Datasets:
Tasks:
Text Generation
Modalities:
Text
Sub-tasks:
language-modeling
Languages:
English
Size:
100K - 1M
License:
File size: 103,733 Bytes
afd65d6 |
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148 149 150 151 152 153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 161 162 163 164 165 166 167 168 169 170 171 172 173 174 175 176 177 178 179 180 181 182 183 184 185 186 187 188 189 190 191 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 199 200 201 202 203 204 205 206 207 208 209 210 211 212 213 214 215 216 217 218 219 220 221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 255 256 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 271 272 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 289 290 291 292 293 294 295 296 297 298 299 300 301 302 303 304 305 306 307 308 309 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 318 319 320 321 322 323 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 332 333 334 335 336 337 338 339 340 341 342 343 344 345 346 347 348 349 350 351 352 353 354 355 356 357 358 359 360 361 362 363 364 365 366 367 368 369 370 371 372 373 374 375 376 377 378 379 380 381 382 383 384 385 386 387 388 389 390 391 392 393 394 395 396 397 398 399 400 401 402 403 404 405 406 407 408 409 410 411 412 413 414 415 416 417 418 419 420 421 422 423 424 425 426 427 428 429 430 431 432 433 434 435 436 437 438 439 440 441 442 443 444 445 446 447 448 449 450 451 452 453 454 455 456 457 458 459 460 461 462 463 464 465 466 467 468 469 470 471 472 473 474 475 476 477 478 479 480 481 482 483 484 485 486 487 488 489 490 491 492 493 494 495 496 497 498 499 500 501 502 503 504 505 506 507 508 509 510 511 512 513 514 515 516 517 518 519 520 521 522 523 524 525 526 527 528 529 530 531 532 533 534 535 536 537 538 539 540 541 542 543 544 545 546 547 548 549 550 551 552 553 554 555 556 557 558 559 560 561 562 563 564 565 566 567 568 569 570 571 572 573 574 575 576 577 578 579 580 581 582 583 584 585 586 587 588 589 590 591 592 593 594 595 596 597 598 599 600 601 602 603 604 605 606 607 608 609 610 611 612 613 614 615 616 617 618 619 620 621 622 623 624 625 626 627 628 629 630 631 632 633 634 635 636 637 638 639 640 641 642 643 644 645 646 647 648 649 650 651 652 653 654 655 656 657 658 659 660 661 662 663 664 665 666 667 668 669 670 671 672 673 674 675 676 677 678 679 680 681 682 683 684 685 686 687 688 689 690 691 692 693 694 695 696 697 698 699 700 701 702 703 704 705 706 707 708 709 710 711 712 713 714 715 716 717 718 719 720 721 722 723 724 725 726 727 728 729 730 731 732 733 734 735 736 737 738 739 740 741 742 743 744 745 746 747 748 749 750 751 752 753 754 755 756 757 758 759 760 761 762 763 764 765 766 767 768 769 770 771 772 773 774 775 776 777 778 779 780 781 782 783 784 785 786 787 788 789 790 791 792 793 794 795 796 797 798 799 800 801 802 803 804 805 806 807 808 809 810 811 812 813 814 815 816 817 818 819 820 821 822 823 824 825 826 827 828 829 830 831 832 833 834 835 836 837 838 839 840 841 842 843 844 845 846 847 848 849 850 851 852 853 854 855 856 857 858 859 860 861 862 863 864 865 866 867 868 869 870 871 872 873 874 875 876 877 878 879 880 881 882 883 884 885 886 887 888 889 890 891 892 893 894 895 896 897 898 899 900 901 902 903 904 905 906 907 908 909 910 911 912 913 914 915 916 917 918 919 920 921 922 923 924 925 926 927 928 929 930 931 932 933 934 935 936 937 938 939 940 941 942 943 944 945 946 947 948 949 950 951 952 953 954 955 956 957 958 959 960 961 962 963 964 965 966 967 968 969 970 971 972 973 974 975 976 977 978 979 980 981 982 983 984 985 986 987 988 989 990 991 992 993 994 995 996 997 998 999 1000 1001 1002 1003 1004 1005 1006 1007 1008 1009 1010 1011 1012 1013 1014 1015 1016 1017 1018 1019 1020 1021 1022 1023 1024 1025 1026 1027 1028 1029 1030 1031 1032 1033 1034 1035 1036 1037 1038 1039 1040 1041 1042 1043 1044 1045 1046 1047 1048 1049 1050 1051 1052 1053 1054 1055 1056 1057 1058 1059 1060 1061 1062 1063 1064 1065 1066 1067 1068 1069 1070 1071 1072 1073 1074 1075 1076 1077 1078 1079 1080 1081 1082 1083 1084 1085 1086 1087 1088 1089 1090 1091 1092 1093 1094 1095 1096 1097 1098 1099 1100 1101 1102 1103 1104 1105 1106 1107 1108 1109 1110 1111 1112 1113 1114 1115 1116 1117 1118 1119 1120 1121 1122 1123 1124 1125 1126 1127 1128 1129 1130 1131 1132 1133 1134 1135 1136 1137 1138 1139 1140 1141 1142 1143 1144 1145 1146 1147 1148 1149 1150 1151 1152 1153 1154 1155 1156 1157 1158 1159 1160 1161 1162 1163 1164 1165 1166 1167 1168 1169 1170 1171 1172 1173 1174 1175 1176 1177 1178 1179 1180 1181 1182 1183 1184 1185 1186 1187 1188 1189 1190 1191 1192 1193 1194 1195 1196 1197 1198 1199 1200 1201 1202 1203 1204 1205 1206 1207 1208 1209 1210 1211 1212 1213 1214 1215 1216 1217 1218 1219 1220 1221 1222 1223 1224 1225 1226 1227 1228 1229 1230 1231 1232 1233 1234 1235 1236 1237 1238 1239 1240 1241 1242 1243 1244 1245 1246 1247 1248 1249 1250 1251 1252 1253 1254 1255 1256 1257 1258 1259 1260 1261 1262 1263 1264 1265 1266 1267 1268 1269 1270 1271 1272 1273 1274 1275 1276 1277 1278 1279 1280 1281 1282 1283 1284 1285 1286 1287 1288 1289 1290 1291 1292 1293 1294 1295 1296 1297 1298 1299 1300 1301 1302 1303 1304 1305 1306 1307 1308 1309 1310 1311 1312 1313 1314 1315 1316 1317 1318 1319 1320 1321 1322 1323 1324 1325 1326 1327 1328 1329 1330 1331 1332 1333 1334 1335 1336 1337 1338 1339 1340 1341 1342 1343 1344 1345 1346 1347 1348 1349 1350 1351 1352 1353 1354 1355 1356 1357 1358 1359 1360 1361 1362 1363 1364 1365 1366 1367 1368 1369 1370 1371 1372 1373 1374 1375 1376 1377 1378 1379 1380 1381 1382 1383 1384 1385 1386 1387 1388 1389 1390 1391 1392 1393 1394 1395 1396 1397 1398 1399 1400 1401 1402 1403 1404 1405 1406 1407 1408 1409 1410 1411 1412 1413 1414 1415 1416 1417 1418 1419 1420 1421 1422 1423 1424 1425 1426 1427 1428 1429 1430 1431 1432 1433 1434 1435 1436 1437 1438 1439 1440 1441 1442 1443 1444 1445 1446 1447 1448 1449 1450 1451 1452 1453 1454 1455 1456 1457 1458 1459 1460 1461 1462 1463 1464 1465 1466 1467 1468 1469 1470 1471 1472 1473 1474 1475 1476 1477 1478 1479 1480 1481 1482 1483 1484 1485 1486 1487 1488 1489 1490 1491 1492 1493 1494 1495 1496 1497 1498 1499 1500 1501 1502 1503 1504 1505 1506 1507 1508 1509 1510 1511 1512 1513 1514 1515 1516 1517 1518 1519 1520 1521 1522 1523 1524 1525 1526 1527 1528 1529 1530 1531 1532 1533 1534 1535 1536 1537 1538 1539 1540 1541 1542 1543 1544 1545 1546 1547 1548 1549 1550 1551 1552 1553 1554 1555 1556 1557 1558 1559 1560 1561 1562 1563 1564 1565 1566 1567 1568 1569 1570 1571 1572 1573 1574 1575 1576 1577 1578 1579 1580 1581 1582 1583 1584 1585 1586 1587 1588 1589 1590 1591 1592 1593 1594 1595 1596 1597 1598 1599 1600 1601 1602 1603 1604 1605 1606 1607 1608 1609 1610 1611 1612 1613 1614 1615 1616 1617 1618 1619 1620 1621 1622 1623 1624 1625 1626 1627 1628 1629 1630 1631 1632 1633 1634 1635 1636 1637 1638 1639 1640 1641 1642 1643 1644 1645 1646 1647 1648 1649 1650 1651 1652 1653 1654 1655 1656 1657 1658 1659 1660 1661 1662 1663 1664 1665 1666 1667 1668 1669 1670 1671 1672 1673 1674 1675 1676 1677 1678 1679 1680 1681 1682 1683 1684 1685 1686 1687 1688 1689 1690 1691 1692 1693 1694 1695 1696 1697 1698 1699 1700 1701 1702 1703 1704 1705 1706 1707 1708 1709 1710 1711 1712 1713 1714 1715 1716 1717 1718 1719 1720 1721 1722 1723 1724 1725 1726 1727 1728 1729 1730 1731 1732 1733 1734 1735 1736 1737 1738 1739 1740 1741 1742 1743 1744 1745 1746 1747 1748 1749 1750 1751 1752 1753 1754 1755 1756 1757 1758 1759 1760 1761 1762 1763 1764 1765 1766 1767 1768 1769 1770 1771 1772 1773 1774 1775 1776 1777 1778 1779 1780 1781 1782 1783 1784 1785 1786 1787 1788 1789 1790 1791 1792 1793 1794 1795 1796 1797 1798 1799 1800 1801 1802 1803 1804 1805 1806 1807 1808 1809 1810 1811 1812 1813 1814 1815 1816 1817 1818 1819 1820 1821 1822 1823 1824 1825 1826 1827 1828 1829 1830 1831 1832 1833 1834 1835 1836 1837 1838 1839 1840 1841 1842 1843 1844 1845 1846 1847 1848 1849 1850 1851 1852 1853 1854 1855 1856 1857 1858 1859 1860 1861 1862 1863 1864 1865 1866 1867 1868 1869 1870 1871 1872 1873 1874 1875 1876 1877 1878 1879 1880 1881 1882 1883 1884 1885 1886 1887 1888 1889 1890 1891 1892 1893 1894 1895 1896 1897 1898 1899 1900 1901 1902 1903 1904 1905 1906 1907 1908 1909 1910 1911 1912 1913 1914 1915 1916 1917 1918 1919 1920 1921 1922 1923 1924 1925 1926 1927 1928 1929 1930 1931 1932 1933 1934 1935 1936 1937 1938 1939 1940 1941 1942 1943 1944 1945 1946 1947 1948 1949 1950 1951 1952 1953 1954 1955 1956 1957 1958 1959 1960 1961 1962 1963 1964 1965 1966 1967 1968 1969 1970 1971 |
\chapter{Set theory}
\label{cha:set-math}
\index{set|(}%
Our conception of sets as types with particularly simple homotopical character, cf.\
\cref{sec:basics-sets}, is quite different from the sets of Zermelo--Fraenkel\index{set theory!Zermelo--Fraenkel} set theory, which form a
cumulative hierarchy with an intricate nested membership structure.
For many mathematical purposes, the homotopy-the\-o\-ret\-ic sets are just as good as
the Zermelo--Fraenkel ones, but there are important differences.
We begin this chapter in \cref{sec:piw-pretopos} by showing that the category $\uset$ has (most of) the usual properties of the category of sets.
\index{mathematics!constructive}%
\index{mathematics!predicative}%
In constructive, predicative, univalent foundations, it is a ``$\Pi\mathsf{W}$-pretopos''; whereas if we assume propositional resizing
\index{propositional!resizing}%
(\cref{subsec:prop-subsets}) it is an elementary topos,\index{topos} and if we assume \LEM{} and \choice{} then it is a model of Lawvere's \emph{Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets}\index{Lawvere}.
\index{Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets}%
This is sufficient to ensure that the sets in homotopy type theory behave like sets as used by most mathematicians outside of set theory.
In the rest of the chapter, we investigate some subjects that traditionally belong to ``set theory''.
In \cref{sec:cardinals,sec:ordinals,sec:wellorderings} we study cardinal and ordinal numbers.
These are traditionally defined in set theory using the global membership relation, but we will see that the univalence axiom enables an equally convenient, more ``structural'' approach.
Finally, in \cref{sec:cumulative-hierarchy} we consider the possibility of constructing \emph{inside} of homotopy type theory a cumulative hierarchy of sets, equipped with a binary membership relation akin to that of Zermelo--Fraenkel set theory.
This combines higher inductive types with ideas from the field of algebraic set theory.
\index{algebraic set theory}%
\index{set theory!algebraic}%
In this chapter we will often use the traditional logical notation described in \cref{subsec:prop-trunc}.
In addition to the basic theory of \cref{cha:basics,cha:logic}, we use higher inductive types for colimits and quotients as in \cref{sec:colimits,sec:set-quotients}, as well as some of the theory of truncation from \cref{cha:hlevels}, particularly the factorization system of \cref{sec:image-factorization} in the case $n=-1$.
In \cref{sec:ordinals} we use an inductive family (\cref{sec:generalizations}) to describe well-foundedness, and in \cref{sec:cumulative-hierarchy} we use a more complicated higher inductive type to present the cumulative hierarchy.
%\section{\texorpdfstring{$\set$}{Set} is a \texorpdfstring{$\Pi$}{Π}W-pretopos}
\section{The category of sets}
\label{sec:piw-pretopos}
Recall that in \cref{cha:category-theory} we defined the category \uset to consist of all $0$-types (in some universe \UU) and maps between them, and observed that it is a category (not just a precategory).
We consider successively the levels of structure which \uset possesses.
\subsection{Limits and colimits}
\label{subsec:limits-sets}
\index{limit!of sets}%
\index{colimit!of sets}%
Since sets are closed under products, the universal property of products in \cref{thm:prod-ump} shows immediately that \uset has finite products.
In fact, infinite products follow just as easily from the equivalence
\[ \Parens{X\to \prd{a:A} B(a)} \eqvsym \Parens{\prd{a:A} (X\to B(a))}.\]
And we saw in \cref{ex:pullback}\index{pullback} that the pullback of $f:A\to C$ and $g:B\to C$ can be defined as $\sm{a:A}{b:B} f(a)=g(b)$; this is a set if $A,B,C$ are and inherits the correct universal property.
Thus, \uset is a \emph{complete} category in the obvious sense.
\index{category!complete}%
\index{complete!category}%
Since sets are closed under $+$ and contain \emptyt, \uset has finite coproducts.
Similarly, since $\sm{a:A}B(a)$ is a set whenever $A$ and each $B(a)$ are, it yields a coproduct of the family $B$ in \uset.
Finally, we showed in \cref{sec:pushouts} that pushouts exist in $n$-types, which includes \uset in particular.
Thus, \uset is also \emph{cocomplete}.
\index{category!cocomplete}%
\index{cocomplete category}%
\subsection{Images}
\label{sec:image}
%We will show that $\uset$ is a $\Pi$W-pretopos.
Next, we show that $\uset$ is a \define{regular category}, i.e.:
\indexdef{category!regular}%
\indexdef{regular!category}%
%
\begin{enumerate}
\item $\uset$ is finitely complete.\label{item:reg1}
\item The kernel pair $\proj1,\proj2: (\sm{x,y:A} f(x)= f(y)) \to A$ of any
function $f : A \to B$ has a coequalizer.\label{item:reg2}
\indexdef{kernel!pair}
\item Pullbacks of regular epimorphisms are again regular epimorphisms.\label{item:reg3}
\end{enumerate}
%
Recall that a \define{regular epimorphism}
\indexdef{epimorphism!regular}%
\indexdef{regular!epimorphism}%
is a morphism that is the coequalizer of \emph{some} pair of maps.
