirs: (colon) Dear Madam: (colon) f.  The details following an announcement For sale: (colon) large lakeside cabin with dock g.  A formal resolution, after the word "resolved:" Resolved: (colon) That this council petition the mayor.
1,317
<h4><strong> “Resolved” before a colon reflects a legislative forum</h4><p>Army Officer School ‘04</p><p><u></strong>(5-12, “# 12, Punctuation – The Colon and Semicolon”, http://usawocc.army.mil/IMI/wg12.htm)</p><p><mark>The colon introduces</u></mark> the following: a.  A list, but only after "as follows," "the following," or a noun for which the list is an appositive: Each scout will carry the following: (colon) meals for three days, a survival knife, and his sleeping bag. The company had four new officers: (colon) Bill Smith, Frank Tucker, Peter Fillmore, and Oliver Lewis. b.  A long quotation (one or more paragraphs): In The Killer Angels Michael Shaara wrote: (colon) You may find it a different story from the one you learned in school. There have been many versions of that battle [Gettysburg] and that war [the Civil War]. (The quote continues for two more paragraphs.) c.  A formal quotation or question: The President declared: (colon) "The only thing we have to fear is fear itself." The question is: (colon) what can we do about it? d.  A second independent clause which explains the first: Potter's motive is clear: (colon) he wants the assignment. e.  After the introduction of a business letter: Dear Sirs: (colon) Dear Madam: (colon) f.  The details following an announcement For sale: (colon) large lakeside cabin with dock g.  <u><mark>A <strong>formal resolution</strong>, after the word "<strong>resolved</strong></mark>:"</p><p><mark>Resolved: (colon)</mark> That <mark>this council petition the mayor.</p></u></mark>
2NC
T
Science
1,131
1,242
123,274
./documents/ndtceda16/Kansas/BhBa/Kansas-Bhatla-Bajwa-Neg-USC-Round6.docx
589,682
N
USC
6
Indiana AS
Manuel
1NC - T-USFG Climate Denial DA (Case) 2NR - T-USFG
ndtceda16/Kansas/BhBa/Kansas-Bhatla-Bajwa-Neg-USC-Round6.docx
null
50,337
BhBa
Kansas BhBa
null
Am.....
Bh.....
Sa.....
Ba.....
19,039
Kansas
Kansas
null
null
1,006
ndtceda16
NDT/CEDA 2016-17
2,016
cx
college
2
4,009,663
Nuke war causes extinction – Ice Age, famines, and war won’t stay limited.
Edwards 17
Edwards 17 – Paul N. Edwards, CISAC’s William J. Perry Fellow in International Security at Stanford’s Freeman Spogli Institute for International Studies. Being interviewed by EarthSky. How nuclear war would affect Earth’s climate. September 8, 2017. earthsky.org/human-world/how-nuclear-war-would-affect-earths-climate
In the nuclear conversation, what are we not talking about that we should be? We are not talking enough about the climatic effects of nuclear war this aspect of nuclear war has faded from view. That’s not good. In the mid-2000s, climate scientists took another look at nuclear winter theory. This time around, they used much-improved and much more detailed climate models than those available 20 years earlier U.S.-Russia war currently seems unlikely, but if it were to occur, hundreds or even thousands of nuclear weapons might be launched. The climatic consequences would be catastrophic: global average temperatures would drop as much as 12 degrees Fahrenheit (7 degrees Celsius) for up to several years — temperatures last seen during the great ice ages. Meanwhile, smoke and dust circulating in the stratosphere would darken the atmosphere enough to inhibit photosynthesis, causing disastrous crop failures, widespread famine and massive ecological disruption. The effect would be similar to that of the giant meteor believed to be responsible for the extinction of the dinosaurs. This time, we would be the dinosaurs. we are closer to a nuclear war than we have been since the early 1960s it’s quite unlikely that any exchange between two nuclear powers would stay limited to these smaller, less destructive bombs.
climate scientists used improved models hundreds or thousands of weapons might be launched temperatures would drop 12 degrees last seen during the ice ages smoke would inhibit photosynthesis, causing crop failures famine and ecological disruption effect would be similar to giant meteor responsible for the extinction of the dinosaurs we would be the dinosaurs. it’s unlikely any exchange would stay limited
In the nuclear conversation, what are we not talking about that we should be? We are not talking enough about the climatic effects of nuclear war. The “nuclear winter” theory of the mid-1980s played a significant role in the arms reductions of that period. But with the collapse of the Soviet Union and the reduction of U.S. and Russian nuclear arsenals, this aspect of nuclear war has faded from view. That’s not good. In the mid-2000s, climate scientists such as Alan Robock (Rutgers) took another look at nuclear winter theory. This time around, they used much-improved and much more detailed climate models than those available 20 years earlier. They also tested the potential effects of smaller nuclear exchanges. The result: an exchange involving just 50 nuclear weapons — the kind of thing we might see in an India-Pakistan war, for example — could loft 5 billion kilograms of smoke, soot and dust high into the stratosphere. That’s enough to cool the entire planet by about 2 degrees Fahrenheit (1.25 degrees Celsius) — about where we were during the Little Ice Age of the 17th century. Growing seasons could be shortened enough to create really significant food shortages. So the climatic effects of even a relatively small nuclear war would be planet-wide. What about a larger-scale conflict? A U.S.-Russia war currently seems unlikely, but if it were to occur, hundreds or even thousands of nuclear weapons might be launched. The climatic consequences would be catastrophic: global average temperatures would drop as much as 12 degrees Fahrenheit (7 degrees Celsius) for up to several years — temperatures last seen during the great ice ages. Meanwhile, smoke and dust circulating in the stratosphere would darken the atmosphere enough to inhibit photosynthesis, causing disastrous crop failures, widespread famine and massive ecological disruption. The effect would be similar to that of the giant meteor believed to be responsible for the extinction of the dinosaurs. This time, we would be the dinosaurs. Many people are concerned about North Korea’s advancing missile capabilities. Is nuclear war likely in your opinion? At this writing, I think we are closer to a nuclear war than we have been since the early 1960s. In the North Korea case, both Kim Jong-un and President Trump are bullies inclined to escalate confrontations. President Trump lacks impulse control, and there are precious few checks on his ability to initiate a nuclear strike. We have to hope that our generals, both inside and outside the White House, can rein him in. North Korea would most certainly “lose” a nuclear war with the United States. But many millions would die, including hundreds of thousands of Americans currently living in South Korea and Japan (probable North Korean targets). Such vast damage would be wrought in Korea, Japan and Pacific island territories (such as Guam) that any “victory” wouldn’t deserve the name. Not only would that region be left with horrible suffering amongst the survivors; it would also immediately face famine and rampant disease. Radioactive fallout from such a war would spread around the world, including to the U.S. It has been more than 70 years since the last time a nuclear bomb was used in warfare. What would be the effects on the environment and on human health today? To my knowledge, most of the changes in nuclear weapons technology since the 1950s have focused on making them smaller and lighter, and making delivery systems more accurate, rather than on changing their effects on the environment or on human health. So-called “battlefield” weapons with lower explosive yields are part of some arsenals now — but it’s quite unlikely that any exchange between two nuclear powers would stay limited to these smaller, less destructive bombs.
3,786
<h4>Nuke war causes <u>extinction</u> – <u>Ice Age</u>, <u>famines</u>, and <u>war</u> won’t stay limited.</h4><p><strong>Edwards 17 </strong>– Paul N. Edwards, CISAC’s William J. Perry Fellow in International Security at Stanford’s Freeman Spogli Institute for International Studies. Being interviewed by EarthSky. How nuclear war would affect Earth’s climate. September 8, 2017. earthsky.org/human-world/how-nuclear-war-would-affect-earths-climate</p><p><u>In the nuclear conversation, what are we not talking about that we should be?</p><p>We are not talking enough about the climatic effects of nuclear<strong> war</u></strong>. The “nuclear winter” theory of the mid-1980s played a significant role in the arms reductions of that period. But with the collapse of the Soviet Union and the reduction of U.S. and Russian nuclear arsenals, <u>this aspect of nuclear war has faded from view. That’s not good. In the mid-2000s, <mark>climate scientists</u></mark> such as Alan Robock (Rutgers) <u>took another look at nuclear winter theory. This time around, they <mark>used </mark>much-<mark>improved</mark> and much more detailed climate <mark>models</mark> than those available 20 years earlier</u>. They also tested the potential effects of smaller nuclear exchanges. The result: an exchange involving just 50 nuclear weapons — the kind of thing we might see in an India-Pakistan war, for example — could loft 5 billion kilograms of smoke, soot and dust high into the stratosphere. That’s enough to cool the entire planet by about 2 degrees Fahrenheit (1.25 degrees Celsius) — about where we were during the Little Ice Age of the 17th century. Growing seasons could be shortened enough to create really significant food shortages. So the climatic effects of even a relatively small nuclear war would be planet-wide. What about a larger-scale conflict? A <u>U.S.-Russia war currently seems unlikely, but if it were to occur, <mark>hundreds or</mark> even <mark>thousands of</mark> nuclear <mark>weapons might be launched</mark>. The climatic consequences would be catastrophic: global average <mark>temperatures would drop</mark> as much as <mark>12 degrees</mark> Fahrenheit (7 degrees Celsius) for up to several years — temperatures <mark>last seen during the </mark>great <mark>ice ages</mark>. Meanwhile, <mark>smoke</mark> and dust circulating in the stratosphere <mark>would </mark>darken the atmosphere enough to <mark>inhibit photosynthesis, causing </mark>disastrous <mark>crop failures</mark>, widespread <mark>famine and </mark>massive <mark>ecological disruption</mark>. The <mark>effect would be similar to</mark> that of the <mark>giant meteor</mark> believed to be <mark>responsible for the extinction of the dinosaurs</mark>. This time, <mark>we would be the dinosaurs.</u></mark> Many people are concerned about North Korea’s advancing missile capabilities. Is nuclear war likely in your opinion? At this writing, I think <u>we are closer to a nuclear war than we have been since the early 1960s</u>. In the North Korea case, both Kim Jong-un and President Trump are bullies inclined to escalate confrontations. President Trump lacks impulse control, and there are precious few checks on his ability to initiate a nuclear strike. We have to hope that our generals, both inside and outside the White House, can rein him in. North Korea would most certainly “lose” a nuclear war with the United States. But many millions would die, including hundreds of thousands of Americans currently living in South Korea and Japan (probable North Korean targets). Such vast damage would be wrought in Korea, Japan and Pacific island territories (such as Guam) that any “victory” wouldn’t deserve the name. Not only would that region be left with horrible suffering amongst the survivors; it would also immediately face famine and rampant disease. Radioactive fallout from such a war would spread around the world, including to the U.S. It has been more than 70 years since the last time a nuclear bomb was used in warfare. What would be the effects on the environment and on human health today? To my knowledge, most of the changes in nuclear weapons technology since the 1950s have focused on making them smaller and lighter, and making delivery systems more accurate, rather than on changing their effects on the environment or on human health. So-called “battlefield” weapons with lower explosive yields are part of some arsenals now — but <u><mark>it’s</mark> quite <mark>unlikely</mark> that <mark>any exchange</mark> between two nuclear powers <mark>would stay limited </mark>to these smaller, less destructive bombs.</p></u>
null
1AC
1AC – Be Like Mike
44,421
1,614
135,635
./documents/hsld21/ScrippsRanch/Sr/Scripps%20Ranch-Sridharan-Aff-Duke%20Invitational-Round4.docx
898,413
A
2 - Duke Invitational
4
Byram Hills EW
Survance, Anthony
1AC - Be Like Mike v1 1NC - Prizes CP - Innovation DA - Climate Patents DA - Case 1AR - Case - Prizes CP - Innovation DA - Climate Patents DA 2NR - Prizes CP - Innovation DA 2AR - Case - Prizes CP - Innovation DA Survance votes for Scripps Ranch AS (W)
hsld21/ScrippsRanch/Sr/Scripps%20Ranch-Sridharan-Aff-Duke%20Invitational-Round4.docx
null
75,319
AgSr
Scripps Ranch AgSr
null
Ag.....
Sr.....
null
null
25,157
ScrippsRanch
Scripps Ranch
CA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
1,314,680
No impact to economic decline – new data
Drezner 2014
Drezner 2014 Daniel, IR prof at Tufts, The System Worked: Global Economic Governance during the Great Recession, World Politics, Volume 66. Number 1, January 2014, pp. 123-164
a dog hasn't barked During the initial stages of the crisis, multiple analysts asserted that the financial crisis would lead states to increase their use of force whether through repression, diversionary wars, arms races, or a ratcheting up of great power conflict The aggregate data suggest otherwise, however the average level of peacefulness in 2012 is approximately the same as it was in 2007 Interstate violence has declined since the start of the financial crisis, as have military expenditures studies confirm that the Great Recession has not triggered any increase in violent conflict The decline in violence that started with the end of the Cold War has not been reversed the crisis has not generated the surge in protectionist nationalism or ethnic exclusion that might have been expected
analysts asserted the crisis would lead states to use of force through diversionary wars, arms races, or great power conflict The aggregate data suggest otherwise the average level of peacefulness in 2012 is the same as 2007 Interstate violence declined as have military expenditures studies confirm the Recession has not triggered violent conflict the crisis has not generated protectionist nationalism or ethnic exclusion
The final significant outcome addresses a dog that hasn't barked: the effect of the Great Recession on cross-border conflict and violence. During the initial stages of the crisis, multiple analysts asserted that the financial crisis would lead states to increase their use of force as a tool for staying in power.42 They voiced genuine concern that the global economic downturn would lead to an increase in conflict—whether through greater internal repression, diversionary wars, arms races, or a ratcheting up of great power conflict. Violence in the Middle East, border disputes in the South China Sea, and even the disruptions of the Occupy movement fueled impressions of a surge in global public disorder. The aggregate data suggest otherwise, however. The Institute for Economics and Peace has concluded that "the average level of peacefulness in 2012 is approximately the same as it was in 2007."43 Interstate violence in particular has declined since the start of the financial crisis, as have military expenditures in most sampled countries. Other studies confirm that the Great Recession has not triggered any increase in violent conflict, as Lotta Themner and Peter Wallensteen conclude: "[T]he pattern is one of relative stability when we consider the trend for the past five years."44 The secular decline in violence that started with the end of the Cold War has not been reversed. Rogers Brubaker observes that "the crisis has not to date generated the surge in protectionist nationalism or ethnic exclusion that might have been expected."43
1,554
<h4>No impact to economic decline – new data</h4><p><u><strong><mark>Drezner 2014</u></strong></mark> Daniel, IR prof at Tufts, The System Worked: Global Economic Governance during the Great Recession, World Politics, Volume 66. Number 1, January 2014, pp. 123-164</p><p>The final significant outcome addresses <u><strong>a dog</u></strong> that <u><strong>hasn't barked</u></strong>: the effect of the Great Recession on cross-border conflict and violence. <u><strong>During the initial stages of the crisis, multiple <mark>analysts asserted</mark> that <mark>the</mark> financial <mark>crisis would lead states to</mark> increase their <mark>use of force</u></strong></mark> as a tool for staying in power.42 They voiced genuine concern that the global economic downturn would lead to an increase in conflict—<u><strong>whether <mark>through</u></strong></mark> greater internal <u><strong>repression, <mark>diversionary wars, arms races, or</mark> a ratcheting up of <mark>great power conflict</u></strong></mark>. Violence in the Middle East, border disputes in the South China Sea, and even the disruptions of the Occupy movement fueled impressions of a surge in global public disorder. <u><strong><mark>The aggregate data suggest otherwise</mark>, however</u></strong>. The Institute for Economics and Peace has concluded that "<u><strong><mark>the average level of peacefulness in 2012 is</mark> approximately <mark>the same as</mark> it was in <mark>2007</u></strong></mark>."43 <u><strong><mark>Interstate violence</u></strong></mark> in particular <u><strong>has <mark>declined</mark> since the start of the financial crisis, <mark>as have military expenditures</u></strong></mark> in most sampled countries. Other <u><strong><mark>studies confirm</mark> that</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>the</mark> Great <mark>Recession has not triggered</mark> any increase in <mark>violent conflict</u></strong></mark>, as Lotta Themner and Peter Wallensteen conclude: "[T]he pattern is one of relative stability when we consider the trend for the past five years."44 <u><strong>The</u></strong> secular <u><strong>decline in violence that started with the end of the Cold War has not been reversed</u></strong>. Rogers Brubaker observes that "<u><strong><mark>the crisis has not</u></strong></mark> to date <u><strong><mark>generated</mark> the surge in <mark>protectionist nationalism or ethnic exclusion</mark> that might have been expected</u></strong>."43</p>
1NC
FDA
null
987
1,375
33,738
./documents/hspolicy15/LiberalArtsAndScience/CuMu/Liberal%20Arts%20And%20Science-Cui-Murdock-Neg-Heritage%20Hall-Round6.docx
647,375
N
Heritage Hall
6
Casady CP
Justin Reinking
1AC - Insider Threats 1NC - T-bulk data TPP Politics Multiplank CP dedev prez powers DA on case 2NC - T prez powers DA case defense 1NR - Politics 2NR - T W
hspolicy15/LiberalArtsAndScience/CuMu/Liberal%20Arts%20And%20Science-Cui-Murdock-Neg-Heritage%20Hall-Round6.docx
null
54,743
CuMu
Liberal Arts And Science CuMu
null
Is.....
Cu.....
Ca.....
Mu.....
19,873
LiberalArtsAndScience
Liberal Arts And Science
null
null
1,014
hspolicy15
HS Policy 2015-16
2,015
cx
hs
2
1,561,463
Moreover, only pleasure and pain are intrinsically valuable. All other values can be explained with reference to pleasure; Occam’s razor requires us to treat these as instrumentally valuable.
Moen 16
Moen 16 [Ole Martin Moen, Research Fellow in Philosophy at University of Oslo “An Argument for Hedonism” Journal of Value Inquiry (Springer), 50 (2) 2016: 267–281] SJDI
I do not think the burden of proof lies on hedonists to explain why the additional values are not intrinsic values. If someone claims that X is intrinsically valuable, this is a substantive, positive claim, and it lies on him or her to explain why we should believe that X is in fact intrinsically valuable. there is something peculiar about the list of additional intrinsic values : the listed values have a strong tendency to be well explained as things that help promote pleasure and avert pain. wisdom, freedom, peace, and security, although they are perhaps not themselves pleasurable, are important means to achieve a happy life, and as such, they are things that hedonists would value highly. Morally good dispositions and virtues, cooperation, and just distribution of goods and evils, moreover, are things that, on a collective level, contribute a happy society, and thus the traits that would be promoted and cultivated if this were something sought after. the suggested non-hedonic intrinsic values are potentially explainable by appeal to just pleasure and pain then—by appeal to Occam’s razor—we have at least a pro tanto reason to resist the introduction of any further intrinsic values and disvalues. It is ontologically more costly to posit a plurality of intrinsic values and disvalues, so in case all values admit of explanation by reference to a single intrinsic value and a single intrinsic disvalue, we have reason to reject more complicated accounts. The fact that suggested non-hedonic intrinsic values tend to be hedonistic instrumental values does not, however, count in favor of hedonism solely in virtue of being most elegantly explained by hedonism; it also does so in virtue of creating an explanatory challenge for pluralists. If the non-hedonic values suggested by pluralists are truly intrinsic values in their own right, then why do they tend to point toward pleasure and away from pain?27
additional values have a tendency to be explained as that help promote pleasure and avert pain wisdom, freedom and securit are important means to achieve a happy life we have reason to resist any further intrinsic values
I think several things should be said in response to Moore’s challenge to hedonists. First, I do not think the burden of proof lies on hedonists to explain why the additional values are not intrinsic values. If someone claims that X is intrinsically valuable, this is a substantive, positive claim, and it lies on him or her to explain why we should believe that X is in fact intrinsically valuable. Possibly, this could be done through thought experiments analogous to those employed in the previous section. Second, there is something peculiar about the list of additional intrinsic values that counts in hedonism’s favor: the listed values have a strong tendency to be well explained as things that help promote pleasure and avert pain. To go through Frankena’s list, life and consciousness are necessary presuppositions for pleasure; activity, health, and strength bring about pleasure; and happiness, beatitude, and contentment are regarded by Frankena himself as “pleasures and satisfactions.” The same is arguably true of beauty, harmony, and “proportion in objects contemplated,” and also of affection, friendship, harmony, and proportion in life, experiences of achievement, adventure and novelty, self-expression, good reputation, honor and esteem. Other things on Frankena’s list, such as understanding, wisdom, freedom, peace, and security, although they are perhaps not themselves pleasurable, are important means to achieve a happy life, and as such, they are things that hedonists would value highly. Morally good dispositions and virtues, cooperation, and just distribution of goods and evils, moreover, are things that, on a collective level, contribute a happy society, and thus the traits that would be promoted and cultivated if this were something sought after. To a very large extent, the intrinsic values suggested by pluralists tend to be hedonic instrumental values. Indeed, pluralists’ suggested intrinsic values all point toward pleasure, for while the other values are reasonably explainable as a means toward pleasure, pleasure itself is not reasonably explainable as a means toward the other values. Some have noticed this. Moore himself, for example, writes that though his pluralistic theory of intrinsic value is opposed to hedonism, its application would, in practice, look very much like hedonism’s: “Hedonists,” he writes “do, in general, recommend a course of conduct which is very similar to that which I should recommend.”24 Ross writes that “[i]t is quite certain that by promoting virtue and knowledge we shall inevitably produce much more pleasant consciousness. These are, by general agreement, among the surest sources of happiness for their possessors.”25 Roger Crisp observes that “those goods cited by non-hedonists are goods we often, indeed usually, enjoy.”26 What Moore and Ross do not seem to notice is that their observations give rise to two reasons to reject pluralism and endorse hedonism. The first reason is that if the suggested non-hedonic intrinsic values are potentially explainable by appeal to just pleasure and pain (which, following my argument in the previous chapter, we should accept as intrinsically valuable and disvaluable), then—by appeal to Occam’s razor—we have at least a pro tanto reason to resist the introduction of any further intrinsic values and disvalues. It is ontologically more costly to posit a plurality of intrinsic values and disvalues, so in case all values admit of explanation by reference to a single intrinsic value and a single intrinsic disvalue, we have reason to reject more complicated accounts. The fact that suggested non-hedonic intrinsic values tend to be hedonistic instrumental values does not, however, count in favor of hedonism solely in virtue of being most elegantly explained by hedonism; it also does so in virtue of creating an explanatory challenge for pluralists. The challenge can be phrased as the following question: If the non-hedonic values suggested by pluralists are truly intrinsic values in their own right, then why do they tend to point toward pleasure and away from pain?27
4,100
<h4><strong>Moreover, only pleasure and pain are intrinsically valuable. All other values can be explained with reference to pleasure; Occam’s razor requires us to treat these as instrumentally valuable. </h4><p>Moen 16</strong> [Ole Martin Moen, Research Fellow in Philosophy at University of Oslo “An Argument for Hedonism” Journal of Value Inquiry (Springer), 50 (2) 2016: 267–281] SJDI</p><p>I think several things should be said in response to Moore’s challenge to hedonists. First, <u><strong>I do not think the burden of proof lies on hedonists to explain why the additional values are not intrinsic values. If someone claims that X is intrinsically valuable, this is a substantive, positive claim, and it lies on him or her to explain why we should believe that X is in fact intrinsically valuable.</u></strong> Possibly, this could be done through thought experiments analogous to those employed in the previous section. Second, <u><strong>there is something peculiar about the list of <mark>additional </mark>intrinsic <mark>values</u></strong></mark> that counts in hedonism’s favor<u><strong>: the listed values <mark>have a </mark>strong <mark>tendency to be</mark> well <mark>explained as</mark> things <mark>that help promote pleasure and avert pain</mark>.</u></strong> To go through Frankena’s list, life and consciousness are necessary presuppositions for pleasure; activity, health, and strength bring about pleasure; and happiness, beatitude, and contentment are regarded by Frankena himself as “pleasures and satisfactions.” The same is arguably true of beauty, harmony, and “proportion in objects contemplated,” and also of affection, friendship, harmony, and proportion in life, experiences of achievement, adventure and novelty, self-expression, good reputation, honor and esteem. Other things on Frankena’s list, such as understanding, <u><strong><mark>wisdom, freedom</mark>, peace, <mark>and securit</mark>y, although they are perhaps not themselves pleasurable, <mark>are important means to achieve a happy life</mark>, and as such, they are things that hedonists would value highly.</u></strong> <u><strong>Morally good dispositions and virtues, cooperation, and just distribution of goods and evils, moreover, are things that, on a collective level, contribute a happy society, and thus the traits that would be promoted and cultivated if this were something sought after.</u></strong> To a very large extent, the intrinsic values suggested by pluralists tend to be hedonic instrumental values. Indeed, pluralists’ suggested intrinsic values all point toward pleasure, for while the other values are reasonably explainable as a means toward pleasure, pleasure itself is not reasonably explainable as a means toward the other values. Some have noticed this. Moore himself, for example, writes that though his pluralistic theory of intrinsic value is opposed to hedonism, its application would, in practice, look very much like hedonism’s: “Hedonists,” he writes “do, in general, recommend a course of conduct which is very similar to that which I should recommend.”24 Ross writes that “[i]t is quite certain that by promoting virtue and knowledge we shall inevitably produce much more pleasant consciousness. These are, by general agreement, among the surest sources of happiness for their possessors.”25 Roger Crisp observes that “those goods cited by non-hedonists are goods we often, indeed usually, enjoy.”26 What Moore and Ross do not seem to notice is that their observations give rise to two reasons to reject pluralism and endorse hedonism. The first reason is that if <u><strong>the suggested non-hedonic intrinsic values are potentially explainable by appeal to just pleasure and pain</u></strong> (which, following my argument in the previous chapter, we should accept as intrinsically valuable and disvaluable), <u><strong>then—by appeal to Occam’s razor—<mark>we have</mark> at least a pro tanto <mark>reason to resist</mark> the introduction of <mark>any further intrinsic values</mark> and disvalues. It is ontologically more costly to posit a plurality of intrinsic values and disvalues, so in case all values admit of explanation by reference to a single intrinsic value and a single intrinsic disvalue, we have reason to reject more complicated accounts.</u></strong> <u><strong>The fact that suggested non-hedonic intrinsic values tend to be hedonistic instrumental values does not, however, count in favor of hedonism solely in virtue of being most elegantly explained by hedonism; it also does so in virtue of creating an explanatory challenge for pluralists.</u></strong> The challenge can be phrased as the following question: <u><strong>If the non-hedonic values suggested by pluralists are truly intrinsic values in their own right, then why do they tend to point toward pleasure and away from pain?27</p></u></strong>
1AC
null
Framing
603,728
1,044
44,937
./documents/hsld21/SouthEugene/Sc/South%20Eugene-Schmidt-Aff-isidore%20newman-Round2.docx
898,959
A
isidore newman
2
Ramsay DF
Carleigh West
1ac- japan 1nc- ballot cp tech da 2nr- tech da
hsld21/SouthEugene/Sc/South%20Eugene-Schmidt-Aff-isidore%20newman-Round2.docx
null
75,336
KeSc
South Eugene KeSc
null
Ke.....
Sc.....
null
null
25,167
SouthEugene
South Eugene
OR
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
3,295,608
Resolved means a legislative policy
Words and Phrases 64
Words and Phrases 64 Words and Phrases Permanent Edition. “Resolved”. 1964.
Definition of the word “resolve,” given by Webster is “to express an opinion or determination by resolution or vote; as ‘it was resolved by the legislature to establish by law
resolve is determination by legislature to establish by law
Definition of the word “resolve,” given by Webster is “to express an opinion or determination by resolution or vote; as ‘it was resolved by the legislature;” It is of similar force to the word “enact,” which is defined by Bouvier as meaning “to establish by law”.
263
<h4><u>Resolved means a legislative policy</h4><p><strong>Words and Phrases 64</u></strong> Words and Phrases Permanent Edition. “Resolved”. 1964.</p><p><u><strong>Definition of the word “<mark>resolve</mark>,” given by Webster <mark>is</mark> “to express an opinion or <mark>determination by</mark> resolution or vote; as ‘it was resolved by the <mark>legislature</u></strong></mark>;” It is of similar force to the word “enact,” which is defined by Bouvier as meaning “<u><strong><mark>to establish by law</u></strong></mark>”. </p>
NC
Offs
1
1,125
2,415
108,144
./documents/hsld18/Enloe/Ge/Enloe-Gedela-Neg-Emory-Doubles.docx
819,769
N
Emory
Doubles
Lake Travis BL
Chris Castillo, Tom Evnen, Charles Karcher
ac - ableism nc - t defend topic v6 cap v9 wounded attachments k case 1ar - case t cap 2nr - t wounds cap case 2ar - case cap
hsld18/Enloe/Ge/Enloe-Gedela-Neg-Emory-Doubles.docx
null
70,214
TeGe
Enloe TeGe
null
Te.....
Ge.....
null
null
23,726
Enloe
Enloe
null
null
1,026
hsld18
HS LD 2018-19
2,018
ld
hs
1
2,369,413
Extinction outweighs
MacAskill 14
MacAskill 14 [William, Oxford Philosopher and youngest tenured philosopher in the world, Normative Uncertainty, 2014]
The human race might go extinct different moral views give opposing answers to question of whether this would be a bad thing However, even if we believe in a moral view which human extinction would be a good thing, we still have strong reason to prevent near-term extinction First extinction is extremely high stakes the number of humans in existence given that we don’t go extinct would be 2×10^14 So if it is good to bring new people into existence, then it’s very good to prevent extinction. Second extinction is irreversible Third, we should expect to progress, morally as we have in the past. in a few centuries’ time we will have better evidence about how to evaluate extinction Suppose that we have 0.2 certain that it’s a good thing to produce new people if we did research for 300 years, we would know for certain whether or not additional people are of positive value there’s a 20% chance of a gain of 2×(10^14), the expected value of which is 4×(10^13). in expected value terms, the cost of waiting is vanishingly small compared with keeping one’s options open
we have strong reason to prevent near-term extinction extremely high stakes extinction is irreversible expect to progress, morally as in the past in time we will have better evidence about how to evaluate extinction if we did research we would know for certain whether or not people positive the cost of waiting is small compared with keeping options open
The human race might go extinct from a number of causes: asteroids, supervolcanoes, runaway climate change, pandemics, nuclear war, and the development and use of dangerous new technologies such as synthetic biology, all pose risks (even if very small) to the continued survival of the human race.184 And different moral views give opposing answers to question of whether this would be a good or a bad thing. It might seem obvious that human extinction would be a very bad thing, both because of the loss of potential future lives, and because of the loss of the scientific and artistic progress that we would make in the future. But the issue is at least unclear. The continuation of the human race would be a mixed bag: inevitably, it would involve both upsides and downsides. And if one regards it as much more important to avoid bad things happening than to promote good things happening then one could plausibly regard human extinction as a good thing.For example, one might regard the prevention of bads as being in general more important that the promotion of goods, as defended historically by G. E. Moore,185 and more recently by Thomas Hurka.186 One could weight the prevention of suffering as being much more important that the promotion of happiness. Or one could weight the prevention of objective bads, such as war and genocide, as being much more important than the promotion of objective goods, such as scientific and artistic progress. If the human race continues its future will inevitably involve suffering as well as happiness, and objective bads as well as objective goods. So, if one weights the bads sufficiently heavily against the goods, or if one is sufficiently pessimistic about humanity’s ability to achieve good outcomes, then one will regard human extinction as a good thing.187 However, even if we believe in a moral view according to which human extinction would be a good thing, we still have strong reason to prevent near-term human extinction. To see this, we must note three points. First, we should note that the extinction of the human race is an extremely high stakes moral issue. Humanity could be around for a very long time: if humans survive as long as the median mammal species, we will last another two million years. On this estimate, the number of humans in existence in the The future, given that we don’t go extinct any time soon, would be 2×10^14. So if it is good to bring new people into existence, then it’s very good to prevent human extinction. Second, human extinction is by its nature an irreversible scenario. If we continue to exist, then we always have the option of letting ourselves go extinct in the future (or, perhaps more realistically, of considerably reducing population size). But if we go extinct, then we can’t magically bring ourselves back into existence at a later date. Third, we should expect ourselves to progress, morally, over the next few centuries, as we have progressed in the past. So we should expect that in a few centuries’ time we will have better evidence about how to evaluate human extinction than we currently have. Given these three factors, it would be better to prevent the near-term extinction of the human race, even if we thought that the extinction of the human race would actually be a very good thing. To make this concrete, I’ll give the following simple but illustrative model. Suppose that we have 0.8 credence that it is a bad thing to produce new people, and 0.2 certain that it’s a good thing to produce new people; and the degree to which it is good to produce new people, if it is good, is the same as the degree to which it is bad to produce new people, if it is bad. That is, I’m supposing, for simplicity, that we know that one new life has one unit of value; we just don’t know whether that unit is positive or negative. And let’s use our estimate of 2×10^14 people who would exist in the future, if we avoid near-term human extinction. Given our stipulated credences, the expected benefit of letting the human race go extinct now would be (.8-.2)×(2×10^14) = 1.2×(10^14). Suppose that, if we let the human race continue and did research for 300 years, we would know for certain whether or not additional people are of positive or negative value. If so, then with the credences above we should think it 80% likely that we will find out that it is a bad thing to produce new people, and 20% likely that we will find out that it’s a good thing to produce new people. So there’s an 80% chance of a loss of 3×(10^10) (because of the delay of letting the human race go extinct), the expected value of which is 2.4×(10^10). But there’s also a 20% chance of a gain of 2×(10^14), the expected value of which is 4×(10^13). That is, in expected value terms, the cost of waiting for a few hundred years is vanishingly small compared with the benefit of keeping one’s options open while one gains new information.
4,914
<h4>Extinction outweighs</h4><p><strong>MacAskill 14</strong> [William, Oxford Philosopher and youngest tenured philosopher in the world, Normative Uncertainty, 2014]</p><p><u><strong>The human race might go extinct </u></strong>from a number of causes: asteroids, supervolcanoes, runaway climate change, pandemics, nuclear war, and the development and use of dangerous new technologies such as synthetic biology, all pose risks (even if very small) to the continued survival of the human race.184 And <u><strong>different moral views give opposing answers to question of whether this would be a </u></strong>good<u><strong> </u></strong>or a <u><strong>bad thing</u></strong>. It might seem obvious that human extinction would be a very bad thing, both because of the loss of potential future lives, and because of the loss of the scientific and artistic progress that we would make in the future. But the issue is at least unclear. The continuation of the human race would be a mixed bag: inevitably, it would involve both upsides and downsides. And if one regards it as much more important to avoid bad things happening than to promote good things happening then one could plausibly regard human extinction as a good thing.For example, one might regard the prevention of bads as being in general more important that the promotion of goods, as defended historically by G. E. Moore,185 and more recently by Thomas Hurka.186 One could weight the prevention of suffering as being much more important that the promotion of happiness. Or one could weight the prevention of objective bads, such as war and genocide, as being much more important than the promotion of objective goods, such as scientific and artistic progress. If the human race continues its future will inevitably involve suffering as well as happiness, and objective bads as well as objective goods. So, if one weights the bads sufficiently heavily against the goods, or if one is sufficiently pessimistic about humanity’s ability to achieve good outcomes, then one will regard human extinction as a good thing.187 <u><strong>However, even if we believe in a moral view </u></strong>according to <u><strong>which human extinction would be a good thing, <mark>we </mark>still <mark>have strong reason to prevent near-term</mark> </u></strong>human<u><strong> <mark>extinction</u></strong></mark>. To see this, we must note three points. <u><strong>First</u></strong>, we should note that the <u><strong>extinction</u></strong> of the human race <u><strong>is </u></strong>an <u><strong><mark>extremely high stakes</u></strong></mark> moral issue. Humanity could be around for a very long time: if humans survive as long as the median mammal species, we will last another two million years. On this estimate, <u><strong>the number of humans in existence </u></strong>in the<u><strong> </u></strong>The future, <u><strong>given that we don’t go extinct</u></strong> any time soon, <u><strong>would be 2×10^14</u></strong>. <u><strong>So if it is good to bring new people into existence, then it’s very good to prevent </u></strong>human<u><strong> extinction. Second</u></strong>, human <u><strong><mark>extinction is</mark> </u></strong>by its nature an <u><strong><mark>irreversible</u></strong></mark> scenario. If we continue to exist, then we always have the option of letting ourselves go extinct in the future (or, perhaps more realistically, of considerably reducing population size). But if we go extinct, then we can’t magically bring ourselves back into existence at a later date. <u><strong>Third, we should <mark>expect</u></strong></mark> ourselves <u><strong><mark>to progress, morally</u></strong></mark>, over the next few centuries, <u><strong><mark>as </mark>we have</u></strong> progressed <u><strong><mark>in the past</mark>.</u></strong> So we should expect that <u><strong><mark>in </mark>a few centuries’ <mark>time we will have better evidence about how to evaluate</u></strong></mark> human <u><strong><mark>extinction</u></strong></mark> than we currently have. Given these three factors, it would be better to prevent the near-term extinction of the human race, even if we thought that the extinction of the human race would actually be a very good thing. To make this concrete, I’ll give the following simple but illustrative model. <u><strong>Suppose that we have</u></strong> 0.8 credence that it is a bad thing to produce new people, and <u><strong>0.2</u></strong> <u><strong>certain that it’s a good thing to produce new people</u></strong>; and the degree to which it is good to produce new people, if it is good, is the same as the degree to which it is bad to produce new people, if it is bad. That is, I’m supposing, for simplicity, that we know that one new life has one unit of value; we just don’t know whether that unit is positive or negative. And let’s use our estimate of 2×10^14 people who would exist in the future, if we avoid near-term human extinction. Given our stipulated credences, the expected benefit of letting the human race go extinct now would be (.8-.2)×(2×10^14) = 1.2×(10^14). Suppose that,<u><strong> <mark>if we</mark> </u></strong>let the human race continue and<u><strong> <mark>did research</mark> for 300 years, <mark>we would know for certain whether or not </mark>additional <mark>people</mark> are of <mark>positive</u></strong></mark> or negative <u><strong>value</u></strong>. If so, then with the credences above we should think it 80% likely that we will find out that it is a bad thing to produce new people, and 20% likely that we will find out that it’s a good thing to produce new people. So there’s an 80% chance of a loss of 3×(10^10) (because of the delay of letting the human race go extinct), the expected value of which is 2.4×(10^10). But <u><strong>there’s</u></strong> also <u><strong>a 20% chance of a gain of 2×(10^14),</u></strong> <u><strong>the expected value of which is 4×(10^13).</u></strong> That is, <u><strong>in expected value terms, <mark>the cost of waiting</mark> </u></strong>for a few hundred years<u><strong> <mark>is </mark>vanishingly <mark>small compared with</mark> </u></strong>the benefit of<u><strong> <mark>keeping </mark>one’s <mark>options open</mark> </u></strong>while one gains new information.</p>
1ac
Framing
null
668,046
1,291
75,558
./documents/hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Er/Strake%20Jesuit-Erdmann-Aff-Yale-Round4.docx
874,372
A
Yale
4
Presentation MS
Saianurag Karavadi
ac - stock with changes in osource nc - carbon tax cp - reform cp - politics da - foucault k - case 1ar - all 2nr - k - carbon tax - politics - case 2ar - case - cp - da
hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Er/Strake%20Jesuit-Erdmann-Aff-Yale-Round4.docx
null
73,799
BeEr
Strake Jesuit BeEr
null
Be.....
Er.....
null
null
24,736
StrakeJesuit
Strake Jesuit
TX
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
4,673,621
Resolved means a Policy.
Louisiana House 5
Louisiana House 5 “Glossary” https://web.archive.org/web/20050211153132/http://house.louisiana.gov/house-glossary.htm //Elmer
Resolution A legislative instrument that generally is used for making declarations, stating policies A bill includes the constitutionally required enacting clause; a resolution uses the term "resolved
Resolution A legislative instrument used for stating policies uses the term "resolved
Resolution A legislative instrument that generally is used for making declarations, stating policies, and making decisions where some other form is not required. A bill includes the constitutionally required enacting clause; a resolution uses the term "resolved". Not subject to a time limit for introduction nor to governor's veto. ( Const. Art. III, §17(B) and House Rules 8.11 , 13.1 , 6.8 , and 7.4)
403
<h4>Resolved means a Policy. </h4><p><strong>Louisiana House 5</strong> “Glossary” https://web.archive.org/web/20050211153132/http://house.louisiana.gov/house-glossary.htm //Elmer</p><p><u><strong><mark>Resolution</u></strong> <u><strong>A legislative instrument</u></strong> <u><strong></mark>that generally is</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>used for</u></strong> <u><strong></mark>making declarations,</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>stating policies</u></strong></mark>, and making decisions where some other form is not required. <u><strong>A bill includes the constitutionally required enacting clause; a resolution</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>uses the term "resolved</u></strong></mark>". Not subject to a time limit for introduction nor to governor's veto. ( Const. Art. III, §17(B) and House Rules 8.11 , 13.1 , 6.8 , and 7.4)</p>
1NC
null
1NC – OFF
1,126
1,429
162,202
./documents/hsld22/DiamondBar/NaCh/DiamondBar-NaCh-Neg-Harvard-Round-2.docx
978,383
N
Harvard
2
Aff Claudia Taylor Johnson MR
Jarvis Xie
1AC - Disability Pess 1NC - T-FW - Disclosure Theory - TT - Silence PIK - Coma K - Incoherency NC - Case 1AR - All 2NR - TT - Case 2AR - Case - TT
hsld22/DiamondBar/NaCh/DiamondBar-NaCh-Neg-Harvard-Round-2.docx
2023-02-18 17:55:46
79,839
NaCh
Diamond Bar NaCh
null
Na.....
Ch.....
null
null
26,840
DiamondBar
Diamond Bar
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
2,121,465
States don’t have the ability to look to individual experiences—can only evaluate averages and aggregates.
Goodin 90.
Goodin 90. Robert Goodin 90, [professor of philosophy at the Australian National University college of arts and social sciences], “The Utilitarian Response,” pgs 141-142 //RS
there is something special about the situation of public officials that makes utilitarianism more probable for them than private individuals. Public officials are obliged to make their choices under uncertainty, and uncertainty of a very special sort at that. private individuals will usually have more complete information on the peculiarities of their own circumstances and on the ramifications that alternative possible choices might have for them. Public officials are relatively poorly informed as to the effects that their choices will have on individuals, one by one. What they typically do know are generalities: averages and aggregates. That is enough to allow public policy-makers to use the utilitarian calculus
Public officials make choices under uncertainty Public officials are poorly informed as to the effects their choices will have on individuals they typically know averages and aggregates That is enough to use utilitarian calculus
My larger argument turns on the proposition that there is something special about the situation of public officials that makes utilitarianism more probable for them than private individuals. Before proceeding with the large argument, I must therefore say what it is that makes it so special about public officials and their situations that make it both more necessary and more desirable for them to adopt a more credible form of utilitarianism. Consider, first, the argument from necessity. Public officials are obliged to make their choices under uncertainty, and uncertainty of a very special sort at that. All choices – public and private alike – are made under some degree of uncertainty, of course. But in the nature of things, private individuals will usually have more complete information on the peculiarities of their own circumstances and on the ramifications that alternative possible choices might have for them. Public officials, in contrast, are relatively poorly informed as to the effects that their choices will have on individuals, one by one. What they typically do know are generalities: averages and aggregates. They know what will happen most often to most people as a result of their various possible choices, but that is all. That is enough to allow public policy-makers to use the utilitarian calculus – assuming they want to use it at all – to choose general rules or conduct.
1,402
<h4>States don’t have the ability to look to individual experiences—can only evaluate averages and aggregates. </h4><p><strong>Goodin 90.</strong> Robert Goodin 90, [professor of philosophy at the Australian National University college of arts and social sciences], “The Utilitarian Response,” pgs 141-142 //RS </p><p>My larger argument turns on the proposition that <u>there is something special about the situation of public officials that makes utilitarianism more probable for them than private individuals.</u> Before proceeding with the large argument, I must therefore say what it is that makes it so special about public officials and their situations that make it both more necessary and more desirable for them to adopt a more credible form of utilitarianism. Consider, first, the argument from necessity. <u><mark>Public officials</mark> are obliged to <mark>make</mark> their <mark>choices under uncertainty</mark>, and uncertainty of a very special sort at that. </u>All choices – public and private alike – are made under some degree of uncertainty, of course. But in the nature of things, <u>private individuals will usually have more complete information on the peculiarities of their own circumstances and on the ramifications that alternative possible choices might have for them. <mark>Public officials</u></mark>, in contrast, <u><mark>are</mark> relatively <mark>poorly informed as to the effects</mark> that <mark>their choices will have on individuals</mark>, one by one. What <mark>they typically</mark> do <mark>know</mark> are generalities: <mark>averages and aggregates</mark>.</u> They know what will happen most often to most people as a result of their various possible choices, but that is all. <u><mark>That is enough to</mark> allow public policy-makers to <mark>use</mark> the <mark>utilitarian calculus</u></mark> – assuming they want to use it at all – to choose general rules or conduct. </p>
null
null
null
332,170
817
63,853
./documents/hsld20/Coppell/Sa/Coppell-Sangani-Neg-Greenhill-Round1.docx
856,336
N
Greenhill
1
Not run yet
Not run yet
null
hsld20/Coppell/Sa/Coppell-Sangani-Neg-Greenhill-Round1.docx
null
72,882
SiSa
Coppell SiSa
null
Si.....
Sa.....
null
null
24,477
Coppell
Coppell
TX
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
4,170,182
No food wars.
Vestby et al. 18
Jonas Vestby et al. 18, Doctoral Researcher at the Peace Research Institute Oslo; Ida Rudolfsen, doctoral researcher at the Department of Peace and Conflict Research at Uppsala University and PRIO; and Halvard Buhaug, Research Professor at the Peace Research Institute Oslo (PRIO), Professor of Political Science at the Norwegian University of Science and Technology (NTNU), and Associate Editor of the Journal of Peace Research and Political Geography, 5/18/2018, “Does hunger cause conflict?” https://blogs.prio.org/ClimateAndConflict/2018/05/does-hunger-cause-conflict/
little scholarly merit in the notion that food increases the probability that conflict will break out violent conflict requires people to have both the means and the will. Most people on the brink of starvation are not in the position to resort to violence In reality, the sources of discontent are considerably more complex---linked to political structures, land ownership, corruption, the desire for democratic reforms and general economic problems Research has shown while the international media tend to seek simple resource-related explanations debates are more complex
little merit that food increases conflict conflict requires means and will. Most on starvation are not resort to violence discontent linked to land corruption democratic reforms and econ while the media seek resource explanations debates are complex
It is perhaps surprising, then, that there is little scholarly merit in the notion that a short-term reduction in access to food increases the probability that conflict will break out. This is because to start or participate in violent conflict requires people to have both the means and the will. Most people on the brink of starvation are not in the position to resort to violence, whether against the government or other social groups. In fact, the urban middle classes tend to be the most likely to protest against rises in food prices, since they often have the best opportunities, the most energy, and the best skills to coordinate and participate in protests. Accordingly, there is a widespread misapprehension that social unrest in periods of high food prices relates primarily to food shortages. In reality, the sources of discontent are considerably more complex---linked to political structures, land ownership, corruption, the desire for democratic reforms and general economic problems---where the price of food is seen in the context of general increases in the cost of living. Research has shown that while the international media have a tendency to seek simple resource-related explanations---such as drought or famine---for conflicts in the Global South, debates in the local media are permeated by more complex political relationships.
1,353
<h4>No food wars.</h4><p>Jonas <strong>Vestby et al. 18</strong>, Doctoral Researcher at the Peace Research Institute Oslo; Ida Rudolfsen, doctoral researcher at the Department of Peace and Conflict Research at Uppsala University and PRIO; and Halvard Buhaug, Research Professor at the Peace Research Institute Oslo (PRIO), Professor of Political Science at the Norwegian University of Science and Technology (NTNU), and Associate Editor of the Journal of Peace Research and Political Geography, 5/18/2018, “Does hunger cause conflict?” https://blogs.prio.org/ClimateAndConflict/2018/05/does-hunger-cause-conflict/</p><p>It is perhaps surprising, then, that there is <u><strong><mark>little</mark> scholarly <mark>merit</strong></mark> in the notion <mark>that</u></mark> a short-term reduction in access to <u><strong><mark>food</strong> increases</mark> the probability that <mark>conflict</mark> will break out</u>. This is because to start or participate in <u><strong>violent <mark>conflict</strong> requires</mark> people to have <strong>both the <mark>means and</mark> the <mark>will</strong>. Most</mark> people <mark>on</mark> the brink of <mark>starvation are not</mark> in the position to <mark>resort to violence</u></mark>, whether against the government or other social groups. In fact, the urban middle classes tend to be the most likely to protest against rises in food prices, since they often have the best opportunities, the most energy, and the best skills to coordinate and participate in protests.</p><p>Accordingly, there is a widespread misapprehension that social unrest in periods of high food prices relates primarily to food shortages. <u><strong>In reality</strong>, <strong>the sources of <mark>discontent</strong></mark> are <strong>considerably more complex</strong>---<mark>linked to</mark> <strong>political structures</strong>, <strong><mark>land</mark> ownership</strong>, <strong><mark>corruption</strong></mark>, the desire for <strong><mark>democratic reforms</strong> and</mark> <strong>general <mark>econ</mark>omic problems</u></strong>---where the price of food is seen in the context of general increases in the cost of living. <u>Research has shown</u> that <u><mark>while <strong>the</mark> international <mark>media</u></strong></mark> have a <u>tend</u>ency <u>to <mark>seek</u></mark> <u><strong>simple <mark>resource</mark>-related <mark>explanations</u></strong></mark>---such as drought or famine---for conflicts in the Global South, <u><mark>debates</u></mark> in the local media <u><mark>are</u></mark> permeated by <u><strong>more <mark>complex</u></strong></mark> political relationships.</p>
1nc---crossings Christian---mich r4
Adv 2
1nc---!---food
6,854
1,148
143,297
./documents/hspolicy22/Gilman/GaMa/Gilman-GaMa-Neg-University-of-Michigan-RR-Round-4.docx
949,292
N
University of Michigan RR
4
Crossings Christian BY
Brown
1ac---Like space AI or something 2nr---condo is good
hspolicy22/Gilman/GaMa/Gilman-GaMa-Neg-University-of-Michigan-RR-Round-4.docx
2022-11-28 19:21:50
79,328
GaMa
Gilman GaMa
chains: gilmangm23@gmail.com tornato@googlegroups.com questions: dgallagher23@students.gilman.edu
Da.....
Ga.....
Ja.....
Ma.....
26,576
Gilman
Gilman
MD
46,484
2,002
hspolicy22
HS Policy 2022-23
2,022
cx
hs
2
2,843,918
Nuclear war fallout between India and Pakistan results in nuclear winter, mass starvation, and an uninhabitable world that converge in extinction.
Starr 15
Starr 15, Steven. “Nuclear War: An Unrecognized Mass Extinction Event Waiting To Happen.” Ratical. March 2015. https://ratical.org/radiation/NuclearExtinction/StevenStarr022815.html / MU
A war fought with 21st century nuclear weapons would be more than just a great catastrophe in human history. If we allow it to happen, such a war would be a mass extinction event that ends human history. There is a profound difference between extinction and “an unprecedented disaster,” or even “the end of civilization,” because even after such an immense catastrophe, human life would go on. extinction, by definition, is an event of utter finality, and a nuclear war that could cause human extinction should really be considered as the ultimate criminal act The world’s leading climatologists now tell us that nuclear war threatens our continued existence as a species studies predict that a large nuclear war, especially one fought with strategic nuclear weapons, would create a post-war environment in which for many years it would be too cold and dark to even grow food not only humans, but most large animals and many other forms of complex life would likely vanish forever in a nuclear darkness The environmental consequences of nuclear war would attack the ecological support systems of life at every level. Radioactive fallout produced not only by nuclear bombs, but also by the destruction of nuclear power plants and their spent fuel pools, would poison the biosphere. Millions of tons of smoke would act to destroy Earth’s protective ozone layer and block most sunlight from reaching Earth’s surface, creating Ice Age weather conditions that would last for decades. research predicts virtually any nuclear war, fought with even a fraction of the operational and deployed nuclear arsenals, will leave the Earth essentially uninhabitable.
A war with nuclear weapons would be a mass extinction event an event of utter finality for many years it would be too cold and dark to grow food Radioactive fallout would poison the biosphere. Millions of tons of smoke would destroy ozone and block sunlight from reaching Earth creating Ice Age for decades virtually any nuclear war will leave the Earth essentially uninhabitable
A war fought with 21st century strategic nuclear weapons would be more than just a great catastrophe in human history. If we allow it to happen, such a war would be a mass extinction event that ends human history. There is a profound difference between extinction and “an unprecedented disaster,” or even “the end of civilization,” because even after such an immense catastrophe, human life would go on. But extinction, by definition, is an event of utter finality, and a nuclear war that could cause human extinction should really be considered as the ultimate criminal act. It certainly would be the crime to end all crimes. The world’s leading climatologists now tell us that nuclear war threatens our continued existence as a species. Their studies predict that a large nuclear war, especially one fought with strategic nuclear weapons, would create a post-war environment in which for many years it would be too cold and dark to even grow food. Their findings make it clear that not only humans, but most large animals and many other forms of complex life would likely vanish forever in a nuclear darkness of our own making. The environmental consequences of nuclear war would attack the ecological support systems of life at every level. Radioactive fallout produced not only by nuclear bombs, but also by the destruction of nuclear power plants and their spent fuel pools, would poison the biosphere. Millions of tons of smoke would act to destroy Earth’s protective ozone layer and block most sunlight from reaching Earth’s surface, creating Ice Age weather conditions that would last for decades. Yet the political and military leaders who control nuclear weapons strictly avoid any direct public discussion of the consequences of nuclear war. They do so by arguing that nuclear weapons are not intended to be used, but only to deter. Remarkably, the leaders of the Nuclear Weapon States have chosen to ignore the authoritative, long-standing scientific research done by the climatologists, research that predicts virtually any nuclear war, fought with even a fraction of the operational and deployed nuclear arsenals, will leave the Earth essentially uninhabitable.
2,175
<h4>Nuclear war fallout between India and Pakistan results in nuclear winter, mass starvation, and an uninhabitable world that converge in extinction. </h4><p><strong>Starr 15<u></strong>, Steven</u>. “Nuclear War: An Unrecognized Mass Extinction Event Waiting To Happen.” Ratical. March 2015. https://ratical.org/radiation/NuclearExtinction/StevenStarr022815.html /<u> MU</p><p><strong><mark>A war</strong> </mark>fought <strong><mark>with</strong></mark> 21st century</u> strategic <u><strong><mark>nuclear weapons</strong></mark> would be more than just a great catastrophe in human history. If we allow it to happen, such a war <strong><mark>would be a mass extinction event</strong></mark> that ends human history. There is a profound difference between extinction and “an unprecedented disaster,” or even “the end of civilization,” because even after such an immense catastrophe, human life would go on. </u>But <u>extinction, by definition, is <strong><mark>an event of utter finality</strong></mark>, and a nuclear war that could cause human extinction should really be considered as the ultimate criminal act</u>. It certainly would be the crime to end all crimes. <u>The world’s leading climatologists now tell us that nuclear war threatens our continued existence as a species</u>. Their <u>studies predict that a large nuclear war, especially one fought with strategic nuclear weapons, would create a post-war environment in which <strong><mark>for many years it would be too cold and dark to</strong></mark> even <strong><mark>grow food</u></strong></mark>. Their findings make it clear that <u>not only humans, but most large animals and many other forms of complex life would likely vanish forever in a nuclear darkness </u>of our own making. <u>The environmental consequences of nuclear war would attack the ecological support systems of life at every level. <strong><mark>Radioactive fallout</strong></mark> produced not only by nuclear bombs, but also by the destruction of nuclear power plants and their spent fuel pools, <strong><mark>would poison the biosphere. Millions of tons of smoke would</strong></mark> act to <strong><mark>destroy</strong></mark> Earth’s protective <strong><mark>ozone</strong></mark> layer <strong><mark>and block</strong></mark> most <strong><mark>sunlight from reaching Earth</strong></mark>’s surface, <strong><mark>creating Ice Age</strong></mark> weather conditions that would last <strong><mark>for decades</strong></mark>. </u>Yet the political and military leaders who control nuclear weapons strictly avoid any direct public discussion of the consequences of nuclear war. They do so by arguing that nuclear weapons are not intended to be used, but only to deter. Remarkably, the leaders of the Nuclear Weapon States have chosen to ignore the authoritative, long-standing scientific research done by the climatologists, <u>research</u> that <u>predicts <strong><mark>virtually any nuclear war</strong></mark>, fought with even a fraction of the operational and deployed nuclear arsenals, <strong><mark>will leave the Earth essentially uninhabitable</strong></mark>.</p></u>
Kashmir AC
1AC – Plan
null
168,110
1,530
90,116
./documents/hsld19/AppletonNorth/Ub/Appleton%20North-Uberoi-Aff-State-Round1.docx
833,151
A
State
1
Neenah WR
Jaya Sims
1AC - IndoPak 1NC - deterrence terror 1AR - IndoPak 2NC - all 2AR - IndoPak
hsld19/AppletonNorth/Ub/Appleton%20North-Uberoi-Aff-State-Round1.docx
null
71,196
MiUb
Appleton North MiUb
null
Mi.....
Ub.....
null
null
23,978
AppletonNorth
Appleton North
WI
null
1,027
hsld19
HS LD 2019-20
2,019
ld
hs
1
2,131,653
“Resolved” before a colon reflects a legislative forum
Army Officer School 2005
Army Officer School 2005 (“# 12, Punctuation – The Colon and Semicolon”, 5-12, http://usawocc.army.mil/IMI/wg12.htm)
The colon introduces A formal resolution, after the word "resolved:" Resolved: (colon) That this council petition the mayor.
The colon introduces A formal resolution, after the word "resolved:" Resolved: (colon)
The colon introduces the following: a. A list, but only after "as follows," "the following," or a noun for which the list is an appositive: Each scout will carry the following: (colon) meals for three days, a survival knife, and his sleeping bag. The company had four new officers: (colon) Bill Smith, Frank Tucker, Peter Fillmore, and Oliver Lewis. b. A long quotation (one or more paragraphs): In The Killer Angels Michael Shaara wrote: (colon) You may find it a different story from the one you learned in school. There have been many versions of that battle [Gettysburg] and that war [the Civil War]. (The quote continues for two more paragraphs.) c. A formal quotation or question: The President declared: (colon) "The only thing we have to fear is fear itself." The question is: (colon) what can we do about it? d. A second independent clause which explains the first: Potter's motive is clear: (colon) he wants the assignment. e. After the introduction of a business letter: Dear Sirs: (colon) Dear Madam: (colon) f. The details following an announcement For sale: (colon) large lakeside cabin with dock g. A formal resolution, after the word "resolved:" Resolved: (colon) That this council petition the mayor.
1,217
<h4>“Resolved” before a colon reflects a legislative forum</h4><p><strong>Army Officer School 2005 </strong>(“# 12, Punctuation – The Colon and Semicolon”, 5-12, http://usawocc.army.mil/IMI/wg12.htm)</p><p><u><mark>The colon introduces</u></mark> the following: a. A list, but only after "as follows," "the following," or a noun for which the list is an appositive: Each scout will carry the following: (colon) meals for three days, a survival knife, and his sleeping bag. The company had four new officers: (colon) Bill Smith, Frank Tucker, Peter Fillmore, and Oliver Lewis. b. A long quotation (one or more paragraphs): In The Killer Angels Michael Shaara wrote: (colon) You may find it a different story from the one you learned in school. There have been many versions of that battle [Gettysburg] and that war [the Civil War]. (The quote continues for two more paragraphs.) c. A formal quotation or question: The President declared: (colon) "The only thing we have to fear is fear itself." The question is: (colon) what can we do about it? d. A second independent clause which explains the first: Potter's motive is clear: (colon) he wants the assignment. e. After the introduction of a business letter: Dear Sirs: (colon) Dear Madam: (colon) f. The details following an announcement For sale: (colon) large lakeside cabin with dock g. <u><mark>A formal resolution, after the word "resolved:" Resolved: (colon) </mark>That this council petition the mayor.</p></u>
null
3
null
1,131
1,242
64,308
./documents/hsld20/DoughertyValley/Ko/Dougherty%20Valley-Kotapati-Neg-Berkeley%20Invitational-Round1.docx
856,943
N
Berkeley Invitational
1
Albuquerque LN
Beth Zhao
1AC - NonT 1NC - TFW Disc New Affs Bad Case 1AR - All 2NR - NAB Movements Case 2AR - idk i wasn't paying attention
hsld20/DoughertyValley/Ko/Dougherty%20Valley-Kotapati-Neg-Berkeley%20Invitational-Round1.docx
null
72,920
SaKo
Dougherty Valley SaKo
null
Sa.....
Ko.....
null
null
24,491
DoughertyValley
Dougherty Valley
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
3,697,027
Should requires immediate, certain legal effect
Summers 94
Summers 94 (Justice – Oklahoma Supreme Court, “Kelsey v. Dollarsaver Food Warehouse of Durant”, 1994 OK 123, 11-8, http://www.oscn.net/applications/oscn/DeliverDocument.asp?CiteID=20287#marker3fn13)
The legal question to be resolved by the court is whether the word "should" may be deemed a ruling in praesenti Certain contexts mandate a construction of the term "should" as more than merely indicating preference or desirability ) ("should" would mean the same as "shall" or "must" In praesenti means literally "at the present time." the phrase denotes law is immediately effective, as opposed to something that will or would become effective in the future
contexts mandate construction of "should" as more than desirability "should" would mean "must" law is immediately effective as opposed to in the future
4 The legal question to be resolved by the court is whether the word "should"13 in the May 18 order connotes futurity or may be deemed a ruling in praesenti.14 The answer to this query is not to be divined from rules of grammar;15 it must be governed by the age-old practice culture of legal professionals and its immemorial language usage. To determine if the omission (from the critical May 18 entry) of the turgid phrase, "and the same hereby is", (1) makes it an in futuro ruling - i.e., an expression of what the judge will or would do at a later stage - or (2) constitutes an in in praesenti resolution of a disputed law issue, the trial judge's intent must be garnered from the four corners of the entire record.16 [CONTINUES – TO FOOTNOTE] 13 "Should" not only is used as a "present indicative" synonymous with ought but also is the past tense of "shall" with various shades of meaning not always easy to analyze. See 57 C.J. Shall § 9, Judgments § 121 (1932). O. JESPERSEN, GROWTH AND STRUCTURE OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE (1984); St. Louis & S.F.R. Co. v. Brown, 45 Okl. 143, 144 P. 1075, 1080-81 (1914). For a more detailed explanation, see the Partridge quotation infra note 15. Certain contexts mandate a construction of the term "should" as more than merely indicating preference or desirability. Brown, supra at 1080-81 (jury instructions stating that jurors "should" reduce the amount of damages in proportion to the amount of contributory negligence of the plaintiff was held to imply an obligation and to be more than advisory); Carrigan v. California Horse Racing Board, 60 Wash. App. 79, 802 P.2d 813 (1990) (one of the Rules of Appellate Procedure requiring that a party "should devote a section of the brief to the request for the fee or expenses" was interpreted to mean that a party is under an obligation to include the requested segment); State v. Rack, 318 S.W.2d 211, 215 (Mo. 1958) ("should" would mean the same as "shall" or "must" when used in an instruction to the jury which tells the triers they "should disregard false testimony"). 14 In praesenti means literally "at the present time." BLACK'S LAW DICTIONARY 792 (6th Ed. 1990). In legal parlance the phrase denotes that which in law is presently or immediately effective, as opposed to something that will or would become effective in the future [in futurol]. See Van Wyck v. Knevals, 106 U.S. 360, 365, 1 S.Ct. 336, 337, 27 L.Ed. 201 (1882).
2,425
<h4><strong>Should requires immediate, certain legal effect</h4><p>Summers 94</strong> (Justice – Oklahoma Supreme Court, “Kelsey v. Dollarsaver Food Warehouse of Durant”, 1994 OK 123, 11-8, http://www.oscn.net/applications/oscn/DeliverDocument.asp?CiteID=20287#marker3fn13)</p><p> 4 <u><strong>The legal question to be resolved by the court is whether the word "should"</u></strong>13 in the May 18 order connotes futurity or <u><strong>may be deemed a ruling in praesenti</u></strong>.14 The answer to this query is not to be divined from rules of grammar;15 it must be governed by the age-old practice culture of legal professionals and its immemorial language usage. To determine if the omission (from the critical May 18 entry) of the turgid phrase, "and the same hereby is", (1) makes it an in futuro ruling - i.e., an expression of what the judge will or would do at a later stage - or (2) constitutes an in in praesenti resolution of a disputed law issue, the trial judge's intent must be garnered from the four corners of the entire record.16 </p><p>[CONTINUES – TO FOOTNOTE]</p><p>13 "Should" not only is used as a "present indicative" synonymous with ought but also is the past tense of "shall" with various shades of meaning not always easy to analyze. See 57 C.J. Shall § 9, Judgments § 121 (1932). O. JESPERSEN, GROWTH AND STRUCTURE OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE (1984); St. Louis & S.F.R. Co. v. Brown, 45 Okl. 143, 144 P. 1075, 1080-81 (1914). For a more detailed explanation, see the Partridge quotation infra note 15. <u><strong>Certain <mark>contexts mandate</mark> a <mark>construction of</mark> the term <mark>"should" as more than</mark> merely indicating preference or <mark>desirability</u></strong></mark>. Brown, supra at 1080-81 (jury instructions stating that jurors "should" reduce the amount of damages in proportion to the amount of contributory negligence of the plaintiff was held to imply an obligation and to be more than advisory); Carrigan v. California Horse Racing Board, 60 Wash. App. 79, 802 P.2d 813 (1990) (one of the Rules of Appellate Procedure requiring that a party "should devote a section of the brief to the request for the fee or expenses" was interpreted to mean that a party is under an obligation to include the requested segment); State v. Rack, 318 S.W.2d 211, 215 (Mo. 1958<u><strong>) (<mark>"should" would mean</mark> the same as "shall" or <mark>"must"</strong></mark> </u>when used in an instruction to the jury which tells the triers they "should disregard false testimony"). 14 <u><strong>In praesenti means literally "at the present time."</u></strong> BLACK'S LAW DICTIONARY 792 (6th Ed. 1990). In legal parlance <u><strong>the phrase denotes</u></strong> that which in <u><strong><mark>law is</u></strong></mark> presently or <u><strong><mark>immediately effective</mark>, <mark>as opposed to</mark> something that will or would become effective <mark>in the future</u></strong></mark> [in futurol]. See Van Wyck v. Knevals, 106 U.S. 360, 365, 1 S.Ct. 336, 337, 27 L.Ed. 201 (1882).</p>
1nr
null
Harmonization
380
1,885
123,700
./documents/ndtceda16/JamesMadison/LeWa/James%20Madison-Lepp-Wardak-Neg-Liberty-Round4.docx
589,452
N
Liberty
4
Georgia YM
John Katsulas
1AC Carbon Tax Warming Harmonization 1NC T Restrictions Spec Econ DA Elections DA TPP DA 2NC Case 1NR Econ Elex 2NR Econ Case
ndtceda16/JamesMadison/LeWa/James%20Madison-Lepp-Wardak-Neg-Liberty-Round4.docx
null
50,313
LeWa
James Madison LeWa
null
Ni.....
Le.....
Ry.....
Wa.....
19,036
JamesMadison
James Madison
null
null
1,006
ndtceda16
NDT/CEDA 2016-17
2,016
cx
college
2
1,581,805
D] Mathematically outweighs.
MacAskill 14
MacAskill 14 [William, Oxford Philosopher and youngest tenured philosopher in the world, Normative Uncertainty, 2014]
The human race might go extinct different moral views give opposing answers to question of whether this would be a bad thing However, even if we believe in a moral view which human extinction would be a good thing, we still have strong reason to prevent near-term human extinction First extinction is extremely high stakes the number of humans in existence given that we don’t go extinct would be 2×10^14 So if it is good to bring new people into existence, then it’s very good to prevent extinction. Second extinction is by its nature an irreversible scenario Third, we should expect to progress, morally as we have in the past. in a few centuries’ time we will have better evidence about how to evaluate human extinction Suppose that we have 0.2 certain that it’s a good thing to produce new people if we did research for 300 years, we would know for certain whether or not additional people are of positive or negative value there’s a 20% chance of a gain of 2×(10^14), the expected value of which is 4×(10^13). in expected value terms, the cost of waiting is vanishingly small compared with benefit of keeping one’s options open
we have reason to prevent extinction extremely high stakes 2×10^14 extinction is irreversible in time we will have better evidence about how to evaluate extinction if we did research we would know for certain whether people positive the cost of waiting is small compared with keeping options open
The human race might go extinct from a number of causes: asteroids, supervolcanoes, runaway climate change, pandemics, nuclear war, and the development and use of dangerous new technologies such as synthetic biology, all pose risks (even if very small) to the continued survival of the human race.184 And different moral views give opposing answers to question of whether this would be a good or a bad thing. It might seem obvious that human extinction would be a very bad thing, both because of the loss of potential future lives, and because of the loss of the scientific and artistic progress that we would make in the future. But the issue is at least unclear. The continuation of the human race would be a mixed bag: inevitably, it would involve both upsides and downsides. And if one regards it as much more important to avoid bad things happening than to promote good things happening then one could plausibly regard human extinction as a good thing.For example, one might regard the prevention of bads as being in general more important that the promotion of goods, as defended historically by G. E. Moore,185 and more recently by Thomas Hurka.186 One could weight the prevention of suffering as being much more important that the promotion of happiness. Or one could weight the prevention of objective bads, such as war and genocide, as being much more important than the promotion of objective goods, such as scientific and artistic progress. If the human race continues its future will inevitably involve suffering as well as happiness, and objective bads as well as objective goods. So, if one weights the bads sufficiently heavily against the goods, or if one is sufficiently pessimistic about humanity’s ability to achieve good outcomes, then one will regard human extinction as a good thing.187 However, even if we believe in a moral view according to which human extinction would be a good thing, we still have strong reason to prevent near-term human extinction. To see this, we must note three points. First, we should note that the extinction of the human race is an extremely high stakes moral issue. Humanity could be around for a very long time: if humans survive as long as the median mammal species, we will last another two million years. On this estimate, the number of humans in existence in the The future, given that we don’t go extinct any time soon, would be 2×10^14. So if it is good to bring new people into existence, then it’s very good to prevent human extinction. Second, human extinction is by its nature an irreversible scenario. If we continue to exist, then we always have the option of letting ourselves go extinct in the future (or, perhaps more realistically, of considerably reducing population size). But if we go extinct, then we can’t magically bring ourselves back into existence at a later date. Third, we should expect ourselves to progress, morally, over the next few centuries, as we have progressed in the past. So we should expect that in a few centuries’ time we will have better evidence about how to evaluate human extinction than we currently have. Given these three factors, it would be better to prevent the near-term extinction of the human race, even if we thought that the extinction of the human race would actually be a very good thing. To make this concrete, I’ll give the following simple but illustrative model. Suppose that we have 0.8 credence that it is a bad thing to produce new people, and 0.2 certain that it’s a good thing to produce new people; and the degree to which it is good to produce new people, if it is good, is the same as the degree to which it is bad to produce new people, if it is bad. That is, I’m supposing, for simplicity, that we know that one new life has one unit of value; we just don’t know whether that unit is positive or negative. And let’s use our estimate of 2×10^14 people who would exist in the future, if we avoid near-term human extinction. Given our stipulated credences, the expected benefit of letting the human race go extinct now would be (.8-.2)×(2×10^14) = 1.2×(10^14). Suppose that, if we let the human race continue and did research for 300 years, we would know for certain whether or not additional people are of positive or negative value. If so, then with the credences above we should think it 80% likely that we will find out that it is a bad thing to produce new people, and 20% likely that we will find out that it’s a good thing to produce new people. So there’s an 80% chance of a loss of 3×(10^10) (because of the delay of letting the human race go extinct), the expected value of which is 2.4×(10^10). But there’s also a 20% chance of a gain of 2×(10^14), the expected value of which is 4×(10^13). That is, in expected value terms, the cost of waiting for a few hundred years is vanishingly small compared with the benefit of keeping one’s options open while one gains new information.
4,914
<h4>D] Mathematically <u>outweighs</u>.</h4><p><strong>MacAskill 14</strong> [William, Oxford Philosopher and youngest tenured philosopher in the world, Normative Uncertainty, 2014]</p><p><u>The human race might go extinct </u>from a number of causes: asteroids, supervolcanoes, runaway climate change, pandemics, nuclear war, and the development and use of dangerous new technologies such as synthetic biology, all pose risks (even if very small) to the continued survival of the human race.184 And <u>different moral views give opposing answers to question of whether this would be a </u>good<u> </u>or a <u>bad thing</u>. It might seem obvious that human extinction would be a very bad thing, both because of the loss of potential future lives, and because of the loss of the scientific and artistic progress that we would make in the future. But the issue is at least unclear. The continuation of the human race would be a mixed bag: inevitably, it would involve both upsides and downsides. And if one regards it as much more important to avoid bad things happening than to promote good things happening then one could plausibly regard human extinction as a good thing.For example, one might regard the prevention of bads as being in general more important that the promotion of goods, as defended historically by G. E. Moore,185 and more recently by Thomas Hurka.186 One could weight the prevention of suffering as being much more important that the promotion of happiness. Or one could weight the prevention of objective bads, such as war and genocide, as being much more important than the promotion of objective goods, such as scientific and artistic progress. If the human race continues its future will inevitably involve suffering as well as happiness, and objective bads as well as objective goods. So, if one weights the bads sufficiently heavily against the goods, or if one is sufficiently pessimistic about humanity’s ability to achieve good outcomes, then one will regard human extinction as a good thing.187 <u>However, even if we believe in a moral view </u>according to <u>which human extinction would be a good thing, <mark>we </mark>still <mark>have <strong></mark>strong <mark>reason to prevent </mark>near-term human <mark>extinction</u></strong></mark>. To see this, we must note three points. <u>First</u>, we should note that the <u>extinction</u> of the human race <u>is </u>an <u><mark>extremely <strong>high stakes</u></strong></mark> moral issue. Humanity could be around for a very long time: if humans survive as long as the median mammal species, we will last another two million years. On this estimate, <u>the number of humans in existence </u>in the<u> </u>The future, <u>given that we don’t go extinct</u> any time soon, <u>would be <strong><mark>2×10^14</u></strong></mark>. <u>So if it is good to bring new people into existence, then it’s very good to prevent </u>human<u> extinction. Second</u>, human <u><strong><mark>extinction is</mark> by its nature an <mark>irreversible</mark> scenario</u></strong>. If we continue to exist, then we always have the option of letting ourselves go extinct in the future (or, perhaps more realistically, of considerably reducing population size). But if we go extinct, then we can’t magically bring ourselves back into existence at a later date. <u>Third, we should expect</u> ourselves <u>to progress, morally</u>, over the next few centuries, <u>as we have</u> progressed <u>in the past.</u> So we should expect that <u><mark>in </mark>a few centuries’ <mark>time we will have <strong>better evidence about how to evaluate</mark> human <mark>extinction</u></strong></mark> than we currently have. Given these three factors, it would be better to prevent the near-term extinction of the human race, even if we thought that the extinction of the human race would actually be a very good thing. To make this concrete, I’ll give the following simple but illustrative model. <u>Suppose that we have</u> 0.8 credence that it is a bad thing to produce new people, and <u>0.2</u> <u>certain that it’s a good thing to produce new people</u>; and the degree to which it is good to produce new people, if it is good, is the same as the degree to which it is bad to produce new people, if it is bad. That is, I’m supposing, for simplicity, that we know that one new life has one unit of value; we just don’t know whether that unit is positive or negative. And let’s use our estimate of 2×10^14 people who would exist in the future, if we avoid near-term human extinction. Given our stipulated credences, the expected benefit of letting the human race go extinct now would be (.8-.2)×(2×10^14) = 1.2×(10^14). Suppose that,<u> <mark>if we</mark> </u>let the human race continue and<u> <mark>did research</mark> for 300 years, <mark>we would know <strong>for certain</strong> whether </mark>or not additional <mark>people</mark> are of <strong><mark>positive</mark> or negative value</u></strong>. If so, then with the credences above we should think it 80% likely that we will find out that it is a bad thing to produce new people, and 20% likely that we will find out that it’s a good thing to produce new people. So there’s an 80% chance of a loss of 3×(10^10) (because of the delay of letting the human race go extinct), the expected value of which is 2.4×(10^10). But <u>there’s</u> also <u>a 20% chance of a gain of 2×(10^14),</u> <u>the expected value of which is 4×(10^13).</u> That is, <u>in expected value terms, <mark>the cost of waiting</mark> </u>for a few hundred years<u> <mark>is <strong></mark>vanishingly <mark>small</strong> compared with</mark> </u>the <u><strong>benefit of <mark>keeping </mark>one’s <mark>options open</strong></mark> </u>while one gains new information.</p>
null
1AC R4 Churchill
1AC – Framing
668,046
1,291
45,723
./documents/hsld21/StrakeJesuit/Sh/Strake%20Jesuit-Shah-Aff-Churchill-Round4.docx
899,775
A
Churchill
4
StMar WK
Brody, Ben
1AC- Debris 1NC- Space Innovation (Lay) Case 1AR- All 2NR- All 2AR- All
hsld21/StrakeJesuit/Sh/Strake%20Jesuit-Shah-Aff-Churchill-Round4.docx
null
75,363
KaSh
Strake Jesuit KaSh
null
Ka.....
Sh.....
null
null
25,176
StrakeJesuit
Strake Jesuit
TX
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
703,575
3. No disease extinction
Barratt 17
Owen Cotton-Barratt 17, et al, PhD in Pure Mathematics, Oxford, Lecturer in Mathematics at Oxford, Research Associate at the Future of Humanity Institute, 2/3/2017, Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf
natural pandemics are very unlikely to cause human extinction. of the 833 recorded plant and animal species extinctions known to have occurred since 1500, less than 4% (31 species) were ascribed to infectious disease None of the mammals and amphibians on this list were globally dispersed, and other factors aside from infectious disease also contributed to their extinction. It seems that our own species, which is very numerous, globally dispersed, and capable of a rational response to problems, is very unlikely to be killed off by a natural pandemic. that highly lethal pathogens can kill their hosts before they have a chance to spread there is a selective pressure for pathogens not to be highly lethal
pandemics are unlikely to cause extinction. of 833 plant and animal extinctions since 1500, less than 4% were ascribed to infectious disease. None were globally dispersed, other factors also contributed our species is numerous, globally dispersed, and capable of a rational response very unlikely to be killed by a highly lethal pathogens can kill hosts before they there is a selective pressure for pathogens not to be lethal
For most of human history, natural pandemics have posed the greatest risk of mass global fatalities.37 However, there are some reasons to believe that natural pandemics are very unlikely to cause human extinction. Analysis of the International Union for Conservation of Nature (IUCN) red list database has shown that of the 833 recorded plant and animal species extinctions known to have occurred since 1500, less than 4% (31 species) were ascribed to infectious disease.38 None of the mammals and amphibians on this list were globally dispersed, and other factors aside from infectious disease also contributed to their extinction. It therefore seems that our own species, which is very numerous, globally dispersed, and capable of a rational response to problems, is very unlikely to be killed off by a natural pandemic. One underlying explanation for this is that highly lethal pathogens can kill their hosts before they have a chance to spread , so there is a selective pressure for pathogens not to be highly lethal. Therefore, pathogens are likely to co-evolve with their hosts rather than kill all possible hosts.39
1,122
<h4>3. No disease extinction</h4><p>Owen Cotton-<strong>Barratt 17</strong>, et al, PhD in Pure Mathematics, Oxford, Lecturer in Mathematics at Oxford, Research Associate at the Future of Humanity Institute, 2/3/2017, Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf</p><p>For most of human history, natural pandemics have posed the greatest risk of mass global fatalities.37 However, there are some reasons to believe that<u> natural <mark>pandemics are</mark> <strong>very <mark>unlikely to cause </mark>human <mark>extinction</strong>.</u></mark> Analysis of the International Union for Conservation of Nature (IUCN) red list database has shown that<u> <mark>of</mark> the <mark>833</mark> recorded <mark>plant and animal</mark> species <mark>extinctions</mark> known to have occurred <mark>since 1500, <strong>less than 4%</strong></mark> (31 species) <mark>were ascribed to infectious disease</u>.</mark>38 <u><mark>None</mark> of the mammals and amphibians on this list <mark>were globally dispersed,</mark> and <mark>other factors</mark> aside from infectious disease <mark>also contributed</mark> to their extinction.</u> <u>It </u>therefore <u>seems that <mark>our</mark> own <mark>species</mark>, which <mark>is <strong></mark>very <mark>numerous</strong>, <strong>globally dispersed</strong>, and capable of a <strong>rational response</mark> to problems</strong>, is <mark>very unlikely to be killed</mark> off <mark>by a</mark> natural pandemic.</p><p></u>One underlying explanation for this is <u>that <mark>highly lethal pathogens can kill</mark> their <mark>hosts before they</mark> have a chance to spread</p><p></u>, so <u><mark>there is a <strong>selective pressure for pathogens not to be</mark> highly <mark>lethal</u></strong></mark>. Therefore, pathogens are likely to co-evolve with their hosts rather than kill all possible hosts.39</p>
null
Deterrence
null
2,356
2,146
15,265
./documents/hsld19/Harker/Th/Harker-Thakur-Neg-Harvard%20Westlake-Round6.docx
838,473
N
Harvard Westlake
6
Marlborough AK
Ghanimian, Levon
1AC - ICBM 1NC - T Eliminate ICBM Modernization cp Security K v2 2NR - Security K v2
hsld19/Harker/Th/Harker-Thakur-Neg-Harvard%20Westlake-Round6.docx
null
71,626
RoTh
Harker RoTh
null
Ro.....
Th.....
null
null
24,119
Harker
Harker
CA
null
1,027
hsld19
HS LD 2019-20
2,019
ld
hs
1
2,552,301
No extinction
Farquhar 17 –
Farquhar 17 – Sebastian Farquhar, Leader of the Global Priorities Project (GPP) at the Centre for Effective Altruism, et al., “Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance”, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf
The most likely levels of global warming are very unlikely to cause human extinction existential risks of climate change stem from tail risk the low probability of extreme levels of warming and interaction with other sources of risk warming of 11-12°C would render most of the planet uninhabitable the timescales over which such changes might happen could mean humanity is able to adapt to avoid extinction in even very extreme scenarios unless strong action is taken soon by major emitters we will pursue a medium-high emissions pathway if we continue to pursue a medium-high emissions pathway probability of eventual warming of 6°C is around 10% and 10°C is 3% These estimates are highly uncertain. It is likely the world will take action against climate change once it begins to impose large costs long before there is warming of 10°C
most likely levels of warming are very unlikely to cause extinction existential risks stem from tail risk the low probability of extreme warming 12°C would render the planet uninhabitable timescales mean humanity is able to adapt to avoid extinction in even extreme scenarios probability of 6° is 10% and 10° is 3% These are highly uncertain It is likely the world will take action once it begins to impose costs long before 10°
The most likely levels of global warming are very unlikely to cause human extinction.15 The existential risks of climate change instead stem from tail risk climate change – the low probability of extreme levels of warming – and interaction with other sources of risk. It is impossible to say with confidence at what point global warming would become severe enough to pose an existential threat. Research has suggested that warming of 11-12°C would render most of the planet uninhabitable,16 and would completely devastate agriculture.17 This would pose an extreme threat to human civilisation as we know it.18 Warming of around 7°C or more could potentially produce conflict and instability on such a scale that the indirect effects could be an existential risk, although it is extremely uncertain how likely such scenarios are.19 Moreover, the timescales over which such changes might happen could mean that humanity is able to adapt enough to avoid extinction in even very extreme scenarios. The probability of these levels of warming depends on eventual greenhouse gas concentrations. According to some experts, unless strong action is taken soon by major emitters, it is likely that we will pursue a medium-high emissions pathway.20 If we do, the chance of extreme warming is highly uncertain but appears non-negligible. Current concentrations of greenhouse gases are higher than they have been for hundreds of thousands of years,21 which means that there are significant unknown unknowns about how the climate system will respond. Particularly concerning is the risk of positive feedback loops, such as the release of vast amounts of methane from melting of the arctic permafrost, which would cause rapid and disastrous warming.22 The economists Gernot Wagner and Martin Weitzman have used IPCC figures (which do not include modelling of feedback loops such as those from melting permafrost) to estimate that if we continue to pursue a medium-high emissions pathway, the probability of eventual warming of 6°C is around 10%,23 and of 10°C is around 3%.24 These estimates are of course highly uncertain. It is likely that the world will take action against climate change once it begins to impose large costs on human society, long before there is warming of 10°C. Unfortunately, there is significant inertia in the climate system: there is a 25 to 50 year lag between CO2 emissions and eventual warming,25 and it is expected that 40% of the peak concentration of CO2 will remain in the atmosphere 1,000 years after the peak is reached.26 Consequently, it is impossible to reduce temperatures quickly by reducing CO2 emissions. If the world does start to face costly warming, the international community will therefore face strong incentives to find other ways to reduce global temperatures.
2,795
<h4>No extinction</h4><p><strong>Farquhar 17 –</strong> Sebastian Farquhar, Leader of the Global Priorities Project (GPP) at the Centre for Effective Altruism, et al., “Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance”, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf</p><p><u>The <strong><mark>most likely</strong> levels of</mark> global <mark>warming are <strong>very unlikely to cause</mark> human <mark>extinction</u></strong></mark>.15 The <u><mark>existential risks</mark> of climate change</u> instead <u><mark>stem from tail risk</u></mark> climate change – <u><mark>the <strong>low probability</strong> of extreme</mark> levels of <mark>warming</u></mark> – <u>and interaction with other sources of risk</u>. It is impossible to say with confidence at what point global warming would become severe enough to pose an existential threat. Research has suggested that <u><strong>warming of 11-<mark>12°C</strong> would render</mark> most of <mark>the planet uninhabitable</u></mark>,16 and would completely devastate agriculture.17 This would pose an extreme threat to human civilisation as we know it.18 Warming of around 7°C or more could potentially produce conflict and instability on such a scale that the indirect effects could be an existential risk, although it is extremely uncertain how likely such scenarios are.19 Moreover, <u>the <mark>timescales</mark> over which such changes might happen could <mark>mean</u></mark> that <u><strong><mark>humanity is able to adapt</u></strong></mark> enough <u><mark>to avoid extinction in <strong>even</mark> very <mark>extreme scenarios</u></strong></mark>.</p><p>The probability of these levels of warming depends on eventual greenhouse gas concentrations. According to some experts, <u>unless strong action is taken soon by major emitters</u>, it is likely that <u>we will pursue a medium-high emissions pathway</u>.20 If we do, the chance of extreme warming is highly uncertain but appears non-negligible. Current concentrations of greenhouse gases are higher than they have been for hundreds of thousands of years,21 which means that there are significant unknown unknowns about how the climate system will respond. Particularly concerning is the risk of positive feedback loops, such as the release of vast amounts of methane from melting of the arctic permafrost, which would cause rapid and disastrous warming.22 The economists Gernot Wagner and Martin Weitzman have used IPCC figures (which do not include modelling of feedback loops such as those from melting permafrost) to estimate that <u>if we continue to pursue a medium-high emissions pathway</u>, the <u><mark>probability of</mark> eventual warming of <mark>6°</mark>C <mark>is</mark> around <strong><mark>10%</u></strong></mark>,23 <u><mark>and</u></mark> of <u><mark>10°</mark>C <mark>is</u></mark> around <u><strong><mark>3%</u></strong></mark>.24 <u><mark>These</mark> estimates <mark>are</u></mark> of course <u><strong><mark>highly uncertain</strong></mark>.</p><p><mark>It is <strong>likely</u></strong></mark> that <u><mark>the world will take action</mark> against climate change <mark>once it begins to impose</mark> large <mark>costs</p><p></u></mark> on human society, <u><strong><mark>long before</mark> there is warming of <mark>10°</mark>C</u></strong>. Unfortunately, there is significant inertia in the climate system: there is a 25 to 50 year lag between CO2 emissions and eventual warming,25 and it is expected that 40% of the peak concentration of CO2 will remain in the atmosphere 1,000 years after the peak is reached.26 Consequently, it is impossible to reduce temperatures quickly by reducing CO2 emissions. If the world does start to face costly warming, the international community will therefore face strong incentives to find other ways to reduce global temperatures. </p>
Case
Adv 2
H3-Warming
18,673
1,614
82,224
./documents/ndtceda19/MichiganState/ScPe/Michigan%20State-Scullion-Pepper-Neg-Texas-Round7.docx
613,708
N
Texas
7
NYU BS
Armands Revelins
1AC -Mining 1NC -T STM -Xi DA -India CP -Jackson K -JP DA 2NR -Xi DA
ndtceda19/MichiganState/ScPe/Michigan%20State-Scullion-Pepper-Neg-Texas-Round7.docx
null
51,952
ScPe
Michigan State ScPe
null
Ja.....
Sc.....
La.....
Pe.....
19,271
MichiganState
Michigan State
null
null
1,009
ndtceda19
NDT/CEDA 2019-20
2,019
cx
college
2
3,194,547
Extinction is a distinct phenomenon that requires prior consideration
Burke et al 16, Associate Professor of International and Political Studies @ UNSW, Australia, Stefanie Fishel is Assistant Professor, Department of Gender and Race Studies at the University of Alabama, Audra Mitchell is CIGI Chair in Global Governance and Ethics at the Balsillie School of International Affairs, Simon Dalby is CIGI Chair in the Political Economy of Climate Change at the Balsillie School of International Affairs, and, Daniel J. Levine is Assistant Professor of Political Science at the University of Alabama, “Planet Politics: Manifesto from the End of IR,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 1–25
Anthony Burke et al 16, Associate Professor of International and Political Studies @ UNSW, Australia, Stefanie Fishel is Assistant Professor, Department of Gender and Race Studies at the University of Alabama, Audra Mitchell is CIGI Chair in Global Governance and Ethics at the Balsillie School of International Affairs, Simon Dalby is CIGI Chair in the Political Economy of Climate Change at the Balsillie School of International Affairs, and, Daniel J. Levine is Assistant Professor of Political Science at the University of Alabama, “Planet Politics: Manifesto from the End of IR,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 1–25
Global ethics must respond to mass extinction for three decades, conservation biologists have been warning of a ‘sixth mass extinction’, which, by definition, could eliminate more than three quarters of currently existing life forms in just a few centuries it could threaten the practical possibility of the survival of earthly life. Mass extinction is not simply extinction (or death) writ large it is a qualitatively different phenomena that demands its own ethical categories. It cannot be grasped by aggregating species extinctions, Not only does it erase diverse, irreplaceable life forms their unique histories and open-ended possibilities, but it threatens the ontological conditions of Earthly life. Cold-War era concepts such as ‘nuclear winter’ and ‘omnicide’ gesture towards harms massive in their scale and moral horror they are asymptotic: they imagine nightmares of a severely denuded planet, yet they do not contemplate the comprehensive negation that a mass extinction event entails. this approach fails to recognise the reality of extinction, which is a matter of being and nonbeing, not one of life and death processes. Confronting the enormity of a possible mass extinction event requires a total overhaul of human perceptions of what is at stake in the disruption of the conditions of Earthly life. The question of what is ‘lost’ in extinction has been addressed in terms of financial cost Yet the enormity, complexity, and scale of mass extinction is so huge that humans need to draw on every possible resource in order to find ways of responding. it is crucial and urgent to realise that extinction is a matter of global ethics It is not simply an issue of management or security, or even of particular visions of the good life Instead, it is about staking a claim as to the goodness of life itself. If it does not fit within the existing parameters of global ethics, then it is these boundaries that need to change we can and should reframe it as authors like Karen Barad ‘entanglement’ is a radical, indeed fundamental condition of being-with, This means that no being is truly autonomous or separate, whether at the scale of international politics or of quantum physics. World emerges from the poetics of existence, the collision of energy and matter, the tumult of agencies, the fusion and diffusion of bonds. Worlds erupt from, and consist in, the intersection of diverse forms of being Because of the tumultuousness of the Earth with which they are entangled, worlds’ are not static, rigid or permanent. They are permeable and fluid They can be created, modified – and, of course, destroyed. Concepts of violence, harm and (in)security that focus only on humans ignore at their peril the destruction and severance of worlds, which undermines the conditions of plurality that enables life on Earth to thrive.
Mass extinction is a qualitatively different phenomena that demands its own ethical categories Not only does it erase life their histories and possibilities, but it threatens the ontological conditions they imagine a denuded planet not the comprehensive negation mass extinction entails this fails to recognise the reality which is a matter of being and nonbeing, not one of life and death Worlds erupt from the intersection of diverse forms of being Concepts of violence that focus only on humans ignore the destruction which undermines the conditions of plurality that enables life to thrive
8. Global ethics must respond to mass extinction. In late 2014, the Worldwide Fund for Nature reported a startling statistic: according to their global study, 52% of species had gone extinct between 1970 and 2010.60 This is not news: for three decades, conservation biologists have been warning of a ‘sixth mass extinction’, which, by definition, could eliminate more than three quarters of currently existing life forms in just a few centuries.61 In other words, it could threaten the practical possibility of the survival of earthly life. Mass extinction is not simply extinction (or death) writ large: it is a qualitatively different phenomena that demands its own ethical categories. It cannot be grasped by aggregating species extinctions, let alone the deaths of individual organisms. Not only does it erase diverse, irreplaceable life forms, their unique histories and open-ended possibilities, but it threatens the ontological conditions of Earthly life.¶ IR is one of few disciplines that is explicitly devoted to the pursuit of survival, yet it has almost nothing to say in the face of a possible mass extinction event.62 It utterly lacks the conceptual and ethical frameworks necessary to foster diverse, meaningful responses to this phenomenon. As mentioned above, Cold-War era concepts such as ‘nuclear winter’ and ‘omnicide’ gesture towards harms massive in their scale and moral horror. However, they are asymptotic: they imagine nightmares of a severely denuded planet, yet they do not contemplate the comprehensive negation that a mass extinction event entails. In contemporary IR discourses, where it appears at all, extinction is treated as a problem of scientific management and biopolitical control aimed at securing existing human lifestyles.63 Once again, this approach fails to recognise the reality of extinction, which is a matter of being and nonbeing, not one of life and death processes.¶ Confronting the enormity of a possible mass extinction event requires a total overhaul of human perceptions of what is at stake in the disruption of the conditions of Earthly life. The question of what is ‘lost’ in extinction has, since the inception of the concept of ‘conservation’, been addressed in terms of financial cost and economic liabilities.64 Beyond reducing life to forms to capital, currencies and financial instruments, the dominant neoliberal political economy of conservation imposes a homogenising, Western secular worldview on a planetary phenomenon. Yet the enormity, complexity, and scale of mass extinction is so huge that humans need to draw on every possible resource in order to find ways of responding. This means that they need to mobilise multiple worldviews and lifeways – including those emerging from indigenous and marginalised cosmologies. Above all, it is crucial and urgent to realise that extinction is a matter of global ethics. It is not simply an issue of management or security, or even of particular visions of the good life. Instead, it is about staking a claim as to the goodness of life itself. If it does not fit within the existing parameters of global ethics, then it is these boundaries that need to change.¶ 9. An Earth-worldly politics. Humans are worldly – that is, we are fundamentally worldforming and embedded in multiple worlds that traverse the Earth. However, the Earth is not ‘our’ world, as the grand theories of IR, and some accounts of the Anthropocene have it – an object and possession to be appropriated, circumnavigated, instrumentalised and englobed.65 Rather, it is a complex of worlds that we share, co-constitute, create, destroy and inhabit with countless other life forms and beings.¶ The formation of the Anthropocene reflects a particular type of worlding, one in which the Earth is treated as raw material for the creation of a world tailored to human needs. Heidegger famously framed ‘earth’ and ‘world’ as two countervailing, conflicting forces that constrain and shape one another. We contend that existing political, economic and social conditions have pushed human worlding so far to one extreme that it has become almost entirely detached from the conditions of the Earth. Planet Politics calls, instead, for a mode of worlding that is responsive to, and grounded in, the Earth. One of these ways of being Earth-worldly is to embrace the condition of being entangled. We can interpret this term in the way that Heidegger66 did, as the condition of being mired in everyday human concerns, worries, and anxiety, to prolong existence. But, in contrast, we can and should reframe it as authors like Karen Barad67 and Donna Haraway68 have done. To them and many others, ‘entanglement’ is a radical, indeed fundamental condition of being-with, or, as Jean-Luc Nancy puts it, ‘being singular plural’.69 This means that no being is truly autonomous or separate, whether at the scale of international politics or of quantum physics. World itself is singular plural: what humans tend to refer to as ‘the’ world is actually a multiplicity of worlds at various scales that intersect, overlap, conflict, emerge as they surge across the Earth. World emerges from the poetics of existence, the collision of energy and matter, the tumult of agencies, the fusion and diffusion of bonds.¶ Worlds erupt from, and consist in, the intersection of diverse forms of being – material and intangible, organic and inorganic, ‘living’ and ‘nonliving’. Because of the tumultuousness of the Earth with which they are entangled, ‘worlds’ are not static, rigid or permanent. They are permeable and fluid. They can be created, modified – and, of course, destroyed. Concepts of violence, harm and (in)security that focus only on humans ignore at their peril the destruction and severance of worlds,70 which undermines the conditions of plurality that enables life on Earth to thrive.
5,848
<h4><strong>Extinction is a distinct phenomenon that requires prior consideration </h4><p></strong>Anthony<strong> Burke et al 16<u>, Associate Professor of International and Political Studies @ UNSW, Australia, Stefanie Fishel is Assistant Professor, Department of Gender and Race Studies at the University of Alabama, Audra Mitchell is CIGI Chair in Global Governance and Ethics at the Balsillie School of International Affairs, Simon Dalby is CIGI Chair in the Political Economy of Climate Change at the Balsillie School of International Affairs, and, Daniel J. Levine is Assistant Professor of Political Science at the University of Alabama, “Planet Politics: Manifesto from the End of IR,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 1–25</p><p></u></strong>8. <u>Global ethics must respond to mass extinction</u>. In late 2014, the Worldwide Fund for Nature reported a startling statistic: according to their global study, 52% of species had gone extinct between 1970 and 2010.60 This is not news: <u>for three decades, conservation biologists have been warning of a ‘sixth mass extinction’, which, by definition, could eliminate more than three quarters of currently existing life forms in just a few centuries</u>.61 In other words, <u>it could threaten the practical possibility of the survival of earthly life. <mark>Mass extinction</mark> is not simply extinction (or death) writ large</u>: <u><strong>it <mark>is a qualitatively different phenomena that demands its own ethical categories</mark>.</u></strong> <u>It cannot be grasped by aggregating species extinctions,</u> let alone the deaths of individual organisms. <u><mark>Not only does it erase</mark> diverse, irreplaceable <mark>life</mark> forms</u>, <u><mark>their</mark> <strong>unique <mark>histories</strong> and</mark> <strong>open-ended <mark>possibilities</strong>, but it <strong>threatens the ontological conditions </mark>of Earthly life</strong>.</u>¶<u> </u>IR is one of few disciplines that is explicitly devoted to the pursuit of survival, yet it has almost nothing to say in the face of a possible mass extinction event.62 It utterly lacks the conceptual and ethical frameworks necessary to foster diverse, meaningful responses to this phenomenon. As mentioned above, <u>Cold-War era concepts such as ‘nuclear winter’ and ‘omnicide’ gesture towards harms massive in their scale and moral horror</u>. However, <u>they are asymptotic: <mark>they imagine</mark> nightmares of <mark>a</mark> severely <mark>denuded planet</mark>, yet they do <mark>not</mark> contemplate <mark>the <strong>comprehensive negation</strong></mark> that a <mark>mass extinction</mark> event <mark>entails</mark>.</u> In contemporary IR discourses, where it appears at all, extinction is treated as a problem of scientific management and biopolitical control aimed at securing existing human lifestyles.63 Once again, <u><mark>this</mark> approach <mark>fails to recognise the reality</mark> of extinction, <mark>which is a <strong>matter of being and nonbeing</strong>, not one of life and death</mark> processes.</u>¶<u> Confronting the enormity of a possible mass extinction event requires a total overhaul of human perceptions of what is at stake in the disruption of the conditions of Earthly life. The question of what is ‘lost’ in extinction has</u>, since the inception of the concept of ‘conservation’, <u>been addressed in terms of financial cost</u> and economic liabilities.64 Beyond reducing life to forms to capital, currencies and financial instruments, the dominant neoliberal political economy of conservation imposes a homogenising, Western secular worldview on a planetary phenomenon. <u>Yet the <strong>enormity, complexity, and scale</strong> of mass extinction is so huge that humans need to <strong>draw on every possible resource in order to find ways of responding</strong>.</u> This means that they need to mobilise multiple worldviews and lifeways – including those emerging from indigenous and marginalised cosmologies. Above all, <u>it is crucial and urgent to realise that extinction is a <strong>matter of global ethics</u></strong>. <u>It is not simply an issue of management or security, or even of particular visions of the good life</u>. <u>Instead, it is about staking a claim as to the goodness of life itself. If it does not fit within the existing parameters of global ethics, then it is these boundaries that need to change</u>.¶ 9. An Earth-worldly politics. Humans are worldly – that is, we are fundamentally worldforming and embedded in multiple worlds that traverse the Earth. However, the Earth is not ‘our’ world, as the grand theories of IR, and some accounts of the Anthropocene have it – an object and possession to be appropriated, circumnavigated, instrumentalised and englobed.65 Rather, it is a complex of worlds that we share, co-constitute, create, destroy and inhabit with countless other life forms and beings.¶ The formation of the Anthropocene reflects a particular type of worlding, one in which the Earth is treated as raw material for the creation of a world tailored to human needs. Heidegger famously framed ‘earth’ and ‘world’ as two countervailing, conflicting forces that constrain and shape one another. We contend that existing political, economic and social conditions have pushed human worlding so far to one extreme that it has become almost entirely detached from the conditions of the Earth. Planet Politics calls, instead, for a mode of worlding that is responsive to, and grounded in, the Earth. One of these ways of being Earth-worldly is to embrace the condition of being entangled. We can interpret this term in the way that Heidegger66 did, as the condition of being mired in everyday human concerns, worries, and anxiety, to prolong existence. But, in contrast, <u>we can and should reframe it as authors like Karen Barad</u>67 and Donna Haraway68 have done. To them and many others, <u>‘entanglement’ is a radical, indeed fundamental condition of being-with,</u> or, as Jean-Luc Nancy puts it, ‘being singular plural’.69 <u>This means that no being is truly autonomous or separate, whether at the scale of international politics or of quantum physics. </u>World itself is singular plural: what humans tend to refer to as ‘the’ world is actually a multiplicity of worlds at various scales that intersect, overlap, conflict, emerge as they surge across the Earth. <u>World emerges from the poetics of existence, the collision of energy and matter, the tumult of agencies, the fusion and diffusion of bonds.</u>¶<u> <mark>Worlds erupt from</mark>, and consist in, <mark>the intersection of <strong>diverse forms of being</u></strong></mark> – material and intangible, organic and inorganic, ‘living’ and ‘nonliving’. <u>Because of the tumultuousness of the Earth with which they are entangled,</u> ‘<u><strong>worlds’ are not static, rigid or permanent. They are permeable and fluid</u></strong>. <u>They can be <strong>created</strong>, <strong>modified</u></strong> <u>– and, of course, destroyed. <mark>Concepts of violence</mark>, harm and (in)security <mark>that focus only on humans ignore</mark> at their peril <mark>the destruction</mark> and severance of worlds,</u>70 <u><strong><mark>which undermines the conditions of plurality that enables life</mark> on Earth <mark>to thrive</mark>.</p></u></strong>
1NR
Flex
A2 Structural Violence First
25,007
1,010
103,689
./documents/ndtceda18/WakeForest/ToMa/Wake%20Forest-Tomasi-Marban-Neg-Northwestern-Round1.docx
609,180
N
Northwestern
1
Army KT
Isak Dunn
1AC--End 702 through courts political trust and black cultural agency 2NR--roberts DA advantage CP (kicked ESR plank) case
ndtceda18/WakeForest/ToMa/Wake%20Forest-Tomasi-Marban-Neg-Northwestern-Round1.docx
null
51,621
ToMa
Wake Forest ToMa
null
Ad.....
To.....
Al.....
Ma.....
19,225
WakeForest
Wake Forest
null
null
1,008
ndtceda18
NDT/CEDA 2018-19
2,018
cx
college
2
3,343,178
Substitutability—only consequentialism explains necessary enablers.
Sinnott-Armstrong 92
Sinnott-Armstrong 92 [Walter, professor of practical ethics. “An Argument for Consequentialism” Dartmouth College Philosophical Perspectives. 1992.]
. A moral reason to do an act is consequential if and only if the reason depends only on the consequences of either doing the act or not doing the act. a moral reason is non-consequential if the reason depends even partly on some property that the act has independently of its consequences. For example, an act can be a lie regardless of what happens as a result of the lie a moral theory is consequentialist if and only if it implies that all basic moral reasons are consequential. A moral theory is then non-consequentialist or deontological if it includes any basic moral reasons which are not consequential if I promise to mow the grass, there is a moral reason for me to mow the grass, and this moral reason is constituted by the fact that mowing the grass fulfills my promise. However if I cannot mow the grass without starting my mower, and starting the mower would enable me to mow the grass, it still would not follow that I have any moral reason to start my mower, since I did not promise to start my mower a moral theory cannot explain substitutability if it claims that properties provide moral reasons.
A moral reason is consequential if the reason depends on the consequences a moral reason is non-consequential if the reason depends on some property that the act has if I promise to mow the grass, there is a moral reason for me to mow constituted by my promise. However if I cannot mow the grass without starting my mower it still would not follow that I have any reason to start my mower a moral theory cannot explain substitutability if it claims that properties provide moral reasons.
-if to do a moral action X, we need to do action Y, and Y will cause X, then we have a moral reason to do Y. Sinnot-Armstrong explains why deont fails this based on nature of actions and why util uniquely can pass along the moral reasoning. A moral reason to do an act is consequential if and only if the reason depends only on the consequences of either doing the act or not doing the act. For example, a moral reason not to hit someone is that this will hurt her or him. A moral reason to turn your car to the left might be that, if you do not do so, you will run over and kill someone. A moral reason to feed a starving child is that the child will lose important mental or physical abilities if you do not feed it. All such reasons are consequential reasons. All other moral reasons are non-consequential. Thus, a moral reason to do an act is non-consequential if and only if the reason depends even partly on some property that the act has independently of its consequences. For example, an act can be a lie regardless of what happens as a result of the lie (since some lies are not believed), and some moral theories claim that that property of being a lie provides amoral reason not to tell a lie regardless of the consequences of this lie. Similarly, the fact that an act fulfills a promise is often seen as a moral reason to do the act, even though the act has that property of fulfilling a promise independently ofits consequences. All such moral reasons are non-consequential. In order to avoid so many negations, I will also call them 'deontological'. This distinction would not make sense if we did not restrict the notion of consequences. If I promise to mow the lawn, then one consequence of my mowing might seem to be that my promise is fulfilled. One way to avoid this problem is to specify that the consequences of an act must be distinct from the act itself. My act of fulfilling my promise and my act of mowing are not distinct, because they are done by the same bodily movements.10 Thus, my fulfilling my promise is not a consequence of my mowing. A consequence of an act need not be later in time than the act, since causation can be simultaneous, but the consequence must at least be different from the act. Even with this clarification, it is still hard to classify some moral reasons as consequential or deontological,11 but I will stick to examples that are clear. In accordance with this distinction between kinds of moral reasons, I can now distinguish different kinds of moral theories. I will say that a moral theory is consequentialist if and only if it implies that all basic moral reasons are consequential. A moral theory is then non-consequentialist or deontological if it includes any basic moral reasons which are not consequential. 5. Against Deontology So defined, the class of deontological moral theories is very large and diverse. This makes it hard to say anything in general about it. Nonetheless, I will argue that no deontological moral theory can explain why moral substitutability holds. My argument applies to all deontological theories because it depends only on what is common to them all, namely, the claim that some basic moral reasons are not consequential. Some deontological theories allow very many weighty moral reasons that are consequential, and these theories might be able to explain why moral substitutability holds for some of their moral reasons: the consequential ones. But even these theories cannot explain why moral substitutability holds for all moral reasons, including the non-consequential reasons that make the theory deontological. The failure of deontological moral theories to explain moral substitutability in the very cases that make them deontological is a reason to reject all deontological moral theories. I cannot discuss every deontological moral theory, so I will discuss only a few paradigm examples and show why they cannot explain moral substitutability. After this, I will argue that similar problems are bound to arise for all other deontological theories by their very nature. The simplest deontological theory is the pluralistic intuitionism of Prichard and Ross. Ross writes that, when someone promises to do something, 'This we consider obligatory in its own nature, just because it is a fulfillment of a promise, and not because of its consequences.'12 Such deontologists claim in effect that, if I promise to mow the grass, there is a moral reason for me to mow the grass, and this moral reason is constituted by the fact that mowing the grass fulfills my promise. This reason exists regardless of the consequences of mowing the grass, even though it might be overridden by certain bad consequences. However, if this is why I have a moral reason to mow the grass, then, even if I cannot mow the grass without starting my mower, and starting the mower would enable me to mow the grass, it still would not follow that I have any moral reason to start my mower, since I did not promise to start my mower, and starting my mower does not fulfill my promise. Thus, a moral theory cannot explain moral substitutability if it claims that properties like this provide moral reasons.
