import topology.metric_space.basic open_locale classical filter topological_space namespace lftcm open filter set /-! # Filters ## Definition of filters -/ def principal {α : Type*} (s : set α) : filter α := { sets := {t | s ⊆ t}, univ_sets := begin -- sorry tauto, -- sorry end, sets_of_superset := begin -- sorry intros U V hU hUV, tauto, -- sorry end, inter_sets := begin -- sorry rintros U V hU hV, intros x xs, split ; tauto, -- sorry end} def at_top : filter ℕ := { sets := {s | ∃ a, ∀ b, a ≤ b → b ∈ s}, univ_sets := begin -- sorry use 42, finish, -- sorry end, sets_of_superset := begin -- sorry rintros U V ⟨N, hN⟩ hUV, use N, tauto, -- sorry end, inter_sets := begin -- sorry rintros U V ⟨N, hN⟩ ⟨N', hN'⟩, use max N N', intros b hb, rw max_le_iff at hb, split ; tauto, -- sorry end} -- The next exercise is slightly more tricky, you should probably keep it for later def nhds (x : ℝ) : filter ℝ := { sets := {s | ∃ ε > 0, Ioo (x - ε) (x + ε) ⊆ s}, univ_sets := begin -- sorry use 42⁻¹, split, norm_num, tauto, -- sorry end, sets_of_superset := begin -- sorry rintros U V ⟨ε, hε⟩ hUV, use ε, tauto, -- sorry end, inter_sets := begin -- sorry rintros U V ⟨ε, hε, hU⟩ ⟨ε', hε', hV⟩, use [min ε ε', lt_min hε hε'], intros b hb, rw mem_Ioo at hb, split, { apply hU, split ; linarith [min_le_left ε ε'] }, { apply hV, split ; linarith [min_le_right ε ε'] }, -- sorry end} /- The filter axiom are also available as standalone lemmas where the filter argument is implicit Compare -/ #check @filter.sets_of_superset #check @mem_of_superset -- And analogously: #check @inter_mem /-! ## Definition of "tends to" -/ -- We'll practive using tendsto by reproving the composition lemma `tendsto.comp` from mathlib -- Let's first use the concrete definition recorded by `tendsto_def` #check @tendsto_def #check @preimage_comp example {α β γ : Type*} {A : filter α} {B : filter β} {C : filter γ} {f : α → β} {g : β → γ} (hf : tendsto f A B) (hg : tendsto g B C) : tendsto (g ∘ f) A C := begin -- sorry rw tendsto_def at *, intros U U_in, rw preimage_comp, apply hf, apply hg, assumption, -- sorry end -- Now let's get functorial (same statement as above, different proof packaging). example {α β γ : Type*} {A : filter α} {B : filter β} {C : filter γ} {f : α → β} {g : β → γ} (hf : tendsto f A B) (hg : tendsto g B C) : tendsto (g ∘ f) A C := begin calc map (g ∘ f) A = map g (map f A) : /- inline sorry -/ map_map/- inline sorry -/ ... ≤ map g B : /- inline sorry -/map_mono hf/- inline sorry -/ ... ≤ C : /- inline sorry -/hg/- inline sorry -/, end /- Let's now focus on the pull-back operation `filter.comap` which takes `f : X → Y` and a filter `G` on `Y` and returns a filter on `X`. -/ #check @mem_comap -- this is by definition, the proof is `iff.rfl` -- It also help to record a special case of one implication: #check @preimage_mem_comap -- The following exercise, which reproves `comap_ne_bot_iff` can start using #check @forall_mem_nonempty_iff_ne_bot example {α β : Type*} {f : filter β} {m : α → β} : (comap m f).ne_bot ↔ ∀ t ∈ f, ∃ a, m a ∈ t := begin -- sorry rw ← forall_mem_nonempty_iff_ne_bot, split ; intro h, { intros t t_in, exact h (m ⁻¹' t) ⟨t, t_in, subset.refl _⟩, }, { rintros s ⟨u, u_in, hu⟩, cases h u u_in with x hx, exact ⟨x, hu hx⟩ }, -- sorry end /-! ## Properties holding eventually -/ /-- The next exercise only needs the definition of filters and the fact that `∀ᶠ x in f, p x` is a notation for `{x | p x} ∈ f`. It is called `eventually_and` in mathlib, and won't be needed below. For instance, applied to `α = ℕ` and the `at_top` filter above, it says that, given