Thus in~\ref{item:reg3} the pullback of a coequalizer is required to again be a coequalizer, but not necessarily of the pulled-back pair.
\index{set-coequalizer}%
\index{image}
The obvious candidate for the coequalizer of the kernel pair of $f:A\to B$ is the \emph{image} of $f$, as defined in \cref{sec:image-factorization}.
Recall that we defined $\im(f)\defeq \sm{b:B} \brck{\hfib f b}$, with functions
$\tilde{f}:A\to\im(f)$ and $i_f:\im(f)\to B$ defined by
\begin{align*}
\tilde{f} & \defeq \lam{a} \Pairr{f(a),\,\bproj{\pairr{a,\refl{f(a)}}}}\\
i_f & \defeq \proj1
\end{align*}
fitting into a diagram:
\begin{equation*}
\xymatrix{
**[l]{\sm{x,y:A} f(x)= f(y)}
\ar@<0.25em>[r]^{\proj1}
\ar@<-0.25em>[r]_{\proj2}
&
{A}
\ar[r]^(0.4){\tilde{f}}
\ar[rd]_{f}
&
{\im(f)}
\ar@{..>}[d]^{i_f}
\\ & &
B
}
\end{equation*}
Recall that a function $f:A\to B$ is called \emph{surjective} if
\index{function!surjective}%
\narrowequation{\fall{b:B}\brck{\hfib f b},}
or equivalently $\fall{b:B} \exis{a:A} f(a)=b$.
We have also said that a function $f:A\to B$ between sets is called \emph{injective} if
\index{function!injective}%
$\fall{a,a':A} (f(a) = f(a')) \Rightarrow (a=a')$, or equivalently if each of its fibers is a mere proposition.
Since these are the $(-1)$-connected and $(-1)$-truncated maps in the sense of \cref{cha:hlevels}, the general theory there implies that $\tilde f$ above is surjective and $i_f$ is injective, and that this factorization is stable under pullback.
We now identify surjectivity and injectivity with the appropriate cat\-e\-go\-ry-theoretic notions.
First we observe that categorical monomorphisms and epimorphisms have a slightly stronger equivalent formulation.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:mono}
For a morphism $f:\hom_A(a,b)$ in a category $A$, the following are equivalent.
\begin{enumerate}
\item $f$ is a \define{monomorphism}:
\indexdef{monomorphism}%
for all $x:A$ and ${g,h:\hom_A(x,a)}$, if $f\circ g = f\circ h$ then $g=h$.\label{item:mono1}
\item (If $A$ has pullbacks) the diagonal map $a\to a\times_b a$ is an isomorphism.\label{item:mono4}
\item For all $x:A$ and $k:\hom_A(x,b)$, the type $\sm{h:\hom_A(x,a)} (k = f\circ h)$ is a mere proposition.\label{item:mono2}
\item For all $x:A$ and ${g:\hom_A(x,a)}$, the type $\sm{h:\hom_A(x,a)} (f\circ g = f\circ h)$ is contractible.\label{item:mono3}
\end{enumerate}
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
The equivalence of conditions~\ref{item:mono1} and~\ref{item:mono4} is standard category theory.
Now consider the function $(f\circ \blank ):\hom_A(x,a) \to \hom_A(x,b)$ between sets.
Condition~\ref{item:mono1} says that it is injective, while~\ref{item:mono2} says that its fibers are mere propositions; hence they are equivalent.
And~\ref{item:mono2} implies~\ref{item:mono3} by taking $k\defeq f\circ g$ and recalling that an inhabited mere proposition is contractible.
Finally,~\ref{item:mono3} implies~\ref{item:mono1} since if $p:f\circ g= f\circ h$, then $(g,\refl{})$ and $(h,p)$ both inhabit the type in~\ref{item:mono3}, hence are equal and so $g=h$.
\end{proof}
\begin{lem}\label{thm:inj-mono}
A function $f:A\to B$ between sets is injective if and only if it is a monomorphism\index{monomorphism} in \uset.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Left to the reader.
\end{proof}
Of course, an \define{epimorphism}
\indexdef{epimorphism}%
\indexsee{epi}{epimorphism}%
is a monomorphism in the opposite category.
We now show that in \uset, the epimorphisms are precisely the surjections, and also precisely the coequalizers (regular epimorphisms).
The coequalizer of a pair of maps $f,g:A\to B$ in $\uset$ is defined as the 0-truncation of a general (homotopy) coequalizer.
For clarity, we may call this the \define{set-coequalizer}.
\indexdef{set-coequalizer}%
\indexsee{coequalizer!of sets}{set-coequalizer}%
It is convenient to express its universal property as follows.
\begin{lem}
\index{universal!property!of set-coequalizer}%
Let $f,g:A\to B$ be functions between sets $A$ and $B$. The
{set-co}equalizer $c_{f,g}:B\to Q$ has the property that, for any set $C$ and any $h:B\to C$ with $h\circ f = h\circ g$, the type
\begin{equation*}
\sm{k:Q\to C} (k\circ c_{f,g} = h)
\end{equation*}
is contractible.
\end{lem}
\begin{lem}\label{epis-surj}
For any function $f:A\to B$ between sets, the following are equivalent:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $f$ is an epimorphism.
\item Consider the pushout diagram
\begin{equation*}
\xymatrix{
{A}
\ar[r]^{f}
\ar[d]
&
{B}
\ar[d]^{\iota}
\\
{\unit}
\ar[r]_{t}
&
{C_f}
}
\end{equation*}
in $\uset$ defining the mapping cone\index{cone!of a function}. Then the type $C_f$ is contractible.
\item $f$ is surjective.
\end{enumerate}
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Let $f:A\to B$ be a function between sets, and suppose it to be an epimorphism; we show $C_f$ is contractible.
The constructor $\unit\to C_f$ of $C_f$ gives us an element $t:C_f$.
We have to show that
\begin{equation*}
\prd{x:C_f} x= t.
\end{equation*}
Note that $x= t$ is a mere proposition, hence we can use induction on $C_f$.
Of course when $x$ is $t$ we have $\refl{t}:t=t$, so it suffices to find
\begin{align*}
I_0 & : \prd{b:B} \iota(b)= t\\
I_1 & : \prd{a:A} \opp{\alpha_1(a)} \ct I_0(f(a))=\refl{t}
\end{align*}
where $\iota:B\to C_f$ and $\alpha_1:\prd{a:A} \iota(f(a))= t$ are the other constructors
of $C_f$. Note that $\alpha_1$ is a homotopy from $\iota\circ f$ to
$\mathsf{const}_t\circ f$, so we find the elements
\begin{equation*}
\pairr{\iota,\refl{\iota\circ f}},\pairr{\mathsf{const}_t,\alpha_1}:
\sm{h:B\to C_f} \iota\circ f \htpy h\circ f.
\end{equation*}
By the dual of \cref{thm:mono}\ref{item:mono3} (and function extensionality), there is a path
\begin{equation*}
\gamma:\pairr{\iota,\refl{\iota\circ f}}=\pairr{\mathsf{const}_t,\alpha_1}.
\end{equation*}
Hence, we may define $I_0(b)\defeq \happly(\projpath1(\gamma),b):\iota(b)=t$.
We also have
\[\projpath2(\gamma) : \trans{\projpath1(\gamma)}{\refl{\iota\circ f}} = \alpha_1. \]
This transport involves precomposition with $f$, which commutes with $\happly$.
Thus, from transport in path types we obtain $I_0(f(a)) = \alpha_1(a)$ for any $a:A$, which gives us $I_1$.
Now suppose $C_f$ is contractible; we show $f$ is surjective.
We first construct a type family $P:C_f\to\prop$ by recursion on $C_f$, which is valid since \prop is a set.
On the point constructors, we define
\begin{align*}
P(t) & \defeq \unit\\
P(\iota(b)) & \defeq \brck{\hfiber{f}b}.
\end{align*}
To complete the construction of $P$, it remains to give a path
\narrowequation{\brck{\hfiber{f}{f(a)}} =_\prop \unit}
for all $a:A$.
However, $\brck{\hfiber{f}{f(a)}}$ is inhabited by $(f(a),\refl{f(a)})$.
Since it is a mere proposition, this means it is contractible --- and thus equivalent, hence equal, to \unit.
This completes the definition of $P$.
Now, since $C_f$ is assumed to be contractible, it follows that $P(x)$ is equivalent to $P(t)$ for any $x:C_f$.
In particular, $P(\iota(b))\jdeq \brck{\hfiber{f}b}$ is equivalent to $P(t)\jdeq \unit$ for each $b:B$, and hence contractible.
Thus, $f$ is surjective.
Finally, suppose $f:A\to B$ to be surjective, and consider a set $C$ and two functions
$g,h:B\to C$ with the property that $g\circ f = h\circ f$. Since $f$
is assumed to be surjective, for all $b:B$ the type $\brck{\hfib f b}$ is contractible.
Thus we have the following equivalences:
\begin{align*}
\prd{b:B} (g(b)= h(b))
& \eqvsym \prd{b:B} \Parens{\brck{\hfib f b} \to (g(b)= h(b))}\\
& \eqvsym \prd{b:B} \Parens{\hfib f b \to (g(b)= h(b))}\\
& \eqvsym \prd{b:B}{a:A}{p:f(a)= b} g(b)= h(b)\\
& \eqvsym \prd{a:A} g(f(a))= h(f(a))
\end{align*}
using on the second line the fact that $g(b)=h(b)$ is a mere proposition, since $C$ is a set.
But by assumption, there is an element of the latter type.
\end{proof}
% \begin{rem}
% The above theorem is not true when we replace $\set$ by $\type$
% (replacing it also in the definition of $\mathsf{epi}$ and $\mathsf{epi}'$).
% However, we do
% get the implications $\textit{ii.}\Rightarrow\textit{iii.}\Rightarrow
% \textit{iv.}$
% \end{rem}
\begin{thm}\label{thm:set_regular}\label{lem:images_are_coequalizers}
The category $\uset$ is regular. Moreover, surjective functions between sets are regular epimorphisms.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
It is a standard lemma in category theory that a category is regular as soon as it admits finite limits and a pullback-stable orthogonal
factorization system\index{orthogonal factorization system} $(\mathcal{E},\mathcal{M})$ with $\mathcal{M}$ the monomorphisms, in which case $\mathcal{E}$ consists automatically of
the regular epimorphisms.
(See e.g.~\cite[A1.3.4]{elephant}.)
The existence of the factorization system was proved in \cref{thm:orth-fact}.
\end{proof}
\begin{lem}\label{lem:pb_of_coeq_is_coeq}
Pullbacks of regular epis in \uset are regular epis.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We showed in \cref{thm:stable-images} that pullbacks of $n$-connected functions are $n$-connected.
By \cref{lem:images_are_coequalizers}, it suffices to apply this when $n=-1$.
\end{proof}
\indexdef{image!of a subset}
One of the consequences of \uset being a regular category is that we have an ``image'' operation on subsets.
That is, given $f:A\to B$, any subset $P:\power A$ (i.e.\ a predicate $P:A\to \prop$) has an \define{image} which is a subset of $B$.
This can be defined directly as $\setof{ y:B | \exis{x:A} f(x)=y \land P(x)}$, or indirectly as the image (in the previous sense) of the composite function
\[ \setof{ x:A | P(x) } \to A \xrightarrow{f} B.\]
\symlabel{subset-image}
We will also sometimes use the common notation $\setof{f(x) | P(x)}$ for the image of $P$.
\subsection{Quotients}\label{subsec:quotients}
\index{set-quotient|(}%
Now that we know that $\uset$ is regular, to show that $\uset$ is exact, we need to show that every
equivalence relation is effective.
\index{effective!equivalence relation|(}%
\index{relation!effective equivalence|(}%
In other words, given an equivalence
relation $R:A\to A\to\prop$, there is a coequalizer $c_R$ of the pair
$\proj1,\proj2:\sm{x,y:A} R(x,y)\to A$ and, moreover, the $\proj1$ and $\proj2$
form the kernel\index{kernel!pair} pair of $c_R$.
We have already seen, in \cref{sec:set-quotients}, two general ways to construct the quotient of a set by an equivalence relation $R:A\to A\to\prop$.
The first can be described as the set-coequalizer of the two projections
\[\proj1,\proj2:\Parens{\sm{x,y:A} R(x,y)} \to A.\]
The important property of such a quotient is the following.
\begin{defn}
A relation $R:A\to A\to\prop$ is said to be \define{effective}
\indexdef{effective!relation}
\indexdef{effective!equivalence relation}%
\indexdef{relation!effective equivalence}%
if the square
\begin{equation*}
\xymatrix{
{\sm{x,y:A} R (x,y)}
\ar[r]^(0.7){\proj1}
\ar[d]_{\proj2}
&
{A}
\ar[d]^{c_R}
\\
{A}
\ar[r]_{c_R}
&
{A/R}
}
\end{equation*}
is a pullback.
\end{defn}
Since the standard pullback of $c_R$ and itself is $\sm{x,y:A} (c_R(x)=c_R(y))$, by \cref{thm:total-fiber-equiv} this is equivalent to asking that the canonical transformation $\prd{x,y:A} R(x,y) \to (c_R(x)=c_R(y))$ be a fiberwise equivalence.
\begin{lem}\label{lem:sets_exact}
Suppose $\pairr{A,R}$ is an equivalence relation. Then there is an equivalence
\begin{equation*}
(c_R(x)= c_R(y))\eqvsym R(x,y)
\end{equation*}
for any $x,y:A$. In other words, equivalence relations are effective.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We begin by extending $R$ to a relation $\widetilde{R}:A/R\to A/R\to\prop$, which we will then show is equivalent
to the identity type on $A/R$. We define $\widetilde{R}$ by double induction on
$A/R$ (note that $\prop$ is a set by univalence for mere propositions). We
define $\widetilde{R}(c_R(x),c_R(y)) \defeq R(x,y)$. For $r:R(x,x')$ and $s:R(y,y')$,
the transitivity and symmetry
of $R$ gives an equivalence from $R(x,y)$ to $R(x',y')$. This completes the
definition of $\widetilde{R}$.
It remains to show that $\widetilde{R}(w,w')\eqvsym (w= w')$ for every $w,w':A/R$.
The direction $(w=w')\to \widetilde{R}(w,w')$ follows by transport once we show that $\widetilde{R}$ is reflexive, which is an easy induction.
The other direction $\widetilde{R}(w,w')\to (w= w')$ is a mere proposition, so since $c_R:A\to A/R$ is surjective, it suffices to assume that $w$ and $w'$ are of the form $c_R(x)$ and $c_R(y)$.
But in this case, we have the canonical map $\widetilde{R}(c_R(x),c_R(y)) \defeq R(x,y) \to (c_R(x)=c_R(y))$.
(Note again the appearance of the encode-decode method.\index{encode-decode method})
\end{proof}
The second construction of quotients is as the set of equivalence classes of $R$ (a subset
of its power set\index{power set}):
\[ A\sslash R \defeq \setof{ P:A\to\prop | P \text{ is an equivalence class of } R}. \]
This requires propositional resizing\index{propositional resizing}\index{impredicative!quotient}\index{resizing} in order to remain in the same universe as $A$ and $R$.
Note that if we regard $R$ as a function from $A$ to $A\to \prop$, then $A\sslash R$ is equivalent to $\im(R)$, as constructed in \cref{sec:image}.