5,169
<h4>Substitutability—only consequentialism explains necessary enablers. </h4><p><u><strong>Sinnott-Armstrong 92</u></strong> [Walter, professor of practical ethics. “An Argument for Consequentialism” Dartmouth College Philosophical Perspectives. 1992.] </p><p>-if to do a moral action X, we need to do action Y, and Y will cause X, then we have a moral reason to do Y. Sinnot-Armstrong explains why deont fails this based on nature of actions and why util uniquely can pass along the moral reasoning<u><strong>.</p><p><mark>A moral reason</mark> to do an act <mark>is consequential if</mark> and only if <mark>the reason depends</mark> only <mark>on the consequences</mark> of either doing the act or not doing the act.</u></strong> For example, a moral reason not to hit someone is that this will hurt her or him. A moral reason to turn your car to the left might be that, if you do not do so, you will run over and kill someone. A moral reason to feed a starving child is that the child will lose important mental or physical abilities if you do not feed it. All such reasons are consequential reasons. All other moral reasons are non-consequential. Thus, <u><strong><mark>a moral reason</u></strong></mark> to do an act<mark> <u><strong>is non-consequential if</mark> </u></strong>and only if<u><strong> <mark>the reason depends</mark> even partly <mark>on some property that the act has</mark> independently of its consequences. For example, an act can be a lie regardless of what happens as a result of the lie </u></strong>(since some lies are not believed), and some moral theories claim that that property of being a lie provides amoral reason not to tell a lie regardless of the consequences of this lie. Similarly, the fact that an act fulfills a promise is often seen as a moral reason to do the act, even though the act has that property of fulfilling a promise independently ofits consequences. All such moral reasons are non-consequential. In order to avoid so many negations, I will also call them 'deontological'. This distinction would not make sense if we did not restrict the notion of consequences. If I promise to mow the lawn, then one consequence of my mowing might seem to be that my promise is fulfilled. One way to avoid this problem is to specify that the consequences of an act must be distinct from the act itself. My act of fulfilling my promise and my act of mowing are not distinct, because they are done by the same bodily movements.10 Thus, my fulfilling my promise is not a consequence of my mowing. A consequence of an act need not be later in time than the act, since causation can be simultaneous, but the consequence must at least be different from the act. Even with this clarification, it is still hard to classify some moral reasons as consequential or deontological,11 but I will stick to examples that are clear. In accordance with this distinction between kinds of moral reasons, I can now distinguish different kinds of moral theories. I will say that<u><strong> a moral theory is consequentialist if and only if it implies that all basic moral reasons are consequential. A moral theory is then non-consequentialist or deontological if it includes any basic moral reasons which are not consequential</u></strong>. 5. Against Deontology So defined, the class of deontological moral theories is very large and diverse. This makes it hard to say anything in general about it. Nonetheless, I will argue that no deontological moral theory can explain why moral substitutability holds. My argument applies to all deontological theories because it depends only on what is common to them all, namely, the claim that some basic moral reasons are not consequential. Some deontological theories allow very many weighty moral reasons that are consequential, and these theories might be able to explain why moral substitutability holds for some of their moral reasons: the consequential ones. But even these theories cannot explain why moral substitutability holds for all moral reasons, including the non-consequential reasons that make the theory deontological. The failure of deontological moral theories to explain moral substitutability in the very cases that make them deontological is a reason to reject all deontological moral theories. I cannot discuss every deontological moral theory, so I will discuss only a few paradigm examples and show why they cannot explain moral substitutability. After this, I will argue that similar problems are bound to arise for all other deontological theories by their very nature. The simplest deontological theory is the pluralistic intuitionism of Prichard and Ross. Ross writes that, when someone promises to do something, 'This we consider obligatory in its own nature, just because it is a fulfillment of a promise, and not because of its consequences.'12 Such deontologists claim in effect that, <u><strong><mark>if I promise to mow the grass, there is a moral reason for me to mow</mark> the grass, and this moral reason is <mark>constituted by</mark> the fact that mowing the grass fulfills <mark>my promise.</mark> </u></strong>This reason exists regardless of the consequences of mowing the grass, even though it might be overridden by certain bad consequences. <u><strong><mark>However</u></strong></mark>, if this is why I have a moral reason to mow the grass, then, even <u><strong><mark>if I cannot mow the grass without starting my mower</mark>, and starting the mower would enable me to mow the grass, <mark>it still would not follow that I have any</mark> moral <mark>reason to start my mower</mark>, since I did not promise to start my mower</u></strong>, and starting my mower does not fulfill my promise. Thus, <u><strong><mark>a moral theory cannot explain</mark> </u></strong>moral<u><strong> <mark>substitutability if it claims that properties</u></strong></mark> like this<u><strong> <mark>provide moral reasons.</p></u></strong></mark>
null
null
Framework
151,894
541
110,729
./documents/hsld18/NewTrier/To/New%20Trier-Tolan-Aff-Blake-Round5.docx
826,824
A
Blake
5
Cypress Bay HL
Chad Meadows
1AC- Egypt 1NC - T DA 2NR - T
hsld18/NewTrier/To/New%20Trier-Tolan-Aff-Blake-Round5.docx
null
70,738
PaTo
New Trier PaTo
null
Pa.....
To.....
null
null
23,836
NewTrier
New Trier
null
null
1,026
hsld18
HS LD 2018-19
2,018
ld
hs
1
1,452,747
Methodological pluralism is a necessary aspect of critique.
Bleiker ’14
Bleiker ’14 (Roland, professor of international relations at the University of Queensland. “International Theory between Reification and Self-Reflective Critique” International Studies Review, Volume 16, Issue 2. June 17, 2014.)
Upholding one subjective position without critical scrutiny can have far-reaching consequences Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of sustainable critique multiple methods to understand the same event or phenomena a scholar oscillates between different methods No single method can gain the upper hand. each should recognize and capture perspectives that the others cannot this means combining methods precisely when they are deemed incompatible.
Upholding one subjective position without critical scrutiny can have far-reaching consequences Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of sustainable critique multiple methods to understand the same event or phenomena a scholar oscillates between different methods No single method can gain the upper hand. each should recognize and capture perspectives that the others cannot this means combining methods precisely when they are deemed incompatible.
This book is part of an increasing trend of scholarly works that have embraced poststructural critique but want to ground it in more positive political foundations, while retaining a reluctance to return to the positivist tendencies that implicitly underpin much of constructivist research. The path that Daniel Levine has carved out is innovative, sophisticated, and convincing. A superb scholarly achievement. For Levine, the key challenge in international relations (IR) scholarship is what he calls “unchecked reification”: the widespread and dangerous process of forgetting “the distinction between theoretical concepts and the real-world things they mean to describe or to which they refer” (p. 15). The dangers are real, Levine stresses, because IR deals with some of the most difficult issues, from genocides to war. Upholding one subjective position without critical scrutiny can thus have far-reaching consequences. Following Theodor Adorno—who is the key theoretical influence on this book—Levine takes a post-positive position and assumes that the world cannot be known outside of our human perceptions and the values that are inevitably intertwined with them. His ultimate goal is to overcome reification, or, to be more precise, to recognize it as an inevitable aspect of thought so that its dangerous consequences can be mitigated. Levine proceeds in three stages: First he reviews several decades of IR theories to resurrect critical moments when scholars displayed an acute awareness of the dangers of reification. He refreshingly breaks down distinctions between conventional and progressive scholarship, for he detects self-reflective and critical moments in scholars that are usually associated with straightforward positivist positions (such as E.H. Carr, Hans Morgenthau, or Graham Allison). But Levine also shows how these moments of self-reflexivity never lasted long and were driven out by the compulsion to offer systematic and scientific knowledge. The second stage of Levine's inquiry outlines why IR scholars regularly closed down critique. Here, he points to a range of factors and phenomena, from peer review processes to the speed at which academics are meant to publish. And here too, he eschews conventional wisdom, showing that work conducted in the wake of the third debate, while explicitly post-positivist and critiquing the reifying tendencies of existing IR scholarship, often lacked critical self-awareness. As a result, Levine believes that many of the respective authors failed to appreciate sufficiently that “reification is a consequence of all thinking—including itself” (p. 68). The third objective of Levine's book is also the most interesting one. Here, he outlines the path toward what he calls “sustainable critique”: a form of self-reflection that can counter the dangers of reification. Critique, for him, is not just something that is directed outwards, against particular theories or theorists. It is also inward-oriented, ongoing, and sensitive to the “limitations of thought itself” (p. 12). The challenges that such a sustainable critique faces are formidable. Two stand out: First, if the natural tendency to forget the origins and values of our concepts are as strong as Levine and other Adorno-inspired theorists believe they are, then how can we actually recognize our own reifying tendencies? Are we not all inevitably and subconsciously caught in a web of meanings from which we cannot escape? Second, if one constantly questions one's own perspective, does one not fall into a relativism that loses the ability to establish the kind of stable foundations that are necessary for political action? Adorno has, of course, been critiqued as relentlessly negative, even by his second-generation Frankfurt School successors (from Jürgen Habermas to his IR interpreters, such as Andrew Linklater and Ken Booth). The response that Levine has to these two sets of legitimate criticisms are, in my view, both convincing and useful at a practical level. He starts off with depicting reification not as a flaw that is meant to be expunged, but as an a priori condition for scholarship. The challenge then is not to let it go unchecked. Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of Levine's sustainable critique. He borrows from what Adorno calls a “constellation”: an attempt to juxtapose, rather than integrate, different perspectives. It is in this spirit that Levine advocates multiple methods to understand the same event or phenomena. He writes of the need to validate “multiple and mutually incompatible ways of seeing” (p. 63, see also pp. 101–102). In this model, a scholar oscillates back and forth between different methods and paradigms, trying to understand the event in question from multiple perspectives. No single method can ever adequately represent the event or should gain the upper hand. But each should, in a way, recognize and capture details or perspectives that the others cannot (p. 102). In practical terms, this means combining a range of methods even when—or, rather, precisely when—they are deemed incompatible. They can range from poststructual deconstruction to the tools pioneered and championed by positivist social sciences. The benefit of such a methodological polyphony is not just the opportunity to bring out nuances and new perspectives. Once the false hope of a smooth synthesis has been abandoned, the very incompatibility of the respective perspectives can then be used to identify the reifying tendencies in each of them. For Levine, this is how reification may be “checked at the source” and this is how a “critically reflexive moment might thus be rendered sustainable” (p. 103). It is in this sense that Levine's approach is not really post-foundational but, rather, an attempt to “balance foundationalisms against one another” (p. 14). There are strong parallels here with arguments advanced by assemblage thinking and complexity theory—links that could have been explored in more detail.
5,989
<h4>Methodological pluralism is a necessary aspect of critique.</h4><p><strong>Bleiker ’14</strong> (Roland, professor of international relations at the University of Queensland. “International Theory between Reification and Self-Reflective Critique” International Studies Review, Volume 16, Issue 2. June 17, 2014.)</p><p>This book is part of an increasing trend of scholarly works that have embraced poststructural critique but want to ground it in more positive political foundations, while retaining a reluctance to return to the positivist tendencies that implicitly underpin much of constructivist research. The path that Daniel Levine has carved out is innovative, sophisticated, and convincing. A superb scholarly achievement. For Levine, the key challenge in international relations (IR) scholarship is what he calls “unchecked reification”: the widespread and dangerous process of forgetting “the distinction between theoretical concepts and the real-world things they mean to describe or to which they refer” (p. 15). The dangers are real, Levine stresses, because IR deals with some of the most difficult issues, from genocides to war. <u><strong><mark>Upholding one subjective position without critical scrutiny can</u></strong></mark> thus <u><strong><mark>have far-reaching consequences</u></strong></mark>. Following Theodor Adorno—who is the key theoretical influence on this book—Levine takes a post-positive position and assumes that the world cannot be known outside of our human perceptions and the values that are inevitably intertwined with them. His ultimate goal is to overcome reification, or, to be more precise, to recognize it as an inevitable aspect of thought so that its dangerous consequences can be mitigated. Levine proceeds in three stages: First he reviews several decades of IR theories to resurrect critical moments when scholars displayed an acute awareness of the dangers of reification. He refreshingly breaks down distinctions between conventional and progressive scholarship, for he detects self-reflective and critical moments in scholars that are usually associated with straightforward positivist positions (such as E.H. Carr, Hans Morgenthau, or Graham Allison). But Levine also shows how these moments of self-reflexivity never lasted long and were driven out by the compulsion to offer systematic and scientific knowledge. The second stage of Levine's inquiry outlines why IR scholars regularly closed down critique. Here, he points to a range of factors and phenomena, from peer review processes to the speed at which academics are meant to publish. And here too, he eschews conventional wisdom, showing that work conducted in the wake of the third debate, while explicitly post-positivist and critiquing the reifying tendencies of existing IR scholarship, often lacked critical self-awareness. As a result, Levine believes that many of the respective authors failed to appreciate sufficiently that “reification is a consequence of all thinking—including itself” (p. 68). The third objective of Levine's book is also the most interesting one. Here, he outlines the path toward what he calls “sustainable critique”: a form of self-reflection that can counter the dangers of reification. Critique, for him, is not just something that is directed outwards, against particular theories or theorists. It is also inward-oriented, ongoing, and sensitive to the “limitations of thought itself” (p. 12). The challenges that such a sustainable critique faces are formidable. Two stand out: First, if the natural tendency to forget the origins and values of our concepts are as strong as Levine and other Adorno-inspired theorists believe they are, then how can we actually recognize our own reifying tendencies? Are we not all inevitably and subconsciously caught in a web of meanings from which we cannot escape? Second, if one constantly questions one's own perspective, does one not fall into a relativism that loses the ability to establish the kind of stable foundations that are necessary for political action? Adorno has, of course, been critiqued as relentlessly negative, even by his second-generation Frankfurt School successors (from Jürgen Habermas to his IR interpreters, such as Andrew Linklater and Ken Booth). The response that Levine has to these two sets of legitimate criticisms are, in my view, both convincing and useful at a practical level. He starts off with depicting reification not as a flaw that is meant to be expunged, but as an a priori condition for scholarship. The challenge then is not to let it go unchecked. <u><strong><mark>Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of</u></strong></mark> Levine's <u><strong><mark>sustainable critique</u></strong></mark>. He borrows from what Adorno calls a “constellation”: an attempt to juxtapose, rather than integrate, different perspectives. It is in this spirit that Levine advocates <u><strong><mark>multiple methods to understand the same event or phenomena</u></strong></mark>. He writes of the need to validate “multiple and mutually incompatible ways of seeing” (p. 63, see also pp. 101–102). In this model, <u><strong><mark>a scholar oscillates</u></strong></mark> back and forth <u><strong><mark>between different methods</u></strong></mark> and paradigms, trying to understand the event in question from multiple perspectives. <u><strong><mark>No single method can</u></strong></mark> ever adequately represent the event or should <u><strong><mark>gain the upper hand.</u></strong></mark> But <u><strong><mark>each should</u></strong></mark>, in a way, <u><strong><mark>recognize and capture</u></strong></mark> details or <u><strong><mark>perspectives that the others cannot</u></strong></mark> (p. 102). In practical terms, <u><strong><mark>this means combining</u></strong></mark> a range of <u><strong><mark>methods</u></strong></mark> even when—or, rather, <u><strong><mark>precisely when</u></strong></mark>—<u><strong><mark>they are deemed incompatible.</u></strong></mark> They can range from poststructual deconstruction to the tools pioneered and championed by positivist social sciences. The benefit of such a methodological polyphony is not just the opportunity to bring out nuances and new perspectives. Once the false hope of a smooth synthesis has been abandoned, the very incompatibility of the respective perspectives can then be used to identify the reifying tendencies in each of them. For Levine, this is how reification may be “checked at the source” and this is how a “critically reflexive moment might thus be rendered sustainable” (p. 103). It is in this sense that Levine's approach is not really post-foundational but, rather, an attempt to “balance foundationalisms against one another” (p. 14). There are strong parallels here with arguments advanced by assemblage thinking and complexity theory—links that could have been explored in more detail.</p>
Bronx r3
Case
Framing
10,116
1,568
40,146
./documents/hsld21/LakeHighland/Ag/Lake%20Highland-Agrawal-Neg-Bronx-Round3.docx
891,042
N
Bronx
3
Harrison JP
Pungchai, Passa
1ac - Women's health 1n - util innovation da case 1ar - all 2n - all 2ar - all
hsld21/LakeHighland/Ag/Lake%20Highland-Agrawal-Neg-Bronx-Round3.docx
null
74,875
YaAg
Lake Highland YaAg
null
Ya.....
Ag.....
null
null
25,040
LakeHighland
Lake Highland
FL
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
3,012,718
Proliferation causes nuclear war and terrorism – not just east asia
Kroenig, 15
Kroenig, 15 - Associate Professor and International Relations Field Chair in the Department of Government and School of Foreign Service at Georgetown University (Matthew, The History of Proliferation Optimism: Does It Have a Future? Journal of Strategic Studies, Volume 38, Issue 1-2)
The spread of nuclear weapons poses at least six severe threats to international peace and security including: nuclear war, nuclear terrorism, global and regional instability, constrained US freedom of action, weakened alliances, and further nuclear proliferation. we should be pessimistic about the likely consequences of nuclear proliferation The greatest threat is nuclear war. The more states in possession of nuclear weapons the greater the probability that somewhere, someday, there will be a catastrophic nuclear war. Before reaching a state of MAD new nuclear states go through a transition period in which they lack a secure-second strike capability one or both states might believe that it has an incentive to use nuclear weapons first given its small size and lack of strategic depth, Israel might not be confident that it could absorb a nuclear strike and respond with a devastating counterstrike Iran might eventually be able to build a large and survivable nuclear arsenal, but, when it first crosses the nuclear threshold, Tehran will have a small and vulnerable nuclear force the state with the nuclear advantage might believe it has a splendid first strike capability. In a crisis, Israel might decide to launch a preventive nuclear strike to disarm Iran’s nuclear capabilities. this incentive might be further increased by Israel’s aggressive strategic culture that emphasizes preemptive action. the state with a small and vulnerable might feel use them or lose them pressures in a crisis, Iran might decide to strike first rather than risk having its entire nuclear arsenal destroyed nuclear war could result due to the reciprocal fear of surprise attack one state might start a nuclear war in the belief that war is inevitable and that it would be better to go first than to go second there is still a risk of nuclear war Iran’s theocratic government contains leaders who hold millenarian religious worldviews and could one day ascend to power. We cannot rule out the possibility that, as nuclear weapons continue to spread, some leader somewhere will choose to launch a nuclear war, nuclear-armed states still have conflicts of interest and leaders still seek to coerce nuclear-armed adversaries leaders can make a ‘threat that leaves something to chance’. They can initiate a nuclear crisis By playing these risky games of nuclear brinkmanship, states can increase the risk of nuclear war in an attempt to force a less resolved adversary to back down. crises have not resulted in nuclear war, but many of them have come close When we think about future nuclear crisis dyads with fewer sources of stability than existed during the Cold War, we can see that there is a real risk that a future crisis could result in a devastating nuclear exchange The spread of nuclear weapons also increases the risk of nuclear terrorism Laden declared it a ‘religious duty’ for Al- Qa’eda to acquire nuclear weapons and radical clerics have issued fatwas declaring it permissible to use nuclear weapons in Jihad against the West as nuclear weapons spread, the possibility that they will eventually fall into terrorist hands increases States could intentionally transfer nuclear weapons to terrorist groups a new nuclear state, with underdeveloped security procedures, might be vulnerable to theft, allowing terrorist groups or corrupt or ideologically-motivated insiders to transfer dangerous material to terrorists. a nuclear-armed state could collapse resulting in a breakdown of law and order and a loose nukes problem Regional Instability The spread of nuclear weapons also emboldens nuclear powers contributing to regional instability States that lack nuclear weapons need to fear direct military attack from other states, but states with nuclear weapons can be confident that they can deter an intentional military attack, giving them an incentive to be more aggressive in the conduct of their foreign policy uclear weapons provide a shield under which states can feel free to engage in lower-level aggression Historically the spread of nuclear weapons has emboldened their possessors and contributed to regional instability Recent scholarly analyses have demonstrated that, after controlling for other relevant factors, nuclear-weapon states are more likely to engage in conflict than nonnuclear weapon states this aggressiveness is more pronounced in new nuclear states that have less experience with nuclear diplomacy. nuclear-armed Iran would likely step up support to terrorist and proxy groups and engage in more aggressive coercive diplomacy we could witness an even more crisis prone Middle East. And in a poly-nuclear Middle East any one of those crises could result in a catastrophic nuclear exchange.
The spread of nuclear weapons poses severe threats to international security including nuclear war terrorism, global instability weakened alliances Before MAD new states lack second strike it has an incentive to use first a preventive strike emphasizes use em or lose em pressures leaders initiate a nuclear crisis By playing brinkmanship states can increase the risk to force a less resolved adversary to back down many of them have come close a future crisis could result in a devastating nuclear exchange spread increases the risk of nuclear terror nuclear weapons embolden nuclear powers, contributing to regional instability states with nuclear weapons engage in lower-level aggression any crises could result in a catastrophic nuclear exchange
The spread of nuclear weapons poses at least six severe threats to international peace and security including: nuclear war, nuclear terrorism, global and regional instability, constrained US freedom of action, weakened alliances, and further nuclear proliferation. Each of these threats has received extensive treatment elsewhere and this review is not intended to replicate or even necessarily to improve upon these previous efforts. Rather the goals of this section are more modest: to usefully bring together and recap the many reasons why we should be pessimistic about the likely consequences of nuclear proliferation. Many of these threats will be illuminated with a discussion of a case of much contemporary concern: Iran’s advanced nuclear program. Nuclear War The greatest threat posed by the spread of nuclear weapons is nuclear war. The more states in possession of nuclear weapons, the greater the probability that somewhere, someday, there will be a catastrophic nuclear war. To date, nuclear weapons have only been used in warfare once. In 1945, the United States used nuclear weapons on Hiroshima and Nagasaki, bringing World War II to a close. Many analysts point to the 65-plus-year tradition of nuclear non-use as evidence that nuclear weapons are unusable, but it would be naïve to think that nuclear weapons will never be used again simply because they have not been used for some time. After all, analysts in the 1990s argued that worldwide economic downturns like the Great Depression were a thing of the past, only to be surprised by the dot-com bubble bursting later in the decade and the Great Recession of the late 2000s.48 This author, for one, would be surprised if nuclear weapons are not used again sometime in his lifetime. Before reaching a state of MAD, new nuclear states go through a transition period in which they lack a secure-second strike capability. In this context, one or both states might believe that it has an incentive to use nuclear weapons first. For example, if Iran acquires nuclear weapons, neither Iran, nor its nuclear-armed rival, Israel, will have a secure, second-strike capability. Even though it is believed to have a large arsenal, given its small size and lack of strategic depth, Israel might not be confident that it could absorb a nuclear strike and respond with a devastating counterstrike. Similarly, Iran might eventually be able to build a large and survivable nuclear arsenal, but, when it first crosses the nuclear threshold, Tehran will have a small and vulnerable nuclear force. In these pre-MAD situations, there are at least three ways that nuclear war could occur. First, the state with the nuclear advantage might believe it has a splendid first strike capability. In a crisis, Israel might, therefore, decide to launch a preventive nuclear strike to disarm Iran’s nuclear capabilities. Indeed, this incentive might be further increased by Israel’s aggressive strategic culture that emphasizes preemptive action. Second, the state with a small and vulnerable nuclear arsenal, in this case Iran, might feel use them or lose them pressures. That is, in a crisis, Iran might decide to strike first rather than risk having its entire nuclear arsenal destroyed. Third, as Thomas Schelling has argued, nuclear war could result due to the reciprocal fear of surprise attack.49 If there are advantages to striking first, one state might start a nuclear war in the belief that war is inevitable and that it would be better to go first than to go second. Fortunately, there is no historic evidence of this dynamic occurring in a nuclear context, but it is still possible. In an Israeli–Iranian crisis, for example, Israel and Iran might both prefer to avoid a nuclear war, but decide to strike first rather than suffer a devastating first attack from an opponent. Even in a world of MAD, however, when both sides have secure, second-strike capabilities, there is still a risk of nuclear war. Rational deterrence theory assumes nuclear-armed states are governed by rational leaders who would not intentionally launch a suicidal nuclear war. This assumption appears to have applied to past and current nuclear powers, but there is no guarantee that it will continue to hold in the future. Iran’s theocratic government, despite its inflammatory rhetoric, has followed a fairly pragmatic foreign policy since 1979, but it contains leaders who hold millenarian religious worldviews and could one day ascend to power. We cannot rule out the possibility that, as nuclear weapons continue to spread, some leader somewhere will choose to launch a nuclear war, knowing full well that it could result in self-destruction. One does not need to resort to irrationality, however, to imagine nuclear war under MAD. Nuclear weapons may deter leaders from intentionally launching full-scale wars, but they do not mean the end of international politics. As was discussed above, nuclear-armed states still have conflicts of interest and leaders still seek to coerce nuclear-armed adversaries. Leaders might, therefore, choose to launch a limited nuclear war.50 This strategy might be especially attractive to states in a position of conventional inferiority that might have an incentive to escalate a crisis quickly to the nuclear level. During the Cold War, the United States planned to use nuclear weapons first to stop a Soviet invasion of Western Europe given NATO’s conventional inferiority.51 As Russia’s conventional power has deteriorated since the end of the Cold War, Moscow has come to rely more heavily on nuclear weapons in its military doctrine. Indeed, Russian strategy calls for the use of nuclear weapons early in a conflict (something that most Western strategists would consider to be escalatory) as a way to de-escalate a crisis. Similarly, Pakistan’s military plans for nuclear use in the event of an invasion from conventionally stronger India. And finally, Chinese generals openly talk about the possibility of nuclear use against a US superpower in a possible East Asia contingency. Second, as was also discussed above, leaders can make a ‘threat that leaves something to chance’.52 They can initiate a nuclear crisis. By playing these risky games of nuclear brinkmanship, states can increase the risk of nuclear war in an attempt to force a less resolved adversary to back down. Historical crises have not resulted in nuclear war, but many of them, including the 1962 Cuban Missile Crisis, have come close. And scholars have documented historical incidents when accidents nearly led to war.53 When we think about future nuclear crisis dyads, such as Iran and Israel, with fewer sources of stability than existed during the Cold War, we can see that there is a real risk that a future crisis could result in a devastating nuclear exchange. Nuclear Terrorism The spread of nuclear weapons also increases the risk of nuclear terrorism.54 While September 11th was one of the greatest tragedies in American history, it would have been much worse had Osama Bin Laden possessed nuclear weapons. Bin Laden declared it a ‘religious duty’ for Al- Qa’eda to acquire nuclear weapons and radical clerics have issued fatwas declaring it permissible to use nuclear weapons in Jihad against the West.55 Unlike states, which can be more easily deterred, there is little doubt that if terrorists acquired nuclear weapons, they would use them.56 Indeed, in recent years, many US politicians and security analysts have argued that nuclear terrorism poses the greatest threat to US national security.57 Analysts have pointed out the tremendous hurdles that terrorists would have to overcome in order to acquire nuclear weapons.58 Nevertheless, as nuclear weapons spread, the possibility that they will eventually fall into terrorist hands increases. States could intentionally transfer nuclear weapons, or the fissile material required to build them, to terrorist groups. There are good reasons why a state might be reluctant to transfer nuclear weapons to terrorists, but, as nuclear weapons spread, the probability that a leader might someday purposely arm a terrorist group increases. Some fear, for example, that Iran, with its close ties to Hamas and Hizballah, might be at a heightened risk of transferring nuclear weapons to terrorists. Moreover, even if no state would ever intentionally transfer nuclear capabilities to terrorists, a new nuclear state, with underdeveloped security procedures, might be vulnerable to theft, allowing terrorist groups or corrupt or ideologically-motivated insiders to transfer dangerous material to terrorists. There is evidence, for example, that representatives from Pakistan’s atomic energy establishment met with Al-Qa’eda members to discuss a possible nuclear deal.59 Finally, a nuclear-armed state could collapse, resulting in a breakdown of law and order and a loose nukes problem. US officials are currently very concerned about what would happen to Pakistan’s nuclear weapons if the government were to fall. As nuclear weapons spread, this problem is only further amplified. Iran is a country with a history of revolutions and a government with a tenuous hold on power. The regime change that Washington has long dreamed about in Tehran could actually become a nightmare if a nuclear-armed Iran suffered a breakdown in authority, forcing us to worry about the fate of Iran’s nuclear arsenal. Regional Instability The spread of nuclear weapons also emboldens nuclear powers, contributing to regional instability. States that lack nuclear weapons need to fear direct military attack from other states, but states with nuclear weapons can be confident that they can deter an intentional military attack, giving them an incentive to be more aggressive in the conduct of their foreign policy. In this way, nuclear weapons provide a shield under which states can feel free to engage in lower-level aggression. Indeed, international relations theories about the ‘stability-instability paradox’ maintain that stability at the nuclear level contributes to conventional instability.60 Historically, we have seen that the spread of nuclear weapons has emboldened their possessors and contributed to regional instability. Recent scholarly analyses have demonstrated that, after controlling for other relevant factors, nuclear-weapon states are more likely to engage in conflict than nonnuclear-weapon states and that this aggressiveness is more pronounced in new nuclear states that have less experience with nuclear diplomacy.61 Similarly, research on internal decision-making in Pakistan reveals that Pakistani foreign policymakers may have been emboldened by the acquisition of nuclear weapons, which encouraged them to initiate militarized disputes against India.62 Currently, Iran restrains its foreign policy because it fears major military retaliation from the United States or Israel, but with nuclear weapons it could feel free to push harder. A nuclear-armed Iran would likely step up support to terrorist and proxy groups and engage in more aggressive coercive diplomacy. With a nuclear-armed Iran increasingly throwing its weight around in the region, we could witness an even more crisis prone Middle East. And in a poly-nuclear Middle East with Israel, Iran, and, in the future, possibly other states, armed with nuclear weapons, any one of those crises could result in a catastrophic nuclear exchange.
11,405
<h4><strong>Proliferation causes nuclear war and terrorism – not just east asia </h4><p><u>Kroenig, 15</u></strong> - Associate Professor and International Relations Field Chair in the Department of Government and School of Foreign Service at Georgetown University (Matthew, The History of Proliferation Optimism: Does It Have a Future? Journal of Strategic Studies, Volume 38, Issue 1-2) </p><p><u><mark>The spread of nuclear weapons poses</mark> at least six <strong><mark>severe threats</strong> to international</mark> peace and <mark>security including</mark>: <strong><mark>nuclear war</strong></mark>, <strong>nuclear <mark>terrorism</strong>, global</mark> and</u> <u>regional <mark>instability</mark>, constrained US freedom of action, <strong><mark>weakened alliances</strong></mark>, and further nuclear proliferation.</u> Each of these threats has received extensive treatment elsewhere and this review is not intended to replicate or even necessarily to improve upon these previous efforts. Rather the goals of this section are more modest: to usefully bring together and recap the many reasons why <u>we should be pessimistic about the likely consequences of nuclear proliferation</u>. Many of these threats will be illuminated with a discussion of a case of much contemporary concern: Iran’s advanced nuclear program. Nuclear War <u>The greatest threat</u> posed by the spread of nuclear weapons <u>is nuclear war. The <strong>more states</strong> in possession of nuclear weapons</u>, <u>the <strong>greater the probability</strong> that somewhere, someday, there will be a <strong>catastrophic nuclear</strong> war.</u> To date, nuclear weapons have only been used in warfare once. In 1945, the United States used nuclear weapons on Hiroshima and Nagasaki, bringing World War II to a close. Many analysts point to the 65-plus-year tradition of nuclear non-use as evidence that nuclear weapons are unusable, but it would be naïve to think that nuclear weapons will never be used again simply because they have not been used for some time. After all, analysts in the 1990s argued that worldwide economic downturns like the Great Depression were a thing of the past, only to be surprised by the dot-com bubble bursting later in the decade and the Great Recession of the late 2000s.48 This author, for one, would be surprised if nuclear weapons are not used again sometime in his lifetime. <u><mark>Before</mark> reaching a state of <strong><mark>MAD</u></strong></mark>, <u><mark>new</mark> nuclear <mark>states </mark>go through a <strong>transition</strong> period in which they<mark> <strong>lack</strong></mark> a secure-<strong><mark>second strike</strong> </mark>capability</u>. In this context, <u>one or both states might believe that <mark>it has an <strong>incentive</strong> to <strong>use</strong></mark> nuclear weapons <strong><mark>first</u></strong></mark>. For example, if Iran acquires nuclear weapons, neither Iran, nor its nuclear-armed rival, Israel, will have a secure, second-strike capability. Even though it is believed to have a large arsenal, <u>given its small size and lack of strategic depth, Israel might not be confident that it could absorb a nuclear strike and respond with a devastating counterstrike</u>. Similarly, <u>Iran might eventually be able to build a large and survivable nuclear arsenal, but, when it first crosses the nuclear threshold, Tehran will have a small and vulnerable nuclear force</u>. In these pre-MAD situations, there are at least three ways that nuclear war could occur. First, <u>the state with the nuclear advantage might believe it has a</u> <u>splendid first strike capability. In a crisis, Israel might</u>, therefore, <u>decide to launch <mark>a <strong>preventive</mark> nuclear <mark>strike</strong></mark> to disarm Iran’s nuclear capabilities. </u>Indeed, <u>this</u> <u><strong>incentive</u></strong> <u>might be further increased by Israel’s aggressive strategic culture that <mark>emphasizes</mark> <strong>preemptive action</strong>.</u> Second, <u>the state with a small and vulnerable</u> nuclear arsenal, in this case Iran, <u>might feel <strong><mark>use </mark>th<mark>em or lose </mark>th<mark>em pressures</u></strong></mark>. That is, <u>in a crisis, Iran might decide to strike first rather than risk having its entire nuclear arsenal destroyed</u>. Third, as Thomas Schelling has argued, <u>nuclear war could result due to the reciprocal fear of surprise attack</u>.49 If there are advantages to striking first, <u>one state might start a nuclear war in the belief that war is inevitable and that it would be better to go first than to go second</u>. Fortunately, there is no historic evidence of this dynamic occurring in a nuclear context, but it is still possible. In an Israeli–Iranian crisis, for example, Israel and Iran might both prefer to avoid a nuclear war, but decide to strike first rather than suffer a devastating first attack from an opponent. Even in a world of MAD, however, when both sides have secure, second-strike capabilities, <u><strong>there is still a risk of nuclear war</u></strong>. Rational deterrence theory assumes nuclear-armed states are governed by rational leaders who would not intentionally launch a suicidal nuclear war. This assumption appears to have applied to past and current nuclear powers, but there is no guarantee that it will continue to hold in the future. <u>Iran’s theocratic government</u>, despite its inflammatory rhetoric, has followed a fairly pragmatic foreign policy since 1979, but it <u>contains leaders who hold millenarian religious worldviews and could one day ascend to power. We cannot rule out the possibility that, as nuclear weapons continue to spread, some leader somewhere will choose to launch a nuclear war,</u> knowing full well that it could result in self-destruction. One does not need to resort to irrationality, however, to imagine nuclear war under MAD. Nuclear weapons may deter leaders from intentionally launching full-scale wars, but they do not mean the end of international politics. As was discussed above, <u>nuclear-armed states still have conflicts of interest and leaders</u> <u>still seek to coerce nuclear-armed adversaries</u>. Leaders might, therefore, choose to launch a limited nuclear war.50 This strategy might be especially attractive to states in a position of conventional inferiority that might have an incentive to escalate a crisis quickly to the nuclear level. During the Cold War, the United States planned to use nuclear weapons first to stop a Soviet invasion of Western Europe given NATO’s conventional inferiority.51 As Russia’s conventional power has deteriorated since the end of the Cold War, Moscow has come to rely more heavily on nuclear weapons in its military doctrine. Indeed, Russian strategy calls for the use of nuclear weapons early in a conflict (something that most Western strategists would consider to be escalatory) as a way to de-escalate a crisis. Similarly, Pakistan’s military plans for nuclear use in the event of an invasion from conventionally stronger India. And finally, Chinese generals openly talk about the possibility of nuclear use against a US superpower in a possible East Asia contingency. Second, as was also discussed above, <u><mark>leaders</mark> can make a ‘threat that leaves something to chance’.</u>52 <u><strong>They can <mark>initiate a nuclear crisis</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>By playing </mark>these risky games of nuclear <mark>brinkmanship</mark>, <mark>states can increase the risk</mark> of nuclear war in an attempt <strong><mark>to force a less resolved adversary</strong> to <strong>back</mark> <mark>down</mark>.</u></strong> Historical <u>crises have not resulted in nuclear war, but <mark>many of them</u></mark>, including the 1962 Cuban Missile Crisis, <u><mark>have <strong>come close</u></strong></mark>. And scholars have documented historical incidents when accidents nearly led to war.53 <u>When we think about future nuclear crisis dyads</u>, such as Iran and Israel, <u>with fewer sources of stability than existed during the Cold War, we can see that there is a real risk that <strong><mark>a future crisis could result in a devastating nuclear exchange</u></strong></mark>. Nuclear Terrorism <u>The <mark>spread</mark> of nuclear weapons also <strong><mark>increases the risk of nuclear terror</mark>ism</u></strong>.54 While September 11th was one of the greatest tragedies in American history, it would have been much worse had Osama Bin Laden possessed nuclear weapons. Bin <u>Laden declared it a ‘religious duty’ for Al- Qa’eda to acquire</u> <u>nuclear weapons and radical clerics have issued fatwas declaring it permissible to use nuclear weapons in Jihad against the West</u>.55 Unlike states, which can be more easily deterred, there is little doubt that if terrorists acquired nuclear weapons, they would use them.56 Indeed, in recent years, many US politicians and security analysts have argued that nuclear terrorism poses the greatest threat to US national security.57 Analysts have pointed out the tremendous hurdles that terrorists would have to overcome in order to acquire nuclear weapons.58 Nevertheless, <u>as nuclear weapons spread, the possibility that they will eventually fall into terrorist hands increases</u>. <u>States could intentionally <strong>transfer nuclear weapons</u></strong>, or the fissile material required to build them, <u>to terrorist groups</u>. There are good reasons why a state might be reluctant to transfer nuclear weapons to terrorists, but, as nuclear weapons spread, the probability that a leader might someday purposely arm a terrorist group increases. Some fear, for example, that Iran, with its close ties to Hamas and Hizballah, might be at a heightened risk of transferring nuclear weapons to terrorists. Moreover, even if no state would ever intentionally transfer nuclear capabilities to terrorists, <u>a new nuclear state, with underdeveloped security procedures, might be vulnerable to <strong>theft</strong>, allowing terrorist groups or corrupt or ideologically-motivated insiders to transfer dangerous material to terrorists.</u> There is evidence, for example, that representatives from Pakistan’s atomic energy establishment met with Al-Qa’eda members to discuss a possible nuclear deal.59 Finally, <u>a nuclear-armed state could collapse</u>, <u>resulting in a breakdown of law and order and a loose nukes problem</u>. US officials are currently very concerned about what would happen to Pakistan’s nuclear weapons if the government were to fall. As nuclear weapons spread, this problem is only further amplified. Iran is a country with a history of revolutions and a government with a tenuous hold on power. The regime change that Washington has long dreamed about in Tehran could actually become a nightmare if a nuclear-armed Iran suffered a breakdown in authority, forcing us to worry about the fate of Iran’s nuclear arsenal. <u><strong>Regional Instability </strong>The spread of <mark>nuclear weapons</mark> also <strong><mark>embolden</mark>s <mark>nuclear powers</u></strong>, <u>contributing to <strong>regional instability</u></strong></mark>. <u>States that lack nuclear weapons need to fear direct</u> <u>military attack from other states, but <mark>states with <strong>nuclear weapons</strong> </mark>can be confident that they can deter an intentional military attack, giving them an incentive</u> <u>to be more aggressive in the conduct of their foreign policy</u>. In this way, n<u>uclear weapons provide a shield under which states can feel free to <mark>engage in <strong>lower-level aggression</u></strong></mark>. Indeed, international relations theories about the ‘stability-instability paradox’ maintain that stability at the nuclear level contributes to conventional instability.60 <u><strong>Historically</u></strong>, we have seen that <u>the <strong>spread of nuclear weapons</strong> has emboldened their possessors and contributed to <strong>regional instability</u></strong>. <u>Recent scholarly analyses have demonstrated that, after controlling for other relevant factors, nuclear-weapon states are more likely to engage in conflict than nonnuclear</u>-<u>weapon states</u> and that <u>this aggressiveness is more pronounced in new nuclear states that have less experience with nuclear diplomacy.</u>61 Similarly, research on internal decision-making in Pakistan reveals that Pakistani foreign policymakers may have been emboldened by the acquisition of nuclear weapons, which encouraged them to initiate militarized disputes against India.62 Currently, Iran restrains its foreign policy because it fears major military retaliation from the United States or Israel, but with nuclear weapons it could feel free to push harder. A <u>nuclear-armed Iran would likely step up support to terrorist and proxy groups and engage in more aggressive coercive diplomacy</u>. With a nuclear-armed Iran increasingly throwing its weight around in the region, <u><strong>we could witness an even more crisis prone Middle East.</u></strong> <u>And in a poly-nuclear Middle East</u> with Israel, Iran, and, in the future, possibly other states, armed with nuclear weapons, <u><strong><mark>any</strong> </mark>one of those <strong><mark>crises</strong> could result in a <strong>catastrophic nuclear exchange</strong></mark>.</u><strong> </p></strong>
null
1NR
1NR – AT: Empirically Denied
6,955
2,098
98,963
./documents/ndtceda18/Dartmouth/EsTa/Dartmouth-Estrada-Tambe-Neg-Dartmouth%20Round%20Robin-Round5.docx
602,761
N
Dartmouth Round Robin
5
Kentucky BT
Hays Watson
1AC - NFU 2NR -- PGS DACase
ndtceda18/Dartmouth/EsTa/Dartmouth-Estrada-Tambe-Neg-Dartmouth%20Round%20Robin-Round5.docx
null
51,280
EsTa
Dartmouth EsTa
null
Jo.....
Es.....
Ra.....
Ta.....
19,175
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,008
ndtceda18
NDT/CEDA 2018-19
2,018
cx
college
2
4,735,238
Non utilitarian ethics are impossible
Greene 07
Greene 07 – Joshua, Associate Professor of Social science in the Department of Psychology at Harvard University (The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul published in Moral Psychology: Historical and Contemporary Readings, accessed: https://www.gwern.net/docs/philosophy/ethics/2007-greene.pdf, pages 47-50)
What turn-of-the-millennium science is telling us is that human moral judgment is not a pristine rational enterprise moral judgments are driven by a hodgepodge of emotional dispositions, which themselves were shaped by a hodgepodge of evolutionary forces, both biological and cultural Because of this, it is exceedingly unlikely that there is any rationally coherent normative moral theory that can accommodate our moral intuitions anyone who claims to have such a theory almost certainly doesn't rationalist deontologists will remain unmoved by the arguments presented here they will insist that I have simply misunderstood what deontologists are all about Deontology, they will say, isn't about this intuition or that intuition Rather, deontology is about taking humanity seriously This is, no doubt, how many deontologists see deontology. But this insider's view may be misleading The problem is that it defines deontology in terms of values that are not distinctively deontological Consider the following analogy with religion. When one asks a religious person to explain the essence of his religion, one often gets an answer like this: "It's about love This sort of answer accurately captures the phenomenology of many people's religion, but it's nevertheless inadequate for distinguishing religion from other things the standard deontological/Kantian self-characterizatons fail to distinguish deontology from other approaches to ethics consequentialists have respect for persons are against treating people as mere objects, wish to act for reasons that rational creatures can share, etc A consequentialist respects other persons, and refrains from treating them as mere objects, by counting every person's well-being in the decision-making process Likewise, a consequentialist attempts to act according to reasons that rational creatures can share by acting according to principles that give equal weight to everyone's interests, i.e. that are impartial If you ask a deontologically-minded person why it's wrong to push someone in front of speeding trolley in order to save five others, you will get answers will be tautological "Because it's murder!" Others will be more sophisticated: "The ends don't justify the means But these answers don't really explain anything if you give the same people the trolley case they'll make the opposite judgment Talk about rights, respect for persons, and reasons we can share are natural attempts to explain, in "cognitive" terms, what we feel when we find ourselves having emotionally driven intuitions that are odds with the cold calculus of consequentialism there seems to be "something deeply right" about them because they give voice to powerful moral emotions But, as with many religious people's accounts of what's essential to religion, they don't really explain what's distinctive about the philosophy in question
science is telling us human moral judgment is not a pristine rational enterprise judgments are driven by a hodgepodge of emotional dispositions shaped by a hodgepodge of evolutionary forces, biological and cultural it is exceedingly unlikely there is any coherent normative moral theory that can accommodate our moral intuitions deontologists insider's view may be misleading it defines deontology in terms of values that are not distinctively deontological consequentialists, are against treating people as mere objects by counting every person's well-being deontologicall answers will be tautological these answers don't really explain anything
What turn-of-the-millennium science is telling us is that human moral judgment is not a pristine rational enterprise, that our moral judgments are driven by a hodgepodge of emotional dispositions, which themselves were shaped by a hodgepodge of evolutionary forces, both biological and cultural. Because of this, it is exceedingly unlikely that there is any rationally coherent normative moral theory that can accommodate our moral intuitions. Moreover, anyone who claims to have such a theory, or even part of one, almost certainly doesn't. Instead, what that person probably has is a moral rationalization. It seems then, that we have somehow crossed the infamous "is"-"ought" divide. How did this happen? Didn't Hume (Hume, 1978) and Moore (Moore, 1966) warn us against trying to derive an "ought" from and "is?" How did we go from descriptive scientific theories concerning moral psychology to skepticism about a whole class of normative moral theories? The answer is that we did not, as Hume and Moore anticipated, attempt to derive an "ought" from and "is." That is, our method has been inductive rather than deductive. We have inferred on the basis of the available evidence that the phenomenon of rationalist deontological philosophy is best explained as a rationalization of evolved emotional intuition (Harman, 1977). Missing the Deontological Point I suspect that rationalist deontologists will remain unmoved by the arguments presented here. Instead, I suspect, they will insist that I have simply misunderstood what Kant and like-minded deontologists are all about. Deontology, they will say, isn't about this intuition or that intuition. It's not defined by its normative differences with consequentialism. Rather, deontology is about taking humanity seriously. Above all else, it's about respect for persons. It's about treating others as fellow rational creatures rather than as mere objects, about acting for reasons rational beings can share. And so on (Korsgaard, 1996a; Korsgaard, 1996b). This is, no doubt, how many deontologists see deontology. But this insider's view, as I've suggested, may be misleading. The problem, more specifically, is that it defines deontology in terms of values that are not distinctively deontological, though they may appear to be from the inside. Consider the following analogy with religion. When one asks a religious person to explain the essence of his religion, one often gets an answer like this: "It's about love, really. It's about looking out for other people, looking beyond oneself. It's about community, being part of something larger than oneself." This sort of answer accurately captures the phenomenology of many people's religion, but it's nevertheless inadequate for distinguishing religion from other things. This is because many, if not most, non-religious people aspire to love deeply, look out for other people, avoid self-absorption, have a sense of a community, and be connected to things larger than themselves. In other words, secular humanists and atheists can assent to most of what many religious people think religion is all about. From a secular humanist's point of view, in contrast, what's distinctive about religion is its commitment to the existence of supernatural entities as well as formal religious institutions and doctrines. And they're right. These things really do distinguish religious from non-religious practices, though they may appear to be secondary to many people operating from within a religious point of view. In the same way, I believe that most of the standard deontological/Kantian self-characterizatons fail to distinguish deontology from other approaches to ethics. (See also Kagan (Kagan, 1997, pp. 70-78.) on the difficulty of defining deontology.) It seems to me that consequentialists, as much as anyone else, have respect for persons, are against treating people as mere objects, wish to act for reasons that rational creatures can share, etc. A consequentialist respects other persons, and refrains from treating them as mere objects, by counting every person's well-being in the decision-making process. Likewise, a consequentialist attempts to act according to reasons that rational creatures can share by acting according to principles that give equal weight to everyone's interests, i.e. that are impartial. This is not to say that consequentialists and deontologists don't differ. They do. It's just that the real differences may not be what deontologists often take them to be. What, then, distinguishes deontology from other kinds of moral thought? A good strategy for answering this question is to start with concrete disagreements between deontologists and others (such as consequentialists) and then work backward in search of deeper principles. This is what I've attempted to do with the trolley and footbridge cases, and other instances in which deontologists and consequentialists disagree. If you ask a deontologically-minded person why it's wrong to push someone in front of speeding trolley in order to save five others, you will get characteristically deontological answers. Some will be tautological: "Because it's murder!" Others will be more sophisticated: "The ends don't justify the means." "You have to respect people's rights." But, as we know, these answers don't really explain anything, because if you give the same people (on different occasions) the trolley case or the loop case (See above), they'll make the opposite judgment, even though their initial explanation concerning the footbridge case applies equally well to one or both of these cases. Talk about rights, respect for persons, and reasons we can share are natural attempts to explain, in "cognitive" terms, what we feel when we find ourselves having emotionally driven intuitions that are odds with the cold calculus of consequentialism. Although these explanations are inevitably incomplete, there seems to be "something deeply right" about them because they give voice to powerful moral emotions. But, as with many religious people's accounts of what's essential to religion, they don't really explain what's distinctive about the philosophy in question.
6,162
<h4>Non utilitarian ethics are impossible</h4><p><strong>Greene 07</strong> – Joshua, Associate Professor of Social science in the Department of Psychology at Harvard University (The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul published in Moral Psychology: Historical and Contemporary Readings, accessed: https://www.gwern.net/docs/philosophy/ethics/2007-greene.pdf, pages 47-50)</p><p><u><strong>What turn-of-the-millennium <mark>science</u></strong> <u><strong>is telling us</mark> is that <mark>human moral judgment is not a pristine rational enterprise</u></strong></mark>, that our <u><strong>moral <mark>judgments are driven by a hodgepodge of emotional dispositions</mark>, which themselves were <mark>shaped by a hodgepodge of evolutionary forces,</mark> both <mark>biological and cultural</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Because of this, <mark>it is exceedingly unlikely</mark> that <mark>there is any</mark> rationally <mark>coherent normative moral theory that can accommodate our moral intuitions</u></strong></mark>. Moreover, <u><strong>anyone who claims to have such a theory</u></strong>, or even part of one, <u><strong>almost certainly doesn't</u></strong>. Instead, what that person probably has is a moral rationalization. It seems then, that we have somehow crossed the infamous "is"-"ought" divide. How did this happen? Didn't Hume (Hume, 1978) and Moore (Moore, 1966) warn us against trying to derive an "ought" from and "is?" How did we go from descriptive scientific theories concerning moral psychology to skepticism about a whole class of normative moral theories? The answer is that we did not, as Hume and Moore anticipated, attempt to derive an "ought" from and "is." That is, our method has been inductive rather than deductive. We have inferred on the basis of the available evidence that the phenomenon of rationalist deontological philosophy is best explained as a rationalization of evolved emotional intuition (Harman, 1977). Missing the Deontological Point I suspect that <u><strong>rationalist deontologists will remain unmoved by the arguments presented here</u></strong>. Instead, I suspect, <u><strong>they</u></strong> <u><strong>will insist that I have simply misunderstood what</u></strong> Kant and like-minded <u><strong>deontologists are all about</u></strong>. <u><strong>Deontology, they will say, isn't about this intuition or that intuition</u></strong>. It's not defined by its normative differences with consequentialism. <u><strong>Rather, deontology is about taking humanity seriously</u></strong>. Above all else, it's about respect for persons. It's about treating others as fellow rational creatures rather than as mere objects, about acting for reasons rational beings can share. And so on (Korsgaard, 1996a; Korsgaard, 1996b). <u><strong>This is, no doubt, how many <mark>deontologists</mark> see deontology. But this <mark>insider's view</u></strong></mark>, as I've suggested, <u><strong><mark>may be misleading</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>The problem</u></strong>, more specifically, <u><strong>is that <mark>it defines deontology in terms of values that are not distinctively deontological</u></strong></mark>, though they may appear to be from the inside. <u><strong>Consider the following analogy with religion. When one asks a religious person to explain the essence of his religion, one often gets an answer like this: "It's about love</u></strong>, really. It's about looking out for other people, looking beyond oneself. It's about community, being part of something larger than oneself." <u><strong>This sort of answer accurately captures the phenomenology of many people's religion, but it's nevertheless inadequate for distinguishing religion from other things</u></strong>. This is because many, if not most, non-religious people aspire to love deeply, look out for other people, avoid self-absorption, have a sense of a community, and be connected to things larger than themselves. In other words, secular humanists and atheists can assent to most of what many religious people think religion is all about. From a secular humanist's point of view, in contrast, what's distinctive about religion is its commitment to the existence of supernatural entities as well as formal religious institutions and doctrines. And they're right. These things really do distinguish religious from non-religious practices, though they may appear to be secondary to many people operating from within a religious point of view. In the same way, I believe that most of <u><strong>the standard deontological/Kantian self-characterizatons fail to distinguish deontology from other approaches to ethics</u></strong>. (See also Kagan (Kagan, 1997, pp. 70-78.) on the difficulty of defining deontology.) It seems to me that <u><strong><mark>consequentialists</u></strong>,</mark> as much as anyone else, <u><strong>have respect for persons</u></strong>, <u><strong><mark>are against treating people as mere objects</mark>,</u></strong> <u><strong>wish to act for reasons that rational creatures can share, etc</u></strong>. <u><strong>A consequentialist respects other persons, and refrains from treating them as mere objects, <mark>by counting every person's well-being </mark>in the decision-making process</u></strong>. <u><strong>Likewise, a consequentialist attempts to act according to reasons that rational creatures can share by acting according to principles that give equal weight to everyone's interests, i.e. that are impartial</u></strong>. This is not to say that consequentialists and deontologists don't differ. They do. It's just that the real differences may not be what deontologists often take them to be. What, then, distinguishes deontology from other kinds of moral thought? A good strategy for answering this question is to start with concrete disagreements between deontologists and others (such as consequentialists) and then work backward in search of deeper principles. This is what I've attempted to do with the trolley and footbridge cases, and other instances in which deontologists and consequentialists disagree. <u><strong>If you ask a <mark>deontologicall</mark>y-minded person why it's wrong to push someone in front of speeding trolley in order to save five others, you will get</u></strong> characteristically deontological <u><strong><mark>answers</u></strong></mark>. Some <u><strong><mark>will be tautological</u></strong></mark>: <u><strong>"Because it's murder!"</u></strong> <u><strong>Others will be more sophisticated: "The ends don't justify the means</u></strong>." "You have to respect people's rights." <u><strong>But</u></strong>, as we know, <u><strong><mark>these answers don't really explain anything</u></strong></mark>, because <u><strong>if you give the same people</u></strong> (on different occasions) <u><strong>the trolley case</u></strong> or the loop case (See above), <u><strong>they'll make the opposite judgment</u></strong>, even though their initial explanation concerning the footbridge case applies equally well to one or both of these cases. <u><strong>Talk about rights, respect for persons, and reasons we can share are natural attempts to explain, in "cognitive" terms, what we feel when we find ourselves having emotionally driven intuitions that are odds with the cold calculus of consequentialism</u></strong>. Although these explanations are inevitably incomplete, <u><strong>there seems to be "something deeply right" about them because they give voice to powerful moral emotions</u></strong>. <u><strong>But, as with many religious people's accounts of what's essential to religion, they don't really explain what's distinctive about the philosophy in question</u></strong>. </p>
null
Framework
Africa
10,110
1,812
165,599
./documents/hsld22/Marlborough/ChTj/Marlborough-ChTj-Aff-Woodward-Round-3.docx
989,811
A
Woodward
3
Immaculate Heart AS
Ezell, Brice
ac: fmp, econ, colonialism, util nc: terror, pic 1ac: all nc: concede pic, rest of it 2ar: all
hsld22/Marlborough/ChTj/Marlborough-ChTj-Aff-Woodward-Round-3.docx
2023-03-18 14:01:41
81,941
ChTj
Marlborough ChTj
null
Ch.....
Tj.....
null
null
26,925
Marlborough
Marlborough
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
3,519,761
Extinction
Xu 17
Yangyang Xu 17, Assistant Professor of Atmospheric Sciences at Texas A&M University; and Veerabhadran Ramanathan, Distinguished Professor of Atmospheric and Climate Sciences at the Scripps Institution of Oceanography, University of California, San Diego, 9/26/17, “Well below 2 °C: Mitigation strategies for avoiding dangerous to catastrophic climate changes,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, Vol. 114, No. 39, p. 10315-10323
We are proposing the following risk categorization: warming greater than 1.5 °C as “dangerous warming greater than 3 °C as “catastrophic?”; and warming in excess of 5 °C as “unknown changes of this magnitude, not experienced in the last 20+ million years, pose existential threats to a majority of the population Our criteria for extending the risk category include potential risks of climate change to the physical climate system, the ecosystem, human health, and species extinction The first major concern is tipping points 3 to 5 °C global warming is likely to be the threshold for tipping points such as the collapse of the western Antarctic ice sheet, shutdown of deep water circulation dieback of Amazon rainforests collapse of the West African monsoon natural scientists refer to these as abrupt and irreversible climate changes Warming of such magnitudes has catastrophic human health effects 2 °C warming would double the land area subject to deadly heat and expose 48% of the population 4 °C would subject 74% of the world population to deadly heat, which could pose existential risks to humans unless massive adaptation measures are implemented Climate risks vary markedly depending on socioeconomic status the poorest 3 billion people livelihood will be severely impacted, if not destroyed rise in sea level (likely with warming in excess of 3 °C) poses existential threat several hundred million people would be subject to famine Climate change-induced species extinction is one major concern with warming of such large magnitudes (>5 °C warming of 6 °C or more accompanied by increase in ocean acidity can act as a major force multiplier and expose 90% of species to extinction climate change-forced species destruction, biodiversity loss, and threats to water and food security motivated us to categorize warming beyond 5 °C as unknown implying existential threats
warming in excess of 5 ° pose existential threats criteria for risks of climate change to the ecosystem and species extinction first is tipping points 3 to 5 °C is the threshold for tipping points abrupt and irreversible climate changes 4 °C could pose existential risks to humans 6 °C accompanied by ocean acidity expose 90% of species to extinction climate change-forced biodiversity loss threats to water and food security motivated us to categorize warming as existential threats
We are proposing the following extension to the DAI risk categorization: warming greater than 1.5 °C as “dangerous”; warming greater than 3 °C as “catastrophic?”; and warming in excess of 5 °C as “unknown??,” with the understanding that changes of this magnitude, not experienced in the last 20+ million years, pose existential threats to a majority of the population. The question mark denotes the subjective nature of our deduction and the fact that catastrophe can strike at even lower warming levels. The justifications for the proposed extension to risk categorization are given below. From the IPCC burning embers diagram and from the language of the Paris Agreement, we infer that the DAI begins at warming greater than 1.5 °C. Our criteria for extending the risk category beyond DAI include the potential risks of climate change to the physical climate system, the ecosystem, human health, and species extinction. Let us first consider the category of catastrophic (3 to 5 °C warming). The first major concern is the issue of tipping points. Several studies (48, 49) have concluded that 3 to 5 °C global warming is likely to be the threshold for tipping points such as the collapse of the western Antarctic ice sheet, shutdown of deep water circulation in the North Atlantic, dieback of Amazon rainforests as well as boreal forests, and collapse of the West African monsoon, among others. While natural scientists refer to these as abrupt and irreversible climate changes, economists refer to them as catastrophic events (49). Warming of such magnitudes also has catastrophic human health effects. Many recent studies (50, 51) have focused on the direct influence of extreme events such as heat waves on public health by evaluating exposure to heat stress and hyperthermia. It has been estimated that the likelihood of extreme events (defined as 3-sigma events), including heat waves, has increased 10-fold in the recent decades (52). Human beings are extremely sensitive to heat stress. For example, the 2013 European heat wave led to about 70,000 premature mortalities (53). The major finding of a recent study (51) is that, currently, about 13.6% of land area with a population of 30.6% is exposed to deadly heat. The authors of that study defined deadly heat as exceeding a threshold of temperature as well as humidity. The thresholds were determined from numerous heat wave events and data for mortalities attributed to heat waves. According to this study, a 2 °C warming would double the land area subject to deadly heat and expose 48% of the population. A 4 °C warming by 2100 would subject 47% of the land area and almost 74% of the world population to deadly heat, which could pose existential risks to humans and mammals alike unless massive adaptation measures are implemented, such as providing air conditioning to the entire population or a massive relocation of most of the population to safer climates. Climate risks can vary markedly depending on the socioeconomic status and culture of the population, and so we must take up the question of “dangerous to whom?” (54). Our discussion in this study is focused more on people and not on the ecosystem, and even with this limited scope, there are multitudes of categories of people. We will focus on the poorest 3 billion people living mostly in tropical rural areas, who are still relying on 18th-century technologies for meeting basic needs such as cooking and heating. Their contribution to CO2 pollution is roughly 5% compared with the 50% contribution by the wealthiest 1 billion (55). This bottom 3 billion population comprises mostly subsistent farmers, whose livelihood will be severely impacted, if not destroyed, with a one- to five-year megadrought, heat waves, or heavy floods; for those among the bottom 3 billion of the world’s population who are living in coastal areas, a 1- to 2-m rise in sea level (likely with a warming in excess of 3 °C) poses existential threat if they do not relocate or migrate. It has been estimated that several hundred million people would be subject to famine with warming in excess of 4 °C (54). However, there has essentially been no discussion on warming beyond 5 °C. Climate change-induced species extinction is one major concern with warming of such large magnitudes (>5 °C). The current rate of loss of species is ∼1,000-fold the historical rate, due largely to habitat destruction. At this rate, about 25% of species are in danger of extinction in the coming decades (56). Global warming of 6 °C or more (accompanied by increase in ocean acidity due to increased CO2) can act as a major force multiplier and expose as much as 90% of species to the dangers of extinction (57). The bodily harms combined with climate change-forced species destruction, biodiversity loss, and threats to water and food security, as summarized recently (58), motivated us to categorize warming beyond 5 °C as unknown??, implying the possibility of existential threats. Fig. 2 displays these three risk categorizations (vertical dashed lines).
5,043
<h4>Extinction</h4><p>Yangyang <strong>Xu 17</strong>, Assistant Professor of Atmospheric Sciences at Texas A&M University; and Veerabhadran Ramanathan, Distinguished Professor of Atmospheric and Climate Sciences at the Scripps Institution of Oceanography, University of California, San Diego, 9/26/17, “Well below 2 °C: Mitigation strategies for avoiding dangerous to catastrophic climate changes,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, Vol. 114, No. 39, p. 10315-10323</p><p><u>We are proposing the following</u> extension to the DAI <u>risk categorization: warming greater than 1.5 °C as “dangerous</u>”; <u>warming greater than 3 °C as “catastrophic?”; and <mark>warming in excess of</u> <u>5 °</mark>C as “unknown</u>??,” with the understanding that <u>changes of this magnitude, not experienced in the last 20+ million years, <mark>pose <strong>existential threats</strong></mark> to a majority of the population</u>. The question mark denotes the subjective nature of our deduction and the fact that catastrophe can strike at even lower warming levels. The justifications for the proposed extension to risk categorization are given below.</p><p>From the IPCC burning embers diagram and from the language of the Paris Agreement, we infer that the DAI begins at warming greater than 1.5 °C. <u>Our <mark>criteria for</mark> extending the risk category</u> beyond DAI <u>include</u> the <u>potential <mark>risks of climate change to</mark> the physical climate system, <mark>the ecosystem</mark>, human health, <mark>and <strong>species extinction</u></strong></mark>. Let us first consider the category of catastrophic (3 to 5 °C warming). <u>The <mark>first</mark> major concern <mark>is</u></mark> the issue of <u><strong><mark>tipping points</u></strong></mark>. Several studies (48, 49) have concluded that <u><mark>3 to 5 °C</mark> global warming <mark>is</mark> likely to be <mark>the threshold for tipping points</mark> such as the collapse of the western Antarctic ice sheet, shutdown of deep water circulation</u> in the North Atlantic, <u>dieback of Amazon rainforests</u> as well as boreal forests, and <u>collapse of the West African monsoon</u>, among others. While <u>natural scientists refer to these as <strong><mark>abrupt and irreversible climate changes</u></strong></mark>, economists refer to them as catastrophic events (49).</p><p><u>Warming of such magnitudes</u> also <u>has <strong>catastrophic human health effects</u></strong>. Many recent studies (50, 51) have focused on the direct influence of extreme events such as heat waves on public health by evaluating exposure to heat stress and hyperthermia. It has been estimated that the likelihood of extreme events (defined as 3-sigma events), including heat waves, has increased 10-fold in the recent decades (52). Human beings are extremely sensitive to heat stress. For example, the 2013 European heat wave led to about 70,000 premature mortalities (53). The major finding of a recent study (51) is that, currently, about 13.6% of land area with a population of 30.6% is exposed to deadly heat. The authors of that study defined deadly heat as exceeding a threshold of temperature as well as humidity. The thresholds were determined from numerous heat wave events and data for mortalities attributed to heat waves. According to this study, a <u>2 °C warming would double the land area subject to deadly heat and expose 48% of the population</u>. A <u><mark>4 °C</u></mark> warming by 2100 <u>would subject</u> 47% of the land area and almost <u>74% of the world population to deadly heat, which <mark>could pose <strong>existential risks to humans</u></strong></mark> and mammals alike <u>unless massive adaptation measures are implemented</u>, such as providing air conditioning to the entire population or a massive relocation of most of the population to safer climates.</p><p><u>Climate risks</u> can <u>vary markedly depending on</u> the <u>socioeconomic status</u> and culture of the population, and so we must take up the question of “dangerous to whom?” (54). Our discussion in this study is focused more on people and not on the ecosystem, and even with this limited scope, there are multitudes of categories of people. We will focus on <u>the poorest 3 billion people</u> living mostly in tropical rural areas, who are still relying on 18th-century technologies for meeting basic needs such as cooking and heating. Their contribution to CO2 pollution is roughly 5% compared with the 50% contribution by the wealthiest 1 billion (55). This bottom 3 billion population comprises mostly subsistent farmers, whose <u>livelihood will be severely impacted, if not destroyed</u>, with a one- to five-year megadrought, heat waves, or heavy floods; for those among the bottom 3 billion of the world’s population who are living in coastal areas, a 1- to 2-m <u>rise in sea level (likely with</u> a <u>warming in excess of 3 °C) poses <strong>existential threat</u></strong> if they do not relocate or migrate. It has been estimated that <u>several hundred million people would be subject to famine</u> with warming in excess of 4 °C (54). However, there has essentially been no discussion on warming beyond 5 °C.</p><p><u>Climate change-induced species extinction is one major concern with warming of such large magnitudes (>5 °C</u>). The current rate of loss of species is ∼1,000-fold the historical rate, due largely to habitat destruction. At this rate, about 25% of species are in danger of extinction in the coming decades (56). Global <u>warming of <mark>6 °C</mark> or more</u> (<u><mark>accompanied by</mark> increase in <mark>ocean acidity</u></mark> due to increased CO2) <u>can act as a major force multiplier and <strong><mark>expose</u></strong></mark> as much as <u><strong><mark>90% of species to</u></strong></mark> the dangers of <u><strong><mark>extinction</u></strong></mark> (57).</p><p>The bodily harms combined with <u><mark>climate change-forced</mark> species destruction, <mark>biodiversity loss</mark>, and <mark>threats to water and food security</u></mark>, as summarized recently (58), <u><mark>motivated us to categorize warming</mark> beyond 5 °C <mark>as</mark> unknown</u>??, <u>implying</u> the possibility of <u><strong><mark>existential threats</u></strong></mark>. Fig. 2 displays these three risk categorizations (vertical dashed lines).</p>
1NC
null
1NC
80,386
858
116,654
./documents/ndtceda17/Northwestern/CaEs/Northwestern-Callahan-Esman-Neg-Ada-Round4.docx
599,613
N
Ada
4
Georgia Weintraub-Yonter
OGorman
1AC - Single Payer 1NC - Midterms DA - Deficit DA - EHR CP - Medicare Part E CP - Medicaid Federalism DA - Economy Turns - Case 2NC - EHR CP - Economy Turns - Case 1NR - Midterms DA 2NR - Midterms DA - Economy Turns - Case
ndtceda17/Northwestern/CaEs/Northwestern-Callahan-Esman-Neg-Ada-Round4.docx
null
51,028
CaEs
Northwestern CaEs
null
Ch.....
Ca.....
Pa.....
Es.....
19,135
Northwestern
Northwestern
null
null
1,007
ndtceda17
NDT/CEDA 2017-18
2,017
cx
college
2
4,075,290
A] Governments must aggregate because their policies benefit some and harm others so the only non-arbitrary way to prioritize is by helping the most amount of people
Mack 4
Mack 4 [(Peter, MBBS, FRCS(Ed), FRCS (Glasg), PhD, MBA, MHlthEcon) “Utilitarian Ethics in Healthcare.” International Journal of the Computer, the Internet, and Management Vol. 12, No.3. 2004. Department of Surgery. Singapore General Hospital.] SJDI
The traditional stance is that each patient is an isolated universe. when the decision involves more than just his own patient other issues have to be considered. unbridled advocacy of the patient may not square with the most advantageous policy to society as a whole. in decisions involving multiple patients more expenses for one will mean less for another. The physician is compelled to enter into a decision mode of one versus many, where the underlying constraint is finiteness of the commodities. ethics is identified with the investigation of rationally justifiable bases for resolving conflict among persons with divergent aims Because of the scarcity of resources, one’s success is another person’s failure. Therefore ethics search for rationally justifiable standards for the resolution of interpersonal conflict. While the realities of human life have given rise to the concepts of property, justice and scarcity, the management of scarcity requires the exercise of choice Exercising choice in turn involves comparisons based on principles. the meaning of these principles must be sought in the moral basis that implementing them would require. all distributive questions should be settled according to which distribution maximises welfare. these tenets require that a policy be judged solely in terms of the resulting utilities achieved by individuals as assessed by the individuals themselves. Issues of who receives the utility, the source of the utility and any non-utility aspects of the situation are ignored.
when the decision involves more other issues have to be considered. unbridled advocacy may not square with the most advantageous policy to society more expenses for one mean less for another. Because of the scarcity of resources ethics search for rationally justifiable standards for the resolution of interpersonal conflict. distributive questions should maximise welfare. policy be judged solely in terms of the resulting utilities
Medicine is a costly science, but of greater concern to the health economist is that it is also a limitless art. Every medical advance created new needs that did not exist until the means of meeting them came into existence. Physicians are reputed to have an infinite capacity to do ever more things, and perform ever more expensive interventions for their patients so long as any of their patients’ health needs remain unfulfilled. The traditional stance of the physician is that each patient is an isolated universe. When confronted with a situation in which his duty involves a competition for scarce medications or treatments, he would plead the patient’s cause by all methods, short of deceit. However, when the physician’s decision involves more than just his own patient, or has some commitment to public health, other issues have to be considered. He then has to recognise that the unbridled advocacy of the patient may not square with what the economist perceives to be the most advantageous policy to society as a whole. Medical professionals characteristically deplore scarcities. Many of them are simply not prepared to modify their intransigent principle of unwavering duty to their patients’ individual interest. However, in decisions involving multiple patients, making available more medication, labour or expenses for one patient will mean leaving less for another. The physician is then compelled by his competing loyalties to enter into a decision mode of one versus many, where the underlying constraint is one of finiteness of the commodities. Although the medical treatment may be simple and inexpensive in many instances, there are situations such as in renal dialysis, where prioritisation of treatment poses a moral dilemma because some patients will be denied the treatment and perish. Ethics and economics share areas of overlap. They both deal with how people should behave, what policies the state should pursue and what obligations citizens owe to their governments. The centrality of the human person in both normative economics and normative ethics is pertinent to this discussion. Economics is the study of human action in the marketplace whereas ethics deals with the “rightness” or “wrongness” of human action in general. Both disciplines are rooted in human reason and human nature and the two disciplines intersect at the human person and the analysis of human action. From the economist’s perspective, ethics is identified with the investigation of rationally justifiable bases for resolving conflict among persons with divergent aims and who share a common world. Because of the scarcity of resources, one’s success is another person’s failure. Therefore ethics search for rationally justifiable standards for the resolution of interpersonal conflict. While the realities of human life have given rise to the concepts of property, justice and scarcity, the management of scarcity requires the exercise of choice, since having more of some goods means having less of others. Exercising choice in turn involves comparisons, and comparisons are based on principles. As ethicists, the meaning of these principles must be sought in the moral basis that implementing them would require. For instance, if the implementation of distributive justice in healthcare is founded on the basis of welfare-based principles, as opposed to say resource-based principles, it means that the health system is motivated by the idea that what is of primary moral importance is the level of welfare of the people. This means that all distributive questions should be settled according to which distribution maximises welfare. Utilitarianism is fundamentally welfarist in its philosophy. Application of the principle to healthcare requires a prior understanding of the welfarist theory as expounded by the economist. Conceptually, welfarist theory is built on four tenets: utility maximisation, consumer sovereignty, consequentialism and welfarism. Utility maximisation embodies the behavioural proposition that individuals choose rationally, but it does not address the morality of rational choice. Consumer sovereignty is the maxim that individuals are the best judge of their own welfare. Consequentialism holds that any action or choice must be judged exclusively in terms of outcomes. Welfarism is the proposition that the “goodness” of the resource allocation be judged solely on the welfare or utility levels in that situation. Taken together these four tenets require that a policy be judged solely in terms of the resulting utilities achieved by individuals as assessed by the individuals themselves. Issues of who receives the utility, the source of the utility and any non-utility aspects of the situation are ignored.
4,743
<h4><u>A] Governments must aggregate because their policies benefit some and harm others so the only non-arbitrary way to prioritize is by helping the most amount of people</h4><p><strong>Mack 4</strong> [(Peter, MBBS, FRCS(Ed), FRCS (Glasg), PhD, MBA, MHlthEcon) “Utilitarian Ethics in Healthcare.” International Journal of the Computer, the Internet, and Management Vol. 12, No.3. 2004. Department of Surgery. Singapore General Hospital.] SJDI</p><p></u>Medicine is a costly science, but of greater concern to the health economist is that it is also a limitless art. Every medical advance created new needs that did not exist until the means of meeting them came into existence. Physicians are reputed to have an infinite capacity to do ever more things, and perform ever more expensive interventions for their patients so long as any of their patients’ health needs remain unfulfilled. <u><strong>The traditional stance </u></strong>of the physician<u><strong> is that each patient is an isolated universe. </u></strong>When confronted with a situation in which his duty involves a competition for scarce medications or treatments, he would plead the patient’s cause by all methods, short of deceit. However, <u><strong><mark>when the</mark> </u></strong>physician’s<u><strong> <mark>decision involves more</mark> than just his own patient</u></strong>, or has some commitment to public health,<u><strong> <mark>other issues have to be considered.</mark> </u></strong>He then has to recognise that the<u><strong> <mark>unbridled advocacy</mark> of the patient <mark>may not square with</u></strong></mark> what the economist perceives to be <u><strong><mark>the most advantageous policy to society</mark> as a whole.</u></strong> Medical professionals characteristically deplore scarcities. Many of them are simply not prepared to modify their intransigent principle of unwavering duty to their patients’ individual interest. However, <u><strong>in decisions involving multiple patients</u></strong>, making available <u><strong><mark>more</mark> </u></strong>medication, labour or <u><strong><mark>expenses for one</mark> </u></strong>patient <u><strong>will <mark>mean</mark> </u></strong>leaving <u><strong><mark>less for another.</mark> The physician is</u></strong> then <u><strong>compelled</u></strong> by his competing loyalties <u><strong>to enter into a decision mode of one versus many, where the underlying constraint is</u></strong> one of <u><strong>finiteness of the commodities.</u></strong> Although the medical treatment may be simple and inexpensive in many instances, there are situations such as in renal dialysis, where prioritisation of treatment poses a moral dilemma because some patients will be denied the treatment and perish. Ethics and economics share areas of overlap. They both deal with how people should behave, what policies the state should pursue and what obligations citizens owe to their governments. The centrality of the human person in both normative economics and normative ethics is pertinent to this discussion. Economics is the study of human action in the marketplace whereas ethics deals with the “rightness” or “wrongness” of human action in general. Both disciplines are rooted in human reason and human nature and the two disciplines intersect at the human person and the analysis of human action. From the economist’s perspective, <u><strong>ethics is identified with the investigation of rationally justifiable bases for resolving conflict among persons with divergent aims</u></strong> and who share a common world. <u><strong><mark>Because of the scarcity of resources</mark>, one’s success is another person’s failure. Therefore <mark>ethics search for rationally justifiable standards for the resolution of interpersonal conflict.</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>While the realities of human life have given rise to the concepts of property, justice and scarcity, the management of scarcity requires the exercise of choice</u></strong>, since having more of some goods means having less of others. <u><strong>Exercising choice in turn involves </u></strong>comparisons, and <u><strong>comparisons </u></strong>are <u><strong>based on principles. </u></strong>As ethicists, <u><strong>the meaning of these principles must be sought in the moral basis that implementing them would require.</u></strong> For instance, if the implementation of distributive justice in healthcare is founded on the basis of welfare-based principles, as opposed to say resource-based principles, it means that the health system is motivated by the idea that what is of primary moral importance is the level of welfare of the people. This means that <u><strong>all <mark>distributive questions should </mark>be settled according to which distribution <mark>maximise</mark>s<mark> welfare.</u></strong></mark> Utilitarianism is fundamentally welfarist in its philosophy. Application of the principle to healthcare requires a prior understanding of the welfarist theory as expounded by the economist. Conceptually, welfarist theory is built on four tenets: utility maximisation, consumer sovereignty, consequentialism and welfarism. Utility maximisation embodies the behavioural proposition that individuals choose rationally, but it does not address the morality of rational choice. Consumer sovereignty is the maxim that individuals are the best judge of their own welfare. Consequentialism holds that any action or choice must be judged exclusively in terms of outcomes. Welfarism is the proposition that the “goodness” of the resource allocation be judged solely on the welfare or utility levels in that situation. Taken together <u><strong>these</u></strong> four <u><strong>tenets require that a <mark>policy be judged solely in terms of the resulting utilities</mark> achieved by individuals as assessed by the individuals themselves. Issues of who receives the utility, the source of the utility and any non-utility aspects of the situation are ignored.</p></u></strong>
1NC
OFF
Standard
327,526
594
139,594
./documents/hsld22/MontaVista/KeRa/MontaVista-KeRa-Neg-Mid-America-Cup-Round-5.docx
929,297
N
Mid America Cup
5
Scripps Ranch Agastya Sridharan
Xie
1AC - levinas + adv 1NC - util, po cp, data da, innovation da, case 1AR - 5 new + benatar 2NR - rvi 2AR - all
hsld22/MontaVista/KeRa/MontaVista-KeRa-Neg-Mid-America-Cup-Round-5.docx
2022-09-25 15:39:56
80,360
KeRa
Monta Vista KeRa
hola.
Ke.....
Ra.....
null
null
26,996
MontaVista
Monta Vista
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
2,654,075
No space war
Pavur 19 AMarb
Pavur 19—DPhil Researcher Cybersecurity Centre for Doctoral Training at Oxford University [James Pavur and Ivan Martinovic (Professor of Computer Science Department of Computer Science at Oxford University), 2019, “The Cyber-ASAT: On the Impact of Cyber Weapons in Outer Space”, 2019 11th International Conference on Cyber Conflict: Silent Battle T. Minárik, S. Alatalu, S. Biondi, M. Signoretti, I. Tolga, G. Visky (Eds.), https://ccdcoe.org/uploads/2019/06/Art_12_The-Cyber-ASAT.pdf] AMarb
a launch programme alone does not guarantee the resources and precision required to operate a meaningful ASAT capability. space wars have not broken out because only the US has ever had the ability to fight one Although launch technology may become cheaper and easier, it is unclear to what extent these advances will be distributed among presently non-spacefaring nations. Limited access to orbit necessarily reduces the scenarios which could plausibly escalate to ASAT usage. fragility of an attacker’s own space assets creates de-escalatory pressures due to the deterrent effect of retaliation. Since the space race, dominant powers have recognized this dynamic and demonstrated an inclination towards de-escalatory space strategies There exists a long-standing normative framework favouring the peaceful use of space. (OST) supported over six decades of relative peace in orbit. norms have become deeply ingrained into the way states describe and perceive space weaponization. Although states have occasionally pushed the boundaries of these norms, this occurred through incremental legal re-interpretation states perceive real costs to breaking this normative tradition and may even moderate their behaviours accordingly. high degree of attributability surrounding ASAT weapons. plausible deniability and stealth are essentially impossible. This imposes high diplomatic costs on ASAT usage A third stabilizing force relates to the orbital debris consequences Since debris particles are indiscriminate and unpredictable, they often threaten the attacker’s own space assets cascade effect of an ASAT attack can constrain the attacker’s long-term use of space Space debris thus acts as a strong strategic deterrent to ASAT usage.
space wars have not broken out Limited access to orbit reduces scenarios which could escalate fragility of an attacker’s own assets creates de-escalatory pressures due to deterrent effect of retaliation. powers demonstrated towards de-escalatory space strategies (OST), supported six decades of peace states perceive costs to breaking this tradition and moderate their behaviours plausible deniability and stealth are impossible. stabilizing force relates to debris consequences debris are indiscriminate they threaten the attacker’s own space assets
A. Limited Accessibility Space is difficult. Over 60 years have passed since the first Sputnik launch and only nine countries (ten including the EU) have orbital launch capabilities. Moreover, a launch programme alone does not guarantee the resources and precision required to operate a meaningful ASAT capability. Given this, one possible reason why space wars have not broken out is simply because only the US has ever had the ability to fight one [21, p. 402], [22, pp. 419–420]. Although launch technology may become cheaper and easier, it is unclear to what extent these advances will be distributed among presently non-spacefaring nations. Limited access to orbit necessarily reduces the scenarios which could plausibly escalate to ASAT usage. Only major conflicts between the handful of states with ‘space club’ membership could be considered possible flashpoints. Even then, the fragility of an attacker’s own space assets creates de-escalatory pressures due to the deterrent effect of retaliation. Since the earliest days of the space race, dominant powers have recognized this dynamic and demonstrated an inclination towards de-escalatory space strategies [23]. B. Attributable Norms There also exists a long-standing normative framework favouring the peaceful use of space. The effectiveness of this regime, centred around the Outer Space Treaty (OST), is highly contentious and many have pointed out its serious legal and political shortcomings [24]–[26]. Nevertheless, this status quo framework has somehow supported over six decades of relative peace in orbit. Over these six decades, norms have become deeply ingrained into the way states describe and perceive space weaponization. This de facto codification was dramatically demonstrated in 2005 when the US found itself on the short end of a 160-1 UN vote after opposing a non-binding resolution on space weaponization. Although states have occasionally pushed the boundaries of these norms, this has typically occurred through incremental legal re-interpretation rather than outright opposition [27]. Even the most notable incidents, such as the 2007-2008 US and Chinese ASAT demonstrations, were couched in rhetoric from both the norm violators and defenders, depicting space as a peaceful global commons [27, p. 56]. Altogether, this suggests that states perceive real costs to breaking this normative tradition and may even moderate their behaviours accordingly. One further factor supporting this norms regime is the high degree of attributability surrounding ASAT weapons. For kinetic ASAT technology, plausible deniability and stealth are essentially impossible. The literally explosive act of launching a rocket cannot evade detection and, if used offensively, retaliation. This imposes high diplomatic costs on ASAT usage and testing, particularly during peacetime. C. Environmental Interdependence A third stabilizing force relates to the orbital debris consequences of ASATs. China’s 2007 ASAT demonstration was the largest debris-generating event in history, as the targeted satellite dissipated into thousands of dangerous debris particles [28, p. 4]. Since debris particles are indiscriminate and unpredictable, they often threaten the attacker’s own space assets [22, p. 420]. This is compounded by Kessler syndrome, a phenomenon whereby orbital debris ‘breeds’ as large pieces of debris collide and disintegrate. As space debris remains in orbit for hundreds of years, the cascade effect of an ASAT attack can constrain the attacker’s long-term use of space [29, pp. 295– 296]. Any state with kinetic ASAT capabilities will likely also operate satellites of its own, and they are necessarily exposed to this collateral damage threat. Space debris thus acts as a strong strategic deterrent to ASAT usage.
3,786
<h4>No space war</h4><p><strong>Pavur 19</strong>—DPhil Researcher Cybersecurity Centre for Doctoral Training at Oxford University [James Pavur and Ivan Martinovic (Professor of Computer Science Department of Computer Science at Oxford University), 2019, “The Cyber-ASAT: On the Impact of Cyber Weapons in Outer Space”, 2019 11th International Conference on Cyber Conflict: Silent Battle T. Minárik, S. Alatalu, S. Biondi, M. Signoretti, I. Tolga, G. Visky (Eds.), https://ccdcoe.org/uploads/2019/06/Art_12_The-Cyber-ASAT.pdf] <u><strong>AMarb</p><p></u></strong>A. Limited Accessibility Space is difficult. Over 60 years have passed since the first Sputnik launch and only nine countries (ten including the EU) have orbital launch capabilities. Moreover, <u><strong>a launch programme alone does not guarantee the resources and precision required to operate a meaningful ASAT capability.</u></strong> Given this, one possible reason why <u><strong><mark>space wars have not broken out</u></strong></mark> is simply <u><strong>because only the US has ever had the ability to fight one</u></strong> [21, p. 402], [22, pp. 419–420]. <u><strong>Although launch technology may become cheaper and easier, it is unclear to what extent these advances will be distributed among presently non-spacefaring nations. <mark>Limited access to orbit</mark> necessarily <mark>reduces</mark> the <mark>scenarios which could</mark> plausibly <mark>escalate</mark> to ASAT usage.</u></strong> Only major conflicts between the handful of states with ‘space club’ membership could be considered possible flashpoints. Even then, the <u><strong><mark>fragility of an attacker’s own</mark> space <mark>assets creates de-escalatory pressures due to</mark> the <mark>deterrent effect of retaliation.</mark> Since</u></strong> the earliest days of <u><strong>the space race, dominant <mark>powers</mark> have recognized this dynamic and <mark>demonstrated</mark> an inclination <mark>towards de-escalatory space strategies</u></strong></mark> [23]. B. Attributable Norms <u><strong>There</u></strong> also <u><strong>exists a long-standing normative framework favouring the peaceful use of space.</u></strong> The effectiveness of this regime, centred around the Outer Space Treaty <u><strong><mark>(OST)</u></strong>,</mark> is highly contentious and many have pointed out its serious legal and political shortcomings [24]–[26]. Nevertheless, this status quo framework has somehow <u><strong><mark>supported</mark> over <mark>six decades of</mark> relative <mark>peace</mark> in orbit.</u></strong> Over these six decades, <u><strong>norms have become deeply ingrained into the way states describe and perceive space weaponization.</u></strong> This de facto codification was dramatically demonstrated in 2005 when the US found itself on the short end of a 160-1 UN vote after opposing a non-binding resolution on space weaponization. <u><strong>Although states have occasionally pushed the boundaries of these norms, this</u></strong> has typically <u><strong>occurred through incremental legal re-interpretation</u></strong> rather than outright opposition [27]. Even the most notable incidents, such as the 2007-2008 US and Chinese ASAT demonstrations, were couched in rhetoric from both the norm violators and defenders, depicting space as a peaceful global commons [27, p. 56]. Altogether, this suggests that <u><strong><mark>states perceive</mark> real <mark>costs to breaking this</mark> normative <mark>tradition and</mark> may even <mark>moderate their behaviours</mark> accordingly.</u></strong> One further factor supporting this norms regime is the <u><strong>high degree of attributability surrounding ASAT weapons.</u></strong> For kinetic ASAT technology, <u><strong><mark>plausible deniability and stealth are</mark> essentially <mark>impossible.</u></strong></mark> The literally explosive act of launching a rocket cannot evade detection and, if used offensively, retaliation. <u><strong>This imposes high diplomatic costs on ASAT usage </u></strong>and testing, particularly during peacetime. C. Environmental Interdependence <u><strong>A third <mark>stabilizing force relates to</mark> the orbital <mark>debris consequences</u></strong></mark> of ASATs. China’s 2007 ASAT demonstration was the largest debris-generating event in history, as the targeted satellite dissipated into thousands of dangerous debris particles [28, p. 4]. <u><strong>Since <mark>debris</mark> particles <mark>are indiscriminate</mark> and unpredictable, <mark>they</mark> often <mark>threaten the attacker’s own space assets</u></strong></mark> [22, p. 420]. This is compounded by Kessler syndrome, a phenomenon whereby orbital debris ‘breeds’ as large pieces of debris collide and disintegrate. As space debris remains in orbit for hundreds of years, the <u><strong>cascade effect of an ASAT attack can constrain the attacker’s long-term use of space</u></strong> [29, pp. 295– 296]. Any state with kinetic ASAT capabilities will likely also operate satellites of its own, and they are necessarily exposed to this collateral damage threat.<u><strong> Space debris thus acts as a strong strategic deterrent to ASAT usage.</p></u></strong>
null
null
1nc prolif advantage
13,310
927
84,343
./documents/ndtceda19/WakeForest/KlMa/Wake%20Forest-Klein-Marban-Neg-Navy-Round6.docx
615,940
N
Navy
6
Dartmouth GM
Theo Noparstak
1ac - russia ssa 1nc - t with t stm nearly all pic sda pic consult nato CP daska DA kinetic DA space dominance good 1nc - t with daska DA 1nr - space dominance good 2nr - daska DA
ndtceda19/WakeForest/KlMa/Wake%20Forest-Klein-Marban-Neg-Navy-Round6.docx
null
52,124
KlMa
Wake Forest KlMa
null
Ru.....
Kl.....
Al.....
Ma.....
19,292
WakeForest
Wake Forest
null
null
1,009
ndtceda19
NDT/CEDA 2019-20
2,019
cx
college
2
2,470,723
Pursuit is inevitable---decline causes lashout and global war.
Beckley 15
Michael Beckley 15. Michael Beckley is a research fellow in the International Security Program at Harvard Kennedy School’s Belfer Center for Science and International Affairs., “The Myth of Entangling Alliances Michael Beckley Reassessing the Security Risks of U.S. Defense Pacts”, http://live.belfercenter.org/files/IS3904_pp007-048.pdf
The finding that entanglement is rare has important implications for international relations scholarship it casts doubt on classic theories of imperial overstretch The U.S. experience instead suggests that great powers can dictate the terms of their security commitments and that allies often help their great power protectors avoid strategic overextension. the rarity of U.S. entanglement suggests that the United States’ current grand strategy of deep engagement may facilitate military restraint The most egregious cases of U.S. overreach have stemmed not from entangling but from the penchant of American leaders to define national interests expansively, disengaging from alliances may unleash the U S to intervene recklessly while leaving it without partners to share the burden when those interventions go awry.
entanglement is rare great powers dictate terms of security allies help avoid overextension rarity of entanglement suggests deep engagement facilitate military restraint most egregious cases of overreach stemmed not from entangling but from penchant of leaders to define national interests expansively disengaging may unleash U S to intervene recklessly leaving it without partners when interventions go awry
The finding that U.S. entanglement is rare has important implications for international relations scholarship and U.S. foreign policy. For scholars, it casts doubt on classic theories of imperial overstretch in which great powers exhaust their resources by accumulating allies that free ride on their protection and embroil them in military quagmires.22 The U.S. experience instead suggests that great powers can dictate the terms of their security commitments and that allies often help their great power protectors avoid strategic overextension. For policy, the rarity of U.S. entanglement suggests that the United States’ current grand strategy of deep engagement, which is centered on a network of standing alliances, does not preclude, and may even facilitate, U.S. military restraint. Since 1945 the United States has been, by some measures, the most militarily active state in the world. The most egregious cases of U.S. overreach, however, have stemmed not from entangling alliances, but from the penchant of American leaders to define national interests expansively, to overestimate the magnitude of foreign threats, and to underestimate the costs of military intervention. Scrapping alliances will not correct these bad habits. In fact, disengaging from alliances may unleash the United States to intervene recklessly abroad while leaving it without partners to share the burden when those interventions go awry.
1,422
<h4>Pursuit is inevitable---decline causes lashout and <u>global war</u>.</h4><p>Michael<strong> Beckley 15</strong>. Michael Beckley is a research fellow in the International Security Program at Harvard Kennedy School’s Belfer Center for Science and International Affairs., “The Myth of Entangling Alliances Michael Beckley Reassessing the Security Risks of U.S. Defense Pacts”, <u>http://live.belfercenter.org/files/IS3904_pp007-048.pdf</p><p>The finding that</u> U.S. <u><mark>entanglement is rare<strong></mark> has important implications for international relations scholarship</u></strong> and U.S. foreign policy. For scholars, <u><strong>it casts doubt on classic theories of imperial overstretch</u></strong> in which great powers exhaust their resources by accumulating allies that free ride on their protection and embroil them in military quagmires.22 <u>The U.S. experience instead suggests that <strong><mark>great powers</mark> can <mark>dictate</mark> the <mark>terms of</mark> their <mark>security</mark> commitments and that <mark>allies</mark> often <mark>help</mark> their great power protectors <mark>avoid</mark> strategic <mark>overextension</mark>. </u></strong>For policy, <u>the <mark>rarity of</mark> U.S. <mark>entanglement suggests</mark> that the United States’ current grand strategy of <mark>deep engagement</u></mark>, which is centered on a network of standing alliances, does not preclude, and <u>may</u> even <u><mark>facilitate</u></mark>, U.S. <u><strong><mark>military restraint</u></strong></mark>. Since 1945 the United States has been, by some measures, the most militarily active state in the world. <u>The <mark>most egregious cases of</mark> U.S. <mark>overreach</u></mark>, however, <u><strong>have <mark>stemmed not from entangling</mark> </u></strong>alliances, <u><mark>but from</mark> the <mark>penchant of</mark> American <mark>leaders <strong>to define national interests expansively</strong></mark>, </u>to overestimate the magnitude of foreign threats, and to underestimate the costs of military intervention. Scrapping alliances will not correct these bad habits. In fact, <u><mark>disengaging</mark> from alliances <mark>may unleash</mark> the <strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><strong><mark>to intervene recklessly</u></strong></mark> abroad <u>while <strong><mark>leaving it without partners</strong></mark> to share the burden <strong><mark>when</mark> those <mark>interventions go awry</strong></mark>.</p></u>
1AC
1AC
Debris Adv---1AC
2,213
760
80,308
./documents/ndtceda19/Emory/CaPa/Emory-Castro-Pak-Aff-3%20-%20Texas-Doubles.docx
610,899
A
3 - Texas
Doubles
Baylor RW
Sean Kennedy, Adam Lipton, Pirzada Ahmad
1AC - ADR - Russia - Adv - Debris 2NR - K - Hegemony Bad
ndtceda19/Emory/CaPa/Emory-Castro-Pak-Aff-3%20-%20Texas-Doubles.docx
null
51,762
CaPa
Emory CaPa
null
Ke.....
Ca.....
An.....
Pa.....
19,247
Emory
Emory
null
null
1,009
ndtceda19
NDT/CEDA 2019-20
2,019
cx
college
2
2,018,838
Staking out an uncooperative role creates scope for states to mitigate warming
Galbraith 17
Jean Galbraith 17, Assistant Professor at University of Pennsylvania Law School, JD from the University of California-Berkeley School of Law, Order of the Coif, BA in Social Studies and the Comparative Study of Religion from Harvard University, “Book Review: Cooperative and Uncooperative Foreign Affairs Federalism, Foreign Affairs Federalism: The Myth of National Exclusivity”, Harvard Law Review, 130 Harv. L. Rev. 2131, Lexis
Mitigating climate change is a challenge for all levels of government -- international, national, state, and local states have embraced climate change mitigation measures In doing so, states have coordinated with foreign counterparts State legislation requires sweeping emissions reductions; California and Quebec sought to integrate cap-and-trade programs; and California has spearheaded a coalition of state and local governments around the world who have committed to climate policy. California even sent a large and high-profile delegation to the United Nations conference on climate change in Paris in 2015. The actions of state governments in this space invite constitutional inquiry. Can California enter into a agreement with other subnational governments, and send to international conferences? During Obama state efforts to reduce g h g emissions were not only congruent with the C A A but also with the executive branch All this will disappear under Trump Trump may try to roll back climate change mitigation efforts by progressive states in addition to reversing international commitments. If it does so the legal questions would center on the norms that govern regulatory practice Sometimes state activity occurs against a backdrop of federal inaction But interaction is far more common sometimes full of contestation scholarship offers insights into how state governments can influence and resist federal policy These themes manifest themselves in foreign affairs This leads to differences between cooperative and uncooperative federalism in foreign affairs examples reflect an "increasing concentration of power at Washington the interactive nature of modern federalism provides state governments with ways to influence federal policy. State and local actors exercise "the power . . . of the servant," which offers the chance "not just to complain about national policy, but to help set it." In shaping federal policy state governments can engage in "uncooperative federalism," including by resisting federal policies that they are charged with enforcing state governments can shape federal policy through their roles in implementing federal law these interactions can affect the distribution of power With regard to climate states have used the power of the servant to try to shape federal policy, including efforts by conservative states to push back against the federal regulatory scheme and by progressive states to make it stronger the more that state governments enhance federal efforts to mitigate climate change, then the more the U S does with respect to addressing this global problem
Mitigating climate is for all levels states embraced In doing coordinated foreign legislation requires sweeping reductions actions invite constitutional inquiry During Obama efforts were congruent this disappear under Trump Trump may roll back mitigation If so questions center on norms that govern practice activity is sometimes full of contestation state s can influence policy in foreign affairs This leads to uncooperative federalism uncoop can shape policy interactions affect distribution With climate states shape policy, including to push back the federal scheme the more state governments enhance efforts to mitigate the more U S does to address this problem
D. Climate Policy Mitigating climate change is a challenge for all levels of government -- international, national, state, and local. As Glennon and Sloane note, some states and cities have embraced climate change mitigation measures (pp. 62-63). In doing so, states have often coordinated with each other and with foreign counterparts in both practical and [*2149] expressivist ways (pp. 62-63). California's efforts are exceptionally notable. State legislation requires sweeping emissions reductions; California and Quebec have sought to integrate their cap-and-trade programs; and California has spearheaded a coalition of state and local governments around the world who have committed to climate policy. California even sent a large and high-profile delegation to the United Nations conference on climate change in Paris in 2015. The issue of climate policy is a rebuttal to all three of the "myths" identified by Glennon and Sloane. It is self-evidently a matter of both domestic and foreign affairs; states and local governments are acting in this space; and some states and local governments are doing so in progressive ways. The actions of state and local governments in this space invite constitutional inquiry. Can California constitutionally regulate carbon emissions, enter into a highly formalized agreement with Quebec and softer agreements with other subnational governments, and send delegations to international negotiating conferences? Yet focusing exclusively on these questions would lead to a highly incomplete sense of the legal scope of California's power to act. For although Glennon and Sloane do not mention it, California is acting amidst a welter of federal laws, regulations, and other executive branch actions applicable to climate change. In 2007, in a lawsuit brought by liberal states against the EPA, the Supreme Court held that the federal Clean Air Act applies to greenhouse gas emissions. This Act explicitly delegates authority to California to pursue stronger emissions [*2150] measures for new motor vehicles than are undertaken at the federal level and in general involves states in the Act's enforcement through cooperative federalism. During the Obama Administration, state and local government efforts to reduce greenhouse gas emissions were not only congruent with the aims of the Clean Air Act (as interpreted to apply to greenhouse gases), but also with the goals of the executive branch. The EPA during the Obama Administration applauded and sought to facilitate state and local efforts. Its leading rule on climate change mitigation measures, known as the Clean Power Plan, explicitly gave states substantial autonomy in crafting their own approaches, although this rule is currently facing a court challenge brought by states that oppose federal efforts to regulate emissions. The Obama White House expressed approval of the transnational coalitions that California and other state and local governments have joined in seeking to address climate change. All this positive reinforcement will presumably diminish or disappear under the Trump Administration. The Trump Administration may even try to roll back climate change mitigation efforts by progressive states and cities, in addition to undermining or reversing Obama era regulations and international commitments. If it does so, however, the legal questions that such efforts would raise probably have fairly [*2151] little to do with the constitutional issues posed by traditional foreign affairs federalism. Instead, they would center on administrative law -- around the interpretation of the Clean Air Act and the laws and norms that govern regulatory practice -- as they had already come to do by the end of the George W. Bush Administration. * * * These four illustrations are far from unique. Sometimes state and local government activity in relation to foreign affairs occurs against a backdrop of federal inaction, as is the case with the incorporation of unratified human rights treaties into the municipal law of progressive cities. But interaction is far more common, sometimes cooperative and sometimes full of contestation. The executive branch approves of and provides some support for states and cities seeking to promote tourism or encourage exports abroad. The federal government collaborates with states in determining U.S. international negotiating positions with respect to insurance. In private international law, the federal government has shown strong interest in using state law rather than federal law to implement certain treaties. And all levels of government deal with security -- both traditional and cyber -- and interact with each other over it. To understand what is going on, we must focus on the political branches as much as (or even more than) the courts. And we must think not just in terms of constitutional law, but also in terms of international law, administrative law, and state law. [*2152] III. COOPERATIVE AND UNCOOPERATIVE FEDERALISM IN THE CONTEXT OF FOREIGN AFFAIRS As foreign affairs federalism becomes increasingly interactive, how much will it resemble cooperative and uncooperative federalism in the domestic context? At the very least, scholarship on cooperative and uncooperative federalism as a domestic matter, especially work focused on the political branches, provides a valuable starting point for understanding foreign affairs federalism today. This scholarship offers insights into how the federal government can incentivize state and local governments to help advance federal interests, how these state and local governments can in turn influence and resist federal policy, and how Congress and the executive branch can each use state and local action to build power at the expense of the other branch. These broad themes manifest themselves in the foreign affairs context as well. Yet the foreign affairs context brings some additional complexities because of its ties to international law and global governance and because it comes with stronger presidential powers. This leads to certain differences between cooperative and uncooperative federalism in the realm of foreign affairs, in terms of both how practice proceeds and of what doctrine should be. A. Structural Implications The interactions between the federal government and state and local governments in relation to foreign affairs mean that federal policy shapes state and local policy. By providing assistance, financial and otherwise, to the sister-cities program, the federal government makes it easier for cities to participate. By signaling its support for state "Buy American" laws, Congress encourages them -- and the Department of Transportation incentivizes them even further by refusing to participate in contracts governed by state "Buy American" laws that are less strict than the federal ones. In the context of immigration and climate change, the federal government incentivizes (and sometimes comes close to forcing) state and local action in support of federal policy. All of these examples in the foreign affairs context reflect an "increasing concentration of power at Washington in the instigation and supervision of local policies," just as cooperative federalism arrangements do in the domestic context. In work focused on the domestic context, Heather Gerken shows that the interactive nature of modern federalism also provides state and local governments with ways to influence federal policy. State and local actors exercise "the power . . . of the servant," which offers the [*2153] chance "not just to complain about national policy, but to help set it." In shaping federal policy, these actors are not simply employing the traditional tools of process federalism; rather, it is their role in administering federal policy that gives them a say in the shape that this implementation will take. Yet the scope of this role also limits what they can do: "power dynamics are fluid; minority rule is contingent, limited, and subject to reversal by the national majority." In related work, Gerken and Jessica Bulman-Pozen elaborate on the ways in which state and local governments can engage in "uncooperative federalism," including by resisting federal policies that they are charged with enforcing. Building on the core insight that state and local governments can help shape federal policy through their roles in implementing federal law, Bulman-Pozen further shows that these interactions can affect the distribution of power between Congress and the executive branch. In a pair of articles, she describes the ways in which state and local activities can strengthen the powers of one branch against the other. The more that Congress invites or effectively requires state and local participation in the administration of a federal statutory regime, the more these actors can serve as checks on the executive branch's power to implement this regime. On the flip side, such shared roles in implementing previously enacted statutory schemes can empower the executive branch and subnational executive actors to work together in ways that crowd out the current Congress. [*2154] Similar dynamics can occur with respect to foreign affairs federalism. Indeed, some of the examples that Gerken and Bulman-Pozen focus on are issues that have transnational implications. With regard to climate, for example, they show how states have used the power of the servant to try to shape federal policy, including efforts by conservative states to push back against the federal regulatory scheme and by progressive states to make it stronger. Bulman-Pozen also uses climate as an example of how "federal and state executives negotiate without Congress" once a broad statutory scheme is in place. Some payoffs for the foreign affairs context here are simply derivative: the more that state and local governments enhance or reduce federal efforts to mitigate climate change, then the more or less the United States does with respect to addressing this global problem. But other implications relate specifically to how the United States engages internationally. Continuing with the climate context, the extent to which President Obama could make commitments on behalf of the United States during the negotiations for the 2015 Paris Agreement was largely limited by the scope of the Clean Air Act, since he had no realistic chance of getting new congressional legislation that would advance his goals with respect to climate. But since California and other progressive state and local actors were doing more than what the Clean Air Act required, President Obama could take this into account in setting the target to which the United States was committing with respect to climate change mitigation. President Obama's option set was thus enhanced by state and local action in the climate context.