two predicates `p` and `q` on natural numbers, p n and q n for n large enough if and only if p n holds for n large enough and q n holds for n large enough. -/ example {α : Type*} {p q : α → Prop} {f : filter α} : (∀ᶠ x in f, p x ∧ q x) ↔ (∀ᶠ x in f, p x) ∧ (∀ᶠ x in f, q x) := begin -- sorry split, { intro h, split, { apply mem_of_superset h, intros x x_in, exact x_in.1 }, { apply mem_of_superset h, intros x x_in, exact x_in.2 } }, { intros h, exact f.inter_sets h.1 h.2, }, -- sorry end /-! ## Topological spaces -/ section -- This is how we can talk about two topological spaces X and Y variables {X Y : Type*} [topological_space X] [topological_space Y] /- Given a topological space `X` and some `A : set X`, we have the usual zoo of predicates `is_open A`, `is_closed A`, `is_connected A`, `is_compact A` (and some more) There are also additional type classes referring to properties of `X` itself, like `compact_space X` or `connected_space X` -/ /-- We can talk about continuous functions from `X` to `Y` -/ example (f : X → Y) : continuous f ↔ ∀ V, is_open V → is_open (f ⁻¹' V) := continuous_def /- Each point `x` of a topological space has a neighborhood filter `𝓝 x` made of sets containing an open set containing `x`. It is always a proper filter, as recorded by `nhds_ne_bot` Asking for continuity is the same as asking for continuity at each point the right-hand side below is known as `continuous_at f x` -/ example (f : X → Y) : continuous f ↔ ∀ x, tendsto f (𝓝 x) (𝓝 (f x)) := continuous_iff_continuous_at /- The topological structure also brings operations on sets. To each `A : set X`, we can associate `closure A`, `interior A` and `frontier A`. We'll focus on `closure A`. It is defined as the intersection of closed sets containing `A` but we can characterize it in terms of neighborhoods. The most concrete version is `mem_closure_iff_nhds : a ∈ closure A ↔ ∀ B ∈ 𝓝 a, (B ∩ A).nonempty` We'll pratice by reproving the slightly more abstract `mem_closure_iff_comap_ne_bot`. First let's review sets and subtypes. Fix a type `X` and recall that `A : set X` is not a type a priori, but Lean coerces automatically when needed to the type `↥A` whose terms are build of a term `x : X` and a proof of `x ∈ A`. In the other direction, inhabitants of `↥A` can be coerced to `X` automatically. This inclusion coercion map is called `coe : A → X` and `coe a` is also denoted by `↑a`. Now assume `X` is a topological space, and let's understand the closure of A in terms of `coe` and the neighborhood filter. In the next exercise, you can use `simp_rw` instead of `rw` to rewrite inside a quantifier -/ #check nonempty_inter_iff_exists_right example {A : set X} {x : X} : x ∈ closure A ↔ (comap (coe : A → X) (𝓝 x)).ne_bot := begin -- sorry simp_rw [mem_closure_iff_nhds, comap_ne_bot_iff, nonempty_inter_iff_exists_right], -- sorry end /- In elementary contexts, the main property of `closure A` is that a converging sequence `u : ℕ → X` such that `∀ n, u n ∈ A` has its limit in `closure A`. Note we don't need all the full sequence to be in `A`, it's enough to ask it for `n` large enough, ie. `∀ᶠ n in at_top, u n ∈ A`. Also there is no reason to use sequences only, we can use any map and any source filter. We hence have the important `mem_closure_of_tendsto` : ∀ {f : β → X} {F : filter β} {a : X} {A : set X}, F ≠ ⊥ → tendsto f F (𝓝 a) → (∀ᶠ x in F, f x ∈ A) → a ∈ closure A If `A` is known to be closed then we can replace `closure A` by `A`, this is `is_closed.mem_of_tendsto`. -/ /- We need one last piece of filter technology: bases. By definition, each neighborhood of