text
stringlengths 0
1.71k
|
---|
'Operation Rescue: Domestic Terrorism or Legitimate Civil Rights |
Protest?' Hastings Center Report, NovemberlDecember 1989, pp. 28- |
32. The biblical passage quoted is from Proverbs 24: 11. The claim |
by Gary Leber about the number of children saved is in his essay |
'We Must Rescue Them', Hastings Center Report, NovemberlDecember |
1989, pp.26-7. On Gennarelli's experiments and the events surrounding |
them, see Lori Gruen and Peter Singer, Animal Liberation: |
A Graphic Guide (London, 1987). On the Animal Liberation Front, |
see also Philip Windeatt, 'They Clearly Now See the Link: Militant |
Voices', in P. Singer (ed.), In Defence of Animals (Oxford, 1985). The |
blockade of the Franklin River is vividly described by a participant |
in James McQueen, The Franklin: Not Just a River (Ringwood, Victoria, |
1983); on the unsuccessful earlier campaign to save Lake Peddar, |
see Kevin Kiernan, 'I Saw My Temple Ransacked', in Cassandra |
Pybus and Richard Flanagan (eds.), The Rest of the World Is Watching |
(Sydney, 1990). |
Henry Thoreau's 'Civil Disobedience' has been reprinted in several |
places, among them H. A. Bedau (ed.), Civil Disobedience: Theory and |
Practice (New York, 1969); the passage quoted is on p. 28 of this collection. |
The immediately following quotation is from p. 18 of R. P. |
Wolff's In Defense of Anarchism (New York, 1970). On the nature of |
conscience, see A. Campbell Garnett, 'Conscience and Conscientiousness', |
in J. Feinberg (ed.), Moral Concepts (Oxford, 1969). |
376 |
Notes and References |
John Locke argued for the importance of settled law in his Second |
Treatise on Civil Government, especially sections 124-6. |
On the sorry history of attempts to reform the law on animal experimentation, |
see Richard Ryder, Victims of Science. |
Mill's proposal for multiple votes for the better educated occurs in |
Chapter 8 of his Representative Government. The quotation from Engels's |
Condition of the Working Class in England, trans. and ed. Henderson and |
Chaloner (Oxford, 1958), p. 108, lowe to John Harris, 'The Marxist |
Conception of Violence', Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 3 (1974), |
which argues persuasively for regarding passive violence as a genuine |
form of violence. See also Harris's book, Violence and Responsibility (London, |
1980); and Ted Honderich, Three Essays on Political Violence (Oxford, |
1976). The quotation from Dave Foreman and Bill Haywood, |
Ecodefense: A Field Guide to Monkeywrenching (Tucson, Ariz., 1987), |
appears on pp. 14 and 17. |
The issues dealt with in the first three sections of this chapter are |
more fully treated in my Democracy and Disobedience (Oxford, 1973). |
Probably the best collection of essays in this area is still J. G. Murphy |
(ed.), Civil Disobedience and Violence (Belmont, 1971), although the |
anthology edited by H. A. Bedau, referred to above, is valuable for its |
emphasis on the writings ofthose who practice civil disobedience rather |
than theorise about it from afar. |
Chapter 12: Why act morally? |
For attempts to reject the title question of this chapter as an improper |
question, see S. Toulmin, The Place of Reason in Ethics (Cambridge, |
1961), p. 162; J. Hospers, Human Conduct (London, 1963), p. 194; and |
M. G. Singer, Generalization in Ethics (London, 1963), pp. 319-27. D. |
H. Monro defines ethical judgments as overriding in Empiricism and |
Ethics (Cambridge, 1967); see, for instance, p. 127. R. M. Hare's prescriptivist |
view of ethics implies that a commitment to act is involved |
in accepting a moral jUdgment, but since only universalisable judgments |
count as moral judgments, this view does not have the consequence |
that whatever judgment we take to be overriding is necessarily |
our moral judgment. Hare's view therefore allows us to give sense to |
our question. On this general issue of the definition of moral terms |
and the consequences of different definitions, see my 'The Triviality of |
the Debate over "Is-Ought" and the Definition of "Moral"', American |
Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 10 (1973). |
The argument discussed in the second section is a distillation of such |
377 |
Notes and References |
sources as Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, bk. 4, par. 4; I. Kant. Groundwork |
of the Metaphysic of Morals; H. J. Paton, The Categorical Imperative |
(London, 1963), pp.245-6; J. Hospers, Human Conduct (London, |
1963), pp. 584-93; and D. Gauthier, Practical Reasoning (Oxford, 1963), |
p.118. |
G. Carlson, 'Ethical Egoism Reconsidered', American Philosophical |
Quarterly, vol. 10 (1973), argues that egoism is irrational because the |
individual egoist cannot defend it publicly without inconsistency; but |
it is not clear why this should be a test ofrationality, since the egoist |
can still defend it to himself. |
Hume defends his view of practical reason in A Treatise of Human |
Nature, bk. 1, pt. iii, sec. 3. T. Nagel's objections to it are in The Possibility |
of Altruism (Oxford, 1970). For a more recent statement of Nagel's |
position, see his The View from Nowhere (New York, 1986). Sidgwick's |
observation on the rationality of egoism is on p. 498 of The Methods of |
Ethics, 7th ed. (London, 1907). |
Bradley's insistence on loving virtue for its own sake comes from |
his Ethical Studies (Oxford, 1876; repr. 1962), pp. 61-3. The same |
position can be found in Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, |
chap. 1, and in D. Z. Phillips, 'Does It Pay to Be Good?' Proceedings of |
the Aristotelian Society, vol. 64 (1964-5). Bradley and Kant are expounding |
what they take to be 'the common moral consciousness' |
rather than their own views. Kant himself adheres to the view of the |
common moral consciousness, but later in Ethical Studies Bradley supports |
a view of morality in which the subjective satisfaction involved |
in the moral life plays a prominent role. |
My account of why we believe that only actions done for the sake |
of morality have moral worth is similar to Hume's view in his Enquiry |
Concerning the Principles of Morals. See also P. H. Nowell-Smith, Ethics, |
pt. 3. |
Maslow presents some sketchy data in support of his theory of personality |
in 'Psychological Data and Value Theory', in A. H. Maslow |
(ed.), New Knowledge in Human Values (New York, 1959); see also A. |
H. Maslow, Motivation and Personality (New York, 1954). Charles |