10,834
<h4>Staking out an <u>uncooperative</u> role creates <u>scope</u> for states to mitigate <u>warming</h4><p></u>Jean <strong>Galbraith 17</strong>, Assistant Professor at University of Pennsylvania Law School, JD from the University of California-Berkeley School of Law, Order of the Coif, BA in Social Studies and the Comparative Study of Religion from Harvard University, “Book Review: Cooperative and Uncooperative Foreign Affairs Federalism, Foreign Affairs Federalism: The Myth of National Exclusivity”, Harvard Law Review, 130 Harv. L. Rev. 2131, Lexis</p><p>D. Climate Policy</p><p><u><mark>Mitigating climate</mark> change <mark>is</mark> a challenge <mark>for <strong>all levels</strong></mark> of government -- international, national, state, and local</u>. As Glennon and Sloane note, some <u><mark>states</u></mark> and cities <u>have <mark>embraced</mark> climate change mitigation measures</u> (pp. 62-63). <u><mark>In doing</mark> so, states have</u> often <u><mark>coordinated</u></mark> with each other and <u>with <strong><mark>foreign</mark> counterparts</u></strong> in both practical and [*2149] expressivist ways (pp. 62-63). California's efforts are exceptionally notable. <u>State <mark>legislation requires <strong>sweeping</strong></mark> emissions <mark>reductions</mark>; California and Quebec</u> have <u>sought to integrate</u> their <u>cap-and-trade programs; and California has spearheaded a coalition of state and local governments around the world who have committed to climate policy. California even sent a large and high-profile delegation to the United Nations conference on climate change in Paris in 2015.</p><p></u>The issue of climate policy is a rebuttal to all three of the "myths" identified by Glennon and Sloane. It is self-evidently a matter of both domestic and foreign affairs; states and local governments are acting in this space; and some states and local governments are doing so in progressive ways. <u>The <mark>actions</mark> of state</u> and local <u>governments in this space <mark>invite <strong>constitutional inquiry</strong></mark>. Can California</u> constitutionally regulate carbon emissions, <u>enter into a</u> highly formalized <u>agreement with</u> Quebec and softer agreements with <u>other subnational governments, and send</u> delegations <u>to international</u> negotiating <u>conferences?</p><p></u>Yet focusing exclusively on these questions would lead to a highly incomplete sense of the legal scope of California's power to act. For although Glennon and Sloane do not mention it, California is acting amidst a welter of federal laws, regulations, and other executive branch actions applicable to climate change. In 2007, in a lawsuit brought by liberal states against the EPA, the Supreme Court held that the federal Clean Air Act applies to greenhouse gas emissions. This Act explicitly delegates authority to California to pursue stronger emissions [*2150] measures for new motor vehicles than are undertaken at the federal level and in general involves states in the Act's enforcement through cooperative federalism.</p><p><u><mark>During</u></mark> the <u><mark>Obama</u></mark> Administration, <u>state</u> and local government <u><mark>efforts</mark> to reduce <strong>g</u></strong>reen<u><strong>h</u></strong>ouse <u><strong>g</u></strong>as <u>emissions <mark>were</mark> not only <strong><mark>congruent</strong></mark> with the</u> aims of the <u><strong>C</u></strong>lean <u><strong>A</u></strong>ir <u><strong>A</u></strong>ct (as interpreted to apply to greenhouse gases), <u>but also with the</u> goals of the <u>executive branch</u>. The EPA during the Obama Administration applauded and sought to facilitate state and local efforts. Its leading rule on climate change mitigation measures, known as the Clean Power Plan, explicitly gave states substantial autonomy in crafting their own approaches, although this rule is currently facing a court challenge brought by states that oppose federal efforts to regulate emissions. The Obama White House expressed approval of the transnational coalitions that California and other state and local governments have joined in seeking to address climate change.</p><p><u>All <mark>this</u></mark> positive reinforcement <u>will</u> presumably diminish or <u><mark>disappear under</u></mark> the <u><mark>Trump</u></mark> Administration. The <u><mark>Trump</u></mark> Administration <u><mark>may</u></mark> even <u>try to <strong><mark>roll back</strong></mark> climate change <mark>mitigation</mark> efforts by progressive states</u> and cities, <u>in addition to</u> undermining or <u>reversing</u> Obama era regulations and <u>international commitments. <mark>If</mark> it does <mark>so</u></mark>, however, <u>the legal <mark>questions</u></mark> that such efforts would raise probably have fairly [*2151] little to do with the constitutional issues posed by traditional foreign affairs federalism. Instead, they <u>would <mark>center on</u></mark> administrative law -- around the interpretation of the Clean Air Act and <u>the</u> laws and <u><strong><mark>norms</strong> that <strong>govern</mark> regulatory <mark>practice</u></strong></mark> -- as they had already come to do by the end of the George W. Bush Administration.</p><p>* * *</p><p>These four illustrations are far from unique. <u>Sometimes state</u> and local government <u><mark>activity</u></mark> in relation to foreign affairs <u>occurs against a backdrop of federal inaction</u>, as is the case with the incorporation of unratified human rights treaties into the municipal law of progressive cities. <u>But <strong>interaction</strong> <mark>is</mark> far more common</u>, sometimes cooperative and <u><mark>sometimes full of <strong>contestation</u></strong></mark>. The executive branch approves of and provides some support for states and cities seeking to promote tourism or encourage exports abroad. The federal government collaborates with states in determining U.S. international negotiating positions with respect to insurance. In private international law, the federal government has shown strong interest in using state law rather than federal law to implement certain treaties. And all levels of government deal with security -- both traditional and cyber -- and interact with each other over it. To understand what is going on, we must focus on the political branches as much as (or even more than) the courts. And we must think not just in terms of constitutional law, but also in terms of international law, administrative law, and state law.</p><p> [*2152] III. COOPERATIVE AND UNCOOPERATIVE FEDERALISM IN THE CONTEXT OF FOREIGN AFFAIRS</p><p>As foreign affairs federalism becomes increasingly interactive, how much will it resemble cooperative and uncooperative federalism in the domestic context? At the very least, scholarship on cooperative and uncooperative federalism as a domestic matter, especially work focused on the political branches, provides a valuable starting point for understanding foreign affairs federalism today. This <u>scholarship offers insights into</u> how the federal government can incentivize state and local governments to help advance federal interests, <u>how</u> these <u><strong><mark>state</u></strong></mark> and local <u>government<strong><mark>s</strong> can</u></mark> in turn <u><strong><mark>influence</strong></mark> and <strong>resist</strong> federal <mark>policy</u></mark>, and how Congress and the executive branch can each use state and local action to build power at the expense of the other branch. <u>These</u> broad <u>themes manifest themselves <mark>in</u></mark> the <u><strong><mark>foreign affairs</u></strong></mark> context as well. Yet the foreign affairs context brings some additional complexities because of its ties to international law and global governance and because it comes with stronger presidential powers. <u><mark>This leads to</u></mark> certain <u>differences between cooperative and <strong><mark>uncooperative federalism</strong></mark> in</u> the realm of <u>foreign affairs</u>, in terms of both how practice proceeds and of what doctrine should be.</p><p>A. Structural Implications</p><p>The interactions between the federal government and state and local governments in relation to foreign affairs mean that federal policy shapes state and local policy. By providing assistance, financial and otherwise, to the sister-cities program, the federal government makes it easier for cities to participate. By signaling its support for state "Buy American" laws, Congress encourages them -- and the Department of Transportation incentivizes them even further by refusing to participate in contracts governed by state "Buy American" laws that are less strict than the federal ones. In the context of immigration and climate change, the federal government incentivizes (and sometimes comes close to forcing) state and local action in support of federal policy. All of these <u>examples</u> in the foreign affairs context <u>reflect an "increasing concentration of power at Washington</u> in the instigation and supervision of local policies," just as cooperative federalism arrangements do in the domestic context.</p><p>In work focused on the domestic context, Heather Gerken shows that <u>the interactive nature of modern federalism</u> also <u>provides state</u> and local <u>governments with ways to <strong>influence federal policy</strong>. State and local actors exercise "the power . . . of the servant," which offers the</u> [*2153] <u>chance "not just to complain about national policy, but to help <strong>set it</strong>." In shaping federal policy</u>, these actors are not simply employing the traditional tools of process federalism; rather, it is their role in administering federal policy that gives them a say in the shape that this implementation will take. Yet the scope of this role also limits what they can do: "power dynamics are fluid; minority rule is contingent, limited, and subject to reversal by the national majority." In related work, Gerken and Jessica Bulman-Pozen elaborate on the ways in which <u>state</u> and local <u>governments can engage in <strong>"<mark>uncoop</mark>erative federalism,"</strong> including by <strong>resisting</strong> federal policies that they are charged with enforcing</u>.</p><p>Building on the core insight that <u>state</u> and local <u>governments <mark>can</u></mark> help <u><strong><mark>shape</mark> federal <mark>policy</strong></mark> through their roles in implementing federal law</u>, Bulman-Pozen further shows that <u>these <mark>interactions</mark> can <strong><mark>affect</mark> the <mark>distribution</mark> of power</u></strong> between Congress and the executive branch. In a pair of articles, she describes the ways in which state and local activities can strengthen the powers of one branch against the other. The more that Congress invites or effectively requires state and local participation in the administration of a federal statutory regime, the more these actors can serve as checks on the executive branch's power to implement this regime. On the flip side, such shared roles in implementing previously enacted statutory schemes can empower the executive branch and subnational executive actors to work together in ways that crowd out the current Congress.</p><p> [*2154] Similar dynamics can occur with respect to foreign affairs federalism. Indeed, some of the examples that Gerken and Bulman-Pozen focus on are issues that have transnational implications. <u><mark>With</mark> regard to <strong><mark>climate</u></strong></mark>, for example, they show how <u><mark>states</mark> have used the power of the servant to try to <strong><mark>shape</mark> federal <mark>policy</strong>, including</mark> efforts by conservative states <mark>to <strong>push back</strong></mark> against <mark>the <strong>federal</mark> regulatory <mark>scheme</strong></mark> and by progressive states to make it stronger</u>. Bulman-Pozen also uses climate as an example of how "federal and state executives negotiate without Congress" once a broad statutory scheme is in place. Some payoffs for the foreign affairs context here are simply derivative: <u><mark>the more</mark> that <mark>state</u></mark> and local <u><mark>governments enhance</u></mark> or reduce <u>federal <mark>efforts to mitigate</mark> climate change, then <mark>the more</u></mark> or less <u>the <strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>does</mark> with respect <mark>to <strong>address</mark>ing <mark>this</mark> global <mark>problem</u></strong></mark>. But other implications relate specifically to how the United States engages internationally. Continuing with the climate context, the extent to which President Obama could make commitments on behalf of the United States during the negotiations for the 2015 Paris Agreement was largely limited by the scope of the Clean Air Act, since he had no realistic chance of getting new congressional legislation that would advance his goals with respect to climate. But since California and other progressive state and local actors were doing more than what the Clean Air Act required, President Obama could take this into account in setting the target to which the United States was committing with respect to climate change mitigation. President Obama's option set was thus enhanced by state and local action in the climate context.</p>
1NC
CP
null
7,198
710
59,743
./documents/hspolicy20/ShawneeMissionSouth/ShSm/Shawnee%20Mission%20South-Shaw-Smith-Neg-Heart%20of%20Texas-Round6.docx
739,411
N
Heart of Texas
6
Solorio RR
Nasim Salehitezangi
1AC - Corporate Crime 1NC - T Courts Neolib K Stimulus 3 DA NGA CP Courts CP 2NR - Neolib K
hspolicy20/ShawneeMissionSouth/ShSm/Shawnee%20Mission%20South-Shaw-Smith-Neg-Heart%20of%20Texas-Round6.docx
null
63,007
ShSm
Shawnee Mission South ShSm
null
Ja.....
Sh.....
An.....
Sm.....
21,800
ShawneeMissionSouth
Shawnee Mission South
KS
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
936,466
New pandemics are coming and cause extinction – preventative measures solve
Diamandis 21
Diamandis 21 (Eleftherios P. Diamandis, Division Head of Clinical Biochemistry at Mount Sinai Hospital and Biochemist-in-Chief at the University Health Network and is Professor & Head, Clinical Biochemistry, Department of Laboratory Medicine and Pathobiology, University of Toronto, Ontario, Canada, April 14th 2021, “The Mother of All Battles: Viruses vs. Humans. Can Humans Avoid Extinction in 50-100 Years?” modified to fix author typo [“could result n” “could result in” https://www.preprints.org/manuscript/202104.0397/v1) MULCH
The recent SARS-CoV-2 pandemic, which is causing COVID 19 disease, has taught us unexpected lessons about the dangers of human extinction through highly contagious and lethal diseases. COVID 19 pandemic is now being controlled by various isolation measures, therapeutics and vaccines, it became clear that our current lifestyle and societal functions may not be sustainable in the long term. We now have to start thinking and planning on how to face the next dangerous pandemic, . Is there any evidence that even worse pandemics could strike us in the near future and threaten the existence of the human race? The answer is unequivocally yes. It is not necessary to get infected by viruses of bats, pangolins and other exotic animals that live in remote forests in order to be in danger. Creditable scientific evidence indicates that the human gut microbiota harbor billions of viruses which are capable of affecting the function of vital human organs such as the immune system, lung, brain, liver, kidney, heart etc. These diseases could result [in] the complete shutdown of our civilization and probably the extinction of human race I will first provide a few independent pieces of scientific facts and then combine this information to come up with some (but certainly not all) hypothetical scenarios that could cause human race misery, even extinction. I hope that these scary scenarios will trigger preventative measures that could reverse or delay the projected adverse outcomes.
COVID taught us about dangers of extinction through diseases We have to start planning on the next pandemic, Is there evi worse pandemics strike in the near future and threaten the existence of the human race? unequivocally yes the human gut harbor billions of viruses capable of affecting organs diseases could result [in] shutdown of civilization and extinction preventative measures could reverse or delay adverse outcomes
The recent SARS-CoV-2 pandemic, which is causing COVID 19 disease, has taught us unexpected lessons about the dangers of human extinction through highly contagious and lethal diseases. As the COVID 19 pandemic is now being controlled by various isolation measures, therapeutics and vaccines, it became clear that our current lifestyle and societal functions may not be sustainable in the long term. We now have to start thinking and planning on how to face the next dangerous pandemic, not just overcoming the one that is upon us now. Is there any evidence that even worse pandemics could strike us in the near future and threaten the existence of the human race? The answer is unequivocally yes. It is not necessary to get infected by viruses of bats, pangolins and other exotic animals that live in remote forests in order to be in danger. Creditable scientific evidence indicates that the human gut microbiota harbor billions of viruses which are capable of affecting the function of vital human organs such as the immune system, lung, brain, liver, kidney, heart etc. It is possible that the development of pathogenic variants in the gut can lead to contagious viruses which can cause pandemics, leading to destruction of vital organs, causing death or various debilitating diseases such as blindness, respiratory, liver, heart and kidney failures. These diseases could result [in] the complete shutdown of our civilization and probably the extinction of human race. In this essay, I will first provide a few independent pieces of scientific facts and then combine this information to come up with some (but certainly not all) hypothetical scenarios that could cause human race misery, even extinction. I hope that these scary scenarios will trigger preventative measures that could reverse or delay the projected adverse outcomes.
1,835
<h4>New pandemics <u>are coming</u> and cause <u>extinction</u> – preventative measures solve</h4><p><strong>Diamandis 21 </strong>(Eleftherios P. Diamandis, Division Head of Clinical Biochemistry at Mount Sinai Hospital and Biochemist-in-Chief at the University Health Network and is Professor & Head, Clinical Biochemistry, Department of Laboratory Medicine and Pathobiology, University of Toronto, Ontario, Canada, April 14th 2021, “The Mother of All Battles: Viruses vs. Humans. Can Humans Avoid Extinction in 50-100 Years?” modified to fix author typo [“could result n” “could result in” https://www.preprints.org/manuscript/202104.0397/v1<u>) MULCH</p><p>The recent SARS-CoV-2 pandemic, which is causing <mark>COVID</mark> 19 disease, has<mark> taught us</mark> unexpected lessons <mark>about</mark> the <strong><mark>dangers of</mark> human <mark>extinction through</mark> highly contagious and lethal <mark>diseases</mark>.</u></strong> As the <u>COVID 19 pandemic is now being controlled by various isolation measures, therapeutics and vaccines, it became clear that our current lifestyle and societal functions may not be sustainable in the long term.</u> <u><strong><mark>We</mark> now <mark>have to start </mark>thinking and <mark>planning on</mark> how to face <mark>the next</mark> dangerous <mark>pandemic,</u></strong></mark> not just overcoming the one that is upon us now<u>. <mark>Is there</mark> any <mark>evi</mark>dence that even <mark>worse pandemics </mark>could <mark>strike</mark> us <mark>in the</mark> <strong><mark>near future</strong> and threaten the <strong>existence of the human race</strong>?</mark> The answer <strong>is <mark>unequivocally yes</mark>.</u></strong> <u>It is not necessary to get infected by viruses of bats, pangolins and other exotic animals that live in remote forests in order to be in danger. Creditable scientific evidence indicates that <mark>the human gut</mark> microbiota <strong><mark>harbor billions of viruses</strong></mark> which are <mark>capable of affecting</mark> the function of vital human <mark>organs</mark> such as the immune system, lung, brain, liver, kidney, heart etc.</u> It is possible that the development of pathogenic variants in the gut can lead to contagious viruses which can cause pandemics, leading to destruction of vital organs, causing death or various debilitating diseases such as blindness, respiratory, liver, heart and kidney failures. <u><strong>These <mark>diseases could result [in]</mark> the complete <mark>shutdown</mark> <mark>of</mark> our <mark>civilization and </mark>probably the <mark>extinction</mark> of human race</u></strong>. In this essay, <u>I will first provide a few independent pieces of scientific facts and then combine this information to come up with some (but certainly not all) hypothetical scenarios that could cause human race misery, even extinction.</u> <u>I hope that these scary scenarios will trigger <mark>preventative measures</mark> that <mark>could reverse or delay</mark> the projected <mark>adverse outcomes</mark>.</p></u>
null
NU 1AC
Innovation – 1AC
4,034
966
22,746
./documents/ndtceda21/MichiganStateUniversity/BeSc/Michigan%20State%20University-Bennett-Scott-Aff-Northwestern%20Season%20Opener-Round6.docx
625,950
A
Northwestern Season Opener
6
UTF LW
Michael Hester
1AC - Federalism and Innovation 1NC - States CP - Enforcement CP - Cap - FTC DA 2NR - Cap
ndtceda21/MichiganStateUniversity/BeSc/Michigan%20State%20University-Bennett-Scott-Aff-Northwestern%20Season%20Opener-Round6.docx
null
52,790
BeSc
Michigan State University BeSc
null
Ep.....
Be.....
Mi.....
Sc.....
19,400
MichiganStateUniversity
Michigan State University
null
null
1,011
ndtceda21
NDT/CEDA 2021-22
2,021
cx
college
2
2,128,823
Debate resource inequities—you’ll say people will steal cards, but that’s good—it’s the only way to truly level the playing field for students such as novices in under-privileged programs.
Antonucci 5
Antonucci 5 [Michael (Debate coach for Georgetown; former coach for Lexington High School); “[eDebate] open source? resp to Morris”; December 8; http://cedadebate.org/pipermail/mailman/2005 December/060990.html]
Open source systems are preferable to the various punishment proposals in circulation It's better to share the wealth than limit production or participation banning interesting or useful research(ers) seems like the most destructive solution possible , open systems may be the only structural, rule-based answer to resource inequities Every other proposal obviously fails at the level of enforcement. Revenue sharing (illegal), salary caps (unenforceable and possibly illegal) and personnel restrictions don't work. This would - for better or worse. an open source system would reduce entry barriers. This is especially true on the novice or JV level. Young teams could plausibly subsist entirely on a diet of scavenged arguments . An open source system would fundamentally change the evidence economy without targetting anyone or putting anyone out of a job
Open source systems are preferable It's better to share the wealth than limit production or participation open systems may be the only structural, rule-based answer to resource inequities. Every other proposal fails at the level of enforcement an open source system would reduce entry barriers. on the novice or JV level An open source system would fundamentally change the evidence economy without targetting anyone
a. Open source systems are preferable to the various punishment proposals in circulation. It's better to share the wealth than limit production or participation. Various flavors of argument communism appeal to different people, but banning interesting or useful research(ers) seems like the most destructive solution possible. Indeed, open systems may be the only structural, rule-based answer to resource inequities. Every other proposal I've seen obviously fails at the level of enforcement. Revenue sharing (illegal), salary caps (unenforceable and possibly illegal) and personnel restrictions (circumvented faster than you can say 'information is fungible') don't work. This would - for better or worse. b. With the help of a middling competent archivist, an open source system would reduce entry barriers. This is especially true on the novice or JV level. Young teams could plausibly subsist entirely on a diet of scavenged arguments. A novice team might not wish to do so, but the option can't hurt. c. An open source system would fundamentally change the evidence economy without targetting anyone or putting anyone out of a job. It seems much smarter (and less bilious) to change the value of a professional card-cutter's work than send the KGB after specific counter-revolutionary teams.
1,297
<h4><u>Debate resource inequities</u>—you’ll say people will steal cards, but that’s good—it’s the only way to truly level the playing field for students such as novices in under-privileged programs.</h4><p><strong>Antonucci 5</strong> [Michael (Debate coach for Georgetown; former coach for Lexington High School); “[eDebate] open source? resp to Morris”; December 8; http://cedadebate.org/pipermail/mailman/2005 December/060990.html]</p><p>a. <u><mark>Open source systems are preferable</mark> to the various punishment proposals in circulation</u>. <u><mark>It's better to share the wealth than limit production or participation</u></mark>. Various flavors of argument communism appeal to different people, but <u>banning interesting or useful research(ers) seems like the most destructive solution possible</u>. Indeed<u>, <mark>open systems may be the only structural, rule-based answer to resource inequities</u>. <u>Every other proposal</u></mark> I've seen <u>obviously <mark>fails at the level of enforcement</mark>. Revenue sharing (illegal), salary caps (unenforceable and possibly illegal) and personnel restrictions</u> (circumvented faster than you can say 'information is fungible') <u>don't work. This would - for better or worse. </u>b. With the help of a middling competent archivist, <u><mark>an open source system would reduce entry barriers. </mark>This is especially true <mark>on the novice or JV level</mark>. Young teams could plausibly subsist entirely on a diet of scavenged arguments</u>. A novice team might not wish to do so, but the option can't hurt. c<u>. <mark>An open source system would fundamentally change the evidence economy <strong>without targetting anyone</strong> </mark>or putting anyone out of a job</u>. It seems much smarter (and less bilious) to change the value of a professional card-cutter's work than send the KGB after specific counter-revolutionary teams. </p>
1NC
1
null
327,790
539
64,188
./documents/hsld20/DoughertyValley/Ko/Dougherty%20Valley-Kotapati-Neg-Arizona%20State%20University%20Invitational-Round5.docx
856,926
N
Arizona State University Invitational
5
Bellarmine DD
Rex Evans
1AC - USChina 1NC - T Bare Plurals Disclosure AI DA CP Heg case 1AR - All 2NR - T Bare Plurals 2AR - T Bare Plurals
hsld20/DoughertyValley/Ko/Dougherty%20Valley-Kotapati-Neg-Arizona%20State%20University%20Invitational-Round5.docx
null
72,920
SaKo
Dougherty Valley SaKo
null
Sa.....
Ko.....
null
null
24,491
DoughertyValley
Dougherty Valley
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
4,020,821
Warming causes extinction.
Kareiva 18
Kareiva 18, Ph.D. in ecology and applied mathematics from Cornell University, director of the Institute of the Environment and Sustainability at UCLA, Pritzker Distinguished Professor in Environment & Sustainability at UCLA, et al. (Peter, “Existential risk due to ecosystem collapse: Nature strikes back,” Futures, 102)
climate change, global freshwater cycle, and ocean acidification pose existential risks This is because of intrinsic positive feedback loops and the fact these different boundaries interact with one another in ways that yield surprises climate, freshwater, and ocean acidification are all directly connected to the provision of food and water, and shortages create conflict and social unrest Climate change intersects with freshwater resources because it is expected to exacerbate drought and water scarcity, Ample clean water is essential for human survival. Climate change also increases storm frequency and severity. Coral reefs and oyster reefs provide protection from storm surge because they reduce wave energy If these reefs are lost due to acidification at the same time as storms become more severe and sea level rises coastal communities will be exposed to unprecedented storm surge and may be ravaged by recurrent storms Society will have a hard time responding to shorter intervals between rare extreme events every 25 years, but is expected to occur once every 5 years by 2050 Humans are remarkably ingenious, and have adapted to crises throughout their history However, the many stories of human ingenuity successfully addressing existential risks represent environmental challenges that are largely linear, have immediate consequences, and operate without positive feedbacks. unlike past environmental challenges, the Earth’s climate system is rife with positive feedback loops In particular, as CO2 increases and the climate warms, that very warming can cause more CO2 release which further increases global warming, and then more CO2, and so on The expectation is that forest fires will become more frequent and severe with climate warming and drought This catastrophic fire embodies the sorts of positive feedbacks and interacting factors that could catch humanity off-guard and produce a true apocalyptic event The key lesson from the long list of potentially positive feedbacks and their interactions is that runaway climate change, and runaway perturbations have to be taken as a serious possibility this list is not exhaustive and the possibility of undiscovered positive feedbacks portends even greater existential risks
climate change and acidification pose existential risks because of positive feedback loops and food and water shortages create conflict Climate change is expected to exacerbate water scarcity clean water is essential for human survival stories of addressing existential risks represent challenges that are linear, and operate without feedbacks Earth’s climate is rife with feedback loops warming can cause more CO2 release fires will become more frequent catastrophic fire could catch humanity off-guard and produce a apocalyptic event runaway climate change portends existential risk
In summary, six of the nine proposed planetary boundaries (phosphorous, nitrogen, biodiversity, land use, atmospheric aerosol loading, and chemical pollution) are unlikely to be associated with existential risks. They all correspond to a degraded environment, but in our assessment do not represent existential risks. However, the three remaining boundaries (climate change, global freshwater cycle, and ocean acidification) do pose existential risks. This is because of intrinsic positive feedback loops, substantial lag times between system change and experiencing the consequences of that change, and the fact these different boundaries interact with one another in ways that yield surprises. In addition, climate, freshwater, and ocean acidification are all directly connected to the provision of food and water, and shortages of food and water can create conflict and social unrest. Climate change has a long history of disrupting civilizations and sometimes precipitating the collapse of cultures or mass emigrations (McMichael, 2017). For example, the 12th century drought in the North American Southwest is held responsible for the collapse of the Anasazi pueblo culture. More recently, the infamous potato famine of 1846–1849 and the large migration of Irish to the U.S. can be traced to a combination of factors, one of which was climate. Specifically, 1846 was an unusually warm and moist year in Ireland, providing the climatic conditions favorable to the fungus that caused the potato blight. As is so often the case, poor government had a role as well—as the British government forbade the import of grains from outside Britain (imports that could have helped to redress the ravaged potato yields). Climate change intersects with freshwater resources because it is expected to exacerbate drought and water scarcity, as well as flooding. Climate change can even impair water quality because it is associated with heavy rains that overwhelm sewage treatment facilities, or because it results in higher concentrations of pollutants in groundwater as a result of enhanced evaporation and reduced groundwater recharge. Ample clean water is not a luxury—it is essential for human survival. Consequently, cities, regions and nations that lack clean freshwater are vulnerable to social disruption and disease. Finally, ocean acidification is linked to climate change because it is driven by CO2 emissions just as global warming is. With close to 20% of the world’s protein coming from oceans (FAO, 2016), the potential for severe impacts due to acidification is obvious. Less obvious, but perhaps more insidious, is the interaction between climate change and the loss of oyster and coral reefs due to acidification. Acidification is known to interfere with oyster reef building and coral reefs. Climate change also increases storm frequency and severity. Coral reefs and oyster reefs provide protection from storm surge because they reduce wave energy (Spalding et al., 2014). If these reefs are lost due to acidification at the same time as storms become more severe and sea level rises, coastal communities will be exposed to unprecedented storm surge—and may be ravaged by recurrent storms. A key feature of the risk associated with climate change is that mean annual temperature and mean annual rainfall are not the variables of interest. Rather it is extreme episodic events that place nations and entire regions of the world at risk. These extreme events are by definition “rare” (once every hundred years), and changes in their likelihood are challenging to detect because of their rarity, but are exactly the manifestations of climate change that we must get better at anticipating (Diffenbaugh et al., 2017). Society will have a hard time responding to shorter intervals between rare extreme events because in the lifespan of an individual human, a person might experience as few as two or three extreme events. How likely is it that you would notice a change in the interval between events that are separated by decades, especially given that the interval is not regular but varies stochastically? A concrete example of this dilemma can be found in the past and expected future changes in storm-related flooding of New York City. The highly disruptive flooding of New York City associated with Hurricane Sandy represented a flood height that occurred once every 500 years in the 18th century, and that occurs now once every 25 years, but is expected to occur once every 5 years by 2050 (Garner et al., 2017). This change in frequency of extreme floods has profound implications for the measures New York City should take to protect its infrastructure and its population, yet because of the stochastic nature of such events, this shift in flood frequency is an elevated risk that will go unnoticed by most people. 4. The combination of positive feedback loops and societal inertia is fertile ground for global environmental catastrophes Humans are remarkably ingenious, and have adapted to crises throughout their history. Our doom has been repeatedly predicted, only to be averted by innovation (Ridley, 2011). However, the many stories of human ingenuity successfully addressing existential risks such as global famine or extreme air pollution represent environmental challenges that are largely linear, have immediate consequences, and operate without positive feedbacks. For example, the fact that food is in short supply does not increase the rate at which humans consume food—thereby increasing the shortage. Similarly, massive air pollution episodes such as the London fog of 1952 that killed 12,000 people did not make future air pollution events more likely. In fact it was just the opposite—the London fog sent such a clear message that Britain quickly enacted pollution control measures (Stradling, 2016). Food shortages, air pollution, water pollution, etc. send immediate signals to society of harm, which then trigger a negative feedback of society seeking to reduce the harm. In contrast, today’s great environmental crisis of climate change may cause some harm but there are generally long time delays between rising CO2 concentrations and damage to humans. The consequence of these delays are an absence of urgency; thus although 70% of Americans believe global warming is happening, only 40% think it will harm them (http://climatecommunication.yale.edu/visualizations-data/ycom-us-2016/). Secondly, unlike past environmental challenges, the Earth’s climate system is rife with positive feedback loops. In particular, as CO2 increases and the climate warms, that very warming can cause more CO2 release which further increases global warming, and then more CO2, and so on. Table 2 summarizes the best documented positive feedback loops for the Earth’s climate system. These feedbacks can be neatly categorized into carbon cycle, biogeochemical, biogeophysical, cloud, ice-albedo, and water vapor feedbacks. As important as it is to understand these feedbacks individually, it is even more essential to study the interactive nature of these feedbacks. Modeling studies show that when interactions among feedback loops are included, uncertainty increases dramatically and there is a heightened potential for perturbations to be magnified (e.g., Cox, Betts, Jones, Spall, & Totterdell, 2000; Hajima, Tachiiri, Ito, & Kawamiya, 2014; Knutti & Rugenstein, 2015; Rosenfeld, Sherwood, Wood, & Donner, 2014). This produces a wide range of future scenarios. Positive feedbacks in the carbon cycle involves the enhancement of future carbon contributions to the atmosphere due to some initial increase in atmospheric CO2. This happens because as CO2 accumulates, it reduces the efficiency in which oceans and terrestrial ecosystems sequester carbon, which in return feeds back to exacerbate climate change (Friedlingstein et al., 2001). Warming can also increase the rate at which organic matter decays and carbon is released into the atmosphere, thereby causing more warming (Melillo et al., 2017). Increases in food shortages and lack of water is also of major concern when biogeophysical feedback mechanisms perpetuate drought conditions. The underlying mechanism here is that losses in vegetation increases the surface albedo, which suppresses rainfall, and thus enhances future vegetation loss and more suppression of rainfall—thereby initiating or prolonging a drought (Chamey, Stone, & Quirk, 1975). To top it off, overgrazing depletes the soil, leading to augmented vegetation loss (Anderies, Janssen, & Walker, 2002). Climate change often also increases the risk of forest fires, as a result of higher temperatures and persistent drought conditions. The expectation is that forest fires will become more frequent and severe with climate warming and drought (Scholze, Knorr, Arnell, & Prentice, 2006), a trend for which we have already seen evidence (Allen et al., 2010). Tragically, the increased severity and risk of Southern California wildfires recently predicted by climate scientists (Jin et al., 2015), was realized in December 2017, with the largest fire in the history of California (the “Thomas fire” that burned 282,000 acres, https://www.vox.com/2017/12/27/16822180/thomas-fire-california-largest-wildfire). This catastrophic fire embodies the sorts of positive feedbacks and interacting factors that could catch humanity off-guard and produce a true apocalyptic event. Record-breaking rains produced an extraordinary flush of new vegetation, that then dried out as record heat waves and dry conditions took hold, coupled with stronger than normal winds, and ignition. Of course the record-fire released CO2 into the atmosphere, thereby contributing to future warming. Out of all types of feedbacks, water vapor and the ice-albedo feedbacks are the most clearly understood mechanisms. Losses in reflective snow and ice cover drive up surface temperatures, leading to even more melting of snow and ice cover—this is known as the ice-albedo feedback (Curry, Schramm, & Ebert, 1995). As snow and ice continue to melt at a more rapid pace, millions of people may be displaced by flooding risks as a consequence of sea level rise near coastal communities (Biermann & Boas, 2010; Myers, 2002; Nicholls et al., 2011). The water vapor feedback operates when warmer atmospheric conditions strengthen the saturation vapor pressure, which creates a warming effect given water vapor’s strong greenhouse gas properties (Manabe & Wetherald, 1967). Global warming tends to increase cloud formation because warmer temperatures lead to more evaporation of water into the atmosphere, and warmer temperature also allows the atmosphere to hold more water. The key question is whether this increase in clouds associated with global warming will result in a positive feedback loop (more warming) or a negative feedback loop (less warming). For decades, scientists have sought to answer this question and understand the net role clouds play in future climate projections (Schneider et al., 2017). Clouds are complex because they both have a cooling (reflecting incoming solar radiation) and warming (absorbing incoming solar radiation) effect (Lashof, DeAngelo, Saleska, & Harte, 1997). The type of cloud, altitude, and optical properties combine to determine how these countervailing effects balance out. Although still under debate, it appears that in most circumstances the cloud feedback is likely positive (Boucher et al., 2013). For example, models and observations show that increasing greenhouse gas concentrations reduces the low-level cloud fraction in the Northeast Pacific at decadal time scales. This then has a positive feedback effect and enhances climate warming since less solar radiation is reflected by the atmosphere (Clement, Burgman, & Norris, 2009). The key lesson from the long list of potentially positive feedbacks and their interactions is that runaway climate change, and runaway perturbations have to be taken as a serious possibility. Table 2 is just a snapshot of the type of feedbacks that have been identified (see Supplementary material for a more thorough explanation of positive feedback loops). However, this list is not exhaustive and the possibility of undiscovered positive feedbacks portends even greater existential risks. The many environmental crises humankind has previously averted (famine, ozone depletion, London fog, water pollution, etc.) were averted because of political will based on solid scientific understanding. We cannot count on complete scientific understanding when it comes to positive feedback loops and climate change.
12,601
<h4>Warming causes extinction. </h4><p><strong>Kareiva 18</strong>, Ph.D. in ecology and applied mathematics from Cornell University, director of the Institute of the Environment and Sustainability at UCLA, Pritzker Distinguished Professor in Environment & Sustainability at UCLA, et al. (Peter, “Existential risk due to ecosystem collapse: Nature strikes back,” Futures, 102)</p><p>In summary, six of the nine proposed planetary boundaries (phosphorous, nitrogen, biodiversity, land use, atmospheric aerosol loading, and chemical pollution) are unlikely to be associated with existential risks. They all correspond to a degraded environment, but in our assessment do not represent existential risks. However, the three remaining boundaries (<u><mark>climate</mark> <mark>change</mark>, global freshwater cycle, <mark>and</mark> ocean <mark>acidification</u></mark>) do <u><mark>pose <strong>existential risks</u></strong></mark>. <u>This is <mark>because of</mark> intrinsic <strong><mark>positive feedback loops</u></strong></mark>, substantial lag times between system change and experiencing the consequences of that change,<u> <mark>and</mark> the fact these different boundaries interact with one another in ways that yield <strong>surprises</u></strong>. In addition, <u>climate, freshwater, and ocean acidification are all directly connected to the provision of <strong><mark>food</strong> and <strong>water</strong></mark>, and <mark>shortages</u></mark> of food and water can <u><mark>create <strong>conflict</strong></mark> and social unrest</u>. Climate change has a long history of disrupting civilizations and sometimes precipitating the collapse of cultures or mass emigrations (McMichael, 2017). For example, the 12th century drought in the North American Southwest is held responsible for the collapse of the Anasazi pueblo culture. More recently, the infamous potato famine of 1846–1849 and the large migration of Irish to the U.S. can be traced to a combination of factors, one of which was climate. Specifically, 1846 was an unusually warm and moist year in Ireland, providing the climatic conditions favorable to the fungus that caused the potato blight. As is so often the case, poor government had a role as well—as the British government forbade the import of grains from outside Britain (imports that could have helped to redress the ravaged potato yields). <u><mark>Climate</mark> <mark>change</mark> intersects with freshwater resources because it <mark>is expected to <strong>exacerbate</mark> drought</strong> and</u> <u><strong><mark>water scarcity</strong></mark>, </u>as well as flooding. Climate change can even impair water quality because it is associated with heavy rains that overwhelm sewage treatment facilities, or because it results in higher concentrations of pollutants in groundwater as a result of enhanced evaporation and reduced groundwater recharge. <u>Ample <mark>clean water</u></mark> is not a luxury—it <u><mark>is essential for human survival</mark>.</u> Consequently, cities, regions and nations that lack clean freshwater are vulnerable to social disruption and disease. Finally, ocean acidification is linked to climate change because it is driven by CO2 emissions just as global warming is. With close to 20% of the world’s protein coming from oceans (FAO, 2016), the potential for severe impacts due to acidification is obvious. Less obvious, but perhaps more insidious, is the interaction between climate change and the loss of oyster and coral reefs due to acidification. Acidification is known to interfere with oyster reef building and coral reefs. <u>Climate change also increases <strong>storm frequency</strong> and severity. Coral reefs and oyster reefs provide protection from storm surge because they reduce wave energy</u> (Spalding et al., 2014). <u>If these reefs are lost due to acidification at the same time as storms become more severe and sea level rises</u>, <u><strong>coastal communities will be exposed to unprecedented storm surge</u></strong>—<u>and may be ravaged by recurrent storms</u>. A key feature of the risk associated with climate change is that mean annual temperature and mean annual rainfall are not the variables of interest. Rather it is extreme episodic events that place nations and entire regions of the world at risk. These extreme events are by definition “rare” (once every hundred years), and changes in their likelihood are challenging to detect because of their rarity, but are exactly the manifestations of climate change that we must get better at anticipating (Diffenbaugh et al., 2017). <u>Society will have a hard time responding to shorter intervals between rare <strong>extreme events</strong> </u>because in the lifespan of an individual human, a person might experience as few as two or three extreme events. How likely is it that you would notice a change in the interval between events that are separated by decades, especially given that the interval is not regular but varies stochastically? A concrete example of this dilemma can be found in the past and expected future changes in storm-related flooding of New York City. The highly disruptive flooding of New York City associated with Hurricane Sandy represented a flood height that occurred once every 500 years in the 18th century, and that occurs now once<u> every 25 years, but is expected to occur once every 5 years by 2050</u> (Garner et al., 2017). This change in frequency of extreme floods has profound implications for the measures New York City should take to protect its infrastructure and its population, yet because of the stochastic nature of such events, this shift in flood frequency is an elevated risk that will go unnoticed by most people. 4. The combination of positive feedback loops and societal inertia is fertile ground for global environmental catastrophes <u>Humans are remarkably ingenious, and have <strong>adapted</strong> to crises throughout their history</u>. Our doom has been repeatedly predicted, only to be averted by innovation (Ridley, 2011). <u>However, the many <mark>stories of</mark> human ingenuity successfully <mark>addressing existential risks</u></mark> such as global famine or extreme air pollution <u><mark>represent</mark> environmental <mark>challenges that are</mark> largely <mark>linear, </mark>have immediate consequences, <mark>and operate without</mark> positive <mark>feedbacks</mark>.</u> For example, the fact that food is in short supply does not increase the rate at which humans consume food—thereby increasing the shortage. Similarly, massive air pollution episodes such as the London fog of 1952 that killed 12,000 people did not make future air pollution events more likely. In fact it was just the opposite—the London fog sent such a clear message that Britain quickly enacted pollution control measures (Stradling, 2016). Food shortages, air pollution, water pollution, etc. send immediate signals to society of harm, which then trigger a negative feedback of society seeking to reduce the harm. In contrast, today’s great environmental crisis of climate change may cause some harm but there are generally long time delays between rising CO2 concentrations and damage to humans. The consequence of these delays are an absence of urgency; thus although 70% of Americans believe global warming is happening, only 40% think it will harm them (http://climatecommunication.yale.edu/visualizations-data/ycom-us-2016/). Secondly, <u>unlike past environmental challenges, <strong>the <mark>Earth’s climate</mark> system <mark>is rife with</mark> positive <mark>feedback loops</u></strong></mark>. <u>In particular, as CO2 increases and the climate warms, that very <mark>warming can cause more CO2</mark> <mark>release</mark> which further increases global warming, and then more CO2, and so on</u>. Table 2 summarizes the best documented positive feedback loops for the Earth’s climate system. These feedbacks can be neatly categorized into carbon cycle, biogeochemical, biogeophysical, cloud, ice-albedo, and water vapor feedbacks. As important as it is to understand these feedbacks individually, it is even more essential to study the interactive nature of these feedbacks. Modeling studies show that when interactions among feedback loops are included, uncertainty increases dramatically and there is a heightened potential for perturbations to be magnified (e.g., Cox, Betts, Jones, Spall, & Totterdell, 2000; Hajima, Tachiiri, Ito, & Kawamiya, 2014; Knutti & Rugenstein, 2015; Rosenfeld, Sherwood, Wood, & Donner, 2014). This produces a wide range of future scenarios. Positive feedbacks in the carbon cycle involves the enhancement of future carbon contributions to the atmosphere due to some initial increase in atmospheric CO2. This happens because as CO2 accumulates, it reduces the efficiency in which oceans and terrestrial ecosystems sequester carbon, which in return feeds back to exacerbate climate change (Friedlingstein et al., 2001). Warming can also increase the rate at which organic matter decays and carbon is released into the atmosphere, thereby causing more warming (Melillo et al., 2017). Increases in food shortages and lack of water is also of major concern when biogeophysical feedback mechanisms perpetuate drought conditions. The underlying mechanism here is that losses in vegetation increases the surface albedo, which suppresses rainfall, and thus enhances future vegetation loss and more suppression of rainfall—thereby initiating or prolonging a drought (Chamey, Stone, & Quirk, 1975). To top it off, overgrazing depletes the soil, leading to augmented vegetation loss (Anderies, Janssen, & Walker, 2002). Climate change often also increases the risk of forest fires, as a result of higher temperatures and persistent drought conditions. <u>The expectation is that forest <mark>fires will become more</mark> <mark>frequent</mark> and severe with climate warming and drought</u> (Scholze, Knorr, Arnell, & Prentice, 2006), a trend for which we have already seen evidence (Allen et al., 2010). Tragically, the increased severity and risk of Southern California wildfires recently predicted by climate scientists (Jin et al., 2015), was realized in December 2017, with the largest fire in the history of California (the “Thomas fire” that burned 282,000 acres, https://www.vox.com/2017/12/27/16822180/thomas-fire-california-largest-wildfire). <u>This <mark>catastrophic fire</mark> embodies the sorts of positive feedbacks and interacting factors that <mark>could <strong>catch humanity off-guard</u></strong> <u>and produce a </mark>true <strong><mark>apocalyptic event</u></strong></mark>. Record-breaking rains produced an extraordinary flush of new vegetation, that then dried out as record heat waves and dry conditions took hold, coupled with stronger than normal winds, and ignition. Of course the record-fire released CO2 into the atmosphere, thereby contributing to future warming. Out of all types of feedbacks, water vapor and the ice-albedo feedbacks are the most clearly understood mechanisms. Losses in reflective snow and ice cover drive up surface temperatures, leading to even more melting of snow and ice cover—this is known as the ice-albedo feedback (Curry, Schramm, & Ebert, 1995). As snow and ice continue to melt at a more rapid pace, millions of people may be displaced by flooding risks as a consequence of sea level rise near coastal communities (Biermann & Boas, 2010; Myers, 2002; Nicholls et al., 2011). The water vapor feedback operates when warmer atmospheric conditions strengthen the saturation vapor pressure, which creates a warming effect given water vapor’s strong greenhouse gas properties (Manabe & Wetherald, 1967). Global warming tends to increase cloud formation because warmer temperatures lead to more evaporation of water into the atmosphere, and warmer temperature also allows the atmosphere to hold more water. The key question is whether this increase in clouds associated with global warming will result in a positive feedback loop (more warming) or a negative feedback loop (less warming). For decades, scientists have sought to answer this question and understand the net role clouds play in future climate projections (Schneider et al., 2017). Clouds are complex because they both have a cooling (reflecting incoming solar radiation) and warming (absorbing incoming solar radiation) effect (Lashof, DeAngelo, Saleska, & Harte, 1997). The type of cloud, altitude, and optical properties combine to determine how these countervailing effects balance out. Although still under debate, it appears that in most circumstances the cloud feedback is likely positive (Boucher et al., 2013). For example, models and observations show that increasing greenhouse gas concentrations reduces the low-level cloud fraction in the Northeast Pacific at decadal time scales. This then has a positive feedback effect and enhances climate warming since less solar radiation is reflected by the atmosphere (Clement, Burgman, & Norris, 2009). <u>The key lesson from the long list of potentially positive feedbacks and their interactions is that</u> <u><strong><mark>runaway climate change</strong></mark>, and runaway perturbations have to be taken as a serious possibility</u>. Table 2 is just a snapshot of the type of feedbacks that have been identified (see Supplementary material for a more thorough explanation of positive feedback loops). However, <u>this list is not exhaustive and the possibility of undiscovered positive feedbacks <mark>portends</mark> <strong>even greater <mark>existential risk</mark>s</u></strong>. The many environmental crises humankind has previously averted (famine, ozone depletion, London fog, water pollution, etc.) were averted because of political will based on solid scientific understanding. We cannot count on complete scientific understanding when it comes to positive feedback loops and climate change.</p>
1AC
1AC---NDT
1AC---Europe Advantage
1,435
1,599
136,627
./documents/ndtceda20/Kansas/MaRe/Kansas-Martin-Revare-Aff-00%20NDT-Round8.docx
618,840
A
8 - NDT
8
Michigan PR
Ahmed, Habiba - Howley, Shannon - McCullough, Hunter
1AC - NEW Georgia 1NC - T Enlargement Deterrence DA Putin DA Response CP NAC CP Territories PIC Con Con CP Hicks DA Harris CP Assurance DA Adv CP A5 PIC Case 2NR - Hicks DA NAC CP
ndtceda20/Kansas/MaRe/Kansas-Martin-Revare-Aff-00%20NDT-Round8.docx
null
52,323
MaRe
Kansas MaRe
null
Na.....
Ma.....
Gr.....
Re.....
19,328
Kansas
Kansas
null
null
1,010
ndtceda20
NDT/CEDA 2020-21
2,020
cx
college
2
1,526,008
Climate change destroys the world.
Specktor 19
Specktor 19 [Brandon writes about the science of everyday life for Live Science, and previously for Reader's Digest magazine, where he served as an editor for five years] 6-4-2019, "Human Civilization Will Crumble by 2050 If We Don't Stop Climate Change Now, New Paper Claims," livescience, https://www.livescience.com/65633-climate-change-dooms-humans-by-2050.html Justin
General climate models United Nations' Panel on Climate Change fail to account for the sheer complexity of Earth's many interlinked geological processes world governments "politely ignoring" scientists the world's ice sheets vanish; brutal droughts kill many Amazon rainforest and the planet plunges into a feedback loop of ever-hotter conditions Thirty-five percent of the global land area, and 55 percent of the global population, are subject to more than 20 days a year of lethal heat conditions, beyond survivability droughts, floods and wildfires regularly ravage the land. Nearly one-third of the world's land surface turns to desert. ecosystems collapse, beginning with the planet's coral reefs, the rainforest and the Arctic ice sheets destroying the region's agriculture and turning more than 1 billion people into refugees. refugees — coupled with shrinking coastlines and severe drops in food and water availability — begin to stress the fabric of the world's largest nations Armed conflicts over resources, perhaps culminating in nuclear war, are likely. The result is "outright chaos" and perhaps "the end of human global civilization as we know it."
models fail to account for interlinked processes governments ignor scientists ice sheets vanish feedback loop Thirty-five percent of land and 55 percent of population subject to lethal heat droughts, floods and wildfires ravage the land one-third turns to desert ecosystems collapse destroying ag turning 1 bil into refugees coastlines and drops in food and water stress nations nuclear war likely end of civilization
The current climate crisis, they say, is larger and more complex than any humans have ever dealt with before. General climate models — like the one that the United Nations' Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) used in 2018 to predict that a global temperature increase of 3.6 degrees Fahrenheit (2 degrees Celsius) could put hundreds of millions of people at risk — fail to account for the sheer complexity of Earth's many interlinked geological processes; as such, they fail to adequately predict the scale of the potential consequences. The truth, the authors wrote, is probably far worse than any models can fathom. How the world ends What might an accurate worst-case picture of the planet's climate-addled future actually look like, then? The authors provide one particularly grim scenario that begins with world governments "politely ignoring" the advice of scientists and the will of the public to decarbonize the economy (finding alternative energy sources), resulting in a global temperature increase 5.4 F (3 C) by the year 2050. At this point, the world's ice sheets vanish; brutal droughts kill many of the trees in the Amazon rainforest (removing one of the world's largest carbon offsets); and the planet plunges into a feedback loop of ever-hotter, ever-deadlier conditions. "Thirty-five percent of the global land area, and 55 percent of the global population, are subject to more than 20 days a year of lethal heat conditions, beyond the threshold of human survivability," the authors hypothesized. Meanwhile, droughts, floods and wildfires regularly ravage the land. Nearly one-third of the world's land surface turns to desert. Entire ecosystems collapse, beginning with the planet's coral reefs, the rainforest and the Arctic ice sheets. The world's tropics are hit hardest by these new climate extremes, destroying the region's agriculture and turning more than 1 billion people into refugees. This mass movement of refugees — coupled with shrinking coastlines and severe drops in food and water availability — begin to stress the fabric of the world's largest nations, including the United States. Armed conflicts over resources, perhaps culminating in nuclear war, are likely. The result, according to the new paper, is "outright chaos" and perhaps "the end of human global civilization as we know it."
2,319
<h4>Climate change <u>destroys the world</u>.</h4><p><strong>Specktor 19</strong> [Brandon writes about the science of everyday life for Live Science, and previously for Reader's Digest magazine, where he served as an editor for five years] 6-4-2019, "Human Civilization Will Crumble by 2050 If We Don't Stop Climate Change Now, New Paper Claims," livescience, https://www.livescience.com/65633-climate-change-dooms-humans-by-2050.html<u> Justin</p><p></u>The current climate crisis, they say, is larger and more complex than any humans have ever dealt with before. <u>General climate <mark>models</u></mark> — like the one that the <u>United Nations' Panel on Climate Change</u> (IPCC) used in 2018 to predict that a global temperature increase of 3.6 degrees Fahrenheit (2 degrees Celsius) could put hundreds of millions of people at risk — <u><mark>fail to account for</mark> the <strong>sheer complexity of Earth's many <mark>interlinked </mark>geological <mark>processes</u></strong></mark>; as such, they fail to adequately predict the scale of the potential consequences. The truth, the authors wrote, is probably far worse than any models can fathom. How the world ends What might an accurate worst-case picture of the planet's climate-addled future actually look like, then? The authors provide one particularly grim scenario that begins with <u>world <mark>governments</mark> "politely <mark>ignor</mark>ing"</u> the advice of <u><mark>scientists</u></mark> and the will of the public to decarbonize the economy (finding alternative energy sources), resulting in a global temperature increase 5.4 F (3 C) by the year 2050. At this point, <u>the world's <mark>ice sheets vanish</mark>; brutal droughts kill many</u> of the trees in the <u>Amazon rainforest</u> (removing one of the world's largest carbon offsets); <u>and the planet plunges into a <mark>feedback loop</mark> of ever-hotter</u>, ever-deadlier <u>conditions</u>. "<u><mark>Thirty-five percent of</mark> the global <mark>land</mark> area, <mark>and <strong>55 percent of </mark>the global <mark>population</mark>, are <mark>subject to</mark> more than 20 days a year of <mark>lethal heat</mark> conditions</strong>, beyond</u> the threshold of human <u>survivability</u>," the authors hypothesized. Meanwhile, <u><mark>droughts, floods and wildfires</mark> regularly <mark>ravage the land</mark>. Nearly <strong><mark>one-third </mark>of the world's land surface <mark>turns to desert</strong></mark>.</u> Entire <u><strong><mark>ecosystems collapse</strong></mark>, beginning with the <strong>planet's coral reefs</strong>, the <strong>rainforest and the Arctic ice sheets</u>.</strong> The world's tropics are hit hardest by these new climate extremes, <u><mark>destroying</mark> the region's <mark>ag</mark>riculture and <mark>turning</mark> more than <mark>1 bil</mark>lion people <mark>into refugees</mark>. </u>This mass movement of <u>refugees — coupled with shrinking <mark>coastlines and</mark> severe <mark>drops in food and water</mark> availability — begin to <strong><mark>stress</mark> the fabric of the world's largest <mark>nations</u></strong></mark>, including the United States. <u>Armed conflicts over resources, perhaps culminating in <strong><mark>nuclear war</mark>, are <mark>likely</strong></mark>. The result</u>, according to the new paper, <u>is "outright chaos" and perhaps "the <mark>end of</mark> human global <mark>civilization</mark> as we know it."</p></u>
null
null
Advantage – Climate Change
14,523
848
43,476
./documents/hsld21/Princeton/Ro/Princeton-Rohacs-Aff-NSD-Round1.docx
897,102
A
NSD
1
MooWal Winston Wang
Jalyn Wu
1AC - Teachers 1NC - Cap 1AR - All 2NR - All 2AR - All
hsld21/Princeton/Ro/Princeton-Rohacs-Aff-NSD-Round1.docx
null
75,257
DaRo
Princeton DaRo
null
Da.....
Ro.....
null
null
25,135
Princeton
Princeton
NJ
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
1,566,181
Existential threats outweigh – all life has infinite value and extinction eliminates the possibility for future generations – err negative, because of innate cognitive biases
GPP 17
GPP 17 (Global Priorities Project, Future of Humanity Institute at the University of Oxford, Ministry for Foreign Affairs of Finland, “Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance,” Global Priorities Project, 2017, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf,
Compare three outcomes: (1) Peace. (2) A nuclear war that kills 99% of the world’s existing population. (3) A nuclear war that kills 100%. Most people believe that the greater difference is between (1) and (2). I believe that the difference between (2) and (3) is very much greater The Earth will remain habitable for at least another billion years. Civilization began only a few thousand years ago. If we do not destroy mankind, these few thousand years may be only a tiny fraction of the whole of civilized human history. The difference between (2) and (3) may thus be the difference between this tiny fraction and all of the rest of this history. If we compare this possible history to a day, what has occurred so far is only a fraction of a second.65 What makes existential catastrophes especially bad is that they would “destroy the future,” as Bostrom, puts it. This future could potentially be extremely long and full of flourishing, and would therefore have extremely large value. Because the value of preventing existential catastrophe is so vast, even a tiny probability of prevention has huge expected value. In some areas, government policy does give significant weight to future generations. However, when it comes to existential risk, it would seem that we fail to live up to principles of intergenerational equity. Existential catastrophe would not only give future generations less than the current generations; it would give them nothing. reducing existential risk plausibly has a quite low cost for us in comparison with the huge expected value it has for future generations. Unless we give up on norms of intergenerational equity, they give us a strong case for significantly increasing our efforts to reduce existential risks. In spite of the importance of existential risk reduction, it probably receives less attention than is warranted. There are several reasons why existential risk reduction is likely to be underinvested in. Firstly, it is a global public good. Economic theory predicts that such goods tend to be underprovided. The benefits of existential risk reduction are widely and indivisibly dispersed around the globe from the countries responsible for taking action. Secondly existential risk reduction is an intergenerational public good: most of the benefits are enjoyed by future generations who have no say in the political process. For these goods, the problem is temporal free riding: the current generation enjoys the benefits of inaction while future generations bear the costs. Thirdly existential risks pose an unprecedented and uncertain future threat. Cognitive biases also lead people to underestimate existential risks. Since there have not been any catastrophes of this magnitude, these risks are not salient to politicians and the public.
Compare Peace war that kills 99% war that kills 100% the difference between (2) and (3) is much greater If we do not destroy mankind these years may be a tiny fraction of the whole of civilized history existential catastrophes would destroy the future This future could be long flourishing and have large value Existential catastrophe would give future generations nothing existential risk receives less attention than warranted pose unprecedented Cognitive biases also lead people to underestimate risks Since there have not been any catastrophes of this magnitude, these risks are not salient to politicians and the public
1.2. THE ETHICS OF EXISTENTIAL RISK In his book Reasons and Persons, Oxford philosopher Derek Parfit advanced an influential argument about the importance of avoiding extinction: I believe that if we destroy mankind, as we now can, this outcome will be much worse than most people think. Compare three outcomes: (1) Peace. (2) A nuclear war that kills 99% of the world’s existing population. (3) A nuclear war that kills 100%. (2) would be worse than (1), and (3) would be worse than (2). Which is the greater of these two differences? Most people believe that the greater difference is between (1) and (2). I believe that the difference between (2) and (3) is very much greater. ... The Earth will remain habitable for at least another billion years. Civilization began only a few thousand years ago. If we do not destroy mankind, these few thousand years may be only a tiny fraction of the whole of civilized human history. The difference between (2) and (3) may thus be the difference between this tiny fraction and all of the rest of this history. If we compare this possible history to a day, what has occurred so far is only a fraction of a second.65 In this argument, it seems that Parfit is assuming that the survivors of a nuclear war that kills 99% of the population would eventually be able to recover civilisation without long-term effect. As we have seen, this may not be a safe assumption – but for the purposes of this thought experiment, the point stands. What makes existential catastrophes especially bad is that they would “destroy the future,” as another Oxford philosopher, Nick Bostrom, puts it.66 This future could potentially be extremely long and full of flourishing, and would therefore have extremely large value. In standard risk analysis, when working out how to respond to risk, we work out the expected value of risk reduction, by weighing the probability that an action will prevent an adverse event against the severity of the event. Because the value of preventing existential catastrophe is so vast, even a tiny probability of prevention has huge expected value.67 Of course, there is persisting reasonable disagreement about ethics and there are a number of ways one might resist this conclusion.68 Therefore, it would be unjustified to be overconfident in Parfit and Bostrom’s argument. In some areas, government policy does give significant weight to future generations. For example, in assessing the risks of nuclear waste storage, governments have considered timeframes of thousands, hundreds of thousands, and even a million years.69 Justifications for this policy usually appeal to principles of intergenerational equity according to which future generations ought to get as much protection as current generations.70 Similarly, widely accepted norms of sustainable development require development that meets the needs of the current generation without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs.71 However, when it comes to existential risk, it would seem that we fail to live up to principles of intergenerational equity. Existential catastrophe would not only give future generations less than the current generations; it would give them nothing. Indeed, reducing existential risk plausibly has a quite low cost for us in comparison with the huge expected value it has for future generations. In spite of this, relatively little is done to reduce existential risk. Unless we give up on norms of intergenerational equity, they give us a strong case for significantly increasing our efforts to reduce existential risks. 1.3. WHY EXISTENTIAL RISKS MAY BE SYSTEMATICALLY UNDERINVESTED IN, AND THE ROLE OF THE INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY In spite of the importance of existential risk reduction, it probably receives less attention than is warranted. As a result, concerted international cooperation is required if we are to receive adequate protection from existential risks. 1.3.1. Why existential risks are likely to be underinvested in There are several reasons why existential risk reduction is likely to be underinvested in. Firstly, it is a global public good. Economic theory predicts that such goods tend to be underprovided. The benefits of existential risk reduction are widely and indivisibly dispersed around the globe from the countries responsible for taking action. Consequently, a country which reduces existential risk gains only a small portion of the benefits but bears the full brunt of the costs. Countries thus have strong incentives to free ride, receiving the benefits of risk reduction without contributing. As a result, too few do what is in the common interest. Secondly, as already suggested above, existential risk reduction is an intergenerational public good: most of the benefits are enjoyed by future generations who have no say in the political process. For these goods, the problem is temporal free riding: the current generation enjoys the benefits of inaction while future generations bear the costs. Thirdly, many existential risks, such as machine superintelligence, engineered pandemics, and solar geoengineering, pose an unprecedented and uncertain future threat. Consequently, it is hard to develop a satisfactory governance regime for them: there are few existing governance instruments which can be applied to these risks, and it is unclear what shape new instruments should take. In this way, our position with regard to these emerging risks is comparable to the one we faced when nuclear weapons first became available. Cognitive biases also lead people to underestimate existential risks. Since there have not been any catastrophes of this magnitude, these risks are not salient to politicians and the public.
5,720
<h4>Existential threats <u>outweigh</u> – all life has <u>infinite value</u> and extinction <u>eliminates the possibility</u> for future generations – err negative, because of innate <u>cognitive biases</u> </h4><p><strong>GPP 17</strong> (Global Priorities Project, Future of Humanity Institute at the University of Oxford, Ministry for Foreign Affairs of Finland, “Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance,” Global Priorities Project, 2017, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf<u>, </p><p></u>1.2. THE ETHICS OF EXISTENTIAL RISK In his book Reasons and Persons, Oxford philosopher Derek Parfit advanced an influential argument about the importance of avoiding extinction: I believe that if we destroy mankind, as we now can, this outcome will be much worse than most people think. <u><mark>Compare</mark> three outcomes: (1) <mark>Peace</mark>. (2) A nuclear <mark>war that kills 99%</mark> of the world’s existing population. (3) A nuclear <mark>war that kills 100%</mark>. </u>(2) would be worse than (1), and (3) would be worse than (2). Which is the greater of these two differences? <u>Most people believe that the greater difference is between (1) and (2).</u> <u>I believe that <mark>the difference between (2) and (3) is</mark> very <mark>much greater</u></mark>. ... <u>The Earth will remain habitable for <strong>at least another billion years</strong>.</u> <u>Civilization began only a few thousand years ago.</u> <u><mark>If we do not destroy mankind</mark>, <mark>these</mark> few thousand <mark>years may be</mark> only <strong><mark>a tiny fraction</strong> of the whole of civilized</mark> human <mark>history</mark>.</u> <u>The difference between (2) and (3) may thus be the difference between this tiny fraction and all of the rest of this history.</u> <u>If we compare this possible history to a day, what has occurred so far is only a <strong>fraction of a second</strong>.65</u> In this argument, it seems that Parfit is assuming that the survivors of a nuclear war that kills 99% of the population would eventually be able to recover civilisation without long-term effect. As we have seen, this may not be a safe assumption – but for the purposes of this thought experiment, the point stands. <u>What makes <mark>existential catastrophes</mark> especially bad is that they <mark>would</mark> “<strong><mark>destroy the future</strong></mark>,” as</u> another Oxford philosopher, Nick <u>Bostrom, puts it.</u>66 <u><mark>This future could</mark> potentially <mark>be</mark> extremely <mark>long</mark> and full of <mark>flourishing</mark>, <mark>and</mark> would therefore <mark>have</mark> extremely <mark>large value</mark>.</u> In standard risk analysis, when working out how to respond to risk, we work out the expected value of risk reduction, by weighing the probability that an action will prevent an adverse event against the severity of the event. <u>Because the value of preventing existential catastrophe is so vast, even a tiny probability of prevention has huge expected value.</u>67 Of course, there is persisting reasonable disagreement about ethics and there are a number of ways one might resist this conclusion.68 Therefore, it would be unjustified to be overconfident in Parfit and Bostrom’s argument. <u>In some areas, government policy does give significant weight to future generations.</u> For example, in assessing the risks of nuclear waste storage, governments have considered timeframes of thousands, hundreds of thousands, and even a million years.69 Justifications for this policy usually appeal to principles of intergenerational equity according to which future generations ought to get as much protection as current generations.70 Similarly, widely accepted norms of sustainable development require development that meets the needs of the current generation without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs.71 <u>However, when it comes to existential risk, it would seem that we fail to live up to principles of intergenerational equity.</u> <u><mark>Existential catastrophe would</mark> not only <mark>give future generations</mark> less than the current generations; <strong>it would give them <mark>nothing</strong></mark>.</u> Indeed, <u>reducing existential risk plausibly has a quite low cost for us in comparison with the huge expected value it has for future generations.</u> In spite of this, relatively little is done to reduce existential risk. <u>Unless we give up on norms of intergenerational equity, they give us a strong case for significantly increasing our efforts to reduce existential risks. </u>1.3. WHY EXISTENTIAL RISKS MAY BE SYSTEMATICALLY UNDERINVESTED IN, AND THE ROLE OF THE INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY <u>In spite of the importance of <mark>existential risk</mark> reduction, it probably <mark>receives less attention than</mark> is <mark>warranted</mark>.</u> As a result, concerted international cooperation is required if we are to receive adequate protection from existential risks. 1.3.1. Why existential risks are likely to be underinvested in <u>There are several reasons why existential risk reduction is likely to be underinvested in.</u> <u>Firstly, it is a global public good.</u> <u>Economic theory predicts that such goods tend to be underprovided.</u> <u>The benefits of existential risk reduction are widely and indivisibly dispersed around the globe from the countries responsible for taking action.</u> Consequently, a country which reduces existential risk gains only a small portion of the benefits but bears the full brunt of the costs. Countries thus have strong incentives to free ride, receiving the benefits of risk reduction without contributing. As a result, too few do what is in the common interest. <u>Secondly</u>, as already suggested above, <u>existential risk reduction is an intergenerational public good: most of the benefits are enjoyed by future generations who have no say in the political process.</u> <u>For these goods, the problem is temporal free riding: the current generation enjoys the benefits of inaction while future generations bear the costs. Thirdly</u>, many <u>existential risks</u>, such as machine superintelligence, engineered pandemics, and solar geoengineering, <u><mark>pose</mark> an <mark>unprecedented</mark> and uncertain future threat.</u> Consequently, it is hard to develop a satisfactory governance regime for them: there are few existing governance instruments which can be applied to these risks, and it is unclear what shape new instruments should take. In this way, our position with regard to these emerging risks is comparable to the one we faced when nuclear weapons first became available. <u><mark>Cognitive biases also lead people to underestimate</mark> existential <mark>risks</mark>.</u> <u><mark>Since there have not been any catastrophes of this magnitude, these risks are not salient to politicians and the public</mark>.</p></u>
1AC – FW
null
null
261
2,546
45,156
./documents/hsld21/SouthlakeCarroll/Dh/Southlake%20Carroll-Dharani-Aff-Grapevine-Triples.docx
899,156
A
Grapevine
Triples
Jayden Bai
JP
1ac- cannabis 1nc- 3-4 shells kant 1ar- all 2nr- kant 2ar- case kant
hsld21/SouthlakeCarroll/Dh/Southlake%20Carroll-Dharani-Aff-Grapevine-Triples.docx
null
75,338
SaDh
Southlake Carroll SaDh
null
Sa.....
Dh.....
null
null
25,168
SouthlakeCarroll
Southlake Carroll
TX
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
4,611,682
5] Apocalyptic images challenge dominant power structures by contesting the implausibility of actions.
Hurley 17
Jessica Hurley 17, Assistant Professor in the Humanities at the University of Chicago, “Impossible Futures: Fictions of Risk in the Longue Durée”, Duke University Press, https://read.dukeupress.edu/american-literature/article/89/4/761/132823/Impossible-Futures-Fictions-of-Risk-in-the-Longue
Buell offers his suggestion for the appropriate literary mode for life lived within a crisis that is both unceasing and inescapable: new voices, “if wise enough….will abandon apocalypse for a sadder realism that recognizes crisis as a place where people dwell This essay argues for the continuing importance of apocalyptic narrative forms in representations of risk to disrupt conservative realisms that maintain the status quo. state logics of implausibility have long undergirded settler colonialism in the United States apocalyptic form deconstruct the claims to verisimilitude that undergird state realism, transforming nuclear waste into a prophecy of the end of the United States rather than a means for imagining its continuation. a deep-time perspective into contemporary America transform the present into a speculative space where catastrophe produces not only unevenly distributed damage but also revolutionary forms of social justice that insist on a truth that probability modeling cannot contain: that the future will be unimaginably different from the present, while the present, too, might yet be utterly different from the real that we think we know the apocalyptic mode in deep time allows narratives of harm and danger to move beyond the paranoid logic of risk. In the world of deep time The endless maybes of risk become certainties. The impossibilities of our own deaths and the deaths of everything else will come. But so too will other impossibilities the end of the colonial occupation of North America, perhaps, or a sudden human determination to let the world live
the continuing importance of apocalyptic narrative forms to disrupt conservative realisms that maintain the status quo. state logics of implausibility have long undergirded the United States apocalyptic form transformi nuclear waste into a prophecy of the end of the United States rather than a means for imagining its continuation perspective transform present into a speculative space where catastrophe produces not only unevenly distributed damage but also revolutionary forms of social justice the future will be unimaginably different from the present apocalyptic mode allows narratives to move beyond the paranoid logic of risk e impossibilities of our own deaths and the deaths of everything else will come. But so too will other impossibilities a human determination to let the world live
If contemporary ecocriticism has a shared premise about environmental risk it is that genre is the key to both perceiving and, possibly, correcting ecological crisis. Frederick Buell’s 2003 From Apocalypse to Way of Life: Environmental Crisis in the American Century has established one of the most central oppositions of this paradigm. As his title suggests, Buell tells the story of a discourse that began in the apocalyptic mode in the 1960s and 70s, when discussions of “the immanent end of nature” most commonly took the form of “prophecy, revelation, climax, and extermination” before turning away from apocalypse when the prophesied ends failed to arrive (112, 78). Buell offers his suggestion for the appropriate literary mode for life lived within a crisis that is both unceasing and inescapable: new voices, “if wise enough….will abandon apocalypse for a sadder realism that looks closely at social and environmental changes in process and recognizes crisis as a place where people dwell” (202-3). In a world of threat, Buell demands a realism that might help us see risks more clearly and aid our survival.¶ Buell’s argument has become a broadly held view in contemporary risk theory and ecocriticism, overlapping fields in the social sciences and humanities that address the foundational question of second modernity: “how do you live when you are at such risk?” (Woodward 2009, 205).1 Such an assertion, however, assumes both that realism is a neutral descriptive practice and that apocalypse is not something that is happening now in places that we might not see, or cannot hear. This essay argues for the continuing importance of apocalyptic narrative forms in representations of environmental risk to disrupt conservative realisms that maintain the status quo. Taking the ecological disaster of nuclear waste as my case study, I examine two fictional treatments of nuclear waste dumps that create different temporal structures within which the colonial history of the United States plays out. The first, a set of Department of Energy documents that use statistical modeling and fictional description to predict a set of realistic futures for the site of the Waste Isolation Pilot Plant in New Mexico (1991), creates a present that is fully knowable and a future that is fully predictable. Such an approach, I suggest, perpetuates the state logics of implausibility that have long undergirded settler colonialism in the United States. In contrast, Leslie Marmon Silko’s contemporaneous novel Almanac of the Dead (1991) uses its apocalyptic form to deconstruct the claims to verisimilitude that undergird state realism, transforming nuclear waste into a prophecy of the end of the United States rather than a means for imagining its continuation. In Almanac of the Dead, the presence of nuclear waste introjects a deep-time perspective into contemporary America, transforming the present into a speculative space where environmental catastrophe produces not only unevenly distributed damage but also revolutionary forms of social justice that insist on a truth that probability modeling cannot contain: that the future will be unimaginably different from the present, while the present, too, might yet be utterly different from the real that we think we know.¶ Nuclear waste is rarely treated in ecocriticism or risk theory, for several reasons: it is too manmade to be ecological; its catastrophes are ongoing, intentionally produced situations rather than sudden disasters; and it does not support the narrative that subtends ecocritical accounts of risk perception in which the nuclear threat gives rise to an awareness of other kinds of threat before reaching the end of its relevance at the end of the Cold War.2 In what follows, I argue that the failure of nuclear waste to fit into the critical frames created by ecocriticism and risk theory to date offers an opportunity to expand those frames and overcome some of their limitations, especially the impulse towards a paranoid, totalizing realism that Peter van Wyck (2005) has described as central to ecocriticism in the risk society. Nuclear waste has durational forms that dwarf the human. It therefore dwells less in the economy of risk as it is currently conceptualized and more in the blown-out realm of deep time. Inhabiting the temporal scale that has recently been christened the Anthropocene, the geological era defined by the impact of human activities on the world’s geology and climate, nuclear waste unsettles any attempt at realist description, unveiling the limits of human imagination at every turn.3 By analyzing risk society through a heuristic of nuclear waste, this essay offers a critique of nuclear colonialism and environmental racism. At the same time, it shows how the apocalyptic mode in deep time allows narratives of environmental harm and danger to move beyond the paranoid logic of risk. In the world of deep time, all that might come to pass will come to pass, sooner or later. The endless maybes of risk become certainties. The impossibilities of our own deaths and the deaths of everything else will come. But so too will other impossibilities: talking macaws and alien visitors; the end of the colonial occupation of North America, perhaps, or a sudden human determination to let the world live. The end of capitalism may yet become more thinkable than the end of the world. Just wait long enough. Stranger things will happen.¶
5,433
<h4>5] Apocalyptic images challenge dominant power structures by contesting the implausibility of actions.</h4><p>Jessica <strong>Hurley 17</strong>, Assistant Professor in the Humanities at the University of Chicago, “Impossible Futures: Fictions of Risk in the Longue Durée”, Duke University Press, https://read.dukeupress.edu/american-literature/article/89/4/761/132823/Impossible-Futures-Fictions-of-Risk-in-the-Longue</p><p>If contemporary ecocriticism has a shared premise about environmental risk it is that genre is the key to both perceiving and, possibly, correcting ecological crisis. Frederick Buell’s 2003 From Apocalypse to Way of Life: Environmental Crisis in the American Century has established one of the most central oppositions of this paradigm. As his title suggests, Buell tells the story of a discourse that began in the apocalyptic mode in the 1960s and 70s, when discussions of “the immanent end of nature” most commonly took the form of “prophecy, revelation, climax, and extermination” before turning away from apocalypse when the prophesied ends failed to arrive (112, 78). <u>Buell offers his suggestion for the appropriate literary mode for life lived within a crisis that is both unceasing and inescapable: new voices, “if wise enough….will abandon apocalypse for a sadder realism that </u>looks closely at social and environmental changes in process and <u>recognizes crisis as a place where people dwell</u>” (202-3). In a world of threat, Buell demands a realism that might help us see risks more clearly and aid our survival.¶ Buell’s argument has become a broadly held view in contemporary risk theory and ecocriticism, overlapping fields in the social sciences and humanities that address the foundational question of second modernity: “how do you live when you are at such risk?” (Woodward 2009, 205).1 Such an assertion, however, assumes both that realism is a neutral descriptive practice and that apocalypse is not something that is happening now in places that we might not see, or cannot hear. <u>This essay argues for <strong><mark>the continuing importance of apocalyptic narrative forms</strong></mark> in representations of</u> environmental <u>risk <strong><mark>to disrupt conservative realisms that maintain the status quo.</u></strong></mark> Taking the ecological disaster of nuclear waste as my case study, I examine two fictional treatments of nuclear waste dumps that create different temporal structures within which the colonial history of the United States plays out. The first, a set of Department of Energy documents that use statistical modeling and fictional description to predict a set of realistic futures for the site of the Waste Isolation Pilot Plant in New Mexico (1991), creates a present that is fully knowable and a future that is fully predictable. Such an approach, I suggest, perpetuates the <u><strong><mark>state logics of implausibility</mark> </u></strong>that <u><strong><mark>have long undergirded</strong> </mark>settler colonialism in <strong><mark>the United States</u></strong></mark>. In contrast, Leslie Marmon Silko’s contemporaneous novel Almanac of the Dead (1991) uses its <u><strong><mark>apocalyptic form</u></strong></mark> to <u>deconstruct the claims to verisimilitude that undergird state realism, <strong><mark>transform</strong>i</mark>ng <strong><mark>nuclear waste into a prophecy of the end of the United States rather than a means for imagining its continuation</strong></mark>.</u> In Almanac of the Dead, the presence of nuclear waste introjects <u>a deep-time <strong><mark>perspective</strong></mark> into contemporary America</u>, <u><strong><mark>transform</u></strong></mark>ing <u>the</u> <u><strong><mark>present into a speculative space where</u></strong></mark> environmental <u><strong><mark>catastrophe produces not only unevenly distributed damage but also revolutionary forms of social justice</strong></mark> that insist on a truth that probability modeling cannot contain: that <strong><mark>the future will be unimaginably different from the present</strong></mark>, while the present, too, might yet be utterly different from the real that we think we know</u>.¶ Nuclear waste is rarely treated in ecocriticism or risk theory, for several reasons: it is too manmade to be ecological; its catastrophes are ongoing, intentionally produced situations rather than sudden disasters; and it does not support the narrative that subtends ecocritical accounts of risk perception in which the nuclear threat gives rise to an awareness of other kinds of threat before reaching the end of its relevance at the end of the Cold War.2 In what follows, I argue that the failure of nuclear waste to fit into the critical frames created by ecocriticism and risk theory to date offers an opportunity to expand those frames and overcome some of their limitations, especially the impulse towards a paranoid, totalizing realism that Peter van Wyck (2005) has described as central to ecocriticism in the risk society. Nuclear waste has durational forms that dwarf the human. It therefore dwells less in the economy of risk as it is currently conceptualized and more in the blown-out realm of deep time. Inhabiting the temporal scale that has recently been christened the Anthropocene, the geological era defined by the impact of human activities on the world’s geology and climate, nuclear waste unsettles any attempt at realist description, unveiling the limits of human imagination at every turn.3 By analyzing risk society through a heuristic of nuclear waste, this essay offers a critique of nuclear colonialism and environmental racism. At the same time, it shows how <u>the <strong><mark>apocalyptic mode</u></strong></mark> <u>in deep time</u> <u><strong><mark>allows narratives</strong></mark> of</u> environmental <u>harm and danger <strong><mark>to move beyond the paranoid logic of risk</strong></mark>. In the world of deep time</u>, all that might come to pass will come to pass, sooner or later. <u>The endless maybes of risk become certainties. <strong>Th<mark>e impossibilities of our own deaths and the deaths of everything else will come. But so too will other impossibilities</u></strong></mark>: talking macaws and alien visitors; <u>the end of the colonial occupation of North America, perhaps, or <mark>a</mark> <strong>sudden <mark>human determination to let the world live</u></strong></mark>. The end of capitalism may yet become more thinkable than the end of the world. Just wait long enough. Stranger things will happen.¶ </p>
null
1ac
Underview
67,221
621
152,875
./documents/hsld22/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory/DiAr/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory-DiAr-Aff-Lexington-Winter-Invitational-Round-5.docx
964,346
A
Lexington Winter Invitational
5
Lake Highland Prep NP
Ruda
1ac-schengen v2 1nc-nebel, setcol, case 1ar-all 2nr-all 2ar-nebel
hsld22/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory/DiAr/StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory-DiAr-Aff-Lexington-Winter-Invitational-Round-5.docx
2023-01-15 15:39:10
80,553
DiAr
Strake Jesuit College Preparatory DiAr
null
Di.....
Ar.....
null
null
27,049
StrakeJesuitCollegePreparatory
Strake Jesuit College Preparatory
TX
36,501
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
4,526,249
To clarify this debate, I offer the following definition of open borders. According to US policy expert---
Longley 22,
Longley 22, [Robert Longley, 12-1-2022, (Longley is a U.S. government and history expert with over 30 years of experience in municipal government and urban planning), "Open Borders: Definition, Pros and Cons," ThoughtCo, https://www.thoughtco.com/open-borders-4684612// Accessed: 12-17-2022] Sachin
open borders” implies that people may travel to and from a country without presenting a passport, visa, or another form of legal documentation
open borders” implies that people may travel to and from a country without presenting a passport, visa, or another form of legal documentation
Open Borders Definitions In the strictest sense, the term “open borders” implies that people may travel to and from a country without presenting a passport, visa, or another form of legal documentation. It does not, however, imply that new immigrants will automatically be granted citizenship.
293
<h4>To clarify this debate, I offer the following definition of open borders. According to US policy expert---</h4><p><strong>Longley 22,</strong> [Robert Longley, 12-1-2022, (Longley is a U.S. government and history expert with over 30 years of experience in municipal government and urban planning), "Open Borders: Definition, Pros and Cons," ThoughtCo, https://www.thoughtco.com/open-borders-4684612// Accessed: 12-17-2022] Sachin</p><p>Open Borders Definitions</p><p>In the strictest sense, the term “<u><mark>open borders” implies that people may travel to and from a country without presenting a passport, visa, or another form of legal documentation</u></mark>. It does not, however, imply that new immigrants will automatically be granted citizenship.</p>
1NC vs Andrew!
1NC---OFF
1NC – NC
1,698,856
1,342
148,737
./documents/hsld22/DurhamAcademy/SaAg/DurhamAcademy-SaAg-Neg-Durham-Round-Robin-Round-2.docx
965,004
N
Durham Round Robin
2
Isidore Newman AB
Tarun Ratnasabapathy, Jack Liu
1AC – Rights 1NC – Util NC Populism DA Disease CP Brain Drain DA Case 1AR – All 2NR – Induction Fails Disease CP Case 2AR – Disease CP Case
hsld22/DurhamAcademy/SaAg/DurhamAcademy-SaAg-Neg-Durham-Round-Robin-Round-2.docx
2023-01-16 16:38:36
81,847
SaAg
Durham Academy SaAg
Phone: 919-797-8192 FB: Sachin Aggarwal Email: 24aggarwal@da.org circuitdebater.org
Sa.....
Ag.....
null
null
26,575
DurhamAcademy
Durham Academy
NC
4,105
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
2,367,224
[6] Pluralism is good
Bleiker 14
Bleiker 14 – (6/17, Roland, Professor of International Relations at the University of Queensland, “International Theory Between Reification and Self-Reflective Critique,” International Studies Review, Volume 16, Issue 2, pages 325–327)
Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of Levine's sustainable critique. No single method can ever adequately represent the event each should, in a way, recognize and capture details or perspectives that the others cannot (p. 102). In practical terms, this means combining a range of methods precisely when—they are deemed incompatible. They can range from poststructual deconstruction to the tools pioneered and championed by positivist social sciences. The benefit is not just the opportunity to bring out nuances identify the reifying tendencies and this is how a “critically reflexive moment might thus be rendered sustainable
Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of sustainable critique No single method can ever adequately represent the event each should recognize details or perspectives that the others cannot this means combining methods precisely when deemed incompatible. The benefit is opportunity to bring out nuances identify the reifying tendencies
Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of Levine's sustainable critique. He borrows from what Adorno calls a “constellation”: an attempt to juxtapose, rather than integrate, different perspectives. It is in this spirit that Levine advocates multiple methods to understand the same event or phenomena. He writes of the need to validate “multiple and mutually incompatible ways of seeing” (p. 63, see also pp. 101–102). In this model, a scholar oscillates back and forth between different methods and paradigms, trying to understand the event in question from multiple perspectives. No single method can ever adequately represent the event or should gain the upper hand. But each should, in a way, recognize and capture details or perspectives that the others cannot (p. 102). In practical terms, this means combining a range of methods even when—or, rather, precisely when—they are deemed incompatible. They can range from poststructual deconstruction to the tools pioneered and championed by positivist social sciences. The benefit of such a methodological polyphony is not just the opportunity to bring out nuances and new perspectives. Once the false hope of a smooth synthesis has been abandoned, the very incompatibility of the respective perspectives can then be used to identify the reifying tendencies in each of them. For Levine, this is how reification may be “checked at the source” and this is how a “critically reflexive moment might thus be rendered sustainable” (p. 103). It is in this sense that Levine's approach is not really post-foundational but, rather, an attempt to “balance foundationalisms against one another” (p. 14). There are strong parallels here with arguments advanced by assemblage thinking and complexity theory—links that could have been explored in more detail.
1,800
<h4>[6] Pluralism is good</h4><p><strong>Bleiker 14</strong> – (6/17, Roland, Professor of International Relations at the University of Queensland, “International Theory Between Reification and Self-Reflective Critique,” International Studies Review, Volume 16, Issue 2, pages 325–327)</p><p><u><strong><mark>Methodological pluralism lies at the heart of </mark>Levine's <mark>sustainable critique</mark>.</u></strong> He borrows from what Adorno calls a “constellation”: an attempt to juxtapose, rather than integrate, different perspectives. It is in this spirit that Levine advocates multiple methods to understand the same event or phenomena. He writes of the need to validate “multiple and mutually incompatible ways of seeing” (p. 63, see also pp. 101–102). In this model, a scholar oscillates back and forth between different methods and paradigms, trying to understand the event in question from multiple perspectives.<u><strong><mark> No single method can ever adequately represent the event </u></strong></mark>or should gain the upper hand. But<u><strong> <mark>each should</mark>, in a way, <mark>recognize </mark>and capture <mark>details or perspectives that the others cannot</mark> (p. 102). In practical terms, <mark>this means combining</mark> a range of <mark>methods</mark> </u></strong>even when—or, rather,<u><strong> <mark>precisely when</mark>—they are <mark>deemed incompatible. </mark>They can range from poststructual deconstruction to the tools pioneered and championed by positivist social sciences. <mark>The benefit</mark> </u></strong>of such a methodological polyphony<u><strong> <mark>is </mark>not just the <mark>opportunity to bring out nuances </u></strong></mark>and new perspectives. Once the false hope of a smooth synthesis has been abandoned, the very incompatibility of the respective perspectives can then be used to<u><strong> <mark>identify the reifying tendencies</mark> </u></strong>in each of them. For Levine, this is how reification may be “checked at the source”<u><strong> and this is how a “critically reflexive moment might thus be rendered sustainable</u></strong>” (p. 103). It is in this sense that Levine's approach is not really post-foundational but, rather, an attempt to “balance foundationalisms against one another” (p. 14). There are strong parallels here with arguments advanced by assemblage thinking and complexity theory—links that could have been explored in more detail.</p>
null
Underview
null
10,116
1,568
75,464
./documents/hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Le/Strake%20Jesuit-Lee-Aff-Glenbrooks-Round6.docx
874,867
A
Glenbrooks
6
Harvard Westlake AG
Nelson Okunlola
AC - Stock NC - Microbubbles CP Econ DA Transition DA Case 1AR - Case Straight Ref Bad CP DA DA 2NR - DA Case Straight Ref Bad 2AR - Straight Ref Bad
hsld20/StrakeJesuit/Le/Strake%20Jesuit-Lee-Aff-Glenbrooks-Round6.docx
null
73,804
DaLe
Strake Jesuit DaLe
null
Da.....
Le.....
null
null
24,736
StrakeJesuit
Strake Jesuit
TX
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
4,598,805
2. Equality— only universalizable reason can effectively explain the perspectives of agents – that’s the best method for combatting oppression.
Farr 02 Accessed 9/21/19 AHS//NPR
Farr 02 Arnold Farr (prof of phil @ UKentucky, focusing on German idealism, philosophy of race, postmodernism, psychoanalysis, and liberation philosophy). “Can a Philosophy of Race Afford to Abandon the Kantian Categorical Imperative?” JOURNAL of SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY, Vol. 33 No. 1, Spring 2002, 17–32. Accessed 9/21/19 AHS//NPR
One criticism of Kant’s moral philosophy is that it is too formalistic. although a distinction between the universal and the concrete is valid the unity of the two is required for agency. Kant is accused of making the moral agent an abstract, empty subject. Nothing could be further from the truth. The Kantian subject is embodied The fact that I cannot simply satisfy my desires without considering the rightness of my actions suggests that my empirical character must be held in check by my intelligible character we formulate principles that keep our impulses in check. The Formula of Universal Law enjoins no more than that we act only on maxims that are open to others also. The individual is not allowed to exclude others as moral agents Hence, universalizability is a principle of consistency and inclusion. I include the perspective of other moral agents.
The fact that I cannot satisfy my desires without considering the rightness of my actions suggests that my empirical character must be held in check The Formula of Universal Law enjoins no more than that we act only on maxims that are open to others also The individual is not allowed to exclude others as moral agents universalizability is a principle of consistency and inclusion I include the perspective of other moral agents
One of the most popular criticisms of Kant’s moral philosophy is that it is too formalistic.13 That is, the universal nature of the categorical imperative leaves it devoid of content. Such a principle is useless since moral decisions are made by concrete individuals in a concrete, historical, and social situation. This type of criticism lies behind Lewis Gordon’s rejection of any attempt to ground an antiracist position on Kantian principles. The rejection of universal principles for the sake of emphasizing the historical embeddedness of the human agent is widespread in recent philosophy and social theory. I will argue here on Kantian grounds that although a distinction between the universal and the concrete is a valid distinction, the unity of the two is required for an understanding of human agency. The attack on Kantian formalism began with Hegel’s criticism of the Kantian philosophy.14 The list of contemporary theorists who follow Hegel’s line of criticism is far too long to deal with in the scope of this paper. Although these theorists may approach the problem of Kantian formalism from a variety of angles, the spirit of their criticism is basically the same: The universality of the categorical imperative is an abstraction from one’s empirical conditions. Kant is often accused of making the moral agent an abstract, empty, noumenal subject. Nothing could be further from the truth. The Kantian subject is an embodied, empirical, concrete subject. However, this concrete subject has a dual nature. Kant claims in the Critique of Pure Reason as well as in the Grounding that human beings have an intelligible and empirical character.15 It is impossible to understand and do justice to Kant’s moral theory without taking seriously the relation between these two characters. The very concept of morality is impossible without the tension between the two. By “empirical character” Kant simply means that we have a sensual nature. We are physical creatures with physical drives or desires. The very fact that I cannot simply satisfy my desires without considering the rightness or wrongness of my actions suggests that my empirical character must be held in check by something, or else I behave like a Freudian id. My empiri- cal character must be held in check by my intelligible character, which is the legislative activity of practical reason. It is through our intelligible character that we formulate principles that keep our empirical impulses in check. The categorical imperative is the supreme principle of morality that is constructed by the moral agent in his/her moment of self-transcendence. What I have called self-transcendence may be best explained in the following passage by Onora O’Neill: In restricting our maxims to those that meet the test of the categorical imperative we refuse to base our lives on maxims that necessarily make our own case an exception. The reason why a universilizability criterion is morally significant is that it makes our own case no special exception (G, IV, 404). In accepting the Categorical Imperative we accept the moral reality of other selves, and hence the possibility (not, note, the reality) of a moral community. The Formula of Universal Law enjoins no more than that we act only on maxims that are open to others also.16 O’Neill’s description of the universalizability criterion includes the notion of self-transcendence that I am working to explicate here to the extent that like self-transcendence, universalizable moral principles require that the individ- ual think beyond his or her own particular desires. The individual is not allowed to exclude others as rational moral agents who have the right to act as he acts in a given situation. For example, if I decide to use another person merely as a means for my own end I must recognize the other person’s right to do the same to me. I cannot consistently will that I use another as a means only and will that I not be used in the same manner by another. Hence, the universalizability criterion is a principle of consistency and a principle of inclusion. That is, in choosing my maxims I attempt to include the perspective of other moral agents. 3] Ideal theory is key: A] Failure to abstract away from our subject position means agents are fully aware of their self-interest and will coopt your movement. B] only ideal theory can say things like racism are always wrong because we have universal standard to hold people too, not just an individual perspective C] Normativity explains why things are bad rather than simply asserting which can’t convince the oppressor D] Ideal theory prevents epistemic bias since by abstracting away from our identities and factors that cloud or judgement we can see what is universally good for everyone not just us.
4,781
<h4>2. <u>Equality</u>— only universalizable reason can effectively explain the perspectives of agents – that’s the best method for combatting oppression.</h4><p><strong>Farr 02</strong> Arnold Farr (prof of phil @ UKentucky, focusing on German idealism, philosophy of race, postmodernism, psychoanalysis, and liberation philosophy). “Can a Philosophy of Race Afford to Abandon the Kantian Categorical Imperative?” JOURNAL of SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY, Vol. 33 No. 1, Spring 2002, 17–32.<u><strong> Accessed 9/21/19 AHS//NPR</p><p>One</u></strong> of the most popular <u><strong>criticism</u></strong>s <u><strong>of Kant’s moral philosophy is that it is too formalistic.</u></strong>13 That is, the universal nature of the categorical imperative leaves it devoid of content. Such a principle is useless since moral decisions are made by concrete individuals in a concrete, historical, and social situation. This type of criticism lies behind Lewis Gordon’s rejection of any attempt to ground an antiracist position on Kantian principles. The rejection of universal principles for the sake of emphasizing the historical embeddedness of the human agent is widespread in recent philosophy and social theory. I will argue here on Kantian grounds that <u><strong>although a distinction between the universal and the concrete is</u></strong> a <u><strong>valid</u></strong> distinction, <u><strong>the unity of the two is required for</u></strong> an understanding of human <u><strong>agency.</u></strong> The attack on Kantian formalism began with Hegel’s criticism of the Kantian philosophy.14 The list of contemporary theorists who follow Hegel’s line of criticism is far too long to deal with in the scope of this paper. Although these theorists may approach the problem of Kantian formalism from a variety of angles, the spirit of their criticism is basically the same: The universality of the categorical imperative is an abstraction from one’s empirical conditions. <u><strong>Kant is</u></strong> often <u><strong>accused of making the moral agent an abstract, empty</u></strong>, noumenal <u><strong>subject. Nothing could be further from the truth. The Kantian subject is</u></strong> an <u><strong>embodied</u></strong>, empirical, concrete subject. However, this concrete subject has a dual nature. Kant claims in the Critique of Pure Reason as well as in the Grounding that human beings have an intelligible and empirical character.15 It is impossible to understand and do justice to Kant’s moral theory without taking seriously the relation between these two characters. The very concept of morality is impossible without the tension between the two. By “empirical character” Kant simply means that we have a sensual nature. We are physical creatures with physical drives or desires. <u><strong><mark>The</u></strong></mark> very <u><strong><mark>fact that I cannot </mark>simply <mark>satisfy my desires without considering the rightness</u></strong> </mark>or wrongness <u><strong><mark>of my actions suggests that my empirical character must be held in check</u></strong> </mark>by something, or else I behave like a Freudian id. My empiri- cal character must be held in check <u><strong>by my intelligible character</u></strong>, which is the legislative activity of practical reason. It is through our intelligible character that <u><strong>we formulate principles that keep our</u></strong> empirical <u><strong>impulses in check.</u></strong> The categorical imperative is the supreme principle of morality that is constructed by the moral agent in his/her moment of self-transcendence. What I have called self-transcendence may be best explained in the following passage by Onora O’Neill: In restricting our maxims to those that meet the test of the categorical imperative we refuse to base our lives on maxims that necessarily make our own case an exception. The reason why a universilizability criterion is morally significant is that it makes our own case no special exception (G, IV, 404). In accepting the Categorical Imperative we accept the moral reality of other selves, and hence the possibility (not, note, the reality) of a moral community. <u><strong><mark>The Formula of Universal Law enjoins no more than that we act only on maxims that are open to others also</mark>.</u></strong>16 O’Neill’s description of the universalizability criterion includes the notion of self-transcendence that I am working to explicate here to the extent that like self-transcendence, universalizable moral principles require that the individ- ual think beyond his or her own particular desires. <u><strong><mark>The individual is not allowed to exclude others as</u></strong></mark> rational <u><strong><mark>moral agents</u></strong> </mark>who have the right to act as he acts in a given situation. For example, if I decide to use another person merely as a means for my own end I must recognize the other person’s right to do the same to me. I cannot consistently will that I use another as a means only and will that I not be used in the same manner by another. <u><strong>Hence,</u></strong> the <u><strong><mark>universalizability</u></strong> </mark>criterion <u><strong><mark>is a principle of consistency and</u></strong> </mark>a principle of <u><strong><mark>inclusion</mark>.</u></strong> That is, in choosing my maxims <u><strong><mark>I</u></strong> </mark>attempt to <u><strong><mark>include the perspective of other moral agents</mark>.</p><p></u></strong>3] Ideal theory is key: A] Failure to abstract away from our subject position means agents are fully aware of their self-interest and will coopt your movement. B] only ideal theory can say things like racism are always wrong because we have universal standard to hold people too, not just an individual perspective C] Normativity explains why things are bad rather than simply asserting which can’t convince the oppressor D] Ideal theory prevents epistemic bias since by abstracting away from our identities and factors that cloud or judgement we can see what is universally good for everyone not just us. </p>
null
AC
Framework
325,498
1,203
152,379
./documents/hsld22/Scarsdale/JeKa/Scarsdale-JeKa-Aff-The-Princeton-Classic-Round-3.docx
951,231
A
The Princeton Classic
3
Summit MR
Maan
1AC - Kant 1NC - CP, DA, T, Theory 1AR - All 2NR - All 2AR - All
hsld22/Scarsdale/JeKa/Scarsdale-JeKa-Aff-The-Princeton-Classic-Round-3.docx
2022-12-03 15:35:43
80,305
JeKa
Scarsdale JeKa
Hey I'm Jessica! Scarsdale '25. She/her. If you have any questions or concerns about the round, please contact me - Email (preferred) - jpkatz2syl@gmail.com You can also find me on Facebook or Messenger as a last resort - Jessica Katz If there is any way you would like me to accommodate for your needs in any way before and during the round, just contact me! I'm happy to do so. Please tell me if there are any specific interps you would like me to meet before round (spikes on top, rob spec, etc.) This is terminal defense to your shell. Feel free to hmu if my wiki isn't working and there are some docs you can't access - I'll send them to you directly. Let me know any content warnings or pronouns before the round so we can make the debate as comfortable as possible for both of us. Good luck!
Je.....
Ka.....
null
null
26,513
Scarsdale
Scarsdale
NY
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
2,158,441
Even a small war causes extinction AND outweighs other existential risks – it’s a threat multiplier and turns every scenario
PND 16
PND 16. internally citing Zbigniew Brzezinski, Council of Foreign Relations and former national security adviser to President Carter, Toon and Robock’s 2012 study on nuclear winter in the Bulletin of Atomic Scientists, Gareth Evans’ International Commission on Nuclear Non-proliferation and Disarmament Report, Congressional EMP studies, studies on nuclear winter by Seth Baum of the Global Catastrophic Risk Institute and Martin Hellman of Stanford University, and U.S. and Russian former Defense Secretaries and former heads of nuclear missile forces, brief submitted to the United Nations General Assembly, Open-Ended Working Group on nuclear risks. A/AC.286/NGO/13. 05-03-2016. http://www.reachingcriticalwill.org/images/documents/Disarmament-fora/OEWG/2016/Documents/NGO13.pdf
Even if the 'other' side does NOT launch in response the smoke will still make the rest of the world uninhabitable inducing global famine lasting decades Toon and Robock note resulting in self assured destruction. Even a 'small' nuclear war between India and Pakistan could produce so much smoke that temperatures would fall below those of the Little Ice Age shortening the growing season around the world and threatening the global food supply massive ozone depletion, allowing more ultraviolet radiation Recent studies predict that agricultural production in parts of the U S and China would decline most likely cause the deaths of most/nearly all/all humans (and severely impact/extinguish other species) as well as destroying the delicate interwoven techno-structure on which latter-day 'civilization' has come to depend. Temperatures would drop to below those of the last ice-age for up to 30 years as a result of the lofting of up to 180 million tonnes of very black soot into the stratosphere where it would remain for decades Though human ingenuity and resilience shouldn't be underestimated, human survival itself is arguably problematic Gareth Evans’ ICNND (International Commission on Nuclear Non-proliferation and Disarmament) Report made it clear that it saw the threat posed by nuclear weapons use as one that threatens human survival with an immediacy that even climate change does not
Even if the 'other' does NOT launch will still make the world uninhabitable inducing global famine lasting decades resulting in self assured destruction. Even a 'small' nuclear war produce smoke and ultraviolet radiation Recent studies predict that agricultural production U S and China would decline most likely cause the deaths of all humans and other species nuclear weapons use threatens human survival with an immediacy that even climate change does not
Consequences human survival 12. Even if the 'other' side does NOT launch in response the smoke from 'their' burning cities (incinerated by 'us') will still make 'our' country (and the rest of the world) uninhabitable, potentially inducing global famine lasting up to decades. Toon and Robock note in ‘Self Assured Destruction’, in the Bulletin of Atomic Scientists 68/5, 2012, that: 13. “A nuclear war between Russia and the United States, even after the arsenal reductions planned under New START, could produce a nuclear winter. Hence, an attack by either side could be suicidal, resulting in self assured destruction. Even a 'small' nuclear war between India and Pakistan, with each country detonating 50 Hiroshima-size atom bombs--only about 0.03 percent of the global nuclear arsenal's explosive power--as air bursts in urban areas, could produce so much smoke that temperatures would fall below those of the Little Ice Age of the fourteenth to nineteenth centuries, shortening the growing season around the world and threatening the global food supply. Furthermore, there would be massive ozone depletion, allowing more ultraviolet radiation to reach Earth's surface. Recent studies predict that agricultural production in parts of the United States and China would decline by about 20 percent for four years, and by 10 percent for a decade.” 14. A conflagration involving USA/NATO forces and those of Russian federation would most likely cause the deaths of most/nearly all/all humans (and severely impact/extinguish other species) as well as destroying the delicate interwoven techno-structure on which latter-day 'civilization' has come to depend. Temperatures would drop to below those of the last ice-age for up to 30 years as a result of the lofting of up to 180 million tonnes of very black soot into the stratosphere where it would remain for decades. 15. Though human ingenuity and resilience shouldn't be underestimated, human survival itself is arguably problematic, to put it mildly, under a 2000+ warhead USA/Russian federation scenario. 16. The Joint Statement on Catastrophic Humanitarian Consequences signed October 2013 by 146 governments mentioned 'Human Survival' no less than 5 times. The most recent (December 2014) one gives it a highly prominent place. Gareth Evans’ ICNND (International Commission on Nuclear Non-proliferation and Disarmament) Report made it clear that it saw the threat posed by nuclear weapons use as one that at least threatens what we now call 'civilization' and that potentially threatens human survival with an immediacy that even climate change does not, though we can see the results of climate change here and now and of course the immediate post-nuclear results for Hiroshima and Nagasaki as well.
2,754
<h4>Even a small war causes extinction AND outweighs <u>other</u> existential risks – it’s a threat multiplier and turns every scenario</h4><p><strong>PND 16</strong>. internally citing Zbigniew Brzezinski, Council of Foreign Relations and former national security adviser to President Carter, Toon and Robock’s 2012 study on nuclear winter in the Bulletin of Atomic Scientists, Gareth Evans’ International Commission on Nuclear Non-proliferation and Disarmament Report, Congressional EMP studies, studies on nuclear winter by Seth Baum of the Global Catastrophic Risk Institute and Martin Hellman of Stanford University, and U.S. and Russian former Defense Secretaries and former heads of nuclear missile forces, brief submitted to the United Nations General Assembly, Open-Ended Working Group on nuclear risks. A/AC.286/NGO/13. 05-03-2016. http://www.reachingcriticalwill.org/images/documents/Disarmament-fora/OEWG/2016/Documents/NGO13.pdf</p><p>Consequences human survival 12. <u><mark>Even if the 'other'</mark> side <mark>does NOT launch</mark> in response the smoke</u> from 'their' burning cities (incinerated by 'us') <u><mark>will still make</u></mark> 'our' country (and <u>the rest of <mark>the world</u></mark>) <u><strong><mark>uninhabitable</u></strong></mark>, potentially <u><mark>inducing global famine lasting</u></mark> up to <u><strong><mark>decades</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>Toon and Robock</strong> note</u> in ‘Self Assured Destruction’, in the Bulletin of Atomic Scientists 68/5, 2012, that: 13. “A nuclear war between Russia and the United States, even after the arsenal reductions planned under New START, could produce a nuclear winter. Hence, an attack by either side could be suicidal, <u><mark>resulting in <strong>self assured destruction</strong>. Even a 'small' nuclear war </mark>between <strong>India</strong> and <strong>Pakistan</u></strong>, with each country detonating 50 Hiroshima-size atom bombs--only about 0.03 percent of the global nuclear arsenal's explosive power--as air bursts in urban areas, <u>could <mark>produce</mark> so much <mark>smoke</mark> that temperatures would fall below those of the Little Ice Age</u> of the fourteenth to nineteenth centuries, <u>shortening the growing season around the world <mark>and</mark> threatening the global food supply</u>. Furthermore, there would be <u>massive ozone depletion, allowing more <strong><mark>ultraviolet</strong></mark> <mark>radiation</u></mark> to reach Earth's surface. <u><strong><mark>Recent studies</strong> predict that agricultural production</mark> in parts of the <strong><mark>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><mark>and <strong>China</strong> would decline</u></mark> by about 20 percent for four years, and by 10 percent for a decade.” 14. A conflagration involving USA/NATO forces and those of Russian federation would <u><mark>most likely cause the deaths of</mark> most/nearly all/<strong><mark>all humans</strong></mark> (<mark>and</mark> severely impact/extinguish <strong><mark>other species</strong></mark>) as well as destroying the delicate interwoven techno-structure on which latter-day 'civilization' has come to depend. Temperatures would drop to below those of the last ice-age for up to 30 years as a result of the lofting of up to 180 million tonnes of very black soot into the stratosphere where it would remain for decades</u>. 15. <u>Though human ingenuity and resilience shouldn't be underestimated, human survival itself is arguably problematic</u>, to put it mildly, under a 2000+ warhead USA/Russian federation scenario. 16. The Joint Statement on Catastrophic Humanitarian Consequences signed October 2013 by 146 governments mentioned 'Human Survival' no less than 5 times. The most recent (December 2014) one gives it a highly prominent place. <u><strong>Gareth Evans</strong>’ ICNND (International Commission on Nuclear Non-proliferation and Disarmament) Report made it clear that it saw the threat posed by <mark>nuclear weapons use</mark> as one that</u> at least threatens what we now call 'civilization' and that potentially <u><strong><mark>threatens human survival with an immediacy that even climate change does not</u></strong></mark>, though we can see the results of climate change here and now and of course the immediate post-nuclear results for Hiroshima and Nagasaki as well. </p>
Emory R6 – 1AC v Westlake AK
Advantage – IHL
Scenario 1 is Militarization
48,363
1,164
65,654
./documents/hsld20/Greenhill/Th/Greenhill-Thoduguli-Aff-Emory-Round6.docx
859,156
A
Emory
6
Westlake AK
X Braithwaite
1AC - IHL v5 1NC - Arms Control K 1AR - all 2NR - all 2AR - all
hsld20/Greenhill/Th/Greenhill-Thoduguli-Aff-Emory-Round6.docx
null
73,053
NiTh
Greenhill NiTh
null
Ni.....
Th.....
null
null
24,529
Greenhill
Greenhill
TX
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
921,728
Resolved means a policy
Louisiana House 5
Louisiana House 5
Resolution A legislative instrument used for stating policies a resolution uses the term "resolved".
Resolution A legislative instrument for policies
(http://house.louisiana.gov/house-glossary.htm) Resolution A legislative instrument that generally is used for making declarations, stating policies, and making decisions where some other form is not required. A bill includes the constitutionally required enacting clause; a resolution uses the term "resolved". Not subject to a time limit for introduction nor to governor's veto. ( Const. Art. III, §17(B) and House Rules 8.11 , 13.1 , 6.8 , and 7.4)
457
<h4>Resolved means a <u>policy</u><strong> </h4><p>Louisiana House 5</p><p></strong>(http://house.louisiana.gov/house-glossary.htm)</p><p><u><mark>Resolution A <strong>legislative</strong> instrument</mark> </u>that generally is <u>used <mark>for</u></mark> making declarations, <u>stating <strong><mark>policies</u></strong></mark>, and making decisions where some other form is not required. A bill includes the constitutionally required enacting clause; <u>a resolution uses the term "resolved". </u>Not subject to a time limit for introduction nor to governor's veto. ( Const. Art. III, §17(B) and House Rules 8.11 , 13.1 , 6.8 , and 7.4)</p>
2NC
T
AT CI---Resolved
1,126
1,429
22,398
./documents/ndtceda21/Kansas/ReSn/Kansas-Revare-Snow-Neg-2%20-%20Districts-Round1.docx
625,013
N
2 - Districts
1
MO State CK
Dill, Ian
1AC - Price Theory 1NC - T USFG Climate PIC Cap Good 2NR - T USFG Dash of Cap Good
ndtceda21/Kansas/ReSn/Kansas-Revare-Snow-Neg-2%20-%20Districts-Round1.docx
null
52,739
ReSn
Kansas ReSn
null
Gr.....
Re.....
Ry.....
Sn.....
19,391
Kansas
Kansas
null
null
1,011
ndtceda21
NDT/CEDA 2021-22
2,021
cx
college
2
1,932,727
USFG is the federal government of the USA, based in DC
Dictionary of Government and Politics ’98
Dictionary of Government and Politics ’98 (Ed. P.H. Collin, p. 292)
United States of America independent country federal government (based in Washington D.C.) is formed of a legislature an executive and a judiciary
United States federal government (based in Washington D.C.)
United States of America (USA) [ju:’naitid ‘steits av e’merike] noun independent country, a federation of states (originally thirteen, now fifty in North America; the United States Code = book containing all the permanent laws of the USA, arranged in sections according to subject and revised from time to time COMMENT: the federal government (based in Washington D.C.) is formed of a legislature (the Congress) with two chambers (the Senate and House of Representatives), an executive (the President) and a judiciary (the Supreme Court). Each of the fifty states making up the USA has its own legislature and executive (the Governor) as well as its own legal system and constitution
683
<h4><u>USFG is the federal government of the USA, based in DC</h4><p></u><strong>Dictionary of Government and Politics ’98</strong> (Ed. P.H. Collin, p. 292)</p><p><u><mark>United States</mark> of America</u> (USA) [ju:’naitid ‘steits av e’merike] noun <u>independent country</u>, a federation of states (originally thirteen, now fifty in North America; the United States Code = book containing all the permanent laws of the USA, arranged in sections according to subject and revised from time to time COMMENT: the <u><mark>federal government (based in Washington D.C.) </mark>is formed of a legislature</u> (the Congress) with two chambers (the Senate and House of Representatives), <u>an executive</u> (the President) <u>and a judiciary</u> (the Supreme Court). Each of the fifty states making up the USA has its own legislature and executive (the Governor) as well as its own legal system and constitution</p>
2NC
2NC – T – USfg
--- 2NC – USFG
16,300
813
57,059
./documents/hspolicy20/MaineEast/PiPi/Maine%20East-Piekut-Piekut-Neg-2%20-%20Greenhill-Quarters.docx
733,802
N
2 - Greenhill
Quarters
Edina AA
Joshua Gonzalez - Kevin McCaffrey - Jacob Bosley
1AC - Logistics 1NC - T-USfg Cap K v1 Chow K Heg DA FBI DA 2NC - T 1NR - Cap K 2NR - T
hspolicy20/MaineEast/PiPi/Maine%20East-Piekut-Piekut-Neg-2%20-%20Greenhill-Quarters.docx
null
62,621
PiPi
Maine East PiPi
null
Be.....
Pi.....
Ni.....
Pi.....
21,704
MaineEast
Maine East
IL
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
1,853,888
USFG is 3 branches
OECD 87
OECD 87 — Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development Council, 1987 (“United States,” The Control and Management of Government Expenditure, p. 179)
Political and organisational structure of government The United States of America is a federal republic consisting of 50 states The Federal Government is composed of three branches: the legislative branch, the executive branch, and the judicial branch
The Federal Government is composed of three branches: legislative executive and judicial
Political and organisational structure of government The United States of America is a federal republic consisting of 50 states. States have their own constitutions and within each State there are at least two additional levels of government, generally designated as counties and cities, towns or villages. The relationships between different levels of government are complex and varied (see Section B for more information). The Federal Government is composed of three branches: the legislative branch, the executive branch, and the judicial branch. Budgetary decisionmaking is shared primarily by the legislative and executive branches. The general structure of these two branches relative to budget formulation and execution is as follows.
741
<h4>USFG is 3 branches</h4><p><strong>OECD 87</strong> — Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development Council, 1987 (“United States,” The Control and Management of Government Expenditure, p. 179)</p><p><u>Political and organisational structure of government</u> <u>The <strong>U</strong>nited <strong>S</strong>tates of America is a federal republic consisting of 50 states</u>. States have their own constitutions and within each State there are at least two additional levels of government, generally designated as counties and cities, towns or villages. The relationships between different levels of government are complex and varied (see Section B for more information). <u><mark>The Federal Government is composed of <strong>three branches</strong>:</mark> the <mark>legislative</mark> branch, the <mark>executive</mark> branch, <mark>and</mark> the <mark>judicial</mark> branch</u>. Budgetary decisionmaking is shared primarily by the legislative and executive branches. The general structure of these two branches relative to budget formulation and execution is as follows.</p>
Elections
2AC 1 – no link aff is juciary committee
1NR-AT: clarification
23,993
1,475
54,423
./documents/hspolicy20/CasadySchool/BaHe/Casady%20School-Barreto-Henry-Neg-Grapevine-Round2.docx
726,746
N
Grapevine
2
Valley International AU
Walter Willis
1AC- Forensic Expert Standards 1NC- Federalism Disad Terror Adv CP Elections Disad T Forensics Courts CP T subsets Abolition K 2NR- Elections Disad
hspolicy20/CasadySchool/BaHe/Casady%20School-Barreto-Henry-Neg-Grapevine-Round2.docx
null
62,012
BaHe
Casady School BaHe
null
Al.....