Now in \cref{lem:images_are_coequalizers} we have shown that images are
coequalizers. In particular, we immediately get the coequalizer diagram
\begin{equation*}
\xymatrix{
**[l]{\sm{x,y:A} R (x)= R (y)}
\ar@<0.25em>[r]^{\proj1}
\ar@<-0.25em>[r]_{\proj2}
&
{A}
\ar[r]
&
{A \sslash R.}
}
\end{equation*}
We can use this to give an alternative proof that any equivalence relation is effective and that the two definitions of quotients agree.
\begin{thm}\label{prop:kernels_are_effective}
For any function $f:A\to B$ between any two sets,
the relation $\ker(f):A\to A\to\prop$ given by
$\ker(f,x,y)\defeq (f(x)= f(y))$ is effective.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
We will use that $\im(f)$ is the coequalizer of $\proj1,\proj2:
(\sm{x,y:A} f(x)= f(y))\to A$.
%we get this equivalence from~\cref{prop:images_are_coequalizers}
Note that the kernel pair of the function
\[c_f\defeq\lam{a} \Parens{f(a),\brck{\pairr{a,\refl{f(a)}}}}
: A \to \im(f)
\]
consists of the two projections
\begin{equation*}
\proj1,\proj2:\Parens{\sm{x,y:A} c_f(x)= c_f(y)}\to A.
\end{equation*}
For any $x,y:A$, we have equivalences
\begin{align*}
(c_f(x)= c_f(y))
& \eqvsym \Parens{\sm{p:f(x)= f(y)} \trans{p}{\brck{\pairr{x,\refl{f(x)}}}} =\brck{\pairr{y,\refl{f(x)}}}}\\
& \eqvsym (f(x)= f(y)),
\end{align*}
where the last equivalence holds because
$\brck{\hfiber{f}b}$ is a mere proposition for any $b:B$.
Therefore, we get that
\begin{equation*}
\Parens{\sm{x,y:A} c_f(x)= c_f(y)}\eqvsym \Parens{\sm{x,y:A} f(x)= f(y)}
\end{equation*}
and hence we may conclude that $\ker f$ is an effective relation
for any function $f$.
\end{proof}
\begin{thm}
Equivalence relations are effective and there is an equivalence $A/R \eqvsym A\sslash R $.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
We need to analyze the coequalizer diagram
\begin{equation*}
\xymatrix{
**[l]{\sm{x,y:A} R (x)= R (y)}
\ar@<0.25em>[r]^{\proj1}
\ar@<-0.25em>[r]_{\proj2}
&
{A}
\ar[r]
&
{A \sslash R}
}
\end{equation*}
By the univalence axiom, the type $R(x) = R(y)$ is equivalent to the type of homotopies from $R(x)$ to $R(y)$, which is
equivalent to
\narrowequation{\prd{z:A} R (x,z)\eqvsym R (y,z).}
Since $R$ is an equivalence relation, the latter space is equivalent to $R(x,y)$. To
summarize, we get that $(R(x) = R(y)) \eqvsym R(x,y)$, so $R $ is effective since it is equivalent to an effective relation. Also,
the diagram
\begin{equation*}
\xymatrix{
**[l]{\sm{x,y:A} R(x, y)}
\ar@<0.25em>[r]^{\proj1}
\ar@<-0.25em>[r]_{\proj2}
&
{A}
\ar[r]
&
{A \sslash R.}
}
\end{equation*}
is a coequalizer diagram. Since coequalizers are unique up to equivalence, it follows that $A/R \eqvsym A\sslash R $.
\end{proof}
We finish this section by mentioning a possible third construction of the quotient of a set $A$ by an equivalence relation $R$.
Consider the precategory with objects $A$ and hom-sets $R$; the type of objects of the Rezk completion
\index{completion!Rezk}%
(see \cref{sec:rezk}) of this precategory will then be the
quotient. The reader is invited to check the details.
\index{effective!equivalence relation|)}%
\index{relation!effective equivalence|)}%
\index{set-quotient|)}%
\subsection{\texorpdfstring{$\uset$}{Set} is a \texorpdfstring{$\Pi\mathsf{W}$}{ΠW}-pretopos}
\label{subsec:piw}
\index{structural!set theory|(}%
The notion of a \emph{$\Pi\mathsf{W}$-pretopos}
\index{PiW-pretopos@$\Pi\mathsf{W}$-pretopos}%
\indexsee{pretopos}{$\Pi\mathsf{W}$-pretopos}
--- that is, a locally cartesian closed category
\index{locally cartesian closed category}%
\index{category!locally cartesian closed}%
with disjoint finite coproducts, effective equivalence relations, and initial algebras for polynomial endofunctors --- is intended as a ``predicative''
\index{mathematics!predicative}%
notion of topos, i.e.\ a category of ``predicative sets'', which can serve the purpose for constructive mathematics
\index{mathematics!constructive}%
that the usual category of sets does for classical
\index{mathematics!classical}%
mathematics.
Typically, in constructive type theory, one resorts to an external construction of ``setoids'' --- an exact completion --- to obtain a category with such closure properties.
\index{setoid}\index{completion!exact}%
In particular, the well-behaved quotients are required for many constructions in mathematics that usually involve (non-constructive) power sets. It is noteworthy that univalent foundations provides these constructions \emph{internally} (via higher inductive types), without requiring such external constructions. This represents a powerful advantage of our approach, as we shall see in subsequent examples.
\begin{thm}
\index{PiW-pretopos@$\Pi\mathsf{W}$-pretopos}
The category $\uset$ is a $\Pi\mathsf{W}$-pretopos.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
We have an initial object
\index{initial!set}%
$\emptyt$ and finite, disjoint sums $A+B$. These are stable under pullback, simply because pullback has a right adjoint\index{adjoint!functor}. Indeed, $\uset$ is locally cartesian closed, since for any map $f:A\to B$ between sets, the ``fibrant replacement'' \index{fibrant replacement} $\sm{a:A}f(a)=b$ is equivalent to $A$ (over $B$), and we have dependent function types for the replacement.
We've just shown that $\uset$ is regular (\cref{thm:set_regular}) and that quotients are effective (\cref{lem:sets_exact}). We thus have a locally cartesian closed pretopos. Finally, since the $n$-types are closed under the formation of $W$-types by \cref{ex:ntypes-closed-under-wtypes}, and by \cref{thm:w-hinit} $W$-types are initial algebras for polynomial endofunctors, we see that $\uset$ is a $\Pi\mathsf{W}$-pretopos.
\end{proof}
\index{topos|(}
One naturally wonders what, if anything, prevents $\uset$ from being an (elementary) topos?
In addition to the structure already mentioned, a topos has a
\emph{subobject classifier}:
\indexdef{subobject classifier}%
\index{classifier!subobject}%
\index{power set}%
a pointed object classifying (equivalence classes of) monomorphisms\index{monomorphism}. (In fact, in the presence of a subobject
classifier, things become somewhat simpler: one merely needs cartesian closure in order to get the colimits.)
In homotopy type theory, univalence implies that the type $\prop \defeq \sm{X:\UU}\isprop(X)$ does classify monomorphisms (by an argument similar to \cref{sec:object-classification}), but in general it is as large as the ambient universe $\UU$.
Thus, it is a ``set'' in the sense of being a $0$-type, but it is not ``small'' in the sense of being an object of $\UU$, hence not an object of the category \uset.
However, if we assume an appropriate form of propositional resizing (see \cref{subsec:prop-subsets}), then we can find a small version of $\prop$, so that \uset becomes an elementary topos.
\begin{thm}\label{thm:settopos}
\index{propositional!resizing}%
If there is a type $\Omega:\UU$ of all mere propositions, then the category $\uset_\UU$ is an elementary topos.
\end{thm}
\index{topos|)}
A sufficient condition for this is the law of excluded middle, in the ``mere-propositional'' form that we have called \LEM{}; for then we have $\prop = \bool$, which \emph{is} small, and which then also classifies all mere propositions.
Moreover, in topos theory a well-known sufficient condition for \LEM{} is the axiom of choice, which is of course often assumed as an axiom in classical\index{mathematics!classical} set theory.
In the next section, we briefly investigate the relation between these conditions in our setting.
\index{structural!set theory|)}%
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
\subsection{The axiom of choice implies excluded middle}
\label{subsec:emacinsets}
% In this section we prove a classic result that the axiom of choice implies excluded
% middle.
We begin with the following lemma.
\begin{lem}\label{prop:trunc_of_prop_is_set}
If $A$ is a mere proposition then its suspension $\susp(A)$ is a set,
and $A$ is equivalent to $\id[\susp(A)]{\north}{\south}$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
To show that $\susp(A)$ is a set, we define a
family $P:\susp(A)\to\susp(A)\to\type$ with the
property that $P(x,y)$ is a mere proposition for each $x,y:\susp(A)$,
and which is equivalent to its identity type $\idtypevar{\susp(A)}$.
%
We make the following definitions:
\begin{align*}
P(\north,\north) & \defeq \unit &
P(\south,\north) & \defeq A\\
P(\north,\south) & \defeq A &
P(\south,\south) & \defeq \unit.
\end{align*}
We have to check that the definition preserves paths.
Given any $a : A$, there is a meridian $\merid(a) : \north = \south$,
so we should also have
%
\begin{equation*}
P(\north, \north) = P(\north, \south) = P(\south, \north) = P(\south, \south).
\end{equation*}
%
But since $A$ is inhabited by $a$, it is equivalent to $\unit$, so we have
%
\begin{equation*}
P(\north, \north) \eqvsym P(\north, \south) \eqvsym P(\south, \north) \eqvsym P(\south, \south).
\end{equation*}
%
The univalence axiom turns these into the desired equalities. Also, $P(x,y)$ is a mere
proposition for all $x, y : \susp(A)$, which is proved by induction on $x$ and $y$, and
using the fact that being a mere proposition is a mere proposition.
Note that $P$ is a reflexive relation.
Therefore we may apply \cref{thm:h-set-refrel-in-paths-sets}, so it suffices to
construct $\tau : \prd{x,y:\susp(A)}P(x,y)\to(x=y)$. We do this by a double induction.
When $x$ is $\north$, we define $\tau(\north)$ by
%
\begin{equation*}
\tau(\north,\north,u) \defeq \refl{\north}
\qquad\text{and}\qquad
\tau(\north,\south,a) \defeq \merid(a).
\end{equation*}
%
If $A$ is inhabited by $a$ then $\merid(a) : \north = \south$ so we also need
\narrowequation{
\trans{\merid(a)}{\tau(\north, \north)} = \tau(\north, \south).
}
This we get by function extensionality using the fact that, for all $x : A$,
%
\begin{multline*}
\trans{\merid(a)}{\tau(\north,\north,x)} =
\tau(\north,\north,x) \ct \opp{\merid(a)} \jdeq \\
\refl{\north} \ct \merid(a) =
\merid(a) =
\merid(x) \jdeq
\tau(\north, \south, x).
\end{multline*}
In a symmetric fashion we may define $\tau(\south)$ by
%
\begin{equation*}
\tau(\south,\north, a) \defeq \opp{\merid(a)}
\qquad\text{and}\qquad
\tau(\south,\south, u) \defeq \refl{\south}.
\end{equation*}
%
To complete the construction of $\tau$, we need to check $\trans{\merid(a)}{\tau(\north)} = \tau(\south)$,
given any $a : A$. The verification proceeds much along the same lines by induction on the
second argument of $\tau$.
Thus, by \cref{thm:h-set-refrel-in-paths-sets} we have that $\susp(A)$ is a set and that $P(x,y) \eqvsym (\id{x}{y})$ for all $x,y:\susp(A)$.
Taking $x\defeq \north$ and $y\defeq \south$ yields $\eqv{A}{(\id[\susp(A)]\north\south)}$ as desired.
\end{proof}
\begin{thm}[Diaconescu]\label{thm:1surj_to_surj_to_pem}
\index{axiom!of choice}%
\index{excluded middle}%
\index{Diaconescu's theorem}\index{theorem!Diaconescu's}%
The axiom of choice implies the law of excluded middle.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
We use the equivalent form of choice given in \cref{thm:ac-epis-split}.
Consider a mere proposition $A$.
The function $f:\bool\to\susp(A)$ defined by
$f(\bfalse) \defeq \north$ and $f(\btrue) \defeq \south$
is surjective.
Indeed, we have
$\pairr{\bfalse,\refl{\north}} : \hfiber{f}{\north}$
and $\pairr{\btrue,\refl{\south}} :\hfiber{f}{\south}$.
Since $\bbrck{\hfiber{f}{x}}$ is a mere proposition, by induction the claimed surjectivity follows.
By \cref{prop:trunc_of_prop_is_set} the suspension $\susp(A)$
is a set, so by the axiom of choice there merely exists a
section $g: \susp(A) \to \bool$ of $f$.
As equality on $\bool$ is decidable we get
\begin{equation*}
(g(f(\bfalse))= g(f(\btrue))) +
\lnot (g(f(\bfalse))= g(f(\btrue))),
\end{equation*}
and, since $g$ is a section of $f$, hence injective,
\begin{equation*}
(f(\bfalse) = f(\btrue)) +
\lnot (f(\bfalse) = f(\btrue)).
\end{equation*}
Finally, since $(f(\bfalse)=f(\btrue)) = (\north=\south) = A$ by \cref{prop:trunc_of_prop_is_set}, we have $A+\neg A$.
\end{proof}
% This conclusion needs only \LEM{}, see \cref{ex:lemnm}.
% \begin{cor}\label{cor:ACtoLEM0}
% If the axiom of choice \choice{} holds then $\brck{A + \neg A}$ for every set $A$.
% \end{cor}
% \begin{proof}
% There is a surjection
% \[
% A + \neg A \epi \brck{A} + \brck{\neg A} \epi
% \brck{(\brck{A} + \brck{\neg A})} = \brck{A} \vee \brck{\neg A} = \brck{A} \vee \neg \brck{A} = \unit,
% \]
% %
% where in the last step excluded middle is available as a consequence of the axiom of choice.
% Again by the axiom of choice there merely exists a section of the surjection, but this
% is none other than an inhabitant of $A + \neg A$. Therefore $\brck{A+\neg A}$.
% \end{proof}
\index{denial}
\begin{thm}\label{thm:ETCS}
\index{Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets}%
\index{category!well-pointed}%
If the axiom of choice holds then the category $\uset$ is a well-pointed boolean\index{topos!boolean}\index{boolean!topos} elementary topos\index{topos} with choice.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
Since \choice{} implies \LEM{}, we have a boolean elementary topos with choice by \cref{thm:settopos} and the remark following it. We leave the proof of well-pointedness as
an exercise for the reader (\cref{ex:well-pointed}).
\end{proof}
\begin{rmk}
The conditions on a category mentioned in the theorem are known as Lawvere's\index{Lawvere}
axioms for the \emph{Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets}~\cite{lawvere:etcs-long}.
\end{rmk}
\section{Cardinal numbers}
\label{sec:cardinals}
\begin{defn}\label{defn:card}
The \define{type of cardinal numbers}
\indexdef{type!of cardinal numbers}%
\indexdef{cardinal number}%
\indexsee{number!cardinal}{cardinal number}%
is the 0-truncation of the type \set of sets:
\[ \card \defeq \pizero{\set} \]
Thus, a \define{cardinal number}, or \define{cardinal}, is an inhabitant of $\card\jdeq \pizero\set$.
Technically, of course, there is a separate type $\card_\UU$ associated to each universe \type.
\end{defn}
%\begin{rmk}
% , but with these conventions we can state theorems beginning with ``for all cardinal numbers\dots''\ and give them exactly the same sort of meaning as those beginning ``for all types\dots''.
%\end{rmk}
As usual for truncations, if $A$ is a set, then $\cd{A}$ denotes its image under the canonical projection $\set \to \trunc0\set \jdeq \card$; we call $\cd{A}$ the \define{cardinality}\indexdef{cardinality} of $A$.