a point `x` contains an *open* neighborhood of `x`. Hence we can often restrict our attention to such neighborhoods. The general definition recording such a situation is: `has_basis` (l : filter α) (p : ι → Prop) (s : ι → set α) : Prop := (mem_iff' : ∀ t, t ∈ l ↔ ∃ i (hi : p i), s i ⊆ t) You can now inspect three examples of how bases allow to restrict attention to certain elements of a filter. -/ #check @has_basis.mem_iff #check @has_basis.tendsto_left_iff #check @has_basis.tendsto_right_iff -- We'll use the following bases: #check @nhds_basis_opens' #check @closed_nhds_basis /-- Our main goal is now to prove the basic theorem which allows extension by continuity. From Bourbaki's general topology book, I.8.5, Theorem 1 (taking only the non-trivial implication): Let `X` be a topological space, `A` a dense subset of `X`, `f : A → Y` a mapping of `A` into a regular space `Y`. If, for each `x` in `X`, `f(y)` tends to a limit in `Y` when `y` tends to `x` while remaining in `A` then there exists a continuous extension `φ` of `f` to `X`. The regularity assumption on `Y` ensures that each point of `Y` has a basis of *closed* neighborhoods, this is `closed_nhds_basis`. It also ensures that `Y` is Hausdorff so limits in `Y` are unique, this is `tendsto_nhds_unique`. mathlib contains a refinement of the above lemma, `dense_inducing.continuous_at_extend`, but we'll stick to Bourbaki's version here. Remember that, given `A : set X`, `↥A` is the subtype associated to `A`, and Lean will automatically insert that funny up arrow when needed. And the (inclusion) coercion map is `coe : A → X`. The assumption "tends to `x` while remaining in `A`" corresponds to the pull-back filter `comap coe (𝓝 x)`. Let's prove first an auxilliary lemma, extracted to simplify the context (in particular we don't need Y to be a topological space here). -/ lemma aux {X Y A : Type*} [topological_space X] {c : A → X} {f : A → Y} {x : X} {F : filter Y} (h : tendsto f (comap c (𝓝 x)) F) {V' : set Y} (V'_in : V' ∈ F) : ∃ V ∈ 𝓝 x, is_open V ∧ c ⁻¹' V ⊆ f ⁻¹' V' := begin -- sorry simpa [and_assoc] using ((nhds_basis_opens' x).comap c).tendsto_left_iff.mp h V' V'_in -- sorry end /-- Let's now turn to the main proof of the extension by continuity theorem. When Lean needs a topology on `↥A` it will use the induced topology, thanks to the instance `subtype.topological_space`. This all happens automatically. The only relevant lemma is `nhds_induced coe : ∀ a : ↥A, 𝓝 a = comap coe (𝓝 ↑a)` (this is actually a general lemma about induced topologies). The proof outline is: The main assumption and the axiom of choice give a function `φ` such that `∀ x, tendsto f (comap coe $ 𝓝 x) (𝓝 (φ x))` (because `Y` is Hausdorff, `φ` is entirely determined, but we won't need that until we try to prove that `φ` indeed extends `f`). Let's first prove `φ` is continuous. Fix any `x : X`. Since `Y` is regular, it suffices to check that for every *closed* neighborhood `V'` of `φ x`, `φ ⁻¹' V' ∈ 𝓝 x`. The limit assumption gives (through the auxilliary lemma above) some `V ∈ 𝓝 x` such `is_open V ∧ coe ⁻¹' V ⊆ f ⁻¹' V'`. Since `V ∈ 𝓝 x`, it suffices to prove `V ⊆ φ ⁻¹' V'`, ie `∀ y ∈ V, φ y ∈ V'`. Let's fix `y` in `V`. Because `V` is *open*, it is a neighborhood of `y`. In particular `coe ⁻¹' V ∈ comap coe (𝓝 y)` and a fortiori `f ⁻¹' V' ∈ comap coe (𝓝 y)`. In addition `comap coe $ 𝓝 y ≠ ⊥` because `A` is dense. Because we know `tendsto f (comap coe $ 𝓝 y) (𝓝 (φ y))` this implies `φ y ∈ closure V'` and, since `V'` is closed, we have proved `φ y ∈ V'`. It remains to prove that `φ` extends `f`. This is were