Ba.....
Ca.....
He.....
21,547
CasadySchool
Casady School
OK
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
1,396,851
Food shortages cause a nuclear World War 3
FDI 12
FDI 12 (Future Directions International, a Research institute providing strategic analysis of Australia’s global interests; citing Lindsay Falvery, PhD in Agricultural Science and former Professor at the University of Melbourne’s Institute of Land and Environment, “Food and Water Insecurity: International Conflict Triggers & Potential Conflict Points,”)
There is a growing appreciation that conflicts in the next century will most likely be fought over a lack of resources. this is not new. Researchers point to the French and Russian revolutions as induced by a lack of food. Germany’s World War Two efforts are said to have been inspired by its perceived need to gain access to more food the scale of the problem in the future could be significantly greater Lindsay Falvey expresses the problem if people are hungry the state is not stable Julian Cribb writes that if “large regions of the world run short of food wholesale, bloody wars are liable to follow.” An increasingly credible scenario for World War 3 is a festering, self-perpetuating chain of resource conflicts A study by the International Peace Research Institute indicates that where food security is an issue, it is more likely to result in some form of conflict Darfur, Rwanda, Eritrea and the Balkans experienced such wars The UK Ministry of Defence, the CIA, the C S I S and the Oslo Peace Research Institute, all identify famine as a potential trigger for nuclear war.
conflicts in the next century will most likely be fought over lack of resources Researchers point to the French and Russian revolutions as induced by lack of food Germany’s World War Two efforts are inspired by need to gain food the scale in the future could be significantly greater if people are hungry the state is not stable if the world run short of food wholesale wars are liable to follow.” An increasingly credible scenario for World War 3 is a festering chain of resource conflicts where food security is an issue, it is likely to result in conflict famine as a trigger for nuclear war
There is a growing appreciation that the conflicts in the next century will most likely be fought over a lack of resources. Yet, in a sense, this is not new. Researchers point to the French and Russian revolutions as conflicts induced by a lack of food. More recently, Germany’s World War Two efforts are said to have been inspired, at least in part, by its perceived need to gain access to more food. Yet the general sense among those that attended FDI’s recent workshops, was that the scale of the problem in the future could be significantly greater as a result of population pressures, changing weather, urbanisation, migration, loss of arable land and other farm inputs, and increased affluence in the developing world. In his book, Small Farmers Secure Food, Lindsay Falvey, a participant in FDI’s March 2012 workshop on the issue of food and conflict, clearly expresses the problem and why countries across the globe are starting to take note. . He writes (p.36), “…if people are hungry, especially in cities, the state is not stable – riots, violence, breakdown of law and order and migration result.” “Hunger feeds anarchy.” This view is also shared by Julian Cribb, who in his book, The Coming Famine, writes that if “large regions of the world run short of food, land or water in the decades that lie ahead, then wholesale, bloody wars are liable to follow.” He continues: “An increasingly credible scenario for World War 3 is not so much a confrontation of super powers and their allies, as a festering, self-perpetuating chain of resource conflicts.” He also says: “The wars of the 21st Century are less likely to be global conflicts with sharply defined sides and huge armies, than a scrappy mass of failed states, rebellions, civil strife, insurgencies, terrorism and genocides, sparked by bloody competition over dwindling resources.” As another workshop participant put it, people do not go to war to kill; they go to war over resources, either to protect or to gain the resources for themselves. Another observed that hunger results in passivity not conflict. Conflict is over resources, not because people are going hungry. A study by the International Peace Research Institute indicates that where food security is an issue, it is more likely to result in some form of conflict. Darfur, Rwanda, Eritrea and the Balkans experienced such wars. Governments, especially in developed countries, are increasingly aware of this phenomenon. The UK Ministry of Defence, the CIA, the US Center for Strategic and International Studies and the Oslo Peace Research Institute, all identify famine as a potential trigger for conflicts and possibly even nuclear war.
2,671
<h4>Food shortages cause a nuclear World War 3</h4><p><strong>FDI 12</strong> (Future Directions International, a Research institute providing strategic analysis of Australia’s global interests; citing Lindsay Falvery, PhD in Agricultural Science and former Professor at the University of Melbourne’s Institute of Land and Environment, “Food and Water Insecurity: International Conflict Triggers & Potential Conflict Points,”)</p><p><u>There is a growing appreciation that</u> the <u><mark>conflicts in the next century will <strong>most likely</strong> be fought over</mark> a <mark>lack of resources</mark>. </u>Yet, in a sense, <u>this is not new. <mark>Researchers point to the French and Russian revolutions as</u></mark> conflicts <u><mark>induced by</mark> a <mark>lack of food</mark>.</u> More recently, <u><strong><mark>Germany’s World War Two</strong> efforts are</mark> said to have been <mark>inspired</u></mark>, at least in part, <u><mark>by</mark> its perceived <mark>need to gain</mark> access to more <mark>food</u></mark>. Yet the general sense among those that attended FDI’s recent workshops, was that <u><mark>the scale</mark> of the problem <mark>in the future could be <strong>significantly greater</u></strong></mark> as a result of population pressures, changing weather, urbanisation, migration, loss of arable land and other farm inputs, and increased affluence in the developing world. In his book, Small Farmers Secure Food, <u>Lindsay Falvey</u>, a participant in FDI’s March 2012 workshop on the issue of food and conflict, clearly <u>expresses the problem</u> and why countries across the globe are starting to take note. . He writes (p.36), “…<u><mark>if people are hungry</u></mark>, especially in cities, <u><strong><mark>the state is not stable</u></strong></mark> – riots, violence, breakdown of law and order and migration result.” “Hunger feeds anarchy.” This view is also shared by <u>Julian Cribb</u>, who in his book, The Coming Famine, <u>writes that <mark>if</mark> “large regions of <mark>the world run short of food</u></mark>, land or water in the decades that lie ahead, then <u><strong><mark>wholesale</mark>, bloody <mark>wars are liable to follow.”</mark> </u></strong>He continues: “<u><mark>An increasingly credible scenario for World War 3 is</u></mark> not so much a confrontation of super powers and their allies, as <u><mark>a <strong>festering</strong></mark>, self-perpetuating <strong><mark>chain</strong> of resource conflicts</u></mark>.” He also says: “The wars of the 21st Century are less likely to be global conflicts with sharply defined sides and huge armies, than a scrappy mass of failed states, rebellions, civil strife, insurgencies, terrorism and genocides, sparked by bloody competition over dwindling resources.” As another workshop participant put it, people do not go to war to kill; they go to war over resources, either to protect or to gain the resources for themselves. Another observed that hunger results in passivity not conflict. Conflict is over resources, not because people are going hungry. <u>A study by <strong>the I</strong>nternational <strong>P</strong>eace <strong>R</strong>esearch <strong>I</strong>nstitute indicates that <mark>where food security is an issue, it is </mark>more <mark>likely to result in</mark> some form of <mark>conflict</u></mark>. <u><strong>Darfur, Rwanda, Eritrea and the Balkans</strong> experienced such wars</u>. Governments, especially in developed countries, are increasingly aware of this phenomenon. <u>The UK Ministry of Defence, the CIA, the</u> US <u><strong>C</u></strong>enter for <u><strong>S</u></strong>trategic and <u><strong>I</u></strong>nternational <u><strong>S</u></strong>tudies <u>and the Oslo Peace Research Institute, <strong>all identify</strong> <mark>famine as a</mark> potential <mark>trigger for</u></mark> conflicts and possibly even <u><strong><mark>nuclear war</strong></mark>.</p></u>
null
null
Oceans
22,024
2,244
37,322
./documents/hspolicy14/NilesNorth/ObWa/Niles%20North-ObertoBessoPando-Walkington-Aff-IHSA-Quarters.docx
636,077
A
IHSA
Quarters
New Trier BL
Mikaela Malsin, Kenny McCaffrey, Sara Sanchez
1AC Offshore Wind (Hurricanes and Oceans) 1NC T-of Synoptic Delusion K TPA Bad China Coal DA 2NR T
hspolicy14/NilesNorth/ObWa/Niles%20North-ObertoBessoPando-Walkington-Aff-IHSA-Quarters.docx
null
53,701
ObWa
Niles North ObWa
null
Da.....
Ob.....
Lu.....
Wa.....
19,619
NilesNorth
Niles North
null
null
1,013
hspolicy14
HS Policy 2014-15
2,014
cx
hs
2
1,722,403
Climate doesn’t cause extinction.
Kerr et al. 19
Kerr et al. 19 – Dr. Amber Kerr, Energy and Resources PhD at the University of California-Berkeley, known agroecologist, former coordinator of the USDA California Climate Hub. Dr. Daniel Swain, Climate Science PhD at UCLA, climate scientist, a research fellow at the National Center for Atmospheric Research. Dr. Andrew King, Earth Sciences PhD, Climate Extremes Research Fellow at the University of Melbourne. Dr. Peter Kalmus, Physics PhD at the University of Colombia, climate scientist at NASA’s Jet Propulsion Lab. Professor Richard Betts, Chair in Climate Impacts at the University of Exeter, a lead author on the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) in Working Group 1. Dr. William Huiskamp, Paleoclimatology PhD at the Climate Change Research Center, climate scientist at the Potsdam Institute for Climate Impact Research. [Claim that human civilization could end in 30 years is speculative, not supported with evidence, 6-4-2019, https://climatefeedback.org/evaluation/iflscience-story-on-speculative-report-provides-little-scientific-context-james-felton/]
There is no scientific basis to suggest climate breakdown will “annihilate intelligent life” (by which I assume the authors mean human extinction) Andrew King, Research fellow, University of Melbourne: Projections of extreme events are very difficult to make and vary greatly between different climate models the eye-catching headline-level claims in the report stem almost entirely from knock-on effects, which are “beyond their capacity to model.” from a scientific perspective, the likelihood of civilization coming to an end is essentially personal speculation rather than a clear conclusion drawn from rigorous assessment of the available evidence
There is no basis to suggest climate breakdown will mean human extinction Projections of extreme events are difficult to make and vary between headline claims stem from knock-on effects “beyond capacity to model.” from a scientific perspective, the likelihood is personal speculation rather than conclusion from rigorous evidence
There is no scientific basis to suggest that climate breakdown will “annihilate intelligent life” (by which I assume the report authors mean human extinction) by 2050. However, climate breakdown does pose a grave threat to civilization as we know it, and the potential for mass suffering on a scale perhaps never before encountered by humankind. This should be enough reason for action without any need for exaggeration or misrepresentation! A “Hothouse Earth” scenario plays out that sees Earth’s temperatures doomed to rise by a further 1°C (1.8°F) even if we stopped emissions immediately. Peter Kalmus, Data Scientist, Jet Propulsion Laboratory: This word choice perhaps reveals a bias on the part of the author of the article. A temperature can’t be doomed. And while I certainly do not encourage false optimism, assuming that humanity is doomed is lazy and counterproductive. Fifty-five percent of the global population are subject to more than 20 days a year of lethal heat conditions beyond that which humans can survive Richard Betts, Professor, Met Office Hadley Centre & University of Exeter: This is clearly from Mora et al (2017) although the report does not include a citation of the paper as the source of that statement. The way it is written here (and in the report) is misleading because it gives the impression that everyone dies in those conditions. That is not actually how Mora et al define “deadly heat” – they merely looked for heatwaves when somebody died (not everybody) and then used that as the definition of a “deadly” heatwave. North America suffers extreme weather events including wildfires, drought, and heatwaves. Monsoons in China fail, the great rivers of Asia virtually dry up, and rainfall in central America falls by half. Andrew King, Research fellow, University of Melbourne: Projections of extreme events such as these are very difficult to make and vary greatly between different climate models . Deadly heat conditions across West Africa persist for over 100 days a year Peter Kalmus, Data Scientist, Jet Propulsion Laboratory: The deadly heat projections (this, and the one from the previous paragraph) come from Mora et al (2017)1. It should be clarified that “deadly heat” here means heat and humidity beyond a two-dimension threshold where at least one person in the region subject to that heat and humidity dies (i.e., not everyone instantly dies). That said, in my opinion, the projections in Mora et al are conservative and the methods of Mora et al are sound. I did not check the claims in this report against Mora et al but I have no reason to think they are in error. 1- Mora et al (2017) Global risk of deadly heat, Nature Climate Change The knock-on consequences affect national security, as the scale of the challenges involved, such as pandemic disease outbreaks, are overwhelming. Armed conflicts over resources may become a reality, and have the potential to escalate into nuclear war. In the worst case scenario, a scale of destruction the authors say is beyond their capacity to model, there is a ‘high likelihood of human civilization coming to an end’. Willem Huiskamp, Postdoctoral research fellow, Potsdam Institute for Climate Impact Research: This is a highly questionable conclusion. The reference provided in the report is for the “Global Catastrophic Risks 2018” report from the “Global Challenges Foundation” and not peer-reviewed literature. (It is worth noting that this latter report also provides no peer-reviewed evidence to support this claim). Furthermore, if it is apparently beyond our capability to model these impacts, how can they assign a ‘high likelihood’ to this outcome? While it is true that warming of this magnitude would be catastrophic, making claims such as this without evidence serves only to undermine the trust the public will have in the science. Daniel Swain, Researcher, UCLA, and Research Fellow, National Center for Atmospheric Research: It seems that the eye-catching headline-level claims in the report stem almost entirely from these knock-on effects, which the authors themselves admit are “beyond their capacity to model.” Thus, from a scientific perspective, the purported “high likelihood of civilization coming to an end by 2050” is essentially personal speculation on the part of the report’s authors, rather than a clear conclusion drawn from rigorous assessment of the available evidence.
4,402
<h4>Climate doesn’t cause extinction.</h4><p><strong>Kerr et al. 19</strong> – Dr. Amber Kerr, Energy and Resources PhD at the University of California-Berkeley, known agroecologist, former coordinator of the USDA California Climate Hub. Dr. Daniel Swain, Climate Science PhD at UCLA, climate scientist, a research fellow at the National Center for Atmospheric Research. Dr. Andrew King, Earth Sciences PhD, Climate Extremes Research Fellow at the University of Melbourne. Dr. Peter Kalmus, Physics PhD at the University of Colombia, climate scientist at NASA’s Jet Propulsion Lab. Professor Richard Betts, Chair in Climate Impacts at the University of Exeter, a lead author on the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) in Working Group 1. Dr. William Huiskamp, Paleoclimatology PhD at the Climate Change Research Center, climate scientist at the Potsdam Institute for Climate Impact Research. [Claim that human civilization could end in 30 years is speculative, not supported with evidence, 6-4-2019, https://climatefeedback.org/evaluation/iflscience-story-on-speculative-report-provides-little-scientific-context-james-felton/]</p><p><u><mark>There is <strong>no</mark> scientific <mark>basis</strong> to suggest</u></mark> that <u><strong><mark>climate breakdown</strong> will</mark> “annihilate <strong>intelligent life</strong>” (by which I assume the</u> report <u>authors <mark>mean <strong>human extinction</strong></mark>)</u> by 2050.</p><p>However, climate breakdown does pose a grave threat to civilization as we know it, and the potential for mass suffering on a scale perhaps never before encountered by humankind. This should be enough reason for action without any need for exaggeration or misrepresentation!</p><p>A “Hothouse Earth” scenario plays out that sees Earth’s temperatures doomed to rise by a further 1°C (1.8°F) even if we stopped emissions immediately.</p><p>Peter Kalmus, Data Scientist, Jet Propulsion Laboratory:</p><p>This word choice perhaps reveals a bias on the part of the author of the article. A temperature can’t be doomed. And while I certainly do not encourage false optimism, assuming that humanity is doomed is lazy and counterproductive.</p><p>Fifty-five percent of the global population are subject to more than 20 days a year of lethal heat conditions beyond that which humans can survive</p><p>Richard Betts, Professor, Met Office Hadley Centre & University of Exeter:</p><p>This is clearly from Mora et al (2017) although the report does not include a citation of the paper as the source of that statement. The way it is written here (and in the report) is misleading because it gives the impression that everyone dies in those conditions. That is not actually how Mora et al define “deadly heat” – they merely looked for heatwaves when somebody died (not everybody) and then used that as the definition of a “deadly” heatwave.</p><p>North America suffers extreme weather events including wildfires, drought, and heatwaves. Monsoons in China fail, the great rivers of Asia virtually dry up, and rainfall in central America falls by half.</p><p><u><strong>Andrew King, Research fellow, University of Melbourne:</p><p></strong><mark>Projections of <strong>extreme events</u></strong></mark> such as these <u><mark>are</mark> <strong>very <mark>difficult</strong> to make and <strong>vary</mark> greatly</strong> <mark>between</mark> <strong>different climate models</p><p></u></strong>.</p><p>Deadly heat conditions across West Africa persist for over 100 days a year</p><p>Peter Kalmus, Data Scientist, Jet Propulsion Laboratory:</p><p>The deadly heat projections (this, and the one from the previous paragraph) come from Mora et al (2017)1.</p><p>It should be clarified that “deadly heat” here means heat and humidity beyond a two-dimension threshold where at least one person in the region subject to that heat and humidity dies (i.e., not everyone instantly dies). That said, in my opinion, the projections in Mora et al are conservative and the methods of Mora et al are sound. I did not check the claims in this report against Mora et al but I have no reason to think they are in error.</p><p>1- Mora et al (2017) Global risk of deadly heat, Nature Climate Change</p><p>The knock-on consequences affect national security, as the scale of the challenges involved, such as pandemic disease outbreaks, are overwhelming. Armed conflicts over resources may become a reality, and have the potential to escalate into nuclear war. In the worst case scenario, a scale of destruction the authors say is beyond their capacity to model, there is a ‘high likelihood of human civilization coming to an end’.</p><p>Willem Huiskamp, Postdoctoral research fellow, Potsdam Institute for Climate Impact Research:</p><p>This is a highly questionable conclusion. The reference provided in the report is for the “Global Catastrophic Risks 2018” report from the “Global Challenges Foundation” and not peer-reviewed literature. (It is worth noting that this latter report also provides no peer-reviewed evidence to support this claim).</p><p>Furthermore, if it is apparently beyond our capability to model these impacts, how can they assign a ‘high likelihood’ to this outcome?</p><p>While it is true that warming of this magnitude would be catastrophic, making claims such as this without evidence serves only to undermine the trust the public will have in the science.</p><p>Daniel Swain, Researcher, UCLA, and Research Fellow, National Center for Atmospheric Research:</p><p>It seems that <u><strong>the eye-catching <mark>headline</mark>-level <mark>claims</strong></mark> in the report <strong><mark>stem</mark> almost entirely</strong> <mark>from</u></mark> these <u><strong><mark>knock-on effects</strong></mark>, which</u> the authors themselves admit <u>are <mark>“beyond</mark> their <mark>capacity to model.”</u></mark> Thus, <u><mark>from <strong>a scientific perspective</strong>, the</u></mark> purported “high <u><mark>likelihood</mark> of civilization coming to an end</u> by 2050” <u><mark>is</mark> <strong>essentially <mark>personal speculation</u></strong></mark> on the part of the report’s authors, <u><mark>rather than</mark> <strong>a clear <mark>conclusion</strong></mark> drawn <mark>from</mark> <strong><mark>rigorous</mark> assessment</strong> of <strong>the available <mark>evidence</u></strong></mark>.</p>
2NC
Adv---Europe
AT: Europe---2NC
7,355
969
51,131
./documents/ndtceda20/Michigan/PiRa/Michigan-Pierry-Rabbini-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
619,932
N
NDT
8
NDT
Habiba Ahmed, Shannon Howley, Hunter McCullough
1AC Georgian Enlargement 2NR NAC CP Hicks DA
ndtceda20/Michigan/PiRa/Michigan-Pierry-Rabbini-Neg-NDT-Round8.docx
null
52,383
PiRa
Michigan PiRa
null
Ra.....
Pi.....
Gi.....
Ra.....
19,334
Michigan
Michigan
null
null
1,010
ndtceda20
NDT/CEDA 2020-21
2,020
cx
college
2
1,210,897
No impact to economic decline --- countries respond with cooperation not conflict
Clary 15
Clary 15—PhD in Political Science from MIT and a Postdoctoral Fellow at the Watson Institute for International and Public Affairs at Brown [Christopher, “Economic Stress and International Cooperation: Evidence from International Rivalries,” MIT Political Science Department, Research Paper No. 2015-8, p. 4]
Economic crises lead to conciliatory behavior (1) Economic crises lead to austerity pressures, which in turn incent leaders to cut defense expenditures (2) Economic crises encourage strategic reassessment, so leaders can argue to their publics that defense spending can be arrested without endangering the state This can lead to threat deflation (3) If a state faces multiple threats, economic crises provoke elites to consider threat prioritization, a process that is postponed during economic normalcy (4) Economic crises increase the political and economic benefit from international economic cooperation Leaders seek foreign aid, enhanced trade, and increased investment from abroad during economic trouble This is easier if tensions are reduced (5) during crises, elites select leaders perceived as capable of resolving economic difficulties, permitting the emergence of leaders who hold heterodox foreign policy these mechanisms make it much more likely a leader will prefer conciliatory policies
Economic crises lead to conciliatory behavior austerity pressures incent leaders to cut defense expenditures crises encourage strategic reassessment This can lead to threat deflation crises provoke threat prioritization crises increase the benefit from cooperation Leaders seek aid, This is easier if tensions are reduced elites select leaders capable of resolving economic difficulties permitting heterodox foreign policy these make it much more likely a leader will prefer conciliatory policies
Economic crises lead to conciliatory behavior through five primary channels. (1) Economic crises lead to austerity pressures, which in turn incent leaders to search for ways to cut defense expenditures. (2) Economic crises also encourage strategic reassessment, so that leaders can argue to their peers and their publics that defense spending can be arrested without endangering the state. This can lead to threat deflation, where elites attempt to downplay the seriousness of the threat posed by a former rival. (3) If a state faces multiple threats, economic crises provoke elites to consider threat prioritization, a process that is postponed during periods of economic normalcy. (4) Economic crises increase the political and economic benefit from international economic cooperation. Leaders seek foreign aid, enhanced trade, and increased investment from abroad during periods of economic trouble. This search is made easier if tensions are reduced with historic rivals. (5) Finally, during crises, elites are more prone to select leaders who are perceived as capable of resolving economic difficulties, permitting the emergence of leaders who hold heterodox foreign policy views. Collectively, these mechanisms make it much more likely that a leader will prefer conciliatory policies compared to during periods of economic normalcy. This section reviews this causal logic in greater detail, while also providing historical examples that these mechanisms recur in practice.
1,478
<h4>No impact to economic decline --- countries respond with cooperation not conflict </h4><p><strong>Clary 15</strong>—PhD in Political Science from MIT and a Postdoctoral Fellow at the Watson Institute for International and Public Affairs at Brown [Christopher, “Economic Stress and International Cooperation: Evidence from International Rivalries,” MIT Political Science Department, Research Paper No. 2015-8, p. 4]</p><p><u><mark>Economic crises lead to conciliatory behavior</u></mark> through five primary channels. <u>(1) Economic crises lead to <mark>austerity pressures</mark>, which in turn <mark>incent leaders to</u></mark> search for ways to <u><mark>cut defense expenditures</u></mark>. <u>(2) Economic <mark>crises</u></mark> also <u><mark>encourage strategic reassessment</mark>, so</u> that <u>leaders can argue to</u> their peers and <u>their publics that defense spending can be arrested without endangering the state</u>. <u><mark>This can lead to threat deflation</u></mark>, where elites attempt to downplay the seriousness of the threat posed by a former rival. <u>(3) If a state faces multiple threats, economic <mark>crises provoke</mark> elites to consider <mark>threat prioritization</mark>, a process that is postponed during</u> periods of <u>economic normalcy</u>. <u>(4) Economic <mark>crises increase the</mark> political and economic <mark>benefit from</mark> international economic <mark>cooperation</u></mark>. <u><mark>Leaders seek</mark> foreign <mark>aid,</mark> enhanced trade, and increased investment from abroad during</u> periods of <u>economic trouble</u>. <u><mark>This</u></mark> search <u><mark>is</u></mark> made <u><mark>easier if tensions are reduced</u></mark> with historic rivals. <u>(5)</u> Finally, <u>during crises, <mark>elites</u></mark> are more prone to <u><mark>select</u></mark> <u><mark>leaders</u></mark> who are <u>perceived as <mark>capable of resolving economic difficulties</mark>, <mark>permitting</mark> the emergence of leaders who hold <mark>heterodox foreign policy</u></mark> views. Collectively, <u><mark>these</mark> mechanisms <mark>make it much more likely</u></mark> that <u><mark>a leader will prefer conciliatory policies</u></mark> compared to during periods of economic normalcy. This section reviews this causal logic in greater detail, while also providing historical examples that these mechanisms recur in practice.</p>
null
1NC
Agriculture
983
2,566
29,670
./documents/hspolicy21/Peninsula/BrYu/Peninsula-Brown-Yu-Neg-La%20Costa%20Canyon%20Winter%20Classic-Round1.docx
753,863
N
La Costa Canyon Winter Classic
1
Northwood LL
Tseng, Alex
1NC - T-protection States CP filibuster DA EPA DA treatment CP Dedev Block - Treatment filibuster Dedev 2nr - DeDev Case
hspolicy21/Peninsula/BrYu/Peninsula-Brown-Yu-Neg-La%20Costa%20Canyon%20Winter%20Classic-Round1.docx
null
64,303
BrYu
Peninsula BrYu
null
Na.....
Br.....
St.....
Yu.....
22,099
Peninsula
Peninsula
CA
null
1,020
hspolicy21
HS Policy 2021-22
2,021
cx
hs
2
4,085,713
Primacy prevents great-power conflict — multipolar revisionism fragments the global order and causes nuclear war
Brands & Edel, 19
Brands & Edel, 19 — Hal Brands; PhD, Henry A. Kissinger Distinguished Professor of Global Affairs at the Johns Hopkins School of Advanced International Studies. Charles Edel; PhD, Senior Fellow and Visiting Scholar at the United States Studies Centre at the University of Sydney. (“The Lessons of Tragedy: Statecraft and World Order;” Ch. 6: Darkening Horizon; Published by Yale University Press; //GrRv)Each of these geopolitical challenges is different, and each reflects the distinctive interests, ambitions, and history of the country undertaking it. Yet there is growing cooperation between the countries that are challenging the regional pillars of the U.S.-led order. Russia and China have collaborated on issues such as energy, sales and development of military technology, opposition to additional U.S. military deployments on the Korean peninsula, and naval exercises from the South China Sea to the Baltic. In Syria, Iran provided the shock troops that helped keep Russia’s ally, Bashar al-Assad, in power, as Moscow provided the air power and the diplomatic cover. “Our cooperation can isolate America,” supreme leader Ali Khamenei told Putin in 2017. More broadly, what links these challenges together is their opposition to the constellation of power, norms, and relationships that the U.S.-led order entails, and in their propensity to use violence, coercion, and intimidation as means of making that opposition effective. Taken collectively, these challenges constitute a geopolitical sea change from the post-Cold War era.
The revival of great-power competition entails arms races, security dilemmas, and sharper conflicts rival powers could overturn the regional balances that have underpinned the U.S.-led order for decades, and that they might construct rival spheres of influence great-power rivalry could lead to great-power war Beijing and Moscow are exercising aggressively for conflicts Russian doctrine emphasizes the use of nuclear weapons The world has returned to great-power struggle Russia does not simply want to be a “regional power” It aspires to the an and extra-regional impact Why else would Moscow deploy into the Midd East? China its ambitions are bolder. . Chinese military forces are deploying ever farther Beijing has projected power into the Arctic and established bases in the Indian and Africa Xi told the C C t P Beijing could take center stage in the world” and act as an alternative to U.S. leadership revisionism may t be only the beginning will move on to grander endeavors geopolitical revisionism has presaged intensifying international conflict, and war America should bolster its defenses,
great-power competition entails arms races, security dilemmas, and sharper conflicts rival powers could overturn the regional balances that have underpinned the U.S.-led order they might construct rival spheres of influence great-power rivalry could lead to great-power war Beijing and Moscow are exercising aggressively for conflicts Russian doctrine emphasizes the use of nuclear weapons The world returned to great-power struggle Russia aspires to an extra-regional impact Why else would Moscow deploy into the Midd East? China s ambitions are bolde Beijing has projected power into the Arctic and established bases in India and Africa Xi told the C C P Beijing could take center stage and act as an alternative to U.S. leadership revisionism may be only the beginning will move on to grander endeavors geopolitical revisionism has presaged intensifying international conflict and war America should bolster its defenses,
The revival of great-power competition entails higher international tensions than the world has known for decades, and the revival of arms races, security dilemmas, and other artifacts of a more dangerous past. It entails sharper conflicts over the international rules of the road on issues ranging from freedom of navigation to the illegitimacy of altering borders by force, and intensifying competitions over states that reside at the intersection of rival powers’ areas of interest. It requires confronting the prospect that rival powers could overturn the favorable regional balances that have underpinned the U.S.-led order for decades, and that they might construct rival spheres of influence from which America and the liberal ideas it has long promoted would be excluded. Finally, it necessitates recognizing that great-power rivalry could lead to great-power war, a prospect that seemed to have followed the Soviet empire onto the ash heap of history. Both Beijing and Moscow are, after all, optimizing their forces and exercising aggressively in preparation for potential conflicts with the United States and its allies; Russian doctrine explicitly emphasizes the limited use of nuclear weapons to achieve escalation dominance in a war with Washington. In Syria, U.S. and Russian forces even came into deadly contact in early 2018. American airpower decimated a contingent of government-sponsored Russian mercenaries that was attacking a base at which U.S. troops were present, an incident demonstrating the increasing boldness of Russian operations and the corresponding potential for escalation. The world has not yet returned to the epic clashes for global dominance that characterized the twentieth century, but it has returned to the historical norm of great-power struggle, with all the associated dangers. Those dangers may be even greater than most observers appreciate, because if today’s great-power competitions are still most intense at the regional level, who is to say where these competitions will end? By all appearances, Russia does not simply want to be a “regional power” (as Obama cuttingly described it) that dominates South Ossetia and Crimea.37 It aspires to the deep European and extra-regional impact that previous incarnations of the Russian state enjoyed. Why else would Putin boast about how far his troops can drive into Eastern Europe? Why else would Moscow be deploying military power into the Middle East? Why else would it be continuing to cultivate intelligence and military relationships in regions as remote as Latin America? Likewise, China is today focused primarily on securing its own geopolitical neighborhood, but its ambitions for tomorrow are clearly much bolder. Beijing probably does not envision itself fully overthrowing the international order, simply because it has profited far too much from the U.S.-anchored global economy. Yet China has nonetheless positioned itself for a global challenge to U.S. influence. Chinese military forces are deploying ever farther from China’s immediate periphery; Beijing has projected power into the Arctic and established bases and logistical points in the Indian Ocean and Horn of Africa. Popular Chinese movies depict Beijing replacing Washington as the dominant actor in sub-Saharan Africa—a fictional representation of a real-life effort long under way. The Belt and Road Initiative bespeaks an aspiration to link China to countries throughout Central Asia, the Middle East, and Europe; BRI, AIIB, and RCEP look like the beginning of an alternative institutional architecture to rival Washington’s. In 2017, Xi Jinping told the Nineteenth National Congress of the Chinese Communist Party that Beijing could now “take center stage in the world” and act as an alternative to U.S. leadership.38 These ambitions may or may not be realistic. But they demonstrate just how significantly the world’s leading authoritarian powers desire to shift the global environment over time. The revisionism we are seeing today may therefore be only the beginning. As China’s power continues to grow, or if it is successful in dominating the Western Pacific, it will surely move on to grander endeavors. If Russia reconsolidates control over the former Soviet space, it may seek to bring parts of the former Warsaw Pact to heel. Historically, this has been a recurring pattern of great-power behavior—interests expand with power, the appetite grows with the eating, risk-taking increases as early gambles are seen to pay off.39 This pattern is precisely why the revival of great-power competition is so concerning—because geopolitical revisionism by unsatisfied major powers has so often presaged intensifying international conflict, confrontation, and even war. The great-power behavior occurring today represents the warning light flashing on the dashboard. It tells us there may be still-greater traumas to come. The threats today are compelling and urgent, and there may someday come a time when the balance of power has shifted so markedly that the postwar international system cannot be sustained. Yet that moment of failure has not yet arrived, and so the goal of U.S. strategy should be not to hasten it by giving up prematurely, but to push it off as far into the future as possible. Rather than simply acquiescing in the decline of a world it spent generations building, America should aggressively bolster its defenses, with an eye to preserving and perhaps even selectively advancing its remarkable achievements.
5,504
<h4>Primacy prevents <u>great-power conflict</u> — multipolar revisionism <u>fragments</u> the <u>global order</u> and causes <u>nuclear war</h4><p></u><strong>Brands & Edel, 19</strong> — Hal Brands; PhD, Henry A. Kissinger Distinguished Professor of Global Affairs at the Johns Hopkins School of Advanced International Studies. Charles Edel; PhD, Senior Fellow and Visiting Scholar at the United States Studies Centre at the University of Sydney. (“The Lessons of Tragedy: Statecraft and World Order;” Ch. 6: Darkening Horizon; Published by Yale University Press; //GrRv)Each of these geopolitical challenges is different, and each reflects the distinctive interests, ambitions, and history of the country undertaking it. Yet there is growing cooperation between the countries that are challenging the regional pillars of the U.S.-led order. Russia and China have collaborated on issues such as energy, sales and development of military technology, opposition to additional U.S. military deployments on the Korean peninsula, and naval exercises from the South China Sea to the Baltic. In Syria, Iran provided the shock troops that helped keep Russia’s ally, Bashar al-Assad, in power, as Moscow provided the air power and the diplomatic cover. “Our cooperation can isolate America,” supreme leader Ali Khamenei told Putin in 2017. More broadly, what links these challenges together is their opposition to the constellation of power, norms, and relationships that the U.S.-led order entails, and in their propensity to use violence, coercion, and intimidation as means of making that opposition effective. Taken collectively, these challenges constitute a geopolitical sea change from the post-Cold War era.</p><p><u>The revival of <strong><mark>great-power competition</strong> entails</u></mark> higher international tensions than the world has known for decades, and the revival of <u><strong><mark>arms races, security dilemmas</strong>, and</mark> </u>other artifacts of a more dangerous past. It entails<u> <strong><mark>sharper conflicts</strong></mark> </u>over the international rules of the road on issues ranging from freedom of navigation to the illegitimacy of altering borders by force, and intensifying competitions over states that reside at the intersection of rival powers’ areas of interest. It requires confronting the prospect that <u><strong><mark>rival powers</strong> could <strong>overturn</strong> the </u></mark>favorable <u><strong><mark>regional balances</strong> that have <strong>underpinned</strong> the U.S.-led order</mark> for decades, and that <mark>they might construct <strong>rival spheres of influence</u></strong></mark> from which America and the liberal ideas it has long promoted would be excluded. Finally, it necessitates recognizing that <u><mark>great-power rivalry could lead to <strong>great-power war</u></strong></mark>, a prospect that seemed to have followed the Soviet empire onto the ash heap of history. Both <u><strong><mark>Beijing</strong> and <strong>Moscow</strong> are</u></mark>, after all, optimizing their forces and<u> <strong><mark>exercising aggressively</strong></mark> </u>in preparation<u> <mark>for</mark> </u>potential<u> <strong><mark>conflicts</strong></mark> </u>with the United States and its allies; <u><mark>Russian doctrine</mark> </u>explicitly<u> <mark>emphasizes the</u></mark> limited <u><mark>use of <strong>nuclear weapons</u></strong></mark> to achieve escalation dominance in a war with Washington. In Syria, U.S. and Russian forces even came into deadly contact in early 2018. American airpower decimated a contingent of government-sponsored Russian mercenaries that was attacking a base at which U.S. troops were present, an incident demonstrating the increasing boldness of Russian operations and the corresponding potential for escalation. <u><mark>The world</u></mark> has not yet returned to the epic clashes for global dominance that characterized the twentieth century, but it <u>has <mark>returned to</mark> </u>the historical norm of<u> <strong><mark>great-power struggle</u></strong></mark>, with all the associated dangers. Those dangers may be even greater than most observers appreciate, because if today’s great-power competitions are still most intense at the regional level, who is to say where these competitions will end? By all appearances, <u><mark>Russia <strong></mark>does not simply want to be</strong> a “<strong>regional power</strong>”</u> (as Obama cuttingly described it) that dominates South Ossetia and Crimea.37 <u>It <strong><mark>aspires</strong></mark> <mark>to</mark> the </u>deep Europe<u><strong><mark>an</strong></mark> and <strong><mark>extra-regional impact</strong></mark> </u>that previous incarnations of the Russian state enjoyed. Why else would Putin boast about how far his troops can drive into Eastern Europe? <u><strong><mark>Why else</strong> would Moscow</u></mark> be <u><strong><mark>deploy</u></strong></mark>ing military power <u><mark>into the <strong>Midd</u></strong></mark>le <u><strong><mark>East?</u></strong></mark> Why else would it be continuing to cultivate intelligence and military relationships in regions as remote as Latin America?<u><strong> </u></strong>Likewise, <u><mark>China</mark> </u>is today focused primarily on securing its own geopolitical neighborhood, but <u>it<mark>s</mark> <mark>ambitions </u></mark>for tomorrow<u> <mark>are</mark> </u>clearly much<u><strong> <mark>bolde</mark>r. </u></strong>Beijing probably does not envision itself fully overthrowing the international order, simply because it has profited far too much from the U.S.-anchored global economy. Yet China has nonetheless positioned itself for a global challenge to U.S. influence<u>.</u> <u>Chinese military forces are deploying <strong>ever farther</strong> </u>from China’s immediate periphery;<u> <mark>Beijing has <strong>projected power</strong> into the <strong>Arctic</strong> and <strong>established bases</strong></mark> </u>and logistical points<u> <mark>in</mark> the <strong><mark>India</mark>n </u></strong>Ocean<u> <mark>and</mark> </u>Horn of<u><strong> <mark>Africa</u></strong></mark>. Popular Chinese movies depict Beijing replacing Washington as the dominant actor in sub-Saharan Africa—a fictional representation of a real-life effort long under way. The Belt and Road Initiative bespeaks an aspiration to link China to countries throughout Central Asia, the Middle East, and Europe; BRI, AIIB, and RCEP look like the beginning of an alternative institutional architecture to rival Washington’s. In 2017, <u><mark>Xi</u></mark> Jinping <u><mark>told the</u></mark> Nineteenth National Congress of the<u> <mark>C</u></mark>hinese<u> <mark>C</u></mark>ommunis<u>t <mark>P</u></mark>arty that <u><mark>Beijing could</u></mark> now “<u><strong><mark>take center stage </strong></mark>in the world”</u> <u><mark>and act as an <strong>alternative</strong> to <strong>U.S. leadership</u></strong></mark>.38 These ambitions may or may not be realistic. But they demonstrate just how significantly the world’s leading authoritarian powers desire to shift the global environment over time. The <u><strong><mark>revisionism</u></strong></mark> we are seeing today <u><mark>may </mark>t</u>herefore<u> <mark>be <strong>only the beginning</u></strong></mark>. As China’s power continues to grow, or if it is successful in dominating the Western Pacific, it<u> <mark>will</mark> </u>surely<u><strong> <mark>move on</strong> to <strong>grander endeavors</u></strong></mark>. If Russia reconsolidates control over the former Soviet space, it may seek to bring parts of the former Warsaw Pact to heel. Historically, this has been a recurring pattern of great-power behavior—interests expand with power, the appetite grows with the eating, risk-taking increases as early gambles are seen to pay off.39 This pattern is precisely why the revival of great-power competition is so concerning—because <u><strong><mark>geopolitical revisionism</strong></mark> </u>by unsatisfied major powers<u> <mark>has</mark> </u>so often<u> <mark>presaged <strong>intensifying international conflict</strong></mark>,</u> confrontation, <u><mark>and</mark> </u>even<u> <strong><mark>war</u></strong></mark>. The great-power behavior occurring today represents the warning light flashing on the dashboard. It tells us there may be still-greater traumas to come. The threats today are compelling and urgent, and there may someday come a time when the balance of power has shifted so markedly that the postwar international system cannot be sustained. Yet that moment of failure has not yet arrived, and so the goal of U.S. strategy should be not to hasten it by giving up prematurely, but to push it off as far into the future as possible. Rather than simply acquiescing in the decline of a world it spent generations building, <u><mark>America should</mark> </u>aggressively <u><strong><mark>bolster its defenses</strong>,</mark> </u>with an eye to preserving and perhaps even selectively advancing its remarkable achievements.</p>
1NC
Contention 1: Military
null
541
755
140,028
./documents/hsld22/Unionville/IaCo/Unionville-IaCo-Neg-National-Speech-and-Debate-Season-Opener-Round-4.docx
923,340
N
National Speech and Debate Season Opener
4
Sage Oak Charter AK
Bokhari
null
hsld22/Unionville/IaCo/Unionville-IaCo-Neg-National-Speech-and-Debate-Season-Opener-Round-4.docx
2022-09-10 22:15:05
80,436
IaCo
Unionville IaCo
null
Ia.....
Co.....
null
null
26,654
Unionville
Unionville
PA
879
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
1,441,889
Extinction– defense is wrong
Millett 17
Piers Millett 17, Consultant for the World Health Organization, PhD in International Relations and Affairs, University of Bradford, Andrew Snyder-Beattie, “Existential Risk and Cost-Effective Biosecurity”, Health Security, Vol 15(4), http://online.liebertpub.com/doi/pdfplus/10.1089/hs.2017.0028
disease events have been responsible for the greatest death tolls on humanity. The 1918 flu was responsible for more than 50 million deaths smallpox killed perhaps 10 times that many in the 20th century alone. The Black Death was responsible for killing over 25% of the European population other pandemics are thought to have killed 25 million a future pandemic could result in outright human extinction or the irreversible collapse of civilization A skeptic would have reasons to think that existential risk from disease is unlikely. Such a disease would need to spread worldwide to remote populations, overcome genetic resistances, and evade detection Virulence and transmission is often a trade-off these arguments they do not rule the possibility out there are recorded instances of species going extinct due to disease are also historical examples of large human populations being almost entirely wiped out by disease, especially when multiple diseases were simultaneously introduced into a population many diseases are proof of principle that each worst-case attribute can be realized independently. some diseases exhibit nearly a 100% case fatality ratio in the absence of treatment . Other diseases have a track record of spreading to virtually every human community worldwide, seroprevalence studies indicate that other pathogens, , can successfully reach over 95% of a population Under optimal virulence theory, natural evolution would be an unlikely source for pathogens with the highest possible levels of transmissibility But advances in biotechnology might allow the creation of diseases that combine such traits. studies have shown that other disease traits, such as incubation time, environmental survival, and available vectors, could be modifie
pandemic could result in human extinction a disease would need to spread worldwide Virulence and transmission is a trade-off arguments do not rule possibility out instances of species going extinct due to disease also examples of human populations being wiped out especially when multiple diseases were introduced some diseases exhibit 100% fatality Other diseases spread to every community worldwide advances in biotech might allow the creation of diseases that combine traits
Historically, disease events have been responsible for the greatest death tolls on humanity. The 1918 flu was responsible for more than 50 million deaths,1 while smallpox killed perhaps 10 times that many in the 20th century alone.2 The Black Death was responsible for killing over 25% of the European population,3 while other pandemics, such as the plague of Justinian, are thought to have killed 25 million in the 6th century—constituting over 10% of the world’s population at the time.4 It is an open question whether a future pandemic could result in outright human extinction or the irreversible collapse of civilization. A skeptic would have many good reasons to think that existential risk from disease is unlikely. Such a disease would need to spread worldwide to remote populations, overcome rare genetic resistances, and evade detection, cures, and countermeasures. Even evolution itself may work in humanity’s favor: Virulence and transmission is often a trade-off, and so evolutionary pressures could push against maximally lethal wild-type pathogens.5,6 While these arguments point to a very small risk of human extinction, they do not rule the possibility out entirely. Although rare, there are recorded instances of species going extinct due to disease—primarily in amphibians, but also in 1 mammalian species of rat on Christmas Island.7,8 There are also historical examples of large human populations being almost entirely wiped out by disease, especially when multiple diseases were simultaneously introduced into a population without immunity. The most striking examples of total population collapse include native American tribes exposed to European diseases, such as the Massachusett (86% loss of population), Quiripi-Unquachog (95% loss of population), and theWestern Abenaki (which suffered a staggering 98% loss of population). In the modern context, no single disease currently exists that combines the worst-case levels of transmissibility, lethality, resistance to countermeasures, and global reach. But many diseases are proof of principle that each worst-case attribute can be realized independently. For example, some diseases exhibit nearly a 100% case fatality ratio in the absence of treatment, such as rabies or septicemic plague. Other diseases have a track record of spreading to virtually every human community worldwide, such as the 1918 flu,10 and seroprevalence studies indicate that other pathogens, such as chickenpox and HSV-1, can successfully reach over 95% of a population.11,12 Under optimal virulence theory, natural evolution would be an unlikely source for pathogens with the highest possible levels of transmissibility, virulence, and global reach. But advances in biotechnology might allow the creation of diseases that combine such traits. Recent controversy has already emerged over a number of scientific experiments that resulted in viruses with enhanced transmissibility, lethality, and/or the ability to overcome therapeutics.13-17 Other experiments demonstrated that mousepox could be modified to have a 100% case fatality rate and render a vaccine ineffective.18 In addition to transmissibility and lethality, studies have shown that other disease traits, such as incubation time, environmental survival, and available vectors, could be modified as well.19-2
3,318
<h4><u>Extinction</u>– defense is wrong </h4><p>Piers <strong>Millett 17</strong>, Consultant for the World Health Organization, PhD in International Relations and Affairs, University of Bradford, Andrew Snyder-Beattie, “Existential Risk and Cost-Effective Biosecurity”, Health Security, Vol 15(4), http://online.liebertpub.com/doi/pdfplus/10.1089/hs.2017.0028</p><p>Historically, <u><strong>disease events have been responsible for the greatest death tolls on humanity. The 1918 flu was responsible for more than 50 million deaths</u></strong>,1 while <u><strong>smallpox killed perhaps 10 times that many in the 20th century alone.</u></strong>2 <u><strong>The Black Death was responsible for killing over 25% of the European population</u></strong>,3 while <u><strong>other pandemics</u></strong>, such as the plague of Justinian, <u><strong>are thought to have killed 25 million</u></strong> in the 6th century—constituting over 10% of the world’s population at the time.4 It is an open question whether <u><strong>a future <mark>pandemic could result in </mark>outright <mark>human extinction</mark> or the irreversible collapse of civilization</u></strong>. </p><p><u><strong>A skeptic would have</u></strong> many good <u><strong>reasons to think that existential risk from disease is unlikely. Such <mark>a disease would need to spread worldwide</mark> to remote populations, overcome</u></strong> rare <u><strong>genetic resistances, and evade detection</u></strong>, cures, and countermeasures. Even evolution itself may work in humanity’s favor: <u><strong><mark>Virulence and transmission is</mark> often <mark>a trade-off</u></strong></mark>, and so evolutionary pressures could push against maximally lethal wild-type pathogens.5,6 </p><p>While <u><strong>these <mark>arguments</u></strong></mark> point to a very small risk of human extinction, <u><strong>they <mark>do not rule </mark>the <mark>possibility out</u></strong></mark> entirely. Although rare, <u><strong>there are recorded <mark>instances of species going extinct due to disease</u></strong></mark>—primarily in amphibians, but also in 1 mammalian species of rat on Christmas Island.7,8 There <u><strong>are <mark>also</mark> historical <mark>examples of</mark> large <mark>human populations being</mark> almost entirely <mark>wiped out</mark> by disease, <mark>especially when multiple diseases were</mark> simultaneously <mark>introduced</mark> into a population </u></strong>without immunity. The most striking examples of total population collapse include native American tribes exposed to European diseases, such as the Massachusett (86% loss of population), Quiripi-Unquachog (95% loss of population), and theWestern Abenaki (which suffered a staggering 98% loss of population). </p><p>In the modern context, no single disease currently exists that combines the worst-case levels of transmissibility, lethality, resistance to countermeasures, and global reach. But <u><strong>many diseases are proof of principle that each worst-case attribute can be realized independently.</u></strong> For example, <u><strong><mark>some diseases exhibit</mark> nearly a <mark>100%</mark> case <mark>fatality</mark> ratio in the absence of treatment</u></strong>, such as rabies or septicemic plague<u><strong>. <mark>Other diseases</mark> have a track record of <mark>spread</mark>ing <mark>to</mark> virtually <mark>every</mark> human <mark>community worldwide</mark>,</u></strong> such as the 1918 flu,10 and <u><strong>seroprevalence studies indicate that other pathogens,</u></strong> such as chickenpox and HSV-1<u><strong>, can successfully reach over 95% of a population</u></strong>.11,12 <u><strong>Under optimal virulence theory, natural evolution would be an unlikely source for pathogens with the highest possible levels of transmissibility</u></strong>, virulence, and global reach. <u><strong>But <mark>advances in biotech</mark>nology <mark>might allow the creation of diseases that combine</mark> such <mark>traits</mark>.</u></strong> Recent controversy has already emerged over a number of scientific experiments that resulted in viruses with enhanced transmissibility, lethality, and/or the ability to overcome therapeutics.13-17 Other experiments demonstrated that mousepox could be modified to have a 100% case fatality rate and render a vaccine ineffective.18 In addition to transmissibility and lethality, <u><strong>studies have shown that other disease traits, such as incubation time, environmental survival, and available vectors, could be modifie</u></strong>d as well.19-2</p>
Malbrough VA
1NC – Off
null
2,127
2,005
39,587
./documents/hsld21/ImmaculateHeart/Sa/Immaculate%20Heart-Sanchez-Neg-Nano%20Nagle%20Classic-Round3.docx
889,807
N
Nano Nagle Classic
3
Marlborough VA
Vishan Chaudhary
AC- MSF AC NC- Innovation DA Consult CP Case 1AR- All Consult Bad 2NR- Consult CP Case Consult Bad 2AR- Case Consult
hsld21/ImmaculateHeart/Sa/Immaculate%20Heart-Sanchez-Neg-Nano%20Nagle%20Classic-Round3.docx
null
74,797
ShSa
Immaculate Heart ShSa
null
Sh.....
Sa.....
null
null
25,023
ImmaculateHeart
Immaculate Heart
CA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
1,123,505
States have authority to implement regulations and solve better
Nolon ’19
Nolon ’19 [John R. Nolon, Distinguished Professor of Law at the Elisabeth Haub School of Law at Pace University where he teaches property, land use, dispute resolution, and sustainable development law courses; “CALMING TROUBLED WATERS: LOCAL SOLUTIONS”; Vermont Law Review Vol. 44:001 (2019); https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3454651]
limits on Congress’s authority under the Commerce Clause constrain CWA jurisdiction the Act can only go as far as the Constitution allows As the Supreme Court explained, the reach of Commerce Clause authority “must be considered in the light of our dual system of government” and cannot swallow the line between what is federal and what is truly local authority over waters is fragmented in many contexts, states have the sole power to implement protective regulations directly or by delegating that authority to their local governments This federalism structure is a hallmark characteristic of the CWA It is meant to respect states’ traditional jurisdiction The federal government therefore has limited jurisdiction over water pollution and leaves much regulation to the states and their municipalities If the interconnected groundwater, wetlands, and surface waters are to be properly protected, state governments must implement their own laws addressing water pollution
authority is fragmented states have sole power to implement protective reg s federalism is hallmark of CWA fed has limited jurisdiction over water and leaves regulation to states If groundwater, wetlands, and surface waters are to be protected, state s must implement laws
The limits on Congress’s authority under the Commerce Clause constrain CWA jurisdiction; the Act can only go as far as the Constitution allows.157 As the Supreme Court explained, the reach of Commerce Clause authority “must be considered in the light of our dual system of government” and cannot swallow the line between what is federal and what is truly local.158 In this way, authority over waters is fragmented, and, in many contexts, states have the sole power to implement protective regulations directly or by delegating that authority to their local governments.159 This federalism structure is a hallmark characteristic of the CWA.160 It is meant to respect states’ traditional jurisdiction over their property.161 The Act states that, “[i]t is the policy of the Congress to recognize, preserve, and protect the primary responsibilities and rights of States.”162 The federal government therefore has limited jurisdiction over water pollution and leaves much regulation to the states and their municipalities.163 If the interconnected groundwater, wetlands, and surface waters in watersheds are to be properly protected, state and local governments must implement their own laws addressing water pollution.164
1,216
<h4>States <u>have authority</u> to implement regulations and <u>solve better </h4><p></u><strong>Nolon ’19 </strong>[John R. Nolon, Distinguished Professor of Law at the Elisabeth Haub School of Law at Pace University where he teaches property, land use, dispute resolution, and sustainable development law courses; “CALMING TROUBLED WATERS: LOCAL SOLUTIONS”; Vermont Law Review Vol. 44:001 (2019); https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3454651]</p><p>The <u>limits on Congress’s authority under the Commerce Clause <strong>constrain</strong> <strong>CWA jurisdiction</u></strong>; <u>the Act can only go as far as the Constitution allows</u>.157 <u>As the Supreme Court explained, the reach of Commerce Clause authority “must be considered in the light of our<strong> dual system</strong> of government” and cannot swallow the line between what is <strong>federal</strong> and what is <strong>truly local</u></strong>.158 In this way, <u><mark>authority </mark>over waters <mark>is <strong>fragmented</u></strong></mark>, and, <u>in many contexts, <mark>states have</mark> the <strong><mark>sole power</strong> to implement <strong>protective reg</mark>ulation<mark>s</strong></mark> directly or by delegating that authority to their local governments</u>.159</p><p><u>This <strong><mark>federalism</mark> structure</strong> <mark>is</mark> a <strong><mark>hallmark</mark> characteristic</strong> <mark>of</mark> the <strong><mark>CWA</u></strong></mark>.160 <u>It is meant to <strong>respect states’</strong> traditional <strong>jurisdiction</u></strong> over their property.161 The Act states that, “[i]t is the policy of the Congress to recognize, preserve, and protect the primary responsibilities and rights of States.”162 <u>The <mark>fed</mark>eral government therefore <mark>has <strong>limited jurisdiction</strong> over <strong>water</mark> pollution</strong> <mark>and leaves</mark> <strong>much <mark>regulation</strong> to</mark> the <mark>states</mark> and their municipalities</u>.163 <u><mark>If</mark> the interconnected <strong><mark>groundwater</strong>, <strong>wetlands</strong>, and <strong>surface waters</u></strong></mark> in watersheds <u><mark>are to be</mark> properly <mark>protected, state</u></mark> and local <u>government<mark>s must implement</mark> their <strong>own <mark>laws</strong></mark> addressing water pollution</u>.164</p>
1NC
OFF
null
32,170
449
28,218
./documents/hspolicy21/Mamaroneck/PeLa/Mamaroneck-Peters-Land-Neg-Blake-Round4.docx
750,625
N
Blake
4
Peninsula RY
Steiner,Rebecca
1AC Water Markets 2NR Cap
hspolicy21/Mamaroneck/PeLa/Mamaroneck-Peters-Land-Neg-Blake-Round4.docx
null
64,038
PeLa
Mamaroneck PeLa
null
Pe.....
Pe.....
Ja.....
La.....
22,044
Mamaroneck
Mamaroneck
NY
null
1,020
hspolicy21
HS Policy 2021-22
2,021
cx
hs
2
1,665,636
Flexible executive power solves national security, rogue states, and WMD prolif – new legal checks are existentially dangerous
Yoo 17
John Yoo 17, J.D. from Yale, Emanuel Heller Professor of Law and director of the Korea Law Center, the California Constitution Center, and the Law School’s Program in Public Law and Policy, "Trump’s Syria Strike Was Constitutional", National Review, https://www.nationalreview.com/2017/04/trump-syria-strike-constitutional-presidents-have-broad-war-powers/
Our Constitution has succeeded because it favors swift presidential action in war A radical change in the system for making war might appease critics of presidential power But it could also seriously threaten American national security In order to forestall another 9/11 or take advantage of a window of opportunity to strike terrorists or rogue nations the executive branch needs flexibility It is not hard to think of situations where congressional consent cannot be obtained in time to act Time for congressional deliberation will come at the price of speed and secrecy Presidents can take the initiative and Congress can use its funding power to check presidents Instead of demanding a legalistic process the Framers left war to politics As we confront the new challenges of terrorism rogue nations and WMD proliferation now is not the time to introduce sweeping untested changes
Constitution favors swift presidential action in war A radical change could seriously threaten American national security to forestall another 9/11 or strike terrorists or rogue nations the executive needs flexibility deliberation will come at the price of speed and secrecy As we confront terrorism, rogue nations, and WMD proliferation, now is not the time to introduce sweeping, untested changes
Our Constitution has succeeded because it favors swift presidential action in war, later checked by Congress’s funding power. If a president continues to wage war without congressional authorization, as in Libya, Kosovo, or Korea, it is only because Congress has chosen not to exercise its easy check. We should not confuse a desire to escape political responsibility for a defect in the Constitution. A radical change in the system for making war might appease critics of presidential power. But it could also seriously threaten American national security. In order to forestall another 9/11 attack, or take advantage of a window of opportunity to strike terrorists or rogue nations, the executive branch needs flexibility. It is not hard to think of situations where congressional consent cannot be obtained in time to act. Time for congressional deliberation, which can lead to passivity and isolation and not smarter decisions, will come at the price of speed and secrecy. The Constitution creates a presidency that can respond forcefully to prevent serious threats to our national security. Presidents can take the initiative, and Congress can use its funding power to check presidents. Instead of demanding a legalistic process to begin war, the Framers left war to politics. As we confront the new challenges of terrorism, rogue nations, and WMD proliferation, now is not the time to introduce sweeping, untested changes in the way we make war.
1,451
<h4>Flexible executive power solves national security, rogue states, and WMD prolif – new legal checks are existentially dangerous</h4><p>John <strong>Yoo 17</strong>, J.D. from Yale, Emanuel Heller Professor of Law and director of the Korea Law Center, the California Constitution Center, and the Law School’s Program in Public Law and Policy, "Trump’s Syria Strike Was Constitutional", National Review, https://www.nationalreview.com/2017/04/trump-syria-strike-constitutional-presidents-have-broad-war-powers/</p><p><u>Our <mark>Constitution </mark>has <strong>succeeded</u></strong> <u>because it <mark>favors <strong>swift presidential action in war</u></strong></mark>, later checked by Congress’s funding power. If a president continues to wage war without congressional authorization, as in Libya, Kosovo, or Korea, it is only because Congress has chosen not to exercise its easy check. We should not confuse a desire to escape political responsibility for a defect in the Constitution. <u><mark>A <strong>radical change</mark> in the system</u></strong> <u>for making war might appease critics of presidential power</u>. <u>But it <mark>could</mark> also <strong><mark>seriously threaten American national security</u></strong></mark>. <u>In order <mark>to <strong>forestall another 9/11</u></strong></mark> attack, <u><mark>or</u></mark> <u>take advantage of a window of opportunity to <strong><mark>strike terrorists</strong> or <strong>rogue nations</u></strong></mark>, <u><mark>the executive</mark> branch <mark>needs <strong>flexibility</u></strong></mark>. <u>It is not hard to think of situations where congressional consent cannot be obtained in time to act</u>. <u>Time for congressional <mark>deliberation</u></mark>, which can lead to passivity and isolation and not smarter decisions, <u><mark>will come at the price of <strong>speed</strong> and <strong>secrecy</u></strong></mark>. The Constitution creates a presidency that can respond forcefully to prevent serious threats to our national security. <u>Presidents can take the initiative</u>, <u>and Congress can use its funding power to check presidents</u>. <u>Instead of demanding a <strong>legalistic process</u></strong> to begin war, <u>the Framers left war to politics</u>. <u><mark>As we confront</mark> the new challenges of</u> <u><strong><mark>terrorism</u></strong>, <u><strong>rogue nations</u></strong>, <u>and</u> <u><strong>WMD proliferation</u></strong>, <u>now is <strong>not the time</strong> to introduce <strong>sweeping</u></strong>, <u><strong>untested changes</u></strong></mark> in the way we make war.</p>
2AC
Recission CP
Flex Good---2AC
7,349
996
49,704
./documents/ndtceda20/GeorgeMason/LoMo/George%20Mason-Loew-Morris-Aff-ADA-Round3.docx
617,644
A
ADA
3
Wichita BL
Galloway
1AC-Baltics 1NC-assurancedip cap flex response cp increase presence cp recission cp 2NR-dip cap
ndtceda20/GeorgeMason/LoMo/George%20Mason-Loew-Morris-Aff-ADA-Round3.docx
null
52,249
LoMo
George Mason LoMo
null
Ni.....
Lo.....
Ia.....
Mo.....
19,318
GeorgeMason
George Mason
null
null
1,010
ndtceda20
NDT/CEDA 2020-21
2,020
cx
college
2
1,605,260
Extinction - generic defense doesn’t apply.
Srivatsa 17 )//Elmer
Srivatsa 17 Kadiyali Srivatsa 1-12-2017 “Superbug Pandemics and How to Prevent Them” https://www.the-american-interest.com/2017/01/12/superbug-pandemics-and-how-to-prevent-them/ (doctor, inventor, and publisher. He worked in acute and intensive pediatric care in British hospitals)//Elmer
It is by now no secret that the human species is locked in a race of its own making with “superbugs.” I do not exclude the possibility that bad actors might deliberately engineer deadly superbugs.1 But even if that does not happen, humanity faces an existential threat largely of its own making in the absence of malign intentions As threats go, this one is entirely predictable. The concept of a “black swan,” Nassim Nicholas Taleb’s term for low-probability but high-impact events, has become widely known in recent year If one likes catchy labels, it better fits the term “gray rhino,” which, explains Michele Wucker, is a high-probability, high-impact event that people manage to ignore anyway for a raft of social-psychological reasons.2 A pandemic is a quintessential gray rhino, for it is no longer a matter of if but of when it will challenge us—and of how prepared we are to deal with it when it happens. When interviewed for a 2015 article, “The Most Predictable Disaster in the History of the Human Race, ” Bill Gates pointed out that one of the costliest disasters of the 20th century, worse even than World War I, was the Spanish Flu pandemic of 1918-19. As the author of the article, Ezra Klein, put it: “No one can say we weren’t warned. And warned. And warned. A pandemic disease is the most predictable catastrophe in the history of the human race, if only because it has happened to the human race so many, many times before.”3 Even with effective new medicines, if we can devise them, we must contain outbreaks of bacterial disease fast, lest they get out of control. In other words, we have a social-organizational challenge before us as well as a strictly medical one. That means getting sufficient amounts of medicine into the right hands and in the right places, but it also means educating people and enabling them to communicate with each other to prevent any outbreak from spreading widely. Bacteria are among the oldest living things on the planet. They are masters of survival and can be found everywhere. Billions of them live on and in every one of us, many of them helping our bodies to run smoothly and stay healthy. Most bacteria that are not helpful to us are at least harmless, but some are not These wonder drugs revolutionized medicine, but one can have too much of a good thing. Doctors have used antibiotics recklessly, prescribing them for just about everything, and in the process helped to create strains of bacteria that are resistant to the medicines we have. We even give antibiotics to cattle that are not sick and use them to fatten chicke Perhaps even worse, hospitals have deployed antimicrobial products on an industrial scale for a long time now, the result being a sharp rise in iatrogenic bacterial illnesses. Overuse of antibiotics and commercial products containing them has helped superbugs to evolve. We now increasingly face microorganisms that cannot be killed by antibiotics, antifungals, antivirals, or any other chemical weapon we throw at them Pandemics are the major risk we run as a result, but it is not the only one. Overuse of antibiotics by doctors, homemakers, and hospital managers could mean that, in the not-too-distant future, something as simple as a minor cut could again become life-threatening if it becomes infected Few non-medical professionals are aware that antibiotics are the foundation on which nearly all of modern medicine rests. Cancer therapy, organ transplants, surgeries minor and major, and even childbirth all rely on antibiotics to prevent infections. If infections become untreatable we stand to lose most of the medical advances we have made over the past fifty years. Neither superbugs nor common bacterial infections produce any special symptoms indicative of their cause. Rashes, fevers, sneezing, runny noses, ear pain, diarrhea, vomiting, coughing, fatigue, and weakness are signs of common and minor illnesses as well as uncommonly deadly ones. Therefore, the major problem for clinicians is to identify a common symptom that may potentially be an early sign of a major infection that could result in an epidemic. We know that dangerous infections in any given geographical area do not start at the same time. They start with one victim and gradually spread. But that victim is only one among hundreds of patients a doctor will typically see, so many doctors will miss patients presenting with infections that are serious have seen doctors treating eczema with antibiotic cream, even though they know that bacteria are resistant to the majority of these drugs. This sort of action encourages simple infections to spread locally, because patients are therefore not instructed to take other, more useful precautions. On top of that, some people are frivolous about infections and assume doctors are exaggerating the threat. This isn’t just an issue of bureaucratic incompetence. The WHO is under-resourced for the problems it is meant to solve. Funding comes from voluntary donations, and there is no mechanism by which it can quickly scale up its efforts during an emergency. The result is that its response to the next major disease outbreak is likely to be as inadequate as were its responses to Ebola, H1N1, and SARS. Creating Conditions for Infections to Spread Superbug infections spread for several interlocking reasons. Some are medical-epidemiological. Most of the infections of the past thirty years have started in one place and in one family. As already noted, they spread because many infectious diseases are highly contagious before the onset of symptoms, and because it is difficult to prevent patients who know they are sick from going to hospitals, work, and school, or from traveling further afield. Worse, the situation is not static. While we sit paralyzed, superbugs are evolving. Epidemiological models now predict how an algorithmic process of disease spread will move through the modern world. All urban centers around the entire globe can become infected within sixty days because we move around and cross borders much more than our ancestors did, thanks to air travel. A new pandemic could start crossing borders before we even know it exists. A flu-like disease could kill more than 33 million people in 250 days.3
the species is locked in a race with “superbugs.” an existential threat of its own making a high-probability, high-impact event that people ignore anyway for social-psychological reasons A pandemic is no longer a matter of if but of when most predictable catastrophe in history hospitals deployed antimicrobial products on an industrial scale Overuse helped superbugs evolve something as simple as a minor cut could become life-threatening if infected superbugs are evolving models predict disease move through the modern world All urban centers can become infected within sixty days pandemic could kill 33 million in days
It is by now no secret that the human species is locked in a race of its own making with “superbugs.” Indeed, if popular science fiction is a measure of awareness, the theme has pervaded English-language literature from Michael Crichton’s 1969 Andromeda Strain all the way to Emily St. John Mandel’s 2014 Station Eleven and beyond. By a combination of massive inadvertence and what can only be called stupidity, we must now invent new and effective antibiotics faster than deadly bacteria evolve—and regrettably, they are rapidly doing so with our help. I do not exclude the possibility that bad actors might deliberately engineer deadly superbugs.1 But even if that does not happen, humanity faces an existential threat largely of its own making in the absence of malign intentions. As threats go, this one is entirely predictable. The concept of a “black swan,” Nassim Nicholas Taleb’s term for low-probability but high-impact events, has become widely known in recent years. Taleb did not invent the concept; he only gave it a catchy name to help mainly business executives who know little of statistics or probability. Many have embraced the “black swan” label the way children embrace holiday gifts, which are often bobbles of little value, except to them. But the threat of inadvertent pandemics is not a “black swan” because its probability is not low. If one likes catchy labels, it better fits the term “gray rhino,” which, explains Michele Wucker, is a high-probability, high-impact event that people manage to ignore anyway for a raft of social-psychological reasons.2 A pandemic is a quintessential gray rhino, for it is no longer a matter of if but of when it will challenge us—and of how prepared we are to deal with it when it happens. We have certainly been warned. The curse we have created was understood as a possibility from the very outset, when seventy years ago Sir Alexander Fleming, the discoverer of penicillin, predicted antibiotic resistance. When interviewed for a 2015 article, “The Most Predictable Disaster in the History of the Human Race, ” Bill Gates pointed out that one of the costliest disasters of the 20th century, worse even than World War I, was the Spanish Flu pandemic of 1918-19. As the author of the article, Ezra Klein, put it: “No one can say we weren’t warned. And warned. And warned. A pandemic disease is the most predictable catastrophe in the history of the human race, if only because it has happened to the human race so many, many times before.”3 Even with effective new medicines, if we can devise them, we must contain outbreaks of bacterial disease fast, lest they get out of control. In other words, we have a social-organizational challenge before us as well as a strictly medical one. That means getting sufficient amounts of medicine into the right hands and in the right places, but it also means educating people and enabling them to communicate with each other to prevent any outbreak from spreading widely. Responsible governments and cooperative organizations have options in that regard, but even individuals can contribute something. To that end, as a medical doctor I have created a computer app that promises to be useful in that regard—of which more in a moment. But first let us review the situation, for while it has become well known to many people, there is a general resistance to acknowledging the severity and imminence of the danger. What Are the Problems? Bacteria are among the oldest living things on the planet. They are masters of survival and can be found everywhere. Billions of them live on and in every one of us, many of them helping our bodies to run smoothly and stay healthy. Most bacteria that are not helpful to us are at least harmless, but some are not. They invade our cells, spread quickly, and cause havoc that we refer to generically as disease. Millions of people used to die every year as a result of bacterial infections, until we developed antibiotics. These wonder drugs revolutionized medicine, but one can have too much of a good thing. Doctors have used antibiotics recklessly, prescribing them for just about everything, and in the process helped to create strains of bacteria that are resistant to the medicines we have. We even give antibiotics to cattle that are not sick and use them to fatten chickens. Companies large and small still mindlessly market antimicrobial products for hands and home, claiming that they kill bacteria and viruses. They do more harm than good because the low concentrations of antimicrobials that these products contain tend to kill friendly bacteria (not viruses at all), and so clear the way for the mass multiplication of surviving unfriendly bacteria. Perhaps even worse, hospitals have deployed antimicrobial products on an industrial scale for a long time now, the result being a sharp rise in iatrogenic bacterial illnesses. Overuse of antibiotics and commercial products containing them has helped superbugs to evolve. We now increasingly face microorganisms that cannot be killed by antibiotics, antifungals, antivirals, or any other chemical weapon we throw at them. Pandemics are the major risk we run as a result, but it is not the only one. Overuse of antibiotics by doctors, homemakers, and hospital managers could mean that, in the not-too-distant future, something as simple as a minor cut could again become life-threatening if it becomes infected. Few non-medical professionals are aware that antibiotics are the foundation on which nearly all of modern medicine rests. Cancer therapy, organ transplants, surgeries minor and major, and even childbirth all rely on antibiotics to prevent infections. If infections become untreatable we stand to lose most of the medical advances we have made over the past fifty years. And the problem is already here. In the summer of 2011, a 43-year-old woman with complications from a lung transplant was transferred from a New York City hospital to the Clinical Center at the National Institutes of Health (NIH), in Bethesda, Maryland. She had a highly resistant superbug known as Klebsiella pneumoniae carbapenemase (KPC). The patient was treated and eventually discharged after doctors concluded that they had contained the infection. A few weeks later, a 34-year-old man with a tumor and no known link to the woman contracted KPC while at the hospital. During the course of the next few months, several more NIH patients presented with KPC. Doctors attacked the outbreak with combinations of antibiotics, including a supposedly powerful experimental drug. A separate intensive care unit for KPC patients was set up and robots disinfected empty rooms, but the infection still spread beyond the intensive care area. Several patients died and then suddenly all was silent on the KPC front, with doctors convinced they had seen the last of the dangerous bacterium. They couldn’t have been more mistaken. A year later, a young man with complications from a bone marrow transplant arrived at NIH. He became infected with KPC and died. This superbug is now present in hospitals in most, if not all U.S. states. This is not good. This past year an outbreak of CRE (carbapenem-resistant enterobacteriaceae) linked to contaminated medical equipment infected 11 patients and killed two in Los Angeles area hospitals. This family of bacteria has evolved resistance to all antibiotics, including the powerful carbapenem antibiotics that are often used as a last resort against serious infections. They are now so resilient that it is virtually impossible to remove them from medical tools such as catheters and breathing tubes placed into the body, even after cleaning. Then we have gonorrhea, chlamydia, and other sexually transmitted diseases that we cannot treat and that are spreading all over the world. Anyone who has sex can catch these infections, and because most people may not exhibit any symptoms they spread infections without anyone knowing about it. Sexually transmitted diseases used to be treatable with antibiotics, but in recent years we have witnessed the rise of multi-drug resistant STDs. Untreated gonorrhea can lead to infertility in men and women and blindness and other congenital defect in babies. As is well known, too, we have witnessed many cases of drug-resistant pneumonia. These problems have arisen in part because of simple mistakes healthcare professionals repeatedly make. Let me explain. Neither superbugs nor common bacterial infections produce any special symptoms indicative of their cause. Rashes, fevers, sneezing, runny noses, ear pain, diarrhea, vomiting, coughing, fatigue, and weakness are signs of common and minor illnesses as well as uncommonly deadly ones. Therefore, the major problem for clinicians is to identify a common symptom that may potentially be an early sign of a major infection that could result in an epidemic. We know that dangerous infections in any given geographical area do not start at the same time. They start with one victim and gradually spread. But that victim is only one among hundreds of patients a doctor will typically see, so many doctors will miss patients presenting with infections that are serious. They will probably identify diseases that kill fast, but slow-spreading infections such as skin infections that can lead to septicemia are rarely diagnosed early. In addition, I have seen doctors treating eczema with antibiotic cream, even though they know that bacteria are resistant to the majority of these drugs. This sort of action encourages simple infections to spread locally, because patients are therefore not instructed to take other, more useful precautions. On top of that, some people are frivolous about infections and assume doctors are exaggerating the threat. And some people are selfish. Once I was called to see a passenger during a flight who had symptoms consistent with infection. He boarded the plane with these symptoms, but began to feel much worse during the flight. I was scared, knowing how infections such as Ebola can spread. This made me think about a way to screen passengers before they board a flight. Airlines could refund a traveler’s ticket, or issue a replacement, in case of sickness—which is not the policy now. We currently have no method to block infectious travelers from boarding flights, and there are no changes in the incentive system to enable conscientious passengers to avoid losing their money if they responsibly miss a flight because of illness. Speaking of selfishness, I once saw a mother drop her daughter off at school with a serious bout of impetigo on her face. When I asked her why she had brought her daughter to school with a contagious infection, she said she could not spare the time to keep her at home or take her to the doctor. By allowing this child to contact other children, a simple infection can become a major threat. Fortunately, I could see the rash on the girl’s face, but other kids in schools may have rashes we cannot see. Incorrect diagnosis of skin problems and mistaken use of antibiotics to treat them is common all over the world, and so we are continually creating superbugs in our communities. Similarly, chest infections, sore throats, and illnesses diagnosed as colds that unnecessarily treated with antibiotics are also a major threat. By prescribing antibiotics for viral infections, we are not only helping bacteria develop resistance, but we are also polluting the environment when these drugs are passed in urine and feces. All of this helps resistant bacteria to spread in the community and become an epidemic. Ebola is very difficult to transmit because people who are contagious have visible and unusual symptoms. However, the emerging infections and pandemics of the future may not have visible symptoms, and they could break out in highly populous countries such as India and China that send thousands of travelers all over the world every day. When a person is infected with a contagious disease, he or she can expect to pass the illness on to an average of two people. This is called the “reproduction number.” Two is not that high a number as these things go; some diseases have far greater rates of infection. The SARS virus had a reproduction number of four. Measles has a reproduction number of 18. One person traveling as an airplane passenger and carrying an infection similar to Ebola can infect three to five people sitting nearby, ten if he or she walks to the toilet. The study that highlighted this was published in a medical journal a few years ago, but the airline industry has not implemented any changes or introduced screening to prevent the spread of infections by air travel passengers, a major vehicle for the rapid spread of disease. It is scary to think that nobody knows what will happen when the world faces a lethal disease we’re not used to, perhaps with a reproduction number of five or eight or even ten. What if it starts in a megacity? What if, unlike Ebola, it’s contagious before patients show obvious symptoms? Past experience isn’t comforting. In 2009, H1N1 flu spread around the world before we even knew it existed. The Questions Remains Why do seemingly intelligent people repeatedly do such collectively stupid things? How did we allow this to happen? The answer is disarmingly simple. It is because people are incentivized to prioritize short-term benefits over long-term considerations. It is what social scientists have called a “logic of collective action” problem. Everyone has his or her specialized niche interest: doctors their patients’ approval, business and airline executives their shareholders’ earnings, hospitals their reputations for best-practice hygienics, homemakers their obligation to keep their own families from illness. But no one owns the longer-term consequences for hundreds of millions of people who are irrelevant to satisfying these short-term concerns. Here is an example. At a recent Superbug Super Drug conference in London that I attended, scientists, health agencies, and pharmaceutical companies were vastly more concerned with investing millions of dollars in efforts to invent another antibiotic, claiming that this has to be the way forward. Money was the most pressing issue because, as everyone at the conference knew, for many years pharmaceutical companies have been pulling back from antibiotics research because they can’t see a profit in it. Development costs run into billions of dollars, yet there is no guarantee that any new drug will successfully fight infections. At the same conference Dr. Lloyd Czaplewski spoke about alternatives to antibiotics, in case we cannot come up with new ones fast enough to outrun superbug evolution. But he omitted mention of preventive strategies that use the internet or communication software to help reduce the spread of infections among families, communities, and countries. It is madness that we don’t have a concrete second-best alternative to new antibiotics, because we need them and we need them quickly. Of course, this is why we have governments, which have been known occasionally in the past as commonwealths. Governments are supposed to look out for the wider, common interests of society that niche-interested professionals take no responsibility for, and that includes public health. It is why nearly every nation’s government has an official who is analogous to the U.S. Surgeon General, and nearly every one has a public health service of some kind. Alas, national governments do not always function as they should. Several years ago physician and former Republican Senator Bill Frist submitted a proposal to the Senate for a U.S. Medical Expeditionary Corps. This would have been a specialized organization that could coordinate and execute rapid responses to global health emergencies such as Ebola. Nothing came of it, because Dr. Frist’s fellow politicians were either too shortsighted or too dimwitted to understand why it was a good idea. Or perhaps they simply realized that they could not benefit politically from supporting it. Plenty of mistakes continue to be made. In 2015, a particularly infectious form of bird flu ripped through 14 U.S. states, leading farmers to preventively slaughter nearly 40 million birds. The result of such callous and unnecessary acts is that, instead of exhausting themselves in the host population of birds, the viruses quickly find alternative hosts in which to survive, and could therefore easily mutate into a form that can infect humans. Earlier, during the 1980s, AIDS garnered more public attention because a handful of rich and famous people were infected, and because the campaign to eradicate it dovetailed with and boosted the political campaign on behalf of homosexual rights. Methicillin resistant Staphylococcus aureus (MRSA) in hospitals, by far the bigger threat at the time, was virtually ignored. Some doctors knew that MRSA would bring us to our knees and kill millions of people worldwide, but pharmaceutical companies and device and equipment manufacturers ignored these doctors and the thousands of patients dying in hospitals as a result of MRSA. They prioritized the wrong thing, and government did not correct the error. And that is partly how antibiotic-resistant infection went from an obscure hospital problem to an incipient global pandemic. Politics well outside the United States plays several other roles in the budding problem that we are confronting. Countries often will not admit they have a problem and request help because of the possible financial implications in terms of investment and travel. Guinea did not declare the Ebola epidemic early on and Chinese leaders, worried about trade and tourism, lied for months in 2002 about the presence of the SARS virus. In 2004, when avian influenza first surfaced in Thailand, officials there displayed a similar reluctance to release information. Hospitals in some countries, including India, are managed and often owned by doctors. They refuse to share information about existing infections and often categorically deny they have a problem. Reporting infections to public health authorities is not mandatory, and so hospitals that fail to say anything are not penalized. Even now, the WHO and the CDC do not have accurate and up-to-date information about the spread of E. coli or other infections, and part of the reason is that for-profit hospitals are reluctant to do anything to diminish their bottom line. Syria and Yemen are among those countries that are so weak and fragmented that they cannot effectively coordinate public healthcare. But their governments are also hostile to external organizations that offer relief. Part of the reason is xenophobia, but part is that this makes the government look bad. Relatedly, most poor-nation governments do not trust the efficacy of international institutions, and think that cooperating with them amounts to a re-importation of imperialism. They would rather their own people suffer and die than ask for needed help. That brings us to the level of international public health governance. Alas, sometimes poor-country governments estimate the efficacy of international institutions accurately. The WHO’s Ebola response in 2014-15 was a disaster. The organization was slow to declare a public health emergency even after public warnings from Médecins Sans Frontières, some of whose doctors had already died on the front line. The outbreak killed more than 28,000 people, far more than would have been the case had it been quickly identified. This isn’t just an issue of bureaucratic incompetence. The WHO is under-resourced for the problems it is meant to solve. Funding comes from voluntary donations, and there is no mechanism by which it can quickly scale up its efforts during an emergency. The result is that its response to the next major disease outbreak is likely to be as inadequate as were its responses to Ebola, H1N1, and SARS. Stakeholders admit that we need another mechanism, and most experts agree that the world needs some kind of emergency response team for dangerous diseases. But no one knows how to set one up amid the dysfunctional global governance structures that presently exist. Maybe they should turn to Bill Frist, whose basic concept was sound; if the U.S. government will not act, perhaps some other governments will, and use the UN system to do so. But as things stand, we lack a health equivalent of the military reserve. Neither government leaders nor doctors can mobilize a team of experts to contain infections. People who want to volunteer, whether for government or NGO efforts, are not paid and the rules, if any, are sketchy about what we do with them when they return from a mission. Are employers going to take them back? What are the quarantine rules? It is all completely ad hoc, meaning that humanity lacks the tools it needs to protect itself. And note, by the way, the contrast between how governments prepare for facing pandemics and how they prepare for making war. War is not more deadly to the human race than pandemics, but national defense against armed aggression is much better planned for than defense against threats to public health. There is a wealth of rules regarding it, too. Human beings study and plan for war, which kills people both deliberately and accidentally, but they do not invest comparable effort planning for pandemics, which are liable to kill orders of magnitude more people. To the mind of a medical doctor, this is strange. Creating Conditions for Infections to Spread Superbug infections spread for several interlocking reasons. Some are medical-epidemiological. Most of the infections of the past thirty years have started in one place and in one family. As already noted, they spread because many infectious diseases are highly contagious before the onset of symptoms, and because it is difficult to prevent patients who know they are sick from going to hospitals, work, and school, or from traveling further afield. But again, one reason for the problem is political, not medical. Many governments have no strategies in place to prevent pandemics because they are unwilling to tell their people how infections spread. They don’t want to worry people with such talk; it will make them, they fear, unpopular. So governments may have mountains of bureaucracy with great heaps of rules and regulations concerning public health, but they are generally unwilling to trust their own citizens to use common sense on their own behalf. This, too, seems very strange. Until now, no one has come forward to help us develop strategies to educate people how to identify and prevent the spread of infection to their families and communities. The majority of stakeholders have also been oblivious to the use of new technologies to help reduce the spread of these infections. There are some exceptions. In a fun blog post called Preparedness 101: Zombie Apocalypse, the CDC uses the threat of a zombie outbreak as a metaphor to encourage people to prepare for emergencies, including pandemics. It is well meaning and insightful, yet when my colleagues and I try to discuss ways of scaling up the CDC’s example with doctors and nurses, they shut down. Nobody plans for an actual crisis partly because it is too scary and hence paralyzing to think about. But it is also because it is not most health professionals’ job; it is not what they are trained and paid to do. It is always someone else’s job, except that it has turned out to be nobody’s job. Worse, the situation is not static. While we sit paralyzed, superbugs are evolving. Epidemiological models now predict how an algorithmic process of disease spread will move through the modern world. All urban centers around the entire globe can become infected within sixty days because we move around and cross borders much more than our ancestors did, thanks to air travel. A new pandemic could start crossing borders before we even know it exists. A flu-like disease could kill more than 33 million people in 250 days.3
24,025
<h4>Extinction - generic defense doesn’t apply. </h4><p><strong>Srivatsa 17</strong> Kadiyali Srivatsa 1-12-2017 “Superbug Pandemics and How to Prevent Them” https://www.the-american-interest.com/2017/01/12/superbug-pandemics-and-how-to-prevent-them/ (doctor, inventor, and publisher. He worked in acute and intensive pediatric care in British hospitals<u><strong>)//Elmer </p><p></strong>It is by now no secret that <mark>the</mark> human <mark>species is locked in a race</mark> of its own making <mark>with “<strong>superbugs</strong>.”</u></mark> Indeed, if popular science fiction is a measure of awareness, the theme has pervaded English-language literature from Michael Crichton’s 1969 Andromeda Strain all the way to Emily St. John Mandel’s 2014 Station Eleven and beyond. By a combination of massive inadvertence and what can only be called stupidity, we must now invent new and effective antibiotics faster than deadly bacteria evolve—and regrettably, they are rapidly doing so with our help. <u>I do not exclude the possibility that bad actors might deliberately engineer deadly superbugs.1 But even if that does not happen, humanity faces <mark>an</mark> <strong><mark>existential threat</strong></mark> largely <mark>of its</mark> <strong><mark>own making</strong></mark> in the absence of malign intentions</u>. <u>As threats go, this one is entirely predictable. The concept of a “black swan,” Nassim Nicholas Taleb’s term for low-probability but high-impact events, has become widely known in recent year</u>s. Taleb did not invent the concept; he only gave it a catchy name to help mainly business executives who know little of statistics or probability. Many have embraced the “black swan” label the way children embrace holiday gifts, which are often bobbles of little value, except to them. But the threat of inadvertent pandemics is not a “black swan” because its probability is not low. <u>If one likes catchy labels, it better fits the term “gray rhino,” which, explains Michele Wucker, is <mark>a</mark> <strong><mark>high-probability, high-impact event</strong></mark> <mark>that people</mark> manage to <strong><mark>ignore anyway</strong></mark> <mark>for</mark> a raft of <strong><mark>social-psychological reasons</strong></mark>.2 <mark>A pandemic</mark> is a quintessential gray rhino, for it <mark>is no longer a matter of if but of <strong>when</strong></mark> it will challenge us—and of how prepared we are to deal with it when it happens. </u>We have certainly been warned. The curse we have created was understood as a possibility from the very outset, when seventy years ago Sir Alexander Fleming, the discoverer of penicillin, predicted antibiotic resistance. <u>When interviewed for a 2015 article, “The Most Predictable Disaster in the History of the Human Race, ” Bill Gates pointed out that one of the costliest disasters of the 20th century, worse even than World War I, was the Spanish Flu pandemic of 1918-19. As the author of the article, Ezra Klein, put it: “No one can say we weren’t warned. And warned. And warned. A pandemic disease is the <strong><mark>most predictable catastrophe in</strong></mark> the <strong><mark>history</strong></mark> of the human race, if only because it has happened to the human race so many, many times before.”3 Even with effective new medicines, if we can devise them, we must contain outbreaks of bacterial disease fast, lest they get out of control. In other words, we have a social-organizational challenge before us as well as a strictly medical one. That means getting sufficient amounts of medicine into the right hands and in the right places, but it also means educating people and enabling them to communicate with each other to prevent any outbreak from spreading widely. </u>Responsible governments and cooperative organizations have options in that regard, but even individuals can contribute something. To that end, as a medical doctor I have created a computer app that promises to be useful in that regard—of which more in a moment. But first let us review the situation, for while it has become well known to many people, there is a general resistance to acknowledging the severity and imminence of the danger. What Are the Problems? <u>Bacteria are among the oldest living things on the planet. They are masters of survival and can be found everywhere. Billions of them live on and in every one of us, many of them helping our bodies to run smoothly and stay healthy. Most bacteria that are not helpful to us are at least harmless, but some are not</u>. They invade our cells, spread quickly, and cause havoc that we refer to generically as disease. Millions of people used to die every year as a result of bacterial infections, until we developed antibiotics. <u>These wonder drugs revolutionized medicine, but one can have too much of a good thing. Doctors have used antibiotics recklessly, prescribing them for just about everything, and in the process helped to create strains of bacteria that are resistant to the medicines we have. We even give antibiotics to cattle that are not sick and use them to fatten chicke</u>ns. Companies large and small still mindlessly market antimicrobial products for hands and home, claiming that they kill bacteria and viruses. They do more harm than good because the low concentrations of antimicrobials that these products contain tend to kill friendly bacteria (not viruses at all), and so clear the way for the mass multiplication of surviving unfriendly bacteria. <u>Perhaps even worse, <mark>hospitals</mark> have <mark>deployed antimicrobial products on an industrial scale</mark> for a long time now, the result being a sharp rise in iatrogenic bacterial illnesses. <mark>Overuse</mark> of antibiotics and commercial products containing them has <mark>helped superbugs</mark> to <mark>evolve</mark>. We now increasingly face microorganisms that cannot be killed by antibiotics, antifungals, antivirals, or any other chemical weapon we throw at them</u>. <u><strong>Pandemics are the major risk we run as a result, but it is not the only one. Overuse of antibiotics by doctors, homemakers, and hospital managers could mean that, in the not-too-distant future, <mark>something as simple as a minor cut could</mark> again <mark>become life-threatening if</mark> it becomes <mark>infected</u></strong></mark>. <u>Few non-medical professionals are aware that antibiotics are the foundation on which nearly all of modern medicine rests. Cancer therapy, organ transplants, surgeries minor and major, and even childbirth all rely on antibiotics to prevent infections. If infections become untreatable we stand to lose most of the medical advances we have made over the past fifty years. </u>And the problem is already here. In the summer of 2011, a 43-year-old woman with complications from a lung transplant was transferred from a New York City hospital to the Clinical Center at the National Institutes of Health (NIH), in Bethesda, Maryland. She had a highly resistant superbug known as Klebsiella pneumoniae carbapenemase (KPC). The patient was treated and eventually discharged after doctors concluded that they had contained the infection. A few weeks later, a 34-year-old man with a tumor and no known link to the woman contracted KPC while at the hospital. During the course of the next few months, several more NIH patients presented with KPC. Doctors attacked the outbreak with combinations of antibiotics, including a supposedly powerful experimental drug. A separate intensive care unit for KPC patients was set up and robots disinfected empty rooms, but the infection still spread beyond the intensive care area. Several patients died and then suddenly all was silent on the KPC front, with doctors convinced they had seen the last of the dangerous bacterium. They couldn’t have been more mistaken. A year later, a young man with complications from a bone marrow transplant arrived at NIH. He became infected with KPC and died. This superbug is now present in hospitals in most, if not all U.S. states. This is not good. This past year an outbreak of CRE (carbapenem-resistant enterobacteriaceae) linked to contaminated medical equipment infected 11 patients and killed two in Los Angeles area hospitals. This family of bacteria has evolved resistance to all antibiotics, including the powerful carbapenem antibiotics that are often used as a last resort against serious infections. They are now so resilient that it is virtually impossible to remove them from medical tools such as catheters and breathing tubes placed into the body, even after cleaning. Then we have gonorrhea, chlamydia, and other sexually transmitted diseases that we cannot treat and that are spreading all over the world. Anyone who has sex can catch these infections, and because most people may not exhibit any symptoms they spread infections without anyone knowing about it. Sexually transmitted diseases used to be treatable with antibiotics, but in recent years we have witnessed the rise of multi-drug resistant STDs. Untreated gonorrhea can lead to infertility in men and women and blindness and other congenital defect in babies. As is well known, too, we have witnessed many cases of drug-resistant pneumonia. These problems have arisen in part because of simple mistakes healthcare professionals repeatedly make. Let me explain. <u>Neither superbugs nor common bacterial infections produce any special symptoms indicative of their cause. Rashes, fevers, sneezing, runny noses, ear pain, diarrhea, vomiting, coughing, fatigue, and weakness are signs of common and minor illnesses as well as uncommonly deadly ones.</u> <u><strong>Therefore, the major problem for clinicians is to identify a common symptom that may potentially be an early sign of a major infection that could result in an epidemic. </strong>We know that dangerous infections in any given geographical area do not start at the same time. They start with one victim and gradually spread. But that victim is only one among hundreds of patients a doctor will typically see, so many doctors will miss patients presenting with infections that are serious</u>. They will probably identify diseases that kill fast, but slow-spreading infections such as skin infections that can lead to septicemia are rarely diagnosed early. In addition, I <u>have seen doctors treating eczema with antibiotic cream, even though they know that bacteria are resistant to the majority of these drugs. This sort of action encourages simple infections to spread locally, because patients are therefore not instructed to take other, more useful precautions. On top of that, some people are frivolous about infections and assume doctors are exaggerating the threat. </u>And some people are selfish. Once I was called to see a passenger during a flight who had symptoms consistent with infection. He boarded the plane with these symptoms, but began to feel much worse during the flight. I was scared, knowing how infections such as Ebola can spread. This made me think about a way to screen passengers before they board a flight. Airlines could refund a traveler’s ticket, or issue a replacement, in case of sickness—which is not the policy now. We currently have no method to block infectious travelers from boarding flights, and there are no changes in the incentive system to enable conscientious passengers to avoid losing their money if they responsibly miss a flight because of illness. Speaking of selfishness, I once saw a mother drop her daughter off at school with a serious bout of impetigo on her face. When I asked her why she had brought her daughter to school with a contagious infection, she said she could not spare the time to keep her at home or take her to the doctor. By allowing this child to contact other children, a simple infection can become a major threat. Fortunately, I could see the rash on the girl’s face, but other kids in schools may have rashes we cannot see. Incorrect diagnosis of skin problems and mistaken use of antibiotics to treat them is common all over the world, and so we are continually creating superbugs in our communities. Similarly, chest infections, sore throats, and illnesses diagnosed as colds that unnecessarily treated with antibiotics are also a major threat. By prescribing antibiotics for viral infections, we are not only helping bacteria develop resistance, but we are also polluting the environment when these drugs are passed in urine and feces. All of this helps resistant bacteria to spread in the community and become an epidemic. Ebola is very difficult to transmit because people who are contagious have visible and unusual symptoms. However, the emerging infections and pandemics of the future may not have visible symptoms, and they could break out in highly populous countries such as India and China that send thousands of travelers all over the world every day. When a person is infected with a contagious disease, he or she can expect to pass the illness on to an average of two people. This is called the “reproduction number.” Two is not that high a number as these things go; some diseases have far greater rates of infection. The SARS virus had a reproduction number of four. Measles has a reproduction number of 18. One person traveling as an airplane passenger and carrying an infection similar to Ebola can infect three to five people sitting nearby, ten if he or she walks to the toilet. The study that highlighted this was published in a medical journal a few years ago, but the airline industry has not implemented any changes or introduced screening to prevent the spread of infections by air travel passengers, a major vehicle for the rapid spread of disease. It is scary to think that nobody knows what will happen when the world faces a lethal disease we’re not used to, perhaps with a reproduction number of five or eight or even ten. What if it starts in a megacity? What if, unlike Ebola, it’s contagious before patients show obvious symptoms? Past experience isn’t comforting. In 2009, H1N1 flu spread around the world before we even knew it existed. The Questions Remains Why do seemingly intelligent people repeatedly do such collectively stupid things? How did we allow this to happen? The answer is disarmingly simple. It is because people are incentivized to prioritize short-term benefits over long-term considerations. It is what social scientists have called a “logic of collective action” problem. Everyone has his or her specialized niche interest: doctors their patients’ approval, business and airline executives their shareholders’ earnings, hospitals their reputations for best-practice hygienics, homemakers their obligation to keep their own families from illness. But no one owns the longer-term consequences for hundreds of millions of people who are irrelevant to satisfying these short-term concerns. Here is an example. At a recent Superbug Super Drug conference in London that I attended, scientists, health agencies, and pharmaceutical companies were vastly more concerned with investing millions of dollars in efforts to invent another antibiotic, claiming that this has to be the way forward. Money was the most pressing issue because, as everyone at the conference knew, for many years pharmaceutical companies have been pulling back from antibiotics research because they can’t see a profit in it. Development costs run into billions of dollars, yet there is no guarantee that any new drug will successfully fight infections. At the same conference Dr. Lloyd Czaplewski spoke about alternatives to antibiotics, in case we cannot come up with new ones fast enough to outrun superbug evolution. But he omitted mention of preventive strategies that use the internet or communication software to help reduce the spread of infections among families, communities, and countries. It is madness that we don’t have a concrete second-best alternative to new antibiotics, because we need them and we need them quickly. Of course, this is why we have governments, which have been known occasionally in the past as commonwealths. Governments are supposed to look out for the wider, common interests of society that niche-interested professionals take no responsibility for, and that includes public health. It is why nearly every nation’s government has an official who is analogous to the U.S. Surgeon General, and nearly every one has a public health service of some kind. Alas, national governments do not always function as they should. Several years ago physician and former Republican Senator Bill Frist submitted a proposal to the Senate for a U.S. Medical Expeditionary Corps. This would have been a specialized organization that could coordinate and execute rapid responses to global health emergencies such as Ebola. Nothing came of it, because Dr. Frist’s fellow politicians were either too shortsighted or too dimwitted to understand why it was a good idea. Or perhaps they simply realized that they could not benefit politically from supporting it. Plenty of mistakes continue to be made. In 2015, a particularly infectious form of bird flu ripped through 14 U.S. states, leading farmers to preventively slaughter nearly 40 million birds. The result of such callous and unnecessary acts is that, instead of exhausting themselves in the host population of birds, the viruses quickly find alternative hosts in which to survive, and could therefore easily mutate into a form that can infect humans. Earlier, during the 1980s, AIDS garnered more public attention because a handful of rich and famous people were infected, and because the campaign to eradicate it dovetailed with and boosted the political campaign on behalf of homosexual rights. Methicillin resistant Staphylococcus aureus (MRSA) in hospitals, by far the bigger threat at the time, was virtually ignored. Some doctors knew that MRSA would bring us to our knees and kill millions of people worldwide, but pharmaceutical companies and device and equipment manufacturers ignored these doctors and the thousands of patients dying in hospitals as a result of MRSA. They prioritized the wrong thing, and government did not correct the error. And that is partly how antibiotic-resistant infection went from an obscure hospital problem to an incipient global pandemic. Politics well outside the United States plays several other roles in the budding problem that we are confronting. Countries often will not admit they have a problem and request help because of the possible financial implications in terms of investment and travel. Guinea did not declare the Ebola epidemic early on and Chinese leaders, worried about trade and tourism, lied for months in 2002 about the presence of the SARS virus. In 2004, when avian influenza first surfaced in Thailand, officials there displayed a similar reluctance to release information. Hospitals in some countries, including India, are managed and often owned by doctors. They refuse to share information about existing infections and often categorically deny they have a problem. Reporting infections to public health authorities is not mandatory, and so hospitals that fail to say anything are not penalized. Even now, the WHO and the CDC do not have accurate and up-to-date information about the spread of E. coli or other infections, and part of the reason is that for-profit hospitals are reluctant to do anything to diminish their bottom line. Syria and Yemen are among those countries that are so weak and fragmented that they cannot effectively coordinate public healthcare. But their governments are also hostile to external organizations that offer relief. Part of the reason is xenophobia, but part is that this makes the government look bad. Relatedly, most poor-nation governments do not trust the efficacy of international institutions, and think that cooperating with them amounts to a re-importation of imperialism. They would rather their own people suffer and die than ask for needed help. That brings us to the level of international public health governance. Alas, sometimes poor-country governments estimate the efficacy of international institutions accurately. The WHO’s Ebola response in 2014-15 was a disaster. The organization was slow to declare a public health emergency even after public warnings from Médecins Sans Frontières, some of whose doctors had already died on the front line. The outbreak killed more than 28,000 people, far more than would have been the case had it been quickly identified. <u>This isn’t just an issue of bureaucratic incompetence. The <strong>WHO is under-resourced for the problems it is meant to solve. Funding comes from voluntary donations, and there is no mechanism by which it can quickly scale up its efforts during an emergency. The result is that its response to the next major disease outbreak is likely to be as inadequate as were its responses to Ebola, H1N1, and SARS</strong>. </u>Stakeholders admit that we need another mechanism, and most experts agree that the world needs some kind of emergency response team for dangerous diseases. But no one knows how to set one up amid the dysfunctional global governance structures that presently exist. Maybe they should turn to Bill Frist, whose basic concept was sound; if the U.S. government will not act, perhaps some other governments will, and use the UN system to do so. But as things stand, we lack a health equivalent of the military reserve. Neither government leaders nor doctors can mobilize a team of experts to contain infections. People who want to volunteer, whether for government or NGO efforts, are not paid and the rules, if any, are sketchy about what we do with them when they return from a mission. Are employers going to take them back? What are the quarantine rules? It is all completely ad hoc, meaning that humanity lacks the tools it needs to protect itself. And note, by the way, the contrast between how governments prepare for facing pandemics and how they prepare for making war. War is not more deadly to the human race than pandemics, but national defense against armed aggression is much better planned for than defense against threats to public health. There is a wealth of rules regarding it, too. Human beings study and plan for war, which kills people both deliberately and accidentally, but they do not invest comparable effort planning for pandemics, which are liable to kill orders of magnitude more people. To the mind of a medical doctor, this is strange. <u>Creating Conditions for Infections to Spread Superbug infections spread for several interlocking reasons. Some are medical-epidemiological. Most of the infections of the past thirty years have started in one place and in one family. As already noted, they spread because many infectious diseases are highly contagious before the onset of symptoms, and because it is difficult to prevent patients who know they are sick from going to hospitals, work, and school, or from traveling further afield. </u>But again, one reason for the problem is political, not medical. Many governments have no strategies in place to prevent pandemics because they are unwilling to tell their people how infections spread. They don’t want to worry people with such talk; it will make them, they fear, unpopular. So governments may have mountains of bureaucracy with great heaps of rules and regulations concerning public health, but they are generally unwilling to trust their own citizens to use common sense on their own behalf. This, too, seems very strange. Until now, no one has come forward to help us develop strategies to educate people how to identify and prevent the spread of infection to their families and communities. The majority of stakeholders have also been oblivious to the use of new technologies to help reduce the spread of these infections. There are some exceptions. In a fun blog post called Preparedness 101: Zombie Apocalypse, the CDC uses the threat of a zombie outbreak as a metaphor to encourage people to prepare for emergencies, including pandemics. It is well meaning and insightful, yet when my colleagues and I try to discuss ways of scaling up the CDC’s example with doctors and nurses, they shut down. Nobody plans for an actual crisis partly because it is too scary and hence paralyzing to think about. But it is also because it is not most health professionals’ job; it is not what they are trained and paid to do. It is always someone else’s job, except that it has turned out to be nobody’s job. <u><strong>Worse, the situation is not static. While we sit paralyzed, <mark>superbugs are evolving</mark>. Epidemiological <mark>models </mark>now <mark>predict </mark>how an algorithmic process of <mark>disease </mark>spread will <mark>move through the modern world</mark>. <mark>All urban centers </mark>around the entire globe <mark>can become infected within sixty days </mark>because we move around and cross borders much more than our ancestors did, thanks to air travel. A new <mark>pandemic </mark>could start crossing borders before we even know it exists. A flu-like disease <mark>could kill </mark>more than <mark>33 million </mark>people <mark>in </mark>250 <mark>days</mark>.3</p></u></strong>
1AC v. Westwood VLo Meadows Round 6
1AC
1AC: Innovation
30,876
612
46,818
./documents/hsld21/Westlake/Ro/Westlake-Roberts-Aff-Meadows-Round6.docx
902,026
A
Meadows
6
Westwood VLo
Claudia Ribera
1AC - Evergreening 1NC - SetCol K Case 1AR - All Must Defend Governmental Action 2NR - Must Defend Governmental Action SetCol K 2AR - All
hsld21/Westlake/Ro/Westlake-Roberts-Aff-Meadows-Round6.docx
null
75,498
MiRo
Westlake MiRo
null
Mi.....
Ro.....
null
null
25,216
Westlake
Westlake
TX
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
886,277
Food shortage doesn’t cause war – best studies
Allouche 11
Allouche 11, research Fellow – water supply and sanitation @ Institute for Development Studies, frmr professor – MIT, ’11 (Jeremy, “The sustainability and resilience of global water and food systems: Political analysis of the interplay between security, resource scarcity, political systems and global trade,” Food Policy, Vol. 36 Supplement 1, p. S3-S8, January)
debates on whether scarcity of food or water will lead to conflict comes from the Malthusian belief that there is an imbalance between resources and population growth most empirical studies do not support these arguments. Tech and capital have dramatically increased productivity the neo-Malthusian view has suffered because humankind has breached resource barriers that seemed unchallengeable. alarmist scenarios linked use of water resources and food insecurity with wars. In the Middle East foreign ministers have used this bellicose rhetoric. The evidence seems quite weak. none of these declarations have been followed up by military action. None of the various and extensive databases on the causes of war show water as a casus belli. Hewitt, Wolf and Hammer found only seven disputes where water seems to have been at least a partial cause 80% of the incidents relating to water were limited to governmental rhetoric more than two-thirds of 1800 water events’ fall on the ‘cooperative’ scale organized political bodies signed more than 3600 water-related treaties There is no correlation between water scarcity and transboundary conflict. Water rich countries have been involved in disputes with other water rich countries perceptions of the amount of available water drives co-operation among riparians the threat of water wars does not make sense in the light of the recent historical record. debates over climate change popularised water wars. Despite growing concern that climate change will lead to instability and violent conflict, the evidence base to substantiate the connections is thin
empirical studies do not support these arguments Tech and capital have increased productivity humankind has breached resource barriers that seemed unchallengeable. alarmist scenarios linked water and food insecurity with wars. None of the various and extensive databases on causes of war show water 80% of incidents were limited to rhetoric two-thirds fall on the ‘cooperative’ scale threat of wars does not make sense in the light of the historical record
The question of resource scarcity has led to many debates on whether scarcity (whether of food or water) will lead to conflict and war. The underlining reasoning behind most of these discourses over food and water wars comes from the Malthusian belief that there is an imbalance between the economic availability of natural resources and population growth since while food production grows linearly, population increases exponentially. Following this reasoning, neo-Malthusians claim that finite natural resources place a strict limit on the growth of human population and aggregate consumption; if these limits are exceeded, social breakdown, conflict and wars result. Nonetheless, it seems that most empirical studies do not support any of these neo-Malthusian arguments. Technological change and greater inputs of capital have dramatically increased labour productivity in agriculture. More generally, the neo-Malthusian view has suffered because during the last two centuries humankind has breached many resource barriers that seemed unchallengeable. Lessons from history: alarmist scenarios, resource wars and international relations In a so-called age of uncertainty, a number of alarmist scenarios have linked the increasing use of water resources and food insecurity with wars. The idea of water wars (perhaps more than food wars) is a dominant discourse in the media (see for example Smith, 2009), NGOs (International Alert, 2007) and within international organizations (UNEP, 2007). In 2007, UN Secretary General Ban Ki-moon declared that ‘water scarcity threatens economic and social gains and is a potent fuel for wars and conflict’ (Lewis, 2007). Of course, this type of discourse has an instrumental purpose; security and conflict are here used for raising water/food as key policy priorities at the international level. In the Middle East, presidents, prime ministers and foreign ministers have also used this bellicose rhetoric. Boutrous Boutros-Gali said; ‘the next war in the Middle East will be over water, not politics’ (Boutros Boutros-Gali in Butts, 1997, p. 65). The question is not whether the sharing of transboundary water sparks political tension and alarmist declaration, but rather to what extent water has been a principal factor in international conflicts. The evidence seems quite weak. Whether by president Sadat in Egypt or King Hussein in Jordan, none of these declarations have been followed up by military action. The governance of transboundary water has gained increased attention these last decades. This has a direct impact on the global food system as water allocation agreements determine the amount of water that can used for irrigated agriculture. The likelihood of conflicts over water is an important parameter to consider in assessing the stability, sustainability and resilience of global food systems. None of the various and extensive databases on the causes of war show water as a casus belli. Using the International Crisis Behavior (ICB) data set and supplementary data from the University of Alabama on water conflicts, Hewitt, Wolf and Hammer found only seven disputes where water seems to have been at least a partial cause for conflict (Wolf, 1998, p. 251). In fact, about 80% of the incidents relating to water were limited purely to governmental rhetoric intended for the electorate (Otchet, 2001, p. 18). As shown in The Basins At Risk (BAR) water event database, more than two-thirds of over 1800 water-related ‘events’ fall on the ‘cooperative’ scale (Yoffe et al., 2003). Indeed, if one takes into account a much longer period, the following figures clearly demonstrate this argument. According to studies by the United Nations Food and Agriculture Organization (FAO), organized political bodies signed between the year 805 and 1984 more than 3600 water-related treaties, and approximately 300 treaties dealing with water management or allocations in international basins have been negotiated since 1945 (FAO, 1978 and FAO, 1984). The fear around water wars have been driven by a Malthusian outlook which equates scarcity with violence, conflict and war. There is however no direct correlation between water scarcity and transboundary conflict. Most specialists now tend to agree that the major issue is not scarcity per se but rather the allocation of water resources between the different riparian states (see for example Allouche, 2005, Allouche, 2007 and [Rouyer, 2000] ). Water rich countries have been involved in a number of disputes with other relatively water rich countries (see for example India/Pakistan or Brazil/Argentina). The perception of each state’s estimated water needs really constitutes the core issue in transboundary water relations. Indeed, whether this scarcity exists or not in reality, perceptions of the amount of available water shapes people’s attitude towards the environment (Ohlsson, 1999). In fact, some water experts have argued that scarcity drives the process of co-operation among riparians (Dinar and Dinar, 2005 and Brochmann and Gleditsch, 2006). In terms of international relations, the threat of water wars due to increasing scarcity does not make much sense in the light of the recent historical record. Overall, the water war rationale expects conflict to occur over water, and appears to suggest that violence is a viable means of securing national water supplies, an argument which is highly contestable. The debates over the likely impacts of climate change have again popularised the idea of water wars. The argument runs that climate change will precipitate worsening ecological conditions contributing to resource scarcities, social breakdown, institutional failure, mass migrations and in turn cause greater political instability and conflict (Brauch, 2002 and Pervis and Busby, 2004). In a report for the US Department of Defense, Schwartz and Randall (2003) speculate about the consequences of a worst-case climate change scenario arguing that water shortages will lead to aggressive wars (Schwartz and Randall, 2003, p. 15). Despite growing concern that climate change will lead to instability and violent conflict, the evidence base to substantiate the connections is thin ( [Barnett and Adger, 2007] and Kevane and Gray, 2008).