By definition, \card is a set.
It also inherits the structure of a semiring from \set.
\begin{defn}
The operation of \define{cardinal addition}
\indexdef{addition!of cardinal numbers}%
\index{cardinal number!addition of}%
\[ (\blank+\blank) : \card \to \card \to \card \]
is defined by induction on truncation:
\[ \cd{A} + \cd{B} \defeq \cd{A+B}.\]
\end{defn}
\begin{proof}
Since $\card\to\card$ is a set, to define $(\alpha+\blank):\card\to\card$ for all $\alpha:\card$, by induction it suffices to assume that $\alpha$ is $\cd{A}$ for some $A:\set$.
Now we want to define $(\cd{A}+\blank) :\card\to\card$, i.e.\ we want to define $\cd{A}+\beta :\card$ for all $\beta:\card$.
However, since $\card$ is a set, by induction it suffices to assume that $\beta$ is $\cd{B}$ for some $B:\set$.
But now we can define $\cd{A}+\cd{B}$ to be $\cd{A+B}$.
\end{proof}
\begin{defn}
Similarly, the operation of \define{cardinal multiplication}
\indexdef{multiplication!of cardinal numbers}%
\index{cardinal number!multiplication of}%
\[ (\blank\cdot\blank) : \card \to \card \to \card \]
is defined by induction on truncation:
\[ \cd{A} \cdot \cd{B} \defeq \cd{A\times B} \]
\end{defn}
\begin{lem}\label{card:semiring}
\card is a commutative semiring\index{semiring}, i.e.\ for $\alpha,\beta,\gamma:\card$ we have the following.
\begin{align*}
(\alpha+\beta)+\gamma &= \alpha+(\beta+\gamma)\\
\alpha+0 &= \alpha\\
\alpha + \beta &= \beta + \alpha\\
(\alpha \cdot \beta) \cdot \gamma &= \alpha \cdot (\beta\cdot\gamma)\\
\alpha \cdot 1 &= \alpha\\
\alpha\cdot\beta &= \beta\cdot\alpha\\
\alpha\cdot(\beta+\gamma) &= \alpha\cdot\beta + \alpha\cdot\gamma
\end{align*}
where $0 \defeq \cd{\emptyt}$ and $1\defeq\cd{\unit}$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We prove the commutativity of multiplication, $\alpha\cdot\beta = \beta\cdot\alpha$; the others are exactly analogous.
Since \card is a set, the type $\alpha\cdot\beta = \beta\cdot\alpha$ is a mere proposition, and in particular a set.
Thus, by induction it suffices to assume $\alpha$ and $\beta$ are of the form $\cd{A}$ and $\cd{B}$ respectively, for some $A,B:\set$.
Now $\cd{A}\cdot \cd{B} \jdeq \cd{A\times B}$ and $\cd{B}\times\cd{A} \jdeq \cd{B\times A}$, so it suffices to show $A\times B = B\times A$.
Finally, by univalence, it suffices to give an equivalence $A\times B \eqvsym B\times A$.
But this is easy: take $(a,b) \mapsto (b,a)$ and its obvious inverse.
\end{proof}
\begin{defn}
The operation of \define{cardinal exponentiation} is also defined by induction on truncation:
\indexdef{exponentiation, of cardinal numbers}%
\index{cardinal number!exponentiation of}%
\[ \cd{A}^{\cd{B}} \defeq \cd{B\to A}. \]
\end{defn}
\begin{lem}\label{card:exp}
For $\alpha,\beta,\gamma:\card$ we have
\begin{align*}
\alpha^0 &= 1\\
1^\alpha &= 1\\
\alpha^1 &= \alpha\\
\alpha^{\beta+\gamma} &= \alpha^\beta \cdot \alpha^\gamma\\
\alpha^{\beta\cdot \gamma} &= (\alpha^{\beta})^\gamma\\
(\alpha\cdot\beta)^\gamma &= \alpha^\gamma \cdot \beta^\gamma
\end{align*}
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Exactly like \cref{card:semiring}.
\end{proof}
\begin{defn}
The relation of \define{cardinal inequality}
\index{order!non-strict}%
\index{cardinal number!inequality of}%
\[ (\blank\le\blank) : \card\to\card\to\prop \]
is defined by induction on truncation:
\symlabel{inj}
\[ \cd{A} \le \cd{B} \defeq \brck{\inj(A,B)} \]
where $\inj(A,B)$ is the type of injections from $A$ to $B$.
\index{function!injective}%
In other words, $\cd{A} \le \cd{B}$ means that there merely exists an injection from $A$ to $B$.
\end{defn}
\begin{lem}
Cardinal inequality is a preorder, i.e.\ for $\alpha,\beta:\card$ we have
\index{preorder!of cardinal numbers}%
\begin{gather*}
\alpha \le \alpha\\
(\alpha \le \beta) \to (\beta\le\gamma) \to (\alpha\le\gamma)
\end{gather*}
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
As before, by induction on truncation.
For instance, since $(\alpha \le \beta) \to (\beta\le\gamma) \to (\alpha\le\gamma)$ is a mere proposition, by induction on 0-truncation we may assume $\alpha$, $\beta$, and $\gamma$ are $\cd{A}$, $\cd{B}$, and $\cd{C}$ respectively.
Now since $\cd{A} \le \cd{C}$ is a mere proposition, by induction on $(-1)$-truncation we may assume given injections $f:A\to B$ and $g:B\to C$.
But then $g\circ f$ is an injection from $A$ to $C$, so $\cd{A} \le \cd{C}$ holds.
Reflexivity is even easier.
\end{proof}
We may likewise show that cardinal inequality is compatible with the semiring operations.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:injsurj}
\index{function!injective}%
\index{function!surjective}%
Consider the following statements:
\begin{enumerate}
\item There is an injection $A\to B$.\label{item:cle-inj}
\item There is a surjection $B\to A$.\label{item:cle-surj}
\end{enumerate}
Then, assuming excluded middle:
\index{excluded middle}%
\index{axiom!of choice}%
\begin{itemize}
\item Given $a_0:A$, we have~\ref{item:cle-inj}$\to$\ref{item:cle-surj}.
\item Therefore, if $A$ is merely inhabited, we have~\ref{item:cle-inj} $\to$ merely \ref{item:cle-surj}.
\item Assuming the axiom of choice, we have~\ref{item:cle-surj} $\to$ merely \ref{item:cle-inj}.
\end{itemize}
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
If $f:A\to B$ is an injection, define $g:B\to A$ at $b:B$ as follows.
Since $f$ is injective, the fiber of $f$ at $b$ is a mere proposition.
Therefore, by excluded middle, either there is an $a:A$ with $f(a)=b$, or not.
In the first case, define $g(b)\defeq a$; otherwise set $g(b)\defeq a_0$.
Then for any $a:A$, we have $a = g(f(a))$, so $g$ is surjective.
The second statement follows from this by induction on truncation.
For the third, if $g:B\to A$ is surjective, then by the axiom of choice, there merely exists a function $f:A\to B$ with $g(f(a)) = a$ for all $a$.
But then $f$ must be injective.
\end{proof}
\begin{thm}[Schroeder--Bernstein]
\index{theorem!Schroeder--Bernstein}%
\index{Schroeder--Bernstein theorem}%
Assuming excluded middle, for sets $A$ and $B$ we have
\[ \inj(A,B) \to \inj(B,A) \to (A\cong B) \]
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
The usual ``back-and-forth'' argument applies without significant changes.
Note that it actually constructs an isomorphism $A\cong B$ (assuming excluded middle so that we can decide whether a given element belongs to a cycle, an infinite chain, a chain beginning in $A$, or a chain beginning in $B$).
\end{proof}
\begin{cor}
Assuming excluded middle, cardinal inequality is a partial order, i.e.\ for $\alpha,\beta:\card$ we have
\[ (\alpha\le\beta) \to (\beta\le\alpha) \to (\alpha=\beta). \]
\end{cor}
\begin{proof}
Since $\alpha=\beta$ is a mere proposition, by induction on truncation we may assume $\alpha$ and $\beta$ are $\cd{A}$ and $\cd{B}$, respectively, and that we have injections $f:A\to B$ and $g:B\to A$.
But then the Schroeder--Bernstein theorem gives an isomorphism $A\cong B$, hence an equality $\cd{A}=\cd{B}$.
\end{proof}
Finally, we can reproduce Cantor's theorem, showing that for every cardinal there is a greater one.
\begin{thm}[Cantor]
\index{Cantor's theorem}%
\index{theorem!Cantor's}%
For $A:\set$, there is no surjection $A \to (A\to \bool)$.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
Suppose $f:A \to (A\to \bool)$ is any function, and define $g:A\to \bool$ by $g(a) \defeq \neg f(a)(a)$.
If $g = f(a_0)$, then $g(a_0) = f(a_0)(a_0)$ but $g(a_0) = \neg f(a_0)(a_0)$, a contradiction.
Thus, $f$ is not surjective.
\end{proof}
\begin{cor}
Assuming excluded middle, for any $\alpha:\card$, there is a cardinal $\beta$ such that $\alpha\le\beta$ and $\alpha\neq\beta$.
\end{cor}
\begin{proof}
Let $\beta = 2^\alpha$.
Now we want to show a mere proposition, so by induction we may assume $\alpha$ is $\cd{A}$, so that $\beta\jdeq \cd{A\to \bool}$.
Using excluded middle, we have a function $f:A\to (A\to \bool)$ defined by
\[f(a)(a') \defeq
\begin{cases}
\btrue &\quad a=a'\\
\bfalse &\quad a\neq a'.
\end{cases}
\]
And if $f(a)=f(a')$, then $f(a')(a) = f(a)(a) = \btrue$, so $a=a'$; hence $f$ is injective.
Thus, $\alpha \jdeq \cd{A} \le \cd{A\to \bool} \jdeq 2^\alpha$.
On the other hand, if $2^\alpha \le \alpha$, then we would have an injection $(A\to\bool)\to A$.
By \cref{thm:injsurj}, since we have $(\lam{x} \bfalse):A\to \bool$ and excluded middle, there would then be a surjection $A \to (A\to \bool)$, contradicting Cantor's theorem.
\end{proof}
\section{Ordinal numbers}
\label{sec:ordinals}
\index{ordinal|(}%
\begin{defn}\label{defn:accessibility}
Let $A$ be a set and
\[(\blank<\blank):A\to A\to \prop\]
a binary relation on $A$.
We define by induction what it means for an element $a:A$ to be \define{accessible}
\indexdef{accessibility}%
\indexsee{accessible}{accessibility}%
by $<$:
\begin{itemize}
\item If $b$ is accessible for every $b<a$, then $a$ is accessible.
\end{itemize}
We write $\acc(a)$ to mean that $a$ is accessible.
\end{defn}
It may seem that such an inductive definition can never get off the ground, but of course if $a$ has the property that there are \emph{no} $b$ such that $b<a$, then $a$ is vacuously accessible.
Note that this is an inductive definition of a family of types, like the type of vectors considered in \cref{sec:generalizations}.
More precisely, it has one constructor, say $\acc_<$, with type
\[ \acc_< : \prd{a:A} \Parens{\prd{b:A} (b<a) \to \acc(b)} \to \acc(a). \]
\index{induction principle!for accessibility}%
The induction principle for $\acc$ says that for any $P:\prd{a:A} \acc(a) \to \type$, if we have
\[f:\prd{a:A}{h:\prd{b:A} (b<a) \to \acc(b)}
\Parens{\prd{b:A}{l:b<a} P(b,h(b,l))} \to
P(a,\acc_<(a,h)),
\]
then we have $g:\prd{a:A}{c:\acc(a)} P(a,c)$ defined by induction, with
\[g(a,\acc_<(a,h)) \jdeq f(a,\,h,\,\lam{b}{l} g(b,h(b,l))).\]
This is a mouthful, but generally we apply it only in the simpler case where $P:A\to\type$ depends only on $A$.
In this case the second and third arguments of $f$ may be combined, so that what we have to prove is
\[f:\prd{a:A} \Parens{\prd{b:A} (b<a) \to \acc(b) \times P(b)}
\to P(a).
\]
That is, we assume every $b<a$ is accessible and $g(b):P(b)$ is defined, and from these define $g(a):P(a)$.
The omission of the second argument of $P$ is justified by the following lemma, whose proof is the only place where we use the more general form of the induction principle.
\begin{lem}
Accessibility\index{accessibility} is a mere property.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We must show that for any $a:A$ and $s_1,s_2:\acc(a)$ we have $s_1=s_2$.
We prove this by induction on $s_1$, with
\[P_1(a,s_1) \defeq \prd{s_2:\acc(a)} (s_1=s_2). \]
Thus, we must show that for any $a:A$ and ${h_1:\prd{b:A} (b<a) \to \acc(b)}$ and
\[ k_1:{\prd{b:A}{l:b<a}{t:\acc(b)} h_1(b,l) = t},\]
we have $\acc_<(a,h) = s_2$ for any $s_2:\acc(a)$.
We regard this statement as $\prd{a:A}{s_2:\acc(a)} P_2(a,s_2)$, where
\[P_2(a,s_2) \defeq
\prd{h_1 : \cdots } %{h_1:\prd{b:A} (b<a) \to \acc(b)}
{k_1 : \cdots} % \Parens{\prd{b:A}{l:b<a}{t:\acc(b)} h_1(b,l) = t} \to
(\acc_<(a,h_1) = s_2);
\]
thus we may prove it by induction on $s_2$.
Therefore, we assume $h_2 : \prd{b:A} (b<a) \to \acc(b)$, and $k_2$ with a monstrous but irrelevant type,
% \begin{narrowmultline*}
% k_2:\prd{b:A}{l:b<a}
% \prd{h_1:\prd{b':A} (b'<b) \to \acc(b')}
% \narrowbreak
% \Parens{\prd{b':A}{l':b'<b}{t':\acc(b')} h_1(b',l') = t'} \to
% (\acc_<(b,h_1) = h_2(b,l)).
% \end{narrowmultline*}
and must show that for any $h_1$ and $k_1$ with types as above,
we have $\acc_<(a,h_1) = \acc_<(a,h_2)$.
By function extensionality, it suffices to show $h_1(b,l) = h_2(b,l)$ for all $b:A$ and $l:b<a$.
This follows from $k_1$.
\end{proof}
\begin{defn}
A binary relation $<$ on a set $A$ is \define{well-founded}
\indexdef{relation!well-founded}%
\indexdef{well-founded!relation}%
if every element of $A$ is accessible.
\end{defn}
The point of well-foundedness is that for $P:A\to \type$, we can use the induction principle of $\acc$ to conclude $\prd{a:A} \acc(a) \to P(a)$, and then apply well-foundedness to conclude $\prd{a:A} P(a)$.
In other words, if from $\fall{b:A} (b<a) \to P(b)$ we can prove $P(a)$, then $\fall{a:A} P(a)$.
This is called \define{well-founded induction}\indexdef{well-founded!induction}.
\begin{lem}
Well-foundedness is a mere property.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Well-foundedness of $<$ is the type $\prd{a:A} \acc(a)$, which is a mere proposition since each $\acc(a)$ is.
\end{proof}
\begin{eg}\label{thm:nat-wf}
Perhaps the most familiar well-founded relation is the usual strict ordering on \nat.
To show that this is well-founded, we must show that $n$ is accessible for each $n:\nat$.
\index{strong!induction}%
This is just the usual proof of ``strong induction'' from ordinary induction on \nat.
Specifically, we prove by induction on $n:\nat$ that $k$ is accessible for all $k\le n$.
The base case is just that $0$ is accessible, which is vacuously true since nothing is strictly less than $0$.
For the inductive step, we assume that $k$ is accessible for all $k\le n$, which is to say for all $k<n+1$; hence by definition $n+1$ is also accessible.