continuity of `f` enters the discussion, together with the fact that `Y` is Hausdorff. -/ example [t3_space Y] {A : set X} (hA : ∀ x, x ∈ closure A) {f : A → Y} (f_cont : continuous f) (hf : ∀ x : X, ∃ c : Y, tendsto f (comap coe $ 𝓝 x) $ 𝓝 c) : ∃ φ : X → Y, continuous φ ∧ ∀ a : A, φ a = f a := begin -- sorry choose φ hφ using hf, use φ, split, { rw continuous_iff_continuous_at, intros x, suffices : ∀ V' ∈ 𝓝 (φ x), is_closed V' → φ ⁻¹' V' ∈ 𝓝 x, by simpa [continuous_at, (closed_nhds_basis _).tendsto_right_iff], intros V' V'_in V'_closed, obtain ⟨V, V_in, V_op, hV⟩ : ∃ V ∈ 𝓝 x, is_open V ∧ coe ⁻¹' V ⊆ f ⁻¹' V', { exact aux (hφ x) V'_in }, suffices : ∀ y ∈ V, φ y ∈ V', from mem_of_superset V_in this, intros y y_in, have hVx : V ∈ 𝓝 y := is_open.mem_nhds V_op y_in, haveI : (comap (coe : A → X) (𝓝 y)).ne_bot := by simpa [mem_closure_iff_comap_ne_bot] using hA y, apply is_closed.mem_of_tendsto V'_closed (hφ y), exact mem_of_superset (preimage_mem_comap hVx) hV }, { intros a, have lim : tendsto f (𝓝 a) (𝓝 $ φ a), by simpa [nhds_induced] using hφ a, exact tendsto_nhds_unique lim f_cont.continuous_at }, -- sorry end end /-! ## Metric spaces -/ /-- We now leave general topology and turn to metric spaces. The distance function is denoted by `dist`. A slight difficulty here is that, as in Bourbaki, many results you may expect to see stated for metric spaces are stated for uniform spaces, a more general notion that also includes topological groups. In this tutorial we will avoid uniform spaces for simplicity. We will prove that continuous functions from a compact metric space to a metric space are uniformly continuous. mathlib has a much more general version (about functions between uniform spaces...). The lemma `metric.uniform_continuous_iff` allows to translate the general definition of uniform continuity to the ε-δ definition that works for metric spaces only. So let's fix `ε > 0` and start looking for `δ`. We will deduce Heine-Cantor from the fact that a real value continuous function on a nonempty compact set reaches its infimum. There are several ways to state that, but here we recommend `is_compact.exists_forall_le`. Let `φ : X × X → ℝ := λ p, dist (f p.1) (f p.2)` and let `K := { p : X × X | ε ≤ φ p }`. Observe `φ` is continuous by assumption on `f` and using `continuous_dist`. And `K` is closed using `is_closed_le` hence compact since `X` is compact. Then we discuss two possibilities using `eq_empty_or_nonempty`. If `K` is empty then we are clearly done (we can set `δ = 1` for instance). So let's assume `K` is not empty, and choose `(x₀, x₁)` attaining the infimum of `φ` on `K`. We can then set `δ = dist x₀ x₁` and check everything works. -/ example {X : Type*} [metric_space X] [compact_space X] {Y : Type*} [metric_space Y] {f : X → Y} (hf : continuous f) : uniform_continuous f := begin -- sorry rw metric.uniform_continuous_iff, intros ε ε_pos, let φ : X × X → ℝ := λ p, dist (f p.1) (f p.2), have φ_cont : continuous φ := continuous_dist.comp (hf.prod_map hf), let K := { p : X × X | ε ≤ φ p }, have K_closed : is_closed K := is_closed_le continuous_const φ_cont, have K_cpct : is_compact K := K_closed.is_compact, cases eq_empty_or_nonempty K with hK hK, { use [1, by norm_num], intros x y hxy, have : (x, y) ∉ K, by simp [hK], simpa [K] }, { rcases K_cpct.exists_forall_le hK continuous_dist.continuous_on with ⟨⟨x₀, x₁⟩, xx_in, H⟩, use dist x₀ x₁, split, { change _ < _, rw dist_pos, intro h, have : ε ≤ 0, by simpa [*] using xx_in, linarith }, { intros x x', contrapose!, intros hxx', linarith [H (x, x') hxx'] } }, -- sorry end end lftcm