6,250
<h4>Food shortage doesn’t cause war – best studies</h4><p><strong>Allouche 11</strong>, research Fellow – water supply and sanitation @ Institute for Development Studies, frmr professor – MIT, ’11 (Jeremy, “The sustainability and resilience of global water and food systems: Political analysis of the interplay between security, resource scarcity, political systems and global trade,” Food Policy, Vol. 36 Supplement 1, p. S3-S8, January)</p><p>The question of resource scarcity has led to many <u>debates on whether scarcity</u> (whether <u>of food or water</u>) <u>will lead to conflict</u> and war. The underlining reasoning behind most of these discourses over food and water wars <u>comes from the Malthusian belief that there is an imbalance between</u> the economic availability of natural <u>resources and population growth</u> since while food production grows linearly, population increases exponentially. Following this reasoning, neo-Malthusians claim that finite natural resources place a strict limit on the growth of human population and aggregate consumption; if these limits are exceeded, social breakdown, conflict and wars result. Nonetheless, it seems that <u><strong>most <mark>empirical studies do not support</u></strong></mark> any of <u><strong><mark>these</u></strong></mark> neo-Malthusian <u><strong><mark>arguments</mark>.</u></strong> <u><mark>Tech</u></mark>nological change <u><mark>and</u></mark> greater inputs of <u><mark>capital have</mark> dramatically <mark>increased</u></mark> labour <u><mark>productivity</u></mark> in agriculture. More generally, <u>the neo-Malthusian view has suffered because</u> during the last two centuries <u><mark>humankind has breached</u></mark> many <u><mark>resource barriers that seemed unchallengeable.</mark> </u>Lessons from history: alarmist scenarios, resource wars and international relations In a so-called age of uncertainty, a number of <u><strong><mark>alarmist scenarios</u></strong></mark> have <u><mark>linked</u></mark> the increasing <u>use of <mark>water</mark> resources <mark>and food insecurity with wars.</u></mark> The idea of water wars (perhaps more than food wars) is a dominant discourse in the media (see for example Smith, 2009), NGOs (International Alert, 2007) and within international organizations (UNEP, 2007). In 2007, UN Secretary General Ban Ki-moon declared that ‘water scarcity threatens economic and social gains and is a potent fuel for wars and conflict’ (Lewis, 2007). Of course, this type of discourse has an instrumental purpose; security and conflict are here used for raising water/food as key policy priorities at the international level. <u><strong>In the Middle East</u></strong>, presidents, prime ministers and <u>foreign ministers have</u> also <u>used this bellicose rhetoric.</u> Boutrous Boutros-Gali said; ‘the next war in the Middle East will be over water, not politics’ (Boutros Boutros-Gali in Butts, 1997, p. 65). The question is not whether the sharing of transboundary water sparks political tension and alarmist declaration, but rather to what extent water has been a principal factor in international conflicts. <u>The evidence seems quite weak.</u> Whether by president Sadat in Egypt or King Hussein in Jordan, <u>none of these declarations have been followed up by military action. </u>The governance of transboundary water has gained increased attention these last decades. This has a direct impact on the global food system as water allocation agreements determine the amount of water that can used for irrigated agriculture. The likelihood of conflicts over water is an important parameter to consider in assessing the stability, sustainability and resilience of global food systems. <u><mark>None of the <strong>various and extensive databases</strong> on</mark> the <mark>causes of war show water</mark> as a casus belli.</u> Using the International Crisis Behavior (ICB) data set and supplementary data from the University of Alabama on water conflicts, <u>Hewitt, Wolf and Hammer found only seven disputes where water seems to have been at least a partial cause</u> for conflict (Wolf, 1998, p. 251). In fact, about <u><mark>80% of</mark> the <mark>incidents</mark> relating to water <mark>were limited</u></mark> purely <u><mark>to</mark> governmental <mark>rhetoric</u></mark> intended for the electorate (Otchet, 2001, p. 18). As shown in The Basins At Risk (BAR) water event database, <u>more than <mark>two-thirds</mark> of</u> over <u>1800 water</u>-related ‘<u>events’ <mark>fall on the ‘cooperative’ scale</u></mark> (Yoffe et al., 2003). Indeed, if one takes into account a much longer period, the following figures clearly demonstrate this argument. According to studies by the United Nations Food and Agriculture Organization (FAO), <u>organized political bodies signed</u> between the year 805 and 1984 <u>more than 3600 water-related treaties</u>, and approximately 300 treaties dealing with water management or allocations in international basins have been negotiated since 1945 (FAO, 1978 and FAO, 1984). The fear around water wars have been driven by a Malthusian outlook which equates scarcity with violence, conflict and war. <u><strong>There is</u></strong> however <u><strong>no</u></strong> direct <u><strong>correlation between water scarcity and transboundary conflict. </u></strong>Most specialists now tend to agree that the major issue is not scarcity per se but rather the allocation of water resources between the different riparian states (see for example Allouche, 2005, Allouche, 2007 and [Rouyer, 2000] ). <u>Water rich countries have been involved in</u> a number of <u>disputes with other</u> relatively <u>water rich countries</u> (see for example India/Pakistan or Brazil/Argentina). The perception of each state’s estimated water needs really constitutes the core issue in transboundary water relations. Indeed, whether this scarcity exists or not in reality, <u>perceptions of the amount of available water</u> shapes people’s attitude towards the environment (Ohlsson, 1999). In fact, some water experts have argued that scarcity <u>drives</u> the process of <u>co-operation among riparians</u> (Dinar and Dinar, 2005 and Brochmann and Gleditsch, 2006). In terms of international relations, <u><strong>the <mark>threat of </mark>water <mark>wars</u></strong></mark> due to increasing scarcity <u><strong><mark>does not make</u></strong></mark> much <u><strong><mark>sense in the light of the</mark> recent <mark>historical record</mark>.</u></strong> Overall, the water war rationale expects conflict to occur over water, and appears to suggest that violence is a viable means of securing national water supplies, an argument which is highly contestable. The <u>debates over</u> the likely impacts of <u>climate change</u> have again <u>popularised</u> the idea of <u>water wars.</u> The argument runs that climate change will precipitate worsening ecological conditions contributing to resource scarcities, social breakdown, institutional failure, mass migrations and in turn cause greater political instability and conflict (Brauch, 2002 and Pervis and Busby, 2004). In a report for the US Department of Defense, Schwartz and Randall (2003) speculate about the consequences of a worst-case climate change scenario arguing that water shortages will lead to aggressive wars (Schwartz and Randall, 2003, p. 15). <u>Despite growing concern that climate change will lead to instability and violent conflict, the evidence base to substantiate the connections is thin</u> ( [Barnett and Adger, 2007] and Kevane and Gray, 2008).</p>
1NC
null
1NC Cyber
28,932
766
21,398
./documents/hspolicy15/Alpharetta/KuKa/Alpharetta-Kumar-Kashibhatla-Neg-Ohio%20Valley-Round2.docx
640,364
N
Ohio Valley
2
Niles West BC
Ava Vargasson
1AC- Backdoors 1NC- OCOS DA Politics DA Lie CP Grids CP Nuclear Timetables CP T Self Aware Neolib K Terror DA China Tech DA Case 2NC- CP T China Tech DA Case 1NR- Politics Terror 2NR- CP Terror Case
hspolicy15/Alpharetta/KuKa/Alpharetta-Kumar-Kashibhatla-Neg-Ohio%20Valley-Round2.docx
null
54,065
KuKa
Alpharetta KuKa
null
Va.....
Ku.....
Sa.....
Ka.....
19,717
Alpharetta
Alpharetta
null
null
1,014
hspolicy15
HS Policy 2015-16
2,015
cx
hs
2
604,847
No war.
Bowen 18
Bowen 18 [Bleddyn Bowen, Lecturer in International Relations at the University of Leicester. The Art of Space Deterrence. February 20, 2018. https://www.europeanleadershipnetwork.org/commentary/the-art-of-space-deterrence/]
Space is an afterthought in the grand strategic views of top-level decision-makers A president may not care that one satellite may be lost or go dark it may cause panic and Twitter hysteria But the terrestrial context as well as the political stakes and symbolism of any exchange of hostilities in space matters more The political and media dimension can magnify the perceived consequences of losing specific sat s out of all proportion to their actual strategic effect
Space is an afterthought in strategic views of top decision-makers A president may not care one sat may be lost terrestrial context matters more. The media magnify perceived consequences of losing sat s out of proportion to actual strategic effect
Space is often an afterthought or a miscellaneous ancillary in the grand strategic views of top-level decision-makers. A president may not care that one satellite may be lost or go dark; it may cause panic and Twitter-based hysteria for the space community, of course. But the terrestrial context and consequences, as well as the political stakes and symbolism of any exchange of hostilities in space matters more. The political and media dimension can magnify or minimise the perceived consequences of losing specific satellites out of all proportion to their actual strategic effect.
585
<h4>No war. </h4><p><strong>Bowen 18</strong> [Bleddyn Bowen, Lecturer in International Relations at the University of Leicester. The Art of Space Deterrence. February 20, 2018. https://www.europeanleadershipnetwork.org/commentary/the-art-of-space-deterrence/]</p><p><u><mark>Space is</u></mark> often <u><mark>an <strong>afterthought</u></strong></mark> or a miscellaneous ancillary <u><mark>in</mark> the <strong>grand <mark>strategic views</strong> of <strong>top</mark>-level <mark>decision-makers</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>A <strong>president</strong> may <strong>not care</strong></mark> that <strong><mark>one sat</mark>ellite <mark>may be lost</strong></mark> or go dark</u>; <u>it may cause panic and</u> <u><strong>Twitter</u></strong>-based <u><strong>hysteria</u></strong> for the space community, of course. <u>But the <strong><mark>terrestrial context</u></strong></mark> and consequences, <u>as well as the political stakes and symbolism of any exchange of hostilities in space <strong><mark>matters more</u></strong>. <u>The</mark> political and <mark>media</mark> dimension can <mark>magnify</u></mark> or minimise <u>the <mark>perceived consequences of losing</mark> specific <strong><mark>sat</u></strong></mark>ellite<u><strong><mark>s</strong></mark> <strong><mark>out of</strong></mark> all <strong><mark>proportion</strong> to</mark> their <strong><mark>actual strategic effect</u></strong></mark>.</p>
Case
null
Asteroid Strike
13,331
431
10,504
./documents/hsld21/CanyonCrest/Li/Canyon%20Crest-Li-Neg-1%20-%20College%20Prep-Round3.docx
884,409
N
1 - College Prep
3
Immaculate Heart JL
Park, Joanne
1AC - China 1NC - Debt K Redistribution CP 2NR - Debt K
hsld21/CanyonCrest/Li/Canyon%20Crest-Li-Neg-1%20-%20College%20Prep-Round3.docx
null
74,461
ViLi
Canyon Crest ViLi
null
Vi.....
Li.....
null
null
24,935
CanyonCrest
Canyon Crest
CA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
2,240,802
[1] The existence of extrinsic goodness requires unconditional human worth—that means we must treat others as ends in themselves.
Korsgaard ’83
Korsgaard ’83 (Christine M., “Two Distinctions in Goodness,” The Philosophical Review Vol. 92, No. 2 (Apr., 1983), pp. 169-195, JSTOR) OS *brackets for gendered language
when a rational being makes a choice or undertakes an action, [they] supposes the object to be good, and its pursuit to be justified In order for there to be any objectively good ends, however, there must be something that is unconditionally good and so can serve as a sufficient condition of their goodness it cannot be an object of inclination for if the inclinations and the needs founded on them did not exist, their object would be without worth the unconditionally valuable thing must be "humanity" regarding your existence as a rational being as an end in itself is a "subjective principle of human action." we must regard ourselves as capable of conferring value upon the objects of our choice, the ends that we set, because we must regard our ends as goo we must regard others as capable of conferring value by reason of their rational choices and so also as ends in themselves The ends that are chosen by any rational being, possessed of the humanity or rational nature that is fully realized in a good will, take on the status of objective goods. They are not intrinsically valuable, but they are objectively valuable
when a rational being undertakes an action, [they] supposes the object to be good there must be something that is unconditionally good and so can serve as a sufficient condition of their goodness it cannot be an object of inclination for if the inclinations and the needs founded on them did not exist, their object would be without worth the unconditionally valuable thing must be "humanity" regarding your existence as a rational being as an end in itself is a "subjective principle of human action we must regard ourselves as capable of conferring value we must regard others also as ends in themselves
The argument shows how Kant's idea of justification works. It can be read as a kind of regress upon the conditions, starting from an important assumption. The assumption is that when a rational being makes a choice or undertakes an action, he or she [they] supposes the object to be good, and its pursuit to be justified. At least, if there is a categorical imperative there must be objectively good ends, for then there are necessary actions and so necessary ends (G 45-46/427-428 and Doctrine of Virtue 43-44/384-385). In order for there to be any objectively good ends, however, there must be something that is unconditionally good and so can serve as a sufficient condition of their goodness. Kant considers what this might be: it cannot be an object of inclination, for those have only a conditional worth, "for if the inclinations and the needs founded on them did not exist, their object would be without worth" (G 46/428). It cannot be the inclinations themselves because a rational being would rather be free from them. Nor can it be external things, which serve only as means. So, Kant asserts, the unconditionally valuable thing must be "humanity" or "rational nature," which he defines as "the power set to an end" (G 56/437 and DV 51/392). Kant explains that regarding your existence as a rational being as an end in itself is a "subjective principle of human action." By this I understand him to mean that we must regard ourselves as capable of conferring value upon the objects of our choice, the ends that we set, because we must regard our ends as good. But since "every other rational being thinks of his existence by the same rational ground which holds also for myself' (G 47/429), we must regard others as capable of conferring value by reason of their rational choices and so also as ends in themselves. Treating another as an end in itself thus involves making that person's ends as far as possible your own (G 49/430). The ends that are chosen by any rational being, possessed of the humanity or rational nature that is fully realized in a good will, take on the status of objective goods. They are not intrinsically valuable, but they are objectively valuable in the sense that every rational being has a reason to promote or realize them. For this reason it is our duty to promote the happiness of others-the ends that they choose-and, in general, to make the highest good our end.
2,407
<h4>[1] The existence of extrinsic goodness requires unconditional human worth—that means we must treat others as ends in themselves.</h4><p><strong>Korsgaard ’83</strong> (Christine M., “Two Distinctions in Goodness,” The Philosophical Review Vol. 92, No. 2 (Apr., 1983), pp. 169-195, JSTOR) OS *brackets for gendered language</p><p>The argument shows how Kant's idea of justification works. It can be read as a kind of regress upon the conditions, starting from an important assumption. The assumption is that <u><mark>when a rational being</mark> makes a choice or <mark>undertakes an action, </u></mark>he or she<u> <mark>[they] supposes the object to be good</mark>, and its pursuit to be justified</u>. At least, if there is a categorical imperative there must be objectively good ends, for then there are necessary actions and so necessary ends (G 45-46/427-428 and Doctrine of Virtue 43-44/384-385). <u>In order for there to be any objectively good ends, however, <mark>there must be something that is unconditionally good and so can serve as a sufficient condition of their goodness</u></mark>. Kant considers what this might be: <u><mark>it cannot be an object of inclination</u></mark>, for those have only a conditional worth, "<u><mark>for if the inclinations and the needs founded on them did not exist, their object would be without worth</u></mark>" (G 46/428). It cannot be the inclinations themselves because a rational being would rather be free from them. Nor can it be external things, which serve only as means. So, Kant asserts, <u><mark>the unconditionally valuable thing must be "humanity"</u></mark> or "rational nature," which he defines as "the power set to an end" (G 56/437 and DV 51/392). Kant explains that <u><mark>regarding your existence as a rational being as an end in itself is a "<strong>subjective principle of human action</strong></mark>."</u> By this I understand him to mean that <u><mark>we must regard ourselves as capable of conferring value</mark> upon the objects of our choice, the ends that we set, because we must regard our ends as goo</u>d. But since "every other rational being thinks of his existence by the same rational ground which holds also for myself' (G 47/429), <u><mark>we must regard others</mark> as capable of conferring value by reason of their rational choices and so <mark>also as ends in themselves</u></mark>. Treating another as an end in itself thus involves making that person's ends as far as possible your own (G 49/430). <u>The ends that are chosen by any rational being, possessed of the humanity or rational nature that is fully realized in a good will, take on the status of objective goods. They are not intrinsically valuable, but they are objectively valuable</u> in the sense that every rational being has a reason to promote or realize them. For this reason it is our duty to promote the happiness of others-the ends that they choose-and, in general, to make the highest good our end.</p>
Stanford R2 Aff Doc
1AC
Framing
44,413
796
69,731
./documents/hsld20/Lexington/Yi/Lexington-Ying-Aff-JF%20-%20Stanford-Round2.docx
865,088
A
JF - Stanford
2
American Heritage Broward Spencer Swickle
Muhammad Khattak
1AC - Kant 1NC - Skep NC - Th Spec Universe - Th Different Warrants for Paradigm Issues - Kant Hijacks on Case 1AR - Cant Deny 1AR Theory Read Evaluate the Debate After the 1NC and Justify New 2NR Paradigm Issues 2NR - Skep NC - Kant Hijacks 2AR - Cant Deny 1AR Theory Read Evaluate the Debate After the 1NC and Justify New 2NR Paradigm Issues
hsld20/Lexington/Yi/Lexington-Ying-Aff-JF%20-%20Stanford-Round2.docx
null
73,323
DeYi
Lexington DeYi
null
De.....
Yi.....
null
null
24,591
Lexington
Lexington
MA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
1,910,253
Existential risks outweigh
Ord 20
Ord 20. Toby Ord, Senior Research Fellow in Philosophy at Oxford University & world-renowned risk-assessment expert who’s advised the World Health Organization, the World Bank, the World Economic Forum, the US National Intelligence Council and the UK Prime Minister’s Office. (3-3-2020, “The Precipice: Existential Risk and the Future of Humanity,” Hachette Book Group & Bloomsbury Publishing, https://www.google.com/books/edition/The_Precipice/3aSiDwAAQBAJ?hl=en&gbpv=0, Google Books)//pacc + AM *bracketed for clarity*
UNDERSTANDING EXISTENTIAL RISK Humanity’s future is ripe with possibility We have achieved a rich understanding of the world and a level of prosperity of which our ancestors could only dream We know of no limits to what we might ultimately achieve extinction would foreclose our future destroy our potential eliminate all possibilities but one: a world [lacking] human flourishing Extinction forever there would be no coming back Bostrom showed that an immense catastrophe has triggered a global collapse of civilization, reducing humanity to a pre-agricultural state it has become impossible for the survivors to ever reestablish civilization Even if such a catastrophe did not cause our extinction, The vast realm of futures currently open to us would have collapsed to a narrow range of meager options We would have a failed world with no way back Following Bostrom, An existential risk is a risk that threatens the destruction of humanity’s longterm potential These capture the idea that the outcome of an existential catastrophe is both dismal and irrevocable We will not just fail to fulfill our potential, but this potential will be permanently lost including everything that humanity could eventually achieve, even if we have yet to invent the means of achieving it should be understood as permanent The challenge is to preserve our vast potential, and to allow our descendants to fulfill our potential, realizing one of the best possible futures open to us I leave the thresholds vague, but it should be understood that in any existential catastrophe the greater part of our potential is gone and very little remains my focus on humanity in the definitions is not supposed to exclude considerations of the value of the environment humans are the only beings we know of that are responsive to moral reasons and moral argument If we fail that capacity to push toward what is just, will vanish Our potential is a matter of what humanity can achieve through the combined actions of each and every human risk must involve some kind of probability Understanding probability in terms of objective long-run frequencies won’t work, as existential catastrophes can only ever happen once, and will always be unprecedented until the moment it is too late We can’t say probability of an existential catastrophe is zero because it hasn’t happened yet these require an evidential sense of probability, which describes the appropriate degree of belief we should have on the basis of the available information the credence humanity should have that it will occur, in light of our best evidence A true existential catastrophe must by its very nature be the decisive moment of human history — the point where we failed We rarely think seriously about risks to humanity’s entire potential But when a risk is made vivid and credible — when it is clear that billions of lives and all future generations are actually on the line — the importance of protecting humanity’s longterm potential is not controversial responding to the threat would immediately become one of the world’s top prioriti and it can aid in decisions about how to set our priorities
extinction would eliminate all possibilities forever reducing humanity to a pre-ag state futures would collapse to meager options a failed world no way back leave the thresholds vague unprecedented until too late these require evidential probability, which describes belief on available infor credence it will occur, in light of best evidence billions are on the line responding would be the world’s top prioriti
UNDERSTANDING EXISTENTIAL RISK Humanity’s future is ripe with possibility. We have achieved a rich understanding of the world we inhabit and a level of health and prosperity of which our ancestors could only dream. We have begun to explore the other worlds in the heavens above us, and to create virtual worlds completely beyond our ancestors’ comprehension. We know of almost no limits to what we might ultimately achieve. Human extinction would foreclose our future. It would destroy our potential. It would eliminate all possibilities but one: a world bereft [lacking] of human flourishing. Extinction would bring about this failed world and lock it in forever — there would be no coming back. The philosopher Nick Bostrom showed that extinction is not the only way this could happen: there are other catastrophic outcomes in which we lose not just the present, but all our potential for the future. Consider a world in ruins: an immense catastrophe has triggered a global collapse of civilization, reducing humanity to a pre-agricultural state. During this catastrophe, the Earth’s environment was damaged so severely that it has become impossible for the survivors to ever reestablish civilization. Even if such a catastrophe did not cause our extinction, it would have a similar effect on our future. The vast realm of futures currently open to us would have collapsed to a narrow range of meager options. We would have a failed world with no way back. Or consider a world in chains: in a future reminiscent of George Orwell’s Nineteen Eighty-Four, the entire world has become locked under the rule of an oppressive totalitarian regime, determined to perpetuate itself. Through powerful, technologically enabled indoctrination, surveillance and enforcement, it has become impossible for even a handful of dissidents to find each other, let alone stage an uprising. With everyone on Earth living under such rule, the regime is stable from threats, internal and external. If such a regime could be maintained indefinitely, then descent into this totalitarian future would also have much in common with extinction: just a narrow range of terrible futures remaining, and no way out. [FIGURE 2.1 Omitted] Following Bostrom, I shall call these “existential catastrophes,” defining them as follows: 3 An existential catastrophe is the destruction of humanity’s longterm potential. An existential risk is a risk that threatens the destruction of humanity’s longterm potential. These definitions capture the idea that the outcome of an existential catastrophe is both dismal and irrevocable. We will not just fail to fulfill our potential, but this very potential itself will be permanently lost. While I want to keep the official definitions succinct, there are several areas that warrant clarification. First, I am understanding humanity’s longterm potential in terms of the set of all possible futures that remain open to us. 4 This is an expansive idea of possibility, including everything that humanity could eventually achieve, even if we have yet to invent the means of achieving it. 5 But it follows that while our choices can lock things in, closing off possibilities, they can’t open up new ones. So any reduction in humanity’s potential should be understood as permanent. The challenge of our time is to preserve our vast potential, and to protect it against the risk of future destruction. The ultimate purpose is to allow our descendants to fulfill our potential, realizing one of the best possible futures open to us. While it may seem abstract at this scale, this is really a familiar idea that we encounter every day. Consider a child with high longterm potential: with futures open to her in which she leads a great life. It is important that her potential is preserved: that her best futures aren’t cut off due to accident, trauma or lack of education. It is important that her potential is protected: that we build in safeguards to make such a loss of potential extremely unlikely. And it is important that she ultimately fulfills her potential: that she ends up taking one of the best paths open to her. So too for humanity. Existential risks threaten the destruction of humanity’s potential. This includes cases where this destruction is complete (such as extinction) and where it is nearly complete, such as a permanent collapse of civilization in which the possibility for some very minor types of flourishing remain, or where there remains some remote chance of recovery. 6 I leave the thresholds vague, but it should be understood that in any existential catastrophe the greater part of our potential is gone and very little remains. Second, my focus on humanity in the definitions is not supposed to exclude considerations of the value of the environment, other animals, successors to Homo sapiens, or creatures elsewhere in the cosmos. It is not that I think only humans count. Instead, it is that humans are the only beings we know of that are responsive to moral reasons and moral argument — the beings who can examine the world and decide to do what is best. If we fail, that upward force, that capacity to push toward what is best or what is just, will vanish from the world. Our potential is a matter of what humanity can achieve through the combined actions of each and every human. The value of our actions will stem in part from what we do to and for humans, but it will depend on the effects of our actions on non-humans too. If we somehow give rise to new kinds of moral agents in the future, the term “humanity” in my definition should be taken to include them. My focus on humanity prevents threats to a single country or culture from counting as existential risks. There is a similar term that gets used this way — when people say that something is “an existential threat to this country.” Setting aside the fact that these claims are usually hyperbole, they are expressing a similar idea: that something threatens to permanently destroy the longterm potential of a country or culture. Third, any notion of risk must involve some kind of probability. What kind is involved in existential risk? Understanding the probability in terms of objective long-run frequencies won’t work, as the existential catastrophes we are concerned with can only ever happen once, and will always be unprecedented until the moment it is too late. We can’t say the probability of an existential catastrophe is precisely zero just because it hasn’t happened yet. Situations like these require an evidential sense of probability, which describes the appropriate degree of belief we should have on the basis of the available information. This is the familiar type of probability used in courtrooms, banks and betting shops. When I speak of the probability of an existential catastrophe, I will mean the credence humanity should have that it will occur, in light of our best evidence.9 There are many utterly terrible outcomes that do not count as existential catastrophes. One way this could happen is if there were no single precipitous event, but a multitude of smaller failures. This is because I take on the usual sense of catastrophe as a single, decisive event, rather than any combination of events that is bad in sum. If we were to squander our future simply by continually treating each other badly, or by never getting around to doing anything great, this could be just as bad an outcome but wouldn’t have come about via a catastrophe. Alternatively, there might be a single catastrophe, but one that leaves open some way for humanity to eventually recover. From our own vantage, looking out to the next few generations, this may appear equally bleak. But a thousand years hence it may be considered just one of several dark episodes in the human story. A true existential catastrophe must by its very nature be the decisive moment of human history — the point where we failed. Even catastrophes large enough to bring about the global collapse of civilization may fall short of being existential catastrophes. While colloquially referred to as “the end of the world,” a global collapse of civilization need not be the end of the human story. It has the required severity, but may not be permanent or irrevocable. In this book, I shall use the term civilization collapse quite literally, to refer to an outcome where humanity across the globe loses civilization (at least temporarily), being reduced to a pre-agricultural way of life. The term is often used loosely to refer merely to a massive breakdown of order, the loss of modern technology, or an end to our culture. But I am talking about a world without writing, cities, law, or any of the other trappings of civilization. This would be a very severe disaster and extremely hard to trigger. For all the historical pressures on civilizations, never once has this happened — not even on the scale of a continent.10 The fact that Europe survived losing 25 to 50 percent of its population in the Black Death, while keeping civilization firmly intact, suggests that triggering the collapse of civilization would require more than 50 percent fatality in every region of the world.11 Even if civilization did collapse, it is likely that it could be reestablished. As we have seen, civilization has already been independently established at least seven times by isolated peoples.12 While one might think resource depletion could make this harder, it is more likely that it has become substantially easier. Most disasters short of human extinction would leave our domesticated animals and plants, as well as copious material resources in the ruins of our cities — it is much easier to re-forge iron from old railings than to smelt it from ore. Even expendable resources such as coal would be much easier to access, via abandoned reserves and mines, than they ever were in the eighteenth century. 13 Moreover, evidence that civilization is possible, and the tools and knowledge to help rebuild, would be scattered across the world. There are, however, two close connections between the collapse of civilization and existential risk. First, a collapse would count as an existential catastrophe if it were unrecoverable. For example, it is conceivable that some form of extreme climate change or engineered plague might make the planet so inhospitable that humanity would be irrevocably reduced to scattered foragers.14 And second, a global collapse of civilization could increase the chance of extinction, by leaving us more vulnerable to subsequent catastrophe. One way a collapse could lead to extinction is if the population of the largest remaining group fell below the minimum viable population — the level needed for a population to survive. There is no precise figure for this, as it is usually defined probabilistically and depends on many details of the situation: where the population is, what technology they have access to, the sort of catastrophe they have suffered. Estimates range from hundreds of people up to tens of thousands.15 If a catastrophe directly reduces human population to below these levels, it will be more useful to classify it as a direct extinction event, rather than an unrecoverable collapse. And I expect that this will be one of the more common pathways to extinction. We rarely think seriously about risks to humanity’s entire potential. We encounter them mostly in action films, where our emotional reactions are dulled by their overuse as an easy way to heighten the drama.16 Or we see them in online lists of “ten ways the world could end,” aimed primarily to thrill and entertain. Since the end of the Cold War, we rarely encounter sober discussions by our leading thinkers on what extinction would mean for us, our cultures or humanity. 17 And so in casual contexts people are sometimes flippant about the prospect of human extinction. But when a risk is made vivid and credible — when it is clear that billions of lives and all future generations are actually on the line — the importance of protecting humanity’s longterm potential is not, for most people, controversial. If we learned that a large asteroid was heading toward Earth, posing a greater than 10 percent chance of human extinction later this century, there would be little debate about whether to make serious efforts to build a deflection system, or to ignore the issue and run the risk. To the contrary, responding to the threat would immediately become one of the world’s top priorities. Thus our lack of concern about these threats is much more to do with not yet believing that there are such threats, than it is about seriously doubting the immensity of the stakes. Yet it is important to spend a little while trying to understand more clearly the different sources of this importance. Such an understanding can buttress feeling and inspire action; it can bring to light new considerations; and it can aid in decisions about how to set our priorities.
12,933
<h4>Existential risks <u>outweigh</h4><p></u><strong>Ord 20</strong>. Toby Ord, Senior Research Fellow in Philosophy at Oxford University & world-renowned risk-assessment expert who’s advised the World Health Organization, the World Bank, the World Economic Forum, the US National Intelligence Council and the UK Prime Minister’s Office. (3-3-2020, “The Precipice: Existential Risk and the Future of Humanity,” Hachette Book Group & Bloomsbury Publishing, https://www.google.com/books/edition/The_Precipice/3aSiDwAAQBAJ?hl=en&gbpv=0<u>, Google Books)//pacc + AM *bracketed for clarity*</p><p>UNDERSTANDING EXISTENTIAL RISK</p><p>Humanity’s future is <strong>ripe</strong> with <strong>possibility</u></strong>. <u>We have achieved a rich understanding of the world</u> we inhabit <u>and a level of</u> health and <u>prosperity of which our ancestors could only dream</u>. We have begun to explore the other worlds in the heavens above us, and to create virtual worlds completely beyond our ancestors’ comprehension. <u>We know of</u> almost <u><strong>no limits</strong> to what we might ultimately achieve</u>. Human <u><strong><mark>extinction</strong> would</mark> <strong>foreclose</strong> our <strong>future</u></strong>. It would <u>destroy our potential</u>. It would <u><strong><mark>eliminate all possibilities</strong></mark> but one: a world</u> bereft<u> [lacking]</u> of <u>human flourishing</u>. <u><strong>Extinction</u></strong> would bring about this failed world and lock it in <u><strong><mark>forever</u></strong></mark> — <u>there would be <strong>no coming back</u></strong>. The philosopher Nick <u><strong>Bostrom</strong> showed that</u> extinction is not the only way this could happen: there are other catastrophic outcomes in which we lose not just the present, but all our potential for the future. Consider a world in ruins: <u>an immense catastrophe has triggered a global <strong>collapse of civilization</strong>, <mark>reducing humanity to a <strong>pre-ag</mark>ricultural <mark>state</u></strong></mark>. During this catastrophe, the Earth’s environment was damaged so severely that <u>it has become <strong>impossible</strong> for the survivors <strong>to</strong> ever <strong>reestablish civilization</u></strong>. <u><strong>Even if</strong> such a catastrophe did <strong>not</strong> cause our <strong>extinction</strong>,</u> it would have a similar effect on our future. <u>The <strong>vast</strong> realm of <strong><mark>futures</strong></mark> currently open to us <strong><mark>would</strong></mark> have <strong><mark>collapse</strong></mark>d <mark>to</mark> a narrow range of <mark>meager options</u></mark>. <u>We would have <mark>a <strong>failed world</strong></mark> with <strong><mark>no way back</u></strong></mark>. Or consider a world in chains: in a future reminiscent of George Orwell’s Nineteen Eighty-Four, the entire world has become locked under the rule of an oppressive totalitarian regime, determined to perpetuate itself. Through powerful, technologically enabled indoctrination, surveillance and enforcement, it has become impossible for even a handful of dissidents to find each other, let alone stage an uprising. With everyone on Earth living under such rule, the regime is stable from threats, internal and external. If such a regime could be maintained indefinitely, then descent into this totalitarian future would also have much in common with extinction: just a narrow range of terrible futures remaining, and no way out. [FIGURE 2.1 Omitted] <u>Following Bostrom,</u> I shall call these “existential catastrophes,” defining them as follows: 3 An existential catastrophe is the destruction of humanity’s longterm potential. <u>An <strong>existential risk</strong> is a risk that <strong>threatens</strong> the destruction of humanity’s <strong>longterm potential</u></strong>. <u>These</u> definitions <u>capture the idea that the outcome of an existential catastrophe is both <strong>dismal</strong> and <strong>irrevocable</u></strong>. <u>We will not just fail to fulfill our potential, but this</u> very <u>potential</u> itself <u>will be <strong>permanently lost</u></strong>. While I want to keep the official definitions succinct, there are several areas that warrant clarification. First, I am understanding humanity’s longterm potential in terms of the set of all possible futures that remain open to us. 4 This is an expansive idea of possibility, <u>including <strong>everything</strong> that humanity could eventually achieve, even if we have yet to invent the means of achieving it</u>. 5 But it follows that while our choices can lock things in, closing off possibilities, they can’t open up new ones. So any reduction in humanity’s potential <u>should be understood as <strong>permanent</u></strong>. <u>The challenge </u>of our time <u>is to <strong>preserve</strong> our vast potential, and</u> to protect it against the risk of future destruction. The ultimate purpose is <u>to allow our <strong>descendants</strong> to <strong>fulfill</strong> our <strong>potential</strong>, realizing one of the <strong>best possible futures</strong> open to us</u>. While it may seem abstract at this scale, this is really a familiar idea that we encounter every day. Consider a child with high longterm potential: with futures open to her in which she leads a great life. It is important that her potential is preserved: that her best futures aren’t cut off due to accident, trauma or lack of education. It is important that her potential is protected: that we build in safeguards to make such a loss of potential extremely unlikely. And it is important that she ultimately fulfills her potential: that she ends up taking one of the best paths open to her. So too for humanity. Existential risks threaten the destruction of humanity’s potential. This includes cases where this destruction is complete (such as extinction) and where it is nearly complete, such as a permanent collapse of civilization in which the possibility for some very minor types of flourishing remain, or where there remains some remote chance of recovery. 6 <u>I <mark>leave the thresholds vague</mark>, but it should be understood that in any existential catastrophe the greater part of our <strong>potential</strong> is <strong>gone</strong> and <strong>very little remains</u></strong>. Second, <u>my focus on humanity in the definitions is <strong>not supposed to exclude</strong> considerations of the value of the <strong>environment</u></strong>, other animals, successors to Homo sapiens, or creatures elsewhere in the cosmos. It is not that I think only humans count. Instead, it is that <u>humans are the only beings we know of that are <strong>responsive to moral reasons</strong> and moral argument</u> — the beings who can examine the world and decide to do what is best. <u><strong>If we fail</u></strong>, that upward force, <u>that capacity to<strong> push</strong> toward what is </u>best or what is <u><strong>just</strong>, will <strong>vanish</u></strong> from the world. <u>Our potential is a matter of what humanity can achieve through the combined actions of <strong>each and every human</u></strong>. The value of our actions will stem in part from what we do to and for humans, but it will depend on the effects of our actions on non-humans too. If we somehow give rise to new kinds of moral agents in the future, the term “humanity” in my definition should be taken to include them. My focus on humanity prevents threats to a single country or culture from counting as existential risks. There is a similar term that gets used this way — when people say that something is “an existential threat to this country.” Setting aside the fact that these claims are usually hyperbole, they are expressing a similar idea: that something threatens to permanently destroy the longterm potential of a country or culture. Third, any notion of <u>risk must involve some kind of probability</u>. What kind is involved in existential risk? <u>Understanding</u> the <u>probability in terms of objective long-run frequencies won’t work, as</u> the <u>existential catastrophes</u> we are concerned with <u>can only ever happen once, and will always be <strong><mark>unprecedented</strong> until</mark> the moment it is <strong><mark>too late</u></strong></mark>. <u>We can’t say</u> the <u><strong>probability</strong> of an existential catastrophe is</u> precisely <u><strong>zero</strong> </u>just<u> because it hasn’t happened yet</u>. Situations like <u><mark>these require</mark> <strong>an <mark>evidential</mark> sense</strong> of <strong><mark>probability</strong>, which describes</mark> the appropriate degree of <mark>belief</mark> we should have <mark>on</mark> the basis of the <mark>available infor</mark>mation</u>. This is the familiar type of probability used in courtrooms, banks and betting shops. When I speak of the probability of an existential catastrophe, I will mean <u>the <strong><mark>credence</strong></mark> humanity should have <strong>that <mark>it will occur</strong>, in light of</mark> <strong>our <mark>best evidence</u></strong></mark>.9 There are many utterly terrible outcomes that do not count as existential catastrophes. One way this could happen is if there were no single precipitous event, but a multitude of smaller failures. This is because I take on the usual sense of catastrophe as a single, decisive event, rather than any combination of events that is bad in sum. If we were to squander our future simply by continually treating each other badly, or by never getting around to doing anything great, this could be just as bad an outcome but wouldn’t have come about via a catastrophe. Alternatively, there might be a single catastrophe, but one that leaves open some way for humanity to eventually recover. From our own vantage, looking out to the next few generations, this may appear equally bleak. But a thousand years hence it may be considered just one of several dark episodes in the human story. <u>A true existential catastrophe must by its very nature be the decisive moment of human history — the point where we failed</u>. Even catastrophes large enough to bring about the global collapse of civilization may fall short of being existential catastrophes. While colloquially referred to as “the end of the world,” a global collapse of civilization need not be the end of the human story. It has the required severity, but may not be permanent or irrevocable. In this book, I shall use the term civilization collapse quite literally, to refer to an outcome where humanity across the globe loses civilization (at least temporarily), being reduced to a pre-agricultural way of life. The term is often used loosely to refer merely to a massive breakdown of order, the loss of modern technology, or an end to our culture. But I am talking about a world without writing, cities, law, or any of the other trappings of civilization. This would be a very severe disaster and extremely hard to trigger. For all the historical pressures on civilizations, never once has this happened — not even on the scale of a continent.10 The fact that Europe survived losing 25 to 50 percent of its population in the Black Death, while keeping civilization firmly intact, suggests that triggering the collapse of civilization would require more than 50 percent fatality in every region of the world.11 Even if civilization did collapse, it is likely that it could be reestablished. As we have seen, civilization has already been independently established at least seven times by isolated peoples.12 While one might think resource depletion could make this harder, it is more likely that it has become substantially easier. Most disasters short of human extinction would leave our domesticated animals and plants, as well as copious material resources in the ruins of our cities — it is much easier to re-forge iron from old railings than to smelt it from ore. Even expendable resources such as coal would be much easier to access, via abandoned reserves and mines, than they ever were in the eighteenth century. 13 Moreover, evidence that civilization is possible, and the tools and knowledge to help rebuild, would be scattered across the world. There are, however, two close connections between the collapse of civilization and existential risk. First, a collapse would count as an existential catastrophe if it were unrecoverable. For example, it is conceivable that some form of extreme climate change or engineered plague might make the planet so inhospitable that humanity would be irrevocably reduced to scattered foragers.14 And second, a global collapse of civilization could increase the chance of extinction, by leaving us more vulnerable to subsequent catastrophe. One way a collapse could lead to extinction is if the population of the largest remaining group fell below the minimum viable population — the level needed for a population to survive. There is no precise figure for this, as it is usually defined probabilistically and depends on many details of the situation: where the population is, what technology they have access to, the sort of catastrophe they have suffered. Estimates range from hundreds of people up to tens of thousands.15 If a catastrophe directly reduces human population to below these levels, it will be more useful to classify it as a direct extinction event, rather than an unrecoverable collapse. And I expect that this will be one of the more common pathways to extinction. <u>We rarely think seriously about risks to humanity’s entire potential</u>. We encounter them mostly in action films, where our emotional reactions are dulled by their overuse as an easy way to heighten the drama.16 Or we see them in online lists of “ten ways the world could end,” aimed primarily to thrill and entertain. Since the end of the Cold War, we rarely encounter sober discussions by our leading thinkers on what extinction would mean for us, our cultures or humanity. 17 And so in casual contexts people are sometimes flippant about the prospect of human extinction. <u>But when a risk is made vivid and credible — when it is clear that <strong><mark>billions</strong></mark> of <strong>lives</strong> and all <strong>future generations</strong> <mark>are</mark> actually <strong><mark>on the line</strong></mark> — the importance of protecting humanity’s longterm potential is not</u>, for most people, <u>controversial</u>. If we learned that a large asteroid was heading toward Earth, posing a greater than 10 percent chance of human extinction later this century, there would be little debate about whether to make serious efforts to build a deflection system, or to ignore the issue and run the risk. To the contrary, <u><strong><mark>responding</strong></mark> to the threat <mark>would</mark> immediately <mark>be</mark>come one of <mark>the world’s</mark> <strong><mark>top prioriti</u></strong></mark>es. Thus our lack of concern about these threats is much more to do with not yet believing that there are such threats, than it is about seriously doubting the immensity of the stakes. Yet it is important to spend a little while trying to understand more clearly the different sources of this importance. Such an understanding can buttress feeling and inspire action; it can bring to light new considerations; <u>and it can <strong>aid</strong> in <strong>decisions</strong> about how to set our <strong>priorities</u></strong>.</p>
1NC
1NC — Framing
1NC — Framing
35,771
485
56,397
./documents/hspolicy20/LawrenceFreeState/RuWi/Lawrence%20Free%20State-Ruland-Wilkus-Neg-08%20-%20Southern%20Bell%20Forum-Round3.docx
732,460
N
08 - Southern Bell Forum
3
St Marks CY
Erik Mathis
1AC - Death Penalty 1NC - T-Enact - White Collar Crime PIC - Hate Crimes PIC v2 - Ex Flex DA - ACA DA - Constitutional Amendment CP - Problematization K - LWP CT - Overrules CT - Abortion CT 2NC - T-Enact - White Collar Crime PIC 1NR - Ex Flex DA - ACA DA - LWP CT 2NR - ACA DA - LWP CT
hspolicy20/LawrenceFreeState/RuWi/Lawrence%20Free%20State-Ruland-Wilkus-Neg-08%20-%20Southern%20Bell%20Forum-Round3.docx
null
62,531
RuWi
Lawrence Free State RuWi
null
Si.....
Ru.....
Ja.....
Wi.....
21,684
LawrenceFreeState
Lawrence Free State
KS
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
705,477
The role of the ballot is to center indigenous scholarship and resistance-- Any ethical commitment requires that the aff place themselves in the center of Native scholarship and demands.
Carlson 16
Carlson 16 (Elizabeth Carlson, PhD, is an Aamitigoozhi, Wemistigosi, and Wasicu (settler Canadian and American), whose Swedish, Saami, German, Scots-Irish, and English ancestors have settled on lands of the Anishinaabe and Omaha Nations which were unethically obtained by the US government. Elizabeth lives on Treaty 1 territory, the traditional lands of the Anishinaabe, Nehiyawak, Dakota, Nakota, and Red River Metis peoples currently occupied by the city of Winnipeg, the province of Manitoba, (2016): Anti-colonial methodologies and practices for settler colonial studies, Settler Colonial Studies, DOI: 10.1080/2201473X.2016.1241213, JKS)
where anticolonialism is a tool used to invoke resistance for the colonized, it is a tool used to invoke accountability for the colonizer’ Relational accountability should be a cornerstone of settler colonial studies. settler colonial studies and scholars should ethically and overtly place themselves in relationship to the centuries of Indigenous oral, scholarship that resists settler colonialism Indigenous people have been speaking for a long time about colonial continuities based on their lived experiences Others, use SCT as a pathway to explain the colonial encounter without engaging with Indigenous people and experience Indigenous resistance is rendered invisible Ethical settler colonial theory would recognize the foundational role Indigenous scholarship has in critiques of settler colonialism. It would acknowledge the limitations of settler scholars in articulating settler colonialism without dialogue with Indigenous peoples, Indigenous oral and academic scholars are indeed the originators of this work. This space is not empty anti-colonial scholars resist these hegemonic pressures and maintain a higher anti-colonial ethic. the theory itself places ethical demands on us as settlers, including the demand that we actively refuse its potential to re-empower our own academic voices and to marginalize Indigenous resistance’ We can centre Indigenous resistance, knowledges, in our work, and contextualize our work in Indigenous sovereignty. We can view oral Indigenous scholarship as legitimate scholarly sources. We can acknowledge explicitly and often the Indigenous traditions of resistance and scholarship that have taught us and pro- vided the foundations for our work. If our work has no foundation of Indigenous scholarship our contributions to settler colonial studies are deeply problematic.
Indigenous people have been speaking for a long time Indigenous resistance is rendered invisible Ethical settler colonial theory would recognize the foundational role Indigenous scholarship the theory itself places ethical demands on us as settlers, including the demand that we actively refuse its potential to re-empower our own academic voices We can centre Indigenous resistance, knowledges in our work can view oral Indigenous scholarship as legitimate scholarly sources. If our work has no foundation of Indigenous scholarship our contributions to settler colonial studies are
Arlo Kempf says that ‘where anticolonialism is a tool used to invoke resistance for the colonized, it is a tool used to invoke accountability for the colonizer’.42 Relational accountability should be a cornerstone of settler colonial studies. I believe settler colonial studies and scholars should ethically and overtly place themselves in relationship to the centuries of Indigenous oral, and later academic scholarship that conceptualizes and resists settler colonialism without necessarily using the term: SCT may be revelatory to many settler scholars, but Indigenous people have been speaking for a long time about colonial continuities based on their lived experiences. Some SCTs have sought to connect with these discussions and to foreground Indigenous resistance, survival and agency. Others, however, seem to use SCT as a pathway to explain the colonial encounter without engaging with Indigenous people and experiences – either on the grounds that this structural analysis already conceptually explains Indigenous experience, or because Indigenous resistance is rendered invisible.43 Ethical settler colonial theory (SCT) would recognize the foundational role Indigenous scholarship has in critiques of settler colonialism. It would acknowledge the limitations of settler scholars in articulating settler colonialism without dialogue with Indigenous peoples, and take as its norm making this dialogue evident. In my view, it is critical that we not view settler colonial studies as a new or unique field being established, which would enact a discovery narrative and contribute to Indigenous erasure, but rather take a longer and broader view. Indigenous oral and academic scholars are indeed the originators of this work. This space is not empty. Of course, powerful forces of socialization and discipline impact scholars in the academy. There is much pressure to claim unique space, to establish a name for ourselves, and to make academic discoveries. I am suggesting that settler colonial studies and anti-colonial scholars resist these hegemonic pressures and maintain a higher anti-colonial ethic. As has been argued, ‘the theory itself places ethical demands on us as settlers, including the demand that we actively refuse its potential to re-empower our own academic voices and to marginalize Indigenous resistance’.44 As settler scholars, we can reposition our work relationally and contextually with humi- lity and accountability. We can centre Indigenous resistance, knowledges, and scholarship in our work, and contextualize our work in Indigenous sovereignty. We can view oral Indigenous scholarship as legitimate scholarly sources. We can acknowledge explicitly and often the Indigenous traditions of resistance and scholarship that have taught us and pro- vided the foundations for our work. If our work has no foundation of Indigenous scholarship and mentorship, I believe our contributions to settler colonial studies are even more deeply problematic.
2,978
<h4><strong>The role of the ballot is to center indigenous scholarship and resistance-- Any ethical commitment requires that the aff place themselves in the center of Native scholarship and demands. </h4><p>Carlson 16</p><p><u>(Elizabeth Carlson, PhD, is an Aamitigoozhi, Wemistigosi, and Wasicu (settler Canadian and American), whose Swedish, Saami, German, Scots-Irish, and English ancestors have settled on lands of the Anishinaabe and Omaha Nations which were unethically obtained by the US government. Elizabeth lives on Treaty 1 territory, the traditional lands of the Anishinaabe, Nehiyawak, Dakota, Nakota, and Red River Metis peoples currently occupied by the city of Winnipeg, the province of Manitoba, (2016): Anti-colonial methodologies and practices for settler colonial studies, Settler Colonial Studies, DOI: 10.1080/2201473X.2016.1241213, JKS)</p><p></u></strong>Arlo Kempf says that ‘<u><strong>where anticolonialism is a tool used to invoke resistance for the colonized, it is a tool used to invoke accountability for the colonizer’</u></strong>.42 <u><strong>Relational accountability should be a cornerstone of settler colonial studies.</u></strong> I believe <u><strong>settler colonial studies and scholars should ethically and overtly place themselves in relationship to the centuries of Indigenous oral, </u></strong>and later academic<u><strong> scholarship that </u></strong>conceptualizes and <u><strong>resists settler colonialism </u></strong>without necessarily using the term: SCT may be revelatory to many settler scholars, but <u><strong><mark>Indigenous people have been speaking for a long time</mark> about colonial continuities based on their lived experiences</u></strong>. Some SCTs have sought to connect with these discussions and to foreground Indigenous resistance, survival and agency. <u><strong>Others, </u></strong>however, seem to <u><strong>use SCT as a pathway to explain the colonial encounter without engaging with Indigenous people and experience</u></strong>s – either on the grounds that this structural analysis already conceptually explains Indigenous experience, or because <u><strong><mark>Indigenous resistance is rendered invisible</u></strong></mark>.43 <u><strong><mark>Ethical settler colonial theory</u></strong></mark> (SCT) <u><strong><mark>would recognize the foundational role Indigenous scholarship</mark> has in critiques of settler colonialism. It would acknowledge the limitations of settler scholars in articulating settler colonialism without dialogue with Indigenous peoples,</u></strong> and take as its norm making this dialogue evident. In my view, it is critical that we not view settler colonial studies as a new or unique field being established, which would enact a discovery narrative and contribute to Indigenous erasure, but rather take a longer and broader view. <u><strong>Indigenous oral and academic scholars are indeed the originators of this work. This space is not empty</u></strong>. Of course, powerful forces of socialization and discipline impact scholars in the academy. There is much pressure to claim unique space, to establish a name for ourselves, and to make academic discoveries. I am suggesting that settler colonial studies and <u><strong>anti-colonial scholars resist these hegemonic pressures and maintain a higher anti-colonial ethic.</u></strong> As has been argued, ‘<u><strong><mark>the theory itself places ethical demands on us as settlers, including the demand that we actively refuse its potential to re-empower our own academic voices</mark> and to marginalize Indigenous resistance’</u></strong>.44 As settler scholars, we can reposition our work relationally and contextually with humi- lity and accountability. <u><strong><mark>We can centre Indigenous resistance, knowledges</mark>, </u></strong>and scholarship<u><strong> <mark>in our work</mark>, and contextualize our work in Indigenous sovereignty. We <mark>can view oral Indigenous scholarship as legitimate scholarly sources.</mark> We can acknowledge explicitly and often the Indigenous traditions of resistance and scholarship that have taught us and pro- vided the foundations for our work. <mark>If our work has no foundation of Indigenous scholarship</mark> </u></strong>and mentorship, I believe<u><strong> <mark>our contributions to settler colonial studies are</mark> </u></strong>even more<u><strong> deeply problematic.</p></u></strong>
NC vs Spec
K
null
41,706
630
15,364
./documents/hsld19/HarvardWestlake/Mo/Harvard%20Westlake-Morrk-Neg-St%20Marks-Round2.docx
839,539
N
St Marks
2
Southlake Caroll PK
Bennett Eckert
AC Deleuze whole res NC disclosed 1AR answers 2NR Test optional 2AR answers
hsld19/HarvardWestlake/Mo/Harvard%20Westlake-Morrk-Neg-St%20Marks-Round2.docx
null
71,679
AlMo
Harvard Westlake AlMo
null
Al.....
Mo.....
null
null
24,122
HarvardWestlake
Harvard Westlake
CA
null
1,027
hsld19
HS LD 2019-20
2,019
ld
hs
1
2,744,323
The text of the resolution calls for debate on hypothetical government action
Ericson 3
Ericson 3 (Jon M., Dean Emeritus of the College of Liberal Arts – California Polytechnic U., et al., The Debater’s Guide, Third Edition, p. 4)
each topic contains certain key elements . 1. An agent doing the acting ---“The United States” in “The United States should adopt the agent is the subject of the sentence. 2. The verb should that urges action For example, should adopt means to put a policy into action though governmental means The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur.
each topic contains key elements An agent doing the acting The United States The verb should that urges action should adopt a policy debate is about whether something ought to occur
The Proposition of Policy: Urging Future Action In policy propositions, each topic contains certain key elements, although they have slightly different functions from comparable elements of value-oriented propositions. 1. An agent doing the acting ---“The United States” in “The United States should adopt a policy of free trade.” Like the object of evaluation in a proposition of value, the agent is the subject of the sentence. 2. The verb should—the first part of a verb phrase that urges action. 3. An action verb to follow should in the should-verb combination. For example, should adopt here means to put a program or policy into action though governmental means. 4. A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired. The phrase free trade, for example, gives direction and limits to the topic, which would, for example, eliminate consideration of increasing tariffs, discussing diplomatic recognition, or discussing interstate commerce. Propositions of policy deal with future action. Nothing has yet occurred. The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur. What you agree to do, then, when you accept the affirmative side in such a debate is to offer sufficient and compelling reasons for an audience to perform the future action that you propose.
1,287
<h4>The <u>text of the resolution</u> calls for debate on hypothetical government action</h4><p><strong>Ericson 3</strong> (Jon M., Dean Emeritus of the College of Liberal Arts – California Polytechnic U., et al., The Debater’s Guide, Third Edition, p. 4)</p><p>The Proposition of Policy: Urging Future Action In policy propositions, <u><strong><mark>each topic</mark> <mark>contains</mark> certain <mark>key elements</u></strong></mark>, although they have slightly different functions from comparable elements of value-oriented propositions<u>. 1. <strong><mark>An agent doing the</mark> <mark>acting</mark> ---“<mark>The United States</mark>” in “The United States should</strong> adopt</u> a policy of free trade.” Like the object of evaluation in a proposition of value, <u><strong>the agent is the subject of the sentence. 2. <mark>The verb should</u></strong></mark>—the first part of a verb phrase <u><strong><mark>that urges action</u></strong></mark>. 3. An action verb to follow should in the should-verb combination. <u><strong>For example, <mark>should</strong> <strong>adopt</u></strong></mark> here <u><strong>means to put <mark>a</u></strong></mark> program or <u><strong><mark>policy</mark> into action though governmental means</u></strong>. 4. A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired. The phrase free trade, for example, gives direction and limits to the topic, which would, for example, eliminate consideration of increasing tariffs, discussing diplomatic recognition, or discussing interstate commerce. Propositions of policy deal with future action. Nothing has yet occurred. <u><strong>The entire <mark>debate is about whether something ought to occur</strong></mark>.</u> What you agree to do, then, when you accept the affirmative side in such a debate is to offer sufficient and compelling reasons for an audience to perform the future action that you propose. </p>
1NC
null
OFF
1,149
3,809
87,025
./documents/hspolicy19/Lexington/PeBa/Lexington-Peng-Barry-Neg-Mamaroneck%20SYBOF-Finals.docx
715,043
N
Mamaroneck SYBOF
Finals
Stuyvesant EP
Ben Morbeck, Jonathan Collins, Will Cheung
1AC - Afrofuturism 1NC - T-USfg Comm Cap K Heg DA 2NC - T-USfg Case 1NR - Cap K 2NR - Case T-USfg
hspolicy19/Lexington/PeBa/Lexington-Peng-Barry-Neg-Mamaroneck%20SYBOF-Finals.docx
null
60,975
PeBa
Lexington PeBa
null
Al.....
Pe.....
Ca.....
Ba.....
21,283
Lexington
Lexington
MA
null
1,018
hspolicy19
HS Policy 2019-20
2,019
cx
hs
2
4,643,842
Rigorous climate simulations.
Reisner et al. 18 ]
Reisner et al. 18 [Jon Reisner – Climate and atmospheric scientist at the Los Alamos National Laboratory. Gennaro D’Angelo – Climate scientist at the Los Alamos National Laboratory, Research scientist at the SETI institute, Associate specialist at the University of California, Santa Cruz, NASA Postdoctoral Fellow at the NASA Ames Research Center, UKAFF Fellow at the University of Exeter. Eunmo Koo - Scientist at Applied Terrestrial, Energy, and Atmospheric Modeling (ATEAM) Team, in Computational Earth Science Group (EES-16) in Earth and Environmental Sciences Division and Co-Lead of Parallel Computing Summer Research Internship (PCSRI) program at the Los Alamos National Laboratory, former Staff research associate at UC Berkeley. Wesley Even - Computational scientist in the Computational Physics and Methods Group at Los Alamos National Laboratory. Matthew Hecht – Atmospheric scientist at the Los Alamos National Laboratory. Elizabeth Hunke - Lead developer for the Los Alamos Sea Ice Model (CICE) at the Los Alamos National Laboratory responsible for development and incorporation of new parameterizations, model testing and validation, computational performance, documentation, and consultation with external model users on all aspects of sea ice modeling, including interfacing with global climate and earth system models. Darin Comeau – Climate scientist at the Los Alamos National Laboratory, Randy Bos - Project leader at the Los Alamos National Laboratory, former Weapons Effects program manager at Tech-Source, James Cooley – Computational scientist at the Los Alamos National Laboratory specializing in weapons physics, emergency response, and computational physics, “Climate impact of a regional nuclear weapons exchange:An improved assessment based on detailed source calculations,” March 16, 2018, https://agupubs.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/full/10.1002/2017JD027331]
The no-rubble simulation produces significantly more intense fire with more spread and a significantly stronger plume with larger amounts of BC reaching into the upper atmosphere While the no-rubble simulation represents the worst-case scenario involving vigorous fire activity only a relatively small amount of carbon makes its way into the stratosphere vertical profiles of BC reside below the stratosphere and can be readily impacted by scavenging from precipitation either via pyro-cumulonimbus produced by the fire itself or other synoptic weather systems these estimates are still at the high end, considering the inherent simplifications in the combustion model that lead to overestimating BC production. Long-term climatic effects critically depend on the height of the soot, with larger quantities reaching the upper troposphere/lower stratosphere inducing a greater cooling impact because of longer residence times Mixing and sedimentation reduce this process, and low altitude emissions are significantly impacted by precipitation Of the initial BC released in the atmosphere 70% rains out within the first month and 78% is removed within the first two months The BC distributions in simulations imply that upward transport of particles is substantially less efficient compared to the case in which BC is directly injected into the upper troposphere the difference can be understood in terms of the air temperature increase caused by BC radiation emission which is several tens of kelvin degrees in simulations of Robock Mills Stenke and Pausata due to high BC concentrations, but amounts to only about 10 K in our ensemble simulations In that scenario as well, somewhat less that 1 Tg of BC remained in the atmosphere after the initial rainout. This suggests that the inclusion of organic carbon aerosols, and ensuing coagulation with BC, should not dramatically alter the climatic effects resulting from our forced ensemble simulations. Moreover, aerosol growth would likely shorten the residence time of the BC particulate in the atmosphere reducing the duration of these effects.
the worst-case scenario only a relatively small amount of carbon makes its way into the stratosphere these estimates are at the high end considering the inherent simplifications that lead to overestimating BC production climatic effects depend on height Mixing and sedimentation reduce this process, and low altitude emissions are significantly impacted by precipitation Of the initial BC 70% rains out within the first month the inclusion of organic carbon aerosols should not dramatically alter the climatic effects aerosol growth shorten the residence time of the BC
The no-rubble simulation produces a significantly more intense fire, with more fire spread, and consequently a significantly stronger plume with larger amounts of BC reaching into the upper atmosphere than the simulation with rubble, illustrated in Figure 5. While the no-rubble simulation represents the worst-case scenario involving vigorous fire activity, only a relatively small amount of carbon makes its way into the stratosphere during the course of the simulation. But while small compared to the surface BC mass, stratospheric BC amounts from the current simulations are significantly higher than what would be expected from burning vegetation such as trees (Heilman et al., 2014), e.g., the higher energy density of the building fuels and the initial fluence from the weapon produce an intense response within HIGRAD with initial updrafts of order 100 m/s in the lower troposphere. Or, in comparison to a mass fire, wildfires will burn only a small amount of fuel in the corresponding time period (roughly 10 minutes) that a nuclear weapon fluence can effectively ignite a large area of fuel producing an impressive atmospheric response. Figure 6 shows vertical profiles of BC multiplied by 100 (number of cities involved in the exchange) from the two simulations. The total amount of BC produced is in line with previous estimates (about 3.69 Tg from no-rubble simulation); however, the majority of BC resides below the stratosphere (3.46 Tg below 12 km) and can be readily impacted by scavenging from precipitation either via pyro-cumulonimbus produced by the fire itself (not modeled) or other synoptic weather systems. While the impact on climate of these more realistic profiles will be explored in the next section, it should be mentioned that these estimates are still at the high end, considering the inherent simplifications in the combustion model that lead to overestimating BC production. 3.3 Climate Results Long-term climatic effects critically depend on the initial injection height of the soot, with larger quantities reaching the upper troposphere/lower stratosphere inducing a greater cooling impact because of longer residence times (Robock et al., 2007a). Absorption of solar radiation by the BC aerosol and its subsequent radiative cooling tends to heat the surrounding air, driving an initial upward diffusion of the soot plumes, an effect that depends on the initial aerosol concentrations. Mixing and sedimentation tend to reduce this process, and low altitude emissions are also significantly impacted by precipitation if aging of the BC aerosol occurs on sufficiently rapid timescales. But once at stratospheric altitudes, aerosol dilution via coagulation is hindered by low particulate concentrations (e.g., Robock et al., 2007a) and lofting to much higher altitudes is inhibited by gravitational settling in the low-density air (Stenke et al., 2013), resulting in more stable BC concentrations over long times. Of the initial BC mass released in the atmosphere, most of which is emitted below 9 km, 70% rains out within the first month and 78%, or about 2.9 Tg, is removed within the first two months (Figure 7, solid line), with the remainder (about 0.8 Tg, dashed line) being transported above about 12 km (200 hPa) within the first week. This outcome differs from the findings of, e.g., Stenke et al. (2013, their high BC-load cases) and Mills et al. (2014), who found that most of the BC mass (between 60 and 70%) is lifted in the stratosphere within the first couple of weeks. This can also be seen in Figure 8 (red lines) and in Figure 9, which include results from our calculation with the initial BC distribution from Mills et al. (2014). In that case, only 30% of the initial BC mass rains out in the troposphere during the first two weeks after the exchange, with the remainder rising to the stratosphere. In the study of Mills et al. (2008) this percentage is somewhat smaller, about 20%, and smaller still in the experiments of Robock et al. (2007a) in which the soot is initially emitted in the upper troposphere or higher. In Figure 7, the e-folding timescale for the removal of tropospheric soot, here interpreted as the time required for an initial drop of a factor e, is about one week. This result compares favorably with the “LT” experiment of Robock et al. (2007a), considering 5 Tg of BC released in the lower troposphere, in which 50% of the aerosols are removed within two weeks. By contrast, the initial e-folding timescale for the removal of stratospheric soot in Figure 8 is about 4.2 years (blue solid line), compared to about 8.4 years for the calculation using Mills et al. (2014) initial BC emission (red solid line). The removal timescale from our forced ensemble simulations is close to those obtained by Mills et al. (2008) in their 1 Tg experiment, by Robock et al. (2007a) in their experiment “UT 1 Tg”, and © 2018 American Geophysical Union. All rights reserved. by Stenke et al. (2013) in their experiment “Exp1”, in all of which 1 Tg of soot was emitted in the atmosphere in the aftermath of the exchange. Notably, the e-folding timescale for the decline of the BC mass in Figure 8 (blue solid line) is also close to the value of about 4 years quoted by Pausata et al. (2016) for their long-term “intermediate” scenario. In that scenario, which is also based on 5 Tg of soot initially distributed as in Mills et al. (2014), the factor-of2 shorter residence time of the aerosols is caused by particle growth via coagulation of BC with organic carbon. Figure 9 shows the BC mass-mixing ratio, horizontally averaged over the globe, as a function of atmospheric pressure (height) and time. The BC distributions used in our simulations imply that the upward transport of particles is substantially less efficient compared to the case in which 5 Tg of BC is directly injected into the upper troposphere. The semiannual cycle of lofting and sinking of the aerosols is associated with atmospheric heating and cooling during the solstice in each hemisphere (Robock et al., 2007a). During the first year, the oscillation amplitude in our forced ensemble simulations is particularly large during the summer solstice, compared to that during the winter solstice (see bottom panel of Figure 9), because of the higher soot concentrations in the Northern Hemisphere, as can be seen in Figure 11 (see also left panel of Figure 12). Comparing the top and bottom panels of Figure 9, the BC reaches the highest altitudes during the first year in both cases, but the concentrations at 0.1 hPa in the top panel can be 200 times as large. Qualitatively, the difference can be understood in terms of the air temperature increase caused by BC radiation emission, which is several tens of kelvin degrees in the simulations of Robock et al. (2007a, see their Figure 4), Mills et al. (2008, see their Figure 5), Stenke et al. (2013, see high-load cases in their Figure 4), Mills et al. (2014, see their Figure 7), and Pausata et al. (2016, see one-day emission cases in their Figure 1), due to high BC concentrations, but it amounts to only about 10 K in our forced ensemble simulations, as illustrated in Figure 10. Results similar to those presented in Figure 10 were obtained from the experiment “Exp1” performed by Stenke et al. (2013, see their Figure 4). In that scenario as well, somewhat less that 1 Tg of BC remained in the atmosphere after the initial rainout. As mentioned before, the BC aerosol that remains in the atmosphere, lifted to stratospheric heights by the rising soot plumes, undergoes sedimentation over a timescale of several years (Figures 8 and 9). This mass represents the effective amount of BC that can force climatic changes over multi-year timescales. In the forced ensemble simulations, it is about 0.8 Tg after the initial rainout, whereas it is about 3.4 Tg in the simulation with an initial soot distribution as in Mills et al. (2014). Our more realistic source simulation involves the worstcase assumption of no-rubble (along with other assumptions) and hence serves as an upper bound for the impact on climate. As mentioned above and further discussed below, our scenario induces perturbations on the climate system similar to those found in previous studies in which the climatic response was driven by roughly 1 Tg of soot rising to stratospheric heights following the exchange. Figure 11 illustrates the vertically integrated mass-mixing ratio of BC over the globe, at various times after the exchange for the simulation using the initial BC distribution of Mills et al. (2014, upper panels) and as an average from the forced ensemble members (lower panels). All simulations predict enhanced concentrations at high latitudes during the first year after the exchange. In the cases shown in the top panels, however, these high concentrations persist for several years (see also Figure 1 of Mills et al., 2014), whereas the forced ensemble simulations indicate that the BC concentration starts to decline after the first year. In fact, in the simulation represented in the top panels, mass-mixing ratios larger than about 1 kg of BC © 2018 American Geophysical Union. All rights reserved. per Tg of air persist for well over 10 years after the exchange, whereas they only last for 3 years in our forced simulations (compare top and middle panels of Figure 9). After the first year, values drop below 3 kg BC/Tg air, whereas it takes about 8 years to reach these values in the simulation in the top panels (see also Robock et al., 2007a). Over crop-producing, midlatitude regions in the Northern Hemisphere, the BC loading is reduced from more than 0.8 kg BC/Tg air in the simulation in the top panels to 0.2-0.4 kg BC/Tg air in our forced simulations (see middle and right panels). The more rapid clearing of the atmosphere in the forced ensemble is also signaled by the soot optical depth in the visible radiation spectrum, which drops below values of 0.03 toward the second half of the first year at mid latitudes in the Northern Hemisphere, and everywhere on the globe after about 2.5 years (without never attaining this value in the Southern Hemisphere). In contrast, the soot optical depth in the calculation shown in the top panels of Figure 11 becomes smaller than 0.03 everywhere only after about 10 years. The two cases show a similar tendency, in that the BC optical depth is typically lower between latitudes 30º S-30º N than it is at other latitudes. This behavior is associated to the persistence of stratospheric soot toward high-latitudes and the Arctic/Antarctic regions, as illustrated by the zonally-averaged, column-integrated mass-mixing ratio of the BC in Figure 12 for both the forced ensemble simulations (left panel) and the simulation with an initial 5 Tg BC emission in the upper troposphere (right panel). The spread in the globally averaged (near) surface temperature of the atmosphere, from the control (left panel) and forced (right panel) ensembles, is displayed in Figure 13. For each month, the plots show the largest variations (i.e., maximum and minimum values), within each ensemble of values obtained for that month, relative to the mean value of that month. The plot also shows yearly-averaged data (thinner lines). The spread is comparable in the control and forced ensembles, with average values calculated over the 33-years run length of 0.4-0.5 K. This spread is also similar to the internal variability of the globally averaged surface temperature quoted for the NCAR Large Ensemble Community Project (Kay et al., 2015). These results imply that surface air temperature differences, between forced and control simulations, which lie within the spread may not be distinguished from effects due to internal variability of the two simulation ensembles. Figure 14 shows the difference in the globally averaged surface temperature of the atmosphere (top panel), net solar radiation flux at surface (middle panel), and precipitation rate (bottom panel), computed as the (forced minus control) difference in ensemble mean values. The sum of standard deviations from each ensemble is shaded. Differences are qualitatively significant over the first few years, when the anomalies lie near or outside the total standard deviation. Inside the shaded region, differences may not be distinguished from those arising from the internal variability of one or both ensembles. The surface solar flux (middle panel) is the quantity that appears most affected by the BC emission, with qualitatively significant differences persisting for about 5 years. The precipitation rate (bottom panel) is instead affected only at the very beginning of the simulations. The red lines in all panels show the results from the simulation applying the initial BC distribution of Mills et al. (2014), where the period of significant impact is much longer owing to the higher altitude of the initial soot distribution that results in longer residence times of the BC aerosol in the atmosphere. When yearly averages of the same quantities are performed over the IndiaPakistan region, the differences in ensemble mean values lie within the total standard deviations of the two ensembles. The results in Figure 14 can also be compared to the outcomes of other previous studies. In their experiment “UT 1 Tg”, Robock et al. (2007a) found that, when only 1 Tg of soot © 2018 American Geophysical Union. All rights reserved. remains in the atmosphere after the initial rainout, temperature and precipitation anomalies are about 20% of those obtained from their standard 5 Tg BC emission case. Therefore, the largest differences they observed, during the first few years after the exchange, were about - 0.3 K and -0.06 mm/day, respectively, comparable to the anomalies in the top and bottom panels of Figure 14. Their standard 5 Tg emission case resulted in a solar radiation flux anomaly at surface of -12 W/m2 after the second year (see their Figure 3), between 5 and 6 time as large as the corresponding anomalies from our ensembles shown in the middle panel. In their experiment “Exp1”, Stenke et al. (2013) reported global mean surface temperature anomalies not exceeding about 0.3 K in magnitude and precipitation anomalies hovering around -0.07 mm/day during the first few years, again consistent with the results of Figure 14. In a recent study, Pausata et al. (2016) considered the effects of an admixture of BC and organic carbon aerosols, both of which would be emitted in the atmosphere in the aftermath of a nuclear exchange. In particular, they concentrated on the effects of coagulation of these aerosol species and examined their climatic impacts. The initial BC distribution was as in Mills et al. (2014), although the soot burden was released in the atmosphere over time periods of various lengths. Most relevant to our and other previous work are their one-day emission scenarios. They found that, during the first year, the largest values of the atmospheric surface temperature anomalies ranged between about -0.5 and -1.3 K, those of the sea surface temperature anomalies ranged between -0.2 and -0.55 K, and those of the precipitation anomalies varied between -0.15 and -0.2 mm/day. All these ranges are compatible with our results shown in Figure 14 as red lines and with those of Mills et al. (2014, see their Figures 3 and 6). As already mentioned in Section 2.3, the net solar flux anomalies at surface are also consistent. This overall agreement suggests that the inclusion of organic carbon aerosols, and ensuing coagulation with BC, should not dramatically alter the climatic effects resulting from our forced ensemble simulations. Moreover, aerosol growth would likely shorten the residence time of the BC particulate in the atmosphere (Pausata et al., 2016), possibly reducing the duration of these effects.
15,823
<h4>Rigorous climate simulations.</h4><p><strong>Reisner et al. 18</strong> [Jon Reisner – Climate and atmospheric scientist at the Los Alamos National Laboratory. Gennaro D’Angelo – Climate scientist at the Los Alamos National Laboratory, Research scientist at the SETI institute, Associate specialist at the University of California, Santa Cruz, NASA Postdoctoral Fellow at the NASA Ames Research Center, UKAFF Fellow at the University of Exeter. Eunmo Koo - Scientist at Applied Terrestrial, Energy, and Atmospheric Modeling (ATEAM) Team, in Computational Earth Science Group (EES-16) in Earth and Environmental Sciences Division and Co-Lead of Parallel Computing Summer Research Internship (PCSRI) program at the Los Alamos National Laboratory, former Staff research associate at UC Berkeley. Wesley Even - Computational scientist in the Computational Physics and Methods Group at Los Alamos National Laboratory. Matthew Hecht – Atmospheric scientist at the Los Alamos National Laboratory. Elizabeth Hunke - Lead developer for the Los Alamos Sea Ice Model (CICE) at the Los Alamos National Laboratory responsible for development and incorporation of new parameterizations, model testing and validation, computational performance, documentation, and consultation with external model users on all aspects of sea ice modeling, including interfacing with global climate and earth system models. Darin Comeau – Climate scientist at the Los Alamos National Laboratory, Randy Bos - Project leader at the Los Alamos National Laboratory, former Weapons Effects program manager at Tech-Source, James Cooley – Computational scientist at the Los Alamos National Laboratory specializing in weapons physics, emergency response, and computational physics, “Climate impact of a regional nuclear weapons exchange:An improved assessment based on detailed source calculations,” March 16, 2018, <u>https://agupubs.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/full/10.1002/2017JD027331<strong>]</p><p></strong>The no-rubble simulation produces </u>a <u>significantly more intense fire</u>, <u>with more </u>fire <u>spread</u>, <u>and </u>consequently <u>a significantly stronger plume with larger amounts of BC reaching into the upper atmosphere</u> than the simulation with rubble, illustrated in Figure 5. <u>While the no-rubble simulation <strong>represents <mark>the worst-case scenario</strong></mark> involving vigorous fire activity</u>, <u><strong><mark>only a relatively small amount of carbon makes its way into the stratosphere</strong></mark> </u>during the course of the simulation. But while small compared to the surface BC mass, stratospheric BC amounts from the current simulations are significantly higher than what would be expected from burning vegetation such as trees (Heilman et al., 2014), e.g., the higher energy density of the building fuels and the initial fluence from the weapon produce an intense response within HIGRAD with initial updrafts of order 100 m/s in the lower troposphere. Or, in comparison to a mass fire, wildfires will burn only a small amount of fuel in the corresponding time period (roughly 10 minutes) that a nuclear weapon fluence can effectively ignite a large area of fuel producing an impressive atmospheric response. Figure 6 shows <u>vertical profiles of BC</u> multiplied by 100 (number of cities involved in the exchange) from the two simulations. The total amount of BC produced is in line with previous estimates (about 3.69 Tg from no-rubble simulation); however, the majority of BC <u>reside</u>s <u><strong>below the stratosphere</u></strong> (3.46 Tg below 12 km) <u>and can be <strong>readily impacted by scavenging from precipitation</strong> either via pyro-cumulonimbus produced by the fire itself</u> (not modeled) <u>or other synoptic weather systems</u>. While the impact on climate of these more realistic profiles will be explored in the next section, it should be mentioned that <u><strong><mark>these estimates are</mark> still <mark>at the high end</strong></mark>, <mark>considering the inherent simplifications</mark> in the combustion model <mark>that lead to <strong>overestimating BC production</strong></mark>. </u>3.3 Climate Results <u>Long-term <mark>climatic effects</mark> critically <mark>depend on</u></mark> <u>the</u> initial injection <u><mark>height</mark> of the soot, with larger quantities reaching the upper troposphere/lower stratosphere inducing a greater cooling impact because of longer residence times</u> (Robock et al., 2007a). Absorption of solar radiation by the BC aerosol and its subsequent radiative cooling tends to heat the surrounding air, driving an initial upward diffusion of the soot plumes, an effect that depends on the initial aerosol concentrations. <u><strong><mark>Mixing and sedimentation</strong></mark> </u>tend to <u><strong><mark>reduce this process</strong>, and low altitude emissions are</mark> </u>also <u><mark>significantly impacted by precipitation</u></mark> if aging of the BC aerosol occurs on sufficiently rapid timescales. But once at stratospheric altitudes, aerosol dilution via coagulation is hindered by low particulate concentrations (e.g., Robock et al., 2007a) and lofting to much higher altitudes is inhibited by gravitational settling in the low-density air (Stenke et al., 2013), resulting in more stable BC concentrations over long times. <u><mark>Of the initial BC</mark> </u>mass <u>released in the atmosphere</u>, most of which is emitted below 9 km, <u><strong><mark>70% rains out within the first month</strong></mark> and 78%</u>, or about 2.9 Tg, <u>is removed within the first two months </u>(Figure 7, solid line), with the remainder (about 0.8 Tg, dashed line) being transported above about 12 km (200 hPa) within the first week. This outcome differs from the findings of, e.g., Stenke et al. (2013, their high BC-load cases) and Mills et al. (2014), who found that most of the BC mass (between 60 and 70%) is lifted in the stratosphere within the first couple of weeks. This can also be seen in Figure 8 (red lines) and in Figure 9, which include results from our calculation with the initial BC distribution from Mills et al. (2014). In that case, only 30% of the initial BC mass rains out in the troposphere during the first two weeks after the exchange, with the remainder rising to the stratosphere. In the study of Mills et al. (2008) this percentage is somewhat smaller, about 20%, and smaller still in the experiments of Robock et al. (2007a) in which the soot is initially emitted in the upper troposphere or higher. In Figure 7, the e-folding timescale for the removal of tropospheric soot, here interpreted as the time required for an initial drop of a factor e, is about one week. This result compares favorably with the “LT” experiment of Robock et al. (2007a), considering 5 Tg of BC released in the lower troposphere, in which 50% of the aerosols are removed within two weeks. By contrast, the initial e-folding timescale for the removal of stratospheric soot in Figure 8 is about 4.2 years (blue solid line), compared to about 8.4 years for the calculation using Mills et al. (2014) initial BC emission (red solid line). The removal timescale from our forced ensemble simulations is close to those obtained by Mills et al. (2008) in their 1 Tg experiment, by Robock et al. (2007a) in their experiment “UT 1 Tg”, and © 2018 American Geophysical Union. All rights reserved. by Stenke et al. (2013) in their experiment “Exp1”, in all of which 1 Tg of soot was emitted in the atmosphere in the aftermath of the exchange. Notably, the e-folding timescale for the decline of the BC mass in Figure 8 (blue solid line) is also close to the value of about 4 years quoted by Pausata et al. (2016) for their long-term “intermediate” scenario. In that scenario, which is also based on 5 Tg of soot initially distributed as in Mills et al. (2014), the factor-of2 shorter residence time of the aerosols is caused by particle growth via coagulation of BC with organic carbon. Figure 9 shows the BC mass-mixing ratio, horizontally averaged over the globe, as a function of atmospheric pressure (height) and time. <u>The BC distributions</u> used <u>in</u> our <u>simulations</u> <u>imply that</u> the <u>upward transport of particles</u> <u>is substantially less efficient compared to the case in</u> <u>which</u> 5 Tg of <u>BC is directly injected into the upper troposphere</u>. The semiannual cycle of lofting and sinking of the aerosols is associated with atmospheric heating and cooling during the solstice in each hemisphere (Robock et al., 2007a). During the first year, the oscillation amplitude in our forced ensemble simulations is particularly large during the summer solstice, compared to that during the winter solstice (see bottom panel of Figure 9), because of the higher soot concentrations in the Northern Hemisphere, as can be seen in Figure 11 (see also left panel of Figure 12). Comparing the top and bottom panels of Figure 9, the BC reaches the highest altitudes during the first year in both cases, but the concentrations at 0.1 hPa in the top panel can be 200 times as large. Qualitatively, <u>the difference can be understood in terms of the air temperature increase caused by BC radiation emission</u>, <u>which is several tens of kelvin degrees in</u> the <u>simulations</u> <u>of Robock</u> et al. (2007a, see their Figure 4), <u>Mills</u> et al. (2008, see their Figure 5), <u>Stenke</u> et al. (2013, see high-load cases in their Figure 4), Mills et al. (2014, see their Figure 7), <u>and Pausata</u> et al. (2016, see one-day emission cases in their Figure 1), <u>due to high BC concentrations, but</u> it <u>amounts to only about 10 K in our</u> forced <u>ensemble simulations</u>, as illustrated in Figure 10. Results similar to those presented in Figure 10 were obtained from the experiment “Exp1” performed by Stenke et al. (2013, see their Figure 4). <u><strong>In that scenario as well, somewhat less that 1 Tg of BC remained in the atmosphere after the initial rainout</strong>. </u>As mentioned before, the BC aerosol that remains in the atmosphere, lifted to stratospheric heights by the rising soot plumes, undergoes sedimentation over a timescale of several years (Figures 8 and 9). This mass represents the effective amount of BC that can force climatic changes over multi-year timescales. In the forced ensemble simulations, it is about 0.8 Tg after the initial rainout, whereas it is about 3.4 Tg in the simulation with an initial soot distribution as in Mills et al. (2014). Our more realistic source simulation involves the worstcase assumption of no-rubble (along with other assumptions) and hence serves as an upper bound for the impact on climate. As mentioned above and further discussed below, our scenario induces perturbations on the climate system similar to those found in previous studies in which the climatic response was driven by roughly 1 Tg of soot rising to stratospheric heights following the exchange. Figure 11 illustrates the vertically integrated mass-mixing ratio of BC over the globe, at various times after the exchange for the simulation using the initial BC distribution of Mills et al. (2014, upper panels) and as an average from the forced ensemble members (lower panels). All simulations predict enhanced concentrations at high latitudes during the first year after the exchange. In the cases shown in the top panels, however, these high concentrations persist for several years (see also Figure 1 of Mills et al., 2014), whereas the forced ensemble simulations indicate that the BC concentration starts to decline after the first year. In fact, in the simulation represented in the top panels, mass-mixing ratios larger than about 1 kg of BC © 2018 American Geophysical Union. All rights reserved. per Tg of air persist for well over 10 years after the exchange, whereas they only last for 3 years in our forced simulations (compare top and middle panels of Figure 9). After the first year, values drop below 3 kg BC/Tg air, whereas it takes about 8 years to reach these values in the simulation in the top panels (see also Robock et al., 2007a). Over crop-producing, midlatitude regions in the Northern Hemisphere, the BC loading is reduced from more than 0.8 kg BC/Tg air in the simulation in the top panels to 0.2-0.4 kg BC/Tg air in our forced simulations (see middle and right panels). The more rapid clearing of the atmosphere in the forced ensemble is also signaled by the soot optical depth in the visible radiation spectrum, which drops below values of 0.03 toward the second half of the first year at mid latitudes in the Northern Hemisphere, and everywhere on the globe after about 2.5 years (without never attaining this value in the Southern Hemisphere). In contrast, the soot optical depth in the calculation shown in the top panels of Figure 11 becomes smaller than 0.03 everywhere only after about 10 years. The two cases show a similar tendency, in that the BC optical depth is typically lower between latitudes 30º S-30º N than it is at other latitudes. This behavior is associated to the persistence of stratospheric soot toward high-latitudes and the Arctic/Antarctic regions, as illustrated by the zonally-averaged, column-integrated mass-mixing ratio of the BC in Figure 12 for both the forced ensemble simulations (left panel) and the simulation with an initial 5 Tg BC emission in the upper troposphere (right panel). The spread in the globally averaged (near) surface temperature of the atmosphere, from the control (left panel) and forced (right panel) ensembles, is displayed in Figure 13. For each month, the plots show the largest variations (i.e., maximum and minimum values), within each ensemble of values obtained for that month, relative to the mean value of that month. The plot also shows yearly-averaged data (thinner lines). The spread is comparable in the control and forced ensembles, with average values calculated over the 33-years run length of 0.4-0.5 K. This spread is also similar to the internal variability of the globally averaged surface temperature quoted for the NCAR Large Ensemble Community Project (Kay et al., 2015). These results imply that surface air temperature differences, between forced and control simulations, which lie within the spread may not be distinguished from effects due to internal variability of the two simulation ensembles. Figure 14 shows the difference in the globally averaged surface temperature of the atmosphere (top panel), net solar radiation flux at surface (middle panel), and precipitation rate (bottom panel), computed as the (forced minus control) difference in ensemble mean values. The sum of standard deviations from each ensemble is shaded. Differences are qualitatively significant over the first few years, when the anomalies lie near or outside the total standard deviation. Inside the shaded region, differences may not be distinguished from those arising from the internal variability of one or both ensembles. The surface solar flux (middle panel) is the quantity that appears most affected by the BC emission, with qualitatively significant differences persisting for about 5 years. The precipitation rate (bottom panel) is instead affected only at the very beginning of the simulations. The red lines in all panels show the results from the simulation applying the initial BC distribution of Mills et al. (2014), where the period of significant impact is much longer owing to the higher altitude of the initial soot distribution that results in longer residence times of the BC aerosol in the atmosphere. When yearly averages of the same quantities are performed over the IndiaPakistan region, the differences in ensemble mean values lie within the total standard deviations of the two ensembles. The results in Figure 14 can also be compared to the outcomes of other previous studies. In their experiment “UT 1 Tg”, Robock et al. (2007a) found that, when only 1 Tg of soot © 2018 American Geophysical Union. All rights reserved. remains in the atmosphere after the initial rainout, temperature and precipitation anomalies are about 20% of those obtained from their standard 5 Tg BC emission case. Therefore, the largest differences they observed, during the first few years after the exchange, were about - 0.3 K and -0.06 mm/day, respectively, comparable to the anomalies in the top and bottom panels of Figure 14. Their standard 5 Tg emission case resulted in a solar radiation flux anomaly at surface of -12 W/m2 after the second year (see their Figure 3), between 5 and 6 time as large as the corresponding anomalies from our ensembles shown in the middle panel. In their experiment “Exp1”, Stenke et al. (2013) reported global mean surface temperature anomalies not exceeding about 0.3 K in magnitude and precipitation anomalies hovering around -0.07 mm/day during the first few years, again consistent with the results of Figure 14. In a recent study, Pausata et al. (2016) considered the effects of an admixture of BC and organic carbon aerosols, both of which would be emitted in the atmosphere in the aftermath of a nuclear exchange. In particular, they concentrated on the effects of coagulation of these aerosol species and examined their climatic impacts. The initial BC distribution was as in Mills et al. (2014), although the soot burden was released in the atmosphere over time periods of various lengths. Most relevant to our and other previous work are their one-day emission scenarios. They found that, during the first year, the largest values of the atmospheric surface temperature anomalies ranged between about -0.5 and -1.3 K, those of the sea surface temperature anomalies ranged between -0.2 and -0.55 K, and those of the precipitation anomalies varied between -0.15 and -0.2 mm/day. All these ranges are compatible with our results shown in Figure 14 as red lines and with those of Mills et al. (2014, see their Figures 3 and 6). As already mentioned in Section 2.3, the net solar flux anomalies at surface are also consistent. <u>This</u> overall agreement <u>suggests that <mark>the <strong>inclusion of organic carbon aerosols</mark>, and</strong> ensuing <strong>coagulation</strong> with BC, <strong><mark>should not dramatically alter the climatic effects</strong></mark> resulting from our forced ensemble simulations. Moreover, <mark>aerosol growth</mark> would likely <strong><mark>shorten the residence time of the BC</mark> particulate in the atmosphere</u></strong> (Pausata et al., 2016), possibly <u><strong>reducing the duration of these effects.</p></u></strong>
2NC
Case
Precision---
10,501
595
161,007
./documents/hspolicy22/WalterPayton/SaWa/WalterPayton-SaWa-Neg-State-Round-3.docx
990,310
N
State
3
Niles North MK
Stephen Pipkin, Jonathan Horowitz
1AC - Maritime Cyber 2NR - Russia War Good
hspolicy22/WalterPayton/SaWa/WalterPayton-SaWa-Neg-State-Round-3.docx
2023-03-21 18:42:30
79,310
SaWa
Walter Payton SaWa
2a: Hank Sanchez (he/they) hanktsanchez@gmail.com 2n: Zoey Walsh (she/her) zwalsh2005@gmail.com sweetnessdebatedocs@gmail.com tornato@googlegroups.com
Ha.....
Sa.....
Zo.....
Wa.....
26,557
WalterPayton
Walter Payton
IL
null
2,002
hspolicy22
HS Policy 2022-23
2,022
cx
hs
2
4,578,192
Populism is slowing. The pandemic iced anti-immigration sentiments due to the lack of global movement.
Robinson, 4-2
Robinson, 4-2-2022 (Tom Robinson, Reporting on conferences for ECPS, "Symposium Report—The Future Course Of Populism In The Post-Pandemic Era: The State Of Globalization, Multilateral Governance, And Democracy," ECPS, https://www.populismstudies.org/symposium-report-the-future-course-of-populism-in-the-post-pandemic-era-the-state-of-globalization-multilateral-governance-and-democracy%ef%bf%bc/, accessed on 12-16-2022) AB
the claim that “the pandemic would bring an end to populism […] is too strong to be held, and it is too early to reach meaningful conclusions” with the pandemic still ongoing in many countries. While early evidence suggested that populists had lost popularity as a result of their own mismanagement of the crisis when compared to non-populists it would be premature to draw long-term conclusions from these short-term trends. the pandemic was new for all global political actors, not just populists. While the link between the emergence of crises and the resonance of populist discourse is well-documented, data from the early months of the pandemic showed a noticeable decline in popularity of populists in power, as scientific denialism and early mismanagement undermined the legitimacy of many populist governments in the West and elsewhere. Overall Burni diagnosed a clear difficulty among populists to capitalize on the Covid-19 crisis: next to the inherent difficulties of mobilizing against a health crisis most governments experienced a drastic ‘rally around the flag effect,’ Staples of populist discourse, like anti-immigration stances faded into the background as many nations shut their borders to prevent the spread of the virus. All these factors , made for a potent anti-populist surge worldwide.
While populists lost popularity as a result of their mismanagement of the crisis it would be premature to draw long-term conclusions the pandemic was new for global political actors data from the pandemic showed a decline in popularity of populists in power scientific denialism and mismanagement undermined legitimacy of populist governments populist anti-immigration stances faded into the background as many nations shut their borders these factors made for a potent anti-populist surge worldwide
In response to more hopeful commentators, Dr. Burni stated from the outset that she believed the claim that “the pandemic would bring an end to populism […] is too strong to be held, and it is too early to reach meaningful conclusions” with the pandemic still ongoing in many countries. She noted that the impact of Covid-19 on populist movements differed substantially from region to region and depending on whether the movement was in government or in opposition. While early evidence suggested that populists had lost popularity as a result of their own mismanagement of the crisis when compared to non-populists, for example, those initial studies focus on populists mainly in Europe and predominantly during the first wave of the pandemic; it would be premature, she argued, to draw long-term conclusions from these short-term trends. According to Dr. Burni, the pandemic was, in many ways, new territory for all global political actors, not just populists. While the link between the emergence of crises and the resonance of populist discourse is well-documented, data from the early months of the pandemic showed a noticeable decline in popularity of populists in power, as scientific denialism and early mismanagement undermined the legitimacy of many populist governments in the West and elsewhere. While populists in opposition also struggled, their popularity stabilized rather quickly. Overall, however, Dr. Burni diagnosed a clear difficulty among populists to capitalize on the Covid-19 crisis: next to the inherent difficulties of mobilizing against a health crisis, she argued that citizens valued, above all, expertise and decisive leadership throughout the pandemic, and that most governments experienced a drastic ‘rally around the flag effect,’ particularly in the early months. Staples of populist discourse, like anti-immigration stances, also quickly faded into the background as many nations shut their borders to prevent the spread of the virus. All these factors, combined with obvious showcases of populist mismanagement in the United States (US), United Kingdom (UK), or Brazil, made for a potent anti-populist surge in many democracies worldwide.
2,175
<h4>Populism is <u>slowing</u>. The pandemic <u>iced</u> anti-immigration sentiments due to the lack of global movement.</h4><p><strong>Robinson, 4-2<u></strong>-2022 (Tom Robinson, Reporting on conferences for ECPS, "Symposium Report—The Future Course Of Populism In The Post-Pandemic Era: The State Of Globalization, Multilateral Governance, And Democracy," ECPS, https://www.populismstudies.org/symposium-report-the-future-course-of-populism-in-the-post-pandemic-era-the-state-of-globalization-multilateral-governance-and-democracy%ef%bf%bc/, accessed on 12-16-2022) AB</p><p></u>In response to more hopeful commentators, Dr. Burni stated from the outset that she believed<u> the claim that “the pandemic would bring an end to populism […] is too strong to be held, and it is too early to reach meaningful conclusions” with the pandemic still ongoing in many countries. </u>She noted that the impact of Covid-19 on populist movements differed substantially from region to region and depending on whether the movement was in government or in opposition. <u><mark>While </mark>early evidence suggested that <mark>populists</mark> had <mark>lost popularity as a result of their</mark> own <mark>mismanagement of the crisis</mark> when compared to non-populists</u>, for example, those initial studies focus on populists mainly in Europe and predominantly during the first wave of the pandemic; <u><mark>it would be premature</u></mark>, she argued, <u><mark>to draw long-term conclusions</mark> from these short-term trends. </p><p></u>According to Dr. Burni,<u> <mark>the pandemic was</u></mark>, in many ways, <u><mark>new</u></mark> territory <u><mark>for</mark> all <mark>global political actors</mark>, not just populists. While the link between the emergence of crises and the resonance of populist discourse is well-documented, <mark>data from</mark> the early months of <mark>the pandemic showed a</mark> noticeable <strong><mark>decline in popularity of populists in power</strong></mark>, as <mark>scientific denialism and</mark> early <mark>mismanagement <strong>undermined</strong> </mark>the <strong><mark>legitimacy</strong> of</mark> many <mark>populist governments</mark> in the West and elsewhere. </u>While populists in opposition also struggled, their popularity stabilized rather quickly. <u>Overall</u>, however, Dr.<u> Burni diagnosed a clear difficulty among populists to capitalize on the Covid-19 crisis: next to the inherent difficulties of mobilizing against a health crisis</u>, she argued that citizens valued, above all, expertise and decisive leadership throughout the pandemic, and that <u>most governments experienced a drastic ‘rally around the flag effect,’<strong> </u></strong>particularly in the early months. <u>Staples of <strong><mark>populist </strong></mark>discourse<strong>, </strong>like<strong> <mark>anti-immigration stances</u></strong></mark>, also quickly <u><strong><mark>faded into the background as many nations shut their borders</mark> to prevent the spread of the virus. </strong>All <mark>these factors</u></mark>, combined with obvious showcases of populist mismanagement in the United States (US), United Kingdom (UK), or Brazil<u>, <mark>made for a potent anti-populist surge</u></mark> in many democracies <u><strong><mark>worldwide</strong></mark>.</u> </p>
null
1NC—Off
2
1,698,884
383
151,945
./documents/hsld22/Peninsula/AaYi/Peninsula-AaYi-Neg-Arizona-State-HDSHC-Invitational-Round-6.docx
961,342
N
Arizona State HDSHC Invitational
6
Palo Alto HL
Huggins
1AC- Climate refugees, econ 1NC- southeast asia pic, populism DA 2NR- pic, econ turns
hsld22/Peninsula/AaYi/Peninsula-AaYi-Neg-Arizona-State-HDSHC-Invitational-Round-6.docx
2023-01-08 15:07:17
79,894
AaYi
Peninsula AaYi
null
Aa.....
Yi.....
null
null
26,744
Peninsula
Peninsula
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
2,277,031
“A” is an indefinite article that modifies “democracy” in the rez – only whole rez is T
CCC , Capital Community College Foundation, a nonprofit 501 c-3 organization that supports scholarships, faculty development, and curriculum innovation) LHSLA JC/SJ
CCC (“Articles, Determiners, and Quantifiers”, http://grammar.ccc.commnet.edu/grammar/determiners/determiners.htm#articles, Capital Community College Foundation, a nonprofit 501 c-3 organization that supports scholarships, faculty development, and curriculum innovation) LHSLA JC/SJ
The article a are a adjective a and an are indefinite articles they are used to refer to something in a less specific manner We refer to something in a generic way by using any of the articles A beagle makes a great hunting dog The indefinite pronoun refers to all members of that class
The article a, are indefinite articles they are used to refer to something in a less specific manne A beagle makes a great hunting dog The indefinite pronoun refers to all members of that class
The three articles — a, an, the — are a kind of adjective. The is called the definite article because it usually precedes a specific or previously mentioned noun; a and an are called indefinite articles because they are used to refer to something in a less specific manner (an unspecified count noun). These words are also listed among the noun markers or determiners because they are almost invariably followed by a noun (or something else acting as a noun). caution CAUTION! Even after you learn all the principles behind the use of these articles, you will find an abundance of situations where choosing the correct article or choosing whether to use one or not will prove chancy. Icy highways are dangerous. The icy highways are dangerous. And both are correct. The is used with specific nouns. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something that is one of a kind: The moon circles the earth. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something in the abstract: The United States has encouraged the use of the private automobile as opposed to the use of public transit. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something named earlier in the text. (See below..) If you would like help with the distinction between count and non-count nouns, please refer to Count and Non-Count Nouns. We use a before singular count-nouns that begin with consonants (a cow, a barn, a sheep); we use an before singular count-nouns that begin with vowels or vowel-like sounds (an apple, an urban blight, an open door). Words that begin with an h sound often require an a (as in a horse, a history book, a hotel), but if an h-word begins with an actual vowel sound, use an an (as in an hour, an honor). We would say a useful device and a union matter because the u of those words actually sounds like yoo (as opposed, say, to the u of an ugly incident). The same is true of a European and a Euro (because of that consonantal "Yoo" sound). We would say a once-in-a-lifetime experience or a one-time hero because the words once and one begin with a w sound (as if they were spelled wuntz and won). Merriam-Webster's Dictionary says that we can use an before an h- word that begins with an unstressed syllable. Thus, we might say an hisTORical moment, but we would say a HIStory book. Many writers would call that an affectation and prefer that we say a historical, but apparently, this choice is a matter of personal taste. For help on using articles with abbreviations and acronyms (a or an FBI agent?), see the section on Abbreviations. First and subsequent reference: When we first refer to something in written text, we often use an indefinite article to modify it. A newspaper has an obligation to seek out and tell the truth. In a subsequent reference to this newspaper, however, we will use the definite article: There are situations, however, when the newspaper must determine whether the public's safety is jeopardized by knowing the truth. Another example: "I'd like a glass of orange juice, please," John said. "I put the glass of juice on the counter already," Sheila replied. Exception: When a modifier appears between the article and the noun, the subsequent article will continue to be indefinite: "I'd like a big glass of orange juice, please," John said. "I put a big glass of juice on the counter already," Sheila replied. Generic reference: We can refer to something in a generic way by using any of the three articles. We can do the same thing by omitting the article altogether. A beagle makes a great hunting dog and family companion. An airedale is sometimes a rather skittish animal. The golden retriever is a marvelous pet for children. Irish setters are not the highly intelligent animals they used to be. The difference between the generic indefinite pronoun and the normal indefinite pronoun is that the latter refers to any of that class ("I want to buy a beagle, and any old beagle will do.") whereas the former (see beagle sentence) refers to all members of that class
4,022
<h4>“A” is an indefinite article that modifies “democracy” in the rez – only whole rez is T</h4><p><strong>CCC</strong> (“Articles, Determiners, and Quantifiers”, http://grammar.ccc.commnet.edu/grammar/determiners/determiners.htm#articles<u><strong>, Capital Community College Foundation, a nonprofit 501 c-3 organization that supports scholarships, faculty development, and curriculum innovation) LHSLA JC/SJ</p><p></strong><mark>The</u></mark> three <u><mark>article</u></mark>s — <u><mark>a</u>,</mark> an, the — <u><mark>are</mark> a</u> kind of <u>adjective</u>. The is called the definite article because it usually precedes a specific or previously mentioned noun; <u>a and an are</u> called <u><mark>indefinite articles</u></mark> because <u><mark>they are used to refer to something in a less specific manne</mark>r</u> (an unspecified count noun). These words are also listed among the noun markers or determiners because they are almost invariably followed by a noun (or something else acting as a noun). caution CAUTION! Even after you learn all the principles behind the use of these articles, you will find an abundance of situations where choosing the correct article or choosing whether to use one or not will prove chancy. Icy highways are dangerous. The icy highways are dangerous. And both are correct. The is used with specific nouns. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something that is one of a kind: The moon circles the earth. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something in the abstract: The United States has encouraged the use of the private automobile as opposed to the use of public transit. The is required when the noun it refers to represents something named earlier in the text. (See below..) If you would like help with the distinction between count and non-count nouns, please refer to Count and Non-Count Nouns. We use a before singular count-nouns that begin with consonants (a cow, a barn, a sheep); we use an before singular count-nouns that begin with vowels or vowel-like sounds (an apple, an urban blight, an open door). Words that begin with an h sound often require an a (as in a horse, a history book, a hotel), but if an h-word begins with an actual vowel sound, use an an (as in an hour, an honor). We would say a useful device and a union matter because the u of those words actually sounds like yoo (as opposed, say, to the u of an ugly incident). The same is true of a European and a Euro (because of that consonantal "Yoo" sound). We would say a once-in-a-lifetime experience or a one-time hero because the words once and one begin with a w sound (as if they were spelled wuntz and won). Merriam-Webster's Dictionary says that we can use an before an h- word that begins with an unstressed syllable. Thus, we might say an hisTORical moment, but we would say a HIStory book. Many writers would call that an affectation and prefer that we say a historical, but apparently, this choice is a matter of personal taste. For help on using articles with abbreviations and acronyms (a or an FBI agent?), see the section on Abbreviations. First and subsequent reference: When we first refer to something in written text, we often use an indefinite article to modify it. A newspaper has an obligation to seek out and tell the truth. In a subsequent reference to this newspaper, however, we will use the definite article: There are situations, however, when the newspaper must determine whether the public's safety is jeopardized by knowing the truth. Another example: "I'd like a glass of orange juice, please," John said. "I put the glass of juice on the counter already," Sheila replied. Exception: When a modifier appears between the article and the noun, the subsequent article will continue to be indefinite: "I'd like a big glass of orange juice, please," John said. "I put a big glass of juice on the counter already," Sheila replied. Generic reference: <u>We</u> can <u>refer to something in a generic way</u> <u>by</u> <u>using any of the</u> three <u>articles</u>. We can do the same thing by omitting the article altogether. <u><strong><mark>A beagle</strong> makes a great hunting dog</u></mark> and family companion. An airedale is sometimes a rather skittish animal. The golden retriever is a marvelous pet for children. Irish setters are not the highly intelligent animals they used to be. <u><mark>The</u></mark> difference between the generic indefinite pronoun and the normal <u><mark>indefinite pronoun</u></mark> is that the latter refers to any of that class ("I want to buy a beagle, and any old beagle will do.") whereas the former (see beagle sentence) <u><strong><mark>refers to all members of that class</p></u></strong></mark>
null
OFF
T – Single Country
327,722
698
71,345
./documents/hsld20/Marlborough/Re/Marlborough-Renwick-Neg-Peninsula-Round4.docx
867,600
N
Peninsula
4
Harvard-Westlake SL
Kuffour, Julian
AC India (Vote Banking QUAD) NC T Whole Res Resignation CP Case Turns (check open-source for case turns) 1AR Vote Banking QUAD NR Resignation CP CAA Case Turn
hsld20/Marlborough/Re/Marlborough-Renwick-Neg-Peninsula-Round4.docx
null
73,434
WyRe
Marlborough WyRe
null
Wy.....
Re.....
null
null
24,612
Marlborough
Marlborough
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
3,292,948
Pleasure and pain are intrinsically valuable. People consistently regard pleasure and pain as good reasons for action. Moreover, only pleasure and pain are intrinsically valuable. All other values can be explained with reference to pleasure.
Moen 16
Moen 16 [Ole Martin Moen, Research Fellow in Philosophy at University of Oslo “An Argument for Hedonism” Journal of Value Inquiry (Springer), 50 (2) 2016: 267–281]
there is something undeniably good about pleasure and undeniably bad about pain I might ask: “What for?” But pleasure is not good for anything further; “We never ask what end is in being pleased, because pleasure is worthy in itself.” pleasure and pain are both places where we reach the end of the line in matters of value.
there is something undeniably good about pleasure and undeniably bad about pain I might ask: “What for?” But pleasure is not good for anything further; “We never ask what end is in being pleased, because pleasure is worthy in itself. pleasure and pain are both places where we reach the end of the line in matters of value.
Let us start by observing, empirically, that a widely shared judgment about intrinsic value and disvalue is that pleasure is intrinsically valuable and pain is intrinsically disvaluable. On virtually any proposed list of intrinsic values and disvalues (we will look at some of them below), pleasure is included among the intrinsic values and pain among the intrinsic disvalues. This inclusion makes intuitive sense, moreover, for there is something undeniably good about the way pleasure feels and something undeniably bad about the way pain feels, and neither the goodness of pleasure nor the badness of pain seems to be exhausted by the further effects that these experiences might have. “Pleasure” and “pain” are here understood inclusively, as encompassing anything hedonically positive and anything hedonically negative.2 The special value statuses of pleasure and pain are manifested in how we treat these experiences in our everyday reasoning about values. If you tell me that you are heading for the convenience store, I might ask: “What for?” This is a reasonable question, for when you go to the convenience store you usually do so, not merely for the sake of going to the convenience store, but for the sake of achieving something further that you deem to be valuable. You might answer, for example: “To buy soda.” This answer makes sense, for soda is a nice thing and you can get it at the convenience store. I might further inquire, however: “What is buying the soda good for?” This further question can also be a reasonable one, for it need not be obvious why you want the soda. You might answer: “Well, I want it for the pleasure of drinking it.” If I then proceed by asking “But what is the pleasure of drinking the soda good for?” the discussion is likely to reach an awkward end. The reason is that the pleasure is not good for anything further; it is simply that for which going to the convenience store and buying the soda is good.3 As Aristotle observes: “We never ask [a man] what his end is in being pleased, because we assume that pleasure is choice worthy in itself.”4 Presumably, a similar story can be told in the case of pains, for if someone says “This is painful!” we never respond by asking: “And why is that a problem?” We take for granted that if something is painful, we have a sufficient explanation of why it is bad. If we are onto something in our everyday reasoning about values, it seems that pleasure and pain are both places where we reach the end of the line in matters of value.