A different relation on \nat which is also well-founded is obtained by setting only $n < \suc(n)$ for all $n:\nat$.
Well-foundedness of this relation is almost exactly the ordinary induction principle of \nat.
\end{eg}
\begin{eg}\label{thm:wtype-wf}
Let $A:\set$ and $B : A \to \set$ be a family of sets.
Recall from \cref{sec:w-types} that the $W$-type $\wtype{a:A} B(a)$ is inductively generated by the single constructor
\begin{itemize}
\item $\supp : \prd{a:A} (B(a) \to \wtype{x:A} B(x)) \to \wtype{x:A} B(x)$
\end{itemize}
We define the relation $<$ on $\wtype{x:A} B(x)$ by recursion on its second argument:
\begin{itemize}
\item For any $a:A$ and $f:B(a) \to \wtype{x:A} B(x)$, we define $w<\supp(a,f)$ to mean that there merely exists a $b:B(a)$ such that $w = f(b)$.
\end{itemize}
Now we prove that every $w:\wtype{x:A} B(x)$ is accessible for this relation, using the usual induction principle for $\wtype{x:A}B(x)$.
This means we assume given $a:A$ and $f:B(a) \to \wtype{x:A} B(x)$, and also a lifting $f' : \prd{b:B(a)} \acc(f(b))$.
But then by definition of $<$, we have $\acc(w)$ for all $w<\supp(a,f)$; hence $\supp(a,f)$ is accessible.
\end{eg}
Well-foundedness allows us to define functions by recursion and prove statements by induction, such as for instance the following.
Recall from \cref{subsec:prop-subsets} that $\power B$ denotes the \emph{power set}\index{power set} $\power B \defeq (B\to\prop)$.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:wfrec}
Suppose $B$ is a set and we have a function
\[ g : \power B \to B \]
Then if $<$ is a well-founded relation on $A$, there is a function $f:A\to B$ such that for all $a:A$ we have
\begin{equation*}
f(a) = g\Big(\setof{ f(a') | a'<a }\Big).
\end{equation*}
\end{lem}
\noindent
(We are using the notation for images of subsets from \cref{sec:image}.)
\begin{proof}
We first define, for every $a:A$ and $s:\acc(a)$, an element $\bar f(a,s):B$.
By induction, it suffices to assume that $s$ is a function assigning to each $a'<a$ a witness $s(a'):\acc(a')$, and that moreover for each such $a'$ we have an element $\bar f(a',s(a')):B$.
In this case, we define
\begin{equation*}
\bar f(a,s) \defeq g\Big(\setof{ \bar f(a',s(a')) | a'<a }\Big).
\end{equation*}
Now since $<$ is well-founded, we have a function $w:\prd{a:A} \acc(a)$.
Thus, we can define $f(a)\defeq \bar f (a,w(a))$.
\end{proof}
In classical\index{mathematics!classical} logic, well-foundedness has a more well-known reformulation.
In the following, we say that a subset $B: \power A$ is \define{nonempty}
\indexdef{nonempty subset}
if it is unequal to the empty subset $(\lam{x}\bot) : \power X$.
We leave it to the reader to verify that assuming excluded middle, this is equivalent to mere inhabitation, i.e.\ to the condition $\exis{x:A} x\in B$.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:wfmin}
\index{excluded middle}%
Assuming excluded middle, $<$ is well-founded if and only if every nonempty subset $B: \power A$ merely has a minimal element.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Suppose first $<$ is well-founded, and suppose $B\subseteq A$ is a subset with no minimal element.
That is, for any $a:A$ with $a\in B$, there merely exists a $b:A$ with $b<a$ and $b\in B$.
We claim that for any $a:A$ and $s:\acc(a)$, we have $a\notin B$.
By induction, we may assume $s$ is a function assigning to each $a'<a$ a proof $s(a'):\acc(a')$, and that moreover for each such $a'$ we have $a'\notin B$.
If $a\in B$, then by assumption, there would merely exist a $b<a$ with $b\in B$, which contradicts this assumption.
Thus, $a\notin B$; this completes the induction.
Since $<$ is well-founded, we have $a\notin B$ for all $a:A$, i.e. $B$ is empty.
Now suppose each nonempty subset merely has a minimal element.
Let $B = \setof{ a:A | \neg \acc(a) }$.
Then if $B$ is nonempty, it merely has a minimal element.
Thus there merely exists an $a:A$ with $a\in B$ such that for all $b<a$, we have $\acc(b)$.
But then by definition (and induction on truncation), $a$ is merely accessible, and hence accessible, contradicting $a\in B$.
Thus, $B$ is empty, so $<$ is well-founded.
\end{proof}
\begin{defn}
A well-founded relation $<$ on a set $A$ is \define{extensional}
\indexdef{relation!extensional}%
\indexdef{extensional!relation}%
if for any $a,b:A$, we have
\[ \Parens{\fall{c:A} (c<a) \Leftrightarrow (c<b)} \to (a=b). \]
\end{defn}
Note that since $A$ is a set, extensionality is a mere proposition.
This notion of ``extensionality'' is unrelated to function extensionality, and also unrelated to the extensionality of identity types.
\index{axiom!of extensionality}%
Rather, it is a ``local'' counterpart of the axiom of extensionality in classical set theory.
\begin{thm}
The type of extensional well-founded relations is a set.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
By the univalence axiom, it suffices to show that if $(A,<)$ is extensional and well-founded and $f:(A,<) \cong (A,<)$, then $f=\idfunc[A]$.
\index{automorphism!of extensional well-founded relations}%
We prove by induction on $<$ that $f(a)=a$ for all $a:A$.
The inductive hypothesis is that for all $a'<a$, we have $f(a')=a'$.
Now since $A$ is extensional, to conclude $f(a)=a$ it is sufficient to show
\[\fall{c:A}(c<f(a)) \Leftrightarrow (c<a).\]
However, since $f$ is an automorphism, we have $(c<a) \Leftrightarrow (f(c)<f(a))$.
But $c<a$ implies $f(c)=c$ by the inductive hypothesis, so $(c<a) \to (c<f(a))$.
On the other hand, if $c<f(a)$, then $f^{-1}(c)<a$, and so $c = f(f^{-1}(c)) = f^{-1}(c)$ by the inductive hypothesis again; thus $c<a$.
Therefore, we have $(c<a) \Leftrightarrow (c<f(a))$ for any $c:A$, so $f(a)=a$.
\end{proof}
\begin{defn}\label{def:simulation}
If $(A,<)$ and $(B,<)$ are extensional and well-founded, a \define{simulation}
\indexdef{simulation}%
\indexsee{function!simulation}{simulation}%
is a function $f:A\to B$ such that
\begin{enumerate}
\item if $a<a'$, then $f(a)<f(a')$, and\label{item:sim1}
\item for all $a:A$ and $b:B$, if $b<f(a)$, then there merely exists an $a'<a$ with $f(a')=b$.\label{item:sim2}
\end{enumerate}
\end{defn}
\begin{lem}
Any simulation is injective.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We prove by double well-founded induction that for any $a,b:A$, if $f(a)=f(b)$ then $a=b$.
The inductive hypothesis for $a:A$ says that for any $a'<a$, and any $b:B$, if $f(a')=f(b)$ then $a=b$.
The inner inductive hypothesis for $b:A$ says that for any $b'<b$, if $f(a)=f(b')$ then $a=b'$.
Suppose $f(a)=f(b)$; we must show $a=b$.
By extensionality, it suffices to show that for any $c:A$ we have $(c<a)\Leftrightarrow (c<b)$.
If $c<a$, then $f(c)<f(a)$ by \cref{def:simulation}\ref{item:sim1}.
Hence $f(c)<f(b)$, so by \cref{def:simulation}\ref{item:sim2} there merely exists $c':A$ with $c'<b$ and $f(c)=f(c')$.
By the inductive hypothesis for $a$, we have $c=c'$, hence $c<b$.
The dual argument is symmetrical.
\end{proof}
In particular, this implies that in \cref{def:simulation}\ref{item:sim2} the word ``merely'' could be omitted without change of sense.
\begin{cor}
If $f:A\to B$ is a simulation, then for all $a:A$ and $b:B$, if $b<f(a)$, there \emph{purely} exists an $a'<a$ with $f(a')=b$.
\end{cor}
\begin{proof}
Since $f$ is injective, $\sm{a:A} (f(a)=b)$ is a mere proposition.
\end{proof}
We say that a subset $C :\power B$ is an \define{initial segment}
\indexdef{initial!segment}%
\indexsee{segment, initial}{initial segment}%
if $c\in C$ and $b<c$ imply $b\in C$.
The image of a simulation must be an initial segment, while the inclusion of any initial segment is a simulation.
Thus, by univalence, every simulation $A\to B$ is \emph{equal} to the inclusion of some initial segment of $B$.
\begin{thm}
For a set $A$, let $P(A)$ be the type of extensional well-founded relations on $A$.
If $\mathord{<_A} : P(A)$ and $\mathord{<_B} : P(B)$ and $f:A\to B$, let $H_{\mathord{<_A}\mathord{<_B}}(f)$ be the mere proposition that $f$ is a simulation.
Then $(P,H)$ is a standard notion of structure over \uset in the sense of \cref{sec:sip}.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
We leave it to the reader to verify that identities are simulations, and that composites of simulations are simulations.
Thus, we have a notion of structure.
For standardness, we must show that if $<$ and $\prec$ are two extensional well-founded relations on $A$, and $\idfunc[A]$ is a simulation in both directions, then $<$ and $\prec$ are equal.
Since extensionality and well-foundedness are mere propositions, for this it suffices to have $\fall{a,b:A} (a<b) \Leftrightarrow (a\prec b)$.
But this follows from \cref{def:simulation}\ref{item:sim1} for $\idfunc[A]$.
\end{proof}
\begin{cor}\label{thm:wfcat}
There is a category whose objects are sets equipped with extensional well-founded relations, and whose morphisms are simulations.
\end{cor}
In fact, this category is a poset.
\begin{lem}
For extensional and well-founded $(A,<)$ and $(B,<)$, there is at most one simulation $f:A\to B$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Suppose $f,g:A\to B$ are simulations.
Since being a simulation is a mere property, it suffices to show $\fall{a:A}(f(a)=g(a))$.
By induction on $<$, we may suppose $f(a')=g(a')$ for all $a'<a$.
And by extensionality of $B$, to have $f(a)=g(a)$ it suffices to have $\fall{b:B}(b<f(a)) \Leftrightarrow (b<g(a))$.
But since $f$ is a simulation, if $b<f(a)$, then we have $a'<a$ with $f(a')=b$.
By the inductive hypothesis, we have also $g(a')=b$, hence $b<g(a)$.
The dual argument is symmetrical.
\end{proof}
Thus, if $A$ and $B$ are equipped with extensional and well-founded relations, we may write $A\le B$ to mean there exists a simulation $f:A\to B$.
\cref{thm:wfcat} implies that if $A\le B$ and $B\le A$, then $A=B$.
\begin{defn}
An \define{ordinal}
\indexdef{ordinal}%
\indexsee{number!ordinal}{ordinal}%
is a set $A$ with an extensional well-founded relation which is \emph{transitive}, i.e.\ satisfies $\fall{a,b,c:A}(a<b)\to (b<c) \to (a<c)$.
\end{defn}
\begin{eg}
Of course, the usual strict order on \nat is transitive.
It is easily seen to be extensional as well; thus it is an ordinal.
As usual, we denote this ordinal by $\omega$.
\end{eg}
\symlabel{ord}
Let \ord denote the type of ordinals.
By the previous results, \ord is a set and has a natural partial order.
We now show that \ord also admits a well-founded relation.
\symlabel{initial-segment}
If $A$ is an ordinal and $a:A$, let $\ordsl A a \defeq \setof{ b:A | b<a}$ denote the initial segment.
\index{initial!segment}%
Note that if $\ordsl A a = \ordsl A b$ as ordinals, then that isomorphism must respect their inclusions into $A$ (since simulations form a poset), and hence they are equal as subsets of $A$.
Therefore, since $A$ is extensional, $a=b$.
Thus the function $a\mapsto \ordsl A a$ is an injection $A\to \ord$.
\begin{defn}
For ordinals $A$ and $B$, a simulation $f:A\to B$ is said to be \define{bounded}
\indexdef{simulation!bounded}%
\indexdef{bounded!simulation}%
if there exists $b:B$ such that $A = \ordsl B b$.
\end{defn}
The remarks above imply that such a $b$ is unique when it exists, so that boundedness is a mere property.
We write $A<B$ if there exists a bounded simulation from $A$ to $B$.
Since simulations are unique, $A<B$ is also a mere proposition.
\begin{thm}\label{thm:ordord}
$(\ord,<)$ is an ordinal.
\end{thm}
\noindent
More precisely, this theorem says that the type $\ord_{\UU_i}$ of ordinals in one universe\index{universe level} is itself an ordinal in the next higher universe, i.e.\ $(\ord_{\UU_i},<):\ord_{\UU_{i+1}}$.
\begin{proof}
Let $A$ be an ordinal; we first show that $\ordsl A a$ is accessible (in \ord) for all $a:A$.
By well-founded induction on $A$, suppose $\ordsl A b$ is accessible for all $b<a$.
By definition of accessibility, we must show that $B$ is accessible in \ord for all $B<\ordsl A a$.
However, if $B<\ordsl A a$ then there is some $b<a$ such that $B = \ordsl{(\ordsl A a)}{b} = \ordsl A b$, which is accessible by the inductive hypothesis.
Thus, $\ordsl A a$ is accessible for all $a:A$.
Now to show that $A$ is accessible in \ord, by definition we must show $B$ is accessible for all $B<A$.
But as before, $B<A$ means $B=\ordsl A a$ for some $a:A$, which is accessible as we just proved.
Thus, \ord is well-founded.
For extensionality, suppose $A$ and $B$ are ordinals such that
\narrowequation{\prd{C:\ord} (C<A) \Leftrightarrow (C<B).}
Then for every $a:A$, since $\ordsl A a<A$, we have $\ordsl A a<B$, hence there is $b:B$ with $\ordsl A a = \ordsl B b$.
Define $f:A\to B$ to take each $a$ to the corresponding $b$; it is straightforward to verify that $f$ is an isomorphism.
Thus $A\cong B$, hence $A=B$ by univalence.
Finally, it is easy to see that $<$ is transitive.
\end{proof}
Treating \ord as an ordinal is often very convenient, but it has its pitfalls as well.
For instance, consider the following lemma, where we pay attention to how universes are used.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:ordsucc}
Let \bbU be a universe.
For any $A:\ord_\bbU$, there is a $B:\ord_\bbU$ such that $A<B$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Let $B=A+\unit$, with the element $\ttt:\unit$ being greater than all elements of $A$.
Then $B$ is an ordinal and it is easy to see that $A\cong \ordsl B \ttt$.
\end{proof}
The ordinal $B$ constructed in the proof of \cref{thm:ordsucc} is called the \define{successor}\indexdef{successor!of an ordinal} of $A$.
This lemma illustrates a potential pitfall of the ``typically ambiguous''\index{typical ambiguity} style of using \UU to denote an arbitrary, unspecified universe.
Consider the following alternative proof of it.
\begin{proof}[Another putative proof of \cref{thm:ordsucc}]
Note that $C<A$ if and only if $C=\ordsl A a$ for some $a:A$.
This gives an isomorphism $A \cong \ordsl \ord A$, so that $A<\ord$.
Thus we may take $B\defeq\ord$.
\end{proof}
The second proof would be valid if we had stated \cref{thm:ordsucc} in a typically ambiguous style.
But the resulting lemma would be less useful, because the second proof would constrain the second ``\ord'' in the lemma statement to refer to a higher universe level than the first one.
The first proof allows both universes to be the same.
Similar remarks apply to the next lemma, which could be proved in a less useful way by observing that $A\le \ord$ for any $A:\ord$.
\begin{lem}\label{thm:ordunion}
Let \bbU be a universe.
For any $X:\type$ and $F:X\to \ord_\bbU$, there exists $B:\ord_\bbU$ such that $Fx\le B$ for all $x:X$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Let $B$ be the set-quotient (see \cref{rmk:quotient-of-non-set}) of the equivalence relation $\eqr$ on $\sm{x:X} Fx$ defined as follows:
\[ (x,y) \eqr (x',y')
\;\defeq\;
\Big(\ordsl{(Fx)}{y} \cong \ordsl{(Fx')}{y'}\Big).
\]
Define $(x,y)<(x',y')$ if $\ordsl{(Fx)}{y} < \ordsl{(Fx')}{y'}$.
This clearly descends to the quotient, and can be seen to make $B$ into an ordinal.
Moreover, for each $x:X$ the induced map $Fx\to B$ is a simulation.
\end{proof}
\section{Classical well-orderings}
\label{sec:wellorderings}
\index{denial|(}%
We now show the equivalence of our ordinals with the more familiar classical\index{mathematics!classical} well-orderings.
\begin{lem}
\index{excluded middle}%
Assuming excluded middle, every ordinal is trichotomous:
\index{trichotomy of ordinals}%
\index{ordinal!trichotomy of}%
\[ \fall{a,b:A} (a<b) \vee (a=b) \vee (b<a). \]
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
By induction on $a$, we may assume that for every $a'<a$ and every $b':A$, we have $(a'<b') \vee (a'=b') \vee (b'<a')$.
Now by induction on $b$, we may assume that for every $b'<b$, we have $(a<b') \vee (a=b') \vee (b'<a)$.
By excluded middle, either there merely exists a $b'<b$ such that $a<b'$, or there merely exists a $b'<b$ such that $a=b'$, or for every $b'<b$ we have $b'<a$.
In the first case, merely $a<b$ by transitivity, hence $a<b$ as it is a mere proposition.
Similarly, in the second case, $a<b$ by transport.
Thus, suppose $\fall{b':A}(b'<b)\to (b'<a)$.
Now analogously, either there merely exists $a'<a$ such that $b<a'$, or there merely exists $a'<a$ such that $a'=b$, or for every $a'<a$ we have $a'<b$.
In the first and second cases, $b<a$, so we may suppose $\fall{a':A}(a'<a)\to (a'<b)$.
However, by extensionality, our two suppositions now imply $a=b$.
\end{proof}
\begin{lem}
A well-founded relation contains no cycles, i.e.\
\[ \fall{n:\mathbb{N}}{a:\mathbb{N}_n\to A} \neg\Big((a_0<a_1) \wedge \dots \wedge (a_{n-1}<a_n)\wedge (a_n<a_0)\Big). \]
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We prove by induction on $a:A$ that there is no cycle containing $a$.
Thus, suppose by induction that for all $a'<a$, there is no cycle containing $a'$.
But in any cycle containing $a$, there is some element less than $a$ and contained in the same cycle.
\end{proof}
\indexdef{relation!irreflexive}%
\index{irreflexivity!of well-founded relation}%
In particular, a well-founded relation must be \define{irreflexive}, i.e.\ $\neg(a<a)$ for all $a$.
\begin{thm}\label{thm:wellorder}
Assuming excluded middle, $(A,<)$ is an ordinal if and only if every nonempty subset $B\subseteq A$ has a least element.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
If $A$ is an ordinal, then by \cref{thm:wfmin} every nonempty subset merely has a minimal element.
But trichotomy implies that any minimal element is a least element.
Moreover, least elements are unique when they exist, so merely having one is as good as having one.
Conversely, if every nonempty subset has a least element, then by \cref{thm:wfmin}, $A$ is well-founded.
We also have trichotomy, since for any $a,b$ the subset
$ \setof{a,b} \defeq \setof{x:A | x=a \lor x=b} $
merely has a least element, which must be either $a$ or $b$.
This implies transitivity, since if $a<b$ and $b<c$, then either $a=c$ or $c<a$ would produce a cycle.
Similarly, it implies extensionality, for if $\fall{c:A}(c<a)\Leftrightarrow (c<b)$, then $a<b$ implies (letting $c$ be $a$) that $a<a$, which is a cycle, and similarly if $b<a$; hence $a=b$.
\end{proof}
In classical\index{mathematics!classical} mathematics, the characterization of \cref{thm:wellorder} is taken as the definition of a \emph{well-ordering}, with the \emph{ordinals} being a canonical set of representatives of isomorphism classes for well-orderings.
In our context, the structure identity principle means that there is no need to look for such representatives: any well-ordering is as good as any other.
We now move on to consider consequences of the axiom of choice.
For any set $X$, let $\powerp X$ denote the type of merely inhabited subsets of $X$:
\symlabel{inhabited-powerset}
\[ \powerp X \defeq \setof{ Y : \power X | \exis{x:X} x\in Y}. \]
Assuming excluded middle, this is equivalently the type of \emph{nonempty}\index{nonempty subset} subsets of $X$, and we have $\power X \eqvsym (\powerp X) + \unit$.
\begin{thm}\label{thm:wop}
\index{axiom!of choice}%
\index{excluded middle}%
Assuming excluded middle, the following are equivalent.
\begin{enumerate}
\item For every set $X$, there merely exists a function
$ f: \powerp X \to X $
such that $f(Y)\in Y$ for all $Y:\powerp X$.\label{item:wop1}
\item Every set merely admits the structure of an ordinal.\label{item:wop2}
\end{enumerate}
\end{thm}
\noindent
Of course,~\ref{item:wop1} is a standard classical\index{mathematics!classical} version of the axiom of choice; see \cref{ex:choice-function}.
\begin{proof}
One direction is easy: suppose~\ref{item:wop2}.
Since we aim to prove the mere proposition~\ref{item:wop1}, we may assume $A$ is an ordinal.
But then we can define $f(B)$ to be the least element of $B$.
Now suppose~\ref{item:wop1}.
As before, since~\ref{item:wop2} is a mere proposition, we may assume given such an $f$.
We extend $f$ to a function
\[ \bar f:\power X \eqvsym (\powerp X) + \unit \longrightarrow X+\unit
\]
in the obvious way.
Now for any ordinal $A$, we can define $g_A:A\to X+\unit$ by well-founded recursion:
\[ g_A(a) \defeq
\bar f\Big(X \setminus \setof{ g_A(b) | \strut (b<a) \wedge (g_A(b) \in X) }\Big)
\]
(regarding $X$ as a subset of $X+\unit$ in the obvious way).
Let $A'\defeq \setof{a:A | g_A(a) \in X}$ be the preimage of $X\subseteq X+\unit$; then we claim the restriction $g_A':A' \to X$ is injective.
For if $a,a':A$ with $a\neq a'$, then by trichotomy and without loss of generality, we may assume $a'<a$.
Thus $g_A(a') \in \setof{ g_A(b) | b<a }$, so since $f(Y)\in Y$ for all $Y$ we have $g_A(a) \neq g_A(a')$.
Moreover, $A'$ is an initial segment of $A$.
For $g_A(a)$ lies in \unit if and only if $\setof{g_A(b)|b<a} = X$, and if this holds then it also holds for any $a'>a$.
Thus, $A'$ is itself an ordinal.
Finally, since \ord is an ordinal, we can take $A\defeq\ord$.
Let $X'$ be the image of $g_\ord':\ord' \to X$; then the inverse of $g_\ord'$ yields an injection $H:X'\to \ord$.
By \cref{thm:ordunion}, there is an ordinal $C$ such that $Hx\le C$ for all $x:X'$.
Then by \cref{thm:ordsucc}, there is a further ordinal $D$ such that $C<D$, hence $Hx<D$ for all $x:X'$.
Now we have
\begin{align*}
g_{\ord}(D) &= \bar f\Big( X \setminus \setof{ g_\ord(B) | \rule{0pt}{1em} B<D \wedge (g_\ord(B) \in X)} \Big)\\
&=\bar f\Big( X \setminus \setof{ g_\ord(B) | \rule{0pt}{1em} g_\ord(B) \in X} \Big)
\end{align*}
since if $B:\ord$ and $(g_\ord(B) \in X)$, then $B = Hx$ for some $x:X'$, hence $B<D$.
Now if
\[\setof{ g_\ord(B) | \rule{0pt}{1em} g_\ord(B) \in X}\]
is not all of $X$, then $g_\ord(D)$ would lie in $X$ but not in this subset, which would be a contradiction since $D$ is itself a potential value for $B$.
So this set must be all of $X$, and hence $g_\ord'$ is surjective as well as injective.
Thus, we can transport the ordinal structure on $\ord'$ to $X$.
\end{proof}
\begin{rmk}
If we had given the wrong proof of \cref{thm:ordsucc} or \cref{thm:ordunion}, then the resulting proof of \cref{thm:wop} would be invalid: there would be no way to consistently assign universe levels\index{universe level}.
As it is, we require propositional resizing (which follows from \LEM{}) to ensure that $X'$ lives in the same universe as $X$ (up to equivalence).
\end{rmk}
\begin{cor}
Assuming the axiom of choice, the function $\ord\to\set$ (which forgets the order structure) is a surjection.
\end{cor}
Note that \ord is a set, while \set is a 1-type.
In general, there is no reason for a 1-type to admit any surjective function from a set.
Even the axiom of choice does not appear to imply that \emph{every} 1-type does so (although see \cref{ex:acnm-surjset}), but it readily implies that this is so for 1-types constructed out of \set, such as the types of objects of categories of structures as in \cref{sec:sip}.
The following corollary also applies to such categories.
\begin{cor}
\index{weak equivalence!of precategories}%
Assuming \choice{}, \uset admits a weak equivalence functor from a strict category.
\end{cor}
\begin{proof}
Let $X_0\defeq \ord$, and for $A,B:X_0$ let $\hom_X(A,B) \defeq (A\to B)$.
Then $X$ is a strict category, since \ord is a set, and the above surjection $X_0 \to \set$ extends to a weak equivalence functor $X\to \uset$.
\end{proof}
Now recall from \cref{sec:cardinals} that we have a further surjection $\cd{\blank}:\set\to\card$, and hence a composite surjection $\ord\to\card$ which sends each ordinal to its cardinality.
\begin{thm}
Assuming \choice{}, the surjection $\ord\to\card$ has a section.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
There is an easy and wrong proof of this: since \ord and \card are both sets, \choice{} implies that any surjection between them \emph{merely} has a section.
However, we actually have a canonical \emph{specified} section: because \ord is an ordinal, every nonempty subset of it has a uniquely specified least element.
Thus, we can map each cardinal to the least element in the corresponding fiber.
\end{proof}
It is traditional in set theory to identify cardinals with their image in \ord: the least ordinal having that cardinality.
It follows that \card also canonically admits the structure of an ordinal: in fact, one isomorphic to \ord.
Specifically, we define by well-founded recursion a function $\aleph:\ord\to\ord$, such that $\aleph(A)$ is the least ordinal having cardinality greater than $\aleph({\ordsl A a})$ for all $a:A$.
Then (assuming \choice{}) the image of $\aleph$ is exactly the image of \card.
\index{denial|)}%
\index{ordinal|)}%
\section{The cumulative hierarchy}
\label{sec:cumulative-hierarchy}
\index{bargaining|(}%
We can define a cumulative hierarchy $V$ of all sets in a given universe $\UU$ as a higher inductive type, in such a way that $V$ is again a set (in a larger universe $\UU'$), equipped with a binary ``membership'' relation $x\in y$ which satisfies the usual laws of set theory.
\begin{defn}\label{defn:V}
The \define{cumulative hierarchy}
\indexdef{cumulative!hierarchy, set-theoretic}%
\indexdef{hierarchy!cumulative, set-theoretic}%
$V$ relative to a type universe $\UU$ is the
higher inductive type generated by the following constructors.
%
\begin{enumerate}
\item For every $A : \UU$ and $f : A \to V$, there is an element $\vset(A, f) : V$.
\item For all $A, B : \UU$, $f : A \to V$ and $g : B \to V$ such that
%
\begin{narrowmultline} \label{eq:V-path}
\big(\fall{a:A} \exis{b:B} \id[V]{f(a)}{g(b)}\big) \land \narrowbreak
\big(\fall{b:B} \exis{a:A} \id[V]{f(a)}{g(b)}\big)
\end{narrowmultline}
%
there is a path $\id[V]{\vset(A,f)}{\vset(B,g)}$.
\item The 0-truncation constructor: for all $x,y:V$ and $p,q:x=y$, we have $p=q$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{defn}
In set-theoretic language, $\vset(A,f)$ can be understood as the set (in the sense of classical set theory) that is the image of $A$ under $f$, i.e.\ $\setof{ f(a) | a \in A }$.
However, we will avoid this notation, since it would clash with our notation for subtypes (but see~\eqref{eq:class-notation} and \cref{def:TypeOfElements} below).
The hierarchy $V$ is
bootstrapped from the empty map $\rec\emptyt(V) : \emptyt \to V$, which gives the empty set as $\emptyset = \vset(\emptyt,\rec\emptyt(V))$.
Then the singleton $\{\emptyset\}$ enters $V$ through $\unit \to V$, defined as $\ttt \mapsto \emptyset$, and so
on.
(The definition can also be adapted to include an arbitrary set of ``atoms'' or ``urelements'', by adding an additional point constructor.)
The type $V$ lives in the same universe as the base universe $\UU$.
The second constructor of $V$ has a form unlike any we have seen before: it involves not only paths in $V$ (which in \cref{sec:hittruncations} we claimed were slightly fishy) but truncations of sums of them.
It certainly does not fit the general scheme described in \cref{sec:naturality}, and thus it may not be obvious what its induction principle should be.
Fortunately, like our first definition of the 0-truncation in \cref{sec:hittruncations}, it can be re-expressed using auxiliary higher inductive types.
We leave it to the reader to work out the details (see \cref{ex:cumhierhit}).
\index{induction principle!for cumulative hierarchy}%
At the end of the day, the induction principle for $V$ (written in pattern matching language) says that given $P:V\to \set$, in order to construct $h:\prd{x:V} P(x)$, it suffices to give the following.
\begin{enumerate}
\item For any $f:A\to V$, construct $h(\vset(A,f))$, assuming as given $h(f(a))$ for all $a:A$.
\item Verify that if $f : A \to V$ and $g : B \to V$ satisfy~\eqref{eq:V-path}, then $\dpath{P}{q}{h(\vset(A,f))}{h(\vset(B,g))}$, where $q$ is the path arising from the second constructor of $V$ and~\eqref{eq:V-path}, assuming inductively that $h(f(a))$ and $h(g(b))$ are defined for all $a:A$ and $b:B$, and that the following condition holds:
\begin{eqnarray*}
& & \big(\fall{a:A} \exis{b:B} \exis{p:f(a)=g(b)} \dpath{P}{p}{h(f(a))}{h(g(b))}\big) \\
& \land & \big(\fall{b:B} \exis{a:A} \exis{p:f(a)=g(b)} \dpath{P}{p}{h(f(a))}{h(g(b))}\big)
\end{eqnarray*}
\end{enumerate}
The second clause checks that the map being defined must respect the paths introduced in \eqref{eq:V-path}.
As usual when we state higher induction principles using pattern matching, it may seem tautologous, but is not.
The point is that ``$h(f(a))$'' is essentially a formal symbol which we cannot peek inside of, which $h(\vset(A,f))$ must be defined in terms of. Thus, in the second clause, we assume equality of these formal symbols when appropriate, and verify that the elements resulting from the construction of the first clause are also equal.
Of course, if $P$ is a family of mere propositions, then the second clause is automatic.