2,521
<h4>Pleasure and pain are intrinsically valuable. People consistently regard pleasure and pain as good reasons for action. Moreover, only pleasure and pain are intrinsically valuable. All other values can be explained with reference to pleasure.</h4><p><strong>Moen 16</strong> [Ole Martin Moen, Research Fellow in Philosophy at University of Oslo “An Argument for Hedonism” Journal of Value Inquiry (Springer), 50 (2) 2016: 267–281] </p><p>Let us start by observing, empirically, that a widely shared judgment about intrinsic value and disvalue is that pleasure is intrinsically valuable and pain is intrinsically disvaluable. On virtually any proposed list of intrinsic values and disvalues (we will look at some of them below), pleasure is included among the intrinsic values and pain among the intrinsic disvalues. This inclusion makes intuitive sense, moreover, for <u><strong><mark>there is something undeniably good about</u></strong></mark> the way <u><strong><mark>pleasure </u></strong></mark>feels <u><strong><mark>and </u></strong></mark>something<u><strong> <mark>undeniably bad about</u></strong></mark> the way <u><strong><mark>pain </u></strong></mark>feels, and neither the goodness of pleasure nor the badness of pain seems to be exhausted by the further effects that these experiences might have. “Pleasure” and “pain” are here understood inclusively, as encompassing anything hedonically positive and anything hedonically negative.2 The special value statuses of pleasure and pain are manifested in how we treat these experiences in our everyday reasoning about values. If you tell me that you are heading for the convenience store, <u><strong><mark>I might ask: “What for?” </u></strong></mark>This is a reasonable question, for when you go to the convenience store you usually do so, not merely for the sake of going to the convenience store, but for the sake of achieving something further that you deem to be valuable. You might answer, for example: “To buy soda.” This answer makes sense, for soda is a nice thing and you can get it at the convenience store. I might further inquire, however: “What is buying the soda good for?” This further question can also be a reasonable one, for it need not be obvious why you want the soda. You might answer: “Well, I want it for the pleasure of drinking it.” If I then proceed by asking “<u><strong><mark>But </u></strong></mark>what is the pleasure of drinking the soda good for?” the discussion is likely to reach an awkward end. The reason is that the <u><strong><mark>pleasure is not good for anything further;</mark> </u></strong>it is simply that for which going to the convenience store and buying the soda is good.3 As Aristotle observes: <u><strong><mark>“We never ask</u></strong> </mark>[a man] <u><strong><mark>what </u></strong></mark>his<u><strong><mark> end is in being pleased, because </u></strong></mark>we assume that <u><strong><mark>pleasure is </u></strong></mark>choice <u><strong><mark>worthy in itself.</mark>”</u></strong>4 Presumably, a similar story can be told in the case of pains, for if someone says “This is painful!” we never respond by asking: “And why is that a problem?” We take for granted that if something is painful, we have a sufficient explanation of why it is bad. If we are onto something in our everyday reasoning about values, it seems that <u><strong><mark>pleasure and pain are both places where we reach the end of the line in matters of value.</u></strong></mark> </p>
null
Util
null
21,420
4,449
107,854
./documents/hsld18/Cypress-Ranch/Zh/Cypress-Ranch-Zhou-Aff-TFA%20State-Round3.docx
818,534
A
TFA State
3
Kinkaid sm
Neville Tom
1nc - biopolitics K 1ar - must spec alt status case and K 2nr - all 2ar - bryant 12 babyyyy
hsld18/Cypress-Ranch/Zh/Cypress-Ranch-Zhou-Aff-TFA%20State-Round3.docx
null
70,099
MiZh
Cypress-Ranch MiZh
null
Mi.....
Zh.....
null
null
23,703
Cypress-Ranch
Cypress-Ranch
null
null
1,026
hsld18
HS LD 2018-19
2,018
ld
hs
1
1,030,497
Capitalism causes war, violence, environmental destruction and extinction
Robinson 14
Robinson 14 (William I., Prof. of Sociology, Global and International Studies, and Latin American Studies, @ UC-Santa Barbara, “Global Capitalism: Crisis of Humanity and the Specter of 21st Century Fascism” The World Financial Review)
the causal origins of global crisis are to be found in over-accumulation and in contradictions of state power because the system is now global, crisis in any one place tends to represent crisis for the system as a whole. given the particular configuration of social and class forces and the correlation of these forces worldwide, national states are hard-pressed to regulate transnational circuits of accumulation and offset explosive contradictions Cyclical crises are recurrent to capitalism about once every 10 years and involve recessions that act as self-correcting mechanisms A systemic crisis involves the replacement of a system by an entirely new system or by an outright collapse. A structural crisis opens up the possibility for a systemic crisis. This is an historic moment of extreme uncertainty, in which collective responses from distinct social and class forces to the crisis are in great flux. ¶ There are multiple and mutually constitutive dimensions – economic, social, political, cultural, ideological and ecological, not to mention the existential crisis of our consciousness The system cannot meet the needs of millions of people The legitimacy of the system has increasingly been called into question by millions perhaps billions and is facing expanded counter-hegemonic challenges. And a canopy that envelops all these dimensions is a crisis of sustainability rooted in climate change and the impending collapse of centralised agricultural systems a crisis of humanity threatening the ability of billions of people to survive, and raising the specter of a collapse of world civilisation The system is fast reaching the ecological limits of its reproduction. Global capitalism now couples human and natural history in such a way as to threaten to bring about what would be the sixth mass extinction there are nine “planetary boundaries” crucial to maintaining an earth system environment in which humans can exist, four of which are experiencing the onset of irreversible environmental degradation and three of which are at “tipping points The magnitude of the means of violence and control is unprecedented, as is the concentration of the means of global communication and symbolic production Computerised wars, drones, bunker-buster bombs, star wars have changed the face of warfare. Warfare has become normalised and sanitised for those not directly at the receiving end of armed aggression. Capitalism is reaching apparent limits to its extensive expansion. There are no longer any new territories of significance that can be integrated into world capitalism, de-ruralisation is now well advanced, and the commodification of the countryside and of pre- and non-capitalist spaces has intensified Capitalism must continually expand or collapse. There is the rise of a vast surplus population inhabiting a “planet of slums,” alienated from the productive economy, thrown into the margins, and subject to sophisticated systems of social control and to destruction - to a mortal cycle of dispossession-exploitation-exclusion. This includes prison-industrial and immigrant-detention complexes, omnipresent policing, militarised gentrification There is a disjuncture between a globalising economy and a nation-state based system of political authority. Transnational state apparatuses have not been able to play the role of hegemon The spread of weapons of mass destruction and the unprecedented militarisation of social life and conflict across the globe makes it hard to imagine that the system can come under any stable political authority that assures its reproduction. The ultra-right is an insurgent force in many countries. this project seeks to fuse reactionary political power with transnational capital and to organise a mass base among historically privileged sectors of the global working class such as white workers that are now experiencing heightened insecurity and the specter of downward mobility. It involves militarism, extreme masculinisation, homophobia, racism and racist mobilisations, including the search for scapegoats, such as immigrant workers and Muslims. Twenty-first century fascism evokes mystifying ideologies, often involving race/culture supremacy and xenophobia, embracing an idealised and mythical past. Neo-fascist culture normalises and glamorises warfare and social violence, indeed, generates a fascination with domination that is portrayed even as heroic.
the origins of global crisis are found in over-accumulation and contradictions of state power crisis in one place represent crisis for the system a canopy that envelops all these dimensions is climate change and the impending collapse of centralised agricultur threatening the ability of billions to survive The system is fast reaching ecological limits of its reproduction The magnitude of violence is unprecedented Computerised wars, drones surplus population alienated from the productive economy and subject to control and destruction prison-industrial complexes, omnipresent policing, militarised gentrification The spread of w m The ultra-right is insurgent It involves masculinisation, homophobia, racism and racist mobilisations Twenty-first century fascism normalises and glamorises warfare and social violence
Cyclical, Structural, and Systemic Crises ¶ Most commentators on the contemporary crisis refer to the “Great Recession” of 2008 and its aftermath. Yet the causal origins of global crisis are to be found in over-accumulation and also in contradictions of state power, or in what Marxists call the internal contradictions of the capitalist system. Moreover, because the system is now global, crisis in any one place tends to represent crisis for the system as a whole. The system cannot expand because the marginalisation of a significant portion of humanity from direct productive participation, the downward pressure on wages and popular consumption worldwide, and the polarisation of income, has reduced the ability of the world market to absorb world output. At the same time, given the particular configuration of social and class forces and the correlation of these forces worldwide, national states are hard-pressed to regulate transnational circuits of accumulation and offset the explosive contradictions built into the system. ¶ Is this crisis cyclical, structural, or systemic? Cyclical crises are recurrent to capitalism about once every 10 years and involve recessions that act as self-correcting mechanisms without any major restructuring of the system. The recessions of the early 1980s, the early 1990s, and of 2001 were cyclical crises. In contrast, the 2008 crisis signaled the slide into a structural crisis. Structural crises reflect deeper contra- dictions that can only be resolved by a major restructuring of the system. The structural crisis of the 1970s was resolved through capitalist globalisation. Prior to that, the structural crisis of the 1930s was resolved through the creation of a new model of redistributive capitalism, and prior to that the struc- tural crisis of the 1870s resulted in the development of corpo- rate capitalism. A systemic crisis involves the replacement of a system by an entirely new system or by an outright collapse. A structural crisis opens up the possibility for a systemic crisis. But if it actually snowballs into a systemic crisis – in this case, if it gives way either to capitalism being superseded or to a breakdown of global civilisation – is not predetermined and depends entirely on the response of social and political forces to the crisis and on historical contingencies that are not easy to forecast. This is an historic moment of extreme uncertainty, in which collective responses from distinct social and class forces to the crisis are in great flux. ¶ Hence my concept of global crisis is broader than financial. There are multiple and mutually constitutive dimensions – economic, social, political, cultural, ideological and ecological, not to mention the existential crisis of our consciousness, values and very being. There is a crisis of social polarisation, that is, of social reproduction. The system cannot meet the needs or assure the survival of millions of people, perhaps a majority of humanity. There are crises of state legitimacy and political authority, or of hegemony and domination. National states face spiraling crises of legitimacy as they fail to meet the social grievances of local working and popular classes experiencing downward mobility, unemployment, heightened insecurity and greater hardships. The legitimacy of the system has increasingly been called into question by millions, perhaps even billions, of people around the world, and is facing expanded counter-hegemonic challenges. Global elites have been unable counter this erosion of the system’s authority in the face of worldwide pressures for a global moral economy. And a canopy that envelops all these dimensions is a crisis of sustainability rooted in an ecological holocaust that has already begun, expressed in climate change and the impending collapse of centralised agricultural systems in several regions of the world, among other indicators. By a crisis of humanity I mean a crisis that is approaching systemic proportions, threatening the ability of billions of people to survive, and raising the specter of a collapse of world civilisation and degeneration into a new “Dark Ages.”2 ¶ This crisis of humanity shares a number of aspects with earlier structural crises but there are also several features unique to the present: ¶ 1. The system is fast reaching the ecological limits of its reproduction. Global capitalism now couples human and natural history in such a way as to threaten to bring about what would be the sixth mass extinction in the known history of life on earth.3 This mass extinction would be caused not by a natural catastrophe such as a meteor impact or by evolutionary changes such as the end of an ice age but by purposive human activity. According to leading environmental scientists there are nine “planetary boundaries” crucial to maintaining an earth system environment in which humans can exist, four of which are experiencing at this time the onset of irreversible environmental degradation and three of which (climate change, the nitrogen cycle, and biodiversity loss) are at “tipping points,” meaning that these processes have already crossed their planetary boundaries. ¶ 2. The magnitude of the means of violence and social control is unprecedented, as is the concentration of the means of global communication and symbolic production and circulation in the hands of a very few powerful groups. Computerised wars, drones, bunker-buster bombs, star wars, and so forth, have changed the face of warfare. Warfare has become normalised and sanitised for those not directly at the receiving end of armed aggression. At the same time we have arrived at the panoptical surveillance society and the age of thought control by those who control global flows of communication, images and symbolic production. The world of Edward Snowden is the world of George Orwell; 1984 has arrived; ¶ 3. Capitalism is reaching apparent limits to its extensive expansion. There are no longer any new territories of significance that can be integrated into world capitalism, de-ruralisation is now well advanced, and the commodification of the countryside and of pre- and non-capitalist spaces has intensified, that is, converted in hot-house fashion into spaces of capital, so that intensive expansion is reaching depths never before seen. Capitalism must continually expand or collapse. How or where will it now expand? ¶ 4. There is the rise of a vast surplus population inhabiting a “planet of slums,”4 alienated from the productive economy, thrown into the margins, and subject to sophisticated systems of social control and to destruction - to a mortal cycle of dispossession-exploitation-exclusion. This includes prison-industrial and immigrant-detention complexes, omnipresent policing, militarised gentrification, and so on; ¶ 5. There is a disjuncture between a globalising economy and a nation-state based system of political authority. Transnational state apparatuses are incipient and have not been able to play the role of what social scientists refer to as a “hegemon,” or a leading nation-state that has enough power and authority to organise and stabilise the system. The spread of weapons of mass destruction and the unprecedented militarisation of social life and conflict across the globe makes it hard to imagine that the system can come under any stable political authority that assures its reproduction. ¶ Global Police State ¶ How have social and political forces worldwide responded to crisis? The crisis has resulted in a rapid political polarisation in global society. Both right and left-wing forces are ascendant. Three responses seem to be in dispute. ¶ One is what we could call “reformism from above.” This elite reformism is aimed at stabilising the system, at saving the system from itself and from more radical re- sponses from below. Nonetheless, in the years following the 2008 collapse of the global financial system it seems these reformers are unable (or unwilling) to prevail over the power of transnational financial capital. A second response is popular, grassroots and leftist resistance from below. As social and political conflict escalates around the world there appears to be a mounting global revolt. While such resistance appears insurgent in the wake of 2008 it is spread very unevenly across countries and regions and facing many problems and challenges. ¶ Yet another response is that I term 21st century fascism.5 The ultra-right is an insurgent force in many countries. In broad strokes, this project seeks to fuse reactionary political power with transnational capital and to organise a mass base among historically privileged sectors of the global working class – such as white workers in the North and middle layers in the South – that are now experiencing heightened insecurity and the specter of downward mobility. It involves militarism, extreme masculinisation, homophobia, racism and racist mobilisations, including the search for scapegoats, such as immigrant workers and, in the West, Muslims. Twenty-first century fascism evokes mystifying ideologies, often involving race/culture supremacy and xenophobia, embracing an idealised and mythical past. Neo-fascist culture normalises and glamorises warfare and social violence, indeed, generates a fascination with domination that is portrayed even as heroic.
9,347
<h4>Capitalism causes war, violence, environmental destruction and extinction</h4><p><strong>Robinson 14 <u></strong>(William I., Prof. of Sociology, Global and International Studies, and Latin American Studies, @ UC-Santa Barbara, “Global Capitalism: Crisis of Humanity and the Specter of 21st Century Fascism” The World Financial Review)</p><p></u>Cyclical, Structural, and Systemic Crises ¶ Most commentators on the contemporary crisis refer to the “Great Recession” of 2008 and its aftermath. Yet <u><mark>the </mark>causal <mark>origins of <strong>global crisis</strong> are</mark> to be <mark>found in over-accumulation and</u></mark> also <u>in <strong><mark>contradictions of state power</u></strong></mark>, or in what Marxists call the internal contradictions of the capitalist system. Moreover, <u>because the system is now global, <mark>crisis in</mark> any <mark>one place</mark> tends to <mark>represent crisis for the system</mark> as a whole.</u> The system cannot expand because the marginalisation of a significant portion of humanity from direct productive participation, the downward pressure on wages and popular consumption worldwide, and the polarisation of income, has reduced the ability of the world market to absorb world output. At the same time, <u>given the particular configuration of social and class forces and the correlation of these forces worldwide, national states are hard-pressed to regulate transnational circuits of accumulation and offset</u> the <u>explosive contradictions</u> built into the system. ¶ Is this crisis cyclical, structural, or systemic? <u>Cyclical crises are recurrent to capitalism about once every 10 years and involve recessions that act as self-correcting mechanisms</u> without any major restructuring of the system. The recessions of the early 1980s, the early 1990s, and of 2001 were cyclical crises. In contrast, the 2008 crisis signaled the slide into a structural crisis. Structural crises reflect deeper contra- dictions that can only be resolved by a major restructuring of the system. The structural crisis of the 1970s was resolved through capitalist globalisation. Prior to that, the structural crisis of the 1930s was resolved through the creation of a new model of redistributive capitalism, and prior to that the struc- tural crisis of the 1870s resulted in the development of corpo- rate capitalism. <u>A systemic crisis involves the replacement of a system by an entirely new system or by an outright collapse. A structural crisis opens up the possibility for a systemic crisis.</u> But if it actually snowballs into a systemic crisis – in this case, if it gives way either to capitalism being superseded or to a breakdown of global civilisation – is not predetermined and depends entirely on the response of social and political forces to the crisis and on historical contingencies that are not easy to forecast. <u>This is an historic moment of extreme uncertainty, in which collective responses from distinct social and class forces to the crisis are in great flux. ¶ </u>Hence my concept of global crisis is broader than financial. <u>There are multiple and mutually constitutive dimensions – economic, social, political, cultural, ideological and ecological, not to mention the existential crisis of our consciousness</u>, values and very being. There is a crisis of social polarisation, that is, of social reproduction. <u>The system cannot meet the needs</u> or assure the survival <u>of millions of people</u>, perhaps a majority of humanity. There are crises of state legitimacy and political authority, or of hegemony and domination. National states face spiraling crises of legitimacy as they fail to meet the social grievances of local working and popular classes experiencing downward mobility, unemployment, heightened insecurity and greater hardships. <u>The legitimacy of the system has increasingly been called into question by millions</u>, <u>perhaps</u> even <u>billions</u>, of people around the world, <u>and is facing expanded counter-hegemonic challenges.</u> Global elites have been unable counter this erosion of the system’s authority in the face of worldwide pressures for a global moral economy. <u>And <mark>a canopy that envelops all these dimensions is</mark> a crisis of sustainability rooted in</u> an ecological holocaust that has already begun, expressed in <u><strong><mark>climate change and the impending collapse of centralised agricultur</mark>al</strong> systems</u> in several regions of the world, among other indicators. By <u>a crisis of humanity</u> I mean a crisis that is approaching systemic proportions, <u><strong><mark>threatening the ability of billions </mark>of people <mark>to survive</strong></mark>, and raising the specter of a collapse of world civilisation</u> and degeneration into a new “Dark Ages.”2 ¶ This crisis of humanity shares a number of aspects with earlier structural crises but there are also several features unique to the present: ¶ 1. <u><mark>The system is fast reaching</mark> the <strong><mark>ecological limits of its reproduction</strong></mark>. Global capitalism now couples human and natural history in such a way as to threaten to bring about what would be the sixth mass extinction</u> in the known history of life on earth.3 This mass extinction would be caused not by a natural catastrophe such as a meteor impact or by evolutionary changes such as the end of an ice age but by purposive human activity. According to leading environmental scientists <u>there are nine “planetary boundaries” crucial to maintaining an earth system environment in which humans can exist, four of which are experiencing</u> at this time <u>the onset of irreversible environmental degradation and three of which</u> (climate change, the nitrogen cycle, and biodiversity loss) <u>are at “tipping points</u>,” meaning that these processes have already crossed their planetary boundaries. ¶ 2. <u><mark>The magnitude</mark> of the means <mark>of <strong>violence</strong></mark> and</u> social <u>control <strong><mark>is unprecedented</strong></mark>, as is the concentration of the means of global communication and symbolic production</u> and circulation in the hands of a very few powerful groups. <u><strong><mark>Computerised wars, drones</mark>, bunker-buster bombs</strong>, star wars</u>, and so forth, <u>have changed the face of warfare. Warfare has become normalised and sanitised for those not directly at the receiving end of armed aggression.</u> At the same time we have arrived at the panoptical surveillance society and the age of thought control by those who control global flows of communication, images and symbolic production. The world of Edward Snowden is the world of George Orwell; 1984 has arrived; ¶ 3. <u>Capitalism is reaching apparent limits to its extensive expansion. There are no longer any new territories of significance that can be integrated into world capitalism, de-ruralisation is now well advanced, and the commodification of the countryside and of pre- and non-capitalist spaces has intensified</u>, that is, converted in hot-house fashion into spaces of capital, so that intensive expansion is reaching depths never before seen. <u>Capitalism must continually expand or collapse.</u> How or where will it now expand? ¶ 4. <u>There is the rise of a vast <mark>surplus population</mark> inhabiting a “planet of slums,”</u>4 <u><mark>alienated from the productive economy</mark>, thrown into the margins, <mark>and subject to </mark>sophisticated systems of social <strong><mark>control and</mark> to <mark>destruction</strong></mark> - to a mortal cycle of dispossession-exploitation-exclusion. This includes <strong><mark>prison-industrial </mark>and immigrant-detention <mark>complexes, omnipresent policing, militarised gentrification</u></strong></mark>, and so on; ¶ 5. <u>There is a disjuncture between a globalising economy and a nation-state based system of political authority.</u> <u>Transnational state apparatuses</u> are incipient and <u>have not been able to play the role of</u> what social scientists refer to as a “<u>hegemon</u>,” or a leading nation-state that has enough power and authority to organise and stabilise the system. <u><mark>The spread of <strong>w</strong></mark>eapons of <strong><mark>m</strong></mark>ass <strong>d</strong>estruction and the unprecedented militarisation of social life and conflict across the globe makes it hard to imagine that the system can come under any stable political authority that assures its reproduction. </u>¶ Global Police State ¶ How have social and political forces worldwide responded to crisis? The crisis has resulted in a rapid political polarisation in global society. Both right and left-wing forces are ascendant. Three responses seem to be in dispute. ¶ One is what we could call “reformism from above.” This elite reformism is aimed at stabilising the system, at saving the system from itself and from more radical re- sponses from below. Nonetheless, in the years following the 2008 collapse of the global financial system it seems these reformers are unable (or unwilling) to prevail over the power of transnational financial capital. A second response is popular, grassroots and leftist resistance from below. As social and political conflict escalates around the world there appears to be a mounting global revolt. While such resistance appears insurgent in the wake of 2008 it is spread very unevenly across countries and regions and facing many problems and challenges. ¶ Yet another response is that I term 21st century fascism.5 <u><mark>The ultra-right is</mark> an <mark>insurgent</mark> force in many countries.</u> In broad strokes, <u>this project seeks to fuse reactionary political power with transnational capital and to organise a mass base among historically privileged sectors of the global working class</u> – <u>such as white workers</u> in the North and middle layers in the South – <u>that are now experiencing heightened insecurity and the specter of downward mobility. <mark>It involves <strong></mark>militarism, extreme <mark>masculinisation, homophobia, racism and racist mobilisations</strong></mark>, including the search for scapegoats, such as immigrant workers and</u>, in the West, <u>Muslims. <strong><mark>Twenty-first century fascism</strong></mark> evokes mystifying ideologies, often involving race/culture supremacy and xenophobia, embracing an idealised and mythical past. Neo-fascist culture <strong><mark>normalises and glamorises warfare</strong> and social violence</mark>, indeed, generates a fascination with domination that is portrayed even as heroic.</p></u>
1NC
null
1NC – OFF
31,023
1,187
24,876
./documents/ndtceda21/WakeForestUniversity/BrSa/Wake%20Forest%20University-Bressler-Sayoto-Neg-Crowe%20Warken%20Debates-Round4.docx
627,757
N
Crowe Warken Debates
4
George Mason VP
Murphy, Devane
1NC - K T 2NR - K
ndtceda21/WakeForestUniversity/BrSa/Wake%20Forest%20University-Bressler-Sayoto-Neg-Crowe%20Warken%20Debates-Round4.docx
null
52,931
BrSa
Wake Forest University BrSa
null
Ge.....
Br.....
Ju.....
Sa.....
19,425
WakeForestUniversity
Wake Forest University
null
null
1,011
ndtceda21
NDT/CEDA 2021-22
2,021
cx
college
2
4,089,882
The “USFG” is three branches.
U.S. Legal ’16
U.S. Legal ’16 [U.S. Legal; 2016; Organization offering legal assistance and attorney access; U.S. Legal, “United States Federal Government Law and Legal Definition,” https://definitions.uslegal.com/u/united-states-federal-government/]
The U S F G is three branches: i) legislature, which is the Congress, ii) Executive the President and iii) Judiciary The Constitution limits the Federal Government all powers not expressly assigned to the Federal Government are reserved to the States
The U S F G is three branches legislature Executive and Judiciary powers not assigned to the Fed are reserved to the States
The United States Federal Government is established by the US Constitution. The Federal Government shares sovereignty over the United Sates with the individual governments of the States of US. The Federal government has three branches: i) the legislature, which is the US Congress, ii) Executive, comprised of the President and Vice president of the US and iii) Judiciary. The US Constitution prescribes a system of separation of powers and ‘checks and balances’ for the smooth functioning of all the three branches of the Federal Government. The US Constitution limits the powers of the Federal Government to the powers assigned to it; all powers not expressly assigned to the Federal Government are reserved to the States or to the people.
741
<h4>The “USFG” is <u>three branches</u>. </h4><p><strong>U.S. Legal ’16 </strong>[U.S. Legal; 2016; Organization offering legal assistance and attorney access; U.S. Legal, “United States Federal Government Law and Legal Definition,” https://definitions.uslegal.com/u/united-states-federal-government/]</p><p><u><mark>The <strong>U</u></strong></mark>nited <u><strong><mark>S</u></strong></mark>tates <u><strong><mark>F</u></strong></mark>ederal <u><strong><mark>G</u></strong></mark>overnment <u><mark>is</u></mark> established by the US Constitution. The Federal Government shares sovereignty over the United Sates with the individual governments of the States of US. The Federal government has <u><mark>three branches</mark>: i)</u> the<u> <strong><mark>legislature</strong></mark>, which is the</u> US <u>Congress, ii) <strong><mark>Executive</u></strong></mark>, comprised of <u>the President</u> and Vice president of the US <u><mark>and</mark> iii) <strong><mark>Judiciary</u></strong></mark>. The US Constitution prescribes a system of separation of powers and ‘checks and balances’ for the smooth functioning of all the three branches of the Federal Government. <u>The</u> US <u>Constitution <strong>limits</u></strong> the powers of <u>the Federal Government</u> to the powers assigned to it; <u>all <mark>powers not</mark> <strong>expressly <mark>assigned</strong> to the Fed</mark>eral Government <mark>are</mark> <strong><mark>reserved</strong> to the <strong>States</u></strong></mark> or to the people.</p>
1NC – Greenhill Round 1
Off
T
1,172
1,430
140,209
./documents/hspolicy22/Edgemont/KuSa/Edgemont-KuSa-Neg-Greenhill-Fall-Classic-Round-1.docx
934,861
N
Greenhill Fall Classic
1
Berkeley Prep TZ
Lee
1AC - Disability K Aff 1NC - T, PIK 2NR - T
hspolicy22/Edgemont/KuSa/Edgemont-KuSa-Neg-Greenhill-Fall-Classic-Round-1.docx
2022-10-14 05:12:13
79,530
KuSa
Edgemont KuSa
Contact Info rsandhuny@gmail.com 2005aryankumar316@gmail.com edgemontcxdocs@gmail.com
Ar.....
Ku.....
Ra.....
Sa.....
26,672
Edgemont
Edgemont
NY
null
2,002
hspolicy22
HS Policy 2022-23
2,022
cx
hs
2
3,550,368
b). Resolved denotes a proposal to be enacted by law
Words and Phrases 64
Words and Phrases 64 Permanent Edition
Definition of the word “resolve is “to express an opinion or determination by resolution or vote; as ‘it was resolved by the legislature;” It is of similar force to the word “enact,” which is defined as meaning “to establish by law
Definition of “resolve,” is “to express an opinion or determination by resolution or vote; as ‘it was resolved by the legislature;” It is of similar force to enact,” defined as to establish by law”.
Definition of the word “resolve,” given by Webster is “to express an opinion or determination by resolution or vote; as ‘it was resolved by the legislature;” It is of similar force to the word “enact,” which is defined by Bouvier as meaning “to establish by law”.
263
<h4>b). Resolved<u> denotes a proposal to be enacted by law </h4><p></u><strong>Words and Phrases 64</strong> Permanent Edition </p><p><u><mark>Definition of</mark> the word <mark>“resolve</u>,”</mark> given by Webster <u><mark>is “to express an opinion or determination by resolution or vote; as ‘it was resolved by the legislature;” It is of similar force to</mark> the word “<mark>enact,” </mark>which is <mark>defined</u></mark> by Bouvier <u><mark>as</mark> meaning “<mark>to establish by law</u>”.</p></mark>
1nc
null
1nc framework
1,125
2,415
117,388
./documents/ndtceda17/WakeForest/Klge/Wake%20Forest-Klein-geraghty-Neg-gonzaga-Round5.docx
601,085
N
gonzaga
5
san francisco state bg
brendon bankey
1ac - community clinics 1nc - single payer cp fw case 2nc - fw 1nr - cp 2nr - fw and cp as a tva
ndtceda17/WakeForest/Klge/Wake%20Forest-Klein-geraghty-Neg-gonzaga-Round5.docx
null
51,135
Klge
Wake Forest Klge
null
Ru.....
Kl.....
fa.....
ge.....
19,153
WakeForest
Wake Forest
null
null
1,007
ndtceda17
NDT/CEDA 2017-18
2,017
cx
college
2
1,846,885
Util is good – existential threats outweigh and cognitive bias goes aff
GPP 17
GPP 17 (Global Priorities Project, Future of Humanity Institute at the University of Oxford, Ministry for Foreign Affairs of Finland, “Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance,” Global Priorities Project, 2017, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf
Compare three outcomes: (1) Peace. (2) A nuclear war that kills 99% of the world’s existing population. (3) A nuclear war that kills 100%. Most people believe that the greater difference is between (1) and (2). I believe that the difference between (2) and (3) is very much greater The Earth will remain habitable for at least another billion years. Civilization began only a few thousand years ago. If we do not destroy mankind, these few thousand years may be only a tiny fraction of the whole of civilized human history. The difference between (2) and (3) may thus be the difference between this tiny fraction and all of the rest of this history. If we compare this possible history to a day, what has occurred so far is only a fraction of a second.65 What makes existential catastrophes especially bad is that they would “destroy the future,” as Bostrom, puts it. This future could potentially be extremely long and full of flourishing, and would therefore have extremely large value. Because the value of preventing existential catastrophe is so vast, even a tiny probability of prevention has huge expected value. In some areas, government policy does give significant weight to future generations. However, when it comes to existential risk, it would seem that we fail to live up to principles of intergenerational equity. Existential catastrophe would not only give future generations less than the current generations; it would give them nothing. reducing existential risk plausibly has a quite low cost for us in comparison with the huge expected value it has for future generations. Unless we give up on norms of intergenerational equity, they give us a strong case for significantly increasing our efforts to reduce existential risks. . WHY EXISTENTIAL RISKS MAY BE SYSTEMATICALLY UNDERINVESTED IN, AND THE ROLE OF THE INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY In spite of the importance of existential risk reduction, it probably receives less attention than is warranted. There are several reasons why existential risk reduction is likely to be underinvested in. Firstly, it is a global public good. Economic theory predicts that such goods tend to be underprovided. The benefits of existential risk reduction are widely and indivisibly dispersed around the globe from the countries responsible for taking action. Secondly existential risk reduction is an intergenerational public good: most of the benefits are enjoyed by future generations who have no say in the political process. For these goods, the problem is temporal free riding: the current generation enjoys the benefits of inaction while future generations bear the costs. Thirdly existential risks pose an unprecedented and uncertain future threat. Cognitive biases also lead people to underestimate existential risks. Since there have not been any catastrophes of this magnitude, these risks are not salient to politicians and the public. This is an example of the misapplication of the availability heuristic, a mental shortcut which assumes that something is important only if it can be readily recalled. Another cognitive bias affecting perceptions of existential risk is scope neglect. People become numbed to the effect of saving lives when the numbers get too large. Scope neglect is a particularly acute problem for existential risk because the numbers at stake are so large. Due to scope neglect, decision-makers are prone to treat existential risks in a similar way to problems which are less severe by many orders of magnitude.
Compare Peace. war that kills 99% war that kills 100%. difference between (2) and (3) is much greater Earth will remain for at least another billion years. existential catastrophes would “destroy the future,” risk reduction is underinvested in it is global benefits are widely indivisibly dispersed the problem is temporal free riding: the current generation enjoys inaction while future bear the costs. Cognitive biases lead people to underestimate risks Since there have not been any catastrophes of this magnitude People become numbed when the numbers get too large decision-makers treat risks similar to problems less severe by many orders of magnitude
1.2. THE ETHICS OF EXISTENTIAL RISK In his book Reasons and Persons, Oxford philosopher Derek Parfit advanced an influential argument about the importance of avoiding extinction: I believe that if we destroy mankind, as we now can, this outcome will be much worse than most people think. Compare three outcomes: (1) Peace. (2) A nuclear war that kills 99% of the world’s existing population. (3) A nuclear war that kills 100%. (2) would be worse than (1), and (3) would be worse than (2). Which is the greater of these two differences? Most people believe that the greater difference is between (1) and (2). I believe that the difference between (2) and (3) is very much greater. ... The Earth will remain habitable for at least another billion years. Civilization began only a few thousand years ago. If we do not destroy mankind, these few thousand years may be only a tiny fraction of the whole of civilized human history. The difference between (2) and (3) may thus be the difference between this tiny fraction and all of the rest of this history. If we compare this possible history to a day, what has occurred so far is only a fraction of a second.65 In this argument, it seems that Parfit is assuming that the survivors of a nuclear war that kills 99% of the population would eventually be able to recover civilisation without long-term effect. As we have seen, this may not be a safe assumption – but for the purposes of this thought experiment, the point stands. What makes existential catastrophes especially bad is that they would “destroy the future,” as another Oxford philosopher, Nick Bostrom, puts it.66 This future could potentially be extremely long and full of flourishing, and would therefore have extremely large value. In standard risk analysis, when working out how to respond to risk, we work out the expected value of risk reduction, by weighing the probability that an action will prevent an adverse event against the severity of the event. Because the value of preventing existential catastrophe is so vast, even a tiny probability of prevention has huge expected value.67 Of course, there is persisting reasonable disagreement about ethics and there are a number of ways one might resist this conclusion.68 Therefore, it would be unjustified to be overconfident in Parfit and Bostrom’s argument. In some areas, government policy does give significant weight to future generations. For example, in assessing the risks of nuclear waste storage, governments have considered timeframes of thousands, hundreds of thousands, and even a million years.69 Justifications for this policy usually appeal to principles of intergenerational equity according to which future generations ought to get as much protection as current generations.70 Similarly, widely accepted norms of sustainable development require development that meets the needs of the current generation without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs.71 However, when it comes to existential risk, it would seem that we fail to live up to principles of intergenerational equity. Existential catastrophe would not only give future generations less than the current generations; it would give them nothing. Indeed, reducing existential risk plausibly has a quite low cost for us in comparison with the huge expected value it has for future generations. In spite of this, relatively little is done to reduce existential risk. Unless we give up on norms of intergenerational equity, they give us a strong case for significantly increasing our efforts to reduce existential risks. 1.3. WHY EXISTENTIAL RISKS MAY BE SYSTEMATICALLY UNDERINVESTED IN, AND THE ROLE OF THE INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY In spite of the importance of existential risk reduction, it probably receives less attention than is warranted. As a result, concerted international cooperation is required if we are to receive adequate protection from existential risks. 1.3.1. Why existential risks are likely to be underinvested in There are several reasons why existential risk reduction is likely to be underinvested in. Firstly, it is a global public good. Economic theory predicts that such goods tend to be underprovided. The benefits of existential risk reduction are widely and indivisibly dispersed around the globe from the countries responsible for taking action. Consequently, a country which reduces existential risk gains only a small portion of the benefits but bears the full brunt of the costs. Countries thus have strong incentives to free ride, receiving the benefits of risk reduction without contributing. As a result, too few do what is in the common interest. Secondly, as already suggested above, existential risk reduction is an intergenerational public good: most of the benefits are enjoyed by future generations who have no say in the political process. For these goods, the problem is temporal free riding: the current generation enjoys the benefits of inaction while future generations bear the costs. Thirdly, many existential risks, such as machine superintelligence, engineered pandemics, and solar geoengineering, pose an unprecedented and uncertain future threat. Consequently, it is hard to develop a satisfactory governance regime for them: there are few existing governance instruments which can be applied to these risks, and it is unclear what shape new instruments should take. In this way, our position with regard to these emerging risks is comparable to the one we faced when nuclear weapons first became available. Cognitive biases also lead people to underestimate existential risks. Since there have not been any catastrophes of this magnitude, these risks are not salient to politicians and the public.72 This is an example of the misapplication of the availability heuristic, a mental shortcut which assumes that something is important only if it can be readily recalled. Another cognitive bias affecting perceptions of existential risk is scope neglect. In a seminal 1992 study, three groups were asked how much they would be willing to pay to save 2,000, 20,000 or 200,000 birds from drowning in uncovered oil ponds. The groups answered $80, $78, and $88, respectively.73 In this case, the size of the benefits had little effect on the scale of the preferred response. People become numbed to the effect of saving lives when the numbers get too large. 74 Scope neglect is a particularly acute problem for existential risk because the numbers at stake are so large. Due to scope neglect, decision-makers are prone to treat existential risks in a similar way to problems which are less severe by many orders of magnitude. A wide range of other cognitive biases are likely to affect the evaluation of existential risks.75
6,739
<h4>Util is good – existential threats outweigh and cognitive bias goes aff</h4><p><strong>GPP 17</strong> (Global Priorities Project, Future of Humanity Institute at the University of Oxford, Ministry for Foreign Affairs of Finland, “Existential Risk: Diplomacy and Governance,” Global Priorities Project, 2017, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf </p><p>1.2. THE ETHICS OF EXISTENTIAL RISK In his book Reasons and Persons, Oxford philosopher Derek Parfit advanced an influential argument about the importance of avoiding extinction: I believe that if we destroy mankind, as we now can, this outcome will be much worse than most people think. <u><mark>Compare</mark> three outcomes: (1) <mark>Peace.</mark> (2) A nuclear <mark>war that kills 99%</mark> of the world’s existing population. (3) A nuclear <mark>war that kills 100%.</mark> </u>(2) would be worse than (1), and (3) would be worse than (2). Which is the greater of these two differences? <u>Most people believe that the greater difference is between (1) and (2).</u> <u>I believe that the <mark>difference between (2) and (3) is </mark>very<mark> much greater</u></mark>. ... <u>The <mark>Earth will remain</mark> habitable <mark>for <strong>at least another billion years</strong>.</u> <u></mark>Civilization began only a few thousand years ago.</u> <u>If we do not destroy mankind, these few thousand years may be only <strong>a tiny fraction</strong> of the whole of civilized human history.</u> <u>The difference between (2) and (3) may thus be the difference between this tiny fraction and all of the rest of this history.</u> <u>If we compare this possible history to a day, what has occurred so far is only a <strong>fraction of a second</strong>.65</u> In this argument, it seems that Parfit is assuming that the survivors of a nuclear war that kills 99% of the population would eventually be able to recover civilisation without long-term effect. As we have seen, this may not be a safe assumption – but for the purposes of this thought experiment, the point stands. <u>What makes <mark>existential catastrophes </mark>especially bad is that they <mark>would “<strong>destroy the future</strong>,”</mark> as</u> another Oxford philosopher, Nick <u>Bostrom, puts it.</u>66 <u>This future could potentially be extremely long and full of flourishing, and would therefore have extremely large value.</u> In standard risk analysis, when working out how to respond to risk, we work out the expected value of risk reduction, by weighing the probability that an action will prevent an adverse event against the severity of the event. <u>Because the value of preventing existential catastrophe is so vast, even a tiny probability of prevention has huge expected value.</u>67 Of course, there is persisting reasonable disagreement about ethics and there are a number of ways one might resist this conclusion.68 Therefore, it would be unjustified to be overconfident in Parfit and Bostrom’s argument. <u>In some areas, government policy does give significant weight to future generations.</u> For example, in assessing the risks of nuclear waste storage, governments have considered timeframes of thousands, hundreds of thousands, and even a million years.69 Justifications for this policy usually appeal to principles of intergenerational equity according to which future generations ought to get as much protection as current generations.70 Similarly, widely accepted norms of sustainable development require development that meets the needs of the current generation without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs.71 <u>However, when it comes to existential risk, it would seem that we fail to live up to principles of intergenerational equity.</u> <u>Existential catastrophe would not only give future generations less than the current generations; <strong>it would give them nothing</strong>.</u> Indeed, <u>reducing existential risk plausibly has a quite low cost for us in comparison with the huge expected value it has for future generations.</u> In spite of this, relatively little is done to reduce existential risk. <u>Unless we give up on norms of intergenerational equity, they give us a strong case for significantly increasing our efforts to reduce existential risks. </u>1.3<u>. WHY EXISTENTIAL RISKS MAY BE SYSTEMATICALLY UNDERINVESTED IN, AND THE ROLE OF THE INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY</u> <u>In spite of the importance of existential risk reduction, it probably receives less attention than is warranted.</u> As a result, concerted international cooperation is required if we are to receive adequate protection from existential risks. 1.3.1. Why existential risks are likely to be underinvested in <u>There are several reasons why existential <mark>risk reduction is </mark>likely to be <mark>underinvested in</mark>.</u> <u>Firstly, <mark>it is</mark> a <mark>global </mark>public good.</u> <u>Economic theory predicts that such goods tend to be underprovided.</u> <u>The <mark>benefits</mark> of existential risk reduction <mark>are widely</mark> and <mark>indivisibly dispersed </mark>around the globe from the countries responsible for taking action.</u> Consequently, a country which reduces existential risk gains only a small portion of the benefits but bears the full brunt of the costs. Countries thus have strong incentives to free ride, receiving the benefits of risk reduction without contributing. As a result, too few do what is in the common interest. <u>Secondly</u>, as already suggested above, <u>existential risk reduction is an intergenerational public good: most of the benefits are enjoyed by future generations who have no say in the political process.</u> <u>For these goods, <mark>the problem is temporal free riding: the current generation enjoys </mark>the benefits of <mark>inaction while future </mark>generations <mark>bear the costs.</mark> Thirdly</u>, many <u>existential risks</u>, such as machine superintelligence, engineered pandemics, and solar geoengineering, <u>pose an unprecedented and uncertain future threat.</u> Consequently, it is hard to develop a satisfactory governance regime for them: there are few existing governance instruments which can be applied to these risks, and it is unclear what shape new instruments should take. In this way, our position with regard to these emerging risks is comparable to the one we faced when nuclear weapons first became available. <u><mark>Cognitive biases </mark>also <mark>lead people to underestimate</mark> existential <mark>risks</mark>.</u> <u><mark>Since there have not been any catastrophes of this magnitude</mark>, these risks are not salient to politicians and the public.</u>72 <u>This is an example of the misapplication of the availability heuristic, a mental shortcut which assumes that something is important only if it can be readily recalled. Another cognitive bias affecting perceptions of existential risk is scope neglect.</u> In a seminal 1992 study, three groups were asked how much they would be willing to pay to save 2,000, 20,000 or 200,000 birds from drowning in uncovered oil ponds. The groups answered $80, $78, and $88, respectively.73 In this case, the size of the benefits had little effect on the scale of the preferred response. <u><mark>People become numbed</mark> to the effect of saving lives <mark>when the numbers get too large</mark>.</u> 74 <u>Scope neglect is a particularly acute problem for existential risk because the numbers at stake are so large.</u> <u>Due to scope neglect, <mark>decision-makers </mark>are prone to <mark>treat</mark> existential <mark>risks</mark> in a <mark>similar</mark> way <mark>to problems</mark> which are <mark>less severe by many orders of magnitude</mark>.</u><strong> A wide range of other cognitive biases are likely to affect the evaluation of existential risks.75</p></strong>
1AC
1AC—CHC BL—Blake K v1
1AC---Framing
261
2,546
54,213
./documents/hspolicy20/CalvertHall/BrLo/Calvert%20Hall-Bressler-Lobo-Aff-Blake-Octas.docx
726,274
A
Blake
Octas
NoBro DR
Misty Tippets, KJ Reese, Brian Rubaie
1ac - IRS v2 1nc - t unidirectional t body ptx gillespie k 2nc - k case 1nr - k 2nr - k case 2ar - cap good lol
hspolicy20/CalvertHall/BrLo/Calvert%20Hall-Bressler-Lobo-Aff-Blake-Octas.docx
null
61,977
BrLo
Calvert Hall BrLo
null
Eu.....
Br.....
Lu.....
Lo.....
21,539
CalvertHall
Calvert Hall
MD
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
953,826
Thus, the only alternative is one of decolonization.
Tuck and Yang 12
Tuck and Yang 12 (Eve Tuck, Unangax, State University of New York at New Paltz K. Wayne Yang University of California, San Diego, Decolonization is not a metaphor, Decolonization: Indigeneity, Education & Society Vol. 1, No. 1, 2012, pp. 1-40, JKS)
An ethic of incommensurability, guides moves that unsettle innocence, stands in contrast to reconciliation, which motivate settler moves to innocence. Reconciliation is about rescuing settler normalcy, rescuing a settler future. Reconciliation is concerned with questions of what will decolonization look like? What will be the consequences for the settler? Incommensurability acknowledges that these questions need not, , be answered for decolonization to exist as a framework. decolonization is not obliged to answer decolonization is not accountable to settlers, or settler futurity. Decolonization is accountable to Indigenous sovereignty and futurity. The answers are not fully in view and can’t be as long as decolonization remains punctuated by metaphor. The answers will not emerge from friendly understanding, and indeed require a dangerous understanding of uncommonality that un-coalesces coalition politics - moves that may feel very unfriendly. we will find the answers as we get there, “in the exact measure that we can discern the movements which give [decolonization] historical form and content” To fully enact an ethic of incommensurability means relinquishing settler futurity, abandoning the hope that settlers may one day be commensurable to Native peoples. It means removing the asterisks, periods, commas, apostrophes, the whereas’s, buts, and conditional clauses that punctuate decolonization and underwrite settler innocence. The Native futures, to be lived once the settler nation is gone are the unwritten possibilities made possible by an ethic of incommensurability.
An ethic of incommensurability , stands in contrast to reconciliation, which motivate settler moves to innocence. Reconciliation is about rescuing settler normalcy, rescuing a settler future. concerned with questions of what will decolonization look like What will be the consequences Incommensurability acknowledges these questions need not, be answered for decolonization to exist decolonization is not obliged to answer not accountable to settlers, or settler futurity. Decolonization is accountable to Indigenous sovereignty and futurity The answers are not fully in view and can’t be as long as decolonization remains punctuated by metaphor we will find the answers as we get there To fully enact an ethic of incommensurability means relinquishing settler futurity, abandoning the hope that settlers may one day be commensurable to Native peoples.
An ethic of incommensurability, which guides moves that unsettle innocence, stands in contrast to aims of reconciliation, which motivate settler moves to innocence. Reconciliation is about rescuing settler normalcy, about rescuing a settler future. Reconciliation is concerned with questions of what will decolonization look like? What will happen after abolition? What will be the consequences of decolonization for the settler? Incommensurability acknowledges that these questions need not, and perhaps cannot, be answered in order for decolonization to exist as a framework. We want to say, first, that decolonization is not obliged to answer those questions - decolonization is not accountable to settlers, or settler futurity. Decolonization is accountable to Indigenous sovereignty and futurity. Still, we acknowledge the questions of those wary participants in Occupy Oakland and other settlers who want to know what decolonization will require of them. The answers are not fully in view and can’t be as long as decolonization remains punctuated by metaphor. The answers will not emerge from friendly understanding, and indeed require a dangerous understanding of uncommonality that un-coalesces coalition politics - moves that may feel very unfriendly. But we will find out the answers as we get there, “in the exact measure that we can discern the movements which give [decolonization] historical form and content” (Fanon, 1963, p. 36). To fully enact an ethic of incommensurability means relinquishing settler futurity, abandoning the hope that settlers may one day be commensurable to Native peoples. It means removing the asterisks, periods, commas, apostrophes, the whereas’s, buts, and conditional clauses that punctuate decolonization and underwrite settler innocence. The Native futures, the lives to be lived once the settler nation is gone - these are the unwritten possibilities made possible by an ethic of incommensurability.
1,946
<h4><strong>Thus, the only alternative is one of decolonization. </h4><p>Tuck and Yang 12</p><p><u></strong>(Eve Tuck, Unangax, State University of New York at New Paltz K. Wayne Yang University of California, San Diego, Decolonization is not a metaphor, Decolonization: Indigeneity, Education & Society Vol. 1, No. 1, 2012, pp. 1-40, JKS)</p><p><mark>An ethic of incommensurability</mark>, </u>which <u>guides moves that unsettle innocence<mark>, stands in contrast</mark> <mark>to</mark> </u>aims of<u> <mark>reconciliation, which motivate settler moves to innocence. Reconciliation is about rescuing settler normalcy, </u></mark>about <u><mark>rescuing a settler future. </mark>Reconciliation is <mark>concerned with questions of what will decolonization look like</mark>? </u>What will happen after abolition? <u><mark>What will be the consequences </u></mark>of decolonization<u> for the settler? <mark>Incommensurability acknowledges </mark>that <mark>these questions need not,</mark> </u>and perhaps cannot<u>, <mark>be answered </u></mark>in order<u> <mark>for decolonization to exist </mark>as a framework. </u>We want to say, first, that <u><strong><mark>decolonization is not obliged to answer </u></strong></mark>those questions -<u><strong> decolonization is <mark>not accountable to settlers, or settler futurity. Decolonization is accountable to Indigenous sovereignty and futurity</mark>. </u></strong>Still, we acknowledge the questions of those wary participants in Occupy Oakland and other settlers who want to know what decolonization will require of them. <u><mark>The answers are not fully in view and can’t be as long as decolonization remains punctuated by metaphor</mark>. The answers will not emerge from friendly understanding, and indeed require a dangerous understanding of uncommonality that un-coalesces coalition politics - moves that may feel very unfriendly. </u>But<u> <mark>we will find</mark> </u>out <u><mark>the answers as we get there</mark>, “in the exact measure that we can discern the movements which give [decolonization] historical form and content”</u> (Fanon, 1963, p. 36). <u><mark>To fully enact an ethic of incommensurability means relinquishing settler futurity, abandoning the hope that settlers may one day be <strong>commensurable to Native peoples</strong>. <strong></mark>It means removing the asterisks, periods, commas, apostrophes, the whereas’s, buts, and conditional clauses that punctuate decolonization and underwrite settler innocence</strong>. The Native futures, </u>the lives <u>to be lived once the settler nation is gone </u>- these<u> are the unwritten possibilities made possible by an ethic of incommensurability.</p></u>
1nc – texas round six
off
settlerism k
7,038
1,258
23,174
./documents/ndtceda21/Dartmouth/BaCh/Dartmouth-Bald-ChangDeutsch-Neg-Texas-Round6.docx
623,321
N
Texas
6
Houston CK
Shree Awsare
1AC - NCAA 2NR - Set Col K 2AR - Condo
ndtceda21/Dartmouth/BaCh/Dartmouth-Bald-ChangDeutsch-Neg-Texas-Round6.docx
null
52,619
BaCh
Dartmouth BaCh
null
Ho.....
Ba.....
Ga.....
Ch.....
19,377
Dartmouth
Dartmouth
null
null
1,011
ndtceda21
NDT/CEDA 2021-22
2,021
cx
college
2
2,185,309
7. Even a limited nuclear war would cause extinction – best science.
Cribb 17
Cribb 17
Surviving the 21st Century, Scientists arguing that the biggest killer of all is likely to be a ‘ nuclear winter triggered by the immense quantities of dust and smoke lofted into the upper atmosphere, and the simultaneous stripping of the Earth’s protective ozone layer: vast areas of the earth could be subjected to prolonged darkness, abnormally low temperatures, violent windstorms, toxic smog and persistent radioactive fallout This would be compounded by the collapse of farming and food production, transport, energy grids, healthcare, sanitation and central government A number of biologists contend the extinction of the human species— is a real possibility decades ago, scientists calculated that nuclear war could throw so much debris and smoke into the air that it would block life- giving sunlight from our atmosphere, causing a ‘nuclear winter How large a nuclear release is required to precipitate a nuclear winter is still subject to debate, but with the greatly improved models developed for climate science, recent estimates suggest as few as 50 Hiroshima-sized bombs or the use of only one weapon in every 200 from the global nuclear arsenal even a limited conflict among lesser actors in the arms race could still imperil the entire world. a ‘limited nuclear war’ is highly unlikely as, with the release of a handful of battlefi eld nukes, things will very quickly spiral out of control as communications fail and panic spreads mushrooming into a more general conflict Firestorms would throw up a shocking amount of smoke, ash and dust A billion people living on the margins of hunger would probably perish within weeks and billions more over the ensuing months. at least eight nations have the tools to terminate the human species on their own,
that the biggest killer of all is a ‘ nuclear winter biologists contend extinction is a real possibility greatly improved models suggest as few as 50 bombs or only one weapon in every 200 from the global nuclear arsenal even a limited conflict could still imperil the entire world a ‘limited nuclear war’ is highly unlikely as, things will very quickly spiral out of control
(Julian, BA Classics@WesternAusstralia, FoundingEditor@ScienceAlert, Surviving the 21st Century, Springer) The most publicised horrors of nuclear war, over the past half-century, were blast damage, fi reball burns and radiation sickness, as they were in Hiroshima and Nagasaki, leading to a perception that those well away from target areas might be spared. Scientists however demur, arguing that the biggest killer of all is likely to be a ‘ nuclear winter ’ , triggered by the immense quantities of dust and smoke from burning cities and forests lofted into the upper atmosphere, and the simultaneous stripping of the Earth’s protective ozone layer: “In the aftermath… vast areas of the earth could be subjected to prolonged darkness, abnormally low temperatures, violent windstorms, toxic smog and persistent radioactive fallout.” This would be compounded by the collapse of farming and food production, transport, energy grids, healthcare, sanitation and central government. Even in regions remote from the actual blasts people would starve, die from freezing temperatures as much as 30 °C below normal, from radiation sickness and a pandemic of skin cancers, pollution and loss of immunity to ordinary diseases. The nuclear winter is in effect the antithesis of global warming, a shock cooling of the entire planet, but one lasting several years only. However, “A number of biologists contend the extinction of many species … - including the human species— is a real possibility,” they say (Turco et al. 2012 ). In the 1980s a group of courageous scientists 1 alerted the leaders of both the US and Russia to the dangers of a nuclear winter. In an atomic war, they warned, there will be no winners. Th en-Soviet president Mikhail Gorbachev took their counsel to heart: “Models made by Russian and American scientists showed that a nuclear war would result in a nuclear winter that would be extremely destructive to all life on Earth; the knowledge of that was a great stimulus to us, to people of honor and morality, to act in that situation,” he subsequently related (Hertsgard 2000 ). US President Ronald Reagan concurred: “A nuclear war cannot be won and must never be fought,” he said in his State of the Union Address in 1984 (Reagan 1984 ). Marking this watershed moment in history Al Gore recounted in his Nobel Prize oration in 2007 “More than two decades ago, scientists calculated that nuclear war could throw so much debris and smoke into the air that it would block life- giving sunlight from our atmosphere, causing a ‘nuclear winter.’ Th eir eloquent warnings here in Oslo helped galvanize the world’s resolve to halt the nuclear arms race.” How large a nuclear release is required to precipitate a nuclear winter is still subject to technical debate, but with the greatly improved models developed for climate science, recent estimates suggest as few as 50 Hiroshima-sized bombs (15 kilotonnes each) would do it—or the use of only one weapon in every 200 from the global nuclear arsenal (Robock 2009 ). Th is puts a very different complexion on the contemporary risks facing humanity. First, it suggests that even a limited conflict among lesser actors in the arms race, for example between Pakistan and India, India and China or Israel and Iran, and involving mainly the use of “battlefi eld” nukes could still imperil the entire world. In Lights Out: how it all ends , nuclear experts Alan Robock and Brian Toon examined the eff ects of a regional war (Robock and Toon 2012 ). To begin with, they argue, a ‘limited nuclear war’ is highly unlikely as, with the release of a handful of battlefi eld nukes, things will very quickly spiral out of control as communications fail and panic spreads, mushrooming into a more general conflict involving dozens of weapons spread over a much wider region. Firestorms in the megacities would throw up a shocking amount of smoke, ash and dust—around 70 billion tonnes is the estimate for an India/Pakistan clash. Running this through climate models they found it would block out sunlight, chilling the planet by an average 1.25° for up to 10 years—enough to cause crop-killing frosts , even in midsummer. Th is would sharply reduce and in some regions eliminate farm production for several years. Normal world grain stocks are suffi cient to feed humanity for only about 2–3 months, so one of the fi rst round eff ects of the war would be worldwide panic and fi nancial collapse as food supplies give out and grain prices soar astronomically. A billion people living on the margins of hunger would probably perish within weeks, and billions more over the ensuing months. In the early twenty-fi rst century at least eight nations, on this calculus, have the tools to terminate civilisation, and possibly the human species, on their own, while at least two more aspire to the power to do so. Meanwhile the shadow of possible nuclear and chemical terrorism, and their consequences, is lengthening.
4,953
<h4>7. <u><strong>Even a limited nuclear war would cause extinction – best science.</h4><p>Cribb 17</p><p></u></strong>(Julian, BA Classics@WesternAusstralia, FoundingEditor@ScienceAlert, <u>Surviving the 21st Century, </u><strong>Springer)</p><p></strong>The most publicised horrors of nuclear war, over the past half-century, were blast damage, fi reball burns and radiation sickness, as they were in Hiroshima and Nagasaki, leading to a perception that those well away from target areas might be spared. <u>Scientists</u> however demur, <u>arguing <mark>that the biggest killer of all is</mark> likely to be <mark>a ‘ nuclear winter</u></mark> ’ , <u>triggered by the immense quantities of dust and smoke </u>from burning cities and forests <u>lofted into the upper atmosphere, and the simultaneous stripping of the Earth’s protective ozone layer:</u> “In the aftermath… <u>vast areas of the earth could be subjected to prolonged darkness, abnormally low temperatures, violent windstorms, toxic smog and persistent radioactive fallout</u>.” <u>This would be compounded by the collapse of farming and food production, transport, energy grids, healthcare, sanitation and central government</u>. Even in regions remote from the actual blasts people would starve, die from freezing temperatures as much as 30 °C below normal, from radiation sickness and a pandemic of skin cancers, pollution and loss of immunity to ordinary diseases. The nuclear winter is in effect the antithesis of global warming, a shock cooling of the entire planet, but one lasting several years only. However, “<u>A number of <mark>biologists contend</mark> <strong>the <mark>extinction</mark> of</u></strong> many species … - including <u><strong>the human species— <mark>is a real possibility</u></strong></mark>,” they say (Turco et al. 2012 ). In the 1980s a group of courageous scientists 1 alerted the leaders of both the US and Russia to the dangers of a nuclear winter. In an atomic war, they warned, there will be no winners. Th en-Soviet president Mikhail Gorbachev took their counsel to heart: “Models made by Russian and American scientists showed that a nuclear war would result in a nuclear winter that would be extremely destructive to all life on Earth; the knowledge of that was a great stimulus to us, to people of honor and morality, to act in that situation,” he subsequently related (Hertsgard 2000 ). US President Ronald Reagan concurred: “A nuclear war cannot be won and must never be fought,” he said in his State of the Union Address in 1984 (Reagan 1984 ). Marking this watershed moment in history Al Gore recounted in his Nobel Prize oration in 2007 “More than two <u>decades ago, scientists calculated that nuclear war could throw so much debris and smoke into the air that it would block life- giving sunlight from our atmosphere, causing a ‘nuclear winter</u>.’ Th eir eloquent warnings here in Oslo helped galvanize the world’s resolve to halt the nuclear arms race.” <u>How large a nuclear release is required to precipitate a nuclear winter is still subject to </u>technical<u> debate, but with the <strong><mark>greatly improved models</mark> developed for climate science, recent estimates <mark>suggest as few as 50</mark> Hiroshima-sized <mark>bombs</u></strong></mark> (15 kilotonnes each) would do it—<u><mark>or</mark> the use of <strong><mark>only one weapon in every 200</strong> from the global nuclear arsenal</u></mark> (Robock 2009 ). Th is puts a very different complexion on the contemporary risks facing humanity. First, it suggests that <u><strong><mark>even a limited conflict</mark> among lesser actors in the arms race</u></strong>, for example between Pakistan and India, India and China or Israel and Iran, and involving mainly the use of “battlefi eld” nukes <u><strong><mark>could still imperil the entire world</mark>.</u></strong> In Lights Out: how it all ends , nuclear experts Alan Robock and Brian Toon examined the eff ects of a regional war (Robock and Toon 2012 ). To begin with, they argue, <u><strong><mark>a ‘limited nuclear war’ is highly unlikely</strong> as,</mark> with the release of a handful of battlefi eld nukes, <mark>things will very quickly spiral out of control</mark> as communications fail and panic spreads</u>, <u>mushrooming into a more general conflict </u>involving dozens of weapons spread over a much wider region. <u>Firestorms</u> in the megacities <u>would throw up a shocking amount of smoke, ash and dust</u>—around 70 billion tonnes is the estimate for an India/Pakistan clash. Running this through climate models they found it would block out sunlight, chilling the planet by an average 1.25° for up to 10 years—enough to cause crop-killing frosts , even in midsummer. Th is would sharply reduce and in some regions eliminate farm production for several years. Normal world grain stocks are suffi cient to feed humanity for only about 2–3 months, so one of the fi rst round eff ects of the war would be worldwide panic and fi nancial collapse as food supplies give out and grain prices soar astronomically. <u>A billion people living on the margins of hunger would probably perish within weeks</u>, <u>and billions more over the ensuing months. </u>In the early twenty-fi rst century <u>at least eight nations</u>, on this calculus, <u>have the tools to terminate </u>civilisation, and possibly <u><strong>the human species</u></strong>, <u>on their own,</u> while at least two more aspire to the power to do so. Meanwhile the shadow of possible nuclear and chemical terrorism, and their consequences, is lengthening. </p>
null
1AC – Nuclear AI
Contention 1 is Automation
340,044
513
67,065
./documents/hsld20/HarvardWestlake/Go/Harvard%20Westlake-Gong-Aff-NDCA-Round2.docx
861,299
A
NDCA
2
Dougherty Valley AM
William Phong
1ac - Nuclear LAWs 1nc - T States - Deterrence DA - Noko PIC 2nr - Noko PIC
hsld20/HarvardWestlake/Go/Harvard%20Westlake-Gong-Aff-NDCA-Round2.docx
null
73,118
AnGo
Harvard Westlake AnGo
null
An.....
Go.....
null
null
24,537
HarvardWestlake
Harvard Westlake
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
3,779,051
Goes nuclear
Tønnesson, history PhD, 15
Tønnesson, history PhD, 15, Stein, well in Norway it’s called a “dr. philos” but that’s a PhD, Research Professor, Peace Research Institute Oslo; Leader of East Asia Peace program, Uppsala University, 2015, “Deterrence, interdependence and Sino–US peace,” International Area Studies Review, Vol. 18, No. 3, p. 297-311
recent works have made contributions to the current understanding of how and under what circumstances nuclear deterrence and economic interdependence may reduce the risk of war between major powers interdependence may both inhibit and drive conflict Interdependence raises the cost of conflict but asymmetrical or unbalanced dependencies and negative trade expectations generate tensions leading to trade wars among interdependent states that increase the risk of military conflict decisions for war are taken by very few people, who act on the basis of their future expectations If leaders begin to seriously fear or anticipate their own nation’s decline they may blame external dependence, appeal to anti-foreign sentiments, contemplate the use of force to gain credibility, adopt protectionist policies, and refuse to be deterred by nuclear arms or prospects of socioeconomic calamities. Such a dangerous shift could happen abruptly in East Asia The greatest risk is not a territorial dispute but that changes in the world economy alter those circumstances in ways that render inter-state peace more precarious This could have unforeseen consequences in the field of security, with nuclear deterrence remaining the only factor to protect the world from Armageddon, and unreliably so. Deterrence could lose its credibility great powers might gamble that the other yield in a cyber-war or conventional war
negative trade expectations generate tensions leading to trade wars that increase risk of military conflict If leaders seriously anticipate decline they may blame external dependence and refuse to be deterred by nuclear arms The greatest risk is that changes in the world economy render inter-state peace precarious Deterrence could lose credibility great powers might gamble in a cyber or conventional war
Several recent works on China and Sino–US relations have made substantial contributions to the current understanding of how and under what circumstances a combination of nuclear deterrence and economic interdependence may reduce the risk of war between major powers. At least four conclusions can be drawn from the review above: first, those who say that interdependence may both inhibit and drive conflict are right. Interdependence raises the cost of conflict for all sides but asymmetrical or unbalanced dependencies and negative trade expectations may generate tensions leading to trade wars among interdependent states that in turn increase the risk of military conflict (Copeland, 2015: 1, 14, 437; Roach, 2014). The risk may increase if one of the interdependent countries is governed by an inward-looking socio-economic coalition (Solingen, 2015); second, the risk of war between China and the US should not just be analysed bilaterally but include their allies and partners. Third party countries could drag China or the US into confrontation; third, in this context it is of some comfort that the three main economic powers in Northeast Asia (China, Japan and South Korea) are all deeply integrated economically through production networks within a global system of trade and finance (Ravenhill, 2014; Yoshimatsu, 2014: 576); and fourth, decisions for war and peace are taken by very few people, who act on the basis of their future expectations. International relations theory must be supplemented by foreign policy analysis in order to assess the value attributed by national decision-makers to economic development and their assessments of risks and opportunities. If leaders on either side of the Atlantic begin to seriously fear or anticipate their own nation’s decline then they may blame this on external dependence, appeal to anti-foreign sentiments, contemplate the use of force to gain respect or credibility, adopt protectionist policies, and ultimately refuse to be deterred by either nuclear arms or prospects of socioeconomic calamities. Such a dangerous shift could happen abruptly, i.e. under the instigation of actions by a third party – or against a third party. Yet as long as there is both nuclear deterrence and interdependence, the tensions in East Asia are unlikely to escalate to war. As Chan (2013) says, all states in the region are aware that they cannot count on support from either China or the US if they make provocative moves. The greatest risk is not that a territorial dispute leads to war under present circumstances but that changes in the world economy alter those circumstances in ways that render inter-state peace more precarious. If China and the US fail to rebalance their financial and trading relations (Roach, 2014) then a trade war could result, interrupting transnational production networks, provoking social distress, and exacerbating nationalist emotions. This could have unforeseen consequences in the field of security, with nuclear deterrence remaining the only factor to protect the world from Armageddon, and unreliably so. Deterrence could lose its credibility: one of the two great powers might gamble that the other yield in a cyber-war or conventional limited war, or third party countries might engage in conflict with each other, with a view to obliging Washington or Beijing to intervene.
3,360
<h4>Goes <u>nuclear</h4><p></u><strong>Tønnesson, history PhD, 15</strong>, Stein, well in Norway it’s called a “dr. philos” but that’s a PhD, Research Professor, Peace Research Institute Oslo; Leader of East Asia Peace program, Uppsala University, 2015, “Deterrence, interdependence and Sino–US peace,” International Area Studies Review, Vol. 18, No. 3, p. 297-311</p><p>Several <u>recent works</u> on China and Sino–US relations <u>have made</u> substantial <u>contributions to the current understanding of how and under what circumstances</u> a combination of <u>nuclear deterrence and economic interdependence may reduce the risk of war between major powers</u>. At least four conclusions can be drawn from the review above: first, those who say that <u>interdependence may <strong>both inhibit and drive conflict</u></strong> are right. <u>Interdependence raises the cost of conflict</u> for all sides <u>but</u> <u>asymmetrical or unbalanced dependencies and <strong><mark>negative trade expectations</u></strong></mark> may <u><mark>generate tensions leading to <strong>trade wars</strong></mark> among interdependent states <mark>that</u></mark> in turn <u><strong><mark>increase</strong></mark> the <strong><mark>risk of military conflict</u></strong></mark> (Copeland, 2015: 1, 14, 437; Roach, 2014). The risk may increase if one of the interdependent countries is governed by an inward-looking socio-economic coalition (Solingen, 2015); second, the risk of war between China and the US should not just be analysed bilaterally but include their allies and partners. Third party countries could drag China or the US into confrontation; third, in this context it is of some comfort that the three main economic powers in Northeast Asia (China, Japan and South Korea) are all deeply integrated economically through production networks within a global system of trade and finance (Ravenhill, 2014; Yoshimatsu, 2014: 576); and fourth, <u>decisions for war</u> and peace <u>are taken by very few people, who act on the basis of their future expectations</u>. International relations theory must be supplemented by foreign policy analysis in order to assess the value attributed by national decision-makers to economic development and their assessments of risks and opportunities. <u><mark>If leaders</u></mark> on either side of the Atlantic <u>begin to <mark>seriously</mark> <strong>fear or <mark>anticipate </mark>their own nation’s <mark>decline</u></strong></mark> then <u><mark>they may blame</u></mark> this on <u><strong><mark>external dependence</strong></mark>, appeal to <strong>anti-foreign sentiments</strong>, contemplate the use of <strong>force</strong> to gain</u> respect or <u>credibility, adopt protectionist policies, <mark>and</u></mark> ultimately <u><strong><mark>refuse to be deterred by</u></strong></mark> either <u><strong><mark>nuclear arms</strong></mark> or prospects of socioeconomic calamities. Such a dangerous shift could happen <strong>abruptly</u></strong>, i.e. under the instigation of actions by a third party – or against a third party.</p><p>Yet as long as there is both nuclear deterrence and interdependence, the tensions <u>in East Asia</u> are unlikely to escalate to war. As Chan (2013) says, all states in the region are aware that they cannot count on support from either China or the US if they make provocative moves. <u><mark>The greatest risk is</mark> <strong>not</u></strong> that <u><strong>a territorial dispute</u></strong> leads to war under present circumstances <u>but <mark>that <strong>changes in the world economy</strong></mark> alter those circumstances in ways that <mark>render <strong>inter-state peace</strong></mark> more <strong><mark>precarious</u></strong></mark>. If China and the US fail to rebalance their financial and trading relations (Roach, 2014) then a trade war could result, interrupting transnational production networks, provoking social distress, and exacerbating nationalist emotions. <u>This could have unforeseen consequences in the field of security, with nuclear deterrence remaining the only factor to protect the world from Armageddon, and unreliably so. <mark>Deterrence could <strong>lose</mark> its <mark>credibility</u></strong></mark>: one of the two <u><mark>great powers might <strong>gamble</strong></mark> that the other yield <mark>in a cyber</mark>-war <mark>or conventional</u></mark> limited <u><mark>war</u></mark>, or third party countries might engage in conflict with each other, with a view to obliging Washington or Beijing to intervene.</p>
1AC BIT—BVW Birzer-Narayanan
1AC Park v1.0
1AC—FDI
142
3,586
125,651
./documents/hspolicy16/BlueValleyWest/BiNa/Blue%20Valley%20West-Birzer-Narayanan-Aff-Washburn%20Rural-Quarters.docx
654,592
A
Washburn Rural
Quarters
Blue Valley Southwest Khan-Lowe
Brian Box, Nick Schroeder, Zoe Crater
*1AC* Park - Washburn Rural Quarters *1NC* Mattei K T - Not QPQ Russia Econ DA Advantage CP Xi Good DA Japan DA JASTA Politics DA Dedev *2NR* T - Not QPQ Dedev
hspolicy16/BlueValleyWest/BiNa/Blue%20Valley%20West-Birzer-Narayanan-Aff-Washburn%20Rural-Quarters.docx
null
55,456
BiNa
Blue Valley West BiNa
null
Da.....
Bi.....
Sr.....
Na.....
20,045
BlueValleyWest
Blue Valley West
null
null
1,015
hspolicy16
HS Policy 2016-17
2,016
cx
hs
2
3,626,516
2. Uncertainty and social contract require governments use util. Gooden 95
Gooden, 1995 (Robert, philsopher at the Research School of the Social Sciences, Utilitarianism as Public Philosophy. P. 62-63)
Gooden, 1995 (Robert, philsopher at the Research School of the Social Sciences, Utilitarianism as Public Philosophy. P. 62-63)
Public officials are obliged to make their choices under uncertainty, All choices—public and private alike—are made under some degree of uncertainty, But in the nature of things, private individuals will usually have more complete information on the peculiarities of their own circumstances Public officials, in contrast, are relatively poorly informed as to the effects that their choices will have on individuals, one by one. What they typically do know are generalities: averages and aggregates. They know what will happen most often to most people as a result of their various possible choices That is enough to allow public policy-makers to use the utilitarian calculus to choose general rules of conduct. Knowing aggregates and averages, they can proceed to calculate the utility payoffs from adopting each alternative possible general rules.
officials make choices under uncertainty private individuals have more complete information officials typically know aggregates what will happen most often to most people as a result of choices That is enough to allow util to choose general rules Knowing aggregates they can calculate utility payoffs
Consider, first, the argument from necessity. Public officials are obliged to make their choices under uncertainty, and uncertainty of a very special sort at that. All choices—public and private alike—are made under some degree of uncertainty, of course. But in the nature of things, private individuals will usually have more complete information on the peculiarities of their own circumstances and on the ramifications that alternative possible choices might have on them. Public officials, in contrast, are relatively poorly informed as to the effects that their choices will have on individuals, one by one. What they typically do know are generalities: averages and aggregates. They know what will happen most often to most people as a result of their various possible choices. But that is all. That is enough to allow public policy-makers to use the utilitarian calculus—if they want to use it at all—to choose general rules of conduct. Knowing aggregates and averages, they can proceed to calculate the utility payoffs from adopting each alternative possible general rules.
1,089
<h4><strong>2. Uncertainty and social contract require governments use util. Gooden 95</h4><p>Gooden, 1995 (Robert, philsopher at the Research School of the Social Sciences, Utilitarianism as Public Philosophy. P. 62-63)</p><p></strong>Consider, first, the argument from necessity. <u><strong>Public <mark>officials</mark> are obliged to <mark>make</mark> their <mark>choices under uncertainty</mark>,</strong> </u>and uncertainty of a very special sort at that. <u><strong>All choices—public and private alike—are made under some degree of uncertainty</strong>,</u> of course. <u><strong>But in the nature of things, <mark>private individuals</mark> will usually <mark>have more complete information</u></mark> <u>on the peculiarities of their own circumstances</u></strong> and on the ramifications that alternative possible choices might have on them. <u><strong>Public <mark>officials</mark>, in contrast, are relatively poorly informed as to the effects that their choices will have on individuals, one by one. What they <mark>typically</mark> do <mark>know</mark> are generalities: averages and <mark>aggregates</mark>. They know <mark>what will happen most often to most people as a result of</mark> their various possible <mark>choices</u></strong></mark>. But that is all. <u><strong><mark>That is enough to allow</mark> public policy-makers to use the <mark>util</mark>itarian calculus</u></strong>—if they want to use it at all—<u><mark>to <strong>choose general rules</mark> of conduct. <mark>Knowing aggregates</mark> and averages, <mark>they can</mark> proceed to <mark>calculate</mark> the <mark>utility payoffs</mark> from adopting each alternative possible general rules.</p></u></strong>
null
Framework
null
52,191
601
120,628
./documents/hsld17/HarvardWestlake/Kl/Harvard%20Westlake-Klink-Aff-Berkeley-Round1.docx
807,235
A
Berkeley
1
Mission San Jose TW
David Dosch
1AC - Discretion NC - Reform CP Court Clog case turns NR - All
hsld17/HarvardWestlake/Kl/Harvard%20Westlake-Klink-Aff-Berkeley-Round1.docx
null
69,181
SpKl
Harvard Westlake SpKl
null
Sp.....
Kl.....
null
null
23,454
HarvardWestlake
Harvard Westlake
null
null
1,025
hsld17
HS LD 2017-18
2,017
ld
hs
1
2,596,904
Extinction outweighs
Bostrom 12
Bostrom 12 [Nick Bostrom, Faculty of Philosophy & Oxford Martin School University of Oxford. Existential Risk Prevention as Global Priority. 2012. www.existential-risk.org/concept.html]
moral uncertainty suggest an alternative, complementary way of looking at existential risk Our present understanding of axiology might well be confused We may not now know what outcomes would count as a big win for humanity If we are indeed profoundly uncertain about our ultimate aims there is a great option value in preserving our ability to recognize value and to steer the future accordingly Ensuring that there will be a future version of humanity is the best way available to us to increase the probability that the future will contain a lot of value To do this, we must prevent any existential catastrophe
moral uncertainty suggest an alternative way of looking at existential risk Our present understanding of axiology might be confused. We may not now know what outcomes would count as a win If we are uncertain about ultimate aims there is a great value in preserving ability to recognize value and to steer the future Ensuring there will be future humanity is the best way to increase probability the future will contain value To do this, we must prevent existential catastrophe
These reflections on moral uncertainty suggest an alternative, complementary way of looking at existential risk; they also suggest a new way of thinking about the ideal of sustainability. Let me elaborate. Our present understanding of axiology might well be confused. We may not now know — at least not in concrete detail — what outcomes would count as a big win for humanity; we might not even yet be able to imagine the best ends of our journey. If we are indeed profoundly uncertain about our ultimate aims, then we should recognize that there is a great option value in preserving — and ideally improving — our ability to recognize value and to steer the future accordingly. Ensuring that there will be a future version of humanity with great powers and a propensity to use them wisely is plausibly the best way available to us to increase the probability that the future will contain a lot of value. To do this, we must prevent any existential catastrophe.
961
<h4>Extinction outweighs</h4><p><strong>Bostrom 12</strong> [Nick Bostrom, Faculty of Philosophy & Oxford Martin School University of Oxford. Existential Risk Prevention as Global Priority. 2012. www.existential-risk.org/concept.html]</p><p>These reflections on <u><strong><mark>moral uncertainty</strong> suggest an alternative</mark>, complementary <mark>way of looking at existential risk</u></mark>; they also suggest a new way of thinking about the ideal of sustainability. Let me elaborate.</p><p><u><mark>Our <strong>present understanding</strong> of <strong>axiology</strong> might</mark> well <mark>be <strong>confused</u></strong>. <u>We <strong>may not now know</u></strong></mark> — at least not in concrete detail — <u><mark>what outcomes would count as a</mark> big <mark>win</mark> for humanity</u>; we might not even yet be able to imagine the best ends of our journey. <u><strong><mark>If we are</strong></mark> indeed profoundly <strong><mark>uncertain</strong> about</mark> our <strong><mark>ultimate aims</u></strong></mark>, then we should recognize that <u><mark>there is a great</mark> option <mark>value in <strong>preserving</u></strong></mark> — and ideally improving — <u>our <mark>ability to <strong>recognize value</strong> and to <strong>steer the future</strong></mark> accordingly</u>. <u><strong><mark>Ensuring</strong></mark> that <mark>there will be</mark> a <strong><mark>future</strong></mark> version of <strong><mark>humanity</u></strong></mark> with great powers and a propensity to use them wisely <u><mark>is</u></mark> plausibly <u><mark>the best way</mark> available to us <mark>to <strong>increase</strong></mark> the <strong><mark>probability</strong></mark> that <mark>the future <strong>will contain</strong></mark> a lot of <strong><mark>value</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>To do this, <strong>we must prevent</strong></mark> any <strong><mark>existential catastrophe</u></strong></mark>.</p>
***1NC***
Case
Extinction First---1NC
15,765
1,693
83,119
./documents/ndtceda19/Northwestern/JaWe/Northwestern-Jankovsky-Weideman-Neg-Harvard-Round6.docx
614,604
N
Harvard
6
George Mason BG
Flynn Makuch
1AC - Sats Bad 1NC - T and Case Turns 2NC - T and Case Turn
ndtceda19/Northwestern/JaWe/Northwestern-Jankovsky-Weideman-Neg-Harvard-Round6.docx
null
52,035
JaWe
Northwestern JaWe
null
Ga.....
Ja.....
Jo.....
We.....
19,277
Northwestern
Northwestern
null
null
1,009
ndtceda19
NDT/CEDA 2019-20
2,019
cx
college
2
3,968,745
Unchecked warming causes extinction.
Kareiva 18
Kareiva 18
Peter, Ph.D. in ecology and applied mathematics from Cornell University, director of the Institute of the Environment and Sustainability at UCLA, Pritzker Distinguished Professor in Environment & Sustainability at UCLA, et al., September 2018, “Existential risk due to ecosystem collapse: Nature strikes back,” Futures, Vol. 102, p. 39-50 climate change, global freshwater cycle, and ocean acidification pose existential risks This is because of intrinsic positive feedback loops, substantial lag times between system change and experiencing the consequences of that change, and the fact these different boundaries interact with one another in ways that yield surprises climate, freshwater, and ocean acidification are all directly connected to the provision of food and water, and shortages create conflict and social unrest Climate change has a long history of disrupting civilizations and sometimes precipitating the collapse of cultures or mass emigrations Climate change intersects with freshwater resources because it is expected to exacerbate drought and water scarcity, as well as flooding Climate change can even impair water quality because it is associated with heavy rains that overwhelm sewage treatment facilities, or because it results in higher concentrations of pollutants Ample clean water is essential for human survival. cities, regions and nations that lack clean freshwater are vulnerable to social disruption and disease ocean acidification is linked to climate change because it is driven by CO2 emissions just as global warming is. With close to 20% of protein coming from oceans the potential for severe impacts due to acidification is obvious Acidification is known to interfere with oyster reef building and coral reefs Climate change also increases storm frequency and severity. Coral reefs and oyster reefs provide protection from storm surge because they reduce wave energy If these reefs are lost due to acidification at the same time as storms become more severe and sea level rises coastal communities will be exposed to unprecedented storm surge and may be ravaged by recurrent storms Society will have a hard time responding to shorter intervals between rare extreme events because in the lifespan of an individual human, a person might experience as few as two or three extreme events The disruptive flooding of New York City associated with Hurricane Sandy represented a flood height that occurred once every 500 years and that occurs now once every 25 years, but is expected to occur once every 5 years by 2050 Humans are remarkably ingenious, and have adapted to crises throughout their history However, the many stories of human ingenuity successfully addressing existential risks represent environmental challenges that are largely linear, have immediate consequences, and operate without positive feedbacks. In contrast, today’s great environmental crisis of climate change may cause some harm but there are generally long time delays between rising CO2 concentrations and damage to humans The consequence of these delays are an absence of urgency unlike past environmental challenges, the Earth’s climate system is rife with positive feedback loops In particular, as CO2 increases and the climate warms, that very warming can cause more CO2 release which further increases global warming, and then more CO2, and so on feedbacks can be neatly categorized into carbon cycle, biogeochemical, biogeophysical, cloud, ice-albedo, and water vapor feedbacks as CO2 accumulates, it reduces the efficiency in which oceans and terrestrial ecosystems sequester carbon, which in return feeds back to exacerbate climate change overgrazing depletes the soil, leading to augmented vegetation loss Climate change often also increases the risk of forest fires The expectation is that forest fires will become more frequent and severe with climate warming and drought This catastrophic fire embodies the sorts of positive feedbacks and interacting factors that could catch humanity off-guard and produce a true apocalyptic event The key lesson from the long list of potentially positive feedbacks and their interactions is that runaway climate change, and runaway perturbations have to be taken as a serious possibility this list is not exhaustive and the possibility of undiscovered positive feedbacks portends even greater existential risks The many environmental crises humankind has previously averted were averted because of political will based on solid scientific understanding. We cannot count on complete scientific understanding when it comes to positive feedback loops and climate change.
climate change and ocean acidification pose existential risks because of feedback loops lag times and surprises connected to food and water shortages create conflict flooding can overwhelm sewage treatment nations are vulnerable to disease Acidification interfere with reefs today’s crisis are The consequence of an absence of urgency the climate is rife with positive feedback loops could catch humanity off-guard and produce apocalyptic event runaway climate change take as a serious possibility possibility of undiscovered feedbacks portends greater existential risks
Peter, Ph.D. in ecology and applied mathematics from Cornell University, director of the Institute of the Environment and Sustainability at UCLA, Pritzker Distinguished Professor in Environment & Sustainability at UCLA, et al., September 2018, “Existential risk due to ecosystem collapse: Nature strikes back,” Futures, Vol. 102, p. 39-50 In summary, six of the nine proposed planetary boundaries (phosphorous, nitrogen, biodiversity, land use, atmospheric aerosol loading, and chemical pollution) are unlikely to be associated with existential risks. They all correspond to a degraded environment, but in our assessment do not represent existential risks. However, the three remaining boundaries (climate change, global freshwater cycle, and ocean acidification) do pose existential risks. This is because of intrinsic positive feedback loops, substantial lag times between system change and experiencing the consequences of that change, and the fact these different boundaries interact with one another in ways that yield surprises. In addition, climate, freshwater, and ocean acidification are all directly connected to the provision of food and water, and shortages of food and water can create conflict and social unrest. Climate change has a long history of disrupting civilizations and sometimes precipitating the collapse of cultures or mass emigrations (McMichael, 2017). For example, the 12th century drought in the North American Southwest is held responsible for the collapse of the Anasazi pueblo culture. More recently, the infamous potato famine of 1846–1849 and the large migration of Irish to the U.S. can be traced to a combination of factors, one of which was climate. Specifically, 1846 was an unusually warm and moist year in Ireland, providing the climatic conditions favorable to the fungus that caused the potato blight. As is so often the case, poor government had a role as well—as the British government forbade the import of grains from outside Britain (imports that could have helped to redress the ravaged potato yields). Climate change intersects with freshwater resources because it is expected to exacerbate drought and water scarcity, as well as flooding. Climate change can even impair water quality because it is associated with heavy rains that overwhelm sewage treatment facilities, or because it results in higher concentrations of pollutants in groundwater as a result of enhanced evaporation and reduced groundwater recharge. Ample clean water is not a luxury—it is essential for human survival. Consequently, cities, regions and nations that lack clean freshwater are vulnerable to social disruption and disease. Finally, ocean acidification is linked to climate change because it is driven by CO2 emissions just as global warming is. With close to 20% of the world’s protein coming from oceans (FAO, 2016), the potential for severe impacts due to acidification is obvious. Less obvious, but perhaps more insidious, is the interaction between climate change and the loss of oyster and coral reefs due to acidification. Acidification is known to interfere with oyster reef building and coral reefs. Climate change also increases storm frequency and severity. Coral reefs and oyster reefs provide protection from storm surge because they reduce wave energy (Spalding et al., 2014). If these reefs are lost due to acidification at the same time as storms become more severe and sea level rises, coastal communities will be exposed to unprecedented storm surge—and may be ravaged by recurrent storms. A key feature of the risk associated with climate change is that mean annual temperature and mean annual rainfall are not the variables of interest. Rather it is extreme episodic events that place nations and entire regions of the world at risk. These extreme events are by definition “rare” (once every hundred years), and changes in their likelihood are challenging to detect because of their rarity, but are exactly the manifestations of climate change that we must get better at anticipating (Diffenbaugh et al., 2017). Society will have a hard time responding to shorter intervals between rare extreme events because in the lifespan of an individual human, a person might experience as few as two or three extreme events. How likely is it that you would notice a change in the interval between events that are separated by decades, especially given that the interval is not regular but varies stochastically? A concrete example of this dilemma can be found in the past and expected future changes in storm-related flooding of New York City. The highly disruptive flooding of New York City associated with Hurricane Sandy represented a flood height that occurred once every 500 years in the 18th century, and that occurs now once every 25 years, but is expected to occur once every 5 years by 2050 (Garner et al., 2017). This change in frequency of extreme floods has profound implications for the measures New York City should take to protect its infrastructure and its population, yet because of the stochastic nature of such events, this shift in flood frequency is an elevated risk that will go unnoticed by most people. 4. The combination of positive feedback loops and societal inertia is fertile ground for global environmental catastrophes. Humans are remarkably ingenious, and have adapted to crises throughout their history. Our doom has been repeatedly predicted, only to be averted by innovation (Ridley, 2011). However, the many stories of human ingenuity successfully addressing existential risks such as global famine or extreme air pollution represent environmental challenges that are largely linear, have immediate consequences, and operate without positive feedbacks. For example, the fact that food is in short supply does not increase the rate at which humans consume food—thereby increasing the shortage. Similarly, massive air pollution episodes such as the London fog of 1952 that killed 12,000 people did not make future air pollution events more likely. In fact it was just the opposite—the London fog sent such a clear message that Britain quickly enacted pollution control measures (Stradling, 2016). Food shortages, air pollution, water pollution, etc. send immediate signals to society of harm, which then trigger a negative feedback of society seeking to reduce the harm. In contrast, today’s great environmental crisis of climate change may cause some harm but there are generally long time delays between rising CO2 concentrations and damage to humans. The consequence of these delays are an absence of urgency; thus although 70% of Americans believe global warming is happening, only 40% think it will harm them (http://climatecommunication.yale.edu/visualizations-data/ycom-us-2016/). Secondly, unlike past environmental challenges, the Earth’s climate system is rife with positive feedback loops. In particular, as CO2 increases and the climate warms, that very warming can cause more CO2 release which further increases global warming, and then more CO2, and so on. Table 2 summarizes the best documented positive feedback loops for the Earth’s climate system. These feedbacks can be neatly categorized into carbon cycle, biogeochemical, biogeophysical, cloud, ice-albedo, and water vapor feedbacks. As important as it is to understand these feedbacks individually, it is even more essential to study the interactive nature of these feedbacks. Modeling studies show that when interactions among feedback loops are included, uncertainty increases dramatically and there is a heightened potential for perturbations to be magnified (e.g., Cox, Betts, Jones, Spall, & Totterdell, 2000; Hajima, Tachiiri, Ito, & Kawamiya, 2014; Knutti & Rugenstein, 2015; Rosenfeld, Sherwood, Wood, & Donner, 2014). This produces a wide range of future scenarios. Positive feedbacks in the carbon cycle involves the enhancement of future carbon contributions to the atmosphere due to some initial increase in atmospheric CO2. This happens because as CO2 accumulates, it reduces the efficiency in which oceans and terrestrial ecosystems sequester carbon, which in return feeds back to exacerbate climate change (Friedlingstein et al., 2001). Warming can also increase the rate at which organic matter decays and carbon is released into the atmosphere, thereby causing more warming (Melillo et al., 2017). Increases in food shortages and lack of water is also of major concern when biogeophysical feedback mechanisms perpetuate drought conditions. The underlying mechanism here is that losses in vegetation increases the surface albedo, which suppresses rainfall, and thus enhances future vegetation loss and more suppression of rainfall—thereby initiating or prolonging a drought (Chamey, Stone, & Quirk, 1975). To top it off, overgrazing depletes the soil, leading to augmented vegetation loss (Anderies, Janssen, & Walker, 2002). Climate change often also increases the risk of forest fires, as a result of higher temperatures and persistent drought conditions. The expectation is that forest fires will become more frequent and severe with climate warming and drought (Scholze, Knorr, Arnell, & Prentice, 2006), a trend for which we have already seen evidence (Allen et al., 2010). Tragically, the increased severity and risk of Southern California wildfires recently predicted by climate scientists (Jin et al., 2015), was realized in December 2017, with the largest fire in the history of California (the “Thomas fire” that burned 282,000 acres, https://www.vox.com/2017/12/27/16822180/thomas-fire-california-largest-wildfire). This catastrophic fire embodies the sorts of positive feedbacks and interacting factors that could catch humanity off-guard and produce a true apocalyptic event. Record-breaking rains produced an extraordinary flush of new vegetation, that then dried out as record heat waves and dry conditions took hold, coupled with stronger than normal winds, and ignition. Of course the record-fire released CO2 into the atmosphere, thereby contributing to future warming. Out of all types of feedbacks, water vapor and the ice-albedo feedbacks are the most clearly understood mechanisms. Losses in reflective snow and ice cover drive up surface temperatures, leading to even more melting of snow and ice cover—this is known as the ice-albedo feedback (Curry, Schramm, & Ebert, 1995). As snow and ice continue to melt at a more rapid pace, millions of people may be displaced by flooding risks as a consequence of sea level rise near coastal communities (Biermann & Boas, 2010; Myers, 2002; Nicholls et al., 2011). The water vapor feedback operates when warmer atmospheric conditions strengthen the saturation vapor pressure, which creates a warming effect given water vapor’s strong greenhouse gas properties (Manabe & Wetherald, 1967). Global warming tends to increase cloud formation because warmer temperatures lead to more evaporation of water into the atmosphere, and warmer temperature also allows the atmosphere to hold more water. The key question is whether this increase in clouds associated with global warming will result in a positive feedback loop (more warming) or a negative feedback loop (less warming). For decades, scientists have sought to answer this question and understand the net role clouds play in future climate projections (Schneider et al., 2017). Clouds are complex because they both have a cooling (reflecting incoming solar radiation) and warming (absorbing incoming solar radiation) effect (Lashof, DeAngelo, Saleska, & Harte, 1997). The type of cloud, altitude, and optical properties combine to determine how these countervailing effects balance out. Although still under debate, it appears that in most circumstances the cloud feedback is likely positive (Boucher et al., 2013). For example, models and observations show that increasing greenhouse gas concentrations reduces the low-level cloud fraction in the Northeast Pacific at decadal time scales. This then has a positive feedback effect and enhances climate warming since less solar radiation is reflected by the atmosphere (Clement, Burgman, & Norris, 2009). The key lesson from the long list of potentially positive feedbacks and their interactions is that runaway climate change, and runaway perturbations have to be taken as a serious possibility. Table 2 is just a snapshot of the type of feedbacks that have been identified (see Supplementary material for a more thorough explanation of positive feedback loops). However, this list is not exhaustive and the possibility of undiscovered positive feedbacks portends even greater existential risks. The many environmental crises humankind has previously averted (famine, ozone depletion, London fog, water pollution, etc.) were averted because of political will based on solid scientific understanding. We cannot count on complete scientific understanding when it comes to positive feedback loops and climate change.
12,941
<h4><strong>Unchecked warming causes extinction.</h4><p>Kareiva 18</p><p><u></strong>Peter, Ph.D. in ecology and applied mathematics from Cornell University, director of the Institute of the Environment and Sustainability at UCLA, Pritzker Distinguished Professor in Environment & Sustainability at UCLA, et al., September 2018, “Existential risk due to ecosystem collapse: Nature strikes back,” Futures, Vol. 102, p. 39-50</p><p></u>In summary, six of the nine proposed planetary boundaries (phosphorous, nitrogen, biodiversity, land use, atmospheric aerosol loading, and chemical pollution) are unlikely to be associated with existential risks. They all correspond to a degraded environment, but in our assessment do not represent existential risks. However, the three remaining boundaries (<u><mark>climate change</mark>, global freshwater cycle, <mark>and ocean acidification</u></mark>) do <u><mark>pose <strong>existential risks</u></strong></mark>. <u>This is <mark>because of</mark> intrinsic <strong>positive <mark>feedback loops</strong></mark>, substantial <strong><mark>lag times</u></strong></mark> <u>between system change and experiencing the consequences of that change, <mark>and</mark> the fact these different boundaries interact with one another in ways that yield <strong><mark>surprises</u></strong></mark>. In addition, <u>climate, freshwater, and ocean acidification are all directly <mark>connected to</mark> the provision of <strong><mark>food</strong> and <strong>water</strong></mark>, and <mark>shortages</u></mark> of food and water can <u><mark>create <strong>conflict</strong></mark> and social unrest</u>. <u>Climate change has a long history of <strong>disrupting civilizations</u></strong> <u>and sometimes precipitating the <strong>collapse of cultures</u></strong> <u>or mass emigrations</u> (McMichael, 2017). For example, the 12th century drought in the North American Southwest is held responsible for the collapse of the Anasazi pueblo culture. More recently, the infamous potato famine of 1846–1849 and the large migration of Irish to the U.S. can be traced to a combination of factors, one of which was climate. Specifically, 1846 was an unusually warm and moist year in Ireland, providing the climatic conditions favorable to the fungus that caused the potato blight. As is so often the case, poor government had a role as well—as the British government forbade the import of grains from outside Britain (imports that could have helped to redress the ravaged potato yields). <u>Climate change intersects with freshwater resources because it is expected to <strong>exacerbate drought</strong> and</u> <u><strong>water scarcity</strong>, as well as <strong><mark>flooding</u></strong></mark>. <u>Climate change <mark>can</mark> even impair water quality because it is associated with heavy rains that <mark>overwhelm sewage treatment</mark> facilities, or because it results in higher concentrations of pollutants</u> in groundwater as a result of enhanced evaporation and reduced groundwater recharge. <u>Ample clean water</u> is not a luxury—it <u>is essential for human survival.</u> Consequently, <u>cities, regions and <mark>nations</mark> that lack clean freshwater <mark>are vulnerable to</mark> social disruption and <strong><mark>disease</u></strong></mark>. Finally, <u>ocean acidification is linked to climate change because it is driven by CO2 emissions just as global warming is. With close to 20% of</u> the world’s <u>protein coming from oceans</u> (FAO, 2016), <u>the potential for severe impacts due to acidification is obvious</u>. Less obvious, but perhaps more insidious, is the interaction between climate change and the loss of oyster and coral reefs due to acidification. <u><mark>Acidification</mark> is known to <mark>interfere with</mark> oyster reef building and <strong>coral <mark>reefs</u></strong></mark>. <u>Climate change also increases <strong>storm frequency</strong> and severity. Coral reefs and oyster reefs provide protection from storm surge because they reduce wave energy</u> (Spalding et al., 2014). <u>If these reefs are lost due to acidification at the same time as storms become more severe and sea level rises</u>, <u><strong>coastal communities will be exposed to unprecedented storm surge</u></strong>—<u>and may be ravaged by recurrent storms</u>. A key feature of the risk associated with climate change is that mean annual temperature and mean annual rainfall are not the variables of interest. Rather it is extreme episodic events that place nations and entire regions of the world at risk. These extreme events are by definition “rare” (once every hundred years), and changes in their likelihood are challenging to detect because of their rarity, but are exactly the manifestations of climate change that we must get better at anticipating (Diffenbaugh et al., 2017). <u>Society will have a hard time responding to shorter intervals between rare extreme events because in the lifespan of an individual human, a person might experience as few as two or three <strong>extreme events</u></strong>. How likely is it that you would notice a change in the interval between events that are separated by decades, especially given that the interval is not regular but varies stochastically? A concrete example of this dilemma can be found in the past and expected future changes in storm-related flooding of New York City. <u>The</u> highly <u>disruptive flooding of New York City associated with Hurricane Sandy represented a flood height that occurred once every 500 years</u> in the 18th century, <u>and that occurs now once every 25 years, but is expected to occur once every 5 years by 2050</u> (Garner et al., 2017). This change in frequency of extreme floods has profound implications for the measures New York City should take to protect its infrastructure and its population, yet because of the stochastic nature of such events, this shift in flood frequency is an elevated risk that will go unnoticed by most people. 4. The combination of positive feedback loops and societal inertia is fertile ground for global environmental catastrophes. <u>Humans are remarkably ingenious, and have <strong>adapted</strong> to crises throughout their history</u>. Our doom has been repeatedly predicted, only to be averted by innovation (Ridley, 2011). <u>However, the many stories of human ingenuity successfully addressing existential risks</u> such as global famine or extreme air pollution <u>represent environmental challenges that are largely linear, have immediate consequences, and operate without positive feedbacks.</u> For example, the fact that food is in short supply does not increase the rate at which humans consume food—thereby increasing the shortage. Similarly, massive air pollution episodes such as the London fog of 1952 that killed 12,000 people did not make future air pollution events more likely. In fact it was just the opposite—the London fog sent such a clear message that Britain quickly enacted pollution control measures (Stradling, 2016). Food shortages, air pollution, water pollution, etc. send immediate signals to society of harm, which then trigger a negative feedback of society seeking to reduce the harm. <u>In contrast, <mark>today’s</mark> great environmental <mark>crisis</mark> of climate change may cause some harm but there <mark>are</mark> generally <strong>long time delays</u></strong> <u>between rising CO2 concentrations and damage to humans</u>. <u><mark>The consequence</mark> <mark>of</mark> these delays are <mark>an <strong>absence of urgency</u></strong></mark>; thus although 70% of Americans believe global warming is happening, only 40% think it will harm them (http://climatecommunication.yale.edu/visualizations-data/ycom-us-2016/). Secondly, <u>unlike past environmental challenges, <strong><mark>the</mark> Earth’s <mark>climate </mark>system <mark>is rife with positive feedback loops</u></strong></mark>. <u>In particular, as CO2 increases and the climate warms, that very warming can cause more CO2 release which further increases global warming, and then more CO2, and so on</u>. Table 2 summarizes the best documented positive feedback loops for the Earth’s climate system. These <u>feedbacks can be neatly categorized into <strong>carbon cycle</strong>, <strong>biogeochemical</strong>, <strong>biogeophysical</strong>, <strong>cloud</strong>, <strong>ice-albedo</strong>, and <strong>water vapor</strong> feedbacks</u>. As important as it is to understand these feedbacks individually, it is even more essential to study the interactive nature of these feedbacks. Modeling studies show that when interactions among feedback loops are included, uncertainty increases dramatically and there is a heightened potential for perturbations to be magnified (e.g., Cox, Betts, Jones, Spall, & Totterdell, 2000; Hajima, Tachiiri, Ito, & Kawamiya, 2014; Knutti & Rugenstein, 2015; Rosenfeld, Sherwood, Wood, & Donner, 2014). This produces a wide range of future scenarios. Positive feedbacks in the carbon cycle involves the enhancement of future carbon contributions to the atmosphere due to some initial increase in atmospheric CO2. This happens because <u>as CO2 accumulates, it reduces the efficiency in which oceans and terrestrial ecosystems sequester carbon, which in return feeds back to exacerbate climate change</u> (Friedlingstein et al., 2001). Warming can also increase the rate at which organic matter decays and carbon is released into the atmosphere, thereby causing more warming (Melillo et al., 2017). Increases in food shortages and lack of water is also of major concern when biogeophysical feedback mechanisms perpetuate drought conditions. The underlying mechanism here is that losses in vegetation increases the surface albedo, which suppresses rainfall, and thus enhances future vegetation loss and more suppression of rainfall—thereby initiating or prolonging a drought (Chamey, Stone, & Quirk, 1975). To top it off, <u>overgrazing depletes the soil, leading to augmented <strong>vegetation loss</u></strong> (Anderies, Janssen, & Walker, 2002). <u>Climate change often also increases the risk of <strong>forest fires</u></strong>, as a result of higher temperatures and persistent drought conditions. <u>The expectation is that forest fires will become more frequent and severe with climate warming and drought</u> (Scholze, Knorr, Arnell, & Prentice, 2006), a trend for which we have already seen evidence (Allen et al., 2010). Tragically, the increased severity and risk of Southern California wildfires recently predicted by climate scientists (Jin et al., 2015), was realized in December 2017, with the largest fire in the history of California (the “Thomas fire” that burned 282,000 acres, https://www.vox.com/2017/12/27/16822180/thomas-fire-california-largest-wildfire). <u>This catastrophic fire embodies the sorts of positive feedbacks and interacting factors that <mark>could</mark> <strong><mark>catch humanity off-guard</u></strong> <u>and produce</mark> a true <strong><mark>apocalyptic event</u></strong></mark>. Record-breaking rains produced an extraordinary flush of new vegetation, that then dried out as record heat waves and dry conditions took hold, coupled with stronger than normal winds, and ignition. Of course the record-fire released CO2 into the atmosphere, thereby contributing to future warming. Out of all types of feedbacks, water vapor and the ice-albedo feedbacks are the most clearly understood mechanisms. Losses in reflective snow and ice cover drive up surface temperatures, leading to even more melting of snow and ice cover—this is known as the ice-albedo feedback (Curry, Schramm, & Ebert, 1995). As snow and ice continue to melt at a more rapid pace, millions of people may be displaced by flooding risks as a consequence of sea level rise near coastal communities (Biermann & Boas, 2010; Myers, 2002; Nicholls et al., 2011). The water vapor feedback operates when warmer atmospheric conditions strengthen the saturation vapor pressure, which creates a warming effect given water vapor’s strong greenhouse gas properties (Manabe & Wetherald, 1967). Global warming tends to increase cloud formation because warmer temperatures lead to more evaporation of water into the atmosphere, and warmer temperature also allows the atmosphere to hold more water. The key question is whether this increase in clouds associated with global warming will result in a positive feedback loop (more warming) or a negative feedback loop (less warming). For decades, scientists have sought to answer this question and understand the net role clouds play in future climate projections (Schneider et al., 2017). Clouds are complex because they both have a cooling (reflecting incoming solar radiation) and warming (absorbing incoming solar radiation) effect (Lashof, DeAngelo, Saleska, & Harte, 1997). The type of cloud, altitude, and optical properties combine to determine how these countervailing effects balance out. Although still under debate, it appears that in most circumstances the cloud feedback is likely positive (Boucher et al., 2013). For example, models and observations show that increasing greenhouse gas concentrations reduces the low-level cloud fraction in the Northeast Pacific at decadal time scales. This then has a positive feedback effect and enhances climate warming since less solar radiation is reflected by the atmosphere (Clement, Burgman, & Norris, 2009). <u>The key lesson from the long list of potentially positive feedbacks and their interactions is that</u> <u><strong><mark>runaway climate change</strong></mark>, and runaway perturbations have to be <mark>take</mark>n <mark>as a serious possibility</u></mark>. Table 2 is just a snapshot of the type of feedbacks that have been identified (see Supplementary material for a more thorough explanation of positive feedback loops). However, <u>this list is not exhaustive and the <mark>possibility of undiscovered</mark> positive <mark>feedbacks portends <strong></mark>even <mark>greater existential risks</u></strong></mark>. <u>The many environmental crises humankind has previously averted</u> (famine, ozone depletion, London fog, water pollution, etc.) <u>were averted because of political will based on solid scientific understanding.</u> <u>We cannot count on complete scientific understanding when it comes to positive feedback loops and climate change.</p></u>
1AC --- NDT
null
null
1,435
1,599
134,120
./documents/ndtceda21/UTD/SeKa/UTD-Sendejas-Karchmer-Aff-CEDA-Round2.docx
627,572
A
CEDA
2
NYU LS
DML
1ac-SDG's 2nr-Cap
ndtceda21/UTD/SeKa/UTD-Sendejas-Karchmer-Aff-CEDA-Round2.docx
null
52,918
SeKa
UTD SeKa
null
Ad.....
Se.....
Ar.....
Ka.....
19,424
UTD
UTD
null
null
1,011
ndtceda21
NDT/CEDA 2021-22
2,021
cx
college
2
2,671,268
Economic decline causes nuclear war
Mann 14 )
Mann 14 (Eric Mann is a special agent with a United States federal agency, with significant domestic and international counterintelligence and counter-terrorism experience. Worked as a special assistant for a U.S. Senator and served as a presidential appointee for the U.S. Congress. He is currently responsible for an internal security and vulnerability assessment program. Bachelors @ University of South Carolina, Graduate degree in Homeland Security @ Georgetown. “AUSTERITY, ECONOMIC DECLINE, AND FINANCIAL WEAPONS OF WAR: A NEW PARADIGM FOR GLOBAL SECURITY,” May 2014, https://jscholarship.library.jhu.edu/bitstream/handle/1774.2/37262/MANN-THESIS-2014.pdf)
economic considerations within states can figure prominently into the calculus for future conflicts security issues with economic or financial underpinnings will transcend classical determinants of war and conflict, and change the manner by which rival states engage in hostile acts toward one another security concerns emanating from economic uncertainty and the inherent vulnerabilities within global financial markets will present new challenges for national security, and provide developing states new asymmetric options for balancing against stronger states. The security areas are likely to mature into global security threats in the immediate future the overlapping security issues associated with economic decline and reduced military spending by the United States will affect allied confidence in America’s security guarantees this outcome could cause regional instability or realignments of strategic partnerships in the Asia-pacific region with ramifications for U.S. national security Rival states and non-state groups may also become emboldened to challenge America’s status The potential risks associated with stolen or loose WMD resulting from poor security, can also pose a threat to U.S. national security financial constraints affect weapons security making weapons vulnerable to theft, and how financial factors can influence WMD proliferation inherent vulnerabilities within the global financial markets will provide terrorists’ organizations and other non-state groups with opportunities to disrupt global finance and perhaps weaken America’s status
economic considerations can figure prominently into future conflicts economic uncertainty will present challenges for national security and states new asymmetric options for balancing against stronger states likely nto global security threats economic decline will affect allied confidence could cause regional instability Rival states may become emboldened to challenge America loose WMD can pose a threat to security financial factors influence prolif vulnerabilities within markets will provide terrorists’ opportunities to weaken America’s status
The conclusions reached in this thesis demonstrate how economic considerations within states can figure prominently into the calculus for future conflicts. The findings also suggest that security issues with economic or financial underpinnings will transcend classical determinants of war and conflict, and change the manner by which rival states engage in hostile acts toward one another. The research shows that security concerns emanating from economic uncertainty and the inherent vulnerabilities within global financial markets will present new challenges for national security, and provide developing states new asymmetric options for balancing against stronger states.¶ The security areas, identified in the proceeding chapters, are likely to mature into global security threats in the immediate future. As the case study on South Korea suggest, the overlapping security issues associated with economic decline and reduced military spending by the United States will affect allied confidence in America’s security guarantees. The study shows that this outcome could cause regional instability or realignments of strategic partnerships in the Asia-pacific region with ramifications for U.S. national security. Rival states and non-state groups may also become emboldened to challenge America’s status in the unipolar international system.¶ The potential risks associated with stolen or loose WMD, resulting from poor security, can also pose a threat to U.S. national security. The case study on Pakistan, Syria and North Korea show how financial constraints affect weapons security making weapons vulnerable to theft, and how financial factors can influence WMD proliferation by contributing to the motivating factors behind a trusted insider’s decision to sell weapons technology. The inherent vulnerabilities within the global financial markets will provide terrorists’ organizations and other non-state groups, who object to the current international system or distribution of power, with opportunities to disrupt global finance and perhaps weaken America’s status. A more ominous threat originates from states intent on increasing diversification of foreign currency holdings, establishing alternatives to the dollar for international trade, or engaging financial warfare against the United States.
2,308
<h4>Economic decline causes nuclear war </h4><p><strong>Mann 14</strong> (Eric Mann is a special agent with a United States federal agency, with significant domestic and international counterintelligence and counter-terrorism experience. Worked as a special assistant for a U.S. Senator and served as a presidential appointee for the U.S. Congress. He is currently responsible for an internal security and vulnerability assessment program. Bachelors @ University of South Carolina, Graduate degree in Homeland Security @ Georgetown. “AUSTERITY, ECONOMIC DECLINE, AND FINANCIAL WEAPONS OF WAR: A NEW PARADIGM FOR GLOBAL SECURITY,” May 2014, https://jscholarship.library.jhu.edu/bitstream/handle/1774.2/37262/MANN-THESIS-2014.pdf<strong>)</p><p></strong>The conclusions reached in this thesis demonstrate how <u><strong><mark>economic considerations</mark> within states <mark>can figure prominently into</mark> the calculus for <mark>future conflicts</u></strong></mark>. The findings also suggest that <u><strong>security issues with economic or financial underpinnings will transcend classical determinants of war and conflict, and change the manner by which rival states engage in hostile acts toward one another</u></strong>. The research shows that <u><strong>security concerns emanating from <mark>economic uncertainty</mark> and the inherent vulnerabilities within global financial markets <mark>will present </mark>new <mark>challenges for national security</mark>, <mark>and</mark> provide developing <mark>states new asymmetric options for balancing</mark> <mark>against stronger states</mark>.</u></strong>¶ <u><strong>The security areas</u></strong>, identified in the proceeding chapters, <u><strong>are <mark>likely </mark>to mature i<mark>nto global security threats</mark> in the immediate future</u></strong>. As the case study on South Korea suggest, <u><strong>the overlapping security issues associated with <mark>economic decline</mark> and reduced military spending by the United States <mark>will affect allied confidence</mark> in America’s security guarantees</u></strong>. The study shows that <u><strong>this outcome <mark>could cause regional instability</mark> or realignments of strategic partnerships in the Asia-pacific region with ramifications for U.S. national security</u></strong>. <u><strong><mark>Rival states</mark> and non-state groups <mark>may</mark> also <mark>become emboldened to challenge America</mark>’s status</u></strong> in the unipolar international system.¶ <u><strong>The potential risks associated with stolen or <mark>loose WMD</u></strong></mark>, <u><strong>resulting from poor security, <mark>can</mark> also <mark>pose a threat to</mark> U.S. national <mark>security</u></strong></mark>. The case study on Pakistan, Syria and North Korea show how <u><strong>financial constraints affect weapons security making weapons vulnerable to theft, and how <mark>financial factors </mark>can <mark>influence </mark>WMD <mark>prolif</mark>eration</u></strong> by contributing to the motivating factors behind a trusted insider’s decision to sell weapons technology. The <u><strong>inherent <mark>vulnerabilities within</mark> the global financial <mark>markets will provide terrorists’</mark> organizations and other non-state groups</u></strong>, who object to the current international system or distribution of power, <u><strong>with <mark>opportunities to</mark> disrupt global finance and perhaps <mark>weaken America’s status</u></strong></mark>. A more ominous threat originates from states intent on increasing diversification of foreign currency holdings, establishing alternatives to the dollar for international trade, or engaging financial warfare against the United States.</p>
1nc
null
4
1,375
1,161
84,724
./documents/ndtceda19/WakeForest/KlMa/Wake%20Forest-Klein-Marban-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
615,939
N
Navy
4
Georgia AW
Wes Rumbaugh
1ac - russia mining 1nc - t stm t with allies CP russia dip cap conviction DA daska DA sea routes DA 2nc - t with daska DA 1nr - dip cap DA 2nr - dip cap DA
ndtceda19/WakeForest/KlMa/Wake%20Forest-Klein-Marban-Neg-Navy-Round4.docx
null
52,124
KlMa
Wake Forest KlMa
null
Ru.....
Kl.....
Al.....
Ma.....
19,292
WakeForest
Wake Forest
null
null
1,009
ndtceda19
NDT/CEDA 2019-20
2,019
cx
college
2
545,241
Should requires action
AHD 2k
AHD 2k
should The will have something take place
should The will have something take place
(American Heritage Dictionary 2000 (Dictionary.com)) should. The will to do something or have something take place: I shall go out if I feel like it.
149
<h4>Should requires <strong>action</h4><p>AHD 2k</p><p></strong>(American Heritage Dictionary 2000 (Dictionary.com))</p><p><u><mark>should</u></mark>. <u><mark>The will </u></mark>to do something or<u><mark> have something take place</u></mark>: I shall go out if I feel like it. </p>
null
1NC
1NC — T
1,185
389
7,773
./documents/ndtceda21/Kansas/SoMa/Kansas-Soper-Mansoor-Neg-Kentucky-Round4.docx
624,683
N
Kentucky
4
Wake Forest BT
Simon Sheaff
1AC - Unyielding Earth 1NC - T Cap K 2NR - T
ndtceda21/Kansas/SoMa/Kansas-Soper-Mansoor-Neg-Kentucky-Round4.docx
null
52,720
SoMa
Kansas SoMa
null
Wi.....
So.....
Za.....
Ma.....
19,391
Kansas
Kansas
null
null
1,011
ndtceda21
NDT/CEDA 2021-22
2,021
cx
college
2
4,571,608
Prefer it – util is impartial, specific to public actors, and resolves infinite regress which explains all value.
Greene 15
Greene 15 — (Joshua Greene, Professor of Psychology @ Harvard, being interviewed by Russ Roberts, “Joshua Greene on Moral Tribes, Moral Dilemmas, and Utilitarianism”, The Library of Economics and Liberty, 1-5-15, Available Online at https://www.econtalk.org/joshua-greene-on-moral-tribes-moral-dilemmas-and-utilitarianism/#audio-highlights, accessed 5-17-20, HKR-AM) **NB: Guest = Greene, and only his lines are highlighted/underlined
utilitarianism is very much misunderstood We should call it what I call 'deep pragmatism' going back to the tragedy of common-sense morality is you've got all these different tribes with all of these different values based on their different ways of life. What can they do to get along In order to resolve any kind of tradeoff, you have to have some kind of common metric. You have to have some kind of common currency. And I think that what utilitarianism, whether it's the moral truth or not, is provide a kind of common currency what is utilitarianism? it's really two ideas put together. One is the idea of impartiality , at least as social decision makers, we should regard everybody's interests as of equal worth. Everybody counts the same. what does it mean to count everybody the same? What is it that really matters for you and for me and for everybody else?' And there the utilitarian's answer is what is sometimes called happiness it's not really happiness in the sense of cherries on sundaes, things that make you smile. It's really the quality of conscious experience. if you start with anything that you value, and say, 'Why do you care about that?' and keep asking you ultimately come down to the quality of someone's conscious experience if I were to say, 'Why did you go to work today?' you'd say, 'Well, I need to make money; and I also enjoy my work.' 'Well, what do you need your money for?' 'Well, I need to have a place to live; it costs money.' 'Well, why can't you just live outside?' 'Well, I need a place to sleep; it's cold at night.' 'Well, what's wrong with being cold?' 'Well, it's uncomfortable.' 'What's wrong with being uncomfortable?' 'It's just bad.' Right? At some point if you keep asking why, why, why, it's going to come down to the conscious experience--in Bentham's terms the pleasure and pain of either you or somebody else that you care about. the utilitarian idea is to say, Okay, we all have our pleasures and pains, and as a moral philosophy we should all count equally. so a good standard for resolving public disagreements is to say we should go with whatever option is going to produce the best overall experience for the people who are affected Which you can think of as shorthand as maximizing happiness one of the biggest criticisms is that utilitarianism doesn't adequately account for people's rights. So I spend a lot of the book trying to understand the psychology of cases like the footbridge case. And you mention these being kind of unrealistic and weird cases. That's actually part of my defense.
util is misunderstood going back to the tragedy of morality you've got tribes with different values based on different ways of life. to resolve tradeoff have some common metric. util is impartiality as social decision makers we should regard everybody's interests as equal What matters for everybody the answer is quality of conscious experience in Bentham's terms the pleasure and pain a good standard for resolving public disagreements is to produce the best overall experience
Guest: Okay. So, I think utilitarianism is very much misunderstood. And this is part of the reason why we shouldn't even call it utilitarianism at all. We should call it what I call 'deep pragmatism', which I think better captures what I think utilitarianism is really like, if you really apply it in real life, in light of an understanding of human nature. But, we can come back to that. The idea, going back to the tragedy of common-sense morality is you've got all these different tribes with all of these different values based on their different ways of life. What can they do to get along? And I think that the best answer that we have is--well, let's back up. In order to resolve any kind of tradeoff, you have to have some kind of common metric. You have to have some kind of common currency. And I think that what utilitarianism, whether it's the moral truth or not, is provide a kind of common currency. So, what is utilitarianism? It's basically the idea that--it's really two ideas put together. One is the idea of impartiality. That is, at least as social decision makers, we should regard everybody's interests as of equal worth. Everybody counts the same. And then you might say, 'Well, but okay, what does it mean to count everybody the same? What is it that really matters for you and for me and for everybody else?' And there the utilitarian's answer is what is sometimes called, somewhat accurately and somewhat misleadingly, happiness. But it's not really happiness in the sense of cherries on sundaes, things that make you smile. It's really the quality of conscious experience. So, the idea is that if you start with anything that you value, and say, 'Why do you care about that?' and keep asking, 'Why do you care about that?' or 'Why do you care about that?' you ultimately come down to the quality of someone's conscious experience. So if I were to say, 'Why did you go to work today?' you'd say, 'Well, I need to make money; and I also enjoy my work.' 'Well, what do you need your money for?' 'Well, I need to have a place to live; it costs money.' 'Well, why can't you just live outside?' 'Well, I need a place to sleep; it's cold at night.' 'Well, what's wrong with being cold?' 'Well, it's uncomfortable.' 'What's wrong with being uncomfortable?' 'It's just bad.' Right? At some point if you keep asking why, why, why, it's going to come down to the conscious experience--in Bentham's terms, again somewhat misleading, the pleasure and pain of either you or somebody else that you care about. So the utilitarian idea is to say, Okay, we all have our pleasures and pains, and as a moral philosophy we should all count equally. And so a good standard for resolving public disagreements is to say we should go with whatever option is going to produce the best overall experience for the people who are affected. Which you can think of as shorthand as maximizing happiness--although I think that that's somewhat misleading. And the solution has a lot of merit to it. But it also has endured a couple of centuries of legitimate criticism. And one of the biggest criticisms--and now we're getting back to the Trolley cases, is that utilitarianism doesn't adequately account for people's rights. So, take the footbridge case. It seems that it's wrong to push that guy off the footbridge. Even if you stipulate that you can save more people's lives. And so anyone who is going to defend utilitarianism as a meta-morality--that is, a solution to the tragedy of common sense morality, as a moral system to adjudicate among competing tribal moral systems--if you are going to defend it in that way, as I do, you have to face up to these philosophical challenges: is it okay to kill on person to save five people in this kind of situation? So I spend a lot of the book trying to understand the psychology of cases like the footbridge case. And you mention these being kind of unrealistic and weird cases. That's actually part of my defense.
3,957
<h4>Prefer it – util is <u>impartial</u>, <u>specific</u> to <u>public actors</u>, and <u>resolves infinite regress</u> which explains <u>all value</u>. </h4><p><strong>Greene 15 </strong>— (Joshua Greene, Professor of Psychology @ Harvard, being interviewed by Russ Roberts, “Joshua Greene on Moral Tribes, Moral Dilemmas, and Utilitarianism”, The Library of Economics and Liberty, 1-5-15, Available Online at https://www.econtalk.org/joshua-greene-on-moral-tribes-moral-dilemmas-and-utilitarianism/#audio-highlights<u>, accessed 5-17-20, HKR-AM) **NB: Guest = Greene, and only his lines are highlighted/underlined</p><p></u>Guest: Okay. So, I think <u><mark>util</mark>itarianism <mark>is</mark> very much <mark>misunderstood</u></mark>. And this is part of the reason why we shouldn't even call it utilitarianism at all. <u>We should call it what I call 'deep pragmatism'</u>, which I think better captures what I think utilitarianism is really like, if you really apply it in real life, in light of an understanding of human nature. But, we can come back to that. The idea, <u><mark>going back to</mark> <mark>the tragedy of</mark> common-sense <mark>morality</mark> is <mark>you've</mark> <mark>got</mark> all these different <mark>tribes</mark> <mark>with</mark> all of these <mark>different values based</mark> <mark>on</mark> their <mark>different ways of life.</mark> What can they do to get along</u>? And I think that the best answer that we have is--well, let's back up. <u>In order <mark>to resolve</mark> any kind of <mark>tradeoff</mark>, you have to <mark>have</mark> <mark>some</mark> kind of <mark>common metric.</mark> You have to have some kind of common currency. And I think that what utilitarianism, whether it's the moral truth or not, is provide a kind of common currency</u>. So, <u>what is <mark>util</mark>itarianism?</u> It's basically the idea that--<u>it's really two ideas put together. One <mark>is</mark> the idea of <mark>impartiality</u></mark>. That is<u>, at least <mark>as social decision makers</mark>, <mark>we should regard</mark> <mark>everybody's interests as</mark> of <mark>equal</mark> worth. Everybody counts the same.</u> And then you might say, 'Well, but okay, <u>what does it mean to count everybody the same? <mark>What</mark> is it that really <mark>matters</mark> for you and for me and <mark>for everybody</mark> else?' And</u> <u>there <mark>the</mark> utilitarian's <mark>answer is</mark> what</u> <u>is sometimes called</u>, somewhat accurately and somewhat misleadingly, <u>happiness</u>. But <u>it's not really happiness in the sense of cherries on sundaes, things that make you smile. It's really the <mark>quality of conscious experience</mark>.</u> So, the idea is that <u>if you start with anything that you value, and say, 'Why do you care about that?' and keep asking</u>, 'Why do you care about that?' or 'Why do you care about that?' <u>you ultimately come down to the quality of someone's conscious experience</u>. So <u>if I were to say, 'Why did you go to work today?' you'd say, 'Well, I need to make money; and I also enjoy my work.' 'Well, what do you need your money for?' 'Well, I need to have a place to live; it costs money.' 'Well, why can't you just live outside?' 'Well, I need a place to sleep; it's cold at night.' 'Well, what's wrong with being cold?' 'Well, it's uncomfortable.' 'What's wrong with being uncomfortable?' 'It's just bad.' Right?</u> <u>At some point if you keep asking why, why, why, it's going to come down to the conscious experience--<mark>in Bentham's terms</u></mark>, again somewhat misleading, <u><mark>the pleasure and pain</mark> of either you or somebody else that you care about.</u> So <u>the utilitarian idea is to say, Okay, we all have our pleasures and pains, and as a moral philosophy we should all count equally.</u> And <u>so <mark>a good standard for resolving public disagreements</mark> <mark>is</mark> to say we should go with whatever option is going <mark>to produce the best overall experience</mark> for the people who are affected</u>. <u>Which you can think of as shorthand as maximizing happiness</u>--although I think that that's somewhat misleading. And the solution has a lot of merit to it. But it also has endured a couple of centuries of legitimate criticism. And <u>one of the biggest criticisms</u>--and now we're getting back to the Trolley cases, <u>is that utilitarianism doesn't adequately account for people's rights.</u> So, take the footbridge case. It seems that it's wrong to push that guy off the footbridge. Even if you stipulate that you can save more people's lives. And so anyone who is going to defend utilitarianism as a meta-morality--that is, a solution to the tragedy of common sense morality, as a moral system to adjudicate among competing tribal moral systems--if you are going to defend it in that way, as I do, you have to face up to these philosophical challenges: is it okay to kill on person to save five people in this kind of situation? <u>So I spend a lot of the book trying to understand the psychology of cases like the footbridge case. And you mention these being kind of unrealistic and weird cases. That's actually part of my defense. </p></u>
null
null
CASE
336,312
761
151,257
./documents/hsld22/Marlborough/LeFi/Marlborough-LeFi-Neg-Harvard-Westlake-Debates-Round-3.docx
963,903
N
Harvard Westlake Debates
3
Walt Whitman HZ
Paramo
1ac-spatial hospitality nc-t fw cap k 1ar-all nr-t fw 2ar-case t
hsld22/Marlborough/LeFi/Marlborough-LeFi-Neg-Harvard-Westlake-Debates-Round-3.docx
2023-01-14 22:54:40
80,515
LeFi
Marlborough LeFi
null
Le.....
Fi.....
null
null
26,925
Marlborough
Marlborough
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
2,005,607
The USFG is the three branches.
U.S. Legal ’16
U.S. Legal ’16 [U.S. Legal; 2016; Organization offering legal assistance and attorney access; U.S. Legal, “United States Federal Government Law and Legal Definition,” https://definitions.uslegal.com/u/united-states-federal-government/; RP]
The U S Federal Government is established by the Constitution. The Government shares sovereignty over the U S with the individual governments of the States The government has three branches: i) the legislature ii) Executive and iii) Judiciary. The Constitution prescribes separation of powers The Constitution limits the powers assigned to it; all powers not expressly assigned to the Federal Government are reserved to the people
The U S F G has three branches legislature Executive and Judiciary
The United States Federal Government is established by the US Constitution. The Federal Government shares sovereignty over the United Sates with the individual governments of the States of US. The Federal government has three branches: i) the legislature, which is the US Congress, ii) Executive, comprised of the President and Vice president of the US and iii) Judiciary. The US Constitution prescribes a system of separation of powers and ‘checks and balances’ for the smooth functioning of all the three branches of the Federal Government. The US Constitution limits the powers of the Federal Government to the powers assigned to it; all powers not expressly assigned to the Federal Government are reserved to the States or to the people.
741
<h4>The USFG is the <u>three branches</u>. </h4><p><strong>U.S. Legal ’16 </strong>[U.S. Legal; 2016; Organization offering legal assistance and attorney access; U.S. Legal, “United States Federal Government Law and Legal Definition,” https://definitions.uslegal.com/u/united-states-federal-government/; RP]</p><p><u><mark>The U</u></mark>nited <u><mark>S</u></mark>tates <u><mark>F</mark>ederal <mark>G</mark>overnment is established by the</u> US <u><strong>Constitution</strong>. The</u> Federal <u>Government shares <strong>sovereignty</strong> over the U</u>nited <u>S</u>ates <u>with the <strong>individual governments</strong> of the States</u> of US. <u>The </u>Federal <u>government <mark>has <strong>three branches</strong></mark>: i) the <mark>legislature</u></mark>, which is the US Congress, <u>ii) <mark>Executive</u></mark>, comprised of the President and Vice president of the US <u><mark>and</mark> iii) <mark>Judiciary</mark>. The</u> US <u>Constitution prescribes</u> a system of <u>separation of powers</u> and ‘checks and balances’ for the smooth functioning of all the three branches of the Federal Government. <u>The</u> US <u>Constitution <strong>limits the powers</u></strong> of the Federal Government to the powers <u>assigned to it; all powers not <strong>expressly assigned</strong> to the Federal Government are reserved to</u> the States or to <u><strong>the people</u></strong>.</p>
Block
ON
2NC -- T
1,172
1,430
59,242
./documents/hspolicy20/Peninsula/SrYa/Peninsula-Sridevan-Yang-Neg-UNLV-Round5.docx
737,800
N
UNLV
5
Sonoma KP
Ryan Morgan
1AC - Body 1NC - T USFG - Resolution - USFG CP - Heg DA 2NR - T USFG
hspolicy20/Peninsula/SrYa/Peninsula-Sridevan-Yang-Neg-UNLV-Round5.docx
null
62,875
SrYa
Peninsula SrYa
null
Sa.....
Sr.....
Ch.....
Ya.....
21,763
Peninsula
Peninsula
CA
null
1,019
hspolicy20
HS Policy 2020-21
2,020
cx
hs
2
1,490,173
The alt doesn’t change realist framework that controls state structures — their heuristic exacerbates war and structural violence
de Araujo 14 — Marcelo de Araujo (professor for Ethics at Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro), “Moral Enhancement and Political Realism,” Journal of Evolution and Technology 24(2): 29-43)
de Araujo 14 — Marcelo de Araujo (professor for Ethics at Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro), “Moral Enhancement and Political Realism,” Journal of Evolution and Technology 24(2): 29-43)
moral enhancement theorists argue a society of morally enhanced individuals would be in a better position to cope with important problems that humankind is likely to face in climate change terrorist attacks catastrophic wars. The assumption here is our inability to cope successfully with these problems stems mainly from a sort of deficit in human beings’ moral motivation If human beings were morally better there would be fewer wars, less terrorism, and more willingness to save our environment. this assumption is false At the root of threats to the survival of humankind in the future is not a deficit in our moral dispositions but the endurance of an old political arrangement that prevents the pursuit of shared goals on a collective basis. Many people, across different countries, already share moral beliefs relating to the wrongness of harming or killing other people arbitrarily, studies suggest that willingness to cooperate with other people may be enhanced by an increase in the levels of oxytoci The assumption that there is a relationship between, threats to the survival of humankind and a sort of “deficit” in our moral dispositions is clearly made by moral enhancements theorists both positions are correct in recognizing the real possibility of global catastrophes resulting from the malevolent use of, for instance, biotechnology or nuclear capabilities. Freud went as far as to suggest that human beings have an ingrained “inclination” to “aggression” and “destruction” attempt to employ Freud’s conception of human nature in understanding international relations has recently been resumed Sparrow correctly argues that “structural issues,” rather than human nature, constitute the main factor underlying political conflicts the question whether moral enhancement will improve the prospect of our coping successfully with survival of humankind to reduce evil in the world states are the only, relevant actors and compete for power Moral considerations are secondary when set against the state’s primary goal namely its own security and survival it is this structure that compels individuals to act as they do in the domain of international affairs. its “anarchical structure,” It means that each individual state is responsible for its own integrity and survival In the absence of a superior authority political leaders feel compelled to favor security over morality even if human beings turn out to become morally enhanced humankind may still have to face the same scary scenarios This is likely to happen if, indeed human beings remain compelled to cooperate under the crushing pressure of having to decide in such a short time, and on the basis of unreliable information, whether or not to retaliate, even a morally enhanced Yeltsin might have given orders to launch a devastating nuclear response in spite of strong moral dispositions to the contrary. What has to be changed is not human moral dispositions but the very structure of the political international system of states moral enhancement will not motivate political leaders to dismantle their nuclear weapons Neither will it deter other political leaders from pursuing nuclear capability at any rate not as long as the structure of international politics compels them to see prospective cooperators in the present as possible enemies in the future. in the absence of the kind of security that law-enforcing institutions have the force to create political leaders will fail to cooperate, and engage in wars in those areas that are critical to their survival this is likely to continue to happen even if, leaders become less egoistic and power-seeking addressing major threats to the survival of humankind in the future by means of bioengineering is unlikely to yield the expected results, so long as moral enhancement is pursued within the present framework of the international system of states.
If human s were morally better there would be fewer wars, less terrorism, and more willingness to save our environment this assumption is false At the root of threats to the survival of humankind is not a deficit in moral dispositions, but an old political arrangement that prevents a collective basis both positions are correct in recognizing the real possibility of global catastrophes resulting from nuclear capabilities “structural issues,” rather than human nature, constitute the factor underlying conflicts states are the only, relevant actors and compete for power in Moral considerations are secondary when set against security and survival is this structure that compels individuals to act as they do in political leaders feel compelled to favor security over morality even if human beings turn out to become morally enhanced humankind may still have to face the same scary scenarios moral enhancement will not motivate political leaders to dismantle nuclear weapons Neither will it deter leaders from pursuing capability as long as the structure of politics compels them to see cooperators in the present as possible enemies in the future leaders will fail to cooperate, and engage in wars, this is likely to continue to happen, even if, leaders become less power-seeking addressing major threats to the survival of humankind by means of bioengineering is unlikely to yield the expected results
Some moral enhancement theorists argue that a society of morally enhanced individuals would be in a better position to cope with important problems that humankind is likely to face in the future such as, for instance, the threats posed by climate change, grand scale terrorist attacks, or the risk of catastrophic wars. The assumption here is quite simple: our inability to cope successfully with these problems stems mainly from a sort of deficit in human beings’ moral motivation. If human beings were morally better – if we had enhanced moral dispositions – there would be fewer wars, less terrorism, and more willingness to save our environment. Although simple and attractive, this assumption is, as I intend to show, false. At the root of threats to the survival of humankind in the future is not a deficit in our moral dispositions, but the endurance of an old political arrangement that prevents the pursuit of shared goals on a collective basis. The political arrangement I have in mind here is the international system of states. In my analysis of the political implications of moral enhancement, I intend to concentrate my attention only on the supposition that we could avoid major wars in the future by making individuals morally better. I do not intend to discuss the threats posed by climate change, or by terrorism, although some human enhancement theorists also seek to cover these topics. I will explain, in the course of my analysis, a conceptual distinction between “human nature realism” and “structural realism,” well-known in the field of international relations theory. Thomas Douglas seems to have been among the first to explore the idea of “moral enhancement” as a new form of human enhancement. He certainly helped to kick off the current phase of the debate. In a paper published in 2008, Douglas suggests that in the “future people might use biomedical technology to morally enhance themselves.” Douglas characterizes moral enhancement in terms of the acquisition of “morally better motives” (Douglas 2008, 229). Mark Walker, in a paper published in 2009, suggests a similar idea. He characterizes moral enhancement in terms of improved moral dispositions or “genetic virtues”: The Genetic Virtue Program (GVP) is a proposal for influencing our moral nature through biology, that is, it is an alternate yet complementary means by which ethics and ethicists might contribute to the task of making our lives and world a better place. The basic idea is simple enough: genes influence human behavior, so altering the genes of individuals may alter the influence genes exert on behavior. (Walker 2009, 27–28) Walker does not argue in favor of any specific moral theory, such as, for instance, virtue ethics. Whether one endorses a deontological or a utilitarian approach to ethics, he argues, the concept of virtue is relevant to the extent that virtues motivate us either to do the right thing or to maximize the good (Walker 2009, 35). Moral enhancement theory, however, does not reduce the ethical debate to the problem of moral dispositions. Morality also concerns, to a large extent, questions about reasons for action. And moral enhancement, most certainly, will not improve our moral beliefs; neither could it be used to settle moral disagreements. This seems to have led some authors to criticize the moral enhancement idea on the ground that it neglects the cognitive side of our moral behavior. Robert Sparrow, for instance, argues that, from a Kantian point of view, moral enhancement would have to provide us with better moral beliefs rather than enhanced moral motivation (Sparrow 2014, 25; see also Agar 2010, 74). Yet, it seems to me that this objection misses the point of the moral enhancement idea. Many people, across different countries, already share moral beliefs relating, for instance, to the wrongness of harming or killing other people arbitrarily, or to the moral requirement to help people in need. They may share moral beliefs while not sharing the same reasons for these beliefs, or perhaps even not being able to articulate the beliefs in the conceptual framework of a moral theory (Blackford 2010, 83). But although they share some moral beliefs, in some circumstances they may lack the appropriate motivation to act accordingly. Moral enhancement, thus, aims at improving moral motivation, and leaves open the question as to how to improve our moral judgments. In a recent paper, published in The Journal of Medical Ethics, neuroscientist Molly Crockett reports the state of the art in the still very embryonic field of moral enhancement. She points out, for example, that the selective serotonin reuptake inhibitor (SSRI) citalopram seems to increase harm aversion. There is, moreover, some evidence that this substance may be effective in the treatment of specific types of aggressive behavior. Like Douglas, Crockett emphasizes that moral enhancement should aim at individuals’ moral motives (Crockett 2014; see also Spence 2008; Terbeck et al. 2013). Another substance that is frequently mentioned in the moral enhancement literature is oxytocin. Some studies suggest that willingness to cooperate with other people,and to trust unknown prospective cooperators, may be enhanced by an increase in the levels of oxytocin in the organism (Zak 2008, 2011; Zak and Kugler 2011; Persson and Savulescu 2012, 118–119). Oxytocin has also been reported to be “associated with the subjective experience of empathy” (Zak 2011, 55; Zak and Kugler 2011, 144). The question I would like to examine now concerns the supposition that moral enhancement – comprehended in these terms and assuming for the sake of argument that, some day, it might become effective and safe – may also help us in coping with the threat of devastating wars in the future. The assumption that there is a relationship between, on the one hand, threats to the survival of humankind and, on the other, a sort of “deficit” in our moral dispositions is clearly made by some moral enhancements theorists. Douglas, for instance, argues that “according to many plausible theories, some of the world’s most important problems — such as developing world poverty, climate change and war — can be attributed to these moral deficits” (2008, 230). Walker, in a similar vein, writes about the possibility of “using biotechnology to alter our biological natures in an effort to reduce evil in the world” (2009, 29). And Julian Savulescu and Ingmar Persson go as far as to defend the “the need for moral enhancement” of humankind in a series of articles, and in a book published in 2012. One of the reasons Savulescu and Persson advance for the moral enhancement of humankind is that our moral dispositions seem to have remained basically unchanged over the last millennia (Persson and Savulescu 2012, 2). These dispositions have proved thus far quite useful for the survival of human beings as a species. They have enabled us to cooperate with each other in the collective production of things such as food, shelter, tools, and farming. They have also played a crucial role in the creation and refinement of a variety of human institutions such as settlements, villages, and laws. Although the possibility of free-riding has never been fully eradicated, the benefits provided by cooperation have largely exceeded the disadvantages of our having to deal with occasional uncooperative or untrustworthy individuals (Persson and Savulescu 2012, 39). The problem, however, is that the same dispositions that have enabled human beings in the past to engage in the collective production of so many artifacts and institutions now seem powerless in the face of the human capacity to destroy other human beings on a grand scale, or perhaps even to annihilate the entire human species. There is, according to Savulescu and Persson, a “mismatch” between our cognitive faculties and our evolved moral attitudes: “[…] as we have repeatedly stressed, owing to the progress of science, the range of our powers of action has widely outgrown the range of our spontaneous moral attitudes, and created a dangerous mismatch” (Persson and Savulescu 2012, 103; see also Persson and Savulescu 2010, 660; Persson and Savulescu 2011b; DeGrazie 2012, 2; Rakić 2014, 2). This worry about the mismatch between, on the one hand, the modern technological capacity to destroy and, on the other, our limited moral commitments is not new. The political philosopher Hans Morgenthau, best known for his defense of political realism, called attention to the same problem nearly fifty years ago. In the wake of the first successful tests with thermonuclear bombs, conducted by the USA and the former Soviet Union, Morgenthau referred to the “contrast” between the technological progress of our age and our feeble moral attitudes as one of the most disturbing dilemmas of our time: The first dilemma consists in the contrast between the technological unification of the world and the parochial moral commitments and political institutions of the age. Moral commitments and political institutions, dating from an age which modern technology has left behind, have not kept pace with technological achievements and, hence, are incapable of controlling their destructive potentialities. (Morgenthau 1962, 174) Moral enhancement theorists and political realists like Morgenthau, therefore, share the thesis that our natural moral dispositions are not strong enough to prevent human beings from endangering their own existence as a species. But they differ as to the best way out of this quandary: moral enhancement theorists argue for the re-engineering of our moral dispositions, whereas Morgenthau accepted the immutability of human nature and argued, instead, for the re-engineering of world politics. Both positions, as I intend to show, are wrong in assuming that the “dilemma” results from the weakness of our spontaneous moral dispositions in the face of the unprecedented technological achievements of our time. On the other hand, both positions are correct in recognizing the real possibility of global catastrophes resulting from the malevolent use of, for instance, biotechnology or nuclear capabilities. The supposition that individuals’ unwillingness to cooperate with each other, even when they would be better-off by choosing to cooperate, results from a sort of deficit of dispositions such as altruism, empathy, and benevolence has been at the core of some important political theories. This idea is an important assumption in the works of early modern political realists such as Machiavelli and Thomas Hobbes. It was also later endorsed by some well-known authors writing about the origins of war in the first half of the twentieth century. It was then believed, as Sigmund Freud suggested in a text from 1932, that the main cause of wars is a human tendency to “hatred and destruction” (in German: ein Trieb zum Hassen und Vernichtung). Freud went as far as to suggest that human beings have an ingrained “inclination” to “aggression” and “destruction” (Aggressionstrieb, Aggressionsneigung, and Destruktionstrieb), and that this inclination has a “good biological basis” (biologisch wohl begründet) (Freud 1999, 20–24; see also Freud 1950; Forbes 1984; Pick 1993, 211–227; Medoff 2009). The attempt to employ Freud’s conception of human nature in understanding international relations has recently been resumed, for instance by Kurt Jacobsen in a paper entitled “Why Freud Matters: Psychoanalysis and International Relations Revisited,” published in 2013. Morgenthau himself was deeply influenced by Freud’s speculations on the origins of war.1 Early in the 1930s, Morgenthau wrote an essay called “On the Origin of the Political from the Nature of Human Beings” (Über die Herkunft des Politischen aus dem Wesen des Menschen), which contains several references to Freud’s theory about the human propensity to aggression.2 Morgenthau’s most influential book, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, first published in 1948 and then successively revised and edited, is still considered a landmark work in the tradition of political realism. According to Morgenthau, politics is governed by laws that have their origin in human nature: “Political realism believes that politics, like society in general, is governed by objective laws that have their roots in human nature” (Morgenthau 2006, 4). Just like human enhancement theorists, Morgenthau also takes for granted that human nature has not changed over recent millennia: “Human nature, in which the laws of politics have their roots, has not changed since the classical philosophies of China, India, and Greece endeavored to discover these laws” (Morgenthau 2006, 4). And since, for Morgenthau, human nature prompts human beings to act selfishly, rather than cooperatively, political leaders will sometimes favor conflict over cooperation, unless some superior power compels them to act otherwise. Now, this is exactly what happens in the domain of international relations. For in the international sphere there is not a supranational institution with the real power to prevent states from pursuing means of self-defense. The acquisition of means of self-defense, however, is frequently perceived by other states as a threat to their own security. This leads to the security dilemma and the possibility of war. As Morgenthau put the problem in an article published in 1967: “The actions of states are determined not by moral principles and legal commitments but by considerations of interest and power” (1967, 3). Because Morgenthau and early modern political philosophers such as Machiavelli and Hobbes defended political realism on the grounds provided by a specific conception human nature, their version of political realism has been frequently called “human nature realism.” The literature on human nature realism has become quite extensive (Speer 1968; Booth 1991; Freyberg-Inan 2003; Kaufman 2006; Molloy 2006, 82–85; Craig 2007; Scheuerman 2007, 2010, 2012; Schuett 2007; Neascu 2009; Behr 2010, 210–225; Brown 2011; Jütersonke 2012). It is not my intention here to present a fully-fledged account of the tradition of human nature realism, but rather to emphasize the extent to which some moral enhancement theorists, in their description of some of the gloomy scenarios humankind is likely to face in the future, implicitly endorse this kind of political realism. Indeed, like human nature realists, moral enhancement theorists assume that human nature has not changed over the last millennia, and that violence and lack of cooperation in the international sphere result chiefly from human nature’s limited inclination to pursue morally desirable goals. One may, of course, criticize the human enhancement project by rejecting the assumption that conflict and violence in the international domain should be explained by means of a theory about human nature. In a reply to Savulescu and Persson, Sparrow correctly argues that “structural issues,” rather than human nature, constitute the main factor underlying political conflicts (Sparrow 2014, 29). But he does not explain what exactly these “structural issues” are, as I intend to do later. Sparrow is right in rejecting the human nature theory underlying the human enhancement project. But this underlying assumption, in my view, is not trivially false or simply “ludicrous,” as he suggests. Human nature realism has been implicitly or explicitly endorsed by leading political philosophers ever since Thucydides speculated on the origins of war in antiquity (Freyberg-Inan 2003, 23–36). True, it might be objected that “human nature realism,” as it was defended by Morgenthau and earlier political philosophers, relied upon a metaphysical or psychoanalytical conception of human nature, a conception that, actually, did not have the support of any serious scientific investigation (Smith 1983, 167). Yet, over the last few years there has been much empirical research in fields such as developmental psychology and evolutionary biology that apparently gives some support to the realist claim. Some of these studies suggest that an inclination to aggression and conflict has its origins in our evolutionary history. This idea, then, has recently led some authors to resume “human nature realism” on new foundations, devoid of the metaphysical assumptions of the early realists, and entirely grounded in empirical research. Indeed, some recent works in the field of international relations theory already seek to call attention to evolutionary biology as a possible new start for political realism. This point is clearly made, for instance, by Bradley Thayer, who published in 2004 a book called Darwin and International Relations: On the Evolutionary Origins of War and Ethnic Conflict. And in a paper published in 2000, he affirms the following: Evolutionary theory provides a stronger foundation for realism because it is based on science, not on theology or metaphysics. I use the theory to explain two human traits: egoism and domination. I submit that the egoistic and dominating behavior of individuals, which is commonly described as “realist,” is a product of the evolutionary process. I focus on these two traits because they are critical components of any realist argument in explaining international politics. (Thayer 2000, 125; see also Thayer 2004) Thayer basically argues that a tendency to egoism and domination stems from human evolutionary history. The predominance of conflict and competition in the domain of international politics, he argues, is a reflex of dispositions that can now be proved to be part of our evolved human nature in a way that Morgenthau and other earlier political philosophers could not have established in their own time. Now, what some moral enhancement theorists propose is a direct intervention in our “evolved limited moral psychology” as a means to make us “fit” to cope with some possible devastating consequences from the predominance of conflict and competition in the domain of international politics (Persson and Savulescu 2010, 664). Moral enhancement theorists comprehend the nature of war and conflicts, especially those conflicts that humankind is likely to face in the future, as the result of human beings’ limited moral motivations. Compared to supporters of human nature realism, however, moral enhancement theorists are less skeptical about the prospect of our taming human beings’ proclivity to do evil. For our knowledge in fields such as neurology and pharmacology does already enable us to enhance people’s performance in a variety of activities, and there seems to be no reason to assume it will not enable us to enhance people morally in the future. But the question, of course, is whether moral enhancement will also improve the prospect of our coping successfully with some major threats to the survival of humankind, as Savulescu and Persson propose, or to reduce evil in the world, as proposed by Walker. V. The point to which I would next like to call attention is that “human nature realism” – which is implicitly presupposed by some moral enhancement theorists – has been much criticized over the last decades within the tradition of political realism itself. “Structural realism,” unlike “human nature realism,” does not seek to derive a theory about conflicts and violence in the context of international relations from a theory of the moral shortcomings of human nature. Structural realism was originally proposed by Kenneth Waltz in Man, the State and War, published in 1959, and then later in another book called Theory of International Politics, published in 1979. In both works, Waltz seeks to avoid committing himself to any specific conception of human nature (Waltz 2001, x–xi). Waltz’s thesis is that the thrust of the political realism doctrine can be retained without our having to commit ourselves to any theory about the shortcomings of human nature. What is relevant for our understanding of international politics is, instead, our understanding of the “structure” of the international system of states (Waltz 1986). John Mearsheimer, too, is an important contemporary advocate of political realism. Although he seeks to distance himself from some ideas defended by Waltz, he also rejects human nature realism and, like Waltz, refers to himself as a supporter of “structural realism” (Mearsheimer 2001, 20). One of the basic tenets of political realism (whether “human nature realism” or “structural realism”) is, first, that the states are the main, if not the only, relevant actors in the context of international relations; and second, that states compete for power in the international arena. Moral considerations in international affairs, according to realists, are secondary when set against the state’s primary goal, namely its own security and survival. But while human nature realists such as Morgenthau explain the struggle for power as a result of human beings’ natural inclinations, structural realists like Waltz and Mearsheimer argue that conflicts in the international arena do not stem from human nature, but from the very “structure” of the international system of states (Mearsheimer 2001, 18). According to Waltz and Mearsheimer, it is this structure that compels individuals to act as they do in the domain of international affairs. And one distinguishing feature of the international system of states is its “anarchical structure,” i.e. the lack of a central government analogous to the central governments that exist in the context of domestic politics. It means that each individual state is responsible for its own integrity and survival. In the absence of a superior authority, over and above the power of each sovereign state, political leaders often feel compelled to favor security over morality, even if, all other things being considered, they would naturally be more inclined to trust and to cooperate with political leaders of other states. On the other hand, when political leaders do trust and cooperate with other states, it is not necessarily their benevolent nature that motivates them to be cooperative and trustworthy, but, again, it is the structure of the system of states that compels them. The concept of human nature, as we can see, does not play a decisive role here. Because Waltz and Mearsheimer depart from “human nature realism,” their version of political realism has also sometimes been called “neo-realism” (Booth 1991, 533). Thus, even if human beings turn out to become morally enhanced in the future, humankind may still have to face the same scary scenarios described by some moral enhancement theorists. This is likely to happen if, indeed, human beings remain compelled to cooperate within the present structure of the system of states. Consider, for instance, the incident with a Norwegian weather rocket in January 1995. Russian radars detected a missile that was initially suspected of being on its way to reach Moscow in five minutes. All levels of Russian military defense were immediately put on alert for a possible imminent attack and massive retaliation. It is reported that for the first time in history a Russian president had before him, ready to be used, the “nuclear briefcase” from which the permission to launch nuclear weapons is issued. And that happened when the Cold War was already supposed to be over! In the event, it was realized that the rocket was leaving Russian territory and Boris Yeltsin did not have to enter the history books as the man who started the third world war by mistake (Cirincione 2008, 382).3 But under the crushing pressure of having to decide in such a short time, and on the basis of unreliable information, whether or not to retaliate, even a morally enhanced Yeltsin might have given orders to launch a devastating nuclear response – and that in spite of strong moral dispositions to the contrary. Writing for The Guardian on the basis of recently declassified documents, Rupert Myers reports further incidents similar to the one of 1995. He suggests that as more states strive to acquire nuclear capability, the danger of a major nuclear accident is likely to increase (Myers 2014). What has to be changed, therefore, is not human moral dispositions, but the very structure of the political international system of states within which we currently live. As far as major threats to the survival of humankind are concerned, moral enhancement might play an important role in the future only to the extent that it will help humankind to change the structure of the system of states. While moral enhancement may possibly have desirable results in some areas of human cooperation that do not badly threaten our security – such as donating food, medicine, and money to poorer countries – it will not motivate political leaders to dismantle their nuclear weapons. Neither will it deter other political leaders from pursuing nuclear capability, at any rate not as long as the structure of international politics compels them to see prospective cooperators in the present as possible enemies in the future. The idea of a “structure” should not be understood here in metaphysical terms, as though it mysteriously existed in a transcendent world and had the magical power of determining leaders’ decisions in this world. The word “structure” denotes merely a political arrangement in which there are no powerful law-enforcing institutions. And in the absence of the kind of security that law-enforcing institutions have the force to create, political leaders will often fail to cooperate, and occasionally engage in conflicts and wars, in those areas that are critical to their security and survival. Given the structure of international politics and the basic goal of survival, this is likely to continue to happen, even if, in the future, political leaders become less egoistic and power-seeking through moral enhancement. On the other hand, since the structure of the international system of states is itself another human institution, there is no reason to suppose that it cannot ever be changed. If people become morally enhanced in the future they may possibly feel more strongly motivated to change the structure of the system of states, or perhaps even feel inclined to abolish it altogether. In my view, however, addressing major threats to the survival of humankind in the future by means of bioengineering is unlikely to yield the expected results, so long as moral enhancement is pursued within the present framework of the international system of states.
26,567
<h4>The alt doesn’t change realist framework that controls state structures — their heuristic exacerbates war and structural violence</h4><p><strong>de Araujo 14<u> — Marcelo de Araujo (professor for Ethics at Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro), “Moral Enhancement and Political Realism,” Journal of Evolution and Technology 24(2): 29-43) </p><p></u></strong>Some <u>moral enhancement theorists argue </u>that <u>a society of <strong>morally enhanced individuals</u></strong> <u>would be in a better position to cope with important problems that humankind is likely to face in</u> the future such as, for instance, the threats posed by <u><strong>climate change</u></strong>, grand scale <u><strong>terrorist attacks</u></strong>, or the risk of <u><strong>catastrophic wars.</u></strong> <u>The assumption here is</u> quite simple: <u>our inability to cope successfully with these problems stems mainly from a sort of deficit in human beings’ <strong>moral motivation</u></strong>. <u><mark>If</mark> <strong><mark>human</strong></mark> being<strong><mark>s</strong></mark> <mark>were morally better</u></mark> – if we had enhanced moral dispositions – <u><mark>there would be <strong>fewer wars, less terrorism</strong>, and more <strong>willingness to save our environment</strong></mark>. </u>Although simple and attractive, <u><strong><mark>this assumption is</u></strong></mark>, as I intend to show, <u><strong><mark>false</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>At the root of threats to the survival of humankind</mark> in the future <mark>is not a deficit</mark> <mark>in</mark> our <mark>moral dispositions</u>, <u>but</mark> the endurance of <mark>an <strong>old political arrangement</strong> that prevents</mark> the pursuit of shared goals on <mark>a collective basis</mark>.</u> The political arrangement I have in mind here is the international system of states. In my analysis of the political implications of moral enhancement, I intend to concentrate my attention only on the supposition that we could avoid major wars in the future by making individuals morally better. I do not intend to discuss the threats posed by climate change, or by terrorism, although some human enhancement theorists also seek to cover these topics. I will explain, in the course of my analysis, a conceptual distinction between “human nature realism” and “structural realism,” well-known in the field of international relations theory. Thomas Douglas seems to have been among the first to explore the idea of “moral enhancement” as a new form of human enhancement. He certainly helped to kick off the current phase of the debate. In a paper published in 2008, Douglas suggests that in the “future people might use biomedical technology to morally enhance themselves.” Douglas characterizes moral enhancement in terms of the acquisition of “morally better motives” (Douglas 2008, 229). Mark Walker, in a paper published in 2009, suggests a similar idea. He characterizes moral enhancement in terms of improved moral dispositions or “genetic virtues”: The Genetic Virtue Program (GVP) is a proposal for influencing our moral nature through biology, that is, it is an alternate yet complementary means by which ethics and ethicists might contribute to the task of making our lives and world a better place. The basic idea is simple enough: genes influence human behavior, so altering the genes of individuals may alter the influence genes exert on behavior. (Walker 2009, 27–28) Walker does not argue in favor of any specific moral theory, such as, for instance, virtue ethics. Whether one endorses a deontological or a utilitarian approach to ethics, he argues, the concept of virtue is relevant to the extent that virtues motivate us either to do the right thing or to maximize the good (Walker 2009, 35). Moral enhancement theory, however, does not reduce the ethical debate to the problem of moral dispositions. Morality also concerns, to a large extent, questions about reasons for action. And moral enhancement, most certainly, will not improve our moral beliefs; neither could it be used to settle moral disagreements. This seems to have led some authors to criticize the moral enhancement idea on the ground that it neglects the cognitive side of our moral behavior. Robert Sparrow, for instance, argues that, from a Kantian point of view, moral enhancement would have to provide us with better moral beliefs rather than enhanced moral motivation (Sparrow 2014, 25; see also Agar 2010, 74). Yet, it seems to me that this objection misses the point of the moral enhancement idea. <u>Many people, across different countries, already share moral beliefs relating</u>, for instance, <u>to the wrongness of harming or killing other people arbitrarily,</u> or to the moral requirement to help people in need. They may share moral beliefs while not sharing the same reasons for these beliefs, or perhaps even not being able to articulate the beliefs in the conceptual framework of a moral theory (Blackford 2010, 83). But although they share some moral beliefs, in some circumstances they may lack the appropriate motivation to act accordingly. Moral enhancement, thus, aims at improving moral motivation, and leaves open the question as to how to improve our moral judgments. In a recent paper, published in The Journal of Medical Ethics, neuroscientist Molly Crockett reports the state of the art in the still very embryonic field of moral enhancement. She points out, for example, that the selective serotonin reuptake inhibitor (SSRI) citalopram seems to increase harm aversion. There is, moreover, some evidence that this substance may be effective in the treatment of specific types of aggressive behavior. Like Douglas, Crockett emphasizes that moral enhancement should aim at individuals’ moral motives (Crockett 2014; see also Spence 2008; Terbeck et al. 2013). Another substance that is frequently mentioned in the moral enhancement literature is oxytocin. Some <u>studies suggest that willingness to cooperate with other people</u>,and to trust unknown prospective cooperators, <u>may be enhanced by an increase in the levels of oxytoci</u>n in the organism (Zak 2008, 2011; Zak and Kugler 2011; Persson and Savulescu 2012, 118–119). Oxytocin has also been reported to be “associated with the subjective experience of empathy” (Zak 2011, 55; Zak and Kugler 2011, 144). The question I would like to examine now concerns the supposition that moral enhancement – comprehended in these terms and assuming for the sake of argument that, some day, it might become effective and safe – may also help us in coping with the threat of devastating wars in the future. <u>The assumption that there is a relationship between,</u> on the one hand, <u>threats to the survival of humankind and</u>, on the other, <u>a sort of “deficit” in our moral dispositions is clearly</u> <u>made by</u> some <u>moral enhancements theorists</u>. Douglas, for instance, argues that “according to many plausible theories, some of the world’s most important problems — such as developing world poverty, climate change and war — can be attributed to these moral deficits” (2008, 230). Walker, in a similar vein, writes about the possibility of “using biotechnology to alter our biological natures in an effort to reduce evil in the world” (2009, 29). And Julian Savulescu and Ingmar Persson go as far as to defend the “the need for moral enhancement” of humankind in a series of articles, and in a book published in 2012. One of the reasons Savulescu and Persson advance for the moral enhancement of humankind is that our moral dispositions seem to have remained basically unchanged over the last millennia (Persson and Savulescu 2012, 2). These dispositions have proved thus far quite useful for the survival of human beings as a species. They have enabled us to cooperate with each other in the collective production of things such as food, shelter, tools, and farming. They have also played a crucial role in the creation and refinement of a variety of human institutions such as settlements, villages, and laws. Although the possibility of free-riding has never been fully eradicated, the benefits provided by cooperation have largely exceeded the disadvantages of our having to deal with occasional uncooperative or untrustworthy individuals (Persson and Savulescu 2012, 39). The problem, however, is that the same dispositions that have enabled human beings in the past to engage in the collective production of so many artifacts and institutions now seem powerless in the face of the human capacity to destroy other human beings on a grand scale, or perhaps even to annihilate the entire human species. There is, according to Savulescu and Persson, a “mismatch” between our cognitive faculties and our evolved moral attitudes: “[…] as we have repeatedly stressed, owing to the progress of science, the range of our powers of action has widely outgrown the range of our spontaneous moral attitudes, and created a dangerous mismatch” (Persson and Savulescu 2012, 103; see also Persson and Savulescu 2010, 660; Persson and Savulescu 2011b; DeGrazie 2012, 2; Rakić 2014, 2). This worry about the mismatch between, on the one hand, the modern technological capacity to destroy and, on the other, our limited moral commitments is not new. The political philosopher Hans Morgenthau, best known for his defense of political realism, called attention to the same problem nearly fifty years ago. In the wake of the first successful tests with thermonuclear bombs, conducted by the USA and the former Soviet Union, Morgenthau referred to the “contrast” between the technological progress of our age and our feeble moral attitudes as one of the most disturbing dilemmas of our time: The first dilemma consists in the contrast between the technological unification of the world and the parochial moral commitments and political institutions of the age. Moral commitments and political institutions, dating from an age which modern technology has left behind, have not kept pace with technological achievements and, hence, are incapable of controlling their destructive potentialities. (Morgenthau 1962, 174) Moral enhancement theorists and political realists like Morgenthau, therefore, share the thesis that our natural moral dispositions are not strong enough to prevent human beings from endangering their own existence as a species. But they differ as to the best way out of this quandary: moral enhancement theorists argue for the re-engineering of our moral dispositions, whereas Morgenthau accepted the immutability of human nature and argued, instead, for the re-engineering of world politics. Both positions, as I intend to show, are wrong in assuming that the “dilemma” results from the weakness of our spontaneous moral dispositions in the face of the unprecedented technological achievements of our time. On the other hand, <u><mark>both positions are correct in recognizing the <strong>real possibility</strong> of global catastrophes resulting from</mark> the malevolent use of, for instance, <strong>biotechnology or <mark>nuclear capabilities</mark>.</u></strong> The supposition that individuals’ unwillingness to cooperate with each other, even when they would be better-off by choosing to cooperate, results from a sort of deficit of dispositions such as altruism, empathy, and benevolence has been at the core of some important political theories. This idea is an important assumption in the works of early modern political realists such as Machiavelli and Thomas Hobbes. It was also later endorsed by some well-known authors writing about the origins of war in the first half of the twentieth century. It was then believed, as Sigmund Freud suggested in a text from 1932, that the main cause of wars is a human tendency to “hatred and destruction” (in German: ein Trieb zum Hassen und Vernichtung). <u>Freud went as far as to suggest that human beings have an ingrained “inclination” to “aggression” and “destruction”</u> (Aggressionstrieb, Aggressionsneigung, and Destruktionstrieb), and that this inclination has a “good biological basis” (biologisch wohl begründet) (Freud 1999, 20–24; see also Freud 1950; Forbes 1984; Pick 1993, 211–227; Medoff 2009). The <u>attempt to employ Freud’s conception of human nature in understanding international relations has recently been resumed</u>, for instance by Kurt Jacobsen in a paper entitled “Why Freud Matters: Psychoanalysis and International Relations Revisited,” published in 2013. Morgenthau himself was deeply influenced by Freud’s speculations on the origins of war.1 Early in the 1930s, Morgenthau wrote an essay called “On the Origin of the Political from the Nature of Human Beings” (Über die Herkunft des Politischen aus dem Wesen des Menschen), which contains several references to Freud’s theory about the human propensity to aggression.2 Morgenthau’s most influential book, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, first published in 1948 and then successively revised and edited, is still considered a landmark work in the tradition of political realism. According to Morgenthau, politics is governed by laws that have their origin in human nature: “Political realism believes that politics, like society in general, is governed by objective laws that have their roots in human nature” (Morgenthau 2006, 4). Just like human enhancement theorists, Morgenthau also takes for granted that human nature has not changed over recent millennia: “Human nature, in which the laws of politics have their roots, has not changed since the classical philosophies of China, India, and Greece endeavored to discover these laws” (Morgenthau 2006, 4). And since, for Morgenthau, human nature prompts human beings to act selfishly, rather than cooperatively, political leaders will sometimes favor conflict over cooperation, unless some superior power compels them to act otherwise. Now, this is exactly what happens in the domain of international relations. For in the international sphere there is not a supranational institution with the real power to prevent states from pursuing means of self-defense. The acquisition of means of self-defense, however, is frequently perceived by other states as a threat to their own security. This leads to the security dilemma and the possibility of war. As Morgenthau put the problem in an article published in 1967: “The actions of states are determined not by moral principles and legal commitments but by considerations of interest and power” (1967, 3). Because Morgenthau and early modern political philosophers such as Machiavelli and Hobbes defended political realism on the grounds provided by a specific conception human nature, their version of political realism has been frequently called “human nature realism.” The literature on human nature realism has become quite extensive (Speer 1968; Booth 1991; Freyberg-Inan 2003; Kaufman 2006; Molloy 2006, 82–85; Craig 2007; Scheuerman 2007, 2010, 2012; Schuett 2007; Neascu 2009; Behr 2010, 210–225; Brown 2011; Jütersonke 2012). It is not my intention here to present a fully-fledged account of the tradition of human nature realism, but rather to emphasize the extent to which some moral enhancement theorists, in their description of some of the gloomy scenarios humankind is likely to face in the future, implicitly endorse this kind of political realism. Indeed, like human nature realists, moral enhancement theorists assume that human nature has not changed over the last millennia, and that violence and lack of cooperation in the international sphere result chiefly from human nature’s limited inclination to pursue morally desirable goals. One may, of course, criticize the human enhancement project by rejecting the assumption that conflict and violence in the international domain should be explained by means of a theory about human nature. In a reply to Savulescu and Persson, <u>Sparrow correctly argues that <strong><mark>“structural issues,”</strong> rather than <strong>human nature</strong>, constitute the </mark>main <mark>factor underlying </mark>political <mark>conflicts</u></mark> (Sparrow 2014, 29). But he does not explain what exactly these “structural issues” are, as I intend to do later. Sparrow is right in rejecting the human nature theory underlying the human enhancement project. But this underlying assumption, in my view, is not trivially false or simply “ludicrous,” as he suggests. Human nature realism has been implicitly or explicitly endorsed by leading political philosophers ever since Thucydides speculated on the origins of war in antiquity (Freyberg-Inan 2003, 23–36). True, it might be objected that “human nature realism,” as it was defended by Morgenthau and earlier political philosophers, relied upon a metaphysical or psychoanalytical conception of human nature, a conception that, actually, did not have the support of any serious scientific investigation (Smith 1983, 167). Yet, over the last few years there has been much empirical research in fields such as developmental psychology and evolutionary biology that apparently gives some support to the realist claim. Some of these studies suggest that an inclination to aggression and conflict has its origins in our evolutionary history. This idea, then, has recently led some authors to resume “human nature realism” on new foundations, devoid of the metaphysical assumptions of the early realists, and entirely grounded in empirical research. Indeed, some recent works in the field of international relations theory already seek to call attention to evolutionary biology as a possible new start for political realism. This point is clearly made, for instance, by Bradley Thayer, who published in 2004 a book called Darwin and International Relations: On the Evolutionary Origins of War and Ethnic Conflict. And in a paper published in 2000, he affirms the following: Evolutionary theory provides a stronger foundation for realism because it is based on science, not on theology or metaphysics. I use the theory to explain two human traits: egoism and domination. I submit that the egoistic and dominating behavior of individuals, which is commonly described as “realist,” is a product of the evolutionary process. I focus on these two traits because they are critical components of any realist argument in explaining international politics. (Thayer 2000, 125; see also Thayer 2004) Thayer basically argues that a tendency to egoism and domination stems from human evolutionary history. The predominance of conflict and competition in the domain of international politics, he argues, is a reflex of dispositions that can now be proved to be part of our evolved human nature in a way that Morgenthau and other earlier political philosophers could not have established in their own time. Now, what some moral enhancement theorists propose is a direct intervention in our “evolved limited moral psychology” as a means to make us “fit” to cope with some possible devastating consequences from the predominance of conflict and competition in the domain of international politics (Persson and Savulescu 2010, 664). Moral enhancement theorists comprehend the nature of war and conflicts, especially those conflicts that humankind is likely to face in the future, as the result of human beings’ limited moral motivations. Compared to supporters of human nature realism, however, moral enhancement theorists are less skeptical about the prospect of our taming human beings’ proclivity to do evil. For our knowledge in fields such as neurology and pharmacology does already enable us to enhance people’s performance in a variety of activities, and there seems to be no reason to assume it will not enable us to enhance people morally in the future. But <u>the question</u>, of course, is <u>whether moral enhancement will </u>also <u>improve the prospect of our coping successfully</u> <u>with</u> some major threats to the <u><strong>survival of humankind</u></strong>, as Savulescu and Persson propose, or <u><strong>to reduce evil in the world</u></strong>, as proposed by Walker. V. The point to which I would next like to call attention is that “human nature realism” – which is implicitly presupposed by some moral enhancement theorists – has been much criticized over the last decades within the tradition of political realism itself. “Structural realism,” unlike “human nature realism,” does not seek to derive a theory about conflicts and violence in the context of international relations from a theory of the moral shortcomings of human nature. Structural realism was originally proposed by Kenneth Waltz in Man, the State and War, published in 1959, and then later in another book called Theory of International Politics, published in 1979. In both works, Waltz seeks to avoid committing himself to any specific conception of human nature (Waltz 2001, x–xi). Waltz’s thesis is that the thrust of the political realism doctrine can be retained without our having to commit ourselves to any theory about the shortcomings of human nature. What is relevant for our understanding of international politics is, instead, our understanding of the “structure” of the international system of states (Waltz 1986). John Mearsheimer, too, is an important contemporary advocate of political realism. Although he seeks to distance himself from some ideas defended by Waltz, he also rejects human nature realism and, like Waltz, refers to himself as a supporter of “structural realism” (Mearsheimer 2001, 20). One of the basic tenets of political realism (whether “human nature realism” or “structural realism”) is, first, that the <u><mark>states are the</u></mark> main, if not the <u><strong><mark>only, relevant actors</mark> </u></strong>in the context of international relations; <u><mark>and</u></mark> second, that states <u><strong><mark>compete for power </u></strong>in</mark> the international arena. <u><strong><mark>Moral</mark> <mark>considerations</u></strong></mark> in international affairs, according to realists, <u><mark>are <strong>secondary</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>when set against </mark>the state’s primary goal</u>, <u><strong>namely its own <mark>security and survival</u></strong></mark>. But while human nature realists such as Morgenthau explain the struggle for power as a result of human beings’ natural inclinations, structural realists like Waltz and Mearsheimer argue that conflicts in the international arena do not stem from human nature, but from the very “structure” of the international system of states (Mearsheimer 2001, 18). According to Waltz and Mearsheimer, <u>it <mark>is this <strong>structure</strong> that compels individuals to act as they do in</mark> the domain of international affairs. </u>And one distinguishing feature of the international system of states is <u>its “anarchical structure,”</u> i.e. the lack of a central government analogous to the central governments that exist in the context of domestic politics. <u>It means that each individual state is responsible for its own integrity and survival</u>. <u>In the absence of a superior authority</u>, over and above the power of each sovereign state, <u><mark>political leaders</mark> </u>often <u><mark>feel compelled to favor <strong>security over morality</u></strong></mark>, even if, all other things being considered, they would naturally be more inclined to trust and to cooperate with political leaders of other states. On the other hand, when political leaders do trust and cooperate with other states, it is not necessarily their benevolent nature that motivates them to be cooperative and trustworthy, but, again, it is the structure of the system of states that compels them. The concept of human nature, as we can see, does not play a decisive role here. Because Waltz and Mearsheimer depart from “human nature realism,” their version of political realism has also sometimes been called “neo-realism” (Booth 1991, 533). Thus, <u><strong><mark>even if</u></strong> <u>human beings turn out to become <strong>morally enhanced</strong></mark> </u>in the future, <u><mark>humankind may still have to face the same <strong>scary scenarios</strong></mark> </u>described by some moral enhancement theorists. <u>This is likely to happen if, indeed</u>, <u>human beings remain compelled to cooperate </u>within the present structure of the system of states. Consider, for instance, the incident with a Norwegian weather rocket in January 1995. Russian radars detected a missile that was initially suspected of being on its way to reach Moscow in five minutes. All levels of Russian military defense were immediately put on alert for a possible imminent attack and massive retaliation. It is reported that for the first time in history a Russian president had before him, ready to be used, the “nuclear briefcase” from which the permission to launch nuclear weapons is issued. And that happened when the Cold War was already supposed to be over! In the event, it was realized that the rocket was leaving Russian territory and Boris Yeltsin did not have to enter the history books as the man who started the third world war by mistake (Cirincione 2008, 382).3 But <u>under the crushing pressure of having to decide in such a short time, and on the basis of unreliable information, whether or not to retaliate, even a morally enhanced Yeltsin might have given orders to launch a devastating nuclear response</u> – and that <u><strong>in spite of strong moral dispositions to the contrary. </u></strong>Writing for The Guardian on the basis of recently declassified documents, Rupert Myers reports further incidents similar to the one of 1995. He suggests that as more states strive to acquire nuclear capability, the danger of a major nuclear accident is likely to increase (Myers 2014). <u>What has to be changed</u>, therefore, <u>is not human moral dispositions</u>, <u><strong>but the very structure of the political international system of states</u></strong> within which we currently live. As far as major threats to the survival of humankind are concerned, moral enhancement might play an important role in the future only to the extent that it will help humankind to change the structure of the system of states. While <u><mark>moral enhancement</u></mark> may possibly have desirable results in some areas of human cooperation that do not badly threaten our security – such as donating food, medicine, and money to poorer countries – it <u><mark>will not motivate political leaders to <strong>dismantle</mark> their <mark>nuclear weapons</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>Neither will it deter</mark> other political <mark>leaders from pursuing</mark> nuclear <mark>capability</u></mark>, <u>at any rate not <mark>as long as the structure of</mark> international <mark>politics compels them to see </mark>prospective <mark>cooperators <strong>in the present as possible enemies in the future</mark>.</u></strong> The idea of a “structure” should not be understood here in metaphysical terms, as though it mysteriously existed in a transcendent world and had the magical power of determining leaders’ decisions in this world. The word “structure” denotes merely a political arrangement in which there are no powerful law-enforcing institutions. And <u>in the absence of the kind of security that law-enforcing institutions have the force to create</u>, <u>political <mark>leaders will</u></mark> often <u><strong><mark>fail to cooperate,</u></strong> <u>and</u></mark> occasionally <u><mark>engage in</u></mark> conflicts and <u><mark>wars</u>,</mark> <u>in those areas that are critical to their </u>security and <u>survival</u>. Given the structure of international politics and the basic goal of survival, <u><mark>this is likely to continue to happen</u>, <u><strong>even if,</u></strong></mark> in the future, political <u><mark>leaders become <strong>less </mark>egoistic and <mark>power-seeking</strong></mark> </u>through moral enhancement. On the other hand, since the structure of the international system of states is itself another human institution, there is no reason to suppose that it cannot ever be changed. If people become morally enhanced in the future they may possibly feel more strongly motivated to change the structure of the system of states, or perhaps even feel inclined to abolish it altogether. In my view, however, <u><mark>addressing major threats to the survival of humankind</mark> in the future <mark>by means of <strong>bioengineering</u></strong></mark> <u><mark>is unlikely to yield the <strong>expected results</strong></mark>, so long as moral enhancement is pursued <strong>within the present framework of the international system of states.</p></u></strong>
Ks
Weheliye K
AT: Don’t Need the Alt To Win
12,502
1,191
41,732
./documents/hsld21/Marlborough/Af/Marlborough-Affleck-Aff-USC-Round2.docx
893,215
A
USC
2
Mission San Jose SS
Derek Hilligoss
1AC - (incarcerated workers V2) NC - (meet 2018 demands CP) (oil spill DA) (util NC) (build back better politics DA) (T subsets) (CP violent and discriminatory strikes) 1AR - (dropped politics and util) (new 2AR arguments OK) NR - (politics DA)
hsld21/Marlborough/Af/Marlborough-Affleck-Aff-USC-Round2.docx
null
74,999
ViAf
Marlborough ViAf
null
Vi.....
Af.....
null
null
25,068
Marlborough
Marlborough
CA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
4,477,936
Disease can’t cause extinction
Ord 20
Dr. Toby Ord 20, Senior Research Fellow in Philosophy at Oxford University, DPhil in Philosophy from the University of Oxford, The Precipice: Existential Risk and the Future of Humanity, Hachette Books, Kindle Edition, p. 124-126
Could a pandemic threaten humanity’s future? the world had become so interconnected that a truly global pandemic was possible Yet even events like these fall short of being a threat to humanity’s longterm potential In addition to historical evidence, there are some deeper biological observations and theories suggesting that pathogens are unlikely to lead to the extinction of their hosts. These include the empirical anti-correlation between infectiousness and lethality, the extreme rarity of diseases that kill more than 75% of those infected, the observed tendency of pandemics to become less virulent as they progress and the theory of optimal virulence [END FOOTNOTE] In the great bubonic plagues we saw civilization in the affected areas falter, but recover. The regional 50 percent death rate was not enough to precipitate a continent-wide collapse
global pandemic fall short of a threat to humanity deep biological theories suggest pathogens are unlikely to lead to extinction These include anti-correlation between infectiousness and lethality extreme rarity that kill more than 75% tendency to become less virulent and optimal virulence civilization recover 50 percent death rate was not enough to precipitate collapse
Are we safe now from events like this? Or are we more vulnerable? Could a pandemic threaten humanity’s future?10 The Black Death was not the only biological disaster to scar human history. It was not even the only great bubonic plague. In 541 CE the Plague of Justinian struck the Byzantine Empire. Over three years it took the lives of roughly 3 percent of the world’s people.11 When Europeans reached the Americas in 1492, the two populations exposed each other to completely novel diseases. Over thousands of years each population had built up resistance to their own set of diseases, but were extremely susceptible to the others. The American peoples got by far the worse end of exchange, through diseases such as measles, influenza and especially smallpox. During the next hundred years a combination of invasion and disease took an immense toll—one whose scale may never be known, due to great uncertainty about the size of the pre-existing population. We can’t rule out the loss of more than 90 percent of the population of the Americas during that century, though the number could also be much lower.12 And it is very difficult to tease out how much of this should be attributed to war and occupation, rather than disease. As a rough upper bound, the Columbian exchange may have killed as many as 10 percent of the world’s people.13 Centuries later, the world had become so interconnected that a truly global pandemic was possible. Near the end of the First World War, a devastating strain of influenza (known as the 1918 flu or Spanish Flu) spread to six continents, and even remote Pacific islands. At least a third of the world’s population were infected and 3 to 6 percent were killed.14 This death toll outstripped that of the First World War, and possibly both World Wars combined. Yet even events like these fall short of being a threat to humanity’s longterm potential.15 [FOONOTE] In addition to this historical evidence, there are some deeper biological observations and theories suggesting that pathogens are unlikely to lead to the extinction of their hosts. These include the empirical anti-correlation between infectiousness and lethality, the extreme rarity of diseases that kill more than 75% of those infected, the observed tendency of pandemics to become less virulent as they progress and the theory of optimal virulence. However, there is no watertight case against pathogens leading to the extinction of their hosts. [END FOOTNOTE] In the great bubonic plagues we saw civilization in the affected areas falter, but recover. The regional 25 to 50 percent death rate was not enough to precipitate a continent-wide collapse
2,649
<h4><strong>Disease can’t cause extinction</h4><p></strong>Dr. Toby <strong>Ord 20</strong>, Senior Research Fellow in Philosophy at Oxford University, DPhil in Philosophy from the University of Oxford, The Precipice: Existential Risk and the Future of Humanity, Hachette Books, Kindle Edition, p. 124-126</p><p>Are we safe now from events like this? Or are we more vulnerable? <u>Could a pandemic threaten <strong>humanity</strong>’s future?</u>10 </p><p>The Black Death was not the only biological disaster to scar human history. It was not even the only great bubonic plague. In 541 CE the Plague of Justinian struck the Byzantine Empire. Over three years it took the lives of roughly 3 percent of the world’s people.11 </p><p>When Europeans reached the Americas in 1492, the two populations exposed each other to completely novel diseases. Over thousands of years each population had built up resistance to their own set of diseases, but were extremely susceptible to the others. The American peoples got by far the worse end of exchange, through diseases such as measles, influenza and especially smallpox. </p><p>During the next hundred years a combination of invasion and disease took an immense toll—one whose scale may never be known, due to great uncertainty about the size of the pre-existing population. We can’t rule out the loss of more than 90 percent of the population of the Americas during that century, though the number could also be much lower.12 And it is very difficult to tease out how much of this should be attributed to war and occupation, rather than disease. As a rough upper bound, the Columbian exchange may have killed as many as 10 percent of the world’s people.13 </p><p>Centuries later, <u>the world had become so interconnected that a truly <mark>global pandemic</mark> was possible</u>. Near the end of the First World War, a devastating strain of influenza (known as the 1918 flu or Spanish Flu) spread to six continents, and even remote Pacific islands. At least a third of the world’s population were infected and 3 to 6 percent were killed.14 This death toll outstripped that of the First World War, and possibly both World Wars combined. </p><p><u>Yet even events like these <strong><mark>fall short</strong> of</mark> being <mark>a threat to <strong>humanity</strong></mark>’s longterm potential</u>.15 </p><p>[FOONOTE]</p><p><u>In addition to</u> this <u><strong>historical</strong> evidence, there are some <strong><mark>deep</strong></mark>er <strong><mark>biological</strong></mark> observations and <mark>theories <strong>suggest</strong></mark>ing that <strong><mark>pathogens are unlikely to lead to</mark> the <mark>extinction</strong></mark> of their hosts. <mark>These include</mark> the <strong>empirical <mark>anti-correlation</strong> between <strong>infectiousness</strong> and <strong>lethality</strong></mark>, the <strong><mark>extreme rarity</strong></mark> of diseases <mark>that kill more than 75%</mark> of those infected, the observed <strong><mark>tendency</strong></mark> of pandemics <mark>to <strong>become less virulent</strong></mark> as they progress <mark>and</mark> the theory of <strong><mark>optimal virulence</u></strong></mark>. However, there is no watertight case against pathogens leading to the extinction of their hosts.</p><p><u>[END FOOTNOTE]</p><p>In the great bubonic plagues we saw <mark>civilization</mark> in the affected areas falter, but <strong><mark>recover</strong></mark>. The regional</u> 25 to <u><strong><mark>50 percent</strong> death rate was <strong>not enough</strong> to <strong>precipitate</mark> a continent-wide <mark>collapse</strong></mark> </p></u>
2nc
disease
Impact D – Disease
996
1,133
146,881
./documents/ndtceda22/MichiganState/GlMe/MichiganState-GlMe-Neg-Gonzaga-Jesuit-Debates-RD-6.docx
940,756
N
Gonzaga Jesuit Debates
RD 6
Georgetown CM - ONLINE
Rivas - ONLINE
1ac - inventorship 1nc - t-subsets, t-ai, nearest person cp, rights creep da, fetal personhood da, agamben k 2nr - rights creep
ndtceda22/MichiganState/GlMe/MichiganState-GlMe-Neg-Gonzaga-Jesuit-Debates-RD-6.docx
2022-10-30 20:32:14
80,736
GlMe
Michigan State GlMe
piper - 2a/1n - she/her - pipermeloche@gmail.com nate - 2n/1a - he/him - nathanglancy124@gmail.com if we're online ask about nate's dog luna! she's prob in the room with us and would love to say hello :)
Na.....
Gl.....
Pi.....
Me.....
26,842
MichiganState
Michigan State
MI
null
2,001
ndtceda22
NDT/CEDA College 2022-23
2,022
cx
college
2
2,743,403
Interp – the cutoff for substantial is between 8% (3/36) and 17% (14/79)- affs that reduce less than 8% definitely aren’t topical
Theohary, 16
Theohary, 16 - Specialist in National Security Policy and Information Operations at the Congressional Research Service (Catherine, “Conventional Arms Transfers to Developing Nations, 2008-2015” CRS Report, 12/19, https://fas.org/sgp/crs/weapons/R44716.pdf
The value of all arms transfer agreements was $65.2 billion, a substantial decrease from the $79.3 billion in 2014 In 2015, the value of all arms deliveries ($33.6 billion) decreased slightly from the value of 2014 deliveries ($36.2 billion
The value of all arms transfer agreements was $65. billion, a substantial decrease from the $79 billion the value of all arms deliveries 33 billion) decreased slightly from 36 billion
The value of all arms transfer agreements with developing nations in 2015 was $65.2 billion, a substantial decrease from the $79.3 billion total in 2014 (Figure 1) (Table 1) (Table 3) (Table 4). In 2015, the value of all arms deliveries to developing nations ($33.6 billion) decreased slightly from the value of 2014 deliveries ($36.2 billion). Deliveries since 2008 peaked in 2014 (Figure 7 and Figure 8) (Table 2) (Table 15).
427
<h4>Interp – the cutoff for substantial is between 8% (3/36) and 17% (14/79)- affs that reduce less than 8% definitely aren’t topical</h4><p><strong>Theohary, 16 </strong>- Specialist in National Security Policy and Information Operations at the Congressional Research Service<strong> </strong>(Catherine, “Conventional Arms Transfers to Developing Nations, 2008-2015” CRS Report, 12/19, https://fas.org/sgp/crs/weapons/R44716.pdf</p><p><u><mark>The value of all arms transfer agreements</u></mark> with developing nations in 2015 <u><mark>was $65.</mark>2 <mark>billion, a <strong>substantial decrease</strong> from the $79</mark>.3 <mark>billion</u></mark> total <u>in 2014</u> (Figure 1) (Table 1) (Table 3) (Table 4). <u>In 2015,</u> <u><mark>the value of all arms deliveries</u></mark> to developing nations <u>($<mark>33</mark>.6 <mark>billion) decreased <strong>slightly</strong> from</mark> the value of 2014 deliveries ($<mark>36</mark>.2 <mark>billion</u></mark>). Deliveries since 2008 peaked in 2014 (Figure 7 and Figure 8) (Table 2) (Table 15).</p>
1NC ALTA R2 V Bingham HL
null
T
78,479
358
87,018
./documents/hspolicy19/LonePeak/AvLu/Lone%20Peak-Avondet-Lunsford-Neg-4%20-%20Alta-Round2.docx
715,755
N
4 - Alta
2
Bingham HL
Jeremiah Etcheverry
1AC - Israel (Indo Pak Humanitarian Colonialism) 1NC - T Substantial T Subsets Suspend CP DIB DA Allies DA 2NR - Suspend and DIB
hspolicy19/LonePeak/AvLu/Lone%20Peak-Avondet-Lunsford-Neg-4%20-%20Alta-Round2.docx
null
61,029
AvLu
Lone Peak AvLu
null
Cl.....
Av.....
Be.....
Lu.....
21,295
LonePeak
Lone Peak
UT
null
1,018
hspolicy19
HS Policy 2019-20
2,019
cx
hs
2
4,562,988
We’ll define open borders.
Longley 12-1
Longley 12-1 [Robert; History and Government Expert, B.S., Texas A&M University; “Open Borders: Definition, Pros and Cons,” https://www.thoughtco.com/open-borders-4684612] brett
Open borders policies allow people to move freely between countries or political jurisdictions with no restrictions The term “open borders” refers to government policies allowing immigrants to enter the country with little or no restriction Open borders are the opposite of closed borders, which bar the entry of foreign nationals except under extraordinary circumstances Open Borders Definitions “open borders” implies that people may travel to and from a country without presenting a passport, visa, or another form of legal documentation It does not imply immigrants will automatically be granted citizenship Countries With Open Borders While no countries currently have borders that are completely open for worldwide travel and immigration several countries are members of multinational conventions that allow free travel between member nations For example, most nations of the E U allow people to travel freely—without visas—between countries that have signed the Schengen Agreement of 1985 This essentially makes Europe a single “country,” as it applies to internal travel
open borders refers to government policies allowing immigrants with little restriction travel without a visa multinational conventions allow free travel between member nations For example Schengen
Open borders policies allow people to move freely between countries or political jurisdictions with no restrictions. A country’s borders may be opened because its government either has no border control laws by choice or because it lacks the resources needed to enforce immigration control laws. The term “open borders” does not apply to the flow of goods and services or to the boundaries between privately owned properties. Within most countries, borders between political subdivisions like cities and states are typically open. Key Takeaways: Open Borders The term “open borders” refers to government policies allowing immigrants to enter the country with little or no restriction. Borders may be open due to the absence of border control laws or the lack of resources needed to enforce such laws. Open borders are the opposite of closed borders, which bar the entry of foreign nationals except under extraordinary circumstances. Open Borders Definitions In the strictest sense, the term “open borders” implies that people may travel to and from a country without presenting a passport, visa, or another form of legal documentation. It does not, however, imply that new immigrants will automatically be granted citizenship. In addition to fully open borders, there are other types of international borders classified according to their “degrees of openness” as determined by the enforcement of border control laws. Understanding these types of borders is critical to understanding the political debate over open border policies. Conditionally Open Borders Conditionally open borders allow people who meet a legally established set of conditions to freely enter the country. These conditions represent exemptions to existing border control laws that would otherwise apply. For example, the United States Refugee Act grants the President of the United States the authority to permit a limited number of foreign nationals to enter and remain in the U.S. if they can prove a “credible and reasonable fear” of racial or political persecution in their home nations. Internationally, the United States along with 148 other nations have agreed to adhere to the 1951 Refugee Convention and its 1967 Protocols, which allow people to cross their borders to escape life-threatening situations in their homelands.1 Controlled Borders Countries with controlled borders place restrictions—sometimes significant—on immigration. Today, the United States and a majority of developed nations have controlled borders. Controlled borders typically require persons crossing them to present a visa or may allow for short-term visa-free visits. Controlled borders may impose internal checks to ensure that people who have entered the country are complying with their conditions of entry and have not overstayed their visas, continuing to reside in the country illegally as undocumented immigrants. In addition, physical passage across controlled borders is usually restricted to a limited number of “points of entry,” such as bridges and airports where conditions for entry can be enforced. Controlled borders typically require physical barriers, such as rivers, oceans, or fences to ensure that the border controls are not bypassed. People wishing to cross the border are directed to authorized border crossing points where any conditions of entry can be properly monitored. Controlled borders also require internal checks and internal enforcement within the jurisdiction to ensure that people who have entered the country for work, holidays, study, and other reasons are complying with any entry conditions and not overstaying temporary visas to reside illegally or as undocumented residents. By legislative statute, as in the U.S., most international borders are controlled borders. However, where there is a lack of adequate internal enforcement or where the borders lack physical barriers, the border is often controlled only on parts of the border, while other parts of the border may remain open to such an extent that it may be considered an open border due to lack of supervision and enforcement. Since taking office in January 2021, the administration of President Joe Biden has been faced with a growing number of migrants at the US-Mexico border, many of whom are now from Venezuela, Cuba, and Nicaragua. Recently released U.S. Customs and Border Protection data shows that in fiscal year 2022, border authorities had encountered more than 2 million migrants, some of whom repeatedly tried to cross the border. The data showed a marked increased from fiscal year 2021 when there were more than 1.7 million such encounters. While control of the U.S. border with Mexico remains a source of political debate, the border is guarded by a powerful and well-funded national security agency. The U.S. Border Patrol has nearly doubled in enforcement capacity since 2000, from fewer than 10,000 agents to more than 19,500 in 2020. President Biden has requested $97.3 billion in funding for the Department of Homeland Security for fiscal year 2023, including billions of dollars for border security and internal immigration enforcement. Additionally, the Biden administration has limited the opportunity to apply for asylum for many migrants at the border by continuing the controversial usage of the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention’s Title 42 public health authority initiated under the Donald Trump administration in response to the COVID-19 pandemic. As a result, the administration has carried out more than 1 million expulsions in the first 11 months of fiscal year 2022, on top of the more than one million deportations conducted during the fiscal year 2021. However, on November 16, 2022, a US District Court gave the Biden administration five weeks to end all enforcement of Title 42, finding it to be an “arbitrary and capricious” policy that violated federal regulatory law. But when it ends, the Title 42 system will be replaced by an expanded application of Title 8 proceedings that were in place at the border before COVID and which can bring criminal charges for repeated improper entries, thus further adding to the administration’s border enforcement capabilities. Rather than specifying COVID, Title 8 defines an inadmissible alien as, “Any alien who is determined … to have a communicable disease of public health significance; …” On March 28, 2022, President Biden submitted his Fiscal Year 2023 budget proposal to Congress, a $5.8 trillion request containing $56.7 billion for the Department of Homeland Security (DHS) and $1.4 billion for the Department of Justice’s immigration courts. The request includes a 700% funding increase for the U.S. Citizenship and Immigration Services (USCIS) and an 80% increase for the immigration courts. Of that request, the administration has requested $765 million specifically for caseload and backlog reductions. The discretionary funding is intended to decrease rising asylum backlogs, improve refugee processing, and address the historic backlog of applications for work authorization, naturalization, green cards, and other immigration benefits. For 2023, U.S. Customs and Border Patrol (CBP) will receive 13% more funding than in 2021, with the administration’s request of $15.3 billion to hire an additional 300 Border Patrol agents and 300 officials to process the paperwork and applications of undocumented people entering the country at the southwest border. The budget prioritizes improvements to border processing and management, with funding earmarked to “enforce immigration law, further secure U.S. borders and ports of entry, and effectively manage irregular migration along the Southwest border.” The budget requests $309 million in modern border security technology and $494 million for “noncitizen processing and care costs. Closed Borders Closed borders completely prohibit the entry of foreign nationals under all but exceptional circumstances. The infamous Berlin Wall that separated the people of East and West Berlin, Germany, during the Cold War was an example of a closed border. Today, the Demilitarized Zone between North and South Korea remains one of the few closed borders. Quota Controlled Borders Both conditionally open and controlled borders may impose quota entry restrictions based on an entrant’s country of origin, health, occupation and skills, family status, financial resources, and criminal record. The United States, for example, applies an annual per-country immigration limit, also taking into consideration “preferential” criteria such as an immigrant’s skills, employment potential, and relationship to current U.S. citizens or legal permanent U.S. residents. Main Advantages of Open Borders Some of the main arguments in favor of open borders are: Controlling borders creates a financial drain on governments. For example, the United States budgeted $1.6 billion for a new border wall along the Gulf of Mexico and $210.5 million to hire Border Patrol Agents in 2019 alone.2 In addition, during 2018, the U.S. government spent $3.0 billion—$8.43 million per day—to detain undocumented immigrants.3 Throughout history, immigration has helped fuel the economies of many nations. In a phenomenon dubbed the “immigration surplus,” immigrants in the workforce increase a nation’s level of human capital, inevitably increasing production and raising its annual Gross Domestic Product. For example, immigrants increase the GDP of the United States by an estimated $36 to $72 billion per year.4 Societies have consistently benefited from ethnic diversity resulting from immigration. The new ideas, skills, and cultural practices brought by new immigrants allow society to grow and thrive. Open borders advocates argue that diversity fuels an environment in which people live and work harmoniously, thus contributing to greater creativity. Main Disadvantages of Open Borders Some of the main arguments against open borders are: Some opponents of open borders argue that open borders lead to increased crime. According to data from the U.S. Department of Justice, undocumented immigrants made up 37% total population of federal prisoners as of 2019.5 In addition, U.S. border control officers seized nearly 4.5 million pounds of illegal narcotics at border crossings and ports of entry in 2018.6 Some opponents of open borders also argue that immigrants only contribute to economic growth if the taxes they pay exceed the costs they create. This happens only if a majority of immigrants attain higher income levels. Historically, opponents contend, many immigrants receive below-average incomes, thus creating a net drain on the economy. Large-scale immigration from poorer countries into richer countries can create a "brain drain" in the source country, where educated professionals leave their home country to live elsewhere, depriving their home countries of an educated workforce. For example, in 2010 more Ethiopian doctors were living in Chicago than there were living in all of Ethiopia itself. In the United States, it has been argued that it may cause increased backlash from the white population who carry a majority of the political vote. This backlash includes preventing immigrants' access to basic forms of government or community support as well as the creation of policies that specifically criminalize immigrants. Countries With Open Borders While no countries currently have borders that are completely open for worldwide travel and immigration, several countries are members of multinational conventions that allow free travel between member nations. For example, most nations of the European Union allow people to travel freely—without visas—between countries that have signed the Schengen Agreement of 1985. This essentially makes most of Europe a single “country,” as it applies to internal travel. However, all European countries continue to require visas for travelers coming from countries outside the region. New Zealand and nearby Australia share “open” borders in the sense that they allow their citizens to travel, live, and work in either country with few restrictions. Several other nation-pairs such as India and Nepal, Russia and Belarus, and Ireland and the United Kingdom share similarly “open” borders.
12,225
<h4>We’ll define <u>open borders</u>.</h4><p><strong>Longley 12-1</strong> [Robert; History and Government Expert, B.S., Texas A&M University; “Open Borders: Definition, Pros and Cons,” https://www.thoughtco.com/open-borders-4684612] brett</p><p><u><strong>Open borders policies allow people to move freely between countries or political jurisdictions with no restrictions</u></strong>. A country’s borders may be opened because its government either has no border control laws by choice or because it lacks the resources needed to enforce immigration control laws. The term “open borders” does not apply to the flow of goods and services or to the boundaries between privately owned properties. Within most countries, borders between political subdivisions like cities and states are typically open. Key Takeaways: Open Borders <u>The term “<strong><mark>open borders</strong></mark>” <mark>refers to <strong>government policies</strong></mark> <mark>allowing immigrants</mark> to</u> <u>enter the country <mark>with <strong>little</strong></mark> or no <strong><mark>restriction</u></strong></mark>. Borders may be open due to the absence of border control laws or the lack of resources needed to enforce such laws. <u>Open borders are the <strong>opposite of closed borders</strong>, which bar the entry of foreign nationals except under extraordinary circumstances</u>. <u><strong>Open Borders Definitions </u></strong>In the strictest sense, the term <u><strong>“open borders”</u></strong> <u>implies</u> <u>that people may <mark>travel</mark> <strong>to and from a country</strong> <mark>without</mark> presenting <mark>a</mark> <strong>passport</strong>, <strong><mark>visa</strong></mark>, or another form of <strong>legal documentation</u></strong>. <u>It does not</u>, however, <u>imply</u> that new <u>immigrants will <strong>automatic</strong>ally be granted <strong>citizenship</u></strong>. In addition to fully open borders, there are other types of international borders classified according to their “degrees of openness” as determined by the enforcement of border control laws. Understanding these types of borders is critical to understanding the political debate over open border policies. Conditionally Open Borders Conditionally open borders allow people who meet a legally established set of conditions to freely enter the country. These conditions represent exemptions to existing border control laws that would otherwise apply. For example, the United States Refugee Act grants the President of the United States the authority to permit a limited number of foreign nationals to enter and remain in the U.S. if they can prove a “credible and reasonable fear” of racial or political persecution in their home nations. Internationally, the United States along with 148 other nations have agreed to adhere to the 1951 Refugee Convention and its 1967 Protocols, which allow people to cross their borders to escape life-threatening situations in their homelands.1 Controlled Borders Countries with controlled borders place restrictions—sometimes significant—on immigration. Today, the United States and a majority of developed nations have controlled borders. Controlled borders typically require persons crossing them to present a visa or may allow for short-term visa-free visits. Controlled borders may impose internal checks to ensure that people who have entered the country are complying with their conditions of entry and have not overstayed their visas, continuing to reside in the country illegally as undocumented immigrants. In addition, physical passage across controlled borders is usually restricted to a limited number of “points of entry,” such as bridges and airports where conditions for entry can be enforced. Controlled borders typically require physical barriers, such as rivers, oceans, or fences to ensure that the border controls are not bypassed. People wishing to cross the border are directed to authorized border crossing points where any conditions of entry can be properly monitored. Controlled borders also require internal checks and internal enforcement within the jurisdiction to ensure that people who have entered the country for work, holidays, study, and other reasons are complying with any entry conditions and not overstaying temporary visas to reside illegally or as undocumented residents. By legislative statute, as in the U.S., most international borders are controlled borders. However, where there is a lack of adequate internal enforcement or where the borders lack physical barriers, the border is often controlled only on parts of the border, while other parts of the border may remain open to such an extent that it may be considered an open border due to lack of supervision and enforcement. Since taking office in January 2021, the administration of President Joe Biden has been faced with a growing number of migrants at the US-Mexico border, many of whom are now from Venezuela, Cuba, and Nicaragua. Recently released U.S. Customs and Border Protection data shows that in fiscal year 2022, border authorities had encountered more than 2 million migrants, some of whom repeatedly tried to cross the border. The data showed a marked increased from fiscal year 2021 when there were more than 1.7 million such encounters. While control of the U.S. border with Mexico remains a source of political debate, the border is guarded by a powerful and well-funded national security agency. The U.S. Border Patrol has nearly doubled in enforcement capacity since 2000, from fewer than 10,000 agents to more than 19,500 in 2020. President Biden has requested $97.3 billion in funding for the Department of Homeland Security for fiscal year 2023, including billions of dollars for border security and internal immigration enforcement. Additionally, the Biden administration has limited the opportunity to apply for asylum for many migrants at the border by continuing the controversial usage of the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention’s Title 42 public health authority initiated under the Donald Trump administration in response to the COVID-19 pandemic. As a result, the administration has carried out more than 1 million expulsions in the first 11 months of fiscal year 2022, on top of the more than one million deportations conducted during the fiscal year 2021. However, on November 16, 2022, a US District Court gave the Biden administration five weeks to end all enforcement of Title 42, finding it to be an “arbitrary and capricious” policy that violated federal regulatory law. But when it ends, the Title 42 system will be replaced by an expanded application of Title 8 proceedings that were in place at the border before COVID and which can bring criminal charges for repeated improper entries, thus further adding to the administration’s border enforcement capabilities. Rather than specifying COVID, Title 8 defines an inadmissible alien as, “Any alien who is determined … to have a communicable disease of public health significance; …” On March 28, 2022, President Biden submitted his Fiscal Year 2023 budget proposal to Congress, a $5.8 trillion request containing $56.7 billion for the Department of Homeland Security (DHS) and $1.4 billion for the Department of Justice’s immigration courts. The request includes a 700% funding increase for the U.S. Citizenship and Immigration Services (USCIS) and an 80% increase for the immigration courts. Of that request, the administration has requested $765 million specifically for caseload and backlog reductions. The discretionary funding is intended to decrease rising asylum backlogs, improve refugee processing, and address the historic backlog of applications for work authorization, naturalization, green cards, and other immigration benefits. For 2023, U.S. Customs and Border Patrol (CBP) will receive 13% more funding than in 2021, with the administration’s request of $15.3 billion to hire an additional 300 Border Patrol agents and 300 officials to process the paperwork and applications of undocumented people entering the country at the southwest border. The budget prioritizes improvements to border processing and management, with funding earmarked to “enforce immigration law, further secure U.S. borders and ports of entry, and effectively manage irregular migration along the Southwest border.” The budget requests $309 million in modern border security technology and $494 million for “noncitizen processing and care costs. Closed Borders Closed borders completely prohibit the entry of foreign nationals under all but exceptional circumstances. The infamous Berlin Wall that separated the people of East and West Berlin, Germany, during the Cold War was an example of a closed border. Today, the Demilitarized Zone between North and South Korea remains one of the few closed borders. Quota Controlled Borders Both conditionally open and controlled borders may impose quota entry restrictions based on an entrant’s country of origin, health, occupation and skills, family status, financial resources, and criminal record. The United States, for example, applies an annual per-country immigration limit, also taking into consideration “preferential” criteria such as an immigrant’s skills, employment potential, and relationship to current U.S. citizens or legal permanent U.S. residents. Main Advantages of Open Borders Some of the main arguments in favor of open borders are: Controlling borders creates a financial drain on governments. For example, the United States budgeted $1.6 billion for a new border wall along the Gulf of Mexico and $210.5 million to hire Border Patrol Agents in 2019 alone.2 In addition, during 2018, the U.S. government spent $3.0 billion—$8.43 million per day—to detain undocumented immigrants.3 Throughout history, immigration has helped fuel the economies of many nations. In a phenomenon dubbed the “immigration surplus,” immigrants in the workforce increase a nation’s level of human capital, inevitably increasing production and raising its annual Gross Domestic Product. For example, immigrants increase the GDP of the United States by an estimated $36 to $72 billion per year.4 Societies have consistently benefited from ethnic diversity resulting from immigration. The new ideas, skills, and cultural practices brought by new immigrants allow society to grow and thrive. Open borders advocates argue that diversity fuels an environment in which people live and work harmoniously, thus contributing to greater creativity. Main Disadvantages of Open Borders Some of the main arguments against open borders are: Some opponents of open borders argue that open borders lead to increased crime. According to data from the U.S. Department of Justice, undocumented immigrants made up 37% total population of federal prisoners as of 2019.5 In addition, U.S. border control officers seized nearly 4.5 million pounds of illegal narcotics at border crossings and ports of entry in 2018.6 Some opponents of open borders also argue that immigrants only contribute to economic growth if the taxes they pay exceed the costs they create. This happens only if a majority of immigrants attain higher income levels. Historically, opponents contend, many immigrants receive below-average incomes, thus creating a net drain on the economy. Large-scale immigration from poorer countries into richer countries can create a "brain drain" in the source country, where educated professionals leave their home country to live elsewhere, depriving their home countries of an educated workforce. For example, in 2010 more Ethiopian doctors were living in Chicago than there were living in all of Ethiopia itself. In the United States, it has been argued that it may cause increased backlash from the white population who carry a majority of the political vote. This backlash includes preventing immigrants' access to basic forms of government or community support as well as the creation of policies that specifically criminalize immigrants. <u><strong>Countries With Open Borders </strong>While no countries currently have borders that are completely open for <strong>worldwide travel and immigration</u></strong>, <u><strong>several countries</strong> are members of <strong><mark>multinational conventions</strong></mark> that <mark>allow <strong>free travel</strong> between <strong>member nations</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong><mark>For example</mark>,</u></strong> <u>most nations of the</u> <u><strong>E</u></strong>uropean <u><strong>U</u></strong>nion <u>allow people to travel freely—<strong>without visas</strong>—between countries that have signed the <strong><mark>Schengen</mark> Agreement</strong> of <strong>1985</u></strong>. <u>This essentially makes</u> most of <u>Europe a single “country,” as it applies to <strong>internal travel</u></strong>. However, all European countries continue to require visas for travelers coming from countries outside the region. New Zealand and nearby Australia share “open” borders in the sense that they allow their citizens to travel, live, and work in either country with few restrictions. Several other nation-pairs such as India and Nepal, Russia and Belarus, and Ireland and the United Kingdom share similarly “open” borders.</p>
null
null
null
1,698,856
1,342
150,698
./documents/hsld22/Livingston/RaBa/Livingston-RaBa-Aff-The-Newark-Invitational-2023-Round-5.docx
960,051
A
newark
5
eastern lw
murno
ac- schenlargenment nc- t, new affs bad, circuitdebater, set col, no borders cp 1ar- all nr- set col 2ar- cp
hsld22/Livingston/RaBa/Livingston-RaBa-Aff-The-Newark-Invitational-2023-Round-5.docx
2023-04-06 18:07:31
80,368
RaBa
Livingston RaBa
null
Ra.....
Ba.....
null
null
26,998
Livingston
Livingston
NJ
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
1,479,796
5] Natural pandemics won’t cause extinction
Farquhar 17
Sebastian Farquhar 1/23/17, director at Oxford's Global Priorities Project, Owen Cotton-Barratt, a Lecturer in Mathematics at St Hugh’s College, Oxford, John Halstead, Stefan Schubert, Haydn Belfield, Andrew Snyder-Beattie, "Existential Risk Diplomacy and Governance", GLOBAL PRIORITIES PROJECT 2017, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf
. natural pandemics are very unlikely to cause human extinction of the 833 recorded species extinctions since 1500, less than 4% (31 species) were ascribed to infectious disease None of the mammals and amphibians on this list were globally dispersed, and other factors aside from infectious disease also contributed to their extinction. It therefore seems that our own species, which is very numerous, globally dispersed, and capable of a rational response to problems, is very unlikely to be killed off by a natural pandemic highly lethal pathogens can kill their hosts before they have a chance to spread, so there is a selective pressure for pathogens not to be highly lethal. Therefore, pathogens are likely to co-evolve with their hosts rather than kill all possible hosts
natural pandemics are very unlikely to cause human extinction of extinctions less than 4% were disease our species is numerous dispersed, and capable of rational response highly lethal pathogens kill their hosts before they spread, so there is a selective pressure for pathogens not to be highly lethal
1.1.3 Engineered pandemics For most of human history, natural pandemics have posed the greatest risk of mass global fatalities.37 However, there are some reasons to believe that natural pandemics are very unlikely to cause human extinction. Analysis of the International Union for Conservation of Nature (IUCN) red list database has shown that of the 833 recorded plant and animal species extinctions known to have occurred since 1500, less than 4% (31 species) were ascribed to infectious disease.38 None of the mammals and amphibians on this list were globally dispersed, and other factors aside from infectious disease also contributed to their extinction. It therefore seems that our own species, which is very numerous, globally dispersed, and capable of a rational response to problems, is very unlikely to be killed off by a natural pandemic. One underlying explanation for this is that highly lethal pathogens can kill their hosts before they have a chance to spread, so there is a selective pressure for pathogens not to be highly lethal. Therefore, pathogens are likely to co-evolve with their hosts rather than kill all possible hosts.39
1,148
<h4>5] Natural pandemics won’t cause extinction</h4><p>Sebastian <strong>Farquhar</strong> 1/23/<strong>17</strong>, director at Oxford's Global Priorities Project, Owen Cotton-Barratt, a Lecturer in Mathematics at St Hugh’s College, Oxford, John Halstead, Stefan Schubert, Haydn Belfield, Andrew Snyder-Beattie, "Existential Risk Diplomacy and Governance", GLOBAL PRIORITIES PROJECT 2017, https://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/Existential-Risks-2017-01-23.pdf</p><p>1.1.3 Engineered pandemics For most of human history, natural pandemics have posed the greatest risk of mass global<u> </u>fatalities<u>.</u>37 However, there are some reasons to believe that <u><strong><mark>natural pandemics are very unlikely to cause human extinction</u></strong></mark>. Analysis of the International Union for Conservation of Nature (IUCN) red list database has shown that <u><mark>of </mark>the 833 recorded </u>plant and animal <u>species <mark>extinctions</u></mark> known to have occurred <u>since 1500, <mark>less than 4%</mark> (31 species) <mark>were</mark> ascribed to infectious <mark>disease</u></mark>.38 <u>None of the mammals and amphibians on this list were globally dispersed, and other factors aside from infectious disease also contributed to their extinction. It therefore seems that <mark>our</mark> own <mark>species</mark>, which <mark>is</mark> very <strong><mark>numerous</strong></mark>, globally <strong><mark>dispersed</strong>, and capable of</mark> a <strong><mark>rational response</strong></mark> to problems, <strong>is very unlikely to be killed off by a natural pandemic</u></strong>. One underlying explanation for this is that <u><mark>highly lethal pathogens</mark> can <mark>kill their hosts before they</mark> have a chance to <mark>spread, so <strong>there is a selective pressure for pathogens not to be highly lethal</strong></mark>. Therefore, pathogens are likely to co-evolve with their hosts rather than kill all possible hosts</u>.39</p>
1NC
Case
Adv 1
2,356
2,146
41,286
./documents/hsld21/Lynbrook/Mo/Lynbrook-Modi-Neg-Nano%20Nagle-Round5.docx
892,807
N
Nano Nagle
5
Harker NA
Gerard Grigsby
1AC - trade secrets 1NC - t reduce AND t ipp AND multiplank cp AND case 1AR - covered 2NR - cp AND case 2AR - covered
hsld21/Lynbrook/Mo/Lynbrook-Modi-Neg-Nano%20Nagle-Round5.docx
null
74,985
ShMo
Lynbrook ShMo
null
Sh.....
Mo.....
null
null
25,064
Lynbrook
Lynbrook
CA
null
1,029
hsld21
HS LD 2021-22
2,021
ld
hs
1
3,298,405
3. Policy education is best for portable skills – discussing legal solutions key.
Nixon 2K
Nixon 2K [Makani Themba-Nixon, Executive Director of The Praxis Project. “Changing the Rules: What Public Policy Means for Organizing.” Colorlines 3.2, 2000.]
By getting into the policy arena in a proactive manner we can take our demands to the next level Our demands can become law with real consequences if the agreement is broken this work requires a certain amount of interaction with "the suits," as well as struggles with the bureaucracy the technical language and the all-too-common resistance by decision makers policy work is just one tool in our organizing arsenal, but it is a tool we simply can't afford to ignore We will need to develop the capacity to translate our information data, stories that are designed to affect the public conversation we will need to move beyond fighting problems and on to framing solutions
By getting into policy in a proactive manner demands can become law with real consequences this work requires struggles with bureaucracy technical language and resistance by decision makers policy work is a tool we can't ignore We need to translate information to affect public conversation and to framing solutions
Getting It in Writing Much of the work of framing what we stand for takes place in the shaping of demands. By getting into the policy arena in a proactive manner, we can take our demands to the next level. Our demands can become law, with real consequences if the agreement is broken. After all the organizing, press work, and effort, a group should leave a decision maker with more than a handshake and his or her word. Of course, this work requires a certain amount of interaction with "the suits," as well as struggles with the bureaucracy, the technical language, and the all-too-common resistance by decision makers. Still, if it's worth demanding, it's worth having in writing-whether as law, regulation, or internal policy. From ballot initiatives on rent control to laws requiring worker protections, organizers are leveraging their power into written policies that are making a real difference in their communities. Of course, policy work is just one tool in our organizing arsenal, but it is a tool we simply can't afford to ignore. Making policy work an integral part of organizing will require a certain amount of retrofitting. We will need to develop the capacity to translate our information, data, stories that are designed to affect the public conversation. Perhaps most important, we will need to move beyond fighting problems and on to framing solutions that bring us closer to our vision of how things should be. And then we must be committed to making it so.
1,478
<h4>3. Policy education is best for <u>portable skills</u> – discussing legal solutions <u>key</u><strong>.</h4><p>Nixon 2K </strong>[Makani Themba-Nixon, Executive Director of The Praxis Project. “Changing the Rules: What Public Policy Means for Organizing.” Colorlines 3.2, 2000.]</p><p>Getting It in Writing Much of the work of framing what we stand for takes place in the shaping of demands. <u><mark>By getting into</mark> the <mark>policy</mark> arena <mark>in a proactive manner</u></mark>, <u>we can take our demands to the next level</u>. <u>Our <strong><mark>demands can become law</u></strong></mark>, <u><mark>with real consequences</mark> if the agreement is broken</u>. After all the organizing, press work, and effort, a group should leave a decision maker with more than a handshake and his or her word. Of course, <u><mark>this work requires</mark> a certain amount of interaction with "the suits," as well as <mark>struggles with</mark> the <mark>bureaucracy</u></mark>, <u>the <mark>technical language</u></mark>, <u><strong><mark>and</strong></mark> the all-too-common <strong><mark>resistance by decision makers</u></strong></mark>. Still, if it's worth demanding, it's worth having in writing-whether as law, regulation, or internal policy. From ballot initiatives on rent control to laws requiring worker protections, organizers are leveraging their power into written policies that are making a real difference in their communities. Of course, <u><mark>policy work</mark> is just one tool in our organizing arsenal, but it <strong><mark>is a tool we</strong></mark> simply <strong><mark>can't</strong></mark> afford to <strong><mark>ignore</u></strong></mark>. Making policy work an integral part of organizing will require a certain amount of retrofitting. <u><mark>We</mark> will <mark>need</mark> to develop the capacity <mark>to translate</mark> our <mark>information</u></mark>, <u>data, stories that are designed <mark>to affect</mark> the <mark>public conversation</u></mark>. Perhaps most important, <u>we will need to move beyond fighting problems <mark>and</mark> on <strong><mark>to framing solutions</u></strong></mark> that bring us closer to our vision of how things should be. And then we must be committed to making it so.</p>
null
null
Framework
1,240,661
568
108,291
./documents/hsld18/ESD/Ha/ESD-Haq-Aff-TFA%20state-Round2.docx
819,303
A
TFA state
2
Clear Brook ASnot 100
Matthew Higgins
1ac- Needles 1nc- T and case else- same
hsld18/ESD/Ha/ESD-Haq-Aff-TFA%20state-Round2.docx
null
70,172
ZaHa
ESD ZaHa
null
Za.....
Ha.....
null
null
23,716
ESD
ESD
null
null
1,026
hsld18
HS LD 2018-19
2,018
ld
hs
1
714,845
The state is inevitable- policymaking is the only way to create change.