Observe that, by induction, for each $v:V$ there merely exist $A:\UU$ and $f:A\to V$ such that $v=\vset(A,f)$.
Thus, it is reasonable to try to define the \define{membership relation}
\indexdef{membership, for cumulative hierarchy}%
$x\in v$ on $V$ by setting:
%
% Note: "membership" rather than "elementhood", because "element" is taken.
%
\symlabel{V-membership}
\begin{equation*}
(x \in \vset(A,f)) \defeq (\exis{a : A} x = f(a)).
\end{equation*}
%
To see that the definition is valid, we must use the recursion principle of $V$. Thus, suppose we have a path $\vset(A, f) = \vset(B, g)$
constructed through~\eqref{eq:V-path}. If $x \in \vset(A,f)$ then there merely is $a : A$ such
that $x = f(a)$, but by~\eqref{eq:V-path} there merely is $b : B$ such that $f(a) = g(b)$, hence
$x = g(b)$ and $x \in \vset(B,g)$. The converse is symmetric.
The \define{subset relation}
\indexdef{subset!relation on the cumulative hierarchy}%
$x\subseteq y$ is defined on $V$ as usual by
%
\begin{equation*}
(x \subseteq y) \defeq \fall{z : V} z \in x \Rightarrow z \in y.
\end{equation*}
A \define{class}
\indexdef{class}%
may be taken to be a mere predicate on~$V$. We can say that a class $C : V \to \prop$ is a
\define{$V$-set}
\indexdef{set!in the cumulative hierarchy}%
if there merely exists $v:V$ such that
%
\begin{equation*}
\fall{x : V} C(x) \Leftrightarrow x \in v.
\end{equation*}
We may also use the conventional notation for classes, which matches our standard notation for subtypes:
\begin{equation}
\setof{ x | C(x) } \defeq \lam{x}C(x).\label{eq:class-notation}
\end{equation}
%
A class $C: V\to \prop$ will be called \define{$\UU$-small}
\indexdef{class!small}%
\indexdef{small!class}%
if all of its values $C(x)$ lie in $\UU$, specifically $C: V\to \prop_{\UU}$.
Since $V$ lives in the same universe $\UU'$ as does the base universe $\UU$ from which it is built, the same is true for the identity types $v=_V w$ for any $v,w:V$. To obtain a well-behaved theory in the absence of propositional resizing,
\index{propositional!resizing}%
\index{resizing}%
therefore, it will be convenient to have a $\UU$-small ``resizing'' of the identity relation, which we can define by induction as follows.
\begin{defn}\label{def:bisimulation}
Define the \define{bisimulation}
\indexdef{bisimulation}%
relation
%
\begin{equation*}
\mathord\bisim : V \times V \longrightarrow \prop_{\UU}
\end{equation*}
%
by double induction over $V$, where for $\vset(A,f)$ and $\vset(B,g)$ we let:
\begin{narrowmultline*}
\vset(A,f) \bisim \vset(B,g) \defeq \narrowbreak
\big(\fall{a:A}\exis{b:B} f(a) \bisim g(b)\big) \land
\big(\fall{b:B}\exis{a:A} f(a) \bisim g(b)\big).
\end{narrowmultline*}
\end{defn}
%
To verify that the definition is correct, we just need to check that it respects paths $\vset(A, f) = \vset(B, g)$ constructed through~\eqref{eq:V-path}, but this is obvious, and that $\prop_{\UU}$ is a set, which it is. Note that $u \bisim v$ is in $\propU$ by construction.
\begin{lem}\label{lem:BisimEqualsId}
For any $u,v:V$ we have $(u=_V v) = (u \bisim v)$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
An easy induction shows that $\bisim$ is reflexive, so by transport we have $(u=_V v)\to (u \bisim v)$.
Thus, it remains to show that $(u \bisim v)\to (u=_V v)$.
By induction on $u$ and $v$, we may assume they are $\vset(A,f)$ and $\vset(B,g)$ respectively.
(We can ignore the path constructors of $V$, since $(u \bisim v)\to (u=_V v)$ is a mere proposition.)
Then by definition, $\vset(A,f)\bisim\vset(B,g)$ implies $(\fall{a:A}\exis{b:B}f(a) \bisim g(b))$ and conversely.
But the inductive hypothesis then tells us that $(\fall{a:A}\exis{b:B}f(a) = g(b))$ and conversely.
So by the path con\-struc\-tor for $V$ we have $\vset(A,f) =_V \vset(B,g)$.
\end{proof}
One might think that we could omit the 0-truncation constructor of $V$ and \emph{prove} that $V$ is 0-truncated by applying \cref{thm:h-set-refrel-in-paths-sets} to the bisimulation.
However, in the proof of \cref{lem:BisimEqualsId} we used the fact that $V$ is 0-truncated, to conclude that $(u \bisim v)\to (u=_V v)$ is a mere proposition so that in the induction it suffices to assume $u$ and $v$ are $\vset(A,f)$ and $\vset(B,g)$.
Now we can use the resized identity relation to get the following useful principle.
\begin{lem}\label{lem:MonicSetPresent}
For every $u:V$ there is a given $A_u:\UU$ and monic $m_u: A_u \mono V$ such that $u = \vset(A_u, m_u)$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Take any presentation $u = \vset(A,f)$ and factor $f:A\to V$ as a surjection followed by an injection:
%
\begin{equation*}
f = m_u\circ e_u : A \epi A_u \mono V.
\end{equation*}
%
Clearly $u = \vset(A_u, m_u)$ if only $A_u$ is still in $\UU$, which holds if the kernel of $e_u : A \epi A_u$ is in $\UU$. But the kernel of $e_u : A \epi A_u$ is the pullback along $f : A\to V$ of the identity on $V$, which we just showed to be $\UU$-small, up to equivalence. Now, this construction of the pair $(A_u, m_u)$ with $m_u :A_u \mono V$ and $u = \vset(A_u, m_u)$ from $u:V$ is unique up to equivalence over $V$, and hence up to identity by univalence. Thus by the principle of unique choice \eqref{cor:UC} there is a map $c : V\to\sm{A:\UU}(A\to V)$ such that $c(u) = (A_u, m_u)$, with $m_u :A_u \mono V$ and $u = \vset(c(u))$, as claimed.
\end{proof}
\begin{defn}\label{def:TypeOfElements}
For $u:V$, the just constructed monic presentation $m_u: A_u \mono V$ such that $u = \vset(A_u, m_u)$ may be called the \define{type of members}
\indexdef{type!of members}%
of $u$ and denoted $m_u : [u] \mono V$, or even $[u] \mono V$. We can think of $[u]$ as the ``subclass of $V$ consisting of members of $u$''.
\end{defn}
\begin{thm}\label{thm:VisCST}
\index{axiom!of set theory, for the cumulative hierarchy}%
The following hold for $(V, {\in})$:
%
\begin{enumerate}
\item \emph{extensionality:}
%
\begin{equation*}
\fall{x, y : V} x \subseteq y \land y \subseteq x \Leftrightarrow x = y.
\end{equation*}
%
\item \emph{empty set:} for all $x:V$, we have $\neg (x\in \emptyset)$.
%
\item \emph{pairing:} for all $u, v:V$, the class $\{u, v\} \defeq \setof{ x | x = u \vee x = v}$ is a $V$-set.
%
\item \emph{infinity:}\index{axiom!of infinity} there is a $v:V$ with $\emptyset\in v$ and $x\in v$ implies $x\cup \{x\}\in v$.
%
\item \emph{union:} for all $v:V$, the class $\cup v\defeq \setof{ x | \exis{u:V} x \in u \in v}$ is a $V$-set.
%
\item \emph{function set:} for all $u, v:V$, the class $v^u \defeq \setof{ x | x : u\to v}$ is a $V$-set.%
\footnote{Here $x:u\to v$ means that $x$ is an appropriate set of ordered pairs, according to the usual way of encoding functions in set theory.}
%
\item \emph{$\in$-induction:} if $C : V \to \prop$ is a class such that $C(a)$ holds whenever $C(x)$ for all $x\in a$, then $C(v)$ for all $v:V$.
%
\item \emph{replacement:}\index{axiom!of replacement} given any $r : V \to V$ and $x : V$, the class
%
\begin{equation*}
\setof{ y | \exis{z : V} z \in x \land y = r(z)}
\end{equation*}
%
is a $V$-set.
%
\item \emph{separation:}\index{axiom!of separation} given any $a : V$ and $\UU$-small $C : V \to \propU$, the class
%
\begin{equation*}
\setof{ x | x \in a \land C(x)}
\end{equation*}
%
is a $V$-set.
\end{enumerate}
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}[Sketch of proof]
\mbox{}
%
\begin{enumerate}
\item Extensionality: if $\vset(A,f) \subseteq \vset(B, g)$ then $f(a) \in \vset(B, g)$
for every $a : A$, therefore for every $a : A$ there merely exists $b : B$ such that
$f(a) = g(b)$. The assumption $\vset(B, g) \subseteq \vset(A, f)$ gives the other half
of~\eqref{eq:V-path}, therefore $\vset(A,f) = \vset(B,g)$.
\item Empty set: suppose $x\in \emptyset = \vset(\emptyt,\rec\emptyt(V))$. Then $\exis{a:\emptyt}x=\, \rec\emptyt(V,a)$, which is absurd.
\item Pairing: given $u$ and $v$, let $w=\vset(\bool,\rec\bool(V,u,v))$.
\index{pair!unordered}
\item Infinity: take $w = \vset(\nat,I)$, where $I: \nat \to V$ is given by the recursion $I(0) \defeq \emptyset$ and $I(n+1) \defeq I(n)\cup \{I(n)\}$.
\item Union: Take any $v:V$ and any presentation $f :A\to V$ with $v=\vset(A,f)$. Then let $\tilde{A} \defeq \sm{a:A}[fa]$, where $m_{fa} : [fa] \mono V$ is the type of members from \cref{def:TypeOfElements}. $\tilde{A}$ is plainly $\UU$-small, and we have $\cup v \defeq \vset(\tilde{A}, \lam{x} m_{f(\proj1(x))}(\proj2(x)))$.
\item Function set: given $u, v:V$, take the types of members $[u] \mono V$ and $[v] \mono V$, and the function type $[u]\to [v]$. We want to define a map
\[
r: ([u]\to [v])\ \longrightarrow\ V
\]
with ``$r(f) = \setof{ \pairr{x, f(x)} | x : [u] }$'', but in order for this to make sense we must first define the ordered pair $\pairr{x, y}$, and then we take the map $r': x \mapsto \pairr{x, f(x)}$, and then we can put $r(f)\defeq \vset([u], r')$. But the ordered pair can be defined in terms of unordered pairing as usual.
\item $\in$-induction: let $C : V \to \prop$ be a class such that $C(a)$ holds whenever $C(x)$ for all $x\in a$, and take any $v=\vset(B,g)$. To show that $C(v)$ by induction, assume that $C(g(b))$ for all $b:B$. For every $x\in v$ there merely exists some $b:B$ with $x = g(b)$, and so $C(x)$. Thus $C(v)$.
\item Replacement: let $C$ denote the class in question.
The statement ``$C$ is a $V$-set'' is a mere proposition, so we may
proceed by induction as follows. Supposing $x$ is $\vset(A, f)$, we claim that $w
\defeq \vset(A, r \circ f)$ is the set we are looking for. If $C(y)$ then there merely exists
$z : V$ and $a : A$ such that $z = f(a)$ and $y = r(z)$, therefore $y \in w$.
Conversely, if $y \in w$ then there merely exists $a : A$ such that $y = r(f(a))$, so
if we take $z \defeq f(a)$ we see that $C(y)$ holds.
\item Let us say that a class $C: V\to\prop$ is \define{separable}
\indexdef{class!separable}%
\indexdef{separable class}%
if for any $a:V$ the class
%
\symlabel{class-intersection}
\begin{equation*}
a \cap C \defeq\setof{x | x\in a \wedge C(x)}
\end{equation*}
%
is a $V$-set.
We need to show that any $\UU$-small $C: V \to \propU$ is separable. Indeed, given $a=\vset(A,f)$, let $A' = \sm{x:A}C(fx)$, and take $f' = f\circ i$, where $i : A' \to A$ is the obvious inclusion. Then we can take $a' = \vset(A',f')$ and we have $x\in a\wedge C(x) \Leftrightarrow x\in a'$ as claimed. We needed the assumption that $C$ lands in $\UU$ in order for $A' = \sm{x:A}C(fx)$ to be in $\UU$.\qedhere
\end{enumerate}
\end{proof}
It is also convenient to have a strictly syntactic criterion of separability, so that one can read off from the expression for a class that it produces a $V$-set. One such familiar condition is being ``$\Delta_0$'', which means that the expression is built up from equality $x=_V y$ and membership $x\in y$, using only mere-propositional connectives $\neg$, $\land$, $\lor$, $\Rightarrow$ and quantifiers $\forall$, $\exists$ over particular sets, i.e.\ of the form $\exists(x\in a)$ and $\forall(y\in b)$ (these are called \define{bounded} quantifiers\index{bounded!quantifier}\index{quantifier!bounded}).\indexdef{separation!.Delta0@$\Delta_0$}%
\begin{cor}\label{cor:Delta0sep}
If the class $C: V \to \prop$ is $\Delta_0$ in the above sense, then it is separable.
\end{cor}
\index{axiom!of $\Delta_0$-separation}%
\begin{proof}
Recall that we have a $\UU$-small resizing $x \bisim y$ of identity $x = y$. Since $x\in y$ is defined in terms of $x=y$, we also have a $\UU$-small resizing of membership
%
\symlabel{resized-membership}
\begin{equation*}
x\bin\vset(A,f) \defeq \exis{a:A} x \bisim f(a).
\end{equation*}
%
Now, let $\Phi$ be a $\Delta_0$ expression for $C$, so that as classes $\Phi = C$ (strictly speaking, we should distinguish expressions from their meanings, but we will blur the difference). Let $\widetilde{\Phi}$ be the result of replacing all occurrences of $=$ and $\in$ by their resized equivalents $\bisim$ and $\bin$. Clearly then $\widetilde{\Phi}$ also expresses $C$, in the sense that for all $x:V$, $\widetilde{\Phi}(x) \Leftrightarrow C(x)$, and hence $\widetilde{\Phi}=C$ by univalence. It now suffices to show that $\widetilde{\Phi}$ is $\UU$-small, for then it will be separable by the theorem.
We show that $\widetilde{\Phi}$ is $\UU$-small by induction on the construction of the expression. The base cases are $x \bisim y$ and $x\bin y$, which have already been resized into $\UU$. It is also clear that $\UU$ is closed under the mere-propositional operations (and $(-1)$-truncation), so it just remains to check the bounded quantifiers $\exists(x\in a)$ and $\forall(y\in b)$. By definition,
\begin{align*}
\exists(x\in a) P(x) &\defeq \Brck {\sm{x:V}(x\bin a \land P(x))},\\
\forall(y\in b) P(x) &\defeq \prd{x:V}(x\bin a \to P(x)).
\end{align*}
Let us consider $\brck {\sm{x:V}(x\bin a \land P(x))}$. Although the body $(x\bin a \land P(x))$ is $\UU$-small since $P(x)$ is so by the inductive hypothesis, the quantification over $V$ need not stay inside $\UU$. However, in the present case we can replace this with a quantification over the type $[a]\mono V$ of members of $a$, and easily show that
\begin{equation*}
\sm{x:V}(x\bin a \land P(x)) = \sm{x:[a]} P(x).
\end{equation*}
The right-hand side does remain in $\UU$, since both $[a]$ and $P(x)$ are in $\UU$. The case of $\prd{x:V}(x\bin a \to P(x))$ is analogous, using $\prd{x:V}(x\bin a \to P(x)) = \prd{x:[a]}P(x)$.