Coverstone 5 Control of the government is what active, participatory citizenry is supposed to be about citizens bear the obligation to discuss and debate what the government should be doing. Absent that discussion motivation for personal political activism is lost personal narratives unconnected to political power are co-opted by those who do learn the language of power role-playing that public policy contest debates encourage promotes active learning of the vocabulary and levers of power in America Imagining the ability to use arguments to influence government action is one of the great virtues of academic debate students’ lack of faith in the power of persuasion reflects the waning of the ideal of civic participation The power to imagine public advocacy makes a difference is one of the great virtues of fiat Simulation is far more empowering than completely abandoning all notions of personal power in the face of governmental hegemony Imagining myself starting a socialist revolution is no less of a fantasy than making a difference on Capitol Hill. One fantasy does make a greater difference one speaks the language of political power The other disables action by making one a laughingstock language of power paves the way for genuine political activism political strategies for pro-social change must confront governmental power
Coverstone 5 Alan Coverstone (masters in communication from Wake Forest, longtime debate coach) “Acting on Activism: Realizing the Vision of Debate with Pro-social Impact” Paper presented at the National Communication Association Annual Conference November 17th 2005 An important concern emerges when Mitchell describes reflexive fiat as a contest strategy capable of “eschewing the power to directly control external actors” (1998b, p. 20). Describing debates about what our government should do as attempts to control outside actors is debilitating and disempowering. Control of the US government is exactly what an active, participatory citizenry is supposed to be all about. After all, if democracy means anything, it means that citizens not only have the right, they also bear the obligation to discuss and debate what the government should be doing. Absent that discussion and debate, much of the motivation for personal political activism is also lost. Those who have co-opted Mitchell’s argument for individual advocacy often quickly respond that nothing we do in a debate round can actually change government policy, and unfortunately, an entire generation of debaters has now swallowed this assertion as an article of faith. The best most will muster is, “Of course not, but you don’t either!” The assertion that nothing we do in debate has any impact on government policy is one that carries the potential to undermine Mitchell’s entire project. If there is nothing we can do in a debate round to change government policy, then we are left with precious little in the way of pro-social options for addressing problems we face. At best, we can pursue some Pilot-like hand washing that can purify us as individuals through quixotic activism but offer little to society as a whole. It is very important to note that Mitchell (1998b) tries carefully to limit and bound his notion of reflexive fiat by maintaining that because it “views fiat as a concrete course of action, it is bounded by the limits of pragmatism” (p. 20). Pursued properly, the debates that Mitchell would like to see are those in which the relative efficacy of concrete political strategies for pro-social change is debated. In a few noteworthy examples, this approach has been employed successfully, and I must say that I have thoroughly enjoyed judging and coaching those debates. The students in my program have learned to stretch their understanding of their role in the political process because of the experience. Therefore, those who say I am opposed to Mitchell’s goals here should take care at such a blanket assertion. However, contest debate teaches students to combine personal experience with the language of political power. Powerful personal narratives unconnected to political power are regularly co-opted by those who do learn the language of power. One need look no further than the annual state of the Union Address where personal story after personal story is used to support the political agenda of those in power. The so-called role-playing that public policy contest debates encourage promotes active learning of the vocabulary and levers of power in America. Imagining the ability to use our own arguments to influence government action is one of the great virtues of academic debate. Gerald Graff (2003) analyzed the decline of argumentation in academic discourse and found a source of student antipathy to public argument in an interesting place. I’m up against…their aversion to the role of public spokesperson that formal writing presupposes. It’s as if such students can’t imagine any rewards for being a public actor or even imagining themselves in such a role. This lack of interest in the public sphere may in turn reflect a loss of confidence in the possibility that the arguments we make in public will have an effect on the world. Today’s students’ lack of faith in the power of persuasion reflects the waning of the ideal of civic participation that led educators for centuries to place rhetorical and argumentative training at the center of the school and college curriculum. (Graff, 2003, p. 57) The power to imagine public advocacy that actually makes a difference is one of the great virtues of the traditional notion of fiat that critics deride as mere simulation. Simulation of success in the public realm is far more empowering to students than completely abandoning all notions of personal power in the face of governmental hegemony by teaching students that “nothing they can do in a contest debate can ever make any difference in public policy.” Contest debating is well suited to rewarding public activism if it stops accepting as an article of faith that personal agency is somehow undermined by the so-called role playing in debate. Debate is role-playing whether we imagine government action or imagine individual action. Imagining myself starting a socialist revolution in America is no less of a fantasy than imagining myself making a difference on Capitol Hill. Furthermore, both fantasies influenced my personal and political development virtually ensuring a life of active, pro-social, political participation. Neither fantasy reduced the likelihood that I would spend my life trying to make the difference I imagined. One fantasy actually does make a greater difference: the one that speaks the language of political power. The other fantasy disables action by making one a laughingstock to those who wield the language of power. Fantasy motivates and role-playing trains through visualization. Until we can imagine it, we cannot really do it. Role-playing without question teaches students to be comfortable with the language of power, and that language paves the way for genuine and effective political activism. Debates over the relative efficacy of political strategies for pro-social change must confront governmental power at some point. There is a fallacy in arguing that movements represent a better political strategy than voting and person-to-person advocacy. Sure, a full-scale movement would be better than the limited voice I have as a participating citizen going from door to door in a campaign, but so would full-scale government action. Unfortunately, the gap between my individual decision to pursue movement politics and the emergence of a full-scale movement is at least as great as the gap between my vote and democratic change. They both represent utopian fiat. Invocation of Mitchell to support utopian movement fiat is simply not supported by his work, and too often, such invocation discourages the concrete actions he argues for in favor of the personal rejectionism that under girds the political cynicism that is a fundamental cause of voter and participatory abstention in America today.
Zanotti 14 Options for resistance to government scripts are not limited to ‘‘rejection, It is found instead in contingent struggles that are within government rationalities and at the same time exceed and transform them This approach questions oversimplifications of complex political rationalities and nurtures a skepticism about identifying universally good or bad actors or abstract solutions to political problems. power interacts in complex ways with diverse political spaces Government as a heuristic invites careful differentiations rather than overarching demonization of ‘‘power,’’ romanticizations of the ‘‘rebel’’ and foster an ethic of political engagement taken through plural and uncertain practices, that demand continuous attention to ‘‘what happens’’ instead of fixations on ‘‘what ought to be. Such ethics of engagement would not await the revolution Instead, it would constantly attempt to twist power by playing with whatever cards are available and would require intense processes of reflexivity on the consequences of political choices So my position leads not to apathy but to hyper- and pessimistic activism.’’84
resistance to government is found in contingent struggles that are within government rationalities and transform them power interacts in complex ways with diverse political spaces Government as a heuristic invites careful differentiations rather than overarching demonization and foster an ethic of political engagement taken through plural practices ethics of engagement would constantly attempt to twist power my position leads not to apathy but to activism.
Working within the state is not a form of complacency within violence, but rather provides a means of understanding the state and breaking it down. Zanotti 14 Dr. Laura Zanotti is an Associate Professor of Political Science at Virginia Tech. Her research and teaching include critical political theory as well as international organizations, UN peacekeeping, democratization and the role of NGOs in post-conflict governance.“Governmentality, Ontology, Methodology: Re-thinking Political Agency in the Global World” – Alternatives: Global, Local, Political – vol 38(4):p. 288-304,. A little unclear if this is late 2013 or early 2014 – The Stated “Version of Record” is Feb 20, 2014, but was originally published online on December 30th, 2013. Obtained via Sage Database. By questioning substantialist representations of power and subjects, inquiries on the possibilities of political agency are reframed in a way that focuses on power and subjects’ relational character and the contingent processes of their (trans)formation in the context of agonic relations. Options for resistance to governmental scripts are not limited to ‘‘rejection,’’ ‘‘revolution,’’ or ‘‘dispossession’’ to regain a pristine ‘‘freedom from all constraints’’ or an immanent ideal social order. It is found instead in multifarious and contingent struggles that are constituted within the scripts of governmental rationalities and at the same time exceed and transform them. This approach questions oversimplifications of the complexities of liberal political rationalities and of their interactions with non-liberal political players and nurtures a radical skepticism about identifying universally good or bad actors or abstract solutions to political problems. International power interacts in complex ways with diverse political spaces and within these spaces it is appropriated, hybridized, redescribed, hijacked, and tinkered with. Governmentality as a heuristic focuses on performing complex diagnostics of events. It invites historically situated explorations and careful differentiations rather than overarching demonizations of ‘‘power,’’ romanticizations of the ‘‘rebel’’ or the ‘‘the local.’’ More broadly, theoretical formulations that conceive the subject in non-substantialist terms and focus on processes of subjectification, on the ambiguity of power discourses, and on hybridization as the terrain for political transformation, open ways for reconsidering political agency beyond the dichotomy of oppression/rebellion. These alternative formulations also foster an ethics of political engagement, to be continuously taken up through plural and uncertain practices, that demand continuous attention to ‘‘what happens’’ instead of fixations on ‘‘what ought to be.’’83 Such ethics of engagement would not await the revolution to come or hope for a pristine ‘‘freedom’’ to be regained. Instead, it would constantly attempt to twist the working of power by playing with whatever cards are available and would require intense processes of reflexivity on the consequences of political choices. To conclude with a famous phrase by Michel Foucault ‘‘my point is not that everything is bad, but that everything is dangerous, which is not exactly the same as bad. If everything is dangerous, then we always have something to do. So my position leads not to apathy but to hyper- and pessimistic activism.’’84
3,387
<h4>The state is inevitable- policymaking is the only way to create change.</h4><p><strong>Coverstone 5</strong> Alan Coverstone (masters in communication from Wake Forest, longtime debate coach) “Acting on Activism: Realizing the Vision of Debate with Pro-social Impact” Paper presented at the National Communication Association Annual Conference November 17th 2005 An important concern emerges when Mitchell describes reflexive fiat as a contest strategy capable of “eschewing the power to directly control external actors” (1998b, p. 20). Describing debates about what our government should do as attempts to control outside actors is debilitating and disempowering. <u><strong><mark>Control of</mark> the</u></strong> US <u><strong><mark>government is</u></strong></mark> exactly <u><strong><mark>what</u></strong></mark> an <u><strong>active, participatory <mark>citizenry is</mark> supposed to be</u></strong> all <u><strong><mark>about</u></strong></mark>. After all, if democracy means anything, it means that <u><strong><mark>citizens</u></strong></mark> not only have the right, they also <u><strong><mark>bear the obligation to discuss</mark> and debate <mark>what the government should be doing</mark>.</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>Absent that</mark> discussion</u></strong> and debate, much of the <u><strong><mark>motivation for</mark> personal political <mark>activism is</u></strong></mark> also <u><strong><mark>lost</u></strong></mark>. Those who have co-opted Mitchell’s argument for individual advocacy often quickly respond that nothing we do in a debate round can actually change government policy, and unfortunately, an entire generation of debaters has now swallowed this assertion as an article of faith. The best most will muster is, “Of course not, but you don’t either!” The assertion that nothing we do in debate has any impact on government policy is one that carries the potential to undermine Mitchell’s entire project. If there is nothing we can do in a debate round to change government policy, then we are left with precious little in the way of pro-social options for addressing problems we face. At best, we can pursue some Pilot-like hand washing that can purify us as individuals through quixotic activism but offer little to society as a whole. It is very important to note that Mitchell (1998b) tries carefully to limit and bound his notion of reflexive fiat by maintaining that because it “views fiat as a concrete course of action, it is bounded by the limits of pragmatism” (p. 20). Pursued properly, the debates that Mitchell would like to see are those in which the relative efficacy of concrete political strategies for pro-social change is debated. In a few noteworthy examples, this approach has been employed successfully, and I must say that I have thoroughly enjoyed judging and coaching those debates. The students in my program have learned to stretch their understanding of their role in the political process because of the experience. Therefore, those who say I am opposed to Mitchell’s goals here should take care at such a blanket assertion. However, contest debate teaches students to combine personal experience with the language of political power. Powerful <u><strong>personal <mark>narratives unconnected to political power are</u></strong></mark> regularly <u><strong><mark>co-opted</mark> by those who do learn the language of power</u></strong>. One need look no further than the annual state of the Union Address where personal story after personal story is used to support the political agenda of those in power. The so-called <u><strong><mark>role-playing</mark> that public policy contest debates encourage <mark>promotes active learning of</mark> the vocabulary and levers of <mark>power </mark>in America</u></strong>. <u><strong>Imagining the ability to use</u></strong> our own <u><strong>arguments to influence government action is one of the great virtues of academic debate</u></strong>. Gerald Graff (2003) analyzed the decline of argumentation in academic discourse and found a source of student antipathy to public argument in an interesting place. I’m up against…their aversion to the role of public spokesperson that formal writing presupposes. It’s as if such students can’t imagine any rewards for being a public actor or even imagining themselves in such a role. This lack of interest in the public sphere may in turn reflect a loss of confidence in the possibility that the arguments we make in public will have an effect on the world. Today’s <u><strong>students’ lack of faith in the power of persuasion reflects the waning of the ideal of civic participation</u></strong> that led educators for centuries to place rhetorical and argumentative training at the center of the school and college curriculum. (Graff, 2003, p. 57) <u><strong>The power to imagine public advocacy</u></strong> that actually <u><strong>makes a difference is one of the great virtues of</u></strong> the traditional notion of <u><strong>fiat</u></strong> that critics deride as mere simulation. <u><strong><mark>Simulation</u></strong></mark> of success in the public realm <u><strong><mark>is</mark> far <mark>more empowering</u></strong></mark> to students <u><strong><mark>than</mark> completely <mark>abandoning </mark>all notions of personal <mark>power in the face of</mark> governmental <mark>hegemony</u></strong></mark> by teaching students that “nothing they can do in a contest debate can ever make any difference in public policy.” Contest debating is well suited to rewarding public activism if it stops accepting as an article of faith that personal agency is somehow undermined by the so-called role playing in debate. Debate is role-playing whether we imagine government action or imagine individual action. <u><strong><mark>Imagining</mark> myself starting a <mark>socialist revolution</u></strong></mark> in America <u><strong><mark>is no less of a fantasy than</u></strong></mark> imagining myself <u><strong>making <mark>a difference on Capitol Hill</mark>.</u></strong> Furthermore, both fantasies influenced my personal and political development virtually ensuring a life of active, pro-social, political participation. Neither fantasy reduced the likelihood that I would spend my life trying to make the difference I imagined. <u><strong><mark>One fantasy</u></strong></mark> actually <u><strong>does make a greater difference</u></strong>: the <u><strong>one</u></strong> that <u><strong><mark>speaks the language of </mark>political <mark>power</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong><mark>The other</u></strong></mark> fantasy <u><strong><mark>disables action</mark> by making one a laughingstock</u></strong> to those who wield the language of power. Fantasy motivates and role-playing trains through visualization. Until we can imagine it, we cannot really do it. Role-playing without question teaches students to be comfortable with the <u><strong>language of power</u></strong>, and that language <u><strong>paves the way for genuine</u></strong> and effective <u><strong>political activism</u></strong>. Debates over the relative efficacy of <u><strong>political <mark>strategies</mark> for pro-social change <mark>must confront governmental power</u></strong></mark> at some point. There is a fallacy in arguing that movements represent a better political strategy than voting and person-to-person advocacy. Sure, a full-scale movement would be better than the limited voice I have as a participating citizen going from door to door in a campaign, but so would full-scale government action. Unfortunately, the gap between my individual decision to pursue movement politics and the emergence of a full-scale movement is at least as great as the gap between my vote and democratic change. They both represent utopian fiat. Invocation of Mitchell to support utopian movement fiat is simply not supported by his work, and too often, such invocation discourages the concrete actions he argues for in favor of the personal rejectionism that under girds the political cynicism that is a fundamental cause of voter and participatory abstention in America today.</p><p><strong>Working within the state is not a form of complacency within violence, but rather provides a means of understanding the state and breaking it down.</strong> <u><strong>Zanotti 14</u></strong> Dr. Laura Zanotti is an Associate Professor of Political Science at Virginia Tech. Her research and teaching include critical political theory as well as international organizations, UN peacekeeping, democratization and the role of NGOs in post-conflict governance.“Governmentality, Ontology, Methodology: Re-thinking Political Agency in the Global World” – Alternatives: Global, Local, Political – vol 38(4):p. 288-304,. A little unclear if this is late 2013 or early 2014 – The Stated “Version of Record” is Feb 20, 2014, but was originally published online on December 30th, 2013. Obtained via Sage Database. By questioning substantialist representations of power and subjects, inquiries on the possibilities of political agency are reframed in a way that focuses on power and subjects’ relational character and the contingent processes of their (trans)formation in the context of agonic relations. <u><strong>Options for <mark>resistance to government</u></strong></mark>al <u><strong>scripts are not limited to ‘‘rejection,</u></strong>’’ ‘‘revolution,’’ or ‘‘dispossession’’ to regain a pristine ‘‘freedom from all constraints’’ or an immanent ideal social order. <u><strong>It <mark>is found</mark> instead <mark>in</mark> </u></strong>multifarious and <u><strong><mark>contingent struggles</u></strong></mark> <u><strong><mark>that are</u></strong></mark> constituted <u><strong><mark>within</u></strong></mark> the scripts of <u><strong><mark>government</u></strong></mark>al <u><strong><mark>rationalities</mark> <mark>and </mark>at the same time exceed and</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>transform them</u></strong></mark>. <u><strong>This approach questions oversimplifications of</u></strong> the <u><strong>complex</u></strong>ities of liberal<u><strong> political rationalities</u></strong> and of their interactions with non-liberal political players <u><strong>and nurtures a</u></strong> radical <u><strong>skepticism about identifying universally good or bad actors or abstract solutions to political problems.</u></strong> International<u><strong> <mark>power</mark> <mark>interacts in complex ways with diverse political spaces</u></strong></mark> and within these spaces it is appropriated, hybridized, redescribed, hijacked, and tinkered with. <u><strong><mark>Government</u></strong></mark>ality <u><strong><mark>as a heuristic</u></strong></mark> focuses on performing complex diagnostics of events. It<u><strong> <mark>invites</u></strong></mark> historically situated explorations and <u><strong><mark>careful differentiations rather than overarching demonization</u></strong></mark>s<u><strong><mark> </mark>of ‘‘power,’’ romanticizations of the ‘‘rebel’’</u></strong> or the ‘‘the local.’’ More broadly, theoretical formulations that conceive the subject in non-substantialist terms <u><strong><mark>and</u></strong></mark> focus on processes of subjectification, on the ambiguity of power discourses, and on hybridization as the terrain for political transformation, open ways for reconsidering political agency beyond the dichotomy of oppression/rebellion. These alternative formulations also <u><strong><mark>foster</mark> <mark>an ethic</u></strong></mark>s<u><strong><mark> of political engagement</u></strong></mark>, to be continuously<u><strong><mark> taken</u></strong></mark> up<u><strong><mark> through plural </mark>and uncertain<mark> practices</mark>, that demand continuous attention to ‘‘what happens’’ instead of fixations on ‘‘what ought to be.</u></strong>’’83 <u><strong>Such <mark>ethics of engagement </mark>would not await the revolution</u></strong> to come or hope for a pristine ‘‘freedom’’ to be regained. <u><strong>Instead, it <mark>would constantly attempt to twist </u></strong></mark>the working of<u><strong><mark> power</mark> by playing with whatever cards are available</u></strong> <u><strong>and would require intense processes of reflexivity on the consequences of political choices</u></strong>. To conclude with a famous phrase by Michel Foucault ‘‘my point is not that everything is bad, but that everything is dangerous, which is not exactly the same as bad. If everything is dangerous, then we always have something to do. <u><strong>So </strong><mark>my position leads not to apathy but to</mark> hyper- and pessimistic <mark>activism.<strong></mark>’’84</u></strong> </p>
null
null
null
37,382
1,475
15,967
./documents/hsld16/WestRanch/Wo/West%20Ranch-Won-Aff-Greenhill-Round1.docx
776,142
A
Greenhill
1
Colleyville Heritage CW
Chris Theis
1AC Armenia AC 1NC T State Bad K Lib NC 1AR T case K NC 2NR T K
hsld16/WestRanch/Wo/West%20Ranch-Won-Aff-Greenhill-Round1.docx
null
66,621
JoWo
West Ranch JoWo
null
Jo.....
Wo.....
null
null
22,783
WestRanch
West Ranch
null
null
1,024
hsld16
HS LD 2016-17
2,016
ld
hs
1
140,481
Most likely cause of global conflict, but solving it is a dampener, and the aff can’t turn it
Lehane 17
Lehane 17 [Sinéad Lehane is research manager for Future Directions International’s Global Food and Water Crises Research program. Her current research projects include Australia’s food system and water security in the Tibetan Plateau region. Shaping Conflict in the 21st Century—The Future of Food and Water Security. February 2, 2017. www.hidropolitikakademi.org/shaping-conflict-in-the-21st-century-the-future-of-food-and-water-security.html]
wars of the 21st century will involve failed states, rebellions, civil conflict, insurgencies and terrorism. All of these elements will be triggered by competition over dwindling resources, rather than global conflicts with clearly defined sides More than 40 countries experienced civil unrest following the food price crisis in 2008 The rapid increase in grain prices and prevailing food insecurity in many states is linked to the outbreak of protests, food riots and the breakdown of governance Widespread food insecurity is a driving factor in creating a disaffected population ripe for rebellion Given the interconnectivity of food security and political stability, it is likely food will continue to act as a political stressor on regimes in the Middle East and elsewhere Improving food security is critical to creating a stable and secure global environment While food shortages contribute to a rising cycle of violence, improving food security outcomes can trigger the opposite and reduce the potential for conflict the likelihood of conflict exacerbated by scarcity over the next century is growing Conflict is likely to be driven by a number of factors and difficult to address through diplomacy or military force Population pressures, changing weather, urbanization, migration, a loss of arable land and freshwater resources are just some of the multi-layered stressors present in many states Future inter-state conflict will move further away from the traditional, clear lines of military conflict
wars of the 21st century will involve failed states, rebellions, civil conflict, insurgencies and terror these will be triggered by resources Given interconnectivity of food security and political stability food will continue to act as a stressor in the Mid East and elsewhere Improving food security is critical to a secure global environment shortages contribute to rising cycle of violence, improving food security reduce conflict likelihood of conflict exacerbated by scarcity is growing difficult to address through diplomacy or force
In his book, The Coming Famine, Julian Cribb writes that the wars of the 21st century will involve failed states, rebellions, civil conflict, insurgencies and terrorism. All of these elements will be triggered by competition over dwindling resources, rather than global conflicts with clearly defined sides. More than 40 countries experienced civil unrest following the food price crisis in 2008. The rapid increase in grain prices and prevailing food insecurity in many states is linked to the outbreak of protests, food riots and the breakdown of governance. Widespread food insecurity is a driving factor in creating a disaffected population ripe for rebellion. Given the interconnectivity of food security and political stability, it is likely food will continue to act as a political stressor on regimes in the Middle East and elsewhere. Addressing Insecurity Improving food and water security and encouraging resource sharing is critical to creating a stable and secure global environment. While food and water shortages contribute to a rising cycle of violence, improving food and water security outcomes can trigger the opposite and reduce the potential for conflict. With the global population expected to reach 9 billion by 2040, the likelihood of conflict exacerbated by scarcity over the next century is growing. Conflict is likely to be driven by a number of factors and difficult to address through diplomacy or military force. Population pressures, changing weather, urbanization, migration, a loss of arable land and freshwater resources are just some of the multi-layered stressors present in many states. Future inter-state conflict will move further away from the traditional, clear lines of military conflict and more towards economic control and influence.
1,777
<h4><strong>Most likely cause of <u>global conflict</u>, but solving it is a <u>dampener</u>, and the aff <u>can’t turn it</h4><p></u>Lehane 17</strong> [Sinéad Lehane is research manager for Future Directions International’s Global Food and Water Crises Research program. Her current research projects include Australia’s food system and water security in the Tibetan Plateau region. Shaping Conflict in the 21st Century—The Future of Food and Water Security. February 2, 2017. www.hidropolitikakademi.org/shaping-conflict-in-the-21st-century-the-future-of-food-and-water-security.html]</p><p>In his book, The Coming Famine, Julian Cribb writes that the <u><strong><mark>wars</strong> of the <strong>21st century</strong> will involve <strong>failed states</strong>, <strong>rebellions</strong>, <strong>civil conflict</strong>, <strong>insurgencies</strong> and <strong>terror</mark>ism</strong>. All of <mark>these</mark> elements <mark>will be triggered by</mark> competition over <strong>dwindling <mark>resources</strong></mark>, <strong>rather than global conflicts</strong> with <strong>clearly defined sides</u></strong>.<u><strong> </strong>More than 40 countries experienced civil unrest following the food price crisis in 2008</u>. <u>The rapid increase in grain prices and prevailing food insecurity in many states is linked to the outbreak of protests, food riots and the <strong>breakdown of governance</u></strong>. <u>Widespread food insecurity is a driving factor in creating a disaffected population ripe for rebellion</u>. <u><mark>Given</mark> the <strong><mark>interconnectivity</strong> of <strong>food security</strong> and <strong>political stability</strong></mark>, it is likely <mark>food will continue to act as a</mark> political <strong><mark>stressor</strong></mark> on regimes <mark>in the <strong>Mid</mark>dle <mark>East</strong> and <strong>elsewhere</u></strong></mark>. Addressing Insecurity <u><mark>Improving food</u></mark> and water <u><mark>security</u></mark> and encouraging resource sharing <u><mark>is critical to</mark> creating <mark>a</mark> <strong>stable</strong> and <strong><mark>secure global environment</u></strong></mark>. <u>While food </u>and water <u><mark>shortages <strong>contribute</strong> to</mark> a <strong><mark>rising cycle of violence</strong>, improving food</u></mark> and water <u><mark>security</mark> outcomes can trigger the <strong>opposite</strong> and <strong><mark>reduce</strong></mark> the potential for <strong><mark>conflict</u></strong></mark>. With the global population expected to reach 9 billion by 2040, <u>the <strong><mark>likelihood of conflict</strong> exacerbated by scarcity</mark> over the next century <mark>is <strong>growing</u></strong></mark>. <u>Conflict is likely to be driven by a number of factors and <strong><mark>difficult to address</strong> through <strong>diplomacy or</strong></mark> military <strong><mark>force</u></strong></mark>. <u>Population pressures, changing weather, urbanization, migration, a loss of arable land and freshwater resources are just some of the <strong>multi-layered stressors</strong> present in many states</u>. <u>Future inter-state conflict will move further away from the traditional, clear lines of military conflict</u> and more towards economic control and influence.</p>
DA – Counterfactual Farm Bill
1NC Shell
DA
34,994
412
1,913
./documents/openev/2019/RKS/Farm Bill Counterfactual - Wake 2019.docx
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
null
1,784,028
The alternative is to affirm the model of the Communist Party – only the Party can provide effective accountability mechanisms to correct unproductive tendencies, educate and mobilize marginalized communities, and connect local struggles to a movement for international liberation
Escalante 18
Alyson Escalante 18, a Marxist-Leninist, Materialist Feminist and Anti-Imperialist activist. “PARTY ORGANIZING IN THE 21ST CENTURY” September 21st, 2018 https://theforgenews.org/2018/09/21/party-organizing-in-the-21st-century/ rvs)
base building and dual power strategy can be best forwarded through party organizing, and that party organizing can allow this emerging movement to solidify into a powerful revolutionary socialist tendency in the United States. the current state of the left in the United States is one in which revolution is not currently possible. The base building emphasis on dual power responds directly to this insight. By building institutions which can meet people’s needs, we are able to concretely demonstrate that communists can offer the oppressed relief from the horrific conditions of capitalism. If it turns out that establishing socialist institutions to meet people’s needs does in fact create sympathy towards the cause of communism, how can we mobilize that base? in order to mobilize the base which base builders hope to create, we need to have already done the work of building a communist party. It is not enough to simply meet peoples needs. Rather, we must build the institutions of dual power in the name of communism. We must refuse covert front organizing and instead have a public face as a communist party. We must be clear that our strategy is revolutionary and in order to make this clear we must adopt party organizing. By “party organizing” I mean an organizational strategy which adopts the party model. Such organizing focuses on building a party whose membership is formally unified around a party line determined by democratic centralist decision making. The party model creates internal methods for holding party members accountable, unifying party member action around democratically determined goals, and for educating party members in communist theory and praxis. Organizations which adopt the party model focus on propagandizing around the need for revolutionary socialism. They function as the forefront of political organizing, empowering local communities to theorize their liberation through communist theory while organizing communities to literally fight for their liberation. our struggle is against a material base which functions not only at the national but at the international level. The formal structures provided by a democratic centralist party model allow individual locals to have a voice in open debate, but also allow for a unified strategy to emerge from democratic consensus. party organizing allows for local organizations and individual organizers to be held accountable for their actions. It allows criticism to function not as one independent group criticizing another independent group, but rather as comrades with a formal organizational unity working together to sharpen each others strategies and to help correct chauvinist ideas and actions. accountability is crucial. As a movement which operates within a settler colonial society, imperialist and colonial ideal frequently infect leftist organizing. Creating formal unity and party procedure for dealing with and correcting these ideas allows us to address these consistent problems within American socialist organizing. individual base building organizations ought to adopt party models for their local organizing. Local organizations ought to be building dual power alongside recruitment into their organizations, education of community members in communist theory and praxis, and the establishment of armed and militant party cadres capable of defending dual power institutions from state terror. The party model remains the most useful method for achieving these ends. It is my hope that we will see future unification of the various local base building organizations into a national party, it ought to become clear that a unified national party will have to be the long term goal of the base building movement. I hope that I have put forward a useful contribution to the discussion about base building organizing, and have demonstrated the need for party organizing in order to ensure that the base building tendency maintains a revolutionary orientation.
base building and dual power strategy can be best forwarded through party organizing party organizing can allow this movement to solidify into a powerful revolutionary socialist tendency revolution is not currently possible. dual power responds By building institutions which can meet people’s needs, we demonstrate that communists can offer relief from capitalism. in order to mobilize the base we need to have already done the work of building a communist party. It is not enough to meet needs. we must build institutions of dual power in the name of communism. We must have a public face as a communist party. membership is formally unified around a party line determined by democratic centralist decision making. for holding party members accountable, unifying action and for educating They empower communities to theorize through communist theory while organizing communities to literally fight for their liberation. formal structures allow individual locals to have a voice in open debate, but also for a unified strategy party organizing allows for organizers to be held accountable It allows criticism to function with unity working together to sharpen strategies and to help correct chauvinist ideas and accountability is crucial. imperialist and colonial ideal frequently infect leftist organizing. Creating formal procedure allows us to address these consistent problems organizations ought to adopt party models alongside recruitment education in communist theory and praxis, and the establishment of militant party cadres capable of defending institutions from state terror. The party model remains the most useful method for achieving these ends. It is my hope that we will see future unification of base building organizations into a national party that a unified national party will be the long term goal
I would argue that within the base building movement, there is a move towards party organizing, but this trend has not always been explicitly theorized or forwarded within the movement. My goal in this essay is to argue that base building and dual power strategy can be best forwarded through party organizing, and that party organizing can allow this emerging movement to solidify into a powerful revolutionary socialist tendency in the United States. One of the crucial insights of the base building movement is that the current state of the left in the United States is one in which revolution is not currently possible. There exists very little popular support for socialist politics. A century of anticommunist propaganda has been extremely effective in convincing even the most oppressed and marginalized that communism has nothing to offer them. The base building emphasis on dual power responds directly to this insight. By building institutions which can meet people’s needs, we are able to concretely demonstrate that communists can offer the oppressed relief from the horrific conditions of capitalism. Base building strategy recognizes that actually doing the work to serve the people does infinitely more to create a socialist base of popular support than electing democratic socialist candidates or holding endless political education classes can ever hope to do. Dual power is about proving that we have something to offer the oppressed. The question, of course, remains: once we have built a base of popular support, what do we do next? If it turns out that establishing socialist institutions to meet people’s needs does in fact create sympathy towards the cause of communism, how can we mobilize that base? Put simply: in order to mobilize the base which base builders hope to create, we need to have already done the work of building a communist party. It is not enough to simply meet peoples needs. Rather, we must build the institutions of dual power in the name of communism. We must refuse covert front organizing and instead have a public face as a communist party. When we build tenants unions, serve the people programs, and other dual power projects, we must make it clear that we are organizing as communists, unified around a party, and are not content simply with establishing endless dual power organizations. We must be clear that our strategy is revolutionary and in order to make this clear we must adopt party organizing. By “party organizing” I mean an organizational strategy which adopts the party model. Such organizing focuses on building a party whose membership is formally unified around a party line determined by democratic centralist decision making. The party model creates internal methods for holding party members accountable, unifying party member action around democratically determined goals, and for educating party members in communist theory and praxis. A communist organization utilizing the party model works to build dual power institutions while simultaneously educating the communities they hope to serve. Organizations which adopt the party model focus on propagandizing around the need for revolutionary socialism. They function as the forefront of political organizing, empowering local communities to theorize their liberation through communist theory while organizing communities to literally fight for their liberation. A party is not simply a group of individuals doing work together, but is a formal organization unified in its fight against capitalism. Party organizing has much to offer the base building movement. By working in a unified party, base builders can ensure that local struggles are tied to and informed by a unified national and international strategy. While the most horrific manifestations of capitalism take on particular and unique form at the local level, we need to remember that our struggle is against a material base which functions not only at the national but at the international level. The formal structures provided by a democratic centralist party model allow individual locals to have a voice in open debate, but also allow for a unified strategy to emerge from democratic consensus. Furthermore, party organizing allows for local organizations and individual organizers to be held accountable for their actions. It allows criticism to function not as one independent group criticizing another independent group, but rather as comrades with a formal organizational unity working together to sharpen each others strategies and to help correct chauvinist ideas and actions. In the context of the socialist movement within the United States, such accountability is crucial. As a movement which operates within a settler colonial society, imperialist and colonial ideal frequently infect leftist organizing. Creating formal unity and party procedure for dealing with and correcting these ideas allows us to address these consistent problems within American socialist organizing. Having a formal party which unifies the various dual power projects being undertaken at the local level also allows for base builders to not simply meet peoples needs, but to pull them into the membership of the party as organizers themselves. The party model creates a means for sustained growth to occur by unifying organizers in a manner that allows for skills, strategies, and ideas to be shared with newer organizers. It also allows community members who have been served by dual power projects to take an active role in organizing by becoming party members and participating in the continued growth of base building strategy. It ensures that there are formal processes for educating communities in communist theory and praxis, and also enables them to act and organize in accordance with their own local conditions. We also must recognize that the current state of the base building movement precludes the possibility of such a national unified party in the present moment. Since base building strategy is being undertaken in a number of already established organizations, it is not likely that base builders would abandon these organizations in favor of founding a unified party. Additionally, it would not be strategic to immediately undertake such complete unification because it would mean abandoning the organizational contexts in which concrete gains are already being made and in which growth is currently occurring. What is important for base builders to focus on in the current moment is building dual power on a local level alongside building a national movement. This means aspiring towards the possibility of a unified party, while pursuing continued local growth. The movement within the Marxist Center network towards some form of unification is positive step in the right direction. The independent party emphasis within the Refoundation caucus should also be recognized as a positive approach. It is important for base builders to continue to explore the possibility of unification, and to maintain unification through a party model as a long term goal. In the meantime, individual base building organizations ought to adopt party models for their local organizing. Local organizations ought to be building dual power alongside recruitment into their organizations, education of community members in communist theory and praxis, and the establishment of armed and militant party cadres capable of defending dual power institutions from state terror. Dual power institutions must be unified openly and transparently around these organizations in order for them to operate as more than “red charities.” Serving the people means meeting their material needs while also educating and propagandizing. It means radicalizing, recruiting, and organizing. The party model remains the most useful method for achieving these ends. The use of the party model by local organizations allows base builders to gain popular support, and most importantly, to mobilize their base of popular support towards revolutionary ends, not simply towards the construction of a parallel economy which exists as an end in and of itself. It is my hope that we will see future unification of the various local base building organizations into a national party, but in the meantime we must push for party organizing at the local level. If local organizations adopt party organizing, it ought to become clear that a unified national party will have to be the long term goal of the base building movement. Many of the already existing organizations within the base building movement already operate according to these principles. I do not mean to suggest otherwise. Rather, my hope is to suggest that we ought to be explicit about the need for party organizing and emphasize the relationship between dual power and the party model. Doing so will make it clear that the base building movement is not pursuing a cooperative economy alongside capitalism, but is pursuing a revolutionary socialist strategy capable of fighting capitalism. The long term details of base building and dual power organizing will arise organically in response to the conditions the movement finds itself operating within. I hope that I have put forward a useful contribution to the discussion about base building organizing, and have demonstrated the need for party organizing in order to ensure that the base building tendency maintains a revolutionary orientation. The finer details of revolutionary strategy will be worked out over time and are not a good subject for public discussion. I strongly believe party organizing offers the best path for ensuring that such strategy will succeed. My goal here is not to dictate the only possible path forward but to open a conversation about how the base building movement will organize as it transitions from a loose network of individual organizations into a unified socialist tendency. These discussions and debates will be crucial to ensuring that this rapidly growing movement can succeed.
9,978
<h4>The alternative is to affirm the model of the Communist Party – only the Party can provide effective accountability mechanisms to correct unproductive tendencies, educate and mobilize marginalized communities, and connect local struggles to a movement for international liberation</h4><p>Alyson<strong> Escalante 18</strong>, a Marxist-Leninist, Materialist Feminist and Anti-Imperialist activist. “PARTY ORGANIZING IN THE 21ST CENTURY” September 21st, 2018 https://theforgenews.org/2018/09/21/party-organizing-in-the-21st-century/ rvs)</p><p>I would argue that within the base building movement, there is a move towards party organizing, but this trend has not always been explicitly theorized or forwarded within the movement. My goal in this essay is to argue that <u><mark>base building and dual power strategy can be best forwarded through party organizing</mark>, and that <mark>party organizing can allow this</mark> emerging <mark>movement to solidify into a powerful revolutionary socialist tendency</mark> in the United States. </u>One of the crucial insights of the base building movement is that <u>the current state of the left in the United States is one in which <mark>revolution is not currently possible.</u></mark> There exists very little popular support for socialist politics. A century of anticommunist propaganda has been extremely effective in convincing even the most oppressed and marginalized that communism has nothing to offer them. <u>The base building emphasis on <mark>dual power responds</mark> directly to this insight. <mark>By building institutions which can meet people’s needs, we</mark> are able to concretely <mark>demonstrate that communists can offer</mark> the oppressed <mark>relief from</mark> the horrific conditions of <mark>capitalism.</u></mark> Base building strategy recognizes that actually doing the work to serve the people does infinitely more to create a socialist base of popular support than electing democratic socialist candidates or holding endless political education classes can ever hope to do. Dual power is about proving that we have something to offer the oppressed. The question, of course, remains: once we have built a base of popular support, what do we do next? <u>If it turns out that establishing socialist institutions to meet people’s needs does in fact create sympathy towards the cause of communism, how can we mobilize that base? </u>Put simply: <u><strong><mark>in order to mobilize the base</mark> which base builders hope to create, <mark>we need to have already done the work of building a communist party.</u></strong> <u>It is not enough to</mark> simply <mark>meet</mark> peoples <mark>needs.</mark> Rather, <mark>we must build</mark> the <mark>institutions of dual power in the name of communism.</u></mark> <u><mark>We must</mark> refuse covert front organizing and instead <mark>have a public face as a communist party.</mark> </u>When we build tenants unions, serve the people programs, and other dual power projects, we must make it clear that we are organizing as communists, unified around a party, and are not content simply with establishing endless dual power organizations. <u>We must be clear that our strategy is revolutionary and in order to make this clear we must adopt party organizing. By “party organizing” I mean an organizational strategy which adopts the party model. Such organizing focuses on building a party whose <mark>membership is formally unified around a party line determined by democratic centralist decision making.</u></mark> <u>The party model creates internal methods <mark>for <strong>holding party members accountable</strong>, unifying</mark> party member <mark>action</mark> around democratically determined goals, <mark>and for educating</mark> party members in communist theory and praxis.</u> A communist organization utilizing the party model works to build dual power institutions while simultaneously educating the communities they hope to serve. <u>Organizations which adopt the party model focus on propagandizing around the need for revolutionary socialism. <mark>They </mark>function as the forefront of political organizing, <mark>empower</mark>ing local <mark>communities to theorize</mark> their liberation <mark>through communist theory while organizing communities to literally fight for their liberation.</u></mark> A party is not simply a group of individuals doing work together, but is a formal organization unified in its fight against capitalism. Party organizing has much to offer the base building movement. By working in a unified party, base builders can ensure that local struggles are tied to and informed by a unified national and international strategy. While the most horrific manifestations of capitalism take on particular and unique form at the local level, we need to remember that <u>our struggle is against a material base which functions not only at the national but at the international level. The <mark>formal structures</mark> provided by a democratic centralist party model <mark>allow individual locals to have a voice in open debate, but also</mark> allow <mark>for a unified strategy</mark> to emerge from democratic consensus. </u>Furthermore, <u><strong><mark>party organizing allows for</mark> local organizations and individual <mark>organizers to be held accountable</mark> for their actions.</u></strong> <u><mark>It allows criticism to function</mark> not as one independent group criticizing another independent group, but rather as comrades <mark>with</mark> a formal organizational <mark>unity working together to sharpen</mark> each others <mark>strategies and to help correct chauvinist ideas and</mark> actions. </u>In the context of the socialist movement within the United States, such <u><mark>accountability is crucial.</u></mark> <u>As a movement which operates within a settler colonial society, <mark>imperialist and colonial ideal frequently infect leftist organizing. Creating formal</mark> unity and party <mark>procedure</mark> for dealing with and correcting these ideas <mark>allows us to address these consistent problems</mark> within American socialist organizing. </u>Having a formal party which unifies the various dual power projects being undertaken at the local level also allows for base builders to not simply meet peoples needs, but to pull them into the membership of the party as organizers themselves. The party model creates a means for sustained growth to occur by unifying organizers in a manner that allows for skills, strategies, and ideas to be shared with newer organizers. It also allows community members who have been served by dual power projects to take an active role in organizing by becoming party members and participating in the continued growth of base building strategy. It ensures that there are formal processes for educating communities in communist theory and praxis, and also enables them to act and organize in accordance with their own local conditions. We also must recognize that the current state of the base building movement precludes the possibility of such a national unified party in the present moment. Since base building strategy is being undertaken in a number of already established organizations, it is not likely that base builders would abandon these organizations in favor of founding a unified party. Additionally, it would not be strategic to immediately undertake such complete unification because it would mean abandoning the organizational contexts in which concrete gains are already being made and in which growth is currently occurring. What is important for base builders to focus on in the current moment is building dual power on a local level alongside building a national movement. This means aspiring towards the possibility of a unified party, while pursuing continued local growth. The movement within the Marxist Center network towards some form of unification is positive step in the right direction. The independent party emphasis within the Refoundation caucus should also be recognized as a positive approach. It is important for base builders to continue to explore the possibility of unification, and to maintain unification through a party model as a long term goal. In the meantime, <u>individual base building <mark>organizations ought to adopt party models</mark> for their local organizing. Local organizations ought to be building dual power <mark>alongside recruitment</mark> into their organizations, <mark>education</mark> of community members <mark>in communist theory and praxis, and the establishment of</mark> armed and <mark>militant party cadres capable of defending</mark> dual power <mark>institutions from state terror.</u></mark> Dual power institutions must be unified openly and transparently around these organizations in order for them to operate as more than “red charities.” Serving the people means meeting their material needs while also educating and propagandizing. It means radicalizing, recruiting, and organizing. <u><mark>The party model remains the most useful method for achieving these ends.</mark> </u>The use of the party model by local organizations allows base builders to gain popular support, and most importantly, to mobilize their base of popular support towards revolutionary ends, not simply towards the construction of a parallel economy which exists as an end in and of itself. <u><mark>It is my hope that we will see future unification of</mark> the various local <mark>base building organizations into a national party</mark>,</u> but in the meantime we must push for party organizing at the local level. If local organizations adopt party organizing, <u>it ought to become clear <mark>that</u> <u><strong>a unified national party will</mark> have to <mark>be the long term goal</mark> of the base building movement. </u></strong>Many of the already existing organizations within the base building movement already operate according to these principles. I do not mean to suggest otherwise. Rather, my hope is to suggest that we ought to be explicit about the need for party organizing and emphasize the relationship between dual power and the party model. Doing so will make it clear that the base building movement is not pursuing a cooperative economy alongside capitalism, but is pursuing a revolutionary socialist strategy capable of fighting capitalism. The long term details of base building and dual power organizing will arise organically in response to the conditions the movement finds itself operating within. <u>I hope that I have put forward a useful contribution to the discussion about base building organizing, and have demonstrated the need for party organizing in order to ensure that the base building tendency maintains a revolutionary orientation.</u> The finer details of revolutionary strategy will be worked out over time and are not a good subject for public discussion. I strongly believe party organizing offers the best path for ensuring that such strategy will succeed. My goal here is not to dictate the only possible path forward but to open a conversation about how the base building movement will organize as it transitions from a loose network of individual organizations into a unified socialist tendency. These discussions and debates will be crucial to ensuring that this rapidly growing movement can succeed.</p>
1NC Round 1 Liberty
OFF
1NC
10,780
1,346
52,483
./documents/ndtceda20/Pittsburgh/LiRe/Pittsburgh-Lim-Reznik-Neg-Liberty-Round1.docx
621,364
N
Liberty
1
Liberty CR
Logan Jancek
1AC - alliances are racist 2NR - K
ndtceda20/Pittsburgh/LiRe/Pittsburgh-Lim-Reznik-Neg-Liberty-Round1.docx
null
52,477
LiRe
Pittsburgh LiRe
null
Za.....
Li.....
Al.....
Re.....
19,343
Pittsburgh
Pittsburgh
null
null
1,010
ndtceda20
NDT/CEDA 2020-21
2,020
cx
college
2
3,867,748
The aff seeks legitimation within academic structures—viewing affirmation as the fulcrum from change create neoliberal enclave politics.
Phillips 99
Phillips 99 Dr. Kendall R., Professor of Communication at Central Missouri State University, PhD in Speech Communication from Pennsylvania State University, MA in Speech Communication from Central Missouri State University, BS in Psychology and Sociology from Southwest Baptist University, “Rhetoric, Resistance, and Criticism: A Response to Sloop and Ono”, Philosophy & Rhetoric, Volume 32, Number 1, p. 96-101
My concern centers around an issue that seem to take as a given, namely, the role of the critic the ease of transition from criticism in the service of resistance to criticism of resistance may obscure the need to address some fundamental issues regarding the general function of rhetorical criticism in an uncertain and contentious world licensing the critic to engage in political struggle, Sloop and Ono advocate the pursuit of covert resistant discourses. only stretches our understanding of rhetoric and criticism, but also alters significantly the relationship between critic and out- law. Critical interrogation of dominant discursive practices in the service of political/cultural reform is supplanted in favor of positioning covert out- law communities as objects of investigation. Invited to seek out subversive discourses, the critic is positioned as the active agent of change and the out-law discourse becomes merely instrumental. Rather than academic criticism acting in service of everyday acts of resistance, everyday acts of resistance are put into the service of academic criticism. Their suggestion that out-law communities are in need of the academic critic contradicts the already disruptive nature of existing out-law discourses Sloop and Ono fail to offer an adequate argument for "taking public speaking out of the streets and studying it in the classroom, for treating it less as an expression of protest" and more as an object for analysis and reproduction within the political economy of the academy Sloop and Ono offer numerous directives for the critic without addressing whether the critic should be examining out-law discourses in the first place Hidden out-law discourses may have good reasons to stay hidden are we to believe that members of out-law communities are prepared to be brought into the arena of public surveillance perhaps the re-presentation of out-law logic within the academic community will bestow a degree of legitimacy on the out-law community. Nonetheless, the effect of legitimizing out-law discourse is unknown and potentially destructive. In an effort to siphon the political energy of out-law discourse into academic practice, we may ultimately destroy the dissatisfaction that serves as a cathexis for these out-law discourses academic recognition might take the place of struggle for material opportunities But, will academic legitimation create any material changes in the conditions of out-law communities? For Sloop and Ono, the critic is an interested party, discerning the underlying values and forces contained within a discourse. Additionally, however, the out-law discourse critic is an analyst focusing on the hidden texts and "rendering] an incoherent or esoteric text comprehensible" these entanglings of power and knowledge are inevitable Turning covert out-law discourses into objects of our analyses runs the risk of subjecting them both to the gaze of the dominant and to the power relations of the academy
concern centers around the role of the critic positioning communities as objects of investigation the critic is the active agent of change and discourse becomes instrumental Their suggestion that out-law communities need the academic critic contradicts the disruptive nature are we to believe members are prepared to be brought into the arena of surveillance perhaps re-presentation will bestow legitimacy Nonetheless, the effect is destructive to siphon energy into academic practice, we destroy a cathexis recognition take the place of material opportunities But, will legitimation create any changes in conditions the critic is focusing on hidden texts and "rendering] comprehensible" Turning covert discourses into objects of analyses risk subjecting them to the gaze of the dominant and the power relations of the academy
My concern with this movement centers around an issue that Sloop and Ono seem to take as a given, namely, the role of the critic. On one hand, calling for the systematic investigation of existing marginalized discourses is a natural extension both of critical rhetoric (see McKerrow 1989, 1991) and of the general ideological turn in criticism (see Wander 1983). On the other hand, the ease of transition from criticism in the service of resistance to criticism of resistance may obscure the need to address some fundamental issues regarding the general function of rhetorical criticism in an uncertain and contentious world. Beyond licensing the critic to engage in political struggle, Sloop and Ono advocate the pursuit of covert resistant discourses. Such a move not only stretches our understanding of rhetoric and criticism, but also alters significantly the relationship between critic and out- law. Critical interrogation of dominant discursive practices in the service of political/cultural reform is supplanted in favor of positioning covert out- law communities as objects of investigation. Invited to seek out subversive discourses, the critic is positioned as the active agent of change and the out-law discourse becomes merely instrumental. Rather than academic criticism acting in service of everyday acts of resistance, everyday acts of resistance are put into the service of academic criticism. Rhetorical resistance That we are "caught within conflicting logics of justice that are culturally struggled over" (Sloop and Ono 1997, 50) and that rhetoric is employed in these struggles seems an uncontroversial statement. Despite the theoretical miasma surrounding judgment, Sloop and Ono accurately note, the material process of rendering judgments (and of disputing the logics of litigation) continues in the world of actually practiced discourse. In the materially contested world, rhetoric is utilized both by those seeking to secure the grounds of dominant judgment and by those seeking to undermine or supplant dominant cultural logics with some out-law notion of justice. The distinction between these two cultural groups, "in-law" and out- law, however, deserves some consideration prior to any discussion of the role of the critic as implied in the out-law discourse project. The discourse of the dominant or those within the bounds of superordinate logics of litigation is reminiscent of Michel De Certeau's (1984) strategic discourse. For De Certeau, strategies are utilized by those who have authority by virtue of their proper position. Strategies exploit the institutionally guaranteed background consensus by which power relations (and litigations) are maintained and advanced. In contrast, tactics are utilized by those having no proper place of authority within the discursive economy who must seek opportunities whereby the discourse of the dominant might be undermined and contested. To extend Sloop and Ono's definition, out-law discourses are those that can (and, by their analysis, do) take advantage of situations (e.g., race riots) to disrupt the regularity of dominant cultural groups. The ongoing struggle between strategically instituted cultural dominants and the "out-law always lurk[ing] in the distance" (66) is acknowledged, even celebrated, by Sloop and Ono. What their acknowledgment fails to provide, however, is a clear need for critical intervention. Indeed, quite the reverse is presented: It is the critic (particularly the left-leaning critic) who needs out-law discourse. While the struggles over justice, equality, and freedom have gone on, the left-leaning critics are those who have theoretically excluded themselves from the disputes. The study of out-law dis- courses, then, provides a means to reinvigorate the intellectual and re-institute (academic) leftist thinking into popular political struggles (53-54). Thus, Sloop and Ono's project incorporates three types of rhetoric: the rhetoric of the in-law, presumably the traditional object of critical attention; the rhetoric of the out-law, the study of which may transform our understanding of judgment as well as reinvigorate leftist democratic critiques; and the rhetoric of the critics who, having lost their political po- tency, can exploit the discourse of the out-law to promote ideological struggles. It is to this critical rhetoric that I now turn. Resistance criticism Sloop and Ono (1997) clearly state the relationship they envision between the rhetorical critic and out-law discourse: "Ultimately, we will argue that the role of critical rhetoricians is to produce 'materialist conceptions of judgment,' using out-law judgments to disrupt dominant logics of judgment" (54; emphasis added). Here the critic seeks out vernacular discourse (60), focuses on the methods and values embodied in these communities (62), listens to and evaluates the out-law community (62-63), and chooses appropriate discourses for the purpose of disrupting dominant practices (63). Essentially, it is the critic who seeks out marginalized discourses and returns them to the center for the purpose of provoking dominant cultural groups (63). Despite acknowledging the efficacy of out-law discourses, Sloop and Ono assume that the critiques generated and presented by the out-law community have only minimal effect. The irony, and indeed arrogance, of this assumption is evident when they claim: "There are cases, however, when, without the prompting of academic critics, out-law discourses serve local purposes at times and at others resonate within dominant discourses, disrupting sedimented ways of thinking, transforming dominant forms of judgment" (60; emphasis added). Sloop and Ono seem to suggest that such locally generated critiques are the exception, whereas the political efficacy of the academic critic is the rule. This seems an odd claim, given that the justification for their out-law discourse project is the lack of politically viable academic critique and the perceived potency of out-law conceptions of judgment. Their suggestion that out-law communities are in need of the academic critic contradicts not only the already disruptive nature of existing out-law discourses (the grounds for using out-law discourse), but also the impotence of contemporary critical discourse (the warrant for studying out-law discourse). By this I do not mean that the critiques and theories generated by academically instituted intellectuals have not been incorporated into subversive discourses. Just as out-law discourses inevitably mount critiques of dominant logics, so, too, the perspectives on rhetoric and criticism generated by academics are used in resistance movements. Feminist critiques of patriarchy, queer theories of homophobia, postcolonial interrogations of race have found their way into the service of resistant groups. The key distinction I wish to make is that the existence of criticism (academic or self-generated) in resistance does not necessitate Sloop and Ono's move to a criticism of resistance. What Sloop and Ono fail to offer is an adequate argument for "taking public speaking out of the streets and studying it in the classroom, for treating it less as an expression of protest" (Wander 1983, 3) and more as an object for analysis and reproduction within the political economy of the academy. Philip Wander made a similar charge against Herbert Wicheln's early critical project, and this concern should remain at the forefront of any discussion aimed at expanding the scope and function of criticism. Sloop and Ono offer numerous directives for the critic without addressing whether the critic should be examining out-law discourses in the first place. While it is too early to suggest any definitive answer to the question of criticism of resistance, some preliminary arguments as to why critics should not pursue out-law discourses can be offered: (1) Hidden out-law discourses may have good reasons to stay hidden. Sloop and Ono specifically instruct us that "the logic of the out-law must constantly be searched for, brought forth" (66) and used to disrupt dominant practices. But are we to believe that all out-law discourses are prepared to mount such a challenge to the dominant cultural logic? Or, indeed, that the members of out-law communities are prepared to be brought into the arena of public surveillance in the service of reconstituting logics of litigation? It seems highly unlikely that all divergent cultural groups have developed equally, or that all members of these groups share Sloop and Ono's "imperial impulse" (51) to promote their conceptions and practices of justice. (2) Academic critical discourse is not transparent. Here I allude to the overall problem of translation (see Foucault 1994; Lyotard 1988; Lyotard and Thebaud 1985; Zabus 1995) as an extension of the previous concern. Critical discourse cannot become the medium of commensurability for divergent language games. Are we to believe that the "use" of out-law dis- course by critics to disrupt dominant practices can fail to do violence to these diverse/divergent logics? Are out-law discourses merely tools to be exploited and discarded in the pursuit of returning leftist academic dis- course to the center? (3) Perhaps the academic translation of out-law discourse could be true to the internal logic of the out-law community. And, perhaps the re-presentation of out-law logic within the academic community will bestow a degree of legitimacy on the out-law community. Nonetheless, the effect of legitimizing out-law discourse is unknown and potentially destructive. In an effort to siphon the political energy of out-law discourse into academic practice, we may ultimately destroy the dissatisfaction that serves as a cathexis for these out-law discourses. It seems possible that academic recognition might take the place of struggle for material opportunities (see Fraser 1997). But, will academic legitimation create any material changes in the conditions of out-law communities? I mean to suggest, not that it is better to allow the out-law community to suffer for its cause, but rather that incorporating the struggle into an (admittedly) impotent academic critique does not offer a prima facie alternative. (4) Criticism of resistance denies the practical and theoretical importance of opportunity. Returning to De Certeau's notion of tactics, the crucial element of these discursive moves is their use of opportunity to disrupt the proper authority of the dominant. The kairos of intervention provides the key to undermining "in-law" discourses. But when is the "right moment in time" for the academic reproduction of out-law discourse? Mapping the points of resistance (ala Foucault and Biesecker) entails interrogating "in-law" discourses for their incongruities and contradictions, not turning the academic gaze upon those communities waiting for an opportunity. Out-laws do not lurk in the forefront (66), hoping to be exposed by academic critics; they wait for the right moment for their disruption. Rhetoricians can provide rhetorical instructions for seeking opportunities and for exploiting these opportunities (literally making the culturally weaker argument the stronger), but this does not justify interrogating (intervening in) the cultural logics of the marginalized. The concerns raised here are not designed to dismiss Sloop and Ono's provocative essay. The divergent critical logic they outline deserves careful consideration within the critical community, and it is my hope that the concerns I raise may help to further problematize the relationship between resistance and rhetorical criticism. Rhetorical criticism As I have suggested, my purpose is to use the provocative nature of Sloop and Ono's project to extend disputes regarding the ends of rhetorical criticism. Diverging perspectives on the ends of criticism have been categorized by Barbara Warnick (1992) as falling along four general lines: artist, analyst, audience, and advocate. Leah Ceccarelli (1997) discerns similar categories around the aesthetic, epistemic, and political ends of rhetorical criticism. The out-law discourse project presents clear ties to the notion of critic as advocate. For Sloop and Ono, the critic is an interested party, discerning (and at times disputing) the underlying values and forces contained within a discourse. Additionally, however, the out-law discourse critic is an analyst focusing on the hidden, aberrant texts of the out-law and "rendering] an incoherent or esoteric text comprehensible" (Warnick 1992, 233). Now, I am not suggesting that a critic must serve only one function or that the roles of advocate and analyst are mutually exclusive; rather, these entanglings of power (political ends) and knowledge (epistemic ends) are inevitable. My concern is that we not neglect the complexity of these entanglements. Turning covert out-law discourses into objects of our analyses runs the risk of subjecting them both to the gaze of the dominant and to the power relations of the academy. As the works of Michel Foucault (especially 1979, 1980) aptly illustrate, practices presented as extending such noble goals as emancipation and humanity may endow institutions of confinement and objectification. Any justification for studying out-law dis- course because doing so may extend our political usefulness in the pursuit of emancipatory goals must not obscure the already existing power relations authorizing such studies. Our attempts to extend our domains of knowledge and expertise (authority) must not be pursued unreflexively.
13,588
<h4>The aff seeks legitimation within academic structures—viewing affirmation as the fulcrum from change create <u>neoliberal enclave politics. </h4><p></u><strong>Phillips 99 </strong>Dr. Kendall R., Professor of Communication at Central Missouri State University, PhD in Speech Communication from Pennsylvania State University, MA in Speech Communication from Central Missouri State University, BS in Psychology and Sociology from Southwest Baptist University, “Rhetoric, Resistance, and Criticism: A Response to Sloop and Ono”, Philosophy & Rhetoric, Volume 32, Number 1, p. 96-101</p><p><u>My <mark>concern</u></mark> with this movement <u><mark>centers around</mark> an issue that</u> Sloop and Ono <u>seem to take as a given, namely, <mark>the <strong>role of the critic</u></strong></mark>. On one hand, calling for the systematic investigation of existing marginalized discourses is a natural extension both of critical rhetoric (see McKerrow 1989, 1991) and of the general ideological turn in criticism (see Wander 1983). On the other hand, <u>the ease of transition from criticism in the service of resistance to criticism of resistance may obscure the need to address some fundamental issues regarding the general function of rhetorical criticism in an uncertain and contentious world</u>. Beyond <u>licensing the critic to engage in political struggle, Sloop and Ono advocate the pursuit of covert resistant discourses.</p><p></u> Such a move not <u>only stretches our understanding of rhetoric and criticism, but also alters significantly the relationship between critic and out- law. Critical interrogation of dominant discursive practices in the service of political/cultural reform is supplanted in favor of <mark>positioning</mark> covert out- law <mark>communities as <strong>objects of investigation</strong></mark>. Invited to seek out subversive discourses, <strong><mark>the critic</strong> is</mark> positioned as <mark>the <strong>active agent of change</strong> and</mark> the out-law <mark>discourse becomes</mark> <strong>merely <mark>instrumental</strong></mark>. Rather than academic criticism acting in service of everyday acts of resistance, everyday acts of resistance are put into the service of academic criticism.</p><p></u> Rhetorical resistance</p><p> That we are "caught within conflicting logics of justice that are culturally struggled over" (Sloop and Ono 1997, 50) and that rhetoric is employed in these struggles seems an uncontroversial statement. Despite the theoretical miasma surrounding judgment, Sloop and Ono accurately note, the material process of rendering judgments (and of disputing the logics of litigation) continues in the world of actually practiced discourse. In the materially contested world, rhetoric is utilized both by those seeking to secure the grounds of dominant judgment and by those seeking to undermine or supplant dominant cultural logics with some out-law notion of justice.</p><p> The distinction between these two cultural groups, "in-law" and out- law, however, deserves some consideration prior to any discussion of the role of the critic as implied in the out-law discourse project. The discourse of the dominant or those within the bounds of superordinate logics of litigation is reminiscent of Michel De Certeau's (1984) strategic discourse. For De Certeau, strategies are utilized by those who have authority by virtue of their proper position. Strategies exploit the institutionally guaranteed background consensus by which power relations (and litigations) are maintained and advanced. In contrast, tactics are utilized by those having no proper place of authority within the discursive economy who must seek opportunities whereby the discourse of the dominant might be undermined and contested. To extend Sloop and Ono's definition, out-law discourses are those that can (and, by their analysis, do) take advantage of situations (e.g., race riots) to disrupt the regularity of dominant cultural groups.</p><p> The ongoing struggle between strategically instituted cultural dominants and the "out-law always lurk[ing] in the distance" (66) is acknowledged, even celebrated, by Sloop and Ono. What their acknowledgment fails to provide, however, is a clear need for critical intervention. Indeed, quite the reverse is presented: It is the critic (particularly the left-leaning critic) who needs out-law discourse. While the struggles over justice, equality, and freedom have gone on, the left-leaning critics are those who have theoretically excluded themselves from the disputes. The study of out-law dis- courses, then, provides a means to reinvigorate the intellectual and re-institute (academic) leftist thinking into popular political struggles (53-54). Thus, Sloop and Ono's project incorporates three types of rhetoric: the rhetoric of the in-law, presumably the traditional object of critical attention; the rhetoric of the out-law, the study of which may transform our understanding of judgment as well as reinvigorate leftist democratic critiques; and the rhetoric of the critics who, having lost their political po- tency, can exploit the discourse of the out-law to promote ideological struggles. It is to this critical rhetoric that I now turn.</p><p> Resistance criticism</p><p> Sloop and Ono (1997) clearly state the relationship they envision between the rhetorical critic and out-law discourse: "Ultimately, we will argue that the role of critical rhetoricians is to produce 'materialist conceptions of judgment,' using out-law judgments to disrupt dominant logics of judgment" (54; emphasis added). Here the critic seeks out vernacular discourse (60), focuses on the methods and values embodied in these communities (62), listens to and evaluates the out-law community (62-63), and chooses appropriate discourses for the purpose of disrupting dominant practices (63). Essentially, it is the critic who seeks out marginalized discourses and returns them to the center for the purpose of provoking dominant cultural groups (63).</p><p>Despite acknowledging the efficacy of out-law discourses, Sloop and Ono assume that the critiques generated and presented by the out-law community have only minimal effect. The irony, and indeed arrogance, of this assumption is evident when they claim: "There are cases, however, when, without the prompting of academic critics, out-law discourses serve local purposes at times and at others resonate within dominant discourses, disrupting sedimented ways of thinking, transforming dominant forms of judgment" (60; emphasis added). Sloop and Ono seem to suggest that such locally generated critiques are the exception, whereas the political efficacy of the academic critic is the rule. This seems an odd claim, given that the justification for their out-law discourse project is the lack of politically viable academic critique and the perceived potency of out-law conceptions of judgment. <u><mark>Their suggestion that out-law communities</mark> are in <mark>need</mark> of <mark>the academic critic <strong>contradicts</u></strong></mark> not only <u><mark>the</mark> already <mark>disruptive nature</mark> of existing out-law discourses</u> (the grounds for using out-law discourse), but also the impotence of contemporary critical discourse (the warrant for studying out-law discourse).</p><p> By this I do not mean that the critiques and theories generated by academically instituted intellectuals have not been incorporated into subversive discourses. Just as out-law discourses inevitably mount critiques of dominant logics, so, too, the perspectives on rhetoric and criticism generated by academics are used in resistance movements. Feminist critiques of patriarchy, queer theories of homophobia, postcolonial interrogations of race have found their way into the service of resistant groups. The key distinction I wish to make is that the existence of criticism (academic or self-generated) in resistance does not necessitate Sloop and Ono's move to a criticism of resistance.</p><p>What <u>Sloop and Ono fail to offer</u> is <u>an adequate argument for "<strong>taking public speaking out of the streets</strong> and <strong>studying it in the classroom</strong>, for treating it less as an <strong>expression of protest</strong>"</u> (Wander 1983, 3) <u>and more as an <strong>object for analysis</strong> and <strong>reproduction</strong> within the <strong>political economy of the academy</u></strong>. Philip Wander made a similar charge against Herbert Wicheln's early critical project, and this concern should remain at the forefront of any discussion aimed at expanding the scope and function of criticism. <u>Sloop and Ono offer numerous directives for the critic without addressing <strong>whether the critic should be examining out-law discourses in the first place</u></strong>. While it is too early to suggest any definitive answer to the question of criticism of resistance, some preliminary arguments as to why critics should not pursue out-law discourses can be offered:</p><p> (1) <u>Hidden out-law discourses may have <strong>good reasons to stay hidden</u></strong>. Sloop and Ono specifically instruct us that "the logic of the out-law must constantly be searched for, brought forth" (66) and used to disrupt dominant practices. But <u><mark>are we to believe</mark> that</u> all out-law discourses are prepared to mount such a challenge to the dominant cultural logic? Or, indeed, that the <u><mark>members</mark> of out-law communities <mark>are prepared to be <strong>brought into the arena of</mark> public <mark>surveillance</u></strong></mark> in the service of reconstituting logics of litigation? It seems highly unlikely that all divergent cultural groups have developed equally, or that all members of these groups share Sloop and Ono's "imperial impulse" (51) to promote their conceptions and practices of justice.</p><p> (2) Academic critical discourse is not transparent. Here I allude to the overall problem of translation (see Foucault 1994; Lyotard 1988; Lyotard and Thebaud 1985; Zabus 1995) as an extension of the previous concern. Critical discourse cannot become the medium of commensurability for divergent language games. Are we to believe that the "use" of out-law dis- course by critics to disrupt dominant practices can fail to do violence to these diverse/divergent logics? Are out-law discourses merely tools to be exploited and discarded in the pursuit of returning leftist academic dis- course to the center?</p><p> (3) Perhaps the academic translation of out-law discourse could be true to the internal logic of the out-law community. And, <u><mark>perhaps</mark> the <mark>re-presentation</mark> of out-law logic within the academic community <mark>will bestow</mark> a degree of <strong><mark>legitimacy</strong></mark> on the out-law community. <strong><mark>Nonetheless</strong>, the effect</mark> of legitimizing out-law discourse <mark>is</mark> unknown and potentially <strong><mark>destructive</strong></mark>. In an effort <mark>to <strong>siphon</mark> the political <mark>energy</strong></mark> of out-law discourse <mark>into academic practice, we</mark> may ultimately <strong><mark>destroy</strong></mark> the dissatisfaction that serves as <mark>a <strong>cathexis</strong></mark> for these out-law discourses</u>. It seems possible that <u>academic <mark>recognition</mark> might <strong><mark>take the place</strong> of</mark> struggle for <mark>material opportunities</u></mark> (see Fraser 1997). <u><mark>But, will</mark> academic <mark>legitimation create <strong>any</mark> material <mark>changes</strong> in</mark> the <mark>conditions</mark> of out-law communities?</u> I mean to suggest, not that it is better to allow the out-law community to suffer for its cause, but rather that incorporating the struggle into an (admittedly) impotent academic critique does not offer a prima facie alternative.</p><p> (4) Criticism of resistance denies the practical and theoretical importance of opportunity. Returning to De Certeau's notion of tactics, the crucial element of these discursive moves is their use of opportunity to disrupt the proper authority of the dominant. The kairos of intervention provides the key to undermining "in-law" discourses. But when is the "right moment in time" for the academic reproduction of out-law discourse? Mapping the points of resistance (ala Foucault and Biesecker) entails interrogating "in-law" discourses for their incongruities and contradictions, not turning the academic gaze upon those communities waiting for an opportunity. Out-laws do not lurk in the forefront (66), hoping to be exposed by academic critics; they wait for the right moment for their disruption. Rhetoricians can provide rhetorical instructions for seeking opportunities and for exploiting these opportunities (literally making the culturally weaker argument the stronger), but this does not justify interrogating (intervening in) the cultural logics of the marginalized.</p><p> The concerns raised here are not designed to dismiss Sloop and Ono's provocative essay. The divergent critical logic they outline deserves careful consideration within the critical community, and it is my hope that the concerns I raise may help to further problematize the relationship between</p><p> resistance and rhetorical criticism.</p><p>Rhetorical criticism</p><p> As I have suggested, my purpose is to use the provocative nature of Sloop and Ono's project to extend disputes regarding the ends of rhetorical criticism. Diverging perspectives on the ends of criticism have been categorized by Barbara Warnick (1992) as falling along four general lines: artist, analyst, audience, and advocate. Leah Ceccarelli (1997) discerns similar categories around the aesthetic, epistemic, and political ends of rhetorical criticism. </p><p>The out-law discourse project presents clear ties to the notion of critic as advocate. <u>For Sloop and Ono, the critic is an <strong>interested party</strong>, discerning</u> (and at times disputing) <u>the underlying values and forces contained within a discourse. Additionally, however, <mark>the</mark> out-law discourse <mark>critic is</mark> an analyst <mark>focusing on</mark> the <strong><mark>hidden</u></strong></mark>, aberrant <u><mark>texts</u></mark> of the out-law <u><mark>and <strong>"rendering]</mark> an incoherent or esoteric text <mark>comprehensible"</u></strong></mark> (Warnick 1992, 233). Now, I am not suggesting that a critic must serve only one function or that the roles of advocate and analyst are mutually exclusive; rather, <u>these entanglings of power</u> (political ends) <u>and knowledge</u> (epistemic ends) <u>are inevitable</u>. My concern is that we not neglect the complexity of these entanglements. <u><strong><mark>Turning covert</mark> out-law <mark>discourses into objects of</mark> our <mark>analyses</mark> runs the <mark>risk</mark> of <mark>subjecting them</mark> both <mark>to the gaze of the dominant and</mark> to <mark>the power relations of the academy</u></strong></mark>. As the works of Michel Foucault (especially 1979, 1980) aptly illustrate, practices presented as extending such noble goals as emancipation and humanity may endow institutions of confinement and objectification. Any justification for studying out-law dis- course because doing so may extend our political usefulness in the pursuit of emancipatory goals must not obscure the already existing power relations authorizing such studies. Our attempts to extend our domains of knowledge and expertise (authority) must not be pursued unreflexively.</p>
null
Cap
null
4,251
444
128,938
./documents/ndtceda21/Harvard/BaHa/Harvard-Barton-Habermann-Neg-NDT-Octas.docx
624,228
N
NDT
Octas
Liberty CR
null
1NC - FW Cap
ndtceda21/Harvard/BaHa/Harvard-Barton-Habermann-Neg-NDT-Octas.docx
null
52,674
BaHa
Harvard BaHa
null
Ad.....
Ba.....
Ju.....
Ha.....
19,385
Harvard
Harvard
null
null
1,011
ndtceda21
NDT/CEDA 2021-22
2,021
cx
college
2
4,429,543
“Resolved” doesn’t require certainty
Webster’s 9
Webster’s 9 – Merriam Webster 2009
re·solved consult, deliberate
re·solved to consult, deliberate
(http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/resolved) # Main Entry: 1re·solve # Pronunciation: \ri-ˈzälv, -ˈzȯlv also -ˈzäv or -ˈzȯv\ # Function: verb # Inflected Form(s): re·solved; re·solv·ing 1 : to become separated into component parts; also : to become reduced by dissolving or analysis 2 : to form a resolution : determine 3 : consult, deliberate
353
<h4><strong>“Resolved” doesn’t require certainty</h4><p>Webster’s 9</strong> – Merriam Webster 2009</p><p>(http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/resolved)</p><p># Main Entry: 1re·solve # Pronunciation: \ri-ˈzälv, -ˈzȯlv also -ˈzäv or -ˈzȯv\ # Function: verb # Inflected Form(s): <u><mark>re·solved</u></mark>; re·solv·ing 1 : to become separated into component parts; also : to become reduced by dissolving or analysis 2 : <mark>to</mark> form a resolution : determine 3 : <u><mark>consult, deliberate</u></mark> </p>
2AC
QPQ
Solvency
1,159
566
145,489
./documents/hspolicy22/SanMarino/LoLi/SanMarino-LoLi-Aff-TOC-Digital-Speech-and-Debate-Series-1-Round-5.docx
952,323
A
TOC Digital Speech and Debate Series 1
5
Taipei American WB
Stockstill
1AC - AI Logistics and Sustainments 1NC - Cap K, QPQ CP, Croatia PIC 2NR - QPQ CP
hspolicy22/SanMarino/LoLi/SanMarino-LoLi-Aff-TOC-Digital-Speech-and-Debate-Series-1-Round-5.docx
2022-12-03 23:40:25
81,536
LoLi
San Marino LoLi
Caroline 2A/1N (she/her) - carolinelouie.t@gmail.com Davis 1A/2N (he/him) - davisliang6107@gmail.com Please add to the chain: smhspolicy@gmail.com Please do not read death good or other arguments endorsing suicide. email if you want osource from last chance
Ca.....
Lo.....
Da.....
Li.....
26,955
SanMarino
San Marino
CA
null
2,002
hspolicy22
HS Policy 2022-23
2,022
cx
hs
2
2,306,539
9] Nuclear war causes extinction
Edwards 17 Note, we are only reading parts of the interview that are directly from Paul Edwards -- MMG
Edwards 17 [Paul N. Edwards, CISAC’s William J. Perry Fellow in International Security at Stanford’s Freeman Spogli Institute for International Studies. Being interviewed by EarthSky. How nuclear war would affect Earth’s climate. September 8, 2017. earthsky.org/human-world/how-nuclear-war-would-affect-earths-climate] Note, we are only reading parts of the interview that are directly from Paul Edwards -- MMG In the nuclear conversation, what are we not talking about that we should be?
We are not talking enough about the climatic effects of nuclear war this aspect of nuclear war has faded from view. That’s not good In the mid-2000s, climate scientists took another look at nuclear winter theory. This time around, they used much-improved and much more detailed climate models than those available 20 years earlier U.S.-Russia war currently seems unlikely, but if it were to occur, hundreds or even thousands of nuclear weapons might be launched The climatic consequences would be catastrophic: global average temperatures would drop as much as 12 degrees for up to several years — temperatures last seen during the great ice ages smoke and dust circulating in the stratosphere would darken the atmosphere enough to inhibit photosynthesis, causing disastrous crop failures, widespread famine and massive ecological disruption The effect would be similar to that of the giant meteor believed to be responsible for the extinction of the dinosaurs This time, we would be the dinosaurs I think we are closer to a nuclear war than we have been since the early 1960s President lacks impulse control, and there are precious few checks on his ability to initiate a nuclear strike it’s quite unlikely that any exchange between two nuclear powers would stay limited to smaller, less destructive bombs
the climatic effects of nuc war faded from view climate scientists used improved models hundreds or thousands of weapons might be launched temperatures would drop 12 degrees last seen during the ice ages smoke would inhibit photosynthesis, causing crop failures famine and ecological disruption The effect would be similar to the giant meteor responsible for the extinction of the dinosaurs we would be the dinosaurs. President lacks control and there are few checks it’s unlikely any exchange would stay limited
We are not talking enough about the climatic effects of nuclear war. The “nuclear winter” theory of the mid-1980s played a significant role in the arms reductions of that period. But with the collapse of the Soviet Union and the reduction of U.S. and Russian nuclear arsenals, this aspect of nuclear war has faded from view. That’s not good. In the mid-2000s, climate scientists such as Alan Robock (Rutgers) took another look at nuclear winter theory. This time around, they used much-improved and much more detailed climate models than those available 20 years earlier. They also tested the potential effects of smaller nuclear exchanges. The result: an exchange involving just 50 nuclear weapons — the kind of thing we might see in an India-Pakistan war, for example — could loft 5 billion kilograms of smoke, soot and dust high into the stratosphere. That’s enough to cool the entire planet by about 2 degrees Fahrenheit (1.25 degrees Celsius) — about where we were during the Little Ice Age of the 17th century. Growing seasons could be shortened enough to create really significant food shortages. So the climatic effects of even a relatively small nuclear war would be planet-wide. What about a larger-scale conflict? A U.S.-Russia war currently seems unlikely, but if it were to occur, hundreds or even thousands of nuclear weapons might be launched. The climatic consequences would be catastrophic: global average temperatures would drop as much as 12 degrees Fahrenheit (7 degrees Celsius) for up to several years — temperatures last seen during the great ice ages. Meanwhile, smoke and dust circulating in the stratosphere would darken the atmosphere enough to inhibit photosynthesis, causing disastrous crop failures, widespread famine and massive ecological disruption. The effect would be similar to that of the giant meteor believed to be responsible for the extinction of the dinosaurs. This time, we would be the dinosaurs. Many people are concerned about North Korea’s advancing missile capabilities. Is nuclear war likely in your opinion? At this writing, I think we are closer to a nuclear war than we have been since the early 1960s. In the North Korea case, both Kim Jong-un and President Trump are bullies inclined to escalate confrontations. President Trump lacks impulse control, and there are precious few checks on his ability to initiate a nuclear strike. We have to hope that our generals, both inside and outside the White House, can rein him in. North Korea would most certainly “lose” a nuclear war with the United States. But many millions would die, including hundreds of thousands of Americans currently living in South Korea and Japan (probable North Korean targets). Such vast damage would be wrought in Korea, Japan and Pacific island territories (such as Guam) that any “victory” wouldn’t deserve the name. Not only would that region be left with horrible suffering amongst the survivors; it would also immediately face famine and rampant disease. Radioactive fallout from such a war would spread around the world, including to the U.S. It has been more than 70 years since the last time a nuclear bomb was used in warfare. What would be the effects on the environment and on human health today? To my knowledge, most of the changes in nuclear weapons technology since the 1950s have focused on making them smaller and lighter, and making delivery systems more accurate, rather than on changing their effects on the environment or on human health. So-called “battlefield” weapons with lower explosive yields are part of some arsenals now — but it’s quite unlikely that any exchange between two nuclear powers would stay limited to these smaller, less destructive bombs.
3,708
<h4>9] Nuclear war causes extinction</h4><p><strong>Edwards 17</strong> [Paul N. Edwards, CISAC’s William J. Perry Fellow in International Security at Stanford’s Freeman Spogli Institute for International Studies. Being interviewed by EarthSky. How nuclear war would affect Earth’s climate. September 8, 2017. earthsky.org/human-world/how-nuclear-war-would-affect-earths-climate] <strong>Note, we are only reading parts of the interview that are directly from Paul Edwards -- MMG</p><p></strong>In the nuclear conversation, what are we not talking about that we should be?</p><p><u>We are <strong>not talking enough</strong> about <mark>the <strong>climatic effects</strong> of <strong>nuc</mark>lear <mark>war</u></strong></mark>. The “nuclear winter” theory of the mid-1980s played a significant role in the arms reductions of that period. But with the collapse of the Soviet Union and the reduction of U.S. and Russian nuclear arsenals, <u>this aspect of nuclear war has <strong><mark>faded from view</strong></mark>. That’s <strong>not good</u></strong>. <u>In the mid-2000s, <mark>climate scientists</u></mark> such as Alan Robock (Rutgers) <u>took <strong>another look</strong> at nuclear winter theory. This time around, they <mark>used </mark>much-<strong><mark>improved</strong></mark> and much more detailed <strong>climate <mark>models</strong></mark> than those available 20 years earlier</u>. They also tested the potential effects of smaller nuclear exchanges. The result: an exchange involving just 50 nuclear weapons — the kind of thing we might see in an India-Pakistan war, for example — could loft 5 billion kilograms of smoke, soot and dust high into the stratosphere. That’s enough to cool the entire planet by about 2 degrees Fahrenheit (1.25 degrees Celsius) — about where we were during the Little Ice Age of the 17th century. Growing seasons could be shortened enough to create really significant food shortages. So the climatic effects of even a relatively small nuclear war would be planet-wide. What about a larger-scale conflict? A <u>U.S.-<strong>Russia</strong> war currently seems unlikely, but if it were to occur, <strong><mark>hundreds</strong> or</mark> even <strong><mark>thousands</strong> of</mark> <strong>nuclear <mark>weapons</strong> might be launched</u></mark>. <u>The <strong>climatic consequences</strong> would be <strong>catastrophic</strong>: global average <mark>temperatures would drop</mark> as much as <strong><mark>12 degrees</u></strong></mark> Fahrenheit (7 degrees Celsius) <u>for up to several years — temperatures <mark>last seen during the <strong></mark>great <mark>ice ages</u></strong></mark>. Meanwhile, <u><mark>smoke</mark> and dust circulating in the stratosphere <mark>would </mark>darken the atmosphere enough to <strong><mark>inhibit photosynthesis</strong>, causing <strong></mark>disastrous <mark>crop failures</strong></mark>, widespread <strong><mark>famine</strong> and <strong></mark>massive <mark>ecological disruption</u></strong></mark>. <u><mark>The effect would be similar to</mark> that of <mark>the <strong>giant meteor</strong></mark> believed to be <mark>responsible for the <strong>extinction of the dinosaurs</u></strong></mark>. <u>This time, <strong><mark>we would be the dinosaurs</u></strong>.</mark> Many people are concerned about North Korea’s advancing missile capabilities. Is nuclear war likely in your opinion? At this writing, <u>I think we are <strong>closer to a nuclear war</strong> than we have been <strong>since the early 1960s</u></strong>. In the North Korea case, both Kim Jong-un and President Trump are bullies inclined to escalate confrontations. <u><strong><mark>President</u></strong></mark> Trump<u><mark> lacks</mark> <strong>impulse <mark>control</strong></mark>, <mark>and there are</mark> precious <strong><mark>few checks</strong></mark> on his ability to initiate a nuclear strike</u>. We have to hope that our generals, both inside and outside the White House, can rein him in. North Korea would most certainly “lose” a nuclear war with the United States. But many millions would die, including hundreds of thousands of Americans currently living in South Korea and Japan (probable North Korean targets). Such vast damage would be wrought in Korea, Japan and Pacific island territories (such as Guam) that any “victory” wouldn’t deserve the name. Not only would that region be left with horrible suffering amongst the survivors; it would also immediately face famine and rampant disease. Radioactive fallout from such a war would spread around the world, including to the U.S. It has been more than 70 years since the last time a nuclear bomb was used in warfare. What would be the effects on the environment and on human health today? To my knowledge, most of the changes in nuclear weapons technology since the 1950s have focused on making them smaller and lighter, and making delivery systems more accurate, rather than on changing their effects on the environment or on human health. So-called “battlefield” weapons with lower explosive yields are part of some arsenals now — but <u><mark>it’s</mark> <strong>quite <mark>unlikely</strong></mark> that <strong><mark>any exchange</strong></mark> between two nuclear powers <mark>would <strong>stay</mark> <mark>limited</strong> </mark>to</u> these <u>smaller, <strong>less destructive</strong> bombs</u>.</p>
1AC
null
1AC – Arms Race
44,421
1,614
72,713
./documents/hsld20/Peninsula/Ra/Peninsula-Ramireddy-Aff-Cal%20RR-Round5.docx
870,300
A
Cal RR
5
Loyola LH
Rex Evans, Ronak Ahuja
1AC China v7 (with changes in doc) 1NC Xi Lashout DA T-States Navy PIC 1AR All 2NR T 2AR T
hsld20/Peninsula/Ra/Peninsula-Ramireddy-Aff-Cal%20RR-Round5.docx
null
73,622
AnRa
Peninsula AnRa
null
An.....
Ra.....
null
null
24,672
Peninsula
Peninsula
CA
null
1,028
hsld20
HS LD 2020-21
2,020
ld
hs
1
3,638,436
Fission – if the hemispheres of my brain were transplanted into two different people neither would be me
Parfit 84.
Parfit 84. Derek Parfit 1984, “Reasons and Persons”, Oxford Paperbacks
one hemisphere is enough. There are many people who have survived, when a stroke or injury puts out of action one of their hemispheres I would survive if my brain was successfully transplanted into my twin's body. And I could survive with only half my brain, the other half having been destroyed My body is fatally injured, as are the brains of my two brothers. My brain is divided, and each half is successfully transplanted into the body of one of my brothers This impossibility thus provides no ground for refusing to consider the imagined case in which we suppose that this can be done personal identity is not what matters If a mind was permanently divided, and its halves developed in different ways, it would become less plausible to claim that the case involves only one person They could live at opposite ends of the Earth they might meet again, and fail even to recognise each other It cannot be true that what I believe to be a stranger, standing there behind the net, is in fact another part of myself
I could survive with only half my brain My body is fatally injured, as are the brains of my two brothers. My brain is divided each half transplanted into the body of one of my brothers personal identity is not what matters If a mind was permanently divided and its halves developed in different ways, it would become less plausible to claim the case involves only one person They could live at opposite ends of the Earth they might fail to recognise each other It cannot be true that what I believe to be a stranger is another part of myself
It is in fact true that one hemisphere is enough. There are many people who have survived, when a stroke or injury puts out of action one of their hemispheres. With his remaining hemisphere, such a person may need to re-learn certain things, such as adult speech, or how to control both hands. But this is possible. In my example I am assuming that, as may be true of certain actual people, both of my hemispheres have the full range of abilities. I could thus survive with either hemisphere, without any need for re-learning.¶ I shall now combine these last two claims. I would survive if my brain was successfully transplanted into my twin's body. And I could survive with only half my brain, the other half having been destroyed. Given these two facts, it seems clear that I would survive if half my brain was successfully transplanted into my twin's body, and the other half was destroyed.¶ What if the other half was not destroyed? This is the case that Wiggins described: that in which a person, like an amoeba, divides.40 To simplify the case, I assume that I am one of three identical triplets. Consider¶ My Division. My body is fatally injured, as are the brains of my two brothers. My brain is divided, and each half is successfully transplanted into the body of one of my brothers. Each of the resulting people believes that he is me, seems to remember living my life, has my character, and is in every other way psychologically continuous with me. And he has a body that is very like mine.¶ This case is likely to remain impossible. Though it is claimed that, in certain people, the two hemispheres may have the same full range of abilities, this claim might be false. I am here assuming that this claim is true when applied to me. I am also assuming that it would be possible to connect a transplanted half-brain with the nerves in its new body. And I am assuming that we could divide, not just the upper hemispheres, but also the lower brain. My first two assumptions may be able to be made true if there is enough progress in neurophysiology. But it seems likely that it would never be possible to divide the lower brain, in a way that did not impair its functioning.¶ Does it matter if, for this reason, this imagined case of complete division will always remain impossible? Given the aims of my discussion, this does not matter. This impossibility is merely technical. The one feature of the case that might be held to be deeply impossible—the division of a person's consciousness into two separate streams—is the feature that has actually happened. It would have been important if this had been impossible, since this might have supported some claim about what we really are. It might have supported the claim that we are indivisible Cartesian Egos. It therefore matters that the division of a person's consciousness is in fact possible. There seems to be no similar connection between a particular view about what we really are and the impossibility of dividing and successfully transplanting the two halves of the lower brain. This impossibility thus provides no ground for refusing to consider the imagined case in which we suppose that this can be done. And considering this case may help us to decide both what we believe ourselves to be, and what in fact we are. As Einstein's example showed, it can be useful to consider impossible thought-experiments.¶ It may help to state, in advance, what I believe this case to show. It provides a further argument against the view that we are separately existing entities. But the main conclusion to be hdrawn is that personal identity is not what matters.¶ It is natural to believe that our identity is what matters. Reconsider the Branch-Line Case, where I have talked to my Replica on Mars, and am about to die. Suppose we believe that I and my Replica are different people. It is then natural to assume that my prospect is almost as bad as ordinary death. In a few days, there will be no one living who will be me. It is natural to assume that this is what matters. In discussing My Division, I shall start by making this assumption.¶ In this case, each half of my brain will be successfully transplanted into the very similar body of one of my two brothers. Both of the resulting people will be fully psychologically continuous with me, as I am now. What happens to me?¶ There are only four possibilities: (1) I do not survive; (2) I survive as one of the two people; (3) I survive as the other; (4) I survive as both.¶ The objection to (1) is this. I would survive if my brain was successfully transplanted. And people have in fact survived with half their brains destroyed. Given these facts, it seems clear that I would survive if half my brain was successfully transplanted, and the other half was destroyed. So how could I fail to survive if the other half was also successfully transplanted? How could a double success be a failure?¶ Consider the next two possibilities. Perhaps one success is the maximum score. Perhaps I shall be one of the two resulting people. The objection here is that, in this case, each half of my brain is exactly similar, and so, to start with, is each resulting person. Given these facts, how can I survive as only one of the two people? What can make me one of them rather than the other?¶ These three possibilities cannot be dismissed as incoherent. We can understand them. But, while we assume that identity is what matters, (1) is not plausible. My Division would not be as bad as death. Nor are (2) and (3) plausible. There remains the fourth possibility: that I survive as both of the resulting people.¶ This possibility might be described in several ways. I might first claim: ‘What we have called “the two resulting people” are not two people. They are one person. I do survive this operation. Its effect is to give me two bodies, and a divided mind.’¶ This claim cannot be dismissed outright. As I argued, we ought to admit as possible that a person could have a divided mind. If this is possible, each half of my divided mind might control its own body. But though this description of the case cannot be rejected as inconceivable, it involves a great distortion in our concept of a person. In my imagined Physics Exam I claimed that this case involved only one person. There were two features of the case that made this plausible. The divided mind was soon reunited, and there was only one body. If a mind was permanently divided, and its halves developed in different ways, it would become less plausible to claim that the case involves only one person. (Remember the actual patient who complained that, when he embraced his wife, his left hand pushed her away.)¶ The case of complete division, where there are also two bodies, seems to be a long way over the borderline. After I have had this operation, the two ‘products’ each have all of the features of a person. They could live at opposite ends of the Earth. Suppose that they have poor memories, and that their appearance changes in different ways. After many years, they might meet again, and fail even to recognise each other. We might have to claim of such a pair, innocently playing tennis: ‘What you see out there is a single person, playing tennis with himself. In each half of his mind he mistakenly believes that he is playing tennis with someone else.’ If we are not yet Reductionists, we believe that there is one true answer to the questionwhether these two tennis-players are a single person. Given what we mean by ‘person’, the answer must be No. It cannot be true that what I believe to be a stranger, standing there behind the net, is in fact another part of myself.
7,651
<h4>Fission – if the hemispheres of my brain were transplanted into two different people neither would be me</h4><p><strong>Parfit 84.</strong> Derek Parfit 1984, “Reasons and Persons”, Oxford Paperbacks</p><p>It is in fact true that <u>one hemisphere is enough. There are many people who have survived, when a stroke or injury puts out of action one of their hemispheres</u>. With his remaining hemisphere, such a person may need to re-learn certain things, such as adult speech, or how to control both hands. But this is possible. In my example I am assuming that, as may be true of certain actual people, both of my hemispheres have the full range of abilities. I could thus survive with either hemisphere, without any need for re-learning.¶ I shall now combine these last two claims. <u>I would survive if my brain was successfully transplanted into my twin's body. And <mark>I could survive with only half my brain</mark>, the other half having been destroyed</u>. Given these two facts, it seems clear that I would survive if half my brain was successfully transplanted into my twin's body, and the other half was destroyed.¶ What if the other half was not destroyed? This is the case that Wiggins described: that in which a person, like an amoeba, divides.40 To simplify the case, I assume that I am one of three identical triplets. Consider¶ My Division. <u><mark>My body is fatally injured, as are the brains of my two brothers. My brain is divided</mark>, and <mark>each half</mark> is successfully <mark>transplanted into the body of one of my brothers</u></mark>. Each of the resulting people believes that he is me, seems to remember living my life, has my character, and is in every other way psychologically continuous with me. And he has a body that is very like mine.¶ This case is likely to remain impossible. Though it is claimed that, in certain people, the two hemispheres may have the same full range of abilities, this claim might be false. I am here assuming that this claim is true when applied to me. I am also assuming that it would be possible to connect a transplanted half-brain with the nerves in its new body. And I am assuming that we could divide, not just the upper hemispheres, but also the lower brain. My first two assumptions may be able to be made true if there is enough progress in neurophysiology. But it seems likely that it would never be possible to divide the lower brain, in a way that did not impair its functioning.¶ Does it matter if, for this reason, this imagined case of complete division will always remain impossible? Given the aims of my discussion, this does not matter. This impossibility is merely technical. The one feature of the case that might be held to be deeply impossible—the division of a person's consciousness into two separate streams—is the feature that has actually happened. It would have been important if this had been impossible, since this might have supported some claim about what we really are. It might have supported the claim that we are indivisible Cartesian Egos. It therefore matters that the division of a person's consciousness is in fact possible. There seems to be no similar connection between a particular view about what we really are and the impossibility of dividing and successfully transplanting the two halves of the lower brain. <u>This impossibility thus provides no ground for refusing to consider the imagined case in which we suppose that this can be done</u>. And considering this case may help us to decide both what we believe ourselves to be, and what in fact we are. As Einstein's example showed, it can be useful to consider impossible thought-experiments.¶ It may help to state, in advance, what I believe this case to show. It provides a further argument against the view that we are separately existing entities. But the main conclusion to be hdrawn is that <u><mark>personal identity is not what matters</u></mark>.¶ It is natural to believe that our identity is what matters. Reconsider the Branch-Line Case, where I have talked to my Replica on Mars, and am about to die. Suppose we believe that I and my Replica are different people. It is then natural to assume that my prospect is almost as bad as ordinary death. In a few days, there will be no one living who will be me. It is natural to assume that this is what matters. In discussing My Division, I shall start by making this assumption.¶ In this case, each half of my brain will be successfully transplanted into the very similar body of one of my two brothers. Both of the resulting people will be fully psychologically continuous with me, as I am now. What happens to me?¶ There are only four possibilities: (1) I do not survive; (2) I survive as one of the two people; (3) I survive as the other; (4) I survive as both.¶ The objection to (1) is this. I would survive if my brain was successfully transplanted. And people have in fact survived with half their brains destroyed. Given these facts, it seems clear that I would survive if half my brain was successfully transplanted, and the other half was destroyed. So how could I fail to survive if the other half was also successfully transplanted? How could a double success be a failure?¶ Consider the next two possibilities. Perhaps one success is the maximum score. Perhaps I shall be one of the two resulting people. The objection here is that, in this case, each half of my brain is exactly similar, and so, to start with, is each resulting person. Given these facts, how can I survive as only one of the two people? What can make me one of them rather than the other?¶ These three possibilities cannot be dismissed as incoherent. We can understand them. But, while we assume that identity is what matters, (1) is not plausible. My Division would not be as bad as death. Nor are (2) and (3) plausible. There remains the fourth possibility: that I survive as both of the resulting people.¶ This possibility might be described in several ways. I might first claim: ‘What we have called “the two resulting people” are not two people. They are one person. I do survive this operation. Its effect is to give me two bodies, and a divided mind.’¶ This claim cannot be dismissed outright. As I argued, we ought to admit as possible that a person could have a divided mind. If this is possible, each half of my divided mind might control its own body. But though this description of the case cannot be rejected as inconceivable, it involves a great distortion in our concept of a person. In my imagined Physics Exam I claimed that this case involved only one person. There were two features of the case that made this plausible. The divided mind was soon reunited, and there was only one body. <u><mark>If a mind was permanently divided</mark>, <mark>and its halves developed in different ways, it would become less plausible to claim</mark> that <mark>the case involves only one person</u></mark>. (Remember the actual patient who complained that, when he embraced his wife, his left hand pushed her away.)¶ The case of complete division, where there are also two bodies, seems to be a long way over the borderline. After I have had this operation, the two ‘products’ each have all of the features of a person. <u><mark>They could live at opposite ends of the Earth</u></mark>. Suppose that they have poor memories, and that their appearance changes in different ways. After many years, <u><mark>they might</mark> meet again, and <mark>fail</mark> even <mark>to recognise each other</u></mark>. We might have to claim of such a pair, innocently playing tennis: ‘What you see out there is a single person, playing tennis with himself. In each half of his mind he mistakenly believes that he is playing tennis with someone else.’ If we are not yet Reductionists, we believe that there is one true answer to the questionwhether these two tennis-players are a single person. Given what we mean by ‘person’, the answer must be No. <u><mark>It cannot be true that what I believe to be a stranger</mark>, standing there behind the net, <mark>is</mark> in fact <mark>another part of myself</u></mark>.</p>
null
null
Framework
340,852
283
121,668
./documents/hsld17/Westwood/Sh/Westwood-Shah-Aff-TFA%20State-Round2.docx
815,377
A
TFA State
2
Strake Jesuit MC
John Sims
1AC - Automation 1NC - Particularism NC SAFA Politics DA 1AR - Nibs bad ALL 2NR - Particularism NC
hsld17/Westwood/Sh/Westwood-Shah-Aff-TFA%20State-Round2.docx
null
69,814
RiSh
Westwood RiSh
null
Ri.....
Sh.....
null
null
23,627
Westwood
Westwood
null
null
1,025
hsld17
HS LD 2017-18
2,017
ld
hs
1
4,625,773
Collapse doesn’t cause war
Clary 15
Clary 15 – Christopher Clary, former International Affairs Fellow in India at the Council on Foreign Relations, Postdoctoral Fellow at the Watson Institute at Brown University, Adjunct Staff Member @ RAND Corporation, Security Studies Program @ MIT, country director for South Asian affairs in the Office of the Secretary of Defense, former Research Fellow @ the Harvard Kennedy School's Belfer Center for Science and International Affairs, former research associate in the Department of National Security Affairs at the Naval Postgraduate School, BA from Wichita State University and an MA from the U.S. Naval Postgraduate School, 2015 (“Economic Stress and International Cooperation: Evidence from International Rivalries,” Massachusetts Institute of Technology Political Science Department Research Paper No. 2015-­‐8, “Economic Stress and International Cooperation: Evidence from International Rivalries,” http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2597712)
Do economic downturns generate pressure for diversionary conflict Or might downturns encourage austerity and economizing behavior in foreign policy This paper provides new evidence that economic stress is associated with conciliatory policies between strategic rivals the biggest step possible toward bilateral cooperation is to terminate the rivalry by taking political steps to manage the competition. Drawing on data from 109 distinct rival dyads since 1950, 67 of which terminated, the evidence suggests rivalries were approximately twice as likely to terminate during economic downturns than they were during periods of economic normalcy This is true controlling for all of the main alternative explanations for peaceful relations between foes as well as many other possible confounding variables This research questions existing theories claiming that economic downturns are associated with diversionary war, and argues that peace may result from economic troubles Economic crises lead to conciliatory behavior through five primary channels Economic crises lead to austerity pressures, which in turn incent leaders to search for ways to cut defense expenditures Economic crises also encourage strategic reassessment so that leaders can argue to their peers and their publics that defense spending can be arrested without endangering the state. This can lead to threat deflation
economic stress is associated with conciliatory policies Drawing on data from 109 distinct dyads rivalries were twice as likely to terminate during economic downturns This is true controlling for all alternative explanations crises lead to austerity which cut defense expenditures crises encourage strategic reassessment This can lead to threat deflation
Do economic downturns generate pressure for diversionary conflict? Or might downturns encourage austerity and economizing behavior in foreign policy? This paper provides new evidence that economic stress is associated with conciliatory policies between strategic rivals. For states that view each other as military threats, the biggest step possible toward bilateral cooperation is to terminate the rivalry by taking political steps to manage the competition. Drawing on data from 109 distinct rival dyads since 1950, 67 of which terminated, the evidence suggests rivalries were approximately twice as likely to terminate during economic downturns than they were during periods of economic normalcy. This is true controlling for all of the main alternative explanations for peaceful relations between foes (democratic status, nuclear weapons possession, capability imbalance, common enemies, and international systemic changes), as well as many other possible confounding variables. This research questions existing theories claiming that economic downturns are associated with diversionary war, and instead argues that in certain circumstances peace may result from economic troubles. Defining and Measuring Rivalry and Rivalry Termination I define a rivalry as the perception by national elites of two states that the other state possesses conflicting interests and presents a military threat of sufficient severity that future military conflict is likely. Rivalry termination is the transition from a state of rivalry to one where conflicts of interest are not viewed as being so severe as to provoke interstate conflict and/or where a mutual recognition of the imbalance in military capabilities makes conflict-causing bargaining failures unlikely. In other words, rivalries terminate when the elites assess that the risks of military conflict between rivals has been reduced dramatically. This definition draws on a growing quantitative literature most closely associated with the research programs of William Thompson, J. Joseph Hewitt, and James P. Klein, Gary Goertz, and Paul F. Diehl.1 My definition conforms to that of William Thompson. In work with Karen Rasler, they define rivalries as situations in which “[b]oth actors view each other as a significant politicalmilitary threat and, therefore, an enemy.”2 In other work, Thompson writing with Michael Colaresi, explains further: The presumption is that decisionmakers explicitly identify who they think are their foreign enemies. They orient their military preparations and foreign policies toward meeting their threats. They assure their constituents that they will not let their adversaries take advantage. Usually, these activities are done in public. Hence, we should be able to follow the explicit cues in decisionmaker utterances and writings, as well as in the descriptive political histories written about the foreign policies of specific countries.3 Drawing from available records and histories, Thompson and David Dreyer have generated a universe of strategic rivalries from 1494 to 2010 that serves as the basis for this project’s empirical analysis.4 This project measures rivalry termination as occurring on the last year that Thompson and Dreyer record the existence of a rivalry.5 Why Might Economic Crisis Cause Rivalry Termination? Economic crises lead to conciliatory behavior through five primary channels. (1) Economic crises lead to austerity pressures, which in turn incent leaders to search for ways to cut defense expenditures. (2) Economic crises also encourage strategic reassessment, so that leaders can argue to their peers and their publics that defense spending can be arrested without endangering the state. This can lead to threat deflation,
3,738
<h4>Collapse doesn’t cause war </h4><p><strong>Clary 15 </strong>– Christopher Clary, former International Affairs Fellow in India at the Council on Foreign Relations, Postdoctoral Fellow at the Watson Institute at Brown University, Adjunct Staff Member @ RAND Corporation, Security Studies Program @ MIT, country director for South Asian affairs in the Office of the Secretary of Defense, former Research Fellow @ the Harvard Kennedy School's Belfer Center for Science and International Affairs, former research associate in the Department of National Security Affairs at the Naval Postgraduate School, BA from Wichita State University and an MA from the U.S. Naval Postgraduate School, 2015 (“Economic Stress and International Cooperation: Evidence from International Rivalries,” Massachusetts Institute of Technology Political Science Department Research Paper No. 2015-­‐8, “Economic Stress and International Cooperation: Evidence from International Rivalries,” http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2597712)</p><p><u>Do economic downturns generate <strong>pressure for diversionary conflict</u></strong>? <u>Or might downturns encourage austerity and economizing behavior in foreign policy</u>? <u>This paper provides new evidence that <mark>economic stress is associated with <strong>conciliatory policies</strong></mark> between strategic rivals</u>. For states that view each other as military threats, <u>the biggest step possible toward bilateral cooperation is to terminate the rivalry by taking political steps to manage the competition. <mark>Drawing on data from 109 distinct </mark>rival <mark>dyads </mark>since 1950, 67 of which terminated, the</u> <u>evidence suggests <mark>rivalries were </mark>approximately <strong><mark>twice as likely to terminate during economic downturns</strong></mark> than they were during periods of economic normalcy</u>. <u><mark>This is true controlling for all </mark>of the main <mark>alternative explanations</mark> for peaceful relations between foes</u> (democratic status, nuclear weapons possession, capability imbalance, common enemies, and international systemic changes), <u>as well as many other possible confounding variables</u>. <u>This research questions existing theories claiming that economic downturns are associated with diversionary war, and</u> instead <u>argues that</u> in certain circumstances <u><strong>peace may result from economic troubles</u></strong>. Defining and Measuring Rivalry and Rivalry Termination I define a rivalry as the perception by national elites of two states that the other state possesses conflicting interests and presents a military threat of sufficient severity that future military conflict is likely. Rivalry termination is the transition from a state of rivalry to one where conflicts of interest are not viewed as being so severe as to provoke interstate conflict and/or where a mutual recognition of the imbalance in military capabilities makes conflict-causing bargaining failures unlikely. In other words, rivalries terminate when the elites assess that the risks of military conflict between rivals has been reduced dramatically. This definition draws on a growing quantitative literature most closely associated with the research programs of William Thompson, J. Joseph Hewitt, and James P. Klein, Gary Goertz, and Paul F. Diehl.1 My definition conforms to that of William Thompson. In work with Karen Rasler, they define rivalries as situations in which “[b]oth actors view each other as a significant politicalmilitary threat and, therefore, an enemy.”2 In other work, Thompson writing with Michael Colaresi, explains further: The presumption is that decisionmakers explicitly identify who they think are their foreign enemies. They orient their military preparations and foreign policies toward meeting their threats. They assure their constituents that they will not let their adversaries take advantage. Usually, these activities are done in public. Hence, we should be able to follow the explicit cues in decisionmaker utterances and writings, as well as in the descriptive political histories written about the foreign policies of specific countries.3 Drawing from available records and histories, Thompson and David Dreyer have generated a universe of strategic rivalries from 1494 to 2010 that serves as the basis for this project’s empirical analysis.4 This project measures rivalry termination as occurring on the last year that Thompson and Dreyer record the existence of a rivalry.5 Why Might Economic Crisis Cause Rivalry Termination? <u><strong>Economic crises lead to conciliatory behavior</u></strong> <u>through five primary channels</u>. (1) <u>Economic <mark>crises lead to austerity </mark>pressures, <mark>which </mark>in turn incent leaders to search for ways to <mark>cut defense expenditures</u></mark>. (2) <u>Economic <mark>crises </mark>also <mark>encourage <strong>strategic reassessment</u></strong></mark>, <u>so that leaders can argue to their peers and their publics that defense spending can be arrested without endangering the state. <mark>This can lead to <strong>threat deflation</u></strong></mark>,</p>
Case
4
1NC – Dedev
983
2,566
153,668
./documents/hsld22/Westridge/TaWe/Westridge-TaWe-Neg-CPS-LD-Invitational-Round-4.docx
956,346
N
CPS LD Invitational
4
Harker VL
Kymn
1ac - africa 1nc - nebel, terror da, populism da, pandemics pic, case (dedev) 1ar - all 2nr - populism da, dedev 2ar - case, dedev, populism
hsld22/Westridge/TaWe/Westridge-TaWe-Neg-CPS-LD-Invitational-Round-4.docx
2022-12-18 02:43:39
79,306
TaWe
Westridge TaWe
meowwww
Ta.....
We.....
null
null
26,555
Westridge
Westridge
CA
null
2,003
hsld22
HS LD 2022-23
2,022
ld
hs
1
3,111,563
Demands that a state not exclude groups doesn’t reaffirm the legitimacy of the state. Individual demands can call into question the legitimacy of the state.
Newman 10
Saul Newman 10, Reader in Political Theory at Goldsmiths, U of London, Theory & Event Volume 13, Issue 2
the notion of demand: making certain demands on the state – say fo an end to draconian policing – is the basic strategies of social movements Making such demands does not necessarily mean working within the state or reaffirming its legitimacy. On the contrary, demands are made from a position outside the political order, and they often exceed the question of the implementation of this or that specific measure. They implicitly call into question the legitimacy and even the sovereignty of the state by highlighting fundamental inconsistencies between a formal constitutional order which guarantees certain rights and equalities, and state practices which in reality violate and deny them
making certain demands on the state – say for an end to draconian policing – is the basic strategies of social movements Making such demands does not mean working within the state or reaffirming its legitimacy position outside the political order, and exceed the question of the implementation of this or that specific measure. The question the legitimacy and even the sovereignty of the state by between a formal order which guarantees certain equalities, and state practices which deny them.
There are two aspects that I would like to address here. Firstly, the notion of demand: making certain demands on the state – say for higher wages, equal rights for excluded groups, to not go to war, or an end to draconian policing – is one of the basic strategies of social movements and radical groups. Making such demands does not necessarily mean working within the state or reaffirming its legitimacy. On the contrary, demands are made from a position outside the political order, and they often exceed the question of the implementation of this or that specific measure. They implicitly call into question the legitimacy and even the sovereignty of the state by highlighting fundamental inconsistencies between, for instance, a formal constitutional order which guarantees certain rights and equalities, and state practices which in reality violate and deny them.
869
<h4>Demands that a state not exclude groups doesn’t reaffirm the legitimacy of the state. Individual demands can call into question the legitimacy of the state.</h4><p>Saul <strong>Newman 10</strong>, Reader in Political Theory at Goldsmiths, U of London, Theory & Event Volume 13, Issue 2</p><p>There are two aspects that I would like to address here. Firstly, <u>the notion of demand:</u> <u><mark>making</u> <u>certain</u> <u>demands on</u> <u>the state – say fo</u>r</mark> higher wages, equal rights for excluded groups, to not go to war, or <u><mark>an end to draconian policing – is</u></mark> one of <u><mark>the basic strategies of social movements</u></mark> and radical groups. <u><mark>Making such demands</mark> <strong><mark>does not</mark> necessarily</u></strong> <u><strong><mark>mean working within the state or reaffirming its legitimacy</strong></mark>. On the contrary,</u> <u>demands are made from a <strong><mark>position outside the political order, and</u></strong></mark> <u><strong>they often <mark>exceed the question of the implementation</u></strong> <u><strong>of this or that specific measure.</u> <u></strong>The</mark>y</u> <u>implicitly</u> <u>call into <mark>question</u> <u>the <strong>legitimacy</strong> and <strong>even the sovereignty</strong> of the state</u> <u>by</mark> highlighting</u> <u>fundamental</u> <u>inconsistencies</u> <u><mark>between</u></mark>, for instance, <u><mark>a formal </mark>constitutional <mark>order which guarantees certain</mark> rights and <mark>equalities, and state practices which</mark> in reality violate and <mark>deny them</u>.</p></mark>
null
1ar
Coloniality
31,086
849
101,402
./documents/ndtceda18/Michigan/WaGo/Michigan-Walrath-Goldschlag-Aff-Wake-Round5.docx
606,185
A
Wake
5
Florida CJ
Thomas
1ac NFU crisis stability 1nc coloniality 2nr coloniality
ndtceda18/Michigan/WaGo/Michigan-Walrath-Goldschlag-Aff-Wake-Round5.docx
null
51,453
WaGo
Michigan WaGo
null
Ca.....
Wa.....
Ja.....
Go.....
19,200
Michigan
Michigan
null
null
1,008
ndtceda18
NDT/CEDA 2018-19
2,018
cx
college
2