\end{proof}
We have shown that in type theory with a universe $\UU$, the cumulative hierarchy $V$ is a model of a ``constructive set theory''
\index{constructive!set theory}%
with many of the standard axioms.
However, as far as we know, it lacks the \emph{strong collection}
\index{axiom!strong collection}%
\index{collection!strong}%
\index{strong!collection}%
and \emph{subset collection}
\index{axiom!subset collection}%
\index{collection!subset}%
\index{subset!collection}%
axioms which are included in \CZF{}~\cite{AczelCZF}.
In the usual interpretation of this set theory into type theory, these two axioms are consequences of the setoid-like definition of equality; while in other constructed models of set theory, strong collection may hold for other reasons.
We do not know whether either of these axioms holds in our model $(V,\in)$, but it seems unlikely.
Since $V$ is a higher inductive type \emph{inside} the system, rather than being an \emph{external} construction, it is not surprising that it differs in some ways from prior interpretations.
Finally, consider the result of adding the axiom of choice for sets to our type theory, in the form $\choice{}$ from \cref{subsec:emacinsets} above. This has the consequence that $\LEM{}$ then also holds, by \cref{thm:1surj_to_surj_to_pem}, and so $\set$ is a topos\index{topos} with subobject classifier $\bool$, by \cref{thm:settopos}. In this case, we have $\prop = \bool:\UU$, and so \emph{all classes are separable}.
Thus we have shown:
\begin{lem}\label{lem:fullsep}
In type theory with $\choice{}$, the law of \define{(full) separation}
\indexdef{separation!full}%
holds for $V$: given \emph{any} class $C : V \to \prop$ and $a : V$, the class $a \cap C$ is a $V$-set.
\end{lem}
\begin{thm}\label{thm:zfc}
In type theory with $\choice{}$ and a universe $\UU$, the cumulative hierarchy $V$ is a model of Zermelo--Fraenkel\index{set theory!Zermelo--Fraenkel} set theory with choice, ZFC.
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
We have all the axioms listed in \cref{thm:VisCST}, plus full separation, so we just need to show that there are power sets\index{power set} $\power a:V$ for all $a:V$. But since we have $\LEM{}$ these are simply function types $\power a = (a\to\bool)$. Thus $V$ is a model of Zermelo--Fraenkel set theory ZF. We leave the verification of the set-theoretic axiom of choice from $\choice{}$ as an easy exercise.
\end{proof}
\index{bargaining|)}%
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
\sectionNotes
The basic properties one expects of the category of sets date back to the early days of elementary topos theory.
The \emph{Elementary theory of the category of sets} referred to in \cref{subsec:emacinsets} was introduced by Lawvere\index{Lawvere} in
\cite{lawvere:etcs-long}, as a category-theoretic axiomatization of set theory.
\index{Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets}%
The notion of $\Pi W$-pretopos, regarded as a predicative version of an elementary topos, was introduced in~\cite{MoerdijkPalmgren2002}; see also~\cite{palmgren:cetcs}.
The treatment of the category of sets in \cref{sec:piw-pretopos} roughly follows that in~\cite{RijkeSpitters}.
The fact that epimorphisms are surjective (\cref{epis-surj}) is well known in classical mathematics, but is not as trivial as it may seem to prove \emph{predicatively}.
\index{mathematics!predicative}%
The proof in~\cite{Mines/R/R:1988} uses the power set operation (which is impredicative), although it can also be seen as a predicative proof of the weaker statement that a map in a universe $\UU_i$ is surjective if it is an epimorphism in the next universe $\UU_{i+1}$.
A predicative proof for setoids was given by Wilander~\cite{Wilander2010}.
Our proof is similar to Wilander's, but avoids setoids by using pushouts and univalence.
The implication in \cref{thm:1surj_to_surj_to_pem} from $\choice{}$ to $\LEM{}$ is an adaptation to homotopy type
theory of a theorem from topos theory due to Diaconescu~\cite{Diaconescu}; it was posed as a problem already by Bishop~\cite[Problem~2]{Bishop1967}.
For the intuitionistic theory of ordinal numbers, see~\cite{taylor:ordinals,Taylor99} and also \cite{JoyalMoerdijk1995}.
Definitions of well-foundedness in type theory by an induction principle, including the inductive predicate of accessibility\index{accessibility}, were studied in~\cite{Huet80,Paulson86,Nordstrom88}, although the idea dates back to Gentzen's proof of the consistency\index{consistency!of arithmetic} of arithmetic~\cite{Gentzen36}.
The idea of algebraic set theory, which informs our development in \cref{sec:cumulative-hierarchy} of the cumulative hierarchy, is due to~\cite{JoyalMoerdijk1995}, but it derives from earlier work by~\cite{AczelCZF}.
\index{algebraic set theory}%
\index{set theory!algebraic}%
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
\sectionExercises
\begin{ex}\label{ex:utype-ct}
Following the pattern of $\uset$, we would like to make a category $\utype$ of all types and maps between them (in a given universe $\UU$). In order for this to be a category in the sense of \cref{sec:cats}, however, we must first declare $\hom(X,Y) \defeq \pizero{X\to Y}$, with composition defined by induction on truncation from ordinary composition $(Y\to Z) \to (X\to Y) \to (X\to Z)$. This was defined as the \emph{homotopy precategory of types} in \cref{ct:hoprecat}. It is still not a category, however, but only a precategory (its type of objects $\UU$ is not even a $0$-type). It becomes a category by Rezk completion
\index{completion!Rezk}%
(see \cref{ct:hocat}), and its type of objects can be identified with $\trunc1\type$ by \cref{ct:ex:hocat}. Show that the resulting category $\utype$, unlike $\uset$, is not a pretopos.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:surjections-have-sections-impl-ac}
Show that if every surjection has a section in the category $\uset$, then the axiom of choice holds.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:well-pointed}
Show that with $\LEM{}$, the category $\uset$ is well-pointed,
\indexdef{category!well-pointed}%
in the sense that the following statement holds: for any $f, g : A\to B$, if $f \neq g$ then there is a function $a : 1\to A$ such that $f(a) \neq g(a)$.
Show that the slice category
\index{category!slice}%
$\uset/\bool$ consisting of functions $A\to \bool$ and commutative triangles does not have this property.
(Hint: the terminal object in $\uset/\bool$ is the identity function $\bool \to \bool$, so in this category, there are objects $X$ that have no elements $1\to X$.)
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:add-ordinals}
\index{addition!of ordinal numbers}%
Prove that if $(A,<_A)$ and $(B,<_B)$ are well-founded, extensional, or ordinals, then so is $A+B$, with $<$ defined by
\begin{align*}
(a<a') &\defeq (a<_A a') & \text{for }& a,a':A\\
(b<b') &\defeq (b<_B b') & \text{for }& b,b':B\\
(a<b) &\defeq \unit & \text{for }& (a:A),(b:B)\\
(b<a) &\defeq \emptyt & \text{for }& (a:A),(b:B).
\end{align*}
\end{ex}
% \begin{proof}
% We first prove by induction on $<_A$ that every element of $A$ is accessible in $A+B$.
% This is easy since the only elements less than $a:A$ in $A+B$ are also in $A$.
% We then prove by induction on $<_B$ that every element of $B$ is accessible in $A+B$.
% This is easy since we have already proven that every element of $A$ is accessible.
% \end{proof}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:multiply-ordinals}
\index{multiplication!of ordinal numbers}%
Prove that if $(A,<_A)$ and $(B,<_B)$ are well-founded, extensional, or ordinals, then so is $A\times B$, with $<$ defined by
\[ ((a,b) <(a',b')) \defeq (a<_A a') \vee ((a=a') \wedge (b<_B b')). \]
\end{ex}
% \begin{proof}
% We prove by induction on $<_A$ that for every $a:A$, every element of the form $(a,b)$ is accessible in $A\times B$.
% The inductive hypothesis is that for all $a'<_A a$, every pair $(a',b)$ is accessible.
% Inside this induction, we prove by induction on $<_B$ that for every $b:B$, the element $(a,b)$ is accessible.
% The nested inductive hypothesis is that for every $b'<_B b$, the element $(a,b')$ is accessible.
% But now, if $(a',b')< (a,b)$, then either $a<_A a'$ in which case $(a',b')$ is accessible by the first inductive hypothesis, or $a=a'$ and $b'<_B b$, in which case $(a,b')$ is accessible by the second inductive hypothesis.
% Thus, by definition of accessibility, $(a,b)$ is accessible.
% This completes both inductions.
% \end{proof}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:algebraic-ordinals}
Define the usual algebraic operations on ordinals, and prove that they satisfy the usual properties.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:prop-ord}
Note that $\bool$ is an ordinal, under the obvious relation $<$ such that $\bfalse<\btrue$ only.
\begin{enumerate}
\item Define a relation $<$ on $\prop$ which makes it into an ordinal.
\item Show that $\id[\ord]\bool\prop$ if and only if \LEM{} holds.
\end{enumerate}
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:ninf-ord}
Recall that we denote \nat by $\omega$ when regarding it as an ordinal; thus we have also the ordinal $\omega+1$.
On the other hand, let us define
\[ \nat_\infty \defeq \setof{a:\nat\to\bool | \fall{n:\nat} (a_n \le a_{\suc(n)}) } \]
where $\le$ denotes the obvious partial order on $\bool$, with $\bfalse\le\btrue$.
\begin{enumerate}
\item Define a relation $<$ on $\nat_\infty$ which makes it into an ordinal.
\item Show that $\id[\ord]{\omega+1}{\nat_\infty}$ if and only if the limited principle of omniscience~\eqref{eq:lpo} holds.%
\index{limited principle of omniscience}%
\end{enumerate}
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:well-founded-extensional-simulation}
Show that if $(A,<)$ is well-founded and extensional and $A:\UU$, then there is a simulation $A\to V$, where $(V,\in)$ is the cumulative hierarchy from \cref{sec:cumulative-hierarchy} built from the universe~\UU.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:choice-function}
Show that \cref{thm:wop}\ref{item:wop1} is equivalent to the axiom of choice~\eqref{eq:ac}.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:cumhierhit}
Given types $A$ and $B$, define a \define{bitotal relation}
\indexsee{bitotal relation}{relation, bitotal}%
\indexdef{relation!bitotal}%
to be $R:A\to B\to \prop$ such that
\[ \Big(\fall{a:A}\exis{b:B} R(a,b) \Big) \land \Big(\fall{b:B}\exis{a:A} R(a,b) \Big). \]
For such $A,B,R$, let $A\sqcup^R B$ be the higher inductive type generated by
\begin{itemize}
\item $i:A\to A\sqcup^R B$
\item $j:B\to A\sqcup^R B$
\item For each $a:A$ and $b:B$ such that $R(a,b)$, a path $i(a)=j(b)$.
\end{itemize}
Show that the cumulative hierarchy $V$ can be defined by the following more straightforward list of constructors, and that the resulting induction principle is the one given in \cref{sec:cumulative-hierarchy}.
\begin{itemize}
\item For every $A : \UU$ and $f : A \to V$, there is an element $\vset(A, f) : V$.
\item For any $A,B:\UU$ and bitotal relation
\index{relation!bitotal}%
$R:A\to B\to \prop$, and any map $h:A\sqcup^R B \to V$, there is a path $\id{\vset(A,h\circ i)}{\vset(B,h\circ j)}$.
\item The 0-truncation constructor.
\end{itemize}
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:strong-collection}
In \CZF, the \define{axiom of strong collection}
\indexdef{axiom!strong collection}%
\indexdef{collection!strong}%
\indexdef{strong!collection}%
has the form:
\begin{multline*}
\Parens{\fall{x\in v}\exis{y} R(x,y)} \Rightarrow \\
\exis{w}\big[\big(\fall{x\in v}\exis{y\in w}R(x,y)\big)\land \big(\fall{y\in w}\exis{x\in v}R(x,y) \big)\big]
\end{multline*}
Does it hold in the cumulative hierarchy $V$? (We do not know the answer to this.)
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:choice-cumulative-hierarchy-choice}
Verify that, if we assume $\choice{}$, then the cumulative hierarchy $V$ satisfies the usual set-theoretic axiom of choice, which may be stated in the form:
\[
\fall{x:V} \Parens{(\fall{y\in x}\exis{z:V} z\in y) \Rightarrow \exis{c\in(\cup x)^x}\fall{y\in x} c(y)\in y}
\]
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:plump-ordinals}
Assuming propositional resizing, show that there is a mere predicate $\mathsf{isPlump}:\ord\to\prop$ such that for any $A:\ord$ we have
\begin{multline*}\label{eq:plump}
\mathsf{isPlump}(A) = \Parens{\fall{B<A} \mathsf{isPlump}(B)} \wedge\narrowbreak
\Parens{\fall{C,B:\ord} C\le B < A \wedge \mathsf{isPlump}(C) \Rightarrow C < A}.
\end{multline*}
Note that $\mathsf{isPlump}$ cannot be defined by a simple well-founded induction over \ord; you must use a different well-founded relation.
We say that an ordinal $A$ is \define{plump}~\cite{taylor:ordinals,Taylor99} if $\mathsf{isPlump}(A)$.
\index{plump!ordinal}\index{ordinal!plump}%
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:not-plump}
Show that \LEM{} is equivalent to the statement ``all ordinals are plump''.
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:plump-successor}
Define the \define{plump successor}\index{plump!successor}\indexdef{successor!plump} of an ordinal $A$ to be
\[ t(A) \defeq \setof{ B:\ord | (B\le A) \wedge \mathsf{isPlump}(B) } \]
\begin{enumerate}
\item By definition, $t(A)$ belongs to the next higher universe.
Show that assuming propositional resizing, it is equal to an ordinal in the same universe as $A$.
\item Again assuming propositional resizing, show that if $A$ is plump (\cref{ex:plump-ordinals}) then so is $t(A)$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:ZF-algebras}
A \define{ZF-algebra}~\cite{JoyalMoerdijk1995}
\index{ZF-algebra}%
relative to a universe $\UU_i$ is a poset (see \cref{ct:orders}) $V:\UU_{i+1}$, which has all suprema indexed by types in $\UU_i$, and is equipped with a ``successor'' function $s:V\to V$ (not necessarily respecting $\le$ in any way).
\begin{enumerate}
\item Show that the cumulative hierarchy $(V_{\UU_i},\subseteq,s)$ is the initial ZF-algebra, where $s(x)$ is the singleton $\setof{x}$.
\item Show that $(\ord_{\UU_i},\le,s)$ is the initial ZF-algebra with the property that $x\le s(x)$ for all $x$, where $s(A)=A+\unit$ is the successor\index{successor!of an ordinal} from \cref{thm:ordsucc}.
\item Assuming propositional resizing, show that $\Parens{\setof{A:\ord_{\UU_i} | \mathsf{isPlump}(A) },\le,t}$ is the initial ZF-algebra with the property that $(x\le y) \Rightarrow (t(x)\le t(y))$ for all $x,y$, where $t$ is the plump successor from \cref{ex:plump-successor}.
\end{enumerate}
\end{ex}
\begin{ex}\label{ex:monos-are-split-monos-iff-LEM-holds}
For a category $A$, a morphism $f: \hom_A(a,b)$ is said to be a \define{split monomorphism} if there exists a morphism $g: \hom_A(b,a)$ such that $\id{g \circ f}{1_a}$. (Such $g$ is called a \define{retraction} of $f$.)
Prove that the following are logically equivalent.
\begin{enumerate}
\item $\LEM{}$.
\item For every sets $A$ and $B$, if $A$ is inhabited then for every monomorphism $f: A \to B$ in $\uset$, $f$ is also a split monomorphism in $\uset$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{ex}
\index{set|)}%
% Local Variables:
% TeX-master: "hott-online"
